Between Capitalism and Community (2020)
Between Capitalism and Community (2020)
Between Capitalism and Community (2020)
“For some time now Michael Lebowitz has been patiently and provocatively
remaking our conception of Marx’s Capital and the potential for human devel-
opment. In standing against a ‘one-sided’ reading of Marx for an insistence
on seeing workers struggling to make their own world, Lebowitz has pushed
to the side stale, top-down theses of social transformation through statist
planning set apart from workers’ organization and participation. Indeed, in
his essential new book it is the building of workers’ capacities and communi-
ties that transforms circumstances and contexts in a process of contested
reproduction against capital. This is a directive to think of community not
as a romanticized place standing against the storms of an outside world, but
community as a process of struggle to meet and self-govern over common
needs against the ceaseless demands of accumulation, alienated work, and
the vandalism of the earth. Could any text be more important to read, dis-
cuss, and debate in the harsh times we face today?”—GREG ALBO, Professor
of Political Economy, York University; coeditor, The Socialist Register
“This book should be mandatory for all economics, political science, and
social philosophy classes. Comrades—especially younger ones—will find it
immensely helpful for years to come. The sweep of the work is truly impres-
sive; comprehensive and clear on everything essential for understanding the
horrors of capitalism and the paths toward a better world.”—TONY SMITH,
Professor of Philosophy and Political Science, Iowa State University
“In twelve concisely and clearly written chapters, Lebowitz, among the best
radical economists in the world, shows that in Capital, Marx failed to fully
appreciate that the accumulation of capital results in two products—com-
modities of all kinds and the workers themselves. The latter, the ‘second
product’ of capitalist production, is shaped by capital so that the working
class is both badly divided and not fully cognizant of an all-encompassing
alienation. Equally missing from Capital is a full grasp of how the collective
actions of workers not only improve their life circumstances but also radically
change them, preparing them to become society’s eventual protagonists,
those who will abolish capitalism and create the collective commonwealth,
which alone can overcome the multiple crises that now confront us, espe-
cially ecological disaster.”—MICHAEL D. YATES, author, Can the Working
Class Change the World?
“In this admirable and timely book, Michael Lebowitz deepens and extends
the understanding of capitalism that he developed in his prize-winning
Beyond Capital. He argues persuasively that building critically on Marx’s
conceptualisation of capitalism as an organic system is indispensable to diag-
nosing the ills of the contemporary world—in particular the growing ‘crisis
of the Earth System’ that threatens to overwhelm us.”—ALEX CALLINICOS,
former Professor of European Studies, King’s College London
“This book is a provocation, as much for traditional Marxists as for the vari-
ous schools of nontraditional Marxism. It puts the question on the table of
whether Marx’s Capital could be an obstacle for understanding class struggle
and revolutionary practice. Michael Lebowitz questions what is taken for
granted by the majority of Marxists. He draws conclusions from this critique,
which also influences the offered vision of a non-capitalist future.”
—MICHAEL HEINRICH, author, Karl Marx and the Birth of Modern Society
BETWEEN
CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
MICHAEL A. LEBOWITZ
MONT H LY R EV I EW PRESS
New York
Copyright © 2020 by Michael A. Lebowitz
All Rights Reserved
M O N T H LY R EV I EW P R E S S , N EW YO R K
monthlyreview.org
54321
Contents
Preface | 7
Introduction: Class Struggle and Capital | 11
Notes | 180
Index | 199
There are those that struggle all of their life.
They are the indispensable ones.
— Bertold Brecht, “In Praise of the Fighters”
What kind of party? This is not arbitrary, and it is definitely not the
disciplined vanguard party (or sect) that purports to change circum-
stances for people. Grasping the centrality of revolutionary practice,
the party that can go beyond capitalism, self-interest, and hierarchy to
develop relations of community is one that stresses protagonism and
the development of the capacities of people through all their activi-
ties. Rather than those who know, delivering their distilled knowledge
to those who do not know, this is a political instrument that listens
and learns. In this, I share the insistence of Marta Harnecker on the
profoundly democratic nature of the necessary political instrument.5
I am happy to be working again with Michael Yates of Monthly
Review Press because my experience with him on previous books has
been all that I could hope for in an editor. Sadly, though, due to her
extended battle against cancer and her death on 14 June 2019, I have
not been able to complete this part of the journey with Marta, my
comrade and partner. We have all lost one of the “indispensables”
who struggle all their lives to build a better world. In completing this
book, I miss not only her loving presence but also her wisdom in
commenting upon my work. If this book does not suffer significantly
as a result, it is because of all that I have already learned from her.
— 2 7 F E B R UA RY 2 0 2 0
INTrODUCTION
Capital. No wonder, then, that the theory of wages is put off until a
later volume or so of Capital.”11
Class struggle in this view relates to distribution, and, before dis-
tribution can be considered, we must understand the production of
surplus value which “sets the parameters within which class strug-
gle can be located.” Indeed, for Fine, “The structures and processes
of accumulation have to be specified before the mode, nature and
impact of class struggle can be assessed.”12 Accordingly, given how
“varied, numerous and complex” are the elements relating to class
struggle, Fine concludes that I have been premature in insisting that
class struggle be considered sooner: “The degree of separation simply
leapfrogs from the abstract to the concrete.”13
There are two central problems in Fine’s argument.14 One is that
the variety, differentiation, and complexity he identifies at the level
of the concrete applies as well to the standard of necessity, the length
and intensity of the workday, and the level of productivity, all con-
cepts essential for developing the concept of surplus value. Contrary
to Fine, the existence of real complexity offers no special impediment
to the introduction of the concept of the degree of separation at the
level of Capital.
More significant, however, is Fine’s premise that class struggle
relates to distribution and not to the production of surplus value; that
is, it occurs post festum. For this premise to hold, class struggle must
be demonstrated to play no role in the determination of the work-
day, the standard of necessity, and the level of productivity. But this
is precisely the begged question. Unless class struggle is irrelevant
to the determination of the production of surplus value, then Fine’s
argument has no substance. Yet, as should be obvious from chapter
10 of Capital, Marx was unequivocal in insisting that class struggle
determines the normal workday and thus is central to the production
of surplus value.
Ironically, Marx’s discussion of the struggle over the workday
provides the basis for a different critique of my argument. Contrary
to “those who argue that there is no class struggle in Capital,” Alex
Callinicos proposes, “Chapter 10 is about class struggle.” Indeed, he
INTrODUCTION 15
declares that “the chapter on the working day is the clearest refuta-
tion of the claim put forward, for example, by Michael Lebowitz, that
‘Capital is one-sided precisely because the worker is not present as the
subject who acts herself against capital.’ ” 15
The point of chapter 10, though, was not to introduce the worker
as subject; rather, its focus was to emphasize capital’s drive to extend
the workday in search of absolute surplus value, a drive that physi-
cally and mentally destroys workers and threatens the reproduction
of the working class. Indeed, the “voracious appetite” of capital is
so destructive, Marx declares, that “the same necessity as forced the
manuring of English fields with guano” brings forth state laws to place
limits on capital’s drive. Summarizing his historical account of capi-
tal’s efforts to go beyond all limits to the workday, Marx noted that
“capital therefore takes no account of the health and length of life of
the worker, unless society forces it to do so.”16
Certainly, the workers immediately affected by capital’s effort to
grow in this manner were an essential (although not the only) part of
society’s opposition to this assault. Yes, of course, Callinicos is right:
Chapter 10 definitely introduces class struggle by workers. “Suddenly,”
Marx announces, “there arises the voice of the worker, which had pre-
viously been stifled in the sound and fury of the production process.”
And, suddenly, we do see that, in addition to the right of the capitalist,
there is also the right of the worker, and that “between equal rights,
force decides.”17
In chapter 10, Marx described how English workers developed as
a class in their struggles against capital’s drive for absolute surplus
value. We see there “the daily more threatening advance of the work-
ing-class movement,” how workers moved from “passive, though
inflexible and unceasing” resistance to begin open class protest; we
see their growing “power of attack” and how a “long class struggle”
shaped the new factory legislation. Indeed, Marx concluded that “the
establishment of a normal workday is therefore the product of a pro-
tracted and more or less concealed civil war between the capitalist
class and the working class.”18
So, what then happens with that working-class subject in Capital?
16 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
Gone! That voice of the worker, that right of the worker, that civil war
from the side of the worker suddenly disappears. Those working-class
subjects who struggle against capital enter left onto the stage in chap-
ter 10, but their bodies are snatched, and they are replaced in Capital
(as we will see) by workers who look upon the requirements of capital
as “self-evident natural laws,” workers who guarantee “in perpetuity”
the reproduction of capital.
Yes, there is that struggle over the workday, but why didn’t the
absence of wage struggles in Capital sound an alarm bell? We know, as
Callinicos does, that Marx was well aware of the struggles at the time
of the working class over wages. Indeed, Callinicos cites Value, Price
and Profit from this period, indicating that Marx stressed that “the
working man constantly presses in the opposite direction” to the capi-
talist over wages. Callinicos describes that work (rather than Capital)
as Marx’s “most developed discussion of the strictly economic strug-
gle.” Accordingly, doesn’t Callinicos’s proposal that this discussion
“may be seen as a complement” to Capital weaken his claim that the
worker is present in Capital as the subject who struggles for herself
against capital?19
If workers as subjects indeed did disappear from Capital after
chapter 10, did that reimposed silence have any implications with
respect to our understanding of the logic of capital? And was chapter
10 the result of a lapse on Marx’s part or did class struggle on the part
of workers not belong there? That is, as Albritton and Fine might sug-
gest, did chapter 10 introduce an alien element into Capital?
