Solution
Solution
Exercises 1.1
1. By definition of a ∈
/ A/B we have ¬(a ∈ A/B), it means that a ∈
/ A or
a ∈ B and by supposition we know a ∈ A. thus it can not be the case that
a∈/ A, so a ∈ B.
1
7. A 6⊂ C means that there exist an a such that a ∈ A and a ∈ / C. by
a∈/ C and A/B ⊆ C we know that a ∈ / A/B which means that a ∈ / A or
a ∈ B. because of a ∈ A it is only possible a ∈ B. so we have a ∈ A and
a ∈ B which means A ∩ B 6= ∅.
Exercises 1.5
1. By paring axiom we get the set {{u}, {v, w}}. Now by union axiom there
exist a set that contains member of member of this set, i.e. {u, v, w}.
2. By the pairing axiom for every two set there is a set that contains them.
take both set A, then we get {A}.
4. By the axiom of regularity the set {A, B} must contain a set which
has nothing in common with that (i.e. ∃(S ∈ {A, B})S ∩ {A, B}). Because
the set {A, B} just contains two set, it must be A or B. it could not be be
B because A ∈ B and A ∈ {A, B}. it just remains A, so A ∩ {A, B} = ∅.
Clearly, B ∈
/ A because it contradicts former claim.
6. By power set axiom we have P(A). Now by subset axiom we can define
{x ∈ P(A) : x ∈ B} which is equal to P(A) ∩ B.
2
10. Suppose that for an x φ(x, y0 ) and φ(x, y1 ) are both true, we prove
that y0 = y1 . Since ∀z(z ∈ y0 ↔ z = x) and ∀z(z ∈ y1 ↔ z = x) we have
∀z(z ∈ y0 ↔ z ∈ y1 ), thus y0 = y1 and φ describe uniquely such a y. So by
φ(x, y) and replacement axiom for every set A we have a set {{x} : x ∈ A}.
Exercises 2.1
1. Let x ∈ A, then it is also true to say x ∈ A ∨ x ∈ B, so A ⊆ A ∪ B. if
x ∈ A ∩ B it is in both A and B, so it is in A, thus A ∩ B ∈ A.
5. i.e. A ∈
/ A.
8. x ∈ A ∩ (B ∪ C) iff x ∈ A ∧ x ∈ B ∪ C
iff x ∈ A ∧ (x ∈ B ∨ x ∈ C) iff (x ∈ A ∧ x ∈ B) ∨ (x ∈ A ∧ x ∈ C)
iff x ∈ (A ∩ B) ∪ (A ∩ C).
21. Let x ∈ P(A) ∪ P(B). if x ∈ P(A) we can say that x ⊆ A, we can say
for every t, t ∈ x → t ∈ A, and also t ∈ x → (t ∈ A ∨ t ∈ B) which is equal
to say x ⊆ A ∪ B, so by definition of power set, we have x ∈ P(A ∪ B).
3
25. if C ∈ F, we can write F = C ∪ X1 U X2 ... for every Xn ∈ F. So it
S
Second Proof: if C ∈ F we can say for every member of C there exist some
set (namely, C) that belongs to F, so by union axiom it also belongs to F.
S
4
34. It is contraposition of Theorem 2.1.3. {x : φ(x)} is a set(not a proper
class) ⇔ ∃A∀x(φ(x) → x ∈ A), so {x : φ(x)} is a proper class (not a set) ⇔.
∀A∃x(φ(x) ∧ x ∈ / A).
Exercises 2.2
6. Since Y = A ∩ B ∈ P(A) and P(A) ∈ P(P( F)) by Theorem 32
S
every g ∈ G(**). the second part means that there are some A ∈ F and
T
also x ∈ ( F ∪ G).
S S
5
13. Let x ∈ (F ∩G), it means that there is some X ∈ (F ∩G) which x ∈ X.
S
Exercises 3.1
2. let x ∈ (A ∪ B) × C, it means that x = (u, v) which u ∈ A ∪ B and
v ∈ C. u ∈ A ∪ B is true iff u ∈ A or u ∈ B. if u ∈ A then (u, v) ∈ A × C. it
is also true to say (u, v) ∈ (A × C) ∪ (B × C). if u ∈ B then (u, v) ∈ B × C,
similarly (u, v) ∈ (A × C) ∪ (B × C).
Exercises 3.2
1. Suppose that empty set is not a relation, so for some s, s ∈ ∅ such that
s 6= (u, v) for any u, v. but empty set has no member and it contradicts with
supposition.
