Sentence and Proposition
Sentence and Proposition
This is a book( the sentence can be translated and expressed into various
language but there is only proposition underlined in all these differently
expressed sentences.)
In proposition, we assert or deny any fact or judgement.
CATAGORICAL – singular, compund
Book highlights
PROPOSITION – subject (compulsion)
A proposition is believed or disbelieved, asserted or denied whereas
sentences are neither asserted nor denied.
Proposition can be true or false whereas sentences cannot be true or false.
Sentences can be valid or invalid
SENTENCES
A sentence is to be understood as any grammatically correct and
complete strings of words, which are expressed in our everyday language.
In short, sentence is a meaningful arrangement of words.
Sentence has three parts:
Subject, predicate and a copula
TYPES OF SENTENCES:
1. INTERROGATIVE SENTENCES- are you alright?
2. EXCLAMATORY SENTENCES- what a beautiful flower is!
3. IMPERATIVE SENTENCES- come here.
4. INFORMATIVE/ DECLARATIVE SENTENCES- fruits are
nutritious.
PROPOSITION
A proposition is a unit of reasoning in logic.
Only indicative sentences can be a proposition.
Proposition asserts that something is the case or something is not.
Every proposition is either true or false.
A proposition is true when it describe the facts correctly and proposition
is false when it does not describe the facts correctly.
ARGUMENTS
With preposition as building blocks we construct arguments. In any we
affirm on preposition on the basis of some other preposition –( features of
argument)
In doing this an inference is drawn. Inference is a process that may tie
together a cluster of prepositions.
Some inference are warranted or correct, others are not. The logician
analyses these clusters of prepositions. Examining the preposition with
Book highlights
which the process begins and with which the process ends. As well as the
relations among these prepositions.
Such a cluster of propositions constitutes an argument. Arguments are the
chief concern of logic. In logic, argument refers strictly to any group of
propositions of which one is claimed to follow from the others, which are
regarded as providing support for the truth of that one. For every possible
inference there is a corresponding argument.
An argument is not merely a collection of propositions; it is a cluster with
a structure that captures or exhibits some inference. We describe this
structure with the terms conclusion and premise.
The conclusion of an argument is the proposition that is affirmed on the
basis of the other propositions of the argument.
Those other propositions, which are affirmed (or assumed) as providing
support for the conclusion, are the premises of the argument.
We will analyze arguments in politics, in ethics, in sports, in religion, in
science, in law, and in everyday life.
Those who defend these arguments, or who attack them, are usually
aiming to establish the truth (or the falsehood) of the conclusions drawn.
First, we will be concerned about the form of an argument under
consideration, to determine if that argument is of a kind that is likely to
yield a warranted conclusion.
Second, we will be concerned about the quality of the argument, to
determine whether it does in fact yield a warranted conclusion.
Third, the simplest kind of argument consists of one premise and a
conclusion that is claimed to follow from it.
The order in which premises and conclusion appear can also vary.
Even when premise and conclusion are united in one sentence, the
conclusion of the argument may come first.
For example
Every law is an evil, for every law is an infraction of liberty.
Book highlights
However, no single proposition can be an argument, because an argument
is made up of a group of propositions. Every argument, however—short
or long, simple or complex—consists of a group of propositions of which
one is the conclusion and the other(s) are the premises offered to support
it.
Book highlights
arguments. inductive arguments may be “better” or “worse,” “weaker” or
“stronger,” and so on
Example of deductive argument –
1st – all mamals have lungs (major premise)
2nd – all whales are mamals (minor premise)
3rd – all whales have lungs (conclusion)
Here,
Lungs – major premise – predicate
Mamals – middle term – never comes in conclusion
Whales – minor premise – subject
Book highlights
as “because,” “for,” “since,” and “therefore”—cannot settle the matter,
because those words are used both in explanations and in arguments
(although “since” can sometimes refer to temporal succession). We need
to know the intention of the author.
2. Therefore is the name of it [the tower] called Babel; because the Lord
did there confound the language of all the earth.
The first passage is clearly an argument. Its conclusion, that one ought to
lay up treasures in heaven, is supported by the premise (here marked by
the word “for”) that one’s heart will be where one’s treasure is laid up.
The second passage, which uses the word “therefore” quite
appropriately, is not an argument. It explains why the tower (whose
construction is recounted in Genesis) is called Babel.
The tower was given this name, we are told, because it was the place
where humankind, formerly speaking one language, became confounded
by many languages—the name is derived from a Hebrew word meaning
“to confound.”
The passage assumes that the reader knows that the tower had that name;
the intention is to explain why that name was given to it.
The phrase, “Therefore is the name of it called Babel,” is not a
conclusion but a completion of the explanation of the naming.
In addition, the clause, “because the Lord did there confound the
language of all the earth,” is not a premise; it could not serve as a reason
for believing that Babel was the name of the tower, because the fact that
that was the name is known by those to whom the passage is addressed.
In this context, “because” indicates that what follows will explain the
giving of that name, Babel, to that tower.
These two passages illustrate the fact that superficially similar passages
may have very different functions.
Whether some passage is an argument or an explanation depends on the
purpose to be served by it.
In an explanation, what is being explained is how the tower of babel
come to have that name. the explanation is that the tower was given this
name because it was the place where humankind, formerly speaking one
Book highlights
language, became confounded by many languages, because the Lord did
there confound the language of all the earth.
Book highlights
All mammals have lungs.
All whales are mammals.
Therefore all whales have lungs.
The true conclusion of this argument does not follow from its true
premises. This will be seen more clearly when the immediately
following illustration is considered.
Book highlights
If Bill Gates owned all the gold in Fort Knox, then
Gates would be wealthy.
Bill Gates does not own all the gold in Fort Knox.
Therefore Bill Gates is not wealthy.
The premises of this argument are true, but its conclusion is false.
Such an argument cannot be valid because it is impossible for the
premises of a valid argument to be true and its conclusion to be
false.
VI. Some invalid arguments also have false premises and a true
conclusion:
Book highlights
All whales have wings.
Therefore all mammals are whales.
These seven examples make it clear that there are valid arguments
with false conclusions (Example II), as well as invalid arguments
with true conclusions (Examples III and VI). Hence it is clear that
the truth or falsity of an argument’s conclusion does not by itself
determine the validity or invalidity of that argument. Moreover,
the fact that an argument is valid does not guarantee the truth of its
conclusion (Example II).
UNIT – 2
LOGIC AND LANGUAGE
Book highlights
In reasoning it is this informative function of language that is the
principal concern.
In this informative mode we can distinguish between facts a
sentence formulates and facts about the speaker who formulates
them. If someone says, “War is always the wrong solution to
international conflict,” that may indeed be true, but it is also
evidence of the beliefs of the person who utters that remark.
When someone says, “I strongly oppose our involvement in this
war on moral grounds,” that is a statement (very probably true)
about the speaker, but it also serves to express a judgment about
the morality of the war under discussion.
Book highlights