When we investigate the concept of capitalism as an organic system,
it returns us to these various critiques, especially that of Thompson,
and opens up questions that I did not pose before. In particular,
revisiting my earlier point about the one-sidedness of Capital is like
pulling on a loose thread and causing much to unravel, not the least
of which are the arguments of many Marxist theorists.
PA RT I
IN PRAISE OF
DIALECTICS
1
how the computer solution will change if one piece of data is changed.
It is obvious that if you change the data fed into that computer, it
will generate a different optimum solution. So, that is the principal
question neoclassical economists pose: let us change the value of one
variable and see what the new equilibrium will be. Significantly, neo-
classical economists do not pose this as a process that occurs in real
time. Rather, they just want to change one variable and to see what the
lightning calculator of pleasure and pain would do. But this is not a
process that occurs in time. Because in a real world if we did change
variable X, this could affect variable Y, and a change in variable Y
might affect variable Z or variable X itself (in other words, create a
feedback process). In real time, there are always processes of interac-
tion, but neoclassical economics is not considering a real process that
occurs in real time. That is why the critical phrase used is “all other
things equal” (or, in Latin, ceteris paribus). We change one bit of data
and nothing else.
So, with that in mind, let’s think like a neoclassical economist.
What happens if we raise the price of one consumer product? Well,
obviously that increases the pain of purchasing that product, so the
computer as consumer will generate a result in which less of that
product is purchased and more of another. A new optimum solution
is generated by the computer. Or let us raise the wage. The computer
as capitalist, in comparison to the original situation, would choose
to use a machine rather than a worker because the pain of hiring
the worker has increased. Or let’s increase payments for welfare. The
computer as worker chooses to go on welfare rather than to get a job.
It’s all very simple. In every case, the question asked by neoclassical
economic theory is what that individual, the instantaneous calculator
of pleasure and pain, will choose in the second case compared to the
first case. And the answer is self-evident. Given that the individual is
an instantaneous calculator of pleasure and pain, he would make a
different decision. If a potential particular pain is increased, choose
less; if a potential particular pleasure is increased, choose more.
In fact, the answer is so self-evident that it is not necessary to derive
the answer from any evidence. All the economists have to do is engage
22 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
the worker would prefer to be fired than to work at a lower wage, and
so the employer fires the worker “to the mutual satisfaction of both
employee and employer.”3
But how do we go from those isolated individual computers to talk
about policy proposals at the level of a society? Well, those neoclassi-
cal economists just combine those computers, assuming that society
is simply the sum of the isolated individuals within it. That’s what
society is for them, the place where those computers can interact. It
is where those isolated self-interested individuals come together for
their mutual benefit. And that’s all society is! No one made this point
better than former British prime minister Margaret Thatcher: “There’s
no such thing as society. There are individual men and women and
there are families.”
So that’s what happens in society according to the neoclassical
economist. We move from a single rational computer to two ratio-
nal computers, each attempting to maximize its self-interest, and they
engage in exchange; they can specialize in a certain kind of activity
and exchange. Just start everyone off with an “initial endowment” and
let the trading begin (quickly, before there are any questions about the
inequality of those initial endowments!). Each person gets what he or
she wants from the other by showing that it is to the other’s advantage.
As Adam Smith stated, “It is not from the benevolence of the butcher,
the brewer or the baker that we expect our dinner, but from regard
to their own interest.” So each party to an exchange benefits or there
wouldn’t be an exchange.
Further, as long as people are free to engage in any exchange, they
will be able to make the best possible exchange. For example, if a par-
ticular capitalist won’t pay a worker what she is worth, the worker can
go elsewhere. So the result is that in a free market everyone will get
what each deserves. John Bates Clark, a leading U.S. economist early
in the last century, said it all very explicitly. He began his book, The
Distribution of Wealth, by announcing:
You get what you deserve. So don’t complain. If you don’t get very
much, it’s because you are not worth very much. But it is the best you
can do.
The result of the combination of these rational, self-seeking indi-
viduals, thus, is that everyone benefits. This is what Adam Smith
called the “Invisible Hand.” It is the proposition that allows neoclas-
sical economists to move from the rational individual to the rational
society. It says, simply, that when an individual seeks his self-interest,
he promotes the public good: “He is in this, as in many other cases,
led by an invisible hand to promote an end which was no part of his
intention.” In other words, selfishness is good. Or, as Gordon Gecko
said in Oliver Stone’s classic movie Wall Street: “Greed is good.”
Where did the invisible hand come from? For Adam Smith and
many others at the time and after, the answer was clear: it came from
God. A familiar view in the eighteenth century was that God created
a world of economic harmony in which everyone benefits everyone
else by following his own self-interest. That particular religious faith
became economic faith, a secular religion, and a central part of that
secular faith is that as long as there is no interference by the state, all
will be well. As the U.S. economist John Kenneth Galbraith described
this view, “In a state of bliss, there is no place for a Ministry of Bliss.”5
Very simply, neoclassical economics is a justification of the exist-
ing society, with all of its inequality and injustice. Neoclassical
economics serves as a justification of capitalism. But not because it
talks about capitalism. Rather, that justification flows from its fun-
damental assumption that “if you can understand the smallest parts
of the system in isolation from one another, then all you have to do
is to put them together correctly in order to understand the whole.”6
Accordingly, since every unit acts rationally and maximizes self-
interest, so also does society, the sum of the many ones. As Frédéric
Bastiat, a nineteenth-century French economist, articulated this
premise, “That which is right with regard to one person is also right
26 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
with regard to society.”7 As long as all are free to choose, it is the best
of all possible worlds.
True, there is a problem with the way neoclassical theory moves
from the premise of a rational individual to the conclusion that the
society is rational. As Keynes pointed out in a famous example, there
is a significant fallacy in this inference. Any individual can decide
to increase his savings and improve his future position. However,
all individuals cannot. By lowering their consumption, they reduce
aggregate spending and that leads to lower production, lower employ-
ment, and lower income for all. This is called the “paradox of thrift,”
and it is a classic example of the “fallacy of composition,” the logical
flaw in saying that what is true for one is necessarily true for all.
When people act as if the properties of the individual parts can be
assumed to be the properties of the whole, the results can be quite dif-
ferent from their expectations. If one person stands up in a theater, he
can see better. But if all people stand up? If one country devalues its
currency, it can increase exports, reduce its imports and stimulate the
economy. But if all countries devalue their currency? What happens
if a country decides that it can be more competitive internationally
by destroying trade unions and driving down the wages of workers?
What happens if all competing countries do the same? One person
goes to university in order to improve his chance at getting a job, but
what if all people do? (Well, the answer is go to graduate school!) In
this case, one writer commented, the value of your education depends
not only on how much you have but also on how much the person
ahead of you in the job line has.
In short, we can’t just add up the individuals. Because they are
interdependent. And interdependence is pervasive in the real world,
as are its effects, which can be seen most obviously in the crisis of our
common home, the earth. In its theory, though, given that it begins
with each rational individual only taking into account the things he
has to pay for, neoclassical economics has some difficulty explaining
how the rational choices of individuals can lead to irrational social
outcomes. So, to the extent that it can, it sweeps results of interdepen-
dency offstage into a category called “externalities.” As it turns out,
ThE ATOMISM Of NEOCL ASSICAL ECONOMICS 27
A river and the drops in this river. The position of every drop,
its relation to the others; its connection with the others; the
direction of its movement; its speed; the line of the movement—
straight, curved, circular, etc.—upwards, downwards. The sum
of the movement. . . . There you have à peu près [approximately]
the picture of the world according to Hegel’s Logic—of course
minus God and the Absolute.7
If the whole is not the sum of its isolated parts, what is the truth of
the whole? Lenin’s response was: “The totality of all sides of the phe-
nomenon, of reality and their reciprocal relations—that is what truth
is composed of.”11 Reciprocal relations, however, are not passive rela-
tions; rather, reciprocal interaction is the process described by Levins
and Lewontin in which “elements recreate each other by interacting
and are recreated by the wholes of which they are parts.” A central
dialectical principle, accordingly, is that “change is a characteristic of
all systems and all aspects of all systems.”12
The truth of the whole, in short, is constant movement and change
as the result of the interaction of the elements it contains. Whereas
“non-dialectical thinkers in every discipline,” Ollman comments, “are
involved in a nonstop search for the ‘outside agitator,’ for something
ThE TrUTh IS ThE WhOLE 33
What all these gentlemen lack is dialectics. All they ever see is
cause on the one hand and effect on the other. But what they fail
to see is that this is an empty abstraction, that in the real world
such metaphysically polar opposites exist only in a crisis, that
instead the whole great process takes place solely and entirely
in the form of interplay. . . . So far as they are concerned, Hegel
might never have existed.16
the belief that “stasis is the normal state of affairs, and change must
be accounted for.” In contrast, “A dialectical view begins from the
opposite end: change is universal and much is happening to change
everything. Therefore, equilibrium and stasis are special situations
that have to be explained.”18
The first question posed, in short, is “in the face of constantly dis-
placing influences, how do things remain recognizably what they
are?” The general answer offered as explanation is “homeostasis,
the self-regulation observed in physiology, ecology, climatology, the
economy and indeed all systems that show any persistence.” While
such system-stability is often modeled mathematically by starting
from a set of variables that are prior entities with intrinsic proper-
ties, thus remaining “vulnerable to the reproach of being large-scale
reductionism,” Levins and Lewontin articulate a specific dialectical
answer that we must keep before us: “Our answer is that things are the
way they are because of the actions of opposing processes.”19
Think about equilibrium and stasis in this context. “Homeostasis
takes place,” Levins and Lewontin indicate, “through the actions of
positive and negative feedback loops. If an initial impact sets pro-
cesses in motion that diminish that initial impact, we refer to it as
negative feedback, whereas if the processes magnify the original
change the feedback is positive.”20As biologists, Levins and Lewontin
draw upon many examples from the natural sciences to illustrate
how negative feedback can negate initial changes, for example, how
pesticides may increase pest population by killing off pest predators
and how rapidly falling blood sugar produces anxiety that is relieved
by rising glucose. However, their example of how rising food prices
stimulate increased agricultural production, which tends in turn to
lower food prices, indicates that the existence of negative feedback
as a support for reproduction of an existing system is not limited to
the natural world.21 Negative feedback is present in all homeostasis
and self-regulation, and the dialectical task is to explain why there is
stability and equilibrium, how “things are the way they are because of
the temporary balance of opposing forces.”22
When the opposing forces contained within a system are balanced,
ThE TrUTh IS ThE WhOLE 35
But how can we know the whole? Levins and Lewontin argue that
we can’t. “Despite Hegel’s dictum that ‘the truth is the whole,’ ” they
explain, “we cannot study ‘the whole.’” Nevertheless, they insist,
Hegel’s assertion has clear practical value. For one, understanding
that the truth is the whole means that we should always try to extend
the boundaries of the questions we are considering. Further, it directs
us to admit that “after we have defined a system in the broadest terms
we can at the time, there is always something more out there that
might intrude to change our conclusions.”25 But given that the con-
cept of the whole is implicit in their declaration (and obvious from
their work), what does it mean to say that we cannot know the whole?
