Semantics (Meaning of Meaning)
Semantics (Meaning of Meaning)
Semantics (Meaning of Meaning)
NIM : E1D0190
CLASS : 5TI-1
The study of meaning in human language is often partitioned into two major
divisions, and in this context the term semantics is used to refer to one of these
divisions. In this narrower sense, semantics is concerned with the inherent meaning of
words and sentences as linguistic expressions, in and of themselves, while pragmatics
is concerned with those aspects of meaning that depend onor derive from the way in
which the words and sentences are used. In the above mentioned quote attributed to
Mark Twain, the basic or “default” meaning of good (the sense most likely to be listed
in a dictionary) would be its semantic content. The negative meaning which Twain
manages to convey is the result of pragmatic inferences triggered by the peculiar way
in which he uses the word.
b. Sentence meaning
A “sentence” is a group of words that express a specific thought: to capture it,
we need to understand how words relate to other words. Example (Paul, Jack’s
brother, is married to Linda. Linda is married to Paul, not Jack.).
But even in these cases, the phonetic shape of the word is partly conventional.
The sound a dog makes is represented by the English word bow-wow, the Balinese
word kong-kong, the Armenian word haf-haf, and the Korean words mung-mung or
wang-wang. This cross-linguistic variation is presumably not motivated by
differences in the way dogs actually bark in different parts of the world. On the other
hand, as these examples indicate, there is a strong tendency for the corresponding
words in most languages to use labial, velar, or labio-velar consonants and low back
vowels.
The relation between the form of a sentence (or other multi-word expression) and its
meaning is generally not arbitrary, but compositional. This term means that the
meaning of the expression is predictable from the meanings of the words it contains
and the way they are combined. To give a very simple example, suppose we know
that the word yellow can be used to describe a certain class of objects (those that are
yellow in color) and that the word submarine can be used to refer to objects of another
sort (those that belong to the class of submarines).
An approach which has proven useful for the linguistic analysis of meaning is
to focus on how speakers use language to talk about the world. Similarly, knowing the
meaning of a sentence will allow us to determine whether that sentence is true in a
particular situation or universe of discourse. When a speaker utters this sentence at a
particular time and place, we can look out the window and determine whether or not
the speaker is telling the truth. The statement is true if its meaning corresponds to the
situation being described: is it raining at that time and place? This approach is
sometimes referred to as the correspondence theory of truth.
We might say that the meaning of a (declarative) sentence is the knowledge or
information which allows speakers and hearers to determine whether it is true in a
particular context. If we know the meaning of a sentence, the principle of
compositionality places an important constraint on the meanings of the words which
the sentence contains: the meaning of individual words (and phrases) must be suitable
to compositionally determine the correct meaning for the sentence as a whole.
In this book we attempt to lay a foundation for investigating these three questions
about meaning. For a brief example of why this is an important facet of the study
of meaning, consider the word please in examples.
What does please mean? It does not seem to have any real semantic content,
i.e., does not contribute to the sentence meaning; but it makes an important
contribution to the utterance meaning, in fact, two important contributions. First, it
identifies the speech act which is performed by the utterances in which it occurs,
indicating that they are reqests. The word please does not occur naturally in other
kinds of speech acts. Second, this word is a marker of politeness; so it indicates
something about the manner in which the speech act is performed, including the kind
of social relationship which the speaker wishes to maintain with the hearer. So we see
that we cannot understand the meaning of please without referring to the speech act
being performed.
The claim that the word please does not contribute to sentence meaning is
supported by the observation that misusing the word does not affect the truth of a
sentence. We said that it normally occurs only in requests. If we insert the word into
other kinds of speech acts, e.g. Rather, the use of please in this context is simply
inappropriate (unless there is some contextual factor which makes it possible to
interpret the sentence as a request).
7. Word Meaning
Focuses on word meanings, starting with the observation that a single word
can have more than one meaning. One of the standard ways of demonstrating this fact
is by observing the ambiguity of sentences like the famous headline in (5). Many of
the issues we discuss in Unit II with respect to “content words” (nouns, verbs,
adjectives, etc.), such as ambiguity, vagueness, idiomatic uses, co-occurrence
restrictions, etc., will turn out to be relevant in our later discussions of various kinds
of “function words” and grammatical morphemes as well. (5) Headline: Reagan wins
on budget, but more lies ahead.
8. Pattern of Pragmatic
Deals with a pattern of pragmatic inference known as
conversationalimplicature: meaning which is intended by the speaker to be understood
by the hearer, but is not part of the literal sentence meaning. Many people consider
the identification of this type of inference, by the philosopher Paul Grice in the 1960s,
to be the “birth-date” of pragmatics as a distinct field of study. It is another
foundational concept that we will refer to in many of the subsequent chapters.As
illustrated above in example (3b), an indirect speech act involves a sentence whose
literal meaning seems to perform one kind of speech act (asking a question: Can you
pass me the salt?) used in a way which implicates a different speech act (request:
Please pass me the salt).
9. Issue of Compositionality
Addresses the issue of compositionality: how the meanings of phrases and
sentences can be predicted based on the meanings of the words they contain and the
way those words are arranged (syntactic structure). It provides a brief introduction to
some basic concepts in set theory, and shows how these concepts can be used to
express the truth conditions of sentences. One topic of special interest is the
interpretation of “quantified” noun phrases such as every person, some animal, or no
student, using set theory to state the meanings of such phrases. In Unit V we will use
this analysis of quantifiers to provide a way of understanding the meanings of modals
(e.g. may, must, should) and if clauses.