Immanuel Kant - Philosophical Correspondence, 1759-1799 (1970)
Immanuel Kant - Philosophical Correspondence, 1759-1799 (1970)
Immanuel Kant - Philosophical Correspondence, 1759-1799 (1970)
PHILOSOPHICAL CORRESPONDENCE
1759-99
ARNULF ZWEIG
THE UNIVERSITY
OF CHICAGO
PRESS
The letters in this collection are translations o£ correspondence contained in
the Prussian Academy edition of Kant's works, Kant's gesammelte Schriften
(Berlin and Leipzig: Walter de Gruyter äc Co.), Vols. X - X I I ( 1 9 2 2 ) and
XXIII ( 1 9 5 5 ) .
Translator's Preface • v
T w o people above all deserve thanks for their help in this work.
The first is Professor Lewis White Beck, whose writing and
teaching first stimulated my interest in Kant and who gave me
many valuable suggestions and much friendly advice on translat-
ing the correspondence. The other is my wife, who not only
encouraged and aided me but who also made many critical sug-
gestions for improving the manuscript. I would also like to express
my thanks to the University of Oregon for granting me sabbatical
leave during 1962-63, to the Research Committee of the Graduate
School of the University of Oregon for two summer research
grants, and to the American Philosophical Association for a grant
in support of this volume. Because of these sources of assistance, I
was able to spend the academic year 1962-63 in Germany and
Austria. I would like particularly to express my pleasure at the
hospitality extended to me and to my family by my colleagues in
the Universities of Vienna and Bonn during that year.
ARNULF ZWEIG
Eugene, Oregoi
vi • Translator's Preface
Contents
Introduction 3
The Letters
From J. G. HAMANN, July 27, 1759 35
TROW J. H. LAMBERT, November 13, 1765 43
To J. H. LAMBERT, December 31, 1765 47
From J. H. LAMBERT, February 3, 1766 50
To MOSES MENDELSSOHN, April 8, 1766 54
To J . H. LAMBERT, September 2, 1770 58
From J. H. LAMBERT, October 1770 60
From MOSES MENDELSSOHN, December 25, /770 67
To MARCUS HERZ, February 21, 1772 70
To MARCUS HERZ [toward the end of 1773] 76
To J. C. LAVATER, April 28, 1775 79
To J. C. LAVATER [after April 28, 1775] 82
To C. H. WOLKE, March 28, 1776 83
To MARCUS HERZ, November 24, 1776 86
To MARCUS HERZ, August 20, 1777 87
To MARCUS HERZ, August 28, 1778 89
To MARCUS HERZ, October 20, 1778 90
From MARCUS HERZ, November 24, 1778 92
To MARCUS HERZ, February 4, 177g 93
To MARCUS HERZ, May 1 , 1781 93
Contents • vii
From F . V . L . PLESSING, March 75, 1784 " 3
From F . V . L . PLESSING, April 3, 1784 115
viii • Contents
From J. S. BECK, May 37, 17 190
To J. S. BECK, July 3, 7792 192
To J . S. BECK, October 16 [or 77], 7792 194
From J. S. BECK, November 10, 1792 195
From SALOMON MAIMON, November 30, 1792 196
To J. S. BECK, December 4, 7792 198
To J . B. ERHARD, December 21, 7792 199
From MARIA VON HERBERT, [January] 7793 200
From J. B. ERHARD, January 17, 7793 203
To ELISABETH MOTHERBY, February 11, 7793 204
To C. F. STXUDLIN, May 4, 7793 205
From J. G. C. C. KIESEWETTER, June 75, 1793 206
To J. S. BECK, August 18, 7793 207
From J . E. BIESTER, October 5, 7793 208
From J. G. C. C. KIESEWETTER, November 23, 7793 209
To K. L. REINHOLD, March 28, 1794 211
To J . E. BIESTER, April 10, 1794, 212
From J. S. BECK, June 77, 7794 213
To J. S. BECK, July 1, 1794 216
To FRIEDRICH WILHELM II [after October 12, 1794] 217
From J. E. BIESTER, December 17, 1794 220
To FRIEDRICH SCHILLER, March 30, 7795 221
From MATERNUS REUSS, April 1, 1796 222
From CONRAD STANG, October 2, 1796 224
Contents • ix
To J . H . TIEPTRUNK., April 5, 1798
To CHRISTIAN GARVE, September 21, ijg8 250
Index 255
x • Contents
Introduction
Introduction
1
Kant expressed himself on this point when he declined to include his letters
in the published correspondence of Lambert and again in that ot Mendelssohn.
See, for example, his remarks to J. Bernoulli, November 16, 1 7 8 1 [ 1 7 2 ] , and
to Marcus Herz, April 7, 1786 [267].
Introduction • 3
•- I. 1759-7°
4. • Introduction
elements of human knowledge," which should discuss "the univer-
sal and necessary possibilities of synthesizing and uniting of simple
concepts." He had read Kant's essay, "Only Possible Proof of the
Existence of God" (1763) and knew that Kant was working on a
reconstruction of the method of metaphysics analogous to one
which he himself advocated. Lambert suggests that they exchange
letters on their research, a proposal which must have flattered Kant
(who called Lambert "the greatest genius in Germany"), for he
replied to Lambert with unusual alacrity. Lambert's letter is amus-
ing also for its uncharitable observations (a prefiguration of C. P.
Snow's "two cultures") on Greek scholars, antiquarians, art critics,
and literati.
Kant's reply self-confidently announces that he has finally found
"the proper method for metaphysics and thereby also for the whole
of philosophy"; but he is not yet prepared to publish his findings
for, as he candidly admits, he lacks examples of propositions that
can be demonstrated by means of this method. He has therefore
put aside the project in order to devote himself to other essays, the
subject of two of these being the metaphysical foundations of
natural philosophy and the metaphysical foundations of practical
philosophy.4 Lambert awaited these books impatiently, as he states
in his next letter, but as it turned out, in vain. We can only guess
what Kant had in mind in 1765, though many scholars regard this
as the beginning of Kant's investigations leading to the Critique of
Pure Reason. It becomes clear that the discovery of the problem to
which Kant's letter of 1772 to Herz is devoted was one cause of
Kant's repeated postponement of his project, though undoubtedly
the heavy burden of his teaching duties (Kant .lectured up to
twenty-eight hours a week, in addition to private seminars) was
also important.
Lambert's reply, February 3, 1766 [37], describes his own
methodology at considerable length, utilizing the distinction be-
tween "formal" and "material" knowledge, a distinction that be-
came an important part of Kant's analysis of metaphysics in the
inaugural dissertation (1770) and also in his later critical writings.
Formal knowledge, Lambert suggests, is expressed in "simple
concepts" a priori; it is concerned only with the organization of
non-formal or material knowledge. Complex, synthesized concepts
4
As a matter of fact, Kant published nothing under these titles until twenty
years later, when the Metaphysical foundations of Natural Science appeared
(1786).
Introduction • 5
must be derived from simple concepts. The latter type of concepts,
such as space and time, require direct acquaintance, that is, intui-
don. The extent of Kant's indebtedness to Lambert is expressed in
his letter to Bernoulli, November 16, 1781 [ 1 7 2 ] .
Hamann. Kant's correspondence with J. G. Hamann (1730-88)
does not discuss any technical questions of philosophy but reveals
very strikingly the conflicting attitudes and convictions of these
philosophers. Hamann, the "wizard (or Magus) of the North" as
he was called, was the most improbable friend one could imagine
for Kant. Passionate, mystical, intellectually and physically untidy,
he was the antithesis of all that Kant and the Enlightenment
represented. His flamboyant style of writing is a language all its
own, using a veritable stream of consciousness technique full of
classical and biblical allusions along with copious, often brilliant
neologisms. Though at one time a deist, Hamann had undergone
a sudden conversion to an intensely fundamentalist and emotional
type of Christianity.3 The long letter of July 27, 1759, expresses
Hamanns' astonishment, rage, and amusement at the efforts of
Kant and J. C. Berens, a long-time friend of Hamann's, to con-
vert him away from zealotry back to what these men regarded as
rational deism. It is a brilliant letter, powerful and sarcastic.8
Less theatrical but nonetheless entertaining was Hamann's sec-
ond letter of 1759 (not included here), and the circumstances that
prompted it are again interesting for what they reveal about Kant.
Apparently Kant and Hamann had discussed collaborating on a
natural science textbook for children. (Kant's interest in education
and his views on that topic are also shown in his letter to Wolke,
March 28, 1776 [109].) Hamann lampoons the idea that Kant is
capable of this and argues that a book by a philosopher, written
for children, would have to be as ostensibly simple and babbling as
a book by God, written for mere human beings. Hamann suggests
basing physics on the biblical account of creation, presenting
physical phenomena with a view to showing their divine origin.
This suggestion could hardly have pleased Kant, and it is not
surprising that he failed to reply to this or to Hamann's subse-
quent effusions on the subject.
3
Kierkegaard must have recognized Hamann as a prehguration of himself.
He quotes Hamann on the title page of Fear and Trembling.
8
An English translation of some parts of the letter may be found in R. G.
Smith, /. G. Hamann (New York: Harper & Bros., i960). The translation in
the present volume is new and complete.
6. • Introduction
Kant's only extant letters to Hamann were written in 1774.
They contained a tedious discussion of Herder's Älteste Urkunde
des Menschengeschlechts, which appeared anonymously in that
year. The main topic concerned Herder's intention in discussing
the occurrence of common symbols in both the biblical account of
creation and the literature of pagan antiquity, and Herder's claim
that this similarity reflected God's effort to instruct the human
race. The letters do include some pleasant academic gossip con-
cerning the promotion of a man of dubious piety—Hamann calls
him a "Roman-apostolic-catholic-heretic-crypto-Jesuit"—to the pro-
fessorship of theology, but they are otherwise rather boring. The
most interesting remark made in them is Kant's concluding plea to
Hamann (April 6. 1774 [86]) to communicate his further ideas
"if possible, in the language of men. For I, poor earthling that I
am, have not been properly trained to understand the divine
language of an Intuitive Reason."
Mendelssohn and the Popular Philosophers, Moses Mendelssohn
(1729-86) was the most distinguished of the so-called popular
philosophers of the German Enlightenment. A group of somewhat
unsystematic intellectuals, more or less Leibnizian in outlook
though often opposed to learned discourse and technical argu-
ments, they preferred to appeal instead to common sense, the
gesunder Menschenverstand, or healthy human understanding.
The men usually included under this heading were J. G. H. Feder,
C. Meiners. C. Garve, J. J. Engel, C. F. Nicolai, and J. E. Biester.
Feder and Meiners taught at Göttingen, where they later founded
the Philosophische Bibliothe\, a journal specifically devoted to
combatting Kant's "critical philosophy." The journal survived
only four volumes. Garve, a more sensitive man (his letters to
Kant are genuinely moving), worked in Breslau. It was Garve's
review of the Critique of Pure Reason (a review edited and
distorted by Feder before its publication in January, 1782, in the
Göttinger Gelehrte Anzeigen) that provoked Kant's wrath 7 and
stimulated him to write certain parts of the Prolegomena to Any
Future Metaphysics (the appendix of that work refers to the
review). Nicolai, a friend of Mendelssohn's and of Lessing's, was
editor of the Bibliothek^ der schönen Wissenschaften (1757-58),
then of the Briefe, die neueste Litteratur betreffend (1759-65)
and, most important, of the Allgemeine deutsche Bibliothe\
Introduction • 7
(1765-1805), a propaganda organ of the Enlightenment. 8 Opposed
to prejudice, superstition, orthodoxy, pietism, mysticism, and Jes-
uitism, he was, for all his zeal, platitudinous and shallow. Kant,
who was for a time on cool but friendly terms with Nicolai,
directed one of his last essays, "Ober die Buchmacherei (1798),
against him, and Nicolai also became a target for Fichte, Goethe,
and Schiller. Biester, who published the Berliner Monatsschrift, to
which Kant contributed, was secretary to the minister of education,
von Zedlitz, as well as librarian in the Royal Library. As one of
Kant's chief ambassadors in the capital, his correspondence with
Kant during the period 1792-94 tells us much about Kant's
difficulties with the censorship of unorthodox religious views. The
French Revolution is also touched upon in these letters.
Of all these men, it was Mendelssohn for whom Kant had the
greatest respect and affection. Unlike most of the popular philoso-
phers, Mendelssohn did not disapprove of careful arguments and
rigorous demonstration. Like Kant, he deplored the fall of philoso-
phy, once the "queen of the sciences," to the shabby status of a
facile, diverting parlor game. In 1763, Mendelssohn and Kant
competed for the Berlin Academy Prize. Mendelssohn's Treatise
on Evidence in the Metaphysical Sciences won, but the judges
praised Kant's essay, An Inquiry into the Distinctness of the
fundamental Principles of Natural Theology and Morals (Unter-
suchung über die Deutlichkeit der Grundsätze der natürlichen
Theologie und der Moral), and the two works were to have been
published together. The topic proposed for this competition was
the question: "Whether metaphysical truths generally, and in
particular the fundamental principles of natural theology and
morals, are capable of proofs as distinct as those of geometry." 9
Mendelssohn maintained that metaphysics can be as certain as
geometry, though it is not as easily comprehended. Kant insisted
that there are fundamental differences between metaphysics and
mathematics, especially with regard to the role of definition or
concept formation. Mathematics arrives at its concepts synthetically,
from definitions; its concepts are constructed figures, from which
3
Nicolai is known also for a parody on Goethe's Sorrows of Werther: The
Joys of Young Werther (Freuden des jungen Werthers [ 1 7 7 5 ] ) .
9
A translation of Kant's essay is included in Kant's Critique of Practical
Reason and Other Writings in Moral Philosophy (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 194g), translated and edited bv L. W. Beck.
8. • Introduction
we can derive only what we have originally put into them. 10
Validity is here independent of what exists in nature. Philosophy,
however, cannot produce its own objects but must take them as
given and try to see them as they are. Definitions are thus the end
of philosophy rather than the beginning. "Metaphysics is without
doubt the most difficult of human insights; but none has ever been
written."
The disagreement with Mendelssohn did not inhibit the start of
a warm friendship. Mendelssohn must have written a cordial letter
early in 1766 to which Kant's letter of February 7 [38] is a reply.
In this letter he expresses his pleasure at the prospect of a corre-
spondence with Mendelssohn, chats about a Jewish student whom
Mendelssohn had recommended to Kant, and asks Mendelssohn to
forward copies of Kant's Dreams of a Ghost-Seer Explained by
Dreams of Metaphysics to various gendemen (including Lam-
bert). Kant refers to it as einige Träumerey ("some reveries") and
adds: "It is, as it were, a casual piece, containing not so much a
working out of such questions as a hasty sketch of the way they
should be treated."
Evidendy the work estranged Mendelssohn by what the latter
took to be an insincere tone, "between jest and earnest." In his
answer to Mendelssohn (the latter's cridcal letter is not extant),
April 8, 1766 [39], Kant forcefully defends his own character. In
addition to this extended self-evaluation, unique in Kant's writ-
ings, he aiso indicates his view, of the worth of current meta-
physics, whose "chimerical insights" lead to folly and error. An
exposure of dogmatism is needed, says Kant, an organon, on
which he is now at work. Kant speaks of having already reached
"important insights" that will denne the proper procedure for
metaphysics.
The discussion of the soul, in this letter, gives us a brief
statement of the position Kant defended in his Dreams of a Ghost-
Seer. He is concerned with the relationship of material and spir-
10
It is interesting to see how Kant remained true to this early thesis
throughout his critical writings. Indeed, the claim is generalized in the
Critique of Pure Reason: all a priori knowledge depends on "what we have
originally put into" our judgments. See Critique A xx, B ix, B xii, B xiii,
B 130. I am grateful to Professor Samuel Todes for pointing out the similarity
of these passages to me. See also Kant's letters on mathematics in this
collection, as listed in the Index.
Introduction • 9
itual substances but is not optimistic about solving such metaphysi-
cal problems. What are the powers o£ spiritual substances, and
how can we discover the precise way in which souls are joined to
material substances? Our philosophical fabrications are completely
unhindered by any data when we discuss theories that purport to
answer these questions. Kant suggests that there are matters
(birth, life, and death) that we can never hope to understand by
means of reason. The main theme of the Dreams of a Ghost-Seer,
to which Kant is referring in this letter, is the parallel between the
dreams and visions of Swedenborg, on the one hand, and the
speculations of allegedly scientific metaphysics, on the other.