36 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
ONE-SIDED MARXISM
3
Marx’s Conceptualization of
Capitalism as an Organic System
What was the whole that Marx presented in Capital? Did that intel-
lectual construct truly represent the real concrete, or was there
“something else out there” that can infect our concept of the whole? To
understand capitalism and the relation of its parts, Marx introduced
the concept of capitalism as an organic system. This is a particular
conception of the whole. In capitalism as an organic system (“the
completed bourgeois system”), “every economic relation presupposes
every other in its bourgeois economic form, and everything posited is
thus also a presupposition; this is the case with every organic system.”1
In short, all the elements within this organic system are parts that
have been produced by the system; the completion of this system (“its
development to its totality”) “consists precisely in subordinating all
elements of society to itself, or in creating out of it the organs which
it still lacks. This is historically how it becomes a totality.” Thus, in
capitalism as an organic system, all the elements of capitalism have
been successfully subordinated within the system.
Characteristic of “every organic system” is that the premises of the
system are results that the system itself produces; this theme of the
reproduction of premises permeates Marx’s discussion in Capital.
44 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
For example, Marx pointed out that capital produces and reproduces
material products and social relations, which are themselves presup-
positions and premises of production. “Those conditions, like these
relations, are on the one hand the presuppositions of the capitalist
production process, on the other its results and creations; they are
both produced and reproduced by it.”2 Similarly, considering the
circuit of capital as a whole, Marx stressed that “all the premises of
the process appear as its result, as premises produced by the process
itself. Each moment appears as a point of departure, of transit, and
of return.” Indeed, all presuppositions, all preconditions, all premises
are themselves results: “In a constantly revolving orbit, every point is
simultaneously a starting point and a point of return.”3
Production and reproduction of premises implies incessant
renewal. As Marx opened his chapter on simple reproduction in
Volume I of Capital:
There you have the point that Marx wanted to stress—the neces-
sity to recognize that capitalism is such a system of reproduction.
“Capitalist production therefore reproduces in the course of its own
process the separation between labour-power and the conditions of
labour. It thereby reproduces and perpetuates the conditions under
which the worker is exploited.”5 In this conception, capitalism is an
organic system because it reproduces its premises—the capitalist and
the wage-laborer:
Premises to Be Reproduced
“On the one hand the capitalist, on the other the wage-labourer.” On
the one hand, the owner of means of production and money who
is focused upon the growth of his capital; on the other, the worker
who lacks those means of production and accordingly must sell her
ability to perform labor in order to purchase the means of subsis-
tence. These, we see, are the specific premises of capitalist production,
premises that must be reproduced in capitalism.
Capitalist and wage-laborer, however, presuppose other premises.
Logically presupposed are commodity and money. Before capital can
exploit wage-laborers in the process of production, it must be able
to purchase labor-power as a commodity with money. The circuit of
capital, in short, requires commodities, money, and labor-power as a
commodity. Similarly, for the circuit of wage-labor, the worker must
be able to take the money received as wages, and “it is the worker
himself who converts the money into whatever use-values he desires;
it is he who buys commodities as he wishes.”14 Thus, commodity
and money are necessary premises for the circuits of capital and
wage-labor.15
48 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
Capital as Premise
The reproduction of the side of capital requires two acts. Not only
must the capitalist be able to compel the production of capital through
the process of production, but he must be able to make that surplus
value real through the process of circulation. The first act flows from
the results of the worker’s sale of his labor-power to the capitalist:
“Firstly, the worker works under the control of the capitalist to whom
his labour belongs,” and “Secondly, the product is the property of the
capitalist and not that of the worker, its immediate producer.”20 As the
result of production within and through this particular set of prop-
erty rights, the capitalist is able to compel the performance of surplus
labor by workers and, as owner of the products of labor, that is, as the
residual claimant, is the beneficiary of the surplus value they latently
contain.
In the second act, however, reproduction of capital involves
more than the existence of commodities containing the products
of exploitation. In particular, “The capitalist must have contrived to
sell his commodities, and to reconvert into capital the greater part
of the money received from their sale.”21 In what Marx designated in
Volume 2 of Capital as the third stage of the circuit of capital (after
capital’s appearance as buyer and as producer of commodities con-
taining surplus value), “the capitalist returns to the market as seller.”
It is in Volume 2 that he explores what Volume 1 left “uninvestigated,”
the metamorphosis of capital through its different forms.22 Here, we
are shown the movement of capital from its commodity form to its
money form through the sale of commodities and through which
the surplus value latent in those commodities is made real (realized).
Further, we are able to follow the movement of this money-capital, as
it is used to purchase means of production and labor-power, arriving
back at capital in the sphere of production where, as productive capi-
tal, the capitalist exploitation of the worker occurs.
From money-capital to productive-capital to commodity-capital
and back to money-capital—there is the circuit of capital as a whole
50 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
Overproduction
one wonder at “the terror which the law of the declining rate of profits
inspires in the economists”?27
However, what does it mean to speak about an “important law of
political economy”? For a student of Hegel “law” has a specific mean-
ing—it is what we postulate as we search for regularities in the chaos
and noise of appearance. Thus, Hegel asserted: “Appearance and law
have one and the same content.”28 Empiricism is its source, and what
is missing from law as such is an understanding of inner connections
and necessity. Lenin grasped this in his reading of the Science of Logic:
“Law is the enduring (the persisting) in appearances.” The concept of
law is one of the stages of cognition, but every law is “narrow, incom-
plete, approximate.”29 And this was explicitly the point Marx made in
one of his earliest works. Political economy, he proposed, has its laws
but “it does not comprehend these laws”; we have to go beyond exter-
nal appearances “to grasp the intrinsic connection.”30
FROP was one such law, a law that the economists formulated but
did not understand. Contrary to their explanations, Marx explained
that the real source of the pattern observed by political economy was
that central to the development of capitalism is the substitution of
means of production for direct living labor, that is, the growth in the
technical composition of capital. As capitalism develops, past labor
(dead labor) plays an increasingly important role in production rel-
ative to present, living labor. But since the source of surplus value,
Marx argued, is the exploitation of living workers, the rise in the tech-
nical composition of capital brings with it a relative reduction in that
portion of capital that yields surplus value.
Thus, the change in the value-composition of capital (the rise in
the organic composition of capital) was Marx’s inner explanation for
the law that classical political economy had identified. Through his
critique of political economy, Marx revealed what was hidden from
the political economists and explicitly rejected their explanations for
their law. However, Marx proceeded then to stress that there were
other tendencies in capitalism as it developed that counteracted and
weakened the tendency for the rate of profit to fall. In particular, two
such tendencies were (1) increases in the rate of surplus value; and
CrISES AND NON-rEPrODUCTION 61
constant or (c) rises.35 Of all the cases he considered there, the only
one that corresponds to the FROP story introduced in chapter 13 of
Volume 3 of Capital is where productivity in the sector producing
material inputs is explicitly assumed constant. Accordingly, Marx
concluded from these exercises that it would appear “that the rate of
profit cannot fall unless” (a) the value of labor-power rises (Ricardo’s
assertion); or (b) “there is a rise in the value of constant capital in
relation to variable. And the latter would appear to be restricted to
cases where the productive power of labour does not rise equally and
simultaneously in all the branches of production which contribute to
produce the commodity.”36 Finally, you can see the same point twice
in Marx’s exposition of FROP in Capital 3, where he admitted that the
rate of profit might remain the same (a) if “the productivity of labour
cheapens all the elements of constant and variable capital to the same
extent”; and (b) “if the increase in productivity affected all the ingre-
dients of the commodity uniformly and simultaneously.”37
Equal productivity changes in all sectors? No falling rate of profit.