2.1. x ∈ dom(R−1 ) iff (x, y) ∈ R−1 for some y, iff (x, y) ∈ R−1 then
(y, x) ∈ R for some y, so x ∈ ran(R).
6
2.2. Let y ∈ ran(R−1 ), so there is some x, such that (x, y) ∈ R−1 . it is
also true to say that (y, x) ∈ R for some x, so y ∈ dom(R).
x, y ∈
SS
R. (it is true similarly for (y, x))
10. let (x, y) ∈ R, then (y, x) ∈ R−1 , because R−1 ⊆ R then (y, x) ∈ R.
7
11. Let (x, y) ∈ R and (y, z) ∈ R, we can concludeq that (x, z) ∈ RoR ,
by assumption (x, z) ∈ R. thus R is transitive.
12. By Theorem 3.2.7 we have R−1 = (R−1 oR)−1 = R−1 o(R−1 )−1 =
R−1 oR = R. thus R−1 oR = RoR ⊆ R by Exercise 11 R is transitive.
Because of R = R−1 we can say R−1 ⊆ R, by Exercise 10, R is symmetric.
14. Let (x, y), (y, z) ∈ G then both of them are in every C ∈ G. because
T
C is transitive and (x, y), (y, z) ∈ C we can conclude that (x, z) ∈ C for
every C ∈ G, thus (x, z) ∈ G and G is transitive.
T T
15. Let x ∈ A, because R is reflexive (x, x) ∈ R and also (x, x) ∈ R−1 , thus
R−1 is reflexive. let (x, y) ∈ R−1 , then (y, x) ∈ R, because R is symmetric
(x, y) ∈ R, thus (y, x) ∈ R−1 and R−1 is symmetric.
Let (x, y), (y, z) ∈ R−1 , then (y, x), (z, y) ∈ R, because of transitivity of
R we have (z, x) ∈ R, then (x, z) ∈ R−1 , so R−1 is transitive.
16. Let (x, y) ∈ RoR, then (x, t) ∈ R and (t, y) ∈ R for some t. because
R is transitive (x, y) ∈ R. to prove converse, let (x, y) ∈ R, because R is
symmetric, (y, y) ∈ R. so we can conclude that (x, y) ∈ RoR .
18. Suppose S ⊆ R(*) and (x, y) ∈ SoR. then (x, t) ∈ R and (t, y) ∈ S
for some t. because of (*) (t, y) ∈ R, on the other hand R is transitive, so
(x, y) ∈ R.
Let (x, y) ∈ R, S is reflexive on A so we have (y, y) ∈ S, therefore (x, y) ∈
SoR.
To prove the converse, assume SoR = R and (x, y) ∈ S, because R is reflexive
(x, x) ∈ R, so we have (x, y) ∈ SoR = R, therefore S ⊆ R.
21. Let x ∈ R[A]/R[B], it means that (a, x) ∈ R for some a ∈ A and there
is no b ∈ B such that (b, x) ∈ R, the latter means for every (y, x) ∈ R then
y∈ / B(*). so by first, we can say there is some a ∈ A such that (a, x) ∈ R
and by (*) a ∈/ B. therefore x ∈ R[A/B].
8
22. Let (x, y) ∈ RoS and (t, y) ∈ RoS. then (x, z) ∈ S and (z, y) ∈ R for
some z. on the other hand, (t, u) ∈ S and (u, y) ∈ R but because R is single
root relation we can say z = u, thus (x, u) ∈ S and (t, u) ∈ S. but because
S is single root we have t = x.
Exercises 3.3
1.(lemma 3.3.5) Let y ∈ F , then there is some x ∈ dom(F ) such that y =
F (x), but from supposition, we have y = F (x) = G(x) for all x in their
ommon domain, it means that (x, y) ∈ G.
4. Let f (x) ∈ f [A], it means there is some u ∈ A such that f (x) = f (u),
but because f is one-to-one, x = u, thus x ∈ A.
9
5. Assume g[A] ∩ g[B] 6= ∅, so there is some a ∈ g[A], g[B]. it means that
there is some u ∈ A such that a = g(u) and some v ∈ B such that a = g(v),
so g(u) = g(v) for some v ∈ B and u ∈ A, but g is one-to-one and we have
u = v, it means u ∈ A ∩ B which contradicts with assumption A ∩ B = ∅.
11(a). Let (x, y), (x, z) ∈ C, then there are some f, g ∈ C such that
S
(x, y) ∈ f and (x, z) ∈ g, by assumption either (x, y), (x, z) ∈ f or (x, y), (x, z) ∈
g, in both case by definition of function we have y = z, so C is a function.