Kant's essay tries to show how a clever manipulation of concepts
can produce ostensible knowledge of the supersensible. He shows
that such structures are mere airy possibilities of thought, unde-
serving of serious attention. The metaphysician's theories are
''dreams of reason," whereas those of the ghost-seer are "dreams of
sensadon." He writes: "I do not know whether there are spirits;
yes, what is more, I do not even know what the word 'spirit'
means." Philosophy "excites the suspicion that it is found in bad
company" when serious efforts are devoted to explaining the
whims of fantastic persons.
Kant's attitude toward traditional metaphysics as shown in this
work and in the letter to Mendelssohn was, in 1766, quite close to
Hume's. The philosopher's task should be to survey the nature and
limits of our cognitive powers. Speculative metaphysics offers no
possibility of scientific certainty, its principles being based on mere
wish fulfilment. The tone of the critical philosophy is there,
though Kant had not yet developed the major theses, nor even
formulated the main questions, of the Critique of Pure Reason.
II. 1770-81
18. • Introduction
bert, Kant states some of the main theses of the dissertation.
Again, Kant is concerned with the need for a transformation of
metaphysics, a program that the separadon of non-empirical from
empirical principles will help to realize. His position at this dme,
pardy influenced by Leibniz' Nouveaux Essais (1765), involved
the separation of a "sense world" and an "intellectual world," with
a corresponding schism in the structure of our cognitive faculties.
In order to reconcile the independence of mathematics from expe-
rience with the applicability of mathematics to reality, Kant pro-
pounds the theory that space and time are forms of intuition,
invariant characteristics of immediate experience. 12 This is essen-
tially the position taken in the transcendental aesthetic of the
Critique of Pure Reason. The Newtonian view, that space and
time are "real beings" existing independently of objects, events,
and observers, Kant argued, makes unintelligible how geometry
(the science of space) can be known a priori to be valid for
everything in space and time. Geometry, on Newton's view of
space, would have to have the status of a merely empirical science.
Ultimately, Kant attempts to mediate between this absolute theory
of space and time and the theory of Leibniz. Though independent
of what fills them, space and time are not independent of knowing
minds. But Kant believed the consequence of his theory—that
space and time are supplied by our own faculty of sensibility—to
be that the objects that we perceive in space and time are only
phenomenal images of noumenal realities, and such noumenal
entities, if they are to be known at all, would have to be reached
by some non-empirical means, viz., pure thought. Thus we have
two "worlds": the world of our sensibility is "appearance," and
that of our understanding is genuine, "intelligible" reality. As
against Leibniz, the distinction between sensibility and under-
standing is made to be one of kind and not of degree—sensibility
is passive; understanding is active or "spontaneous." In addition,
along with the Platonic distinction of two worlds, Kant followed
Introduction • 11
Leibniz in assuming that the categories or non-empirical concepts
of the intellect (causality, substance, necessity, and so on) have not
only a "logical use," that is, in the organization of experience, but
also a "real use," in which they provide knowledge of the world of
true Being.
It is this "dogmatic" position (in contrast to the skeptical view
of metaphysics in Dreams of a Ghost-Seer) against which Kant
reacted in the decade between 1770 and the appearance of the
Critique of Pure Reason in 1781. The change is recorded primarily
in Kant's letters to Marcus Herz (1747-1803). Along with Kant's
later correspondence with his apostatic disciples, these letters com-
prise perhaps the most significant philosophical material to be
found in Kant's letters.13
Hers and the letter of tfjT.. Herz studied in Königsberg from
1755 to 1770 and acted as "respondent" or "public defender" for
Kant's inaugural dissertation, a fact indicative of Kant's respect for
him. After studying medicine in Halle, Herz returned to Berlin in
1774 to begin his medical practice. By 1776, he was also giving
public lectures on the philosophy of Kant; several letters of 1778
deal with Herz's request for lecture notes from Kant. One of the
most distinguished members of Herz's audience was von Zedlitz,
the minister of spiritual affairs (which included education) to
whom Kant later dedicated the Critique of Pure Reason. But
Kant's confidence in Herz stemmed not only from the latter's
philosophical talents; Herz was a physician, and Kant a hypochon-
driac. Most of Kant's letters to Herz make mention of symptoms
and ailments, sometimes very extensively described, with discus-
sions of possible treatments and requests for advice. Though Kant
was never seriously ill, he constantly complained about his health
and the adverse effects of his indisposition (mainly gastric and
intestinal) on his work. 14
13
For a discussion of Herz and Kant, see L. W. Beck, "Kant's Letter to
Marcus Herz," in Studies in the Philosophy of Kant (Indianapolis: Bobbs-
Merriil Co., 1965), an essay that appeared originally in Philosophical Forum
(Boston University), XHI ( 1 9 5 5 ) . For another recent discussion of this letter,
see R. P. WoLff, Kant's Theory of Mental Activity (Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press, 1963). Virtually all of the standard commentaries
on Kant make some mention of the letter. Some scholars (for example,
Norman Kemp Smith) see it as supporting the "patchwork theory" of the
deduction of the categories, whereas others (for example, H. J. Paton) oppose
this interpretation. There is a good discussion of the letter in T. D. Weldon,
Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (London: Oxford University Press, 1958).
14
In one of his last works, The Strife of the Faculties, Kant blamed his
lifelong hypochondria on the narrowness o£ his chest.
12. • Introduction
The letter of February 21, 1772, shows Kant's thinking at the
point at which the Leibnizian aspects of the theory In his inaugu-
ral dissertation first became suspect to him. Suddenly he is trou-
bled by the uncritical assumption he had made, that categories or
"intellectual representations," which Kant had characterized only
negatively as "ideas we employ that are not derived from our
experience of objects," could nevertheless be supposed to agree
with those objects and thus to represent things as they are. How
can concepts that do not produce their objects (like God's think-
ing) and that are not produced in us by the objects to which they
refer (like empirical concepts) be applicable a priori to an inde-
pendent reality? In other words, Kant is asking for a justification
or "deduction" of the "real use" of pure concepts when these con-
cepts are to apply not simply to mathematical "objects" that we
ourselves construct but to things existing independently of our
minds. He wants to know how we can tell that a concept "spon-
taneously" created by the mind actually corresponds to anything.
Kant says that he has found a way to classify these concepts "fol-
lowing a few fundamental laws of the understanding" and that
in three months he will be ready with his solution—an extra-
ordinarily sanguine prediction, as it turned out. For by the time
Kant had completed the Critique of Pure Reason, the "recollection
of David Hume," as he characterizes it in the Introduction to the
Prolegomena, had "interrupted [his] dogmatic slumbers. . . . ,"
and the problem stated as it is in this letter to Herz was found to
be incapable of solution. The categories could not be shown to
agree with the nature of things, if "thing" is taken to refer to
noumenal entities in a non-empirical world.
Though Kant had not yet arrived at the most distinctive argu-
ment of his critical position, the transcendental deduction, he had
evidently reached a form of the table of categories and, more
important, a formulation of what was to become the central
problem of the Critique of Pure Reason, viz., how are synthetic a
priori judgments possible. Here in the letter to Herz he mentions
that work for the first time by name. It was this momentous work
that took up most of Kant's attention in the "?ilent decade" of the
seventies.
Kant published very little between 1770 and 1781, and the
number of letters he wrote is also small. His correspondence with
Hamann in 1774 has already been mentioned. A few letters to
Herz tell of his progress or lack of progress on the Critique, along
Introduction • 13
with some very detailed discussion of his physical debilities, and
these letters are not only biographically important but help us to
see how intimate the friendship of these two men must have been.
The correspondence with Lavater and Wolke, however, presents
us with an entirely different side of Kant's intellectual interests.
Lavater. J. C. Lavater ( 1 7 4 1 - 1 8 0 1 ) was a Swiss poet, mystic,
and a renowned physiognomist, a man who influenced Goethe and
who was also close to Hamann. Lavater was an ardent reader of
Kant, his Lieblingsschriftsteller. His letters to Kant indicate that
the literary and learned world was awaiting Kant's new writings
with great eagerness. "Are you dead to the world?" Lavater asks.
"Why is it that so many scribble who cannot write, while you who
write so well are silent?" Lavater tells Kant that he and his
countrymen are anxious to see the Critique. In one letter he asks
Kant to evaluate his own book, on faith and prayer, somehow
imagining that Kant would approve of it. One can imagine how
Lavater's enthusiasm for Kant must have been tempered by the
latter's reply (April 28, 1773 [99] and [100]) for Kant's views
were already those of Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone.
The letters are in fact a clear and eloquent summary of Kant's
position. A certain cooling off on Lavater's part is confirmed by his
failure to reply to Kant for almost a year, although the two men
afterward remained on good terms and Lavater later once wrote to
Kant of his jov at having found someone to talk with "to satiety
and still not to satiety" about Kant's ideas. Though the corre-
spondence between them ended, Kant mentions Lavater a number
of times in various works, critically but not disrespectfully. He had
no patience for the Lavaterian attempt to analyze character by
means of the study of facial lines, calling it "indistinct concepts
without any order," and in his lectures on anthropology in 1785
Kant maintained that physiognomists are correct in their analyses
of character only when they know the people they are supposedly
analyzing. Elsewhere Kant refers to Lavater as a Schwärmer—a
fanatic or enthusiast inspired by a delusion—but Kant did not
always use this word abusively.
Letters on Education: Wol\e. Kant's interest in education was
always intense, to such an extent that he was even willing to
interrupt his work on the Critique in order to write and speak in
15
Cf. his reference to Maria von Herbert as die kleine Schwärmerin in a
letter to Elisabeth Motherbv, February n , 1793 [559].
14. • Introduction
support of the educational reforms of an experimental school, the
Philanthropin. This institution was founded in Dessau in 1774 by
J. B. Basedow, a man whose views on education Kant regarded
highly. Kant used Basedow's Methodenbuch as the text in his
lectures on practical pedagogy in the winter semester of 1776-77.
The Philanthropin was based more or less on the liberal principles
of Rousseau's £mile.le From the very beginning, the school was in
serious financial difficulties, for which Basedow's enthusiasm failed
to compensate. Kant's correspondence with Basedow and the men
who replaced him, C. H . Wolke and J. H . Campe, reflects Kant's
efforts to keep the Philanthropin in business.17 The most impor-
tant of these letters, for a view of Kant's ideas on education and
especially on religious instruction, is the letter to Wolke of 1776
[109]. Kant believed that a child "must be raised in freedom, but
in such a way that he will allow others to be free as well"
(Reflexionen zur Anthropologie, No. 1473). In the letter to
Wolke, he makes explicit his opposition to traditional methods of
education and especially to customary religious education. Kant
urges that a child not even be introduced to prayer until his
understanding has matured to such a degree that he can under-
stand (what Kant regards as) the true purpose of devotional acts,
viz., to apprehend his duties as if the latter were divine commands.
16
The "natural" method of education at the Philanthropin insisted on
treating children as children. Powdered hair, swords, gilded coats, and makeup
were forbidden. The children had short haircuts and wore sailor jackets. They
learned languages in a sort of "Berlitz" program. The curriculum included
Latin, German, French, mathematics, geography, physics, music, dancing,
drawing, and physical education. Religion was taught in such a way that
sectarian distinctions in theology were completely avoided.
17
To this end, Kant published several appeals for subscriptions in the
Königsberger gelehrte und politische Zeitung.
Introduction • 15
unsympathetic. T o Mendelssohn and to Garve Kant wrote in 1783,
carefully setting forth some of the main theses of the Critique and
defending himself against various criticisms, especially that of
"unpopularity" in style of writing. Kant challenges Garve to
compose a deduction of the categories that will make pleasant
reading, or to try to construct a "whole new science" without the
difficult arguments and distinctions in the Critique (to Garve,
August 7 [205]; to Mendelssohn, August 16 [206]).
These letters taken together provide not only a nice introduction
to those theses but also show Kant's view (in 1783) on two
matters which his critics have frequently debated and about which
it must be admitted Kant himself was never entirely clear: the
distinction between appearance and thing-in-itself, on the one
hand, and the distinction between sensible and supersensible ob-
jects. Talking about the first distinction. Kant says to Garve that it
is a difference between two concepts or ways of talking about all
given objects. Viewed in this light, the distinction does not commit
Kant to the two "worlds" theory of the dissertation. In the letter to
Mendelssohn, however, Kant speaks of the existence of two radi-
cally different kinds of entities. The Critique, he says, does not
aim to deny the existence of objects (Gegenstände) that are not
objects of possible experience; in fact, the existence of such entities
is required by it! It would seem, then, that the claim that there
exist supersensible objects (übersinnliche Gegenstände") must be
distinguished from the appearance versus thing-in-itself dualism,
for, as Kant had indicated only a week earlier, in distinguishing
appearances from things as they are in themselves, the phrase
"thing-in-itself" refers not to some object other than the object we
encounter in experience but to that same object considered apart
from its relation to a knowing subject. In the decades following,
the problem of the status of the Kantian thing-in-itself became one
of the main targets for Kant's critics. Discussion centered around
the question whether Kant's theory of perception entails the claim
that unknowable things in themselves are the cause of our sense
impressions. Kant's ablest student, J. S. Beck, attempted to save
him from inconsistency by interpreting his theory to mean that
"thing-in-itself" is just another way of talking about the object that
appears and that it is this phenomenal object, not some mysterious
supersensible entity, that affects our senses. Kant's answers to
Beck's letters do not positively endorse this interpretation—by then
Kant was old and, as he told his followers, no longer equipped for
16. • Introduction
overly subtle discussions—but the letter to Garve may be taken as
one piece of evidence in support of Beck's interpretation.
Disciples and Critics. The sudden profusion of letters after 1783
attests to the impact of the Critique of Pure Reason on the
intellectual life of Germany and Europe. Though Kant's reputa-
tion in the learned world was already high, his fame now became
extended well beyond the sphere of the universities. Kant's phi-
losophy was the topic of discussion in literary salons and court
gatherings. Young ladies wrote to him for moral guidance, and
religious zealots and political absolutists, deploring the popularity
of his liberal ideas, wrote to him to try to convert him. Kant was
hailed as the benefactor of mankind, liberator of the human spirit
and defender of freedom. Journals were founded to spread the
critical philosophy, and several of Kant's students wrote populari-
zations of his work to make him understandable to the general
reading public. The progress of Kant's philosophy did not go
unchallenged, however. An upsurge of fanaticism, religious reac-
tion, and political interference in the form of censorship and
loyalty oaths was about to begin. As early as 1783 Kant heard
from his friend F. V. L. Plessing that the enemies of the Enlight-
enment were gathering strength, a lament which Plessing repeated
in his letter of March 15, 1784 [226]. Rumor had it that "a
Protestant king is supposed secretly to be a J-s-t!" wrote Plessing.
The Jesuits, "those hellish spirits," had poisoned the hearts of
princes. But as far as the government was concerned, Plessing's
dire warnings were a few years premature. Kant's most vocal
enemies, at this time, were not political figures but the old guard
philosophy professors who defended Leibniz and Wolff.
Although Kant was attacked and misunderstood by popular
philosophers, empiricists (who assailed Kant for subscribing to
synthetic a priori judgments), and rationalists (who assailed him
for limiting knowledge to the domain of experience), the favora-
ble reactions of younger men more than compensated for these
hostile opinions. The spread of Kantianism was aided by the
dedication of Kant's new disciples at the University of Jena,
especially C. G. Schütz, C. F. Schmid, and K . L . Reinhold. The
Allgemeine Literaturzeitung, to which Kant contributed, did
much to promote the critical philosophy. Schütz, whose corre-
spondence with Kant is of interest in tracing the progress of
Kant's writings after the Critique of Pure Reason, was the author
of the first sensible review of the Critique, and it was he who
Introduction • 17
persuaded Kant to write a review of Herder's Ideen (1785) for the
^JL-Z. 1 8 (Schütz was moved to tears fay Kant's refusal of the
generous honorarium offered by the journal.) Schmid's support of
Kantianism came in the form of an elucidatory dictionary of
Kantian terminology, Wörterbuch zum leichteren Gebrauche der
Kantischen Schriften (1788), and Reinhold's Letters concerning
the Kantian Philosophy (1786/87 in the Deutsche Merf^ür; 1790 as
a book) was most important in popularizing Kant. 1 3 By 1787,
when Reinhoid was professor of philosophy at the University of
Jena, people spoke of the "Kant-Reinhold" philosophy—a phrase
that lost its cogency, however, when Reinhold later became a
follower of Fichte. 20
Reinhold's letters to Kant, in 1787 and 1788, are rhapsodic in
praising the critical philosophy and its creator. They also contain
some nice academic gossip, including some anecdotes about Kant's
enemy at Jena, a Professor Ulrich, who made a practice of inviting
Reinhold's students to dinner in order to seduce them away from
the study of Kant! Kant's letter to Reinhoid, in 1788, expresses his
opinion of various contemporaries and states his approval of Rein-
hold's work. Of greater philosophical interest, however, are Kant's
letters in the following year, in which he gives a lengthy account
of his objections to the Wolffian philosopher, Eberhard.
