Quality Imlicatures
Quality Imlicatures
Quantity implicatures
Overview of the course
1 Quantity implicatures
2 Nonce inferences or defaults?
3 “Embedded” implicatures
4 Free choice permission
5 Non-pragmatic alternatives
Quantity implicatures
Overview of the course
1 Quantity implicatures
Grice
Quantity implicatures
Scalar implicatures
Disjunction
2 Nonce inferences or defaults?
3 “Embedded” implicatures
4 Free choice permission
5 Non-pragmatic alternatives
Quantity implicatures
Grice
Quantity implicatures
Quantity implicatures
Grice on conversational implicatures
Philosophical background.
Not everything that is conveyed by way of a linguistic
utterance φ is part of φ’s meaning.
An important part of the information conveyed is inferred
on the assumption that the speaker seeks to be cooperative.
Example:
A: I am out of petrol.
B: There is a garage round the corner.
; For all B knows, the garage is open and has petrol to sell.
Such inferences Grice calls “conversational implicatures”.
This is not a psychological theory. Rather, Grice is
concerned primarily with speakers’ commitments.
Quantity implicatures
Inference to the best explanation
Quantity implicatures
Conversational implicatures are:
derived from:
an utterance made by a speaker S (“what S has said”)
+ the assumption that S is trying to be cooperative.
cancellable:
B: There is a garage around the corner, but I’m not sure it is
open.
non-linguistic: they are licensed by general principles of
rational cooperative behaviour.
Methodological corollary:
+ All else being equal, an explanation in terms of
conversational implicature is better than any alternative
explanation in linguistic terms.
Quantity implicatures
Cancellability
Quantity implicatures
Implicatures aren’t really cancellable
Explicit cancellation:
Implicit cancellation:
Here it’s probably better to say that the implicature never arose
in the first place.
Quantity implicatures
Summing up
Quantity implicatures
Quantity implicatures
Quantity implicatures
Quantity implicatures
Quantity implicatures
Varieties of Q-implicature
Quantity implicatures
The Standard Recipe for deriving Q-implicatures
Quantity implicatures
The Standard Recipe for deriving Q-implicatures
Quantity implicatures
The Standard Recipe for deriving Q-implicatures
Quantity implicatures
Bivalence, Competence, and No Opinion
Quantity implicatures
Bivalence, Competence, and No Opinion
non-belief
¬BelS (φ)
z }| {
BelS (φ) BelS (¬φ) ¬BelS (φ) ∧ ¬BelS (¬φ)
belief disbelief no opinion
| {z }
BelS (φ) ∨ BelS (¬φ)
bivalence
Quantity implicatures
Weak implicatures aren’t always strenghtened
Implicatures:
Quantity implicatures
Reminder: Q-implicatures are abductive inferences
Quantity implicatures
Relevance
Quantity implicatures
But what is relevance?
Quantity implicatures
Relevance I: discourse goals
Quantity implicatures
Relevance II: hearers’ personal interests
Quantity implicatures
Relevance III: general interest
Quantity implicatures
Relevance III: general interest (cont.)
Cf.
Quantity implicatures
Relevance III: general interest (cont.) Matsumoto (1995)
Quantity implicatures
So, what’s relevance now?
Uuuuh . . .
Whatever relevance is, it is likely to be a multi-faceted
thing.
Perhaps, as I have suggested, relevance is hearer-centred.
With few exceptions, the R-issue is avoided in the
literature on Q-implicature.
Quantity implicatures
Scalar implicatures
Quantity implicatures
Varieties of Q-implicature
Quantity implicatures
Synopsis
Quantity implicatures
Horn scales
Quantity implicatures
Horn scales: examples
Quantity implicatures
The generative method
Quantity implicatures
Downward entailment
(2) a. All [cars] [are navy blue] ⇒ All [cars] [are blue]
b. All [blue cars] [are cheap] ⇒ All [navy blue cars] [are cheap]
Quantity implicatures
Downward entailment and scalar implicatures
Quantity implicatures
“Scale reversal”
Quantity implicatures
Scalar implicatures with Horn sets
Replace Horn scales with Horn sets, like {all, some, most,
many}, {brilliant, clever}, etc.
Let φ(α) be a sentence, where α is an expression in φ.
φ(β) is an alternative to φ(α) iff
α, β ∈ H, where H is a Horn set, and
φ(β) is stronger than φ(α) (i.e. φ(β) entails φ(α) but not
vice versa).
Examples:
Sentence: Betty ate many of the tarts
Alternatives: Betty ate most of the tarts
Betty ate all of the tarts
Sentence: Betty didn’t eat many of the tarts
Alternatives: Betty didn’t eat some of the tarts
Quantity implicatures
Scalar implicatures with Horn sets
Lesson #1:
For the purpose of calculating Q-implicatures, strength is
measured at sentence level, not below.
Lesson #2:
We don’t need scales: The best way of implementing the
generative method uses sets rather than scales.
Quantity implicatures
Assorted worries about Horn scales/sets
Quantity implicatures
Disjunction
Quantity implicatures
Disjunction
Quantity implicatures
Two types of inference associated with “or”
1 Exclusivity inferences:
; ¬BelS (A and B) (weak exclusivity)
; BelS ¬(A and B) (strong exclusivity)
2 Ignorance inferences:
; ¬BelS (A) and ¬BelS (¬A)
; ¬BelS (B) and ¬BelS (¬B)
Quantity implicatures
Two problems with exclusive “or”
Quantity implicatures
A problem with strong exclusivity
Quantity implicatures
A problem with n-ary disjunctions (n ≥ 1)
Quantity implicatures
A problem with n-ary disjunctions (n ≥ 1)
Idea #1:
Generalise “or” to an n-ary connective:
or(φ1 , . . . , φn ) means that at least one of φ1 , . . . , φn is true.
Ditto for “and”:
and(φ1 , . . . , φn ) means that all of φ1 , . . . , φn are true.
But this yields inferences that are too weak:
“A, B, or C” implicates merely that BelS (¬and(A, B, C)),
i.e., S believes that not all of A, B, and C are true.
Quantity implicatures
A problem with n-ary disjunctions (n ≥ 1)
Idea #2:
Stick to the binary analysis of the connectives:
The underlying form of “A, B, or C”
is either “A or (B or C)” or “(A or B) or C”.
Hence, the stronger alternatives to “A, B, or C” are
A and (B and C) (A and B) and C
either: A and (B or C) or: (A and B) or C
A or (B and C) (A or B) and C
Note: This requires multiple substitutions.
Quantity implicatures
A problem with n-ary disjunctions (n ≥ 1)
A and (B and C)
Take the first set of alternatives: A and (B or C)
A or (B and C)
Quantity implicatures
A problem with n-ary disjunctions (n ≥ 1)
Conclusion:
The generative method doesn’t seem to work: in the
general case, exclusivity inferences don’t seem to be scalar
implicatures.
How bad is this?
Quantity implicatures
Ignorance inferences
Ignorance inferences:
; ¬BelS (A) and ¬BelS (¬A)
; ¬BelS (B) and ¬BelS (¬B)
Quantity implicatures
A pseudo-dichotomy
Quantity implicatures
A deflationist view on scalar implicatures
Quantity implicatures
Where are we now?
1 Quantity implicatures
Grice
Quantity implicatures
Scalar implicatures
Disjunction
2 Nonce inferences or defaults?
3 “Embedded” implicatures
4 Free choice permission
5 Non-pragmatic alternatives
Quantity implicatures