S
11(b). Let (x, y), (z, y) ∈ C then there are some f, g ∈ C such that
S
(x, y) ∈ f and (z, y) ∈ g, by assumption either (x, y), (z, y) ∈ f or (x, y), (z, y) ∈
g, both of them are one-to-one, so in either case we have x = z.
12. Let y ∈ f [f −1 [C]], then there is some x ∈ f −1 [C] such that y = f (x),
but x ∈ f −1 [C] means that f (x) ∈ C, so y ∈ C.
10
13. One side is provided by last exercise. we prove other side. let y ∈ C,
because f is onto, there must be some x ∈ A such that y = f (x), so f (x) ∈ C
iff x ∈ f −1 [C] iff f (x) ∈ f [f −1 [C]].
15. Let G[X] = G[Y ] for some X, Y ∈ P(A), it means that f [X] = f [Y ]
i.e. y ∈ f [X] iff y ∈ f [Y ]. let x ∈ X then f (x) ∈ f [Y ] which means there
is some y ∈ Y such that f (x) = f (y), because f is one-to-one y = x. the
converse is similar.
19. Suppose that F (F (x)) = F (x) for all x ∈ A, let (x, y) ∈ F and
(y, z) ∈ F , it means that F (x) = y and F (y) = z, from supposition we
have F (F (x)) = F (y) = F (x) = y, so we have F (x) = z which means that
(x, z) ∈ F , so F is transitive.
11
22. Let (An , n ∈ N + ) be an indexed function such that An = {x ∈ R | 0 <
x < n1 }, by axiom of choice we have a indexed function (xn , n ∈ N + ) such
that xn ∈ An which means that 0 < xn < n1 .
Exercises 3.4
1. We want to prove that is partial order. for every x we have x ≤ x and
x + x = 2x and is even, so we have x x for all x and relation is reflexive.
let x y and y x, it means that x ≤ y and x + y = 2k. also we have y ≤ x
and y + x = 2k, because ≤ is a anti-symmetric relation, we have x = y. so
is also anti-symmetric. let x y and y z, we have x ≤ y and y ≤ z,
and also x + y = 2k and y + z = 2k 0 , by transitivity of ≤ we have x ≤ z and
also sum of them is even, because x + z = 2k − y + 2k 0 − y = 2(k + k 0 − y).
1(a). No, because some members are not comparable, for example 2 and 3.
sum of them is an odd number.
1(b). Yes, because the usual order is total and sum of two odd number is
always even.
1(c). It has no lower and upper bound.
1(d). maximal:4,5. minimal : 1,2.
12
5. because l g for every l among lower bounds, we have also g 0 g.
also from similar argument we kno what g g 0 , because of antisymmetry we
have g = g 0 .
6. (a) upper bound= {{a, b}, {a, b, c}}}, lub={a, b}. lower bound={a, ∅},
glb={a}.
(b) upper bound= {{a, b}, {a, b, c}}}, lub={a, b}. lower bound={∅}.
(c)
9. No.
10. Let h(x) = h(y), so we have h(x) ≤ h(y) and h(y) ≤ h(x). also x ≤ y
and y ≤ x. so because ≤ is antisymmetric we have x = y.
11. Reflexive: let x7inA, we have h(x) 0 h(x) because order is reflexive,
thus by definition of we have x x.
Antisymmetry: let x y and y x, so we have h(x) 0 h(y) and h(y) 0
h(x) we have h(x) = h(y), because h is one-to-one x = y.
Transitive: let x y and y z, it means that h(x) 0 h(y) and h(y) 0 h(z),
because of transitivity we have h(x) 0 h(z), thus x z.
12. From last Exercise we know that is poset. we need to prove that
it is total. let x, y ∈ A, by totallity of 0 we have either h(x) 0 h(y) or
h(y) 0 h(x), from this we can conlude that either x y or y x.
13
14. x C y iff x y and x, y ∈ C. Reflexive: for every x ∈ C we have
x x, thus x C x.
Antisymmetry: let x C y and y C x, it means that x, y ∈ C and x y
and y x, thus x = y.
Transitive: let let x C y and y C z, it means x, y, z ∈ C and x y and
y z, thus by x z and x, z ∈ C we have x C z.
if is total, for every x, y ∈ A we have either x y or y x, because C ⊆ A
it is also true to say that for every x, y ∈ A we have x y or y x which
means that x C y or y C x.