J. A. Eberhard, professor of philosophy at Halle, was founder of
the Philosophisches Magazin, a periodical dedicated to destroying
Kant's philosophy. He denied the originality of Kant's analytic/
synthetic distinction, rejected the "Copernican revolution" with its
consequent limitation of the understanding to objects of sensible
18
In February, 1785, Schütz wrote Co Kant saying that Herder ought to
take pride in Kant's discussion of his book—the review was generally
recognized as Kant's even though it appeared unsigned. But Herder's reaction
to it was not what Schütz predicted, as can be seen from a letter Herder wrote
to Hamann in which he expresses his vexation and accuses Kant of being
bitter toward him for having decided not to follow the path of his former
teacher's "verbal juggling." Herder objects especially to being treated like a
schoolboy now that he is forty years old and a thinker in his own right.
19
Reinhoid, who was born in Vienna in 1758, started his career as a Jesuit.
Stirred by the Enlightenment under Emperor Josef, he came to reject most
orthodox dogmas and eventually he abandoned the Jesuit order and was
converted to Protestantism. In 1783, in Weimar, Reinhoid became the son-in-
law of C. M. Wieland, the famous novelist.
20
Reinhold's uncommon candor is shown by his public pronouncement,
while still at the height of his fame, thac Fichte had refuted him. He died,
virtually forgotten, in 1823.
18. • Introduction
intuition, and argued that reason, being capable of intellectual
intuitions, can furnish its own "material" without the aid of the
senses, Kant, in his letters to Reinhold, is especially critical of
Eberhard's attempt to use the principles of contradiction and
sufficient reason as devices for achieving knowledge of objects.
Some of the material in these letters was later incorporated into
Kant's polemical essay against Eberhard, On a Discovery accord-
ing to Which All New Critique of Pure Reason Is Supposed To
Be Obviated by an Earlier One (lieber eine Entdeckung nach der
alle neue Kriti\ der reinen Vernunft durch eine ältere entbehrlich
gemacht werden soll [1790]), in which Kant attacks the meta-
sensible use of reason, refutes Eberhard's objections to his notion
of synthetic judgments, and offers an interpretation of Leibniz that
contains the argument that Leibniz's theory requires completion
by Kant's own philosophy. The. main points in this essay against
the philosophical ancien regime may be found in the letters to
Reinhold of 1789.
Other Opposition: Marburg and Berlin. Eberhard's controversy
with Kant was by no means the only occasion on which the
entrenched partisans of competing philosophies did batde with
Kant and his followers. In Marburg the conflict came to a head
earlier than elsewhere. At the probable instigation of the' Wolff-
ians, Kant's theories were investigated for alleged impiety or
skepticism, and in 1786 lecturers were actually forbidden to discuss
his philosophy. 21 Apparently Kant's critic Feder, still stung by the
untoward aftereffects of his hostile review of the Critique, was one
of the main forces behind the ban.
Meanwhile in Berlin, the death of Frederick the Great (1786)
and the accession of Frederick William II created a climate that
proved to be hostile not only to Kant but to all the Enlightenment,
including some of Kant's bitter opponents. Whereas the Wolffians
regarded Kant as insufficiendy rationalistic, the inspired irrational-
ists who now came to power could see him only as the embodi-
ment of rationalism and as the enemy of orthodox, historical
Christianity, an intractable critic of every form of mysticism and
zealotry. The actual suppression of heresy did not get seriously
started until 1788. As late as December, 1787, Kant learned from J.
C. Berens that the new king was still allowing the same freedom
21
See notes to Kant's letter to J. Bering, April 7, 1786 [266].
Introduction • 19
of the press enjoyed under his predecessor (Berens to Kant,
December 5, 1787 [3x0]). But one year later, the troubles had
begun (Berens to Kant, October 25, 1788 [338]). It was suspected
in some quarters that since Kant had claimed that reason was
incapable of providing theoretical knowledge of the supersensible,
he must be secretly sympathetic to the religious reactionaries. His
friends implored him to make his position emphatically clear so as
to stop the fanatics. The bookdealer Meyer wrote from Berlin
(September 5, 1788 [ 3 3 3 ] ) asking Kant to compose an essay on
freedom of the press to fight the growing suppression. Kiesewetter
and Biester kept Kant informed of developments in the capital,
where, for a dme, the liberal theologians and clerics paid little
attention to the government's edicts on religion. In the decade that
followed, the antics of Frederick William II and his pious counse-
lors were to become more than the joking matter they first ap-
peared to be. The king's mystical visions and sexual escapades are
reported in a number of Kiesewetter's gossipy letters of 1790 and
after, a few samples of which have been included in this collection.
The heretic-hunting mood reached its climax, for Kant's career, in
1793-94, when Kant's publications on religion were brought under
the censorship of the royal Commission on Spiritual Affairs. In
1792, Fichte had sought Kant's advice on how to get his own
Critique of Revelation approved by the censor of theology in the
University of Halle. Thus, it was not oniv the government that
sought to suppress freedom of thought but some of the theological
faculties in the universities themselves. Kant explained to Stäudlin
(May 4, 1793 [574]) what he had tried to do in his Religion
within the Limits of Reason Alone and how he had presented the
book to the theological faculty in Königsberg to avoid conflict with
the authorities. In the fall of 1794, however, the order condemning
Kant's book, and any further expression of his unorthodox views,
was issued by the king's minister, Woellner. Kant was obedient,
though his response to the king (letter [642]) is in no way
obsequious. Kant's religion of "rational faith" is given a powerful
statement here.
Granting the forcefulness of Kant's letter to Frederick William
II, we must admit nevertheless that Kant was a constitutionally
timid person. Even twenty years earlier Kant had shown some-
thing of this character when, in considering an opportunity for a
better position, he confessed to Herz that "all change frightens
20. • Introduction
me" (early April, 1778 [ 1 3 4 ] ) . Now in his old age Kant was
unwilling to spend his remaining energy on political (or for that
matter philosophical) disputes. His letters of 1789 and after speak
repeatedly of his advancing age and increasing frailty. Again and
again he excuses himself for failing to act vigorously against his
various opponents. Biester respectfully but disappointedly accepted
Kant's decision to comply with the royal decree commanding
Kant's silence (December 17, 1794 [646]). Only after the death of
Frederick William II in 1797 did Kant feel himself freed from his
promise (on the rather casuistic grounds that the pronoun in
"Your Majesty's servant" referred specifically to that monarch, so
that the obligation to remain silent had been undertaken only to
him). Though Kant took a lively interest in the public contro-
versies and political turbulence of the decade following 1789, he
devoted himself as much as possible to the completion of his
philosophical system. Only on rare occasions did he allow himself
to be distracted from this work. One such occasion was the famous
Mendelssohn-Jacobi feud in the 1780's. Two others, of more per-
sonal than literary or philosophical interest, were the Plessing
affair and the tragic case of Maria von Herbert. Each of these three
topics requires some explanation.
Mendelssohn, Lessing, and Jacobi. The literary quarrel between
Mendelssohn and Jacobi 22 dominated the discussions of German
intellectuals for several years, until finally Kant himself was drawn
into the dispute. (Kant's essay, What Is Orientation in Think-
ing? contains his answer to the disputants, both of whom had
attempted to gain his support.) The story of this controversy is
somewhat complicated. F . H . Jacobi ( 1 7 4 3 - 1 8 1 9 ) , the "philos-
opher of faith," had maintained that Spinoza's philosophy con-
tained the only logically acceptable system of metaphysics. Since
this system was monistic, however, it entailed the denial of any
genuine theism. To accept Spinozism was therefore to become an
atheist. Hume, according to Jacobi, had performed an important
service by exposing the pretensions of natural theology, for he had
made it clear that God is an affair of the heart, not of reason, and
that philosophy (that is, Spinozism) must be givfcn up in the name
of faith. Jacobi also argued for the possibility of immediate intui-
tions of a supersensible reality. Like Kant, however, he held that
22
See also n. 1 to the letter from Marcus Herz, February 27, 1786 [260].
Introduction • 21
the field of knowledge is restricted to objects of possible experi-
ence. Reason is incapable of penetrating beyond the sensible.23 So
much the worse for reason.
Now Lessing's position was not altogether opposed to Jacobi's.
Lessing had published some works of the deist H. S. Reimarus
(1694-1768) (under the title WOldenbüttel Fragments) but un-
like the deists, Lessing did not believe religious truths capable of
proof. A pioneer of the "higher criticism," Lessing believed that
faith rests on inner experience and that religious ideas are to be
judged by their effect on conduct. Lessing died in 1781, iust after
he had admitted to Jacobi that Spinoza's theory seemed to him to
be correct. This is what Jacobi wrote to Mendelssohn in 1783, and
from this disclosure arose their furious controversy, a controversy
on which some were even to put the blame for Mendelssohn's
death in I786."4 Since pantheism seemed to Jacobi indistinguish-
able from atheism, he was shocked at Lessing's confession. Men-
delssohn, however, took Jacobi's attack on Lessing to be also an
attack on himself, and even though Mendelssohn was not a panthe-
ist he felt called upon to defend Spinoza and Lessing. In his book
Morning Lessons (1785), Mendelssohn challenged Jacobi, who re-
plied by publishing his answer to Mendelssohn and their letters to
, each other. Herder and Goethe were drawn into the argument,
and both of them rejected Jacobi's equadon of Spinozism with
atheism.
What Lessing had said to Jacobi was that orthodox ideas about
.God were of no utility to him. God is One and All, and if Lessing
had to name anyone as philosophically sound, it would have to be
Spinoza. Like Spinoza, Lessing believed human actions to be
determined. God is the ultimate cause of the world order, and
everything that exists is a part of him. "Why should not the ideas
that God has of real things be these real things themselves?"
23
Unlike Kant, Jacobi maintained that we perceive tilings as they are in
themselves. He also rejected Kant's formalism in ethics and defended the
possibility of immediate moral intuitions. Jacobi's criticism of Kant's theory of
the thing-in-itseif became famous and was iacer repeated by various critics: the
affirmation of things-in-themselves, he argued, can be justified only by using
the causal principle, which principle is supposed to be subjectively grounded
and applicable only intraphenomenally. An epigrammatic remark of Jacobi's
was often quoted: "Without it [the assumption of things-in-themselves] I
could not get into the system; with it, I could not stay."
24
See notes to the letter from Marcus Herz, February 27, 17S6 [260].
22. • Introduction
asked Lessing. 25 One consequence of the Pantheismusstreit, as it
came to be called, was the revival of interest in the study of
Spinoza. Another, as has been mentioned, was Kant's essay on
orientation. The main letters mentioning the feud are those from
Mendelssohn (October 16, 1785), Biester (June 1 1 , 1786), and
Herz (February 27, 1786 [260]) 26 and Kant's letter to Herz
(April 7, 1786 [267]). In the last of these, Kant condemns Jacobi
as guilty of a frivolous and affected "inspiration" (Genieschwär-
merey) and goes on to speak of "the excellent Moses," so that it is
clear where Kant's sympathies lay.
L'affaire Plessing. When the editors of Kant's correspondence
were assembling their manuscripts, it was with considerable reluc-
tance that an indelicate letter of Plessing's (April 3, 1784 [228])
was included in the Prussian Academy edition of Kant's corre-
spondence. Plessing's friendship with Kant is a significant counter-
example for any theory that pictures Kant the "stern moralist" as
utterly inflexible, prudish, or inhuman. F . V . L. Plessing (1749-
1806) was a fascinating and unstable person who figured not only
in Kant's life but also in Goethe's (whose Harzreise im Winter
deals with Plessing). In his youth, Plessing studied at one univer-
sity after another, unable to settle on any one subject or in any one
place. His life was beset with neurotic and financial difficulties
involving his family. In 1782 he came to know Kant and Hamann
in Königsberg and decided that it might still be possible to make
something of himself, whereupon he studied for the doctorate with
Kant. Plessing did in fact become a philosopher,27 and some of his
correspondence with Kant is concerned with his philosophy of
history. He was a brooding, troubled man who found himself able
to accept Kant's negative doctrines, though he remained basically
dissatisfied with Kant's faith grounded on morality.
As Plessing's letters to Kant make clear, Plessing had become
involved in (and had lost) a paternity suit, and Kant had helped
him by acting as intermediary in transmitting Plessing's mainte-
nance payments. Kant's willingness to become involved in such an
unprofessional and undignified problem seems to reveal a less
25
"On the Reality of Things outside God," an essay for Mendelssohn.
26
These are not of any intrinsic interest and have not been included here.
27
In 1788 he accepted a professorship at Duisberg, one of the smallest
universities in Germany, far removed from the frontiers of intellectual debate,
which was just as he wished.
Introduction • 23
rigoristic attitude on his part than one might have expected. A
careful reading of the letter will disclose that Kant's tolerance of
Plessing's human failings did not, however, extend to a condoning
of the "unnatural" and calculated practice of birth control. Pless-
ing's arguments against Kant on this matter show a lively wit. It is
unfortunate that Kant's answer to Plessing is not available to us.
(Kant's highly puritanical attitude toward sex is made very ex-
plicit, however, in another letter, where even marital sexual rela-
tions are viewed as unsavory and the sexual libertine likened to a
cannibal! [To C. G. Schütz, July 10, 1797 ( 7 6 1 ) ] )
Maria von Herbert. Whatever difficulties Kant's philosophy may
have encountered in Prussia and other northern German states, the
spread of Kantian ideas in Austria and southern Germany aroused
even more opposition. (This may be seen in the letters of M. Reuss
[699] and C. Stang [ 7 1 5 ] , two Benedictine followers of Kant.) In
the town of Klagenfurt in southern Austria, however, there lived a
Baron Franz Paul von Herbert, one of the few people in reaction-
ary Austria who was interested in the philosophy of Kant. The
extent of his dedication is shown by the fact that in 1789, "driven
by a philosophical itch" (as K . Vorländer puts it), 23 he left his lead
factory, wife, and child to journey to Weimar, then to Jena, for the
sake of studying Kant's philosophy. In 1791 he returned to Kla-
genfurt, bringing with him some of the revolutionary spirit of the
critical philosophy. Herbert's house then became a center for the
passionate discussion of Kant's philosophy. It was, in the words of
one of Fichte's students, "a new Athens," dedicated to, among
other things, the improvement of religion, a task that required
replacing piety with morality.
Maria, the young sister of Franz Paul, who participated in these
discussions, was born in 1769. In family circles she was called
"Mizza" and her face was said to be very beautiful. If her physical
appearance is somewhat a matter of conjecture to us, the intensity
of her emotions and the sensitivity of her mind (notwithstanding
her charmingly bad spelling) are not. In 1791 she wrote her first
letter to Kant, a letter full of despair, which impressed him so
deeply that he showed it to his friend Borowski and prepared a
careful preliminary draft of his answer to her plea. Erhard, a friend
of her brother's and of Kant's, explained in a letter that she had
thrown herself into the arms of a certain man "in order to realize
- 3 K . Vorländer, Immanuel Kant, der Mann und das Werk. (Leipzig: Felix
Meiner, 1924), II, p. 1 1 6 .
24. • Introduction
an idealistic love." Evidendy the man turned out to be a cad for, as
Erhard says, he "misused her." Maria fell in love a second time,
and for a while she deceived her new lover about her previous
relationship. When she finally disclosed her earlier affair to him,
his love for her cooled. In her letter, she begs Kant for guidance.