Indeed, Marx explicitly added that “the rate of profit could even rise,
if the rise in the rate of surplus value was coupled with a significant
reduction in the value of the elements of constant capital, and fixed
capital in particular.”38 Once we consider capitalism as a system,
FROP appears as a tendency whose realization depends upon the
relative strength of feedback loops associated with productivity
changes, feedback that is internal to the system rather than an exter-
nal counterforce. In this respect, Marx proposed with respect to
FROP that “the law operates therefore simply as a tendency, whose
effect is decisive only under particular circumstances and over long
periods.”39
What are those “particular circumstances” and why only over long
periods? Significantly, Marx proposed that it was only in “isolated
cases” that cheapening of “all the elements of constant and variable
capital to the same extent” prevents the rise in the organic composi-
tion of capital and the fall in the rate of profit. Rather than affecting “all
ingredients of the commodity uniformly and simultaneously,” Marx
stressed that in practice “the development of labour productivity is far
64 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
labour is also bound up with natural conditions, which are often less
favourable as productivity rises—as far as that depends on social con-
ditions.” Precisely because “we not only have the social productivity
of labour to consider but also its natural productivity which depends
on the natural conditions within which labour is carried on,” the feed-
back of productivity from increases in the technical composition of
capital in such cases (and thus also its effect as counter-tendency) is
weakened. 43
Was Marx, then, fleeing “from economics to seek refuge in organic
chemistry,” as he described Ricardo’s falling rate of profit theory?44
Hardly. Whereas Ricardo’s argument was based upon diminish-
ing productivity and a fall in the rate of surplus value, for Marx the
tendency of the rate of profit to fall was associated with rising pro-
ductivity and a rising rate of surplus value. Further, whereas Ricardo
“thinks that agriculture must become unproductive absolutely,”
for Marx the fall in the rate of profit would occur not, for example,
because “the yield of cotton cultivation had declined, but only that it
had not become more productive in the same ratio as cotton manufac-
turing. Therefore only a relative reduction in its productivity, despite
the absolute increase in it.”
Such a relative decline due to “the natural conditions within which
labour is carried on,” Marx proposed, only demonstrates “that indus-
try and agriculture do not develop to the same degree in bourgeois
production. If they do not do this, that alone is sufficient to explain
the decline in the rate of profit.”45 Is this, then, sufficient to explain
the ultimate and inevitable non-reproduction of capitalism? Perhaps.
“Over long periods,” this relative lag in productivity may mean that
the falling rate of profit will have a “decisive” effect.
Well before this lonely last hour, however, Marx stressed that natu-
ral conditions affect the course of capitalist development. “Plant and
animal products, whose growth and production are subject to cer-
tain organic laws involving naturally determined periods of time,
cannot suddenly be increased in the same degree as, say, machines
and other fixed capital, coal, ore, etc.” Thus, it is “indeed unavoidable
when capitalist production is fully developed, that the production
66 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
objects, by which they are given new use values. The exploration
of the earth in all directions, to discover new things of use as well
as new useful qualities of the old; such as new qualities of them as
raw materials etc; the development of the natural sciences, hence,
to their highest point . . . is likewise a condition of production
founded on capital.52
This gives rise to the delusion that the “laws” of economics can
lead the way out of a crisis just as they lead into it. Whereas
what happened in reality was that—because of the passivity of
the proletariat—the capitalist class was in a position to break the
deadlock and start the machine going again.55
Theses, divides “society into two parts, one part of which is superior
to society.” Characteristic of Marx’s revolutionary materialism, in
contrast, was the key link of human development and practice: “The
coincidence of the changing of circumstances and of human activity
or self-change can be conceived and rationally understood only as
revolutionary practice.”
All other things equal, the people produced within particular rela-
tions of production tend to be premises for the reproduction of those
relations. As we saw, the second products of capital are people who
look upon the requirements of capital as “self-evident natural laws,”
common sense. However, work under capital is not the only relation
in which those workers produce themselves. The key link of human
development and practice points to another product within capital-
ism: through their struggles, workers change themselves and make
themselves fit to create a new world. Thus, Marx’s message to work-
ers in 1850 was that “you will have to go through 15, 20, 50 years of
civil wars and national struggles not only to bring about a change in
society but also to change yourselves, and prepare yourselves for the
exercise of political power.”25 Over two decades later (after the defeat
of the Paris Commune), he continued to stress the inseparability of
human activity and self-change: the working class knows that “they
will have to pass through long struggles, through a series of historic
processes, transforming circumstances and men.”26
Struggle, in short, is a process of production—one in which work-
ers produce themselves differently. Although capitalist relations of
production determine the working class as a class-in-itself, Marx in
The Poverty of Philosophy explained that through its struggles, “this
mass becomes united, and constitutes itself as a class for itself.”27
By informing themselves about their own interests and acting in
common, workers can emerge (as The German Ideology predicted)
“as a revolutionary, united mass.”28 And this is something only they
can do. Precisely because revolutionary practice is the way that work-
ers transform themselves, Marx criticized sects (which possess all the
answers in their pockets to the suffering of the masses): “Here [refer-
ring to Germany], where the worker is regulated bureaucratically
from childhood onwards, where he believes in authority, in those set
over him, the main thing is to teach him to walk by himself.”29
No one has described the intrinsic link between their activity and
their self-change better than Engels. Even though they had lost the
NEvEr fOrgET ThE SECOND PArT 81
battle over the Ten Hours Bill, he argued that workers changed sig-
nificantly in the course of that struggle:
Consider the value of the commodity that the worker sells to the
capitalist. What the worker sells, Marx argued in Capital, is his
labor-power (rather than labor), and (following in the footsteps
of classical political economy), its value is “determined, as in the
case of every other commodity, by the labour-time necessary for
the production, and consequently also the reproduction, of this
specific article.”3 Accordingly, “as in the case of every other com-
modity,” the value of this commodity will fall with reductions in
the labor-time necessary for its production, that is, with increases
in productivity.
There is, in short, symmetry in the treatment of labor-power and
other commodities, a symmetry in which Marx followed Ricardo,
whom he credited as the first to formulate accurately relations (laws)
that Marx elaborated in Capital.4 Ricardo expressed this symmetry in
his Principles of Political Economy as follows:
“The cynical Ricardo,” Marx called him in 1844. But he was not
commenting upon a personal characteristic of Ricardo; rather,
Ricardo’s teaching was the perspective of “English political economy,
i.e. the scientific reflection of English economic conditions.”6 That
political economy, Marx commented, viewed “man as worker, as a
commodity” and was indifferent to the production of man as “a men-
tally and physically dehumanised being.” Indeed, its only interest in
workers was with respect to their direct relation to capital.7 But the
cynicism of political economy, Marx explained in his Poverty of
Philosophy, was just a statement of “the facts” in capitalism. Quoting
the above passage from Ricardo, Marx commented:
By the time Marx wrote Capital, he had come to understand that there
was a difference between this classical premise of a fixed set of neces-
sities and “the facts.” Certainly, he accepted the classical premise for
his presentation of the concept of relative surplus value in chapter 12
of Volume 1. However, outside of this theoretical chapter, Marx else-
where commented in Capital that workers are able to expand their
consumption of means of subsistence under the appropriate condi-
tions. The fixed character of workers’ needs, he indicated in Volume
3, “is mere illusion. If means of subsistence were cheaper or money-
wages higher, the workers would buy more of them.”15 Similarly, in
Volume 2, he explained that with rising real wages “the demand of the
workers for necessary means of subsistence will grow. Their demand
for luxury articles will increase to a smaller degree, or else a demand
will arise for articles that previously did not enter the area of their
consumption.”16 Further, he pointed out in Volume 1 that, with higher
wages, workers “can extend the circle of their enjoyments, make addi-
tions to their consumption fund of clothes, furniture, etc., and lay by
a small reserve fund of money.”17
We need, accordingly, to distinguish between the theoretical expo-
sition of relative surplus value and passing observations made in
ThE BUrDEN Of CL ASSICAL POLITICAL ECONOMY 89
alongside and interacted with it. Money, Marx revealed, was essential
for the “metamorphosis of commodities,” the movement from one
commodity in the hands of its owner via the medium of money to a
second commodity that could be a use-value for the owner of the first.
Without stressing the distinct existence and centrality of money, like
the classical political economists we do not understand the inherent
possibility of crisis or the nature of capital as a social relation.
But there is more. The place of money in Marx’s analysis points
to the error in treating the production of hats and men symmetri-
cally. Money doesn’t matter for the production of hats, a vertically
integrated process of production extending from primary products,
which contingently may be interrupted by the equivalent exchange of
intermediary inputs, to the completed use-value. But we cannot talk
about the production and reproduction of the wage-laborer without
incorporating the place of money.
Rather than existing solely within a sphere of production, the pro-
duction of labor-power involves a complex sequence encompassing
(a) the moment of production of articles of consumption; (b) the
payment of money-wages to the worker; (c) a moment of circula-
tion in which the worker exchanges his or her money for articles of
consumption; (d) a second moment of production in which those
use-values (as well as concrete, uncounted labor) are consumed in
order to prepare labor-power for exchange; and (e) the sale of labor-
power to the capitalist.27 By treating the two processes symmetrically,
only the first of these moments in the production of labor-power is
considered. In classical political economy, the cost of production of
the consumption bundle leapfrogs over several moments to become
the cost of production of the worker (leaving the latter a mere foot-
note to the former).
In contrast, as we have seen, Marx understood the importance of
money with respect to workers. The suggestion of a fixed standard of
necessity, he insisted, is “mere illusion. If means of subsistence were
cheaper or money-wages higher, the workers would buy more of
them.”28 Again, the higher money-wages are relative to money-prices,
the more that workers “can extend the circle of their enjoyments,
94 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
now open, now hidden “struggle between collective capital and col-
lective labour, i.e. the class of capitalists, and collective labour, i.e. the
working class.”2
Without classical political economy’s stifling assumption, we
would recognize that capital faces a working class that develops its
capacity and organization through its struggles, a working class that
is transforming social relations among its members. And that raises
the question as to whether the absence of that particular part infects
our theoretical conception of the whole.
Insofar as workers are atomized and compete, they act in the interest
of capital. Accordingly, Marx concluded that “the competition among
workers is only another form of the competition among capitals.”12
Divide, Divide
“is fully aware of.” And, as long as that is a secret, it means you do not
understand the enemy.