17. Let x ∈ A then (x, x) ∈ or equivalently {{x}, {x, x}} = {{x}} ∈,
it means that {x} ∈ , and also x ∈ , so A ⊆ . To prove
S SS SS
every member of are in the form of (u, v), it means that C = {u} or
C = {u, v} which means that x = u or x = v but because ⊆ A × A, we
14
have u, v ∈ A so x ∈ A, thus A = but by Exercise number 6 of 3.2 we
SS
Exercises 3.5
1. Assume f (x) = f (y), it means that [x] = [y]. because A/ is singleton we
have x = y which means x = y, thus f is one-to-one. Assume some y ∈ [x]
such that x 6= y, then we have [x] = [y] so f (x) = f (y) but f is one-to-one,
thus x = y which is contradiction. 2.
Exercises 4.1
1. Because I and K both are inductive set, ∅ ∈ I ∩ J. let x ∈ I ∩ J, it means
x ∈ I and x ∈ J, so x+ ∈ I and x+ ∈ J, thus we have x+ ∈ I ∩ J.
A ⊆ A, then A⊆
S SS S
4.if A.
15
8. n 6= n+ means that n 6⊆ n+ or n+ 6⊆ n, obviously n ⊆ n+ , thus we just
have n+ 6⊆ n.
11. if A = A then A ⊆ A.
S S
that x ∈ y.
Exercises 4.2
1. 2. Let j, k ∈ A and f (j) = f (k) and j 6= k. because h is onto, we have
some x, y ∈ ω such that j = h(x), k = h(y), thus we have f (h(x)) = f (h(y)),
but by (2) we have h(x+ ) = f (h(x)) = f (h(y)) = h(y + ) it means that
x+ = y + , thus x = y and it means that j = h(x) = h(y) = k which is
contradiction.
there is some t ∈ C such that x = f (t), but t ∈ C means that t ∈ B for all
16
B ∈ C for which we have F [B] ⊆ B, thus x = f (t) ∈ B for all B ∈ C, so
x ∈ C.
(d) for every B ⊆ A, if y ∈ B and F [B] ⊆ B then B ∈ S and because
C = S we have C ⊆ B.
T
Exercises 4.3
1. Assume that n 6= 0, by Theorem 4.1.6 we have n = k + for some k ∈ ω.
then we have m + k + = 0, so by (A2) we have (m + k)+ = 0 which means
that m + k ∈ 0 , but it is contradiction because 0 = ∅. similar argument can
be given for m = 0.
17
thus n+ ∈ I and I = ω.
18
+
= mn .mk by (E2)
+
so k ∈ I.
Thus, k + ∈ I and I = ω.
Exercises 4.4
1. let I = {n ∈ ω : 1 ∈ n+ }. because 1 = 0+ we have 0 ∈ I. assume n ∈ I,
then 1 ∈ n+ iff 1 = n+ or 1 ∈ n+ . if first, we know that n+ ∈ (n+ )+, thus
1 ∈ (n+ )+. if second, 1 ∈ (n+ )+ by transitivity. in either case 1∈ (n+ )+ ,
thus (n+ )+ ∈ I.
Proof two: by Lemma 4.4.6 we have 0 ∈ n for every n ∈ ω. by Lemma
4.4.7 we have 0+ ∈ n+ , which means 1 ∈ n+ for all n ∈ ω.
19
then we have both a ∈ n and n ∈ a which contradicts the trichotomy law. if
a = n then we have n ∈ n by assumption which is again contradiction. thus
it just remain n+ ∈ a or n+ = a which is equal to n+ ∈a.
20
(2) Assume p¬0 and m.p = n.p, just like above we have either m ∈ n or
n ∈ m or m = n. by Theorem 4.4.11(2) we get that the only possible case is
m = n.
13. One side follows from exercise 12, let’s prove the other side. if m+p+ =
n for some p ∈ ω, by Exercise 11 we have m ∈ m + p+ , then m ∈ n.
21
16. Let U = {x ∈ n+ : e ∈ x for all e ∈ E}, thus U is upper bound of E.
By well-ordering U has a least element m. we prove that m ∈ E. Assume
that m 6∈ E. it means that x ∈ m for all x ∈ E (*)(and it is not possible
x = m for any case). Certainly m 6= 0 because E 6= ∅ (when E = ∅ we
would have U = n+ which contains 0), thus we have m = k + for some k ∈ ω.
thus we can rewrite (*) like this : x ∈ k + for all x ∈ E, by Exerecise 2 we
have x ∈ k for all x ∈ E, thus k ∈ U , but on the other hand we have k ∈ m
(because k ∈ k + = m) and m is least element which is a contradiction, thus
m ∈ E.
22