Kant's answer is interesting for what it reveals about his own
sensitivity to the nuances of emotional and moral problems and
about his views on love. He presents his statement in the manner
of a sermon, and there is a gently didactic tone throughout. Kant
seems willing to make seme concessions to the natural weaknesses
of human beings. He says in effect that, although we have a duty
to abstain from lying and from insincerity, we are to be forgiven
for failing to pour out every secret of our hearts to someone we
love. An ideal love would consist in mutual esteem and a totally
uninhibited sharing, but the inability to be utterly open with
another person is a sort of reticence that lies in human nature and
does not constitute a weakness of character. These consoling re-
marks are followed, however, by some more characteristically
Kantian moralizing: Maria is not to have any moral credit for
confessing her earlier deception, if the motive of her disclosure was
a desire to achieve peace of mind rather than true repentence for
having lied. Nor should she brood over the new lover's change of
heart; if his affection does not return, it was probably only sensual
in the first place. Besides, the value of one's life does not depend
on whether or not one achieves happiness.
The second and third letters Maria sent to her "spiritual physi-
cian" are less agitated than the first, but it is not so much
resignation as a deeper despair and a sense of overwhelming
apathy that breathes through them. The inner emptiness she
expresses, the sense of being "almost superfluous" to herself, of
being incapable of significant action (even morality has become
uninterestingly easy for her, since she feels no temptation to
transgress its laws), suggest a beautiful personality destroying
itself by the very clarity of its self-awareness. Maria tells Kant, in
her third letter (sometime early in 1794 [ 6 1 4 ] ) that she had in
fact been on the point of suicide but that though death would
please her she will not take her own life out of consideration for
morality and the feelings of her friends. Kant did not answer
either of these letters but sent them to Elizabeth Motherby, the
daughter of an English friend, as a warning to the young woman
(whose "good training had, however, made such a warning unnec-
Introduction • 25
essary," Kant said) of what happens to ladies when they think too
much and fail to control their fantasies! For all his perceptiveness
and liberalism, Kant was not enthusiastic about women's rights or
greatly concerned about the frustrations suffered by intelligent
ladies in a society that regarded them as merely useful or decora-
tive ornaments.29 In 1803, nine years after her last letter, Maria did
in fact commit suicide.
From Kant to Fichte. Although Kant's philosophical letters in
the 1790's touch on a great number of topics, some of the most
interesting letters are those that show the gradual defection of
Kant's once ardent admirers and that enable us to see the develop-
ment of Kant's own thinking in response to their criticisms. It is a
pity that there are no very serious philosophical exchanges with
Fichte in the correspondence.30 However, the correspondence with
S. Maimon, J. S. Beck, and J. H. Tieftrunk provides a wealth of
discussion of just those issues (principally the problems concerning
the Ding an sich, the "affecting" of sensibility, and the primary
significance of synthesis, or Zusammensetzung) that make the
transition from Kant to Fichte comprehensible.
In 1789 Salomon Maimon (1753-1800) sent Kant the manu-
script of his Essay on the Transcendental Philosophy ("Versuch
über die Transzendentalphilosophie [1790]). Their mutual friend
Herz described Maimon :o Kant as "formerly one of the rawest
Polish Jews" who by virtue of his brilliance and perseverance had
miraculously managed to educate himself in all the sciences. (See
Herz's letter, April 7, 1789 [351]-) Herz had read the book, and it
was on his advice that Maimon asked for Kant's opinion of it.
Kant answered Maimon's criticisms in a letter to Herz (May 26,
29
T h e limitations of Kant's sympathy for egalitarianism is shown also in his
attitude toward the rights of servants. See his letter to C. G. Schütz, July 10,
!
7 9 7 [ 7 6 1 ] . hi which he discusses the right to possess another person (a
household servant) as if the latter were a thing.
30
Kant's letter of February 2, 1792 [504] containing his advice to Fichte on
how to deal with the censorhip authorities in Halle is included in this
collection; it contains a good statement of Kant's religious beliefs. A number
of other letters in 1792 concern Kant's efforts to help Fichte publish his
Critique of Revelation (Versuch einer Kritik aller Offenbarung) and, with the
subsequent confusion as to its authorship, Fichte's explanation and apologies
for the confusion, and so on. (See notes to the letter to Fichte of February 2,
1792 [504].) The book was attributed to Kant himself, partly because it came
from his publisher, Härtung. Härtung had inadvertently left out the Preface,
in which Fichte spoke of the work as "my first venture before the public," a
phrase that would have made clear that the anonymous author was noc
Kant.
26. • Introduction
1789 [362]), and callcd his work a book full of "the most subtle
investigations" written by an astute critic who had understood him
better than any other. Maimon wrote again in July, 1789, express-
ing his gratitude for Kant's rejoinder, though he was not satisfied
with Kant's reply. He wrote several times in 1790, again in 1791
(see his letter of September 20 [486]), 1792, and 1793, but Kant
did not answer him. 31 Maimon's criticism of Kant in 1789 already
pointed the way to Fichte and the idealist movement that was soon
to take hold. He denied Kant's basic distinction between passive
sensibility and the active, spontaneous understanding. He main-
tained that the human mind is part of an infinite world soul that
produces not only the form but also the content of experience. The
understanding is intuitive, not merely discursive. Maimon ac-
cepted the negative, antidogmatic part of Kant's theory as correct
but rejected the positive theory of the thing-in-itself (which he
interpreted to mean the claimed existence of a thinkable entity
without any determinate characteristics) as inconceivable. We can-
not form a clear concept of either an object-in-itself or of a subject-
in-itself. The thing-in-itself loses its character of thinghood, in
Maimon's philosophy, and becomes merely an irrational limit of
rational cognition, the idea of an endless task whose completion is
constantly retreating as knowledge advances. The self-contradic-
tory assumption of the existence of things independent of all
consciousness arose in the attempt to explain the origin of the
"content" of appearances; but there is in fact no content or
material of experience independent of form. The distinction be-
tween the matter and form of knowledge is only a contrast
between a complete and an incomplete consciousness of what is
present to us, the incomplete consciousness being what we refer to
as the given, that irrational residue that we distinguish from the a
priori forms of consciousness. The contrast is only one of degree;
form and matter are the terminal members of an infinite series of
gradations of consciousness. The given is therefore only an idea of
the limit of this series.
31
In 1794, Kant spoke disparagingly of Maimon, in a letter to Reinhold on
March 28 [620]. It is one of the few places where Kant makes an anti-Semitic
remark. Perhaps it should be forgiven, on the grounds that Kant was
extremely sensitive to criticism and to the apostasy of his followers, and 1794
was a bad year for him not only on these two accounts but also because of his
troubles with the official proscription of his work on religion. The persecution
from which Kant suffered seemed serious enough to Kant's friends to warrant
an offer of asylum from one of them (the educator J. H. Campe).
Introduction • 27
While on some issues Maimon took Hume's position against
Kant's (for example, he maintained that the concept of causality is
the product of habit, not a pure concept of the understanding), his
indebtedness to Leibniz is also evident. For some reason Maimon
called himself a skeptic, but his rejection of Kant's account of
things-in-themselves and the given, along with his conception of
the human understanding as part of the divine understanding,
clearly foreshadows Fichte and the development of "absolute ideal-
ism." In fact, Fichte wrote to Reinhoid, in 1795, "My esteem for
Maimon's talent is boundless. I firmly believe and am ready to
prove that through Maimon's work the whole Kantian philosophy,
as it is understood by everyone including yourself, is completely
overturned. . . . All this he has accomplished without anyone's
noticing it and while people even condescend to him. I think that
future generations will mock our century bitterly." 32
Kant's correspondence with Jakob Beck ( 1 7 6 1 - 1 8 4 0 ) contains
not only some of the most penetrating criticisms of Kant's theory
but also an indication of how Kant was himself being influenced
by the men he denounced as "my hypercritical friends." By 1799,
the seventy-five-year-old Kant (who complained to Garve, Septem-
ber 2 1 , 1798 [820] that his condition was reduced to that of a
vegetable) was so saddened by the independent line that his
former students had taken that he angrily criticized the position of
Fichte (whose books he had not read) and Beck (whose position
he had virtually adopted as his own) in an "Open letter on
Fichte's Wissenschaftslehre" (the last letter in this collection, Au-
gust 7, 1799). There he charged that his Critique of Pure Reason
had not been intended as a propaedeutic to any future system of
metaphysics, that it was in fact the complete statement of pure
philosophy, and that no "standpoint" (the allusion is to Beck's
Only Possible Standpoint from which the Critical Philosophy
Must Be Judged) of any interpreter or commentator is required in
order to comprehend it.
All of these remarks are either false or misleading. The occasion
of the open letter was a challenge put to Kant by a reviewer
in the Erlanger Literaturzeitung, January n , 1799, who asked
Kant whether his theories were really meant to be taken literally
32
There is a fairly lengthy discussion of Maimon's importance in Richard
Kroner's Von Kant bis Hegel (Tübingen: J. C. B. Möhr [Paul Siebeck],
1 9 2 1 - 2 4 ) . A more recent work devoted entirely to Maimon is Samuel Atlas'
From Critical to Speculative Idealism: The Philosophy of Solomon Maimon
(The Hague: Martinus Nijhorf, 1964).
28. • Introduction
{buchstäblich) or as interpreted by Fichte or Beck. Kant's personal
attack on Fichte as a "treacherous friend" may have been encour-
aged by his overly zealous disciple Johann Schultz, on whom Kant
relied for an account of Fichte's position and whom Kant had
earlier (see the letter to J. A . Schlettwein, May 29, 1797 [752])
endorsed as his most reliable expositor. Certainly, neither Fichte
nor Beck had done anything to deserve it. Fichte's official reply, in
the form of an open letter to Schelling, was temperate. Privately,
however, he declared Kant's theory to be "total nonsense" unless
given a Fichtean interpretation; he even called Kant "no more
than three-quarters of a mind" who had "mightily prostituted
himself." 33 That the Critique was supposed to be a propaedeutic
to a reconstruction of metaphysics was not only asserted by Kant
himself in numerous passages in the Critique but clearly implied
by him in his references to the system of metaphysics he intended
to compose when "the critical part of [his] task" was finished.
This is what he had written to L. H. Jakob [303] and to Reinhold
[322] in 1787 and 1788 in connection with his completion of the
third Critique.** A sketch of Kant's planned system of metaphysics
was even included in a letter to Beck in 1792 [500], and the
oudine Kant gives there agrees with the reorganized form of the
Critique that Beck recommended in his own letters. It would seem
then that the doctrinal gulf between Kant and his erstwhile
disciples was not at all as wide as Kant seems to suggest in the
declaration against Fichte.
Like Maimon, Beck denied the positive role that Kant's theory
of perception seemed to have given to the thing-in-itself. Beck
argued that when Kent spoke of objects affecting our sensibility it
could only be phenomenal objects that he had meant, not an
33
K . Vorländer, op. dt., II, 265.
34
Kant's statement to Jakob that on completion of the critical part of his
plan he could proceed to the dogmatic is puzzling if one recalls Kant's
customary use of the word "dogmatic" to stigmatize the philosophical method
he rejected, viz., one that proceeds without a prior investigation of reason's
competence to answer the questions it is asking. But perhaps Kant was
thinking of "dogmatic" in the sense in which he distinguished "dogmata"
from "mathemata" in the Critique of ?ure "Reason A 7 3 6 - B 764 and not in the
derogratory sense. In the Critique, a dogma is one sort of non-analytic
apodeictic proposition, viz., a synthetic proposition that can be "directly derived
from concepts." Mathemata are the other sort of synthetic a priori proposition,
not found in philosophy, which can be "directly obtained through the
construction of concepts." There are no dogmata "in the whole domain of
pure reason, in its merely speculative employment," Kant argued (loc. cit.).
Introduction • 29
unknowable thing-in-itself acting on an unknowable subject-in-
itself. T h e self that is affected and the object that acts on it must
both be viewed as products of a more basic activity of the under-
standing, an acdvity that we presuppose when we regard our
experiences as produced in us either by an independent object or
by our own power of thinking. This most basic activity Beck
equated with the function of producing the transcendental unity
of apperception in Kant's deduction of the categories, and it is this
"standpoint" one needs to attain in order to understand Kant's
theory. It is a unique act of synthesizing a priori, an act whereby
the subject constitutes himself as a conscious thinker.
Kant's agreement with Beck is shown most clearly in his will-
ingness to make the activity of synthesis (Zusammensetzung) the
basic condition of all cognition. Beck used the phrase "original
attribution" {ursprüngliche Beylegung), which Kant at first (and
with justification) found unintelligible; Beck's colleague J. H.
Tieftrunk spoke of an act of Setzen ("positing") [787]; and in
Fichte's Wissenschaftslehre the ego "posits" the non-ego in an
original Tathandlung. Although each of these men found his own
views to be either subtly or dramatically different from those of the
others (Beck, for example, tried to convince Kant that he was
radically opposed to Fichte), they agreed that Kant's theory of
affection must be reconsidered. But Kant himself had certainly
already modified his position when he wrote to Beck, as early as
January, 1792 [500]: "The content [of a representation] must
thus . . . be created [gemacht] by an inner activity . . . that
precedes a priori the manner in which the manifold is given."
Beck thought that Kant's method of exposition in the Critique
was only a concession to the uninitiated reader who had not yet
arrived at the "standpoint" of seeing "objects" as the product of
that original activity of the understanding. He and Tieftrunk,
both of them perhaps reiterating the criticisms of G. E. Schulze,
argued that it was inconsistent of Kant to make an unknowable
thing-in-itself that which affects us—inconsistent because "affect-
ing" is a causal relation and the concept of cause is supposed to be
meaningful only intraphenomenally and because Kant seems to
know a great deal about unknowables here, for example, that they
are real (another category illegitimately used) and efficacious.
Beck's suggested reconstruction of Kant's theory, which would
begin with the "standpoint," that is, the original activity of mind
that first produces the "I think" expressed in the categories, was, as
30. • Introduction
has already been pointed out, not at all uncongenial to Kant, and
the extent of Beck's influence on Kant may be seen in Kant's Opus
Postumum?5
36
For a discussion of this, sec Herman-J. de Vleeschauwer, The Develop-
ment of Kantian Thought, translated by A. R. C. Duncan (London: Thomas
Nelson & Sons, Ltd., 1 9 6 2 ) . This book is an altogether invaluable study for an
understanding of Kant's relationship to his contemporaries. Kant's Opus
Postumum is also discussed at some length in F . Copleston's History of
Philosophy, Vol. VI (London: Burns & Oates, Ltd., 1 9 6 0 ) , though Copleston
attributes to Fichte the influence I believe to be Beck's. Since Kant had not
read Fichte's Wissenschaftslehre and knew it only from a review and from
what Johann Shultz told him of it, Copleston's conjecture seems mistaken.
36
Kant's correspondence with Schiller deals with the latter's request that
Kant contribute an article to the journal Die Hören. Kant declined. The letters
are respectful on both sides. It is not clear whether Kant was aware of
Schiller's poetry and dramas.
37
Gourmet readers may be interested in Kiesewetter's advice on how to
cook these turnips (November 25, 1798 [ 8 2 7 ] ) . They must be washed in
w a r m water, dropped at once into boiling water, and then cooked for no more
than fifteen minutes. They must be stored in a dry place.
38
T h e translation was published in two volumes in London, 1 7 9 8 - 9 9 .
Richardson sent a letter June 2 1 , 1798 [808] (not included in this collection)
along with the first volume of the translation.
39
Friedrich Nicolovius ( 1 7 6 8 - 1 8 3 6 ) had a publishing firm in Königsberg
(1790-1818).
40
December 25, 1797 [ 791 ].
Introduction • 31
physics. Until 1801, his seventy-seventh year, he devoted what
energy he had to this project. But in April of 1802 he wrote, 41 " M y
strength diminishes daily, my muscles vanish, and even though I
have never had any actual illness and have none now, it is two
years since I have been out of the house. Nevertheless I view all
changes that are in store for me with calm." In April, 1803, he
celebrated his last (seventy-ninth) birthday with his dinner com-
panions. In October of that year he became ill (after eating his
favorite English cheese) but recovered sufficiently to entertain his
usual dinner guests later that month. From December until the
following February, however, he grew much weaker and his death
came on the twelfth of February, "a cessation of life and not a
violent act of nature," said his friend and biographer, Wasianski.' 2
41
To the fiance of his brother's daughter, Pastor K. C. Schoen, April 23,
i3O2 [892].