If you do not understand the centrality of capital’s need to sepa-
rate workers, you will not grasp that such characteristics as racism,
patriarchy, and xenophobia do not drop from the sky, and you will
suggest that we obscure relations of class exploitation by emphasizing
these. On the contrary, these characteristics are produced and repro-
duced within a capitalism that must divide the working class if it is to
be reproduced. Silence about “the secret by which the capitalist class
maintains its power” disarms the working class and, indeed, betrays
it. Rejecting the tendency of some Marxists to treat race and gender
oppression as outside the logic of capital, David Roediger correctly
argues that “Marx left the production of difference untheorized in a
way that we cannot afford to.”28
Was the theoretical silence about capital’s absolute necessity to
divide workers a matter of incompleteness rather than a serious flaw
of Capital? Recall the point from Levins and Lewontin: “Seizing upon
one side of a dichotomous pair or a contradiction as if it were the
whole thing,” can infect our concept of the whole with “one-sided-
ness.”29 When an element is excluded from our concept of the whole,
they predicted, it “may take its revenge in leading us astray.”30 This is
precisely what occurred.
If there is a way to divide the working class, capital will find it and
use it. Changes in the organization of production and in the tech-
nical composition of capital introduced by capital must be seen in
this light.
When capital initiates such changes in the organization of produc-
tion, it does so on the premise that it will be the beneficiary, either
because of the existing atomism of the working class or the expec-
tation that the change will have that effect.
If the benefits of productivity increases are to be captured by an
organized working class, capital has no interest in developing pro-
ductive forces. The expanded reproduction of capital has as its
premise the separation of the working class.
The separation of the working class is also the premise of the oper-
ation of the blind laws of supply and demand. Marx’s statement that
“the movement of the law of supply and demand of labour” as the
CAPITAL'S NEED TO SEPArATE WOrkErS 107
CONTESTED
REPRODUCTION
8
Beyond Atomism
The Tragedy of Atomism
premise is that the market yields fair results; as for the former case,
the presumed unfairness flows from the violation of the implicit con-
tract in a “reference transaction” that occurred under previous (and
fair) market conditions.
Of course, the limited information these atomistic subjects are pro-
vided surely reflects their particular judgments as to fairness. If, for
instance, they were informed that workers were super-exploited (in
the reference transaction) as the result of racism and sexism, would
they still conclude that it is fair for the employer to lower wages if his
raw material costs rise? As Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler admit,
justice is not to be confused with this conception of fairness: “The
reference transaction provides a basis for fairness judgments because
it is normal, not necessarily because it is just” and “Terms of exchange
that are initially seen as unfair may in time acquire the status of a
reference transaction.”14 As in the “moral economy” examples cited
above, the concept of fairness here involves looking backward. In
short, super-exploitation may come in time to be viewed as “self-evi-
dent natural laws.”
Although the particular judgments of these survey respondents
certainly may be questioned, a concept of fairness clearly appears to
be part of their preference function. For Kahneman, Knetsch, and
Thaler, incorporation of fairness enriches the standard model and
helps to explain what appear to be anomalies for the model of homo
economicus.15 But does it challenge the standard neoclassical model?
Fairness simply becomes here an additional element in the deter-
mination of the optimal position of atomistic individuals. A more
realistic homo economicus that permits better predictions, perhaps,
but still the same model.
Yet some behavioral economics studies point in a quite differ-
ent direction, alerting us to contradictions between the self-interest
characteristic of homo economicus and matters of fairness, morals, or
what economist Sam Bowles calls “social preferences.” In his book The
Moral Economy Bowles defines social preferences as encompassing
“motives such as altruism, reciprocity, intrinsic pleasure in helping
others, aversion to inequity, ethical commitment, and other motives
BEYOND ATOMISM 117
that induce people to help others more than is consistent with maxi-
mizing their own wealth or material payoff.”16 Not only do many
studies demonstrate that self-interest and social preferences coex-
ist, but they also reveal particular characteristics of their interaction.
Bowles illustrates this phenomenon at the outset of his book:
other increases.”19 Thus, the fine for tardiness at the childcare center
“appears to have undermined the parents’ sense of ethical obligation
to avoid inconveniencing the teachers, leading them to think of late-
ness as just another commodity they could purchase,” and the fines
placed on the Boston firemen went counter to their pride in serving
the public.20
The second takeaway from Bowles’s review of the various studies
demonstrates the importance of the second product. Our emphasis
upon the second product predicts that acting in response to material
incentives tends to produce a different person than one who acts in
accordance with social preferences. And that is precisely the lesson
stressed by Bowles. Considering the long-term effects of material
incentives, Bowles argues that “the economy is a great teacher, and its
lessons are neither fleeting nor confined within its boundaries.” Material
incentives, he proposes, may “affect the long-term learning process
whose results persist over decades, even entire lifetimes.” Indeed, “the
incentive alters the long term, not easily reversed preference-learning
process.” Very simply, “economies structured by differing incentives
are likely to produce people with differing preferences,” or, as Bowles
declares in a subhead, “The Economy Produces People.”21
What kinds of people are produced by the use of material incen-
tives? Exactly what you would expect as the result of what Bowles
calls “the corrosive effect of markets and incentives on social prefer-
ences.”22 Not only do incentives “crowd out” social preferences in the
short run, but they also “constitute part of a learning environment
in which preferences are durably modified.”23 More than mere sub-
stitutes for social preferences, material incentives shape people. As a
result, the people produced by markets and incentives are substitutes
for people characterized by motives such as altruism, opposition to
inequity, and intrinsic pleasure in helping others. How Bowles feels
about this is clear from the subtitle of his book: Why Good Incentives
Are No Substitute for Good Citizens.
Nevertheless, despite his own obvious social preferences, Bowles
sees the necessity to utilize material incentives in the hope of achiev-
ing desirable goals. Perhaps because of his understanding of how
BEYOND ATOMISM 119
system. Once capital has developed upon its own foundation (once “it
is itself presupposed, and proceeds from itself to create the conditions
of its maintenance and growth”), it produces its own premises in their
“bourgeois economic form.”29 Commodities, money, markets, labor-
power as a commodity, and the separation of workers are produced
and reproduced as are the seemingly independent self-seekers who
respond to the compulsion of the market, which is “external to the
individuals and independent of them.” That apparent external com-
pulsion, which ensures the reproduction of capitalism as an organic
system, is precisely why Marx stressed the importance of the “sacred”
law of supply and demand in maintaining the despotism of capital
and why he identified the political economy of capital as grounded in
“the blind rule of the supply and demand laws.”
Let us consider, on the other hand, the system that produces indi-
viduals who collectively are guided by “motives such as altruism,
reciprocity, intrinsic pleasure in helping others, aversion to inequity,
ethical commitment, and other motives that induce people to help
others.” In contrast to a concept of fairness that rests upon the market
and only rejects as unfair those violations of existing norms developed
as the result of the interactions of atomistic actors, focus upon social
preferences implies the view that selfishness, inequality, and insensi-
tivity to the needs of others are unfair and unjust behavior for people
within society. We are pointing here to an alternative organic system
in which social preferences are common sense. As Ostrom indicated,
in a system based explicitly upon the association of people, people
take pride in being viewed “as reliable members of the community.”
Whether labeled the solidarian society, the solidarity economy, the
communal society, or communism, the starting point of this system
is community, the recognition of the needs of others within society.30
Begin with communality, Marx proposed, and “instead of a divi-
sion of labour . . . there would take place an organization of labour.”
There, the producers, “working with the means of production held
in common,“ combine their capacities “in full self-awareness as one
single social labour force.”31 In this system, Marx explained in the
Grundrisse, “communal production, communality, is presupposed as
BEYOND ATOMISM 121
social preferences are substitutes, that they tend to “crowd out” each
other and that the people produced by each are substitutes. Given his
chosen audience, he seeks to convince the wise legislator to search for
the mechanism that will produce the most salutary combination of
the two motives. But that does not abolish the contradictions between
the two systems.
Capital, we know, is constantly attempting to separate producers in
order to weaken them. It gains always by turning workers against each
other and to see each other as competitors, as usurpers, as threats, as
enemies. It does whatever it can to foster atomism and to turn every-
thing into market relations; capital’s goal in this respect is complete
commodification, what Marx described as a “time when everything,
moral or physical, having become a marketable value, is brought to
the market,” a time of “universal venality.”37 Capital, in short, con-
stantly drives to crowd out all traces of the system of community. To
think that a wise mechanism design is sufficient to withstand this
impulse is utopianism.
Material incentive versus social preferences, atomism versus com-
munity, separation versus solidarity, homo economicus versus homo
solidaricus, the political economy of capital versus the political
economy of the working class—these are sides of the class struggle
within existing capitalism.38 Rather than hoping for “a wise combina-
tion” of each, the wise revolutionary understands that it is essential to
struggle by all means possible to defeat capitalism, to decommodify
everything, to build the system of community where producers act
in common. And, simultaneously in that process, how they produce
themselves as the working class the system of community needs.
9
and it was capitalist employers who were now the residual claimants
of production, producers struggled to extract themselves from wage-
labor. Indeed, as Marx pointed out, “centuries are required before the
‘free’ worker . . . makes a voluntary agreement” to sell “the whole of
his active life, his capacity for labour in return for the price of his cus-
tomary means of subsistence.”23 Accordingly, as noted earlier, in “the
historical genesis of capitalist production,” accumulation of capital
drove up money-wages; where possible, this allowed workers to meet
their monetary requirements and to spend more time on other activ-
ity. Negative feedback following the growth of capital at such times
tended to generate the non-reproduction of the wage-labor relation.24
And that is precisely why capital drew upon the state through “bloody
discipline,” “police methods,” and “state compulsion” to ensure the
submission of workers to the needs of capital.25
Though this negative feedback that tended to check the reproduc-
tion of capitalism was present in the Old World, nowhere was it more
obvious than in the New World, the “colonies.” There, the high wages
generated by the accumulation of capital provided an opportunity
for workers to save in order to extract themselves from wage labor.
As a result, Marx explained, “Today’s wage-labourer is tomorrow’s
independent peasant or artisan, working for himself.” In short, in the
colonies the relative supply and demand for workers meant that the
relationship of wage labor was not automatically reproduced: where
“the worker receives more than is required for the reproduction of his
labour capacity and very soon becomes a peasant farming indepen-
dently, etc., the original relation is not constantly reproduced.”26 And
that meant that the reproduction of capital was threatened because the
reproduction of the worker as wage laborer “is the absolutely neces-
sary condition for capitalist production.”27 The answer to this problem,
accordingly, was state legislation to impose a price upon land (as pre-
scribed by E. G. Wakefield, the English theorist of colonization). Here
was “the secret discovered in the New World by the political economy
of the Old World”—capitalism has as its “fundamental condition the
annihilation of that private property which rests on the labour of the
individual himself; in other words, the expropriation of the worker.”28
BETWEEN OrgANIC SYSTEMS 131
from the old society. At the very outset of his Critique, he pointed
to two immediate changes that occur in the new society and that
develop further “in proportion as the new society develops.” Those
two changes are introduced in his discussion of deductions from the
total product of labor, deductions to be made before there is to be
any consideration of distribution of the residual among individuals.
One deduction concerns production “intended for the common sat-
isfaction of needs.” “From the outset,” Marx insisted, “this part grows
considerably in comparison with present-day society, and it grows in
proportion as the new society develops.”
So, from the outset, a new principle of distribution begins to crowd
out the old. There is increased production for the commons and a
diminishing residual for distribution in accordance with contribu-
tion. “What the producer is deprived of in his capacity as a private
individual benefits him directly or indirectly in his capacity as a
member of society.” As the new society develops, we no longer regard
the producers one-sidedly, that is, “only as workers and nothing more
is seen in them, everything else being ignored.” Rather, the producers
are understood as a whole, as members of society.
There are other deductions from the total social product, and
these include “replacement of means of production used up” and a
“portion for expansion of production.” Those deductions are “an eco-
nomic necessity and their magnitude is to be determined according
to available means and forces.” But there was one other deduction
particularly relevant to building the new society upon its own founda-
tions, and that concerns the state—“the general costs of administration
not belonging to production.” That deduction would fall: “This part
will, from the outset, be very considerably restricted in comparison
with present-day society and it diminishes in proportion as the new
society develops.”
But why the “very considerably restricted” deduction for the state
from the outset? Observation of subsequent socialist experiments
would suggest precisely the opposite course, namely, growing bureau-
cracy and petty tutelage over all aspects of the society! For Marx,
however, the point was self-evident. As he had learned from the
hOW TO fIND A PATh TO COMMUNITY 145
Paris Commune four years earlier, from the very outset, state func-
tions are to be “wrested from an authority usurping pre-eminence
over society itself and restored to the responsible agents of society.”12
If the Commune had succeeded, Marx proposed, in place of the old
centralized government, “all France would have been organized into
self-working and self-governing communes.” And the result would
be “state functions reduced to a few functions for general national
purposes.”13 In the words of the Critique, the state would be converted
more and more “from an organ superimposed upon society into one
completely subordinate to it.”
Underlying his stress upon a “very considerably restricted” state,
Marx obviously had in mind a different kind of state, one that involved
new organs, those self-working and self-governing communes. As the
new system developed, gone would be another defect—the old state
inherited from capitalism with its “systematic and hierarchic divi-
sion of labour” and where state administration and governing are
treated as “mysteries, transcendent functions only to be trusted to
the hands of a trained caste—state parasites, richly paid sycophants
and sinecurists.”14 The new state from below, “the political form at last
discovered under which to work out the economical emancipation
of Labour,” immediately makes despotic inroads and increasingly
crowds out the old state as a measure of the development of the new
society.15
Following Marx in writing history backwards from communism,
we can identify what has to happen for the future to become what it
must. As the new system develops, it must increasingly produce its
own premises. By producing consciously for common needs and pur-
poses and directing society through self-working and self-governing
communes, the associated producers transform society and transform
themselves. They produce communist society as it has developed on
its own foundations.
But what if the system that emerges from capitalism, infected “in
every respect, economically, morally, and intellectually,” does not
remove the defects it has inherited? If the system were dynamically
stable such that any initial deviations nevertheless would converge,
146 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
There are two hierarchical relations here. One is the internal rela-
tion within the party. “Democratic centralism,” in principle, ensures
that there is the greatest possible democracy in arriving at decisions
and the greatest possible centralization and discipline in executing
those decisions. The two aspects, democracy and discipline, may vary
in their weight in practice: democracy is often episodic, confined to
party congresses and collective decision-making occasions, whereas
discipline is meant to be part of daily life. The potential for imbalance
148 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
is very high: those toward the top in the hierarchy may want confi-
dence that their subordinates will carry out party policy faithfully; in
this respect, rather than the bottom selecting the top, as democratic
centralism would suggest, the top selects the bottom.21 Implicit in the
vanguard party are the acceptance of discipline and the reluctance to
engage in “individualistic behavior,” characteristics of internal party
life within “real socialism.”22
The other hierarchical relation is that between the party and soci-
ety. The party takes on the role of educator to pupil, leader to the led,
conductor to the conducted. From this perspective, social movements
are considered below the party as such and are viewed as bodies from
which to recruit potential party cadres and to subordinate to the party
completely, as occurs especially in “real socialism.” The presumed
superiority of the party, following from its “banked knowledge” in the
form of “Marxism-Leninism,” gives it the license to work to change
circumstances for people, irrespective of Marx’s comment that such a
doctrine divides “society into two parts, one part of which is superior
to society.”
Identification of the roots of “real socialism” with the vanguard
party is not at all a critique of the role of any party in providing
leadership to go beyond capitalism and to build the system of com-
munity. Consider a party instead that stresses the process by which
people transform themselves and develop their capacities. Envision
a party that rejects a focus upon delivering “banked knowledge” to
the underlying population, one that rejects the conception, described
by Paulo Freire, in which “knowledge is a gift bestowed by those who
consider themselves knowledgeable upon those who they consider to
know nothing.”23
In contrast to the vanguard party, a party focused upon the cen-
trality of the concept of revolutionary practice, that simultaneous
changing of circumstance and self-change, is not likely to converge at
“real socialism.” As Leontiev argued, “A small, hardly perceptible mis-
take in the description of the original base-year position of an unstable
dynamic system is bound to bring about a major error in the predic-
tion, that is, explanation of its later states.” The difference between the
hOW TO fIND A PATh TO COMMUNITY 149
classic vanguard party and a party that is guided by the concept of the
second product, though, is hardly small and imperceptible.
11
If you don’t know where you want to go, no path will take you there.
But we do know where we want to go. We want a society in which the
relation between its members is guided by “motives such as altruism,
reciprocity, intrinsic pleasure in helping others, aversion to inequity,
ethical commitment, and other motives that induce people to help
others.” In communal society, the self-evident natural law for homo
solidaricus would be that “the free development of each is the con-
dition for the free development of all.”1 And that means we want a
society based upon protagonism in all aspects of life and solidar-
ity. In this society characterized by “free individuality, based on the
universal development of individuals and on their subordination of
their communal, social productivity as their social wealth,” the pro-
ducers combine their capacities “in full self-awareness as one single
social labour force” and “all the springs of cooperative wealth flow
more abundantly.”
Communal society, like all organic systems, produces its own premises.
As discussed in chapter 8, communal society has as its premise the end
TAkINg A PATh TO COMMUNITY 151
But what has to happen in the present for the future to become what
it must? From the vantage point of community, we ask the second
question of Levins and Lewontin, “How did things get the way they
are?”8 How were the premises of community constructed? For Levins
and Lewontin, “Things are the way they are because they got that way,
and not because they have to be that way, or always were that way, or
because it’s the only way to be.”
As we have seen, the movement from capitalism to community is
not inevitable. True, capitalism constantly generates crises, but these
contain within themselves self-correcting tendencies, including the
TAkINg A PATh TO COMMUNITY 153
are not only the product of capital. Once engaged in struggle, work-
ers transform circumstances and themselves. And they do so through
all their struggles because they are not defined solely by their direct
relation to capital but are the ensemble of all their social relations.10
Yet the changes in people as the result of their various struggles
do not automatically make them fit for communality. In the process
of contested reproduction, there is interaction and interpenetration.
Accordingly, the path to community cannot be “pure” but inevitably is
“in every respect, economically, morally, and intellectually” infected
by the old society, a whole in which the side of capital deforms the
side of community. What is the result of that infection?
Every collective struggle of people for their common needs, how-
ever it may transform them, occurs in the context of the atomism
and separation characteristic of capitalism. Because those engaged in
struggle have a dual nature, both as people transforming themselves
through their practice and as hosts of the second product of capital,
their separation does not miraculously disappear. Accordingly, instead
of a leap from individual atomism to community, the immediate result
of their activity may be the development of collective atomism, a pro-
cess in which differences within are reduced while differences outside
the group are increased. As noted earlier, Engels pointed out that sepa-
ration in different units “restricts the workers to seeing their interest
in that of their employers, thus making every single section of workers
into an auxiliary army for the class employing them.”11
This tendency to view competitors as the Other was present in the
market-self-managed enterprises of Yugoslavia. Solidarity among
members of the collective was present because of their common
interest in maximizing income per worker; however, there was soli-
darity neither with the workers of other enterprises, with which they
competed or bargained, nor with the members of society as a whole.
Loyalty to their own particular enterprise was demonstrated when 70
percent of self-managing agreements between enterprises (developed
because the Yugoslav state was attempting to replace the anarchy of
market forces with a medium-term process of planning from below)
were abandoned unilaterally when inflation altered relative prices.