42
Quoted in K. Vorländer, Immanuel Kants Leben (2d ed.; Leipzig: Felix
Meiner, 1 9 2 1 ) , p. 207.
32. • Introduction
The Letters
From J. G. Hamann, July 27,
- II - VOL. x, pp. j-16
Honored tutor,
I do not hold it against you that you are my rival or that
you have enjoyed your new friend [Berens] for weeks during all
of which I only saw him for a few scattered hours, like a phantom
or even more like a clever scout.1 I shall however bear this grudge
against your friend, that he ventured to introduce you yourself
into my very own seclusion; and that he not only tempted me to
let you see my sensiuvity, wrath, and jealousy but even exposed
you to the danger of getting quite close to a man whom the disease
of his passions has given an intensity of thinking and of feeling
that a healthy person does not possess. This is what I wanted to
say to your sweetheart right in the ear when I thanked you for the
honor of your first visit.
if you are Socrates and your friend wants to be Alcibiades, then
for your instruction you need the voice of a genius. And that role
is one I was born for; nor can I be suspected of pride in saying this
—an actor lays aside his royal mask, no longer walks and speaks
on suits, as soon as he leaves the stage—allow me therefore to be
called "genius" and to speak to you as a genius out of the clouds,
as long as I am writing this letter. But if I am to speak as a genius,
I beg that you give me at least the patience and attentiveness with
which an illustrious, handsome, clever, and informed public re-
cently heard the farewell address of a mortal concerning the
fragments of an urn on which one could with effort decipher the
1
This letter from Hamann to Kant was written shortly after Kant and J. C.
Berens ( 1 7 2 9 - 9 2 ) visited Hamann in Königsberg. The point of the visit was
to convert Hamann away from the orthodox Chrisdanity he had recently
embraced. Before Hamann's trip to London in 1757 and his sudden conver-
sion, he and Berens had both been enamored of deism and world citizenship.
In an effort to restore him to what Berens and Kant regarded as sanity, Kant
tried to persuade Hamann to translate some articles from the French 'Ency-
clopedic. As is obvious from this letter, the efforts of Kant and Berens were in
vain.
2
The allusion is to the academic farewell address of Matthias Friedrich
Watson, professor of poetry in Königsberg, 1756-59. Hamann thought the
speech incredible. Evidently it consisted largely of autobiographical anecdotes,
together with extracts from a book entitled Critical Outline of a Selected
Library [Bibliothek.] for Friends of Philosophy and Belles-Lettres.
3
The famous Encyclopedic ou Dictionnaire Raisonee des Sciences, des Arts
et des Metiers ( 1 7 5 1 ) .
4
The article, "Beau," is by Diderot. In its historical introduction, there is a
discussion of Francis Hutcheson's aesthetics.
5
N . A. Boulanger's article, "Corvee."
6
Ovid Heroides, Epis. X V , v. 53-56 (trans, by Grant Showerman; Cam-
bridge, Mass.: Loeb Classical Library, 1 9 1 4 ) .
7
Ovid Amores 2, 5, 31 f. (trans, by Grant Showerman; Cambridge, Mass.:
Loeb Classical Library, 1 9 1 4 ) .
9
Charles Batteux, Les Beaux Arts Reduits a urt Me me Principe (Paris,
1 7 4 7 ) , P- 9: "The spirit which is father to the arts must imitate nature."
10
Prov. 21:1.
II
Ps. 1 9 : 1 0 - 1 1 .
12
Ps. 1 1 9 : 72, 99-ioo, 98.
13
Monsieur Jourdain. in Moliere's Le Bourgeois Gentilhomme, Act II, scene
6.
14
Prov. 2 5 : 2 .
15
William Hogarth's The Analysis of Beauty (London, 1753).
Dear sir:
I believe that the similarity of our ways of thinking will
excuse this letter, its frankness, and the omission of customary
21
The allusion is to Herodotus' story concerning the treasure of Rhampsin-
itos. See his History, Bk. II, chap. 1 2 1 .
22
From the eighth stanza of the song, "Sei Lob und Ehr' dem Höchsten
Gut," by the famous Johann Schütz (1640-90).
23
Gen. 1 1 : 7 - 9 .
1
Gotthilf Christian Reccard ( 1 7 3 5 - 9 8 ) came to Königsberg as professor of
theology in 1765.
•Johann Georg Suizer ( 1 7 2 0 - 7 9 ) , aesthetician, member of the Berlin
Academy of Sciences, and one of the men to whom Kant rent his inaugural
dissertation for review. His letter to Kant of December 8, 1770 [62], con-
tains some interesting remarks on space and time, but for some reason
Kant did not take his criticisms as seriously as he did those of Lambert and
Mendelssohn.
3
Neues Organon oder Gedanken über die Erforschung und Bezeichnung
des Wahren und dessen Unterscheidung vom Irrthum und Schein ("New
Organon, or Thoughts on the Discovery and Designation of Truth and its
Differentiation from Error and Appearance") (Leipzig, 1764).
4
Anlage zur Architectonic oder Theorie des Einfachen und des Ersten in
der philosophischen und mathematischen Erkenntr.iss ("Oudine of Architec-
tonic, or Theory of the Simple and Primary Elements of Philosophical and
Mathematical Knowledge") (Riga, 1 7 7 1 ) .
3
See Kant's Werk?, II, 68 f., for the preface to Kant's Only Possible Proof
of the Existence of God, in which a footnote refers to his earlier General
Natural History and Theory of the Heavens (Allgemeine Naturgeschichte und
Theorie des Himmels) and to Lambert's agreement with ideas on the
formation of the world, the Milky Way, and the fixed stars, as expressed in
Lambert's Cosmological Letters of 1 7 6 1 . Kant's General Natural History was
published in 1755, but the publisher went bankrupt just as the book came out.
As a result, Kant's theories, specifically the nebular hypothesis, were not well
known to Lambert and other physicists. Laplace, forty-one years later, does not
mention Kant's book.
7
Cosmological Letters on the Establishment of the Universe (Cosmologische
Briefe über die Einrichtung des Weltbauses [Augsburg, 1 7 6 1 ] ) .
3
An Original Theory and New Hypothesis of the Universe, by Thomas
Wright of Durham ( 1 7 5 0 ) . Kant credits this work with stimulating his own
composition of the General Natural History. Kant knew of Wright's ideas
from a 1 7 5 1 review of his book in a Hamburg newspaper.
J . H . LAMBERT
, Professor and member of the
Royal Academy of Sciences
Berlin
Dear sir:
1
Kant's Metaphysiche Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft did not in fact
appear unti! twenty years later, 1786. No "metaphysical foundations of
practical philosophy" was ever published by Kant. See L . W . Beck's Commen-
tary on Kant's Critique of Practical Reason (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, i960), chap, i, for a full account of Kant's plans, and changes of plans,
for a book on the foundations of ethics.
From J. H. Lambert,N o v e m b e r1 3 , 1 7 6 5• 49
From f . H. Lambert, February IJ66
- 37 - VOL. X, Pp. 62-6j
Dear sir,
Dear sir,
For your kind efforts in forwarding the writings I sent
you, I again send my sincerest thanks and my readiness to recipro-
cate in any way that I might be of service.1
The unfavorable impression you express concerning the tone of
my little book proves to me that you have formed a good opinion
of the sincerity of my character, and your very reluctance to see
that character ambiguously expressed is both precious and pleas-
ing to me. In fact, you shall never have cause to change this
opinion. For though there may be flaws that even the most
steadfast determination cannot eradicate completely, I shall cer-
tainly never become a fickle or fraudulent person, after having
devoted the largest part of my life to studying how to despise those
things that tend to corrupt one's character. Losing the self-respect
that stems from a sense of honesty would therefore be the greatest
evil that could, but most certainly shall not, befall me. Although I
am absolutely convinced of many things that I shall never have the
courage to say, I shall never say anything I do not believe.
I don't know whether, in reading this rather untidily completed
book, you noticed certain indications of my reluctance to write it.
For I saw that my prying inquiry into Swedenborg's "visions"
would make a great stir among people who knew him personally
1
T h e letter is a reply to Mendelssohn's letter, not extant, of some time
between February 7 and April 8. On the former date, Kant replied to another
letter of Mendelssohn's (also not extant). He expressed his pleasure at the
prospect of a correspondence with Mendelssohn and asked him to forward
some copies of Kant's Dreams of a Ghost-Seer Explained by Dreams oj
Metaphysics (Träume eines Geistersehers, erläutert durch Träume der Meta-
physic^ [ 1 7 6 6 ] ) to various gentlemen (including Lambert). Kant referred to
the book as einige Träumerey ("some reveries") and added: "It is, as it were,
a casual piece, containing not so much a working out of these questions as a
hasty sketch of the way they should be decided." He asked for Mendelssohn's
opinion. As is evident from Kant's reply, the opinion was not what Kant had
hoped. Mendelssohn was offended by what he took to be the tone of Kant's
essay, "between jest and earnest."
Noble sir,
Honored professor,
I am taking advantage of the opportunity I have of
sending you my [inaugural] dissertation by way of the respondent
of that work, a capable Jewish student of mine. At the same time,
I should like to destroy an unpleasant misunderstanding caused by
my protracted delay in answering your valued letter. The reason
was none other than the striking importance of what I gleaned
from that letter, and this occasioned the long postponement of a
suitable answer. Since I had spent much time investigating the
science [metaphysics] on which you focused your attention there,
for I was attempting to discover the nature and if possible the
evident and immutable laws of that science, it could not have
pleased me more that a man of such discriminating acuteness and
universality of insight, with whose method of thinking I had often
been in agreement, should offer his services tor a united testing
and pursuit of the pian for the secure construction of this science. I
could not persuade myself to send you anything less than a clear
summary of how I view this science and a definite idea of the
proper method for it. The carrying out of this intention entangled
me in investigations that were new to me and, what with my
exhausting academic work, necessitated one postponement after
another. For perhaps a year now, I believe I have arrived at a
position that, I flatter myself, I shall never have to change, even
though extensions will be needed, a position from which all sorts
of metaphysical questions can be examined according to wholly
certain and easy criteria. The extent to which these questions can
or cannot be resolved will be decidable with certainty.
I could summarize this whole science, as far as its nature, the
sources of its judgments, and the method with which one can
progress in it are concerned; and this summary could be made in a
rather small space, namely, in a few letters, to be submitted to your
thorough and knowledgeable judgment. It is that judgment for
Dear sir,
Your letter and also your dissertation concerning the
sensible and intellectual world gave me great pleasure, especially
because I regard the latter as a sample of how metaphysics and
ethics could be improved. I hope very much that your new position
may occasion more of such essays, since you have not decided to
publish it separately.
You remind me of my suggestion of five years ago, of a possible
future collaboration. I wrote to Mr. Holland 1 about it at that time,
and would have written to some other scholars, too, had not the
book catalogs shown me that belles-lettres are displacing everything
1
Georg Jonathan Kolland ( 1 7 4 2 - 8 4 ) , mathematician and philosopher.
2
The propositions are as follows: ( 1 ) The idea of time does not originate
in, but is presupposed by, the senses. (2) The idea of time is singular, not
general. (3) The idea of time, therefore, is an intuition . . . not a sensuous
but a pure intuition. (4) Time is a continuous quantity. . . . (Kant's Werk.e,
II, 398 ff.)
3
In discussing the fourth proposition (see n. 2), Kant argues: " A contin-
uous quantity is one that does not consist of simple parts. . . . The metaphys-
ical [Leibnizian] law of continuity is this: All changes are continuous or
Sowing, that is, opposite states succeed each other only by an intermediate
series of different states." Lambert is criticising the Wolffian metaphysics,
which maintained that "if in a composite the parts are arranged next to each
other in turn in such an order that it is absolutely impossible that others be
placed between them in some other order, then the composite is called a
continuum. By the agency of God, continuity precludes the possible existence
of a distinct part intermediate between two adjoining parts." (See Christian
Wolff, Philosophia prima, Sive Ontologia [173Ö], No. 554, and Cosmologia
Generalis [ 1 7 3 1 ], Nos. 176 ff.)
* " T i m e is the subjective condition necessary, because of the nature of the
human mind, for co-ordinating any sensible objects among themselves by
means of a certain law." (Kant's IVer^e, II, 400.)
Noble sir,
Distinguished professor,
Mr. Marcus Herz, who is indebted to you for your
instruction and even more for the wisdom you imparted to him in
your personal association, continues gloriously on the path that he
began under your tutelage. I endeavor to encourage his progress a
little through my friendship. I am sincerely fond of him and have
the pleasure of almost daily conversations with him. Nature has
truly been generous to him. He has a clear understanding, a gentle
heart, a controlled imagination, and a certain subtlety of mind that
seems to be peculiar to that race. But how lucky for him that these
natural gifts were so early led on the path of truth and goodness.
How many people, without this good fortune, left to themselves in
the immeasurable region of truth and error, have had to consume
their valuable time and best energies in a hundred vain attempts,
so that they lacked both time and power to follow the right road
when at last, after much groping about, they found it. Would that
I might have had a Kant for a friend before my twentieth year!
Your dissertation has now reached my eager hands, and I have
read it with much pleasure. Unfortunately my nervous infirmities
make it impossible for me of late to give as much effort of thought
to a speculative work of this stature as it deserves. One can see that
Noble sir,
Esteemed friend,
You do me no injustice if you become indignant at the
total absence of my replies; but lest you draw any disagreeable
conclusions from it, let me appeal to your understanding of the
way I think. Instead of excuses, I shall give you a brief account of
the kind of things that have occupied my thoughts and that cause
me to put off letter-writing in my idle hours. After your departure
from Königsberg I examined once more, in the intervals between
my professional duties and my sorely needed relaxation, the project
that we had debated, in order to adapt it to the whole of philoso-
phy and other knowledge and in order to understand its extent
1
Herz's Betrachtungen aus der spekulativen Weltwetsheit ( 1 7 7 1 ) .
2
Sec Lambert's letter of October 1 3 , 1770 [ 6 1 ] .
I. K A N T
Königsberg
. Noble sir,
Esteemed friend,
It pleases me to receive news of the good progress of your
endeavors, but even more to see the signs of kind remembrance
r, April 28, I J J ; • 81
mysterious heip of God, we shall (without meritorious "works" of
any sort) partake of this divine supplement. Now, it is very clear
that the apostles took this btblical doctrine of divine aid as the
fundamental thesis of the Gospels, and whatever might be the
actual basis of our salvation from God's point of view, the aposdes
took the essential requirement for salvadon to be not the honoring
of the holy teacher's religious doctrine of conduct but rather the
veneration of this teacher himself and a sort of wooing of favor by
means of ingrauation and encomium—the very things against
which that teacher had so explicidy and repeatedly preached.
Their procedure was in fact more suitable for those times (for
which they were writing, without concern for later ages) than for
our own. For in those days the old miracles had to be opposed by
new miracles, and Jewish dogmas by Christian dogmas.
Here I must quickly break off, postponing the rest till my next
letter (which I enclose). My most devoted compliments to your
worthy friend Mr. Pfenniger.
Noble sir,
Esteemed professor,
With sincerest pleasure I take this opportunity, while
carrying out an assignment I have been given, to let you know of
my great sympathy for your excellent school, the Philanthropin.
Mr. Robert Motherby, a local English merchant and my dear
friend, would like to entrust his only son, George Motherby, to the
care of your school. Mr. Motherby's principles agree completely
Noble doctor,
Dearest friend,
Today Mr. Mendelssohn, your worthy friend and mine
(for so I flatter myself), is departing. To have a man like him in
Königsberg on a permanent basis, as an indmate acquaintance, a
man of such gende temperament, good spirits, and enlightenment
—how that would give my soul the nourishment it has lacked so
completely here, a nourishment I miss more and more as I grow
older! For as far as bodily nourishment goes, you know I hardly
worry about that and I am quite content with my share of earthly
goods. I fear I did not manage to take full advantage of my one
opportunity to enjoy this rare man, partly because I worried about
interfering with his business here. The day before yesterday he
honored me by attending two of my lectures, taking potluck, so to
speak, since the table was not set for such a distinguished guest.