156 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
Thus the four critical questions are: how to link struggles of nega-
tion to community, how to link prefigurative activities to struggles
of negation, how to link separate struggles, and how to fight the ten-
dency for hierarchy. They all pose the same problem: in contested
reproduction between capitalism and community, there is no spon-
taneous path to community. To advance along that path, a political
instrument is essential.
12
within the whole and are the product of interpenetration, in this con-
tested reproduction the working class does not stand outside capital
but is contained within it.
What are the implications of understanding the working class
within this whole as the product of the interpenetration of capital?
As we saw in the preceding chapter, the struggle of the working class
against capital and for community is also a struggle within the work-
ing class against capital—a struggle versus atomism and separation,
a struggle for solidarity and equality, a struggle against hierarchy and
domination.
Against Spontaneity
To believe that the battle against capitalism and for community will
succeed without a conscious struggle against inherent tendencies
produced by capitalism is a comforting fairy tale. The hegemony
of capital is not an accident nor is it the result of an inherited cul-
ture. Rather, the tendency within the working class to accept the
rules of life under capitalism is reproduced spontaneously every day.
Accordingly, to build the society of community we are left with the
challenges with which we ended the last chapter: the need to link
struggles of negation to community, to link prefigurative activities
to struggles of negation, to link separate struggles, and to fight the
tendency for hierarchy. Once we understand the interpenetration
characteristic of contested reproduction, the necessity for the politi-
cal instrument to combat spontaneity is obvious.
That has always been the tenet of the vanguard party. But you do
not need to be a self-described Marxist-Leninist to insist upon the
need for a political instrument to struggle to replace capitalism with
community.1 Decrying “the myth of the purely spontaneous revolu-
tion,” Murray Bookchin, a self-described ex-anarchist, insisted that a
revolutionary Left “must resolutely confront the problem of organi-
zation.” Can we conceive, he asks, of “a popular movement gaining
power without an agency that can provide it with guidance?” On
the contrary, what is required is the “creation and maintenance of
164 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
Revolutionary Practice
Recall the dialectical relation of acts and capacities in which acts create
capacities, capacities enable acts. Capacity, Lucien Sève indicated, is
“the ensemble of actual potentialities, innate or acquired, to carry out
any act whatever and whatever its level.”7 Accordingly, by stressing
a “political instrument that encourages popular protagonism in the
most varied social and political milieus in the country,” Harnecker
communicates that, by struggling with respect to all aspects of its
social relations, the working class develops the capacities that will
permit it to defeat capital.
We have already seen how direct struggles against the capital rela-
tion help the working class to transform itself. But revolutionary
practice is not limited to this sphere nor is the role of the political
instrument. The struggles against racism and patriarchy, for example,
transform people so they can enter into all their relations with this
new potentiality. They change circumstances—for example, through
victories in battles—and simultaneously invest in the development of
their capacities.
Once we start from the centrality of revolutionary practice, we
understand that organizational forms matter. The large mass meeting
inspires and communicates a sense of strength. In itself, however, it
does not build capacity. Rather, as Harnecker argued, you need spaces
small enough both to facilitate “the protagonism of those attending by
making them feel comfortable and encouraging them to speak freely”
and also to allow them to engage in the multiplicity of acts that can
build their capacities.8 You need, in short, to create spaces that allow
people to take those steps through which they transform themselves.
Yet small spaces for protagonism are not the goal; nor is it a con-
federation of freely associated communities that for anarchists is the
alternative to a “state.” Rather, when you “decentralize all that you can
decentralize,” the principle that Harnecker identifies as “subsidiarity,”
the central point is to build the capacities of people.9 As Harnecker and
economist José Bartolomé say in Planning from Below, decentralized
166 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
Traditional Models
walk on two legs, both to capture the existing state in order to reverse
policies supportive of capital and also to build and nurture the ele-
ments of a new socialist state based upon self-government from
below.18
But the desire for electoral success based upon the existing correla-
tion of forces proved too strong. Syriza’s electoral program presented
in September 2014 contained no pledge to cancel the memoranda,
no call for public ownership of the banks, and, in place of any
anti-capitalist (let alone socialist) measures, proposed a National
Reconstruction Plan, a Keynesian program of public investment and
tax reduction for the middle class. Further, there was little sign of the
earlier determination to use the state to foster development of the
cells of a new state, nothing that challenged capital as the demand
for workers’ councils and workers’ control would have. Everything
in the electoral program was consistent with support for capital. The
proposal contained in that program was to walk on two legs along the
road to social democracy.
As so often, going down the road to social democracy led not
to democratic socialism but to the reinforcement of capitalism.
Following its successful election, Syriza proceeded from initial
retreats in post-electoral negotiations with finance capital to succes-
sive surrenders to ultimate rout and capitulation. Every illusion in
social democracy should have been dispelled by the Syriza govern-
ment’s refusal to accept the verdict of the population when it rejected
the popular referendum in July 2015 against austerity proposals.
The debacle of Syriza did not come as a surprise in Greece to those
who were always suspicious of its social democracy. But not only
them. For those who view the crisis as not one of neoliberalism but
rather as that of the capitalist economy as such, the accommoda-
tions of social democracy everywhere ultimately support capitalism.
In this alternative view of the conjuncture, capitalism has entered
(or is on the threshold of) an economic crisis that will demonstrate
to all that the economic system is no longer viable and must be
replaced. Rather than periodic crises of overaccumulation and of the
underproduction of surplus value (both considered in chapter 4),
170 BETWEEN CAPITALISM AND COMMUNITY
capitalism now faces the “Big One,” the apocalypse promised accord-
ing to this reading of Capital.
Accordingly, from this perspective, the political instrument
required is a disciplined and centralized organization that can lead
the working class through the ensuing chaos produced by the coming
crisis. That is the logic underlying the classical vanguard party dis-
cussed in chapter 10. As I argued in The Contradictions of “Real
Socialism, given its understanding of the need for a political instru-
ment to defeat the enemies of the working class in order to replace
capitalism with socialism, this perspective insists upon “a disciplined,
centralized and united revolutionary party—our party.”19 To prepare
the vanguard party is thus the principal task of organization.
Two problems with this perspective, however, were identified in
earlier chapters. One, discussed in chapter 4, is that its certainty about
the existing or pending ultimate crisis forgets that capital is not pas-
sive and continually searches for means to go beyond all barriers to its
growth, barriers manifested in falling profit rates. Those who empha-
size the coming capitalist crisis forget the negative feedback in the
system that reverses extended crises. Indeed, alternating phases of
boom tend to be seen as mere aberrations, epiphenomena that pave
the way for ever-greater future collapses. Theory rules, impervious to
all developments that may challenge it.
The second problem, as we have stressed, is the working class
this theory presumes. Rather than recognizing that capitalism
tends to produce a working class that looks upon capital’s require-
ments as “self-evident natural laws,” the militance of their idealized
working class needs merely a kiss at the appropriate time to awaken
to its appointed tasks. However, in the absence of a working class
that has developed its capacities through its protagonism, the exist-
ing working class is the product of capital. What Lukàcs called the
immaturity of the working class ensures that capitalist crises will
be resolved through capital’s initiatives. Unfortunately, rather than
addressing this problem, those with this perspective often look
upon social movements as fertile ground for the recruitment of
cadres for the disciplined phalanxes with which they can celebrate
ThE POLITICAL INSTrUMENT WE NEED 171
the distilled purity of their brands and their preparedness for the
next October.
Obviously, there are major differences between those who reject
a revolutionary rupture and stress electoral gains versus those dedi-
cated to building the vanguard party. However, neither identifies the
capacity of the working class as the central problem. For one, the
working class as it exists needs an electoral program consistent with
its consciousness (and of a coalition with other sectors of society).
For the other, the working class as it exists will be transformed by
a crisis external to it that makes it the working class that it must be
and thus receptive to the revolutionary program. Missing in both is a
focus upon building the working class as a process. However, in the
absence of a working class that has developed its capacity, dignity,
and strength through its protagonism and practice, the immediate
response of workers to crises is to accept the necessity for the repro-
duction of capitalism.
and that they have a duty to continue fighting to defend their ideas
precisely because they may be right. Further, it is necessary to respect
differences and to avoid attempting to homogenize militants accord-
ing to a single norm. In this respect, she proposes that we must avoid
rigidity and “create a type of organization that can house the widest
range of militants, allowing for diverse levels of membership.”28
We need to say more about the internal characteristics of the
political instrument that can foster the ideas of people in social move-
ments. How, for example, do you foster the development of political
cadres as popular pedagogues rather than as those having a military
mentality? The relation of cadres to movements cannot be separated
from the way they are formed internally. Verticalism, however, is built
into a structure in which discipline and acceptance of the decisions
of higher bodies are characteristics of daily life in between policy
conventions. As discussed in the section “Finally, the Party” in The
Socialist Alternative:
The Earth System as it exists faces such a rupture. But what kind
of rupture? One centered in the natural sphere or one centered in the
social sphere? An end to capitalist domination of the social sphere
would point beyond the destruction of the natural sphere. Although
it is possible that the severity of the crisis at a given time may create
conditions in which an anti-capitalist party is able to become the gov-
erning power, to avoid repeating the experience of social democracy,
“it must not only use that opportunity to defeat the logic of capital
and to reduce capital’s power over the state but also to use the power
it has to foster the accelerated development of the sprouts of the new
state.”33
While there may be days, as Marx commented, “into which 20
years are compressed,” building the capacities of the working class
and the constituent elements of the new state from below generally
does not occur overnight.34 That apparent gradualness, though, is
not the antithesis of a revolutionary rupture. The crisis of the Earth
System creates the opportunity for the political instrument to build
ThE POLITICAL INSTrUMENT WE NEED 179
Preface
1. Marx noted that characteristic of these efforts to prove the theory
correct was “crass empiricism,” “phrases in a scholastic way,” and
“cunning argument.” See the discussion of Marx’s disciples in “Why
Beyond Capital?,” in chap. 2 of Michael A. Lebowitz, Beyond Capital:
Marx’s Political Economy of the Working Class, 2nd ed. (New York:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2003), esp. 20–21.