The lecture must have seemed somewhat incoherent to him, since
I had to spend most of the hour reviewing what I "had said before
vacation. The clarity and order of the original lecture were largely
absent. Please help me to keep up my friendship with this fine
man.
You have made me two presents, dear friend, that show me
that both in talent and in feeling you are that rare student who
makes all the effort that goes into my often thankless job seem
amply rewarded.
Your book for doctors was thoroughly appealing to me and
gave me genuine pleasure, though I cannot take the slightest credit
for the honor it will bring you. 1 An observant, practical mind
shines through the book, along with that subtle handling of
general ideas that I have noticed in you before. You are sure to
achieve disunction in the medical profession if you continue to
practice the art not simply as a means of livelihood but as a way of
1
Briefe an Aerzte (Mitau, 1 7 7 7 ) .
2
Johann Gerhard Trümmer.
3
Donald Monro (1729—92), An Essay on the Dropsy and its Different
Species (London, 1756). A German translation bv K. C. Krause was published
in Leipzig, 1777.
1
Herz had requested a set of lecture notes that he might use in Berlin for
his o w n lectures on Kant's philosophy.
1
Ksrl Abraham von Zedlitz ( 1 7 3 1 - 9 3 ) , minister of education in the
Department of Spiritual Affairs, to whom Kant dedicated the Critique.
In the current Easter book fair there will appear a book of mine,
entided Critique of Pure Reason. It is being published by Hart-
Esteemed sir,
I received your letter of November ist on the 10th. I have
an obligation to satisfy your request in regard to Lambert's corre-
spondence, an obligation that is based not only on my duty to the
distinguished man's literary estate but on my own interests as well,
1
Mendelssohn wrote, in a letter to Elise Reimarus, January 5, 17S4: "Very
nice to hear that your brother does not think much of the 'Critique of Pure
Reason.' For my part, I must admit that I don't understand it. The summary
that Mr. Garve put in the Bibliotek. is clear to me, but other people say that
Garve didn't understand him properly. It is therefore pleasant to know that I
am not missing much if I go thence without understanding this work."
Honored sir,
* [Kant's footnote] The key is already provided, though its initial use is
unfamiliar and therefore difficult. It consists in this: that all objects that are
given to us can be interpreted in two ways [nach zweyerley Begriffen nehmen
kar. ]: on the one hand, as appearances; on the other hand, as things in
themselves. If one takes appearances to be things in themselves and demands
of those appearances the absolutely unconditioned in the series of conditions,
one gets into nothing but contradictions. These contradictions, however, fall
away when one shows that there cannot be anything wholly unconditioned
among appearances; such a thing could only be a thing in itself. On the other
hand, if one takes a thing in itself (which can contain the condition of
something in the world) to be an appearance, one creates contradictions where
none are necessary, for example, in the matter of freedom; and this contradic-
tion fails away as soon as attention is paid to the variable meaning that objects
can have.
1
Possibly the foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, which appeared in
April, 1785.
2
David Friedländer, friend of Herz and Mendelssohn ( 1 7 5 0 - 1 8 3 4 ) , a
merchant in Königsberg who later became a banker and Stadrat in Berlin.
1
Johann Schultz ( 1 7 3 9 - 1 8 0 5 ) , court preacher, professor of mathematics in
Königsberg, and Kant's favorite expositor.
2
In his postcript to a letter of August 2 1 , 1783 [208] Schultz asked
"whether in each of the four groups of categories, the third category might
not be derived from the first, as follows: totality is a plurality in which no
unity is lacking or negated; limitation is a reality containing negation;
community is that condition of a substance in which cause and effect are
considered together; necessity is the impossibility of non-existence."
You will be kind enough to forgive me, dear sir, for failing to
answer your two most excellent letters, but business and other
3
Kant also added this remark to the second edition of the Critique,
B 1 1 0 f.
4
Leibniz, in his Dissertation de arte combinatoria ( 1 6 6 6 ) , proposed a sort
of universal algebra that would exhibit the relations among simple ideas. The
bask thought was that all complex ideas are compounded from a certain
number of simple ideas and that, by constructing an ideal language, the
properly selected name of a complex idea would show immediately what the
constituent simple ideas were—in other words, that the analysis of the
complex could be seen at a glance. The "Art of Combination" would be a
method of invention whereby all the possible combinations of simple ideas
would be shown, providing a table of all the possibilities in the world.
1
That is, the review of the Critique written by Garve but mutilated by
Feder.
2
Erläuterungen über des Herrn Professor Kant Krittk_ der reinen Vernunft,
1784.
3
See the letter of August 26, 1783 [ 2 1 0 ] .
J . SCHULTZ
Since there is mail leaving for West Prussia I shall send along
this note to you, to express my eternal esteem for you and to assure
you that I think of you always with the deepest feelings of which
my soul is capable. I have been very ill this winter and am still
suffering from eye trouble that makes me utterly unfit for work.
But now I hope to get better. Because my father happens to be
sending letters to Graudenz today, I am writing these few words
to thank you for your kindness in carrying out my request, as your
letter of Februarv. 3 informed me.2 Trustingo in the very/ noble
sentiments I know you to have, I am taking the liberty again of
sending three thalers to that same woman, with my most humble
1
Entde^te Theorie der Parallelen nebst einer Untersuchung über den
Ursprung ihrer bisherigen Schwierigkeit (Königsberg, 1 7 8 4 ) .
1
Friedrich Victor Leberecht Plessing ( 1 7 4 9 - 1 8 0 6 ) . See Introduction, pp.
2 3 - 2 4 , and the letter of April 3, 1784 [ 2 2 8 ] .
2
Kant acted as intermediary in transmitting money from Plessing to a
woman whose child Plessing was accused of fathering. See also the letter of
April 3 , 1784 [ 2 2 8 ] .
3
George Friedrich John ( 1 7 4 2 - 1 8 0 0 ) , author and financial officer.
4
Johann Georg Schrepfer ( 1 7 3 9 - 7 4 ) , a leading apostle of Rosicrucianism,
also a cafe proprietor in Leipzig. He was influential in the highest government
circles, for example, on Bischoffswerder, 'a favorite of Friedrich Wilhelm
II's.
5
Joseph II of Austria (1741—50) issued his toleration edict in 1 7 8 1 .
Plessing
Dear sir,
Esteemed sir,
My heartfelt thanks for the trouble and the care that you
have up till now always taken on my behalf. I shall never cease to
acknowledge my indebtedness for it. The thought of you will be
with me always.
I want to answer your letter immediately. 1 You are a just man
and have an ardent feeling for the duties of humanity, and
therefore your displeasure is aroused against a certain unnamed
man, because you believe that he has not adequately done his duty
6
The inhabitants of Abdera were considered proverbially stupid by the
ancient Greeks, though Protagoras and Democritus also lived in this Thracian
town.
' J o h a n n August Urlsperger ( 1 7 2 8 - 1 8 0 6 ) . The society was the Deutsche
Christentums Gesellschaft zur Beförderung reiner Lehre und wahrer Gottselig-
keit ("German Christian Society for the Advancement of Pure Doctrine and
True Piety").
8
Johann Esias Silberschlag; Apitch was a merchant.
9
Frederick the Great died in 1786.
1
Sometime in March, 1784; not extant.
Esteemed teacher,
You will receive, dearest teacher, via Mr. D. Joel, a copy
of my Essay on Vertigo [Versuch über den Schwindel], which I
mentioned in my letter of 25 November. I once expressed the main
idea of the work in one of the conversations I was fortunate
enough to have with you—I still recall all of them with delight.
The idea lay in my mind awaiting adequate knowledge of physiol-
ogy before it could have whatever weak influence it may have on
practice. You see, dearest sir, that I am not entirely disioval to you,
that I am much more a deserter who still wears your uniform and
who, while associating with other (not hostile) powers, is still in
your service. Or. to express myself less Prussianlv, 1 enjoy wander-
ing around the border towns of both countries, philosophy and
medicine, and it gives me joy when I can make suggestions and
arrangements for their common government. I think it would be a
good thing if similar border areas between philosophy and its
neighboring territories were diligently visited by philosophers as
well as by people in practical studies and artists of all sorts. The
one would avoid thereby the frequently valid charge of useless
meditation, the others that of empiricism.
What do you say to the uproar that has started up among our
preachers and inspired heads, exorcists and droll poets, enthusiasts
and musicians, since and concerning Moses' [Mendelssohn] death,
an uproar for which the counselor of Pimplendorf [Pempelfort—
the reference is to F. H. Jacobi] gave the signal? 1 If only a man
3
See Kant's Werlte, VIII, 58-66.
1
For a general account of the Mendelssohn-Jacobi feud, see the Introduction
to this volume of letters. The uproar to which Herz refers is enormously
Concerning Spinoza's
complicated. Mendelssohn had replied to Jacobi's book.
Theory. Moses Men-
The reply appeared after Mendelssohn's death, entitled
delssohn to the Friends of Lessing: An Appendix to Mr. Jacobi's Corre-
I found the lovely work 1 with which you have once again made
me a present worthy of you, my dearest friend, as far as I have
read—for my current distractions (on account of which I beg you
also to forgive the brevity of this letter) have not allowed me the
time to read it through completely.
The Jacobi [-Mendelssohn] controversy is nothing serious; it is
only an affectation of inspired fanatics trying to make a name for
themselves and is hardly worthy of a serious refutation. It is pos-
sible that I shall publish something in the Berliner Monatsschrift
to expose this fraud. 2 Reichardt, too, has been infected with the
genius-disease and associates himself with the chosen ones. It is all
the same to him how he does it, as long as he can make a big
impression, as an author no less, and as to that too much has been
granted him. I regret very much that no usable manuscripts can be
1 Versuch über den Schwindel. Cf. letter from Herz, February 27, 1786
[260].
2
See Kant's essay, What Is Orientation in Thinking?
Esteemed sir,
3
Car! Hemmerde, printer in Halle.
4
Friedrich August Grunert, printer in Halle.
5
The Critique of Judgment appeared in 1790. On Kant's "dogmatic" plans,
see the introduction to this collection of letters, p. 29, n. 34.
6
Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten ( 1 7 1 4 - 6 2 ) , aesthetician and professor of
philosophy in Frankfurt and elsewhere, whose works Kant used as text-
books.
[Berens tells of his travels through West Prussia. Kant and his
Critique are taking hold in Halle, Leipzig, and elsewhere. As yet
there is no actual intrigue against Kant's philosophy, but teachers
are reluctant to abandon their old ways and dislike seeing the
foundations of their system undermined.]
. . . Plattner 2 refused to discuss your philosophy; he said only
"We teach Kant" [wir lesen Kanten}. His elegant lectures are
more on philosophizing than on philosophy as such. The year
draws to a close; otherwise I would have liked to lock up
Wieland 3 and Reinhoid,4 both of whom are very enthusiastic
about [the Critique of] Pure Reason, or so their countrymen tell
me. Wieland maintains that if it is Kant who has denned the
limits of .the understanding we can all rest contented with that
position. Reinhoid, a former Capuchin monk or even Jesuit 3 but a
thoroughly intelligent, unprejudiced man (he was in Berlin re-
cently), weeps, or so Dr. Biester 5 told me, when he hears that
your holy doctrine is not vet universally recognized. Prof. Eber-
hard 7 fears the moral consequences of your new philosophy and
thinks you should have followed the old view. Your former
admirer, Prof. Ulrich,3 is becoming your enemy, since Reinhoid
has taken away his laurels. . . . So far we still have freedom of
1
Johann Cristoph Berens ( 1 7 2 9 - 9 2 ) , merchant, friend of Kant's and
Hamann's.
2
E r n s t Plattner ( 1 7 4 4 - 1 8 1 3 ) , professor of medicine and physiology in
Leipzig.
3
Christoph Martin Wieland ( 1 7 3 3 — 1 8 1 3 ) , the famous German author.
4
Karl Leonhard Reinhoid ( 1 7 5 8 - 1 8 2 3 ) , son-in-law of Wieland, who be-
came one of Kant's most famous disciples and popularizers. See the various
letters to and from Kant in this collection.
3
Jesuit.
6
Johann Erich Biester ( 1 7 4 9 - 1 8 1 6 ) . See his letter of October 5, 1793
[596], n. 1 .
' Johann August Eberhard ( 1 7 3 8 - 1 8 0 9 ) , professor of philosophy in Halle,
opponent of Kant's. On Eberhard, see Kant's letters to Reinhoid of May 1 2
and 19, 1789 [359 and 3 6 0 ] .
3
Johann August Heinrich Ulrich ( 1 7 4 4 - 1 8 0 7 ) , professor of philosophy in
Jena.
. . . I was very pleased to learn at last that you are the author of
those excellent Letters} I had asked the printer Mr. Grunert in
Halle to send you a copy of my Critique of Practical Reason as a
small token of my respect, but till now I did not know your exact
address and Grunert was therefore unable to carry out my request.
If you would please show him the enclosed letter he will do it if he
sdll has copies. This little book will sufficiently resolve the many
contradicdons that the followers of the old guard philosophy
imagine they see in my Critique, and at the same time the
contradictions in which they themselves are unavoidably involved
if they refuse to abandon their botched job are made perspicu-
ous. . . .
Without becoming guiity of self-conceit, I can assure you that the
longer I continue on my path the less worried I become that any
contradicuon or alliance (of the sort that is common nowadays)
will ever significantly damage my system. My inner conviction
grows, as I discover in working on different topics that not only
does my system remain self-consistent but also, when somedmes I
cannot see the right way to investigate a certain subject, I find that
I need only look back at the general picture of the elements of
knowledge, and of the mental powers pertaining to them, in order
to discover elucidadons I had not expected. I am now at work on
the critique of taste, and I have discovered a kind of a priori
principle different from those heretofore observed. For there are
three faculties of the mind: the faculty of cognition, the faculty of
feeling pleasure and displeasure, and the faculty of desire. In the
Critique of Pure (theoretical) Reason, I found a priori principles
1
Kar! Leonhard Reinhold ( 1 7 5 8 - 1 8 2 3 ) , professor of philosophy in Jena,
then Kiel, one of Kant's most important popularizers, disciples, and later,
apostates. His Letters on the Kantian Philosophy (Briefe über die Kantische
Philosophie [ 1 7 8 6 - 8 8 ] ) did much to bring Kant's ideas to the public.
I . KAMT
Esteemed sir,
Filled with the veneration owed to a man who has
reformed philosophy and thereby reformed all other sciences as
well, I am emboldened to approach you only by the love of
truth.
Condemned at birth to live out the best years of my life in the
woods of Lithuania, deprived of every assistance in acquiring
knowledge, I finally had the good fortune to get to Berlin, late
though it was. Here the support of certain noble-minded persons
has put me in a position to study the sciences. It was natural, I
think, that my eagerness to arrive at my main goal—the truth—
should make me neglect to some extent those subordinate studies,
language, method, and so on. Therefore, for a long time I dared
not make any of my thoughts public, to expose them to a world
whose taste is currently so sophisticated, even though I had read
various systems of philosophy, had thought through them and,
now and then, discovered something new. Finally I was lucky
enough to see your immortal book, to study it, and to reconstruct
the whole of my thinking in order to come into accord with it. I
have tried as hard as I can to draw the final implications from this
work, to impress them on my memory, and to seek out the track
of the main argument, so that I might penetrate the author's mind.
With this end in view, I have written down my results and have
made a few comments, mainly concerning the following points:
1. The distinction you draw between analytic and synthetic
propositions and the reality of the latter.
1
David Hartley ( 1 7 0 5 - 5 7 ) . The book referred to is his Observations on
Man, His Frame, His Duty, and His Expectations (London, 1749). Part I, Ch.
III, Sec. II, deals with mathematical judgments.
2
Thomas Reid ( 1 7 1 0 - 9 6 ) .
3
Joseph Priestley, Hartley's Theory of the Human Mind: On the Principle
of the Association of Ideas (London, 1 7 7 5 ) , Ch. III, Sec. Ill, Prop. 41.
1
"On the Distinction between Analytic and Synthetic Judgments."
2
Eberhard wrote: "The distinction between analytic and synthetic judg-
ments would seem to be this: analytic judgments are those whose predicates
state the essence or some of the essential parts of the subject; those whose
predicates assert no determination belonging to the essence or to the essential
parts of the subject are synthetic. This is what Mr. Kant must say, if he
presents the contrast so that the first are merely explicative and the latter are
ampliative, insofar as we can make anything definite out of his explana-
tion."
4
Reinhoid used Kant's replies to Eberhard in the fena Allgemeine Litera-
turzeitung, 1789. Kant's polemical essay On a Discovery according to Which
Any New Critique of Pure Reason Has Been Made Superfluous by a Previous
One (Ueber eine Entdeckung, nach der alle neue Kritik der reinen Vernunft
durch eine ältere entbehrlich gemacht werden soll) appeared in 1790; see
Werke, VIII, pp. 1 8 5 - 2 5 1 , and 492-97.
3
Eberhard attacks the question, "Can we attribute external reality—a
possibility or actuality—beyond our cognitive power" to objects that we judge
to be external? His proof that external objects are actual is then derived from
"healthy reason" [gesunden Vernuft], which requires "true objects external to
it," corresponding to those representations that are not grounded in the subject
himself.
1
Maimon wrote: "The material completeness of a concept, insofar as this
completeness cannot be given in intuition, is an idea of the understanding
[V erstandsidee]. For example, the understanding dictates a rule or condition
to itself: that from a given point, an infinite number of equal lines can be
drawn. Out of this (by the uniting of their end points), the concept of a circle
is produced. The possibility of this rule, and thus the possibility of the concept
itself, can be shown in intuition (by the movement of a line around a given
point). Consequendy, the formal completeness (the unity in the manifold) can
also be shown. However, its material completeness (in the manifold) cannot
be given in intuition, for one can always draw only a finite number of lines
equal to one another. It is therefore not a concept of the understanding
[Verstandsbegriff] to which an object corresponds but only an idea of the
understanding [Verstandsidee], which one can approach asymptotically in
intuition by means of the successive production of such lines. It is thus a
limiting concept [Gränzbegriff]." Versuch über die Transcendentalphilosophie
(Berlin, 1790), pp. 75 f. Cf. Maimon's letter to Kant of April 7, 1789 [ 3 5 2 ] ,
p. 1 3 3 .
Esteemed sir:
The gift from Count von Windisch-Graetz,1 containing
his philosophical essays, has arrived (thanks to you and to Privy
Commercial Counselor R. Fischer), and I have also received the
first edition of Histoire metaphysique . . . from the book dealer
Sixt.
Please thank the Count for me and assure him of my respect for
his philosophical talent, a talent that he combines with the noblest
atdtudes of a cosmopolite. In the last mendoned work, I observed
with pleasure that the Count discusses, with the clarity and mod-
esty of one who is at home in the great world, the same matters
with which I in my scholastic fashion have also been concerned,
viz., the definition and encouragement of human nature's noblest
incentives [Triebfedern], incendves that have so often been con-
fused with (and even taken for) physical urges and that have
failed to produce the results that one rightfully expects of them. I
long passionately to see him complete this work, for it obviously is
systematically related to his other two books (the one on secret
sociedes and the one on voluntary changes of the constitution in
monarchies). This system would certainly have great influence,
pardy as a wonderfully realized prophecy, partly as sage counsel to
despots, in the current European crisis. No statesman has hereto-
fore inquired so deeply into the principles of the art of governing
men or has even known how to go about such an inquiry. But that
1
Joseph Nicolaus v. Windisch-Graetz ( 1 7 4 4 - 1 8 0 2 ) , a writer on political
philosophy, whom Kant mentions also in Perpetual Peace. His position
resembled Kant's on several points; for example, he insisted that human
activity could not be understood in terms of merely passive sensations, he
rejected eudaemonism, and he argued that the idea of immortality must be
based on virtue, not vice versa. The writings to which Kant alludes are:
Solution provisoire d'un Probleme, ou Histoire metaphysique de I'organiza-
tion antmale (1789), Objections aux societes secretes ( 1 7 8 8 ) , and 2 dis-
course on the question whether a monarch has the right to change a
constitution (1789).
than ever, Kant's friend Berens wrote to him. One man wanted to print
Luther's essay on freedom of thought, especially the sentence, "Knights,
Bishops, and Nobles are fools if they meddle in matters of faith." Berens
thought that similar passages written by the late Frederick the Great should be
published as an appendix. He asked Kant (as had others before him) to
express his views on the problem in Biester's journal, the Berliner Monats-
schrift.
For a time, Wöllner pretended to be friendly to Kant, allowing Kiesewetter
to lecture on Kant's philosophy (though with his own spy sometimes in
attendance). See Kiesewetter's letter of June 14, 1791 [474].
5
Levin von Geysau, a Prussian army officer.
8
Friedrich August III ( 1 7 6 3 - 1 8 1 7 ) ; after 1806, as king, Friedrich August
I.
7
Julie von Voss, Countess Lugenheim, another mistress of Friedrich Wil-
helm II ( 1 7 6 7 - 8 9 ) .
8
Dr. Carl Brown, royal physician.
9
Against Austria.
10
W . J. H. v. Möllendort, general field marshall, governor of Berlin
(1724-1816).
11
Carl Wm. Ferdinand, Prussian field marshall ( 1 7 3 5 - 1 8 0 6 ) .
12
D u k e of York ( 1 7 6 3 - 1 8 2 7 ) .
13
Girolamo Lucchesini ( 1 7 5 2 - 1 8 2 5 ) , Italian by birth, at that time sent to
Warsaw by Friedrich Wilhelm II as envoy extraordinary and minister plenipo-
tentiary.
14
March 3, 1790 [409], in Werke, XI, 1 3 7 .
10
Andreas Jakob Hecker ( 1 7 4 6 - 1 8 1 9 ) , chaplain at the Dreifaltigkeitskirche
and, from 1785, director of the united institutes of the royal Realschule.
16
Johann Julius Hecker ( 1 7 0 7 - 6 8 ) , founder of the Realschule in Berlin.
Dearest professor,
[Kiesewetter apologizes for not writing. He sends Kant a
copy of his new logic book, which he has dedicated to Kant.] . . .
* Georg Christoph Lichtenberg ( 1 7 4 2 - ^ 9 ) . In 1791 Lichtenberg published
an edition of "Erxleben's book.
Great Kant,
As a believer calls to his God, I call upon you for help,
for solace, or for counsel to prepare me for death. The reasons you
gave in your books were sufficient to convince me of a future
existence—that is why I have recourse to you—only I found
nothing, nothing at all for this life, nothing that could replace the
good I have lost. For I loved an object that seemed to me to
encompass everything within itself, so that I lived only for him.
He was the opposite of everything else for me, and everything else
seemed to me a bauble, and I really felt as if human beings were
7
Prince Friedrich, Duke of York ( 1 7 6 3 - 1 8 2 7 ) married Princess Friederike
Charlotte Ulrike Katharine, daughter of Friedrich Wilhelm's first marriage.
8
Friedrich Wilhelm Snell ( 1 7 6 1 - 1 8 2 7 ) , Darstellung and Erläuterung der
Kantischen Kritik, der ästhetischen Urtheilskrajt (Mannheim, 1791 and
1792).
9
Karl Spatzier ( 1 7 6 1 - 1 8 0 5 ) , Versuch einer kurzen und jasslichen Darstel-
lung der teleologischen Principien, ein Auszug aus Kants Kritik der teleolo-
gische Urtheilskraft (Neuwied, 1 7 9 1 ) .
Dear sir,
Esteemed professor,
I know how unjust is any man who robs you of the least
bit of your time, so precious to the world. I know that nothing
could be more important to you than to complete your work. Yet I
cannot refrain from bothering you, with just this one letter.
I vowed some dme ago that I would henceforth read nothing
but your books. I am totally convinced by the skeptical part of
your Critique. As for the dogmatic part, it can be assumed
hypothetically and, even though I have constructed a psychological
deduction of the categories and ideas (which I attribute not to the
understanding and to reason but to the power of imagination), I
can nevertheless grant what you propound as at least problem-
atical. Thus I have made my peace with the Critique very nicely.
To K. L. Reinhold, September.21,
- 487 - VOL. XI, pp. 28J-89
1
T h e reference is to Reinhold's Versuch einer neuen Theorie des menschli-
chen Vorstellungsvermögens (1789).
* Probably the first part of Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen
Vernunft ("Religion within the Limits of Reason A l o n e " ) .
Your
I. KANT
Königsberg
P.S. Please mail the enclosed letters right away.
Dear brother,
1
In his letter of January 23, 1792 [ 5 0 1 ] , Fichte explains his position on
faith and miracles. No miracle as such can be proved. There might be other
good grounds for believing a revelation, however; viz., the miracles it reports
may inspire awe in the mind of someone who needs this. But a revelation can
extend neither our dogmatic nor our moral knowledge, since it concerns
transcendent objects of which we may believe the "that" but cannot know the
" h o w . " It might be "subjectively true" for someone who wants to believe it;
but it is not knowledge. (Kant's Werke, XI, 3 1 7 . )
Fichte's manuscript, " A Critique of Revelation" ("Versuch einer Kritik aller
Offenbarung"), had been denied the Imprimatur by J. L. Schulze, dean of the
theological faculty in the University of Halle. Schulze's successor, G. C.
Knapp, however, allowed the book to be published without any changes. Since
the work appeared anonymously, and was published by the Königsberg
publisher Härtung (at Kant's suggestion), many people believed it to be by
Kant himself. This was the start of Fichte's career. As Kant indicates in the
present letter, he had not actually read the book before recommending it to
Härtung. See also a letter to Borowski [485], not included in this book.
2
Kant, after refusing to lend Fichte some money for which he had asked,
had secured him a position as private tutor in the household of Count
Reinhold of Crackow.
Your deeply felt letter is the product of a heart that must have
been created for the sake of virtue and honesty, since it is so
receptive to instruction in those qualities, instruction that will not
stoop to flattery. I am thus compelled to do as you asked, namely,
to put myself in your place and to reflect on the prescription for a
pure moral sedative (the only thorough kind) for you. The object
of your love must be just as sincere and respectful of virtue and
uprightness, the spirit of virtue, as you are, though I do not know
whether your relationship to him is one of marriage or merely
friendship. I take it as probable from what you say that it is the
latter, but it makes no significant difference for the problem that
disturbs you. For love, be it for one's spouse or for a friend,
presupposes the same mutual esteem for the other's character,
without which it is no more than a very perishable, sensual
delusion.
A love like that, the only virtuous love (for the other sort is only
a blind inciination), wants to communicate itself completely, and
it expects of its respondent a similar sharing of heart, unweakened
by any distrustful reticence. That is how it should be and that is
what the ideal of friendship demands. But there is in man an
element of improbity, which puts a limit on such candor, in some
men more than in others. Even the sages of old complained of this
obstacle to the mutual outpouring of the heart, this secret distrust
and reticence, which makes a man keep some part of his thoughts
locked within himself, even when he is most intimate with his
confidant: "My dear friends, there is no such thing as a friend!"
And yet the superior soul passionately desires friendship, regard-
ing it as the sweetest thing a human life may contain. Only with
candor can it prevail.
This reticence, however, this want of candor—a candor that,
taking mankind en masse, we cannot expect of people, since
everyone fears that to reveal himself completely would make him
despised by others—is still very different from that lack of sincerity
that consists in dishonesty in the actual expression of our thoughts.
BECK
[. . . Beck sends back the part of his manuscript dealing with the
deduction of the categories. He reports on conversations between
Garve and Eberhard. As much as Garve defended the Critique of
Pure Reason, he was forced to admit that critical idealism was
identical to Berkeleian idealism. Beck cannot agree.]
Even if we assume that the Critique should not even have
mentioned the distinction between things-in-themselves and ap-
pearances, we would still have to recall that one must pay attention
to the conditions under which something is an object. If we ignore
these, we fall into error. Appearances are the objects of intuition,
and they are what everybody means when he speaks of objects that
surround us. But it is the reality of just these objects that Berkeley
denies and that the Critique, on the other hand, defends. If one
once sees that space and time are the conditions of the intuiting of
objects and then considers what the conditions of the thinking of
objects are, one sees easily that the dignity that representations
achieve in referring to objects consists in the fact that the synthesis
of the manifold is thus thought as necessary. This determination
of thought is, however, the same as the function in a judgment. In
this way the contribution of the categories to our knowledge has
become clear to me, in that the investigation has made me see that
they are the concepts through which the manifold of a sensuous
intuition is presented as necessarily (valid for everyone) grasped
together. Certain summarizers, as I see it, have expressed them-
selves incorrecdy on this matter. They say, T o judge means to
grasp objective representations together. It is quite another thing
when the Critique tells us: T o judge is to bring representations to
an objective unity of consciousness, through which the activity of
synthesis, represented as necessary, is expressed. . . .
1
Gottlob Ernst Schulze ( 1 7 6 1 - 1 8 3 3 ) , known as "Aenesidemus-Schulze"
because of his book Aenesidemus, which appeared anonymously in 1792. The
full ride of the work is Aenesidemus; or, On the Foundations of Professor
Reinhoid of fena's Elementarphilosophie, together with a Defense of Skepti-
cism against the Presumptions of the Critique of Reason. Schulze, who was
later Schopenhauer's teacher, was one of the sharpest critics of Kant and
Reinhoid. Like Jacobi, he argued that it was inconsistent to make an
unknowable thing in itself the cause of the "material" of experience, since
causality is supposed to be a mere form of the subject's thinking. Schulze
maintained further that Kant had refuted neither the skepticism of Hume nor
the idealism of Berkeley and that Kant's position was in fact "dogmatic."
I. KANT
Just as little I think, can one hold those people responsible who
ERHARD
1
Daughter of Kant's friend Robert Motherby, an English merchant in
Königsberg.
2
From Maria von Herbert.
3
B. Erhard to Kant, January 1 7 , 1793 [ 5 3 7 ] .
. . . The plan I prescribed for myself a long dme ago calls for an
examination of the field of pure philosophy with a view to solving
three problems: ( i ) What can I know? (metaphysics). (2) What
ought I to do? (moral philosophy). (3) What may I hope?
(philosophy of religion). A fourth question ought to follow,
finally: What is man? (anthropology, a subject on which I have
lectured for over twenty years). With the enclosed work, Religion
within the Limits [of Reason Alone], I have tried to complete the
third part of my plan. In this book I have proceeded conscien-
tiously and with genuine respect for the Christian religion but also
with a befitting candor, concealing nothing but rather presenting
openly the way in which I believe that a possible union of
Christianity with the purest practical reason is possible.
The biblical theologican can oppose reason only with another
reason or with force, and if he intends to avoid the criticism that
attends the latter move (in the current crisis, when freedom of
public expression is universally restricted, the appeal to force is
much to be feared), he must show our rational grounds to be
weak, if he thinks ours are wrong, by offering other rational
grounds. He must not attack us with anathemas launched from
out of the clouds over officialdom. This is what I meant to say in
my Preface on page xix. The complete education of a biblical
theologian should unite into one system the products of his own
powers and whatever contrary lessons he can learn from philoso-
phy. (My book is that sort of combination.) By assessing his
doctrines from the point of view of rational grounds, he shall be
armed against any future attack.
Perhaps you will be alienated by my Preface, which is in a way
rather violent. What occasioned it was this: the whole book was
supposed to appear in four issues of the Berliner Monatsschrift,
1
Carl Friedrick Stäudlin 1761—1826), professor of theology in Göttingen.
Kant dedicated his Der Streit der jakultäten ("Strife of the Faculties" [ 1 7 9 8 ] )
to Stäudlin.
1
Nicholaus Tilling, theology student in Mitau and Jena (1769—1823).
.Your servant,
I. KANT
Esteemed professor,
I took the liberty of sending you a litde tub of Teltow
turnips1 about two weeks ago and I would have informed you
sooner had I not wished to include thefirstissue of the Philoso-
3
In a footnote to Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone Kant calls
Schiller's essay a "masterful treatise" and explains how he agrees and
disagrees with Schiller. See Kant's Werke, VI, 23 f., or the translation by T .
M. Greene and H. H. Hudson (New York: Harper & Bros., i960), 18 f.
4
In Thalia ( 1 7 9 3 ) , second issue, published separately.
1
Kant was enormously fond of these turnips. Kiesewetter kept him regu-
larly supplied for a number of years. Some of Kant's last letters deal with
Teltow turnips, requesting more and discussing the proper way to cook them.
1
See letter of December 4, 1792 [549], n. 1, for further details about
Aenesidemus.