2. Michael A. Lebowitz, “The One-Sidedness of Capital,” Review of
Radical Political Economics 14/ 4 (1982); Lebowitz, 2003.
3. More recently, the study of Marx’s late notebooks on ecological matters
has revealed another critical silence in Capital as handed down. See
in particular Kohei Saito, Karl Marx’s Ecosocialism: Capital, Nature
and the Unfinished Critique of Political Economy (New York: Monthly
Review Press, 2017).
4. Michael A. Lebowitz, Build It Now: Socialism for the Twenty-First
Century (New York: Monthly Review Press, 2006); The Socialist
Alternative: Real Human Development (New York: Monthly Review
Press, 2010); The Socialist Imperative: From Gotha to Now (New York:
Monthly Review Press, 2015).
5. See “A New Political Instrument for a New Hegemony,” Part 3 in Marta
Harnecker, A World to Build: New Paths toward Twenty-First Century
Socialism (New York: Monthly Review Press, 2015).
Introduction
1. Michael A. Lebowitz, Beyond Capital: Marx’s Political Economy of the
Working Class (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003).
NOTES TO PAgES 11–20 181
labour and the like” will not be abolished by “pure thinking” but only
“in a practical, objective way.” Marx and Engels, The Holy Family, in
Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 4 (New York: International
Publishers, 1975), 52–53.
9. Marx and Engels, German Ideology, in Marx and Engels, Collected
Works, vol. 5 (New York: International Publishers, 1976), 36.
10. Ibid., 53.
11. Ibid., 323.
12. Ibid., 214.
13. Marx, Theses on Feuerbach, in Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 5
(New York: International Publishers, 1976), 3.
14. Marx, 1844 mss, 329, 332–33, 342.
15. Marx, Theses on Feuerbach, 4.
16. We may not grasp the centrality of this point because the third thesis
in Engels’s widely read edit of Marx’s Theses on Feuerbach reads: “The
coincidence of the changing of circumstances and of human activity
can be conceived and rationally understood only as revolutionising
practice.” That is, it strangely deletes “or self-change” from Marx’s text.
Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 5 (New York: International
Publishers, 1976), 7.
17. Marx, Grundrisse, 494.
18. Marx, Capital, 1:283.
19. Marx, Capital, 1:548, 643, 799.
20. Marx, Capital, vol. 1, 772.
21. Karl Marx, Capital, 3:178; Marx, Capital, 1:447.
22. Marx, Grundrisse, 488, 541, 708.
23. Marx, Grundrisse, 158–59.
24. Karl Marx, Critique of the Gotha Programme, in Marx and Engels,
Selected Works, vol. 2 (Moscow: Foreign Languages Press, 1962), 24.
25. Karl Marx, “Revelations Concerning the Communist Trial in Cologne,”
in Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 11 (New York: International
Publishers, 1979), 403.
26. Marx, The Civil War in France, in Marx and Engels, On the Paris
Commune (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1971), 76.
27. Marx, Poverty of Philosophy, 211.
28. Marx, Capital, 1:902–4.
29. Marx to Schweitzer, 1 October 13, 1868, in Marx and Engels, Collected
Works, vol. 43 (New York: International Publishers, 1988), 133–34.
Emphasis in the original.
30. Friedrich Engels, “The Ten Hours’ Question,” in Marx and Engels,
Collected Works, vol. 10 ((New York: International Publishers, 1978),
275.
188 NOTES TO PAgES 81–87
31. Marx, Theories of Surplus Value, 2:329; Lebowitz, Beyond Capital, 185.
32. Marx, Capital, 1:412.
33. Lucien Sève, Man in Marxist Theory and the Psychology of Personality
(Sussex: Harvester Press, 1978), 304.
34. Ibid., 313.
35. Lebowitz, Beyond Capital, 142.
36. In chapter 8 of Beyond Capital, “The One-Sidedness of Wage-Labour,”
I posited patriarchy as rooted in a slave relation within the household
with the result that male and female wage-laborers are produced
differently (144–54).
37. I stressed this point, noting the problem of education that could not be
utilized, in a talk I presented at the University of Havana in November
2016, subsequently published as Michael A. Lebowitz, “Protagonism
and Productivity” in Monthly Review 69/6 (November 2017).
38. Just as Marx spoke metaphorically of the renewal of the worker in his
free time as “the production of fixed capital, this fixed capital being
man himself,” one might speak of a tendency for moral depreciation of
human capacity that has been built up, all other things equal, if it is not
used. Marx, Grundrisse, 711–12.
39. See the discussion of simple, contracted, and expanded reproduction of
capacity in Lebowitz, “Protagonism and Productivity,”
32. The political economy of the working class “stresses the combination of
labour as the source of social productivity and the separation of workers
as the condition for their exploitation.” Lebowitz, Beyond Capital: 87.
33. Marx, Capital, 1:793–94.
8. Beyond Atomism
1. Frederick Engels, “The Constitutional Question in Germany” (1847),
in Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 6 (New York, International
Publishers, 1976), 83–84.
2. Ibid.
3. For example, see Elinor Ostrom, Governing the Commons: The Evolution
of Institutions for Collective Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1990); and Daniel W. Bromley, ed., Making the Commons Work:
Theory, Practice, Policy (San Francisco: ICS Press, 1992).
4. Marx, Capital, 3:754n. See Lebowitz, The Socialist Imperative, 22–26,
32–34, esp. “Expanding the Commons,” 146–48.
5. Ostrom, Governing the Commons, 88.
6. Lebowitz, The Socialist Alternative, 66–68; Lebowitz, The Socialist
Imperative, 26–27. See also Marx, Grundrisse, 158, 171–72.
7. E. P. Thompson, “The Moral Economy of the English Crowd in the
Eighteenth Century,” Past and Present 50 (1971).
8. James C. Scott, The Moral Economy of the Peasant: Rebellion and Subsistence
in Southeast Asia (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1976), 4–5, 7.
9. Lebowitz, The Socialist Imperative, chap. 9.
10. Thompson, “The Moral Economy of the English Crowd in the
Eighteenth Century,” 129.
11. Marx, Value, Price and Profit, 143–45.
12. Ibid., 148–49.
13. Daniel Kahneman, Jack L. Knetsch, Richard H. Thaler, “Fairness and
the Assumptions of Economics,” Journal of Business, 59/4 (October
1986).
14. Daniel Kahneman, Jack L. Knetsch, Richard H. Thaler, “Fairness as a
Constraint on Profit Seeking: Entitlements in the Market,” American
Economic Review 76/4 (September 1986): 730–31.
15. Kahneman, Knetsch, Thaler, “Fairness and the Assumptions of
Economics,” S299.
16. Samuel Bowles, The Moral Economy: Why Good Incentives Are No
Substitute for Good Citizens (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2016).
17. Ibid., 4. Bowles refers to 51 studies, involving 26,000 subjects in 36
countries.
18. Ibid., 5, 9, 98–9.
19. Ibid., 50.
192 NOTES TO PAgES 118–124
struggle and, 82; teleology and, surplus value and, 55–56; for
139; “Why Dialectics?,” 138 working-class, 70
The Dialectical Biologist (Levins exchange, 24, 48, 55
and Lewontin), 29 experimental economics, 114–19
directionality, 138 exploitation: of class, 105; com-
distribution, 144 modities and, 49; fairness and,
The Distribution of Wealth (Clark), 114–15; production and, 106,
24–25 131–32; reproduction and,
dynamic systems, 137–38 52–53, 134; of workers, 47, 60,
154–55
Earth system, 68–70, 175–79 expropriation, 130–31
Economic Manuscripts (Marx), externalities, 26–27
62–63
economics: behavioral, 115; of fairness, 113–19, 146, 157
boom periods, 66; of bourgeois fallacy of composition, 26
system, 47; of commodities, falling rate of profit (FROP),
56, 92–93; contradiction in, 67; 59–60, 62–63, 65, 67
of crashes, 58; crisis in, 67–68, families, 22–23, 75
169–70; economists, 21–22; of feedback: from accumulation,
equilibrium, 20–21; experimen- 98–99; change from, 35;
tal, 114–19; of markets, 101; for equilibrium, 114, 135;
of money, 92–95; neoclassical, non-reproduction and, 130;
19–28, 113; political economy, productivity and, 62; reduction-
55, 59–60; Principles of Political ism and, 34; for systems, 61,
Economy, 85–86; of supply-and- 63, 178; wages and, 98; workers
demand law, 104; theory and, and, 68–70
25–26 feudalism, 133, 139–40
education, 26 Feurbach, Ludwig, 74, 77
egalitarianism, 159 Fine, Ben, 13–14, 16
employment, 22–23, 129–30, 146 First International, 103, 112
Engels, Friedrich, 33; atomism for, fixed capital, 66, 188n38
111; Marx and, 75–77, 90, 157, Foster, John Bellamy, 68
187n16; self-change for, Freire, Paolo, 148, 159, 171–72
80–81; separation for, 155;
struggle for, 85; trade unions Galbraith, John Kenneth, 25
for, 103 General Council (First
equal rights, 15 International), 112
equilibrium: dialectic thinking German Ideology (Engels and
and, 33–34, 67–68; economics Marx), 75–77
of, 20–21; feedback for, 114, Gorbachev, Mikhail, 143
135; production and, 57–58, 63; Greece, 168–69
202 INDEx