. . . If your muse should permit it, you know how grateful all
your readers would be for another essay.
I have had the opportunity of reading your defense submitted to
the Department of Spiritual Affairs, concerning the accusation
against your Religion within the Limits of Reason.1 It is noble,
manly, meritorious, thorough. But everyone will regret your vol-
untary promise not to discuss positive and natural religion any
more. You thereby prepare a great triumph for the enemies of the
Enlightenment, and the good cause suffers a great loss. It seems to
me that you did not need to make this promise. You could have
continued to write on the topics in question, in the philosophical
and respectable way you always have, which you justify so excel-
lently. Granted, you would then perhaps have had to defend
yourself again on specific points. Or you could even have remained
silent for the rest of your life but without giving these people the
satisfaction of being released from the fear of your words. I say,
for the rest of your life; for people will in any event continue to
work on the great philosophical and theological enlightenment
that you have so happily begun, and we may hope that at least our
descendants may someday (perhaps it will be soon) read these
works and use them—of that we are all convinced, out of our love
for reason and morality.
Be well, excellent man, and be for us ever an example of how a
wise and noble person can maintain his calm and inner peace, even
when reason is threatened by storms.
BIESTER
1
See Kant's letter of sometime after October 1 2 , 1 7 9 4 [642], to Friedrich
Wilhelm II.
Esteemed sir,
I am always delighted to know and engage in literary
discussions with such a talented and learned man as you, my
dearest friend. I received the plan for a periodical that you sent me
last summer and also the twofirstmonthly issues. I found your Let-
ters on the Aesthetic Education of Mankind splendid, and I shall
study them so as to be able to give you my thoughts about them-
The paper on sexual differences in organic nature, in the second
issue, is impossible for me to decipher, even though the author
seems to be an intelligent fellow.2 There was once a severely
critical discussion in the Allgemeine Ltteraturzeitung about the
ideas expressed in the letters of Mr. Hube of Thorn 3 concerning a
similar relationship extending throughout nature. The ideas were
attacked as romantic twaddle [Schwärmerei]. To be sure, we
somedmes find something like that running through our heads,
without knowing 0
what to make of it. The organization
o
of nature
has always struck me as amazing and as a sort of chasm of
thought; I mean, the idea that fertilization, in both realms of
nature, always needs two sexes in order for the species to be
propagated. After all, we don't want to believe that providence has
chosen this arrangement, almost playfully, for the sake of variety.
On the contrary, we have reason to believe that propagation is not
possible in any other way. This opens a prospect on what lies
beyond thefieldof vision, out of which, however, we can unfortu-
1
Friedrich Schiller ( 1 7 5 9 - 1 8 0 5 ) , the great poet and essayist, wrote to Kant,
June 1 3 , 1794, asking Kant to contribute an essay to a new literary magazine,
Die Horen (12 vols., 1 7 9 5 - 9 7 ) . He assures Kant of his devotion to Kant's
moral system and expresses profuse gratitude to K a n t for illuminating his
spirit. On March j , 1 7 9 5 , Schiller wrote again, repeating his request and
sending two issues of Die Horen. He confesses that he is the author of the
Letters on the Aesthetic Education of the Human Race, a work he believes
to be an application of Kant's philosophy and hopes that Kant will like it.
2
The article was by Wilhelm von Humboldt: "Ueber den Geschlechts
unterschied und dessen Einfluss auf die organirche N a t u r . "
3
Johann Michael Hube ( 1 7 3 7 - 1 8 0 7 ) , director and professor at the military
academy in Warsaw, author or a book on natural science (Naturlehre).
221
To Friedrich Schüler, March 30,1795 '
nately make nothing, as little as out of what Milton's angel told
Adam about the creation: "Male light of distant suns mixes itself
with female, for purposes unknown." 4 I feel that it may harm
your magazine not to have the authors sign their names, to make
themselves thus responsible for their considered opinions; the
reading public is very eager to know who they are.
For your gift, then, I offer my most respectful thanks; with
regard to my small contribution to this journal, your present to the
public, I must however beg a somewhat lengthy postponement.
Since discussions of political and religious topics are currently
subject to certain restrictions and there are hardly any other
matters, at least at this time, that interest the general reading
public, one must keep one's eye on this change of the weather, so
as to conform prudently to the times.
Please greec Professor Fichte and give him my thanks for
sending me his various works. I would have done this myself but-
for the discomfort of ageing that oppresses me, with ail the mani-
fold tasks I still have before me, which, however, excuses nothing
but my postponement. Please give my regards also to Messrs. Schütz
and Hufeland.
And so, dearest sir, I wish your talents and your worthy objec-
tives the strength, health, and long life they deserve, and also the
friendship, with which you wish to honor one who is ever
Your most devoted, loyal servant,
I. K A N T
1
Johann August Schlettwein ( 1 7 3 1 - 1 8 0 2 ) , prominent German physiocrat.
This letter is a reply to an open letter to Kant, published by Schlettwein in the
Berlinische Blätter, September, 1797 ( 7 5 1 , in Kant's Werke, XII, 362-66.)
Schlettwein's letter is incredibly insulting, accusing Kant of contempt for his
great predecessors and contemporaries, of pride, self-love, and self-seeking, the
arrogant claim of infallibility and originality, and so on. He calls it a scandal
that so-called critical philosophers dispute the sense and spirit of Kant's works
and asks Kant to say which one of his disciples has understood him correctly.
Schlettwein claims to have a refutation of Kant ready but does not in fact state
any arguments. A hint of his own position is given in the assertion that "true
philosophy teaches the incontrovertible doctrine of the reality of an infinite
power, the forces of nature, and the marvelous and sublime properties and
capacities of physical and spiritual man." He states that philosophy, in its
practical part, should seek to bring people ever closer to God, "not by means
of a loveless, despotic categorical imperative, contrary to the very nature of
reason, but through the gende, all-powerful tie of love that animates ail
things" (p. 366).
Kant's answer appeared in the Allgemeine Literaturzettung on June 14,
1797. Schlettwein responded with another open letter (753, Werke, XII,
368-70), which is uninteresting. A lost letter of Kant's, May 19, 1797, is
alluded to in it.
Esteemed sir,
. . . You say that the purpose of your letter 1 is the swift
and public removal of a disagreement over the fundamental prin-
ciples of the critical philosophy. And Court Preacher [Schultz]
attributes to me the claim that "reality is the original synthesis of
the homogeneous in sensation, which proceeds from the whole to
its parts."2 (The question must be yours, sir, when he asks, quite
1
Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi ( 1 7 4 3 - 1 8 1 9 ) , the well-known "philosopher of
faith" who fought Mendelssohn. David Hume über den Glauben was
published in 17S7.
1
Sometime before June 20, 1797; the letter is not extant.
2
Beck in fact wrote that the category of reality is the original synthesis of
the homogeneous, proceeding from the whole to its part. See Kant's Werlte,
XIII, 452, and Beck's explanation in the next paragraph of the present letter.
3
Possibly an interpretation of Beck's claim that "the understanding origi-
nally posits a something [Etwas]."
* Cf. Critique of Pure Reason B 130.
5Principles of Philosophy, I, 53: "We can conceive extension without figure
or action."
Your Reverence,
Esteemed sir,
Your efforts in the investigation of my genealogy, rever-
end sir, and your kindness in informing me of your results,
2
Kant's parenthetical remark.
1
J a k o b Axelson Lindblom ( 1 7 4 6 - 1 S 1 9 ) , Swedish bishop.
Your Reverence's
KANT
Treasured friend,
I am content with Mr. Beck's decision to announce that
his Standpoint2 is not my own position but his. Let me only
remark on this point that when he proposes to start out with the
categories he is busying himself with the mere form of thinking,
that is, concepts without objects, concepts that as yet are without
any meaning.3 It is more natural to begin with the given, that is,
with intuitions insofar as these are possible a priori, furnishing us
with synthetic a priori propositions that disclose only the appear-
ances of objects. For then the claim that objects are intuited only
in accordance with the form in which the subject is affected by
them is seen to be certain and necessary.
It gave me pleasure to hear of your discussions with Mr. Beck
(please convey my respects to him). I hope they may bring about a
unanimity of purpose. I am also pleased to learn of your pians for
an explanatory summary of my critical writings, and I appre-
ciate your offering to let me collaborate on this work. May I take
the opportunity to ask you to keep my hypercritical friends Fichte
and Reinhoid in mind and to treat them with the circumspection
that their philosophical achievements fully merit.4
I am not surprised that my Doctrine of Right [Rechtslehre] has
found many enemies, in view of its attack on a number of principles
1
T h e first paragraph translated here is taken from a draft of this letter,
which Kant did not send.
~ The reference is to J.S. Beck's Only Possible Standpoint from Which the
Critical Philosophy May Be Judged.
3
Cf. Critique of Pure Reason 8 1 7 8 = A 139: ". . . Concepts are al-
together impossible, and can have no meaning, if no object is given for
them. . . . " Kant altered this to "are for us without meaning." See N. Kemp-
Smith's translation of the Critique (New York: Humanities Press, 1950), p.
181 n.
4
This often quoted remark, indicative of Kant's disappointment with his
erstwhile disciples, seems ironic in tone, but the corresponding lines in Kant's
unsent draft do not. There he writes, "I hope your explanatory summary may
lead my hypercritical friends back onto the path they once trod; but please do
it in a friendly w a y . " Werke, XIII. 463.
5
See Kant's Werkte, VI, 356 ft. and 5 1 9 . The review, which was published
in the Gättingische Anzeigen, February 18, 1797, was by Friedrich Bouterwek
( 1 7 6 6 - 1 8 2 8 ) , a philosopher who also corresponded with Kant.
6
K . L . Pörschke ( 1 7 5 1 - 1 8 1 2 ) , professor of poetry in Königsberg, wrote
Vorbereitungen zu einem populären Naturrechte ( 1 7 9 5 ) . He asks, " H o w is
natural right possible ' " and answers, "Man ought to be, and has to be no more
than, man; he is an animal and a rational being, and that he should remain."
The principle, "Man, be m a n ! " is the rational foundation of all duties,
according to Pörschke.
7 Der Streit der Fakultäten ("Strife of the Faculties"), Pts. I and II; the
work was in fact published in 1798. Johann Friedrich Gensichen ( 1 7 5 9 - 1 8 0 7 )
was one of Kant's dinner companions. He was professor (extraordinarius) of
mathematics.
2
" T h e Ground of the Distinction of All Objects in General into Phenomena
and Noumena," Bk. n , Chap. III. B 294 S. = A 235 ft.
Treasured friend,
Though I am distracted by a multitude of tasks that
interrupt one another while I think constantly of-myfinalgoal, the
completion of my project before it is too late, I am anxious to
clarify the sentence in the Critique of Pure Reason that you
mendoned in your kind letter of November 5, the sentence that
occurs on page 177 [A 138 = B 177, "The Schematism of the Pure
Concepts of Understanding"] and deals with the application of the
categories to experiences or appearances. I believe I now know
how to satisfy your worry and at the sametimehow to make this
part of the system of the Critique more clear. My remarks here,
however, must be taken as mere raw suggestions. We can make
the discussion more elegant after we have exchanged ideas on it
again.
The concept of the synthesized in general [des Zusammen-
gesetzten überhaupt] is not itself a particular category. Rather, it is
included in every category (as synthetic unity of apperception).
For that which is synthesized [that is, complex] cannot as such be
intuited; rather, the concept or consciousness of synthesizing (a
function that, as synthetic unity of apperception, is the foundation
of all the categories) must be presupposed in order to think the
manifold of intuition (that is, of what is given) as unified in one
consciousness. In other words, in order to think the object as
something that has been synthesized, I must presuppose the func-
tion of synthesizing; and this is accomplished by means of the
schematism of the faculty of judgment, whereby synthesizing is
related to inner sense, in conformity with the representation of
time, on the one hand, but also in conformity wjth the manifold of
intuition (the given), on the other hand. All the categories are
directed upon some material synthesized a priori; if this material is
homogeneous, they express mathematical functions, [and] if it is
not homogeneous, they express dynamic functions.1 Extensive
1
Sec Critique of Pure Reason B no.
Esteemed teacher,
The great and well-known Meckel asks to be commended
to the great, all-knowing Kant, via me, so little known, so little
knowing. I would hesitate greatly to satisfy this superfluous desire,
were it not an opportunity, long coveted, to call up in the mind of
my unforgettable mentor and friend the name of Herz and to tell
him once more how much the memory of those early years of my
education under his guidance still spreads joy over my whole
being and tell him how burning is my desire to see him again and
to embrace him again while there is still time. Why am I not a
great obstetrician, a cataract specialist, or healer of cancer, that I
might be summoned to Königsberg by some Russian aristocrat?
Alas, I have learned absolutely nothing! The little skill I possess
can be found tenfold in any village in Kamchatka, and thus I must
* [Kant's footnote] You will notice ray haste and brevity here, which might
be remedied in another essay.
2
In £act, the rumor was incorrect.
Index • 255
Beck and Tieftrunk and partic- Fichte, J. G., 8, i8(n.2o), 26,
ular topics 26(11.30), 27, 28, 29, 30,
Crusius, Christian August, 72, 31(^35), 186 f., 232 ff., 238,
144 250, 253 ff.
Form and matter o£ knowledge,
Deduction of pure concepts, 13, 51ff.,141 f.
175 Form and Principles of the Sen-
Definitions, 8, 9, 155 sible and Intelligible World,
Der einzig mögliche Beweisgrund The. See Inaugural dissertation
zu einer Demonstration des Formal science, 86, 102. See also
Daseins Gottes. See Only Pos- Form and matter of knowledge
sible Proof of the Existence of Foundations of the Metaphysics
God of Morals, 4(n.2), I07(n.i)
Dialectic of pure reason, 107 Frederick the Great, 19, 164(0.4)
Dönhoff, Sophie Juliane Frieder- Frederick William (Friedrich
ike Wilheimine Dönhoff, Count- Wilhelm) II, 19, 114(0.4),
ess of, marriage of, to Fried- 163ff.,173 f., 2x7-20
rich Wilhelm II, 163(0.2), 173 Freedom, 99 n., i6r f.
Dogmatic, 29(0.34), 196(11.1) French Revolution, 207, 209
Dogmatism, 145, 158 Friedländer, David, 107, 121 (n.x)
Dreams of a. Ghost-Seer Explained
by Dreams of Metaphysics, 9, Garve, Christian, 7, 7 n., 15, 16,
10, 12, 54(0.1) 28, 9Ö(n.i), 98-104, 107, 110.
195, 250 ff.
Eberhard, J. A., 18, 19, 126(0.7), General Natural History and
136-50, 195 Theory of the Heavens, 4(11.3),
Education, Kant's views on, 14 f., 46(0.6)
83-85 Gensichen, J. F., 4(0.3), 171 f.,
Encyclopedic ou Dictionnaire Rai- 239
sonee des Sciences, des Arts, et God, 40ff.,79-82, 84 f.
des Metiers, 36 Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von,
End of All Things, The (Das 8(n.8), 14, 23
Ground aod consequent, 138 f.,
Ende aller Dinge), 213
146 f.
Enge!, J. r„ 7. 86, i2o(n.r)
Grundlegung zur Metaphysi\ der
Enlightenment, 7, 8, rS(n.i9)
Sitten. See Foundations of the
Epicurus, 10 n. Metaphysics of Morals
Erhard, J. B., 24, 199 f., 203, 2x2
Erxleben, J. C. P., 171 Hamann, J. G., 4, 6, 13, 14,
Essence, logical vs. real, 139 i8(n.i8), 35-43, 99 t2t(n.i)
Hartkooch, J. F., 47, 94
Faith, 79-82, 186 f. Hartley, David, 135(0.1)
Feder, J. G. H., 7, 19, 31, 99, Hammg, G. L., 26(0.30)
122 (n.x) Herbert, Franz Paul von, 24
256 Index
Herbert, Maria von, 14 n., 24 ff., Josef II, emperor of Austria,
174 f., 188-90, 200-204 i8(n.i9), n4> 224
Herder, J. G. von, 41, 7, 18, Judgments, types of, 14S. See also
i8(n.i8), 90 n., 158 A priori; Analytic synthetic dis-
Hermes, H. D., 210, 213(3.4) tinction; Synthetic a priori judg-
Herz, Marcus, 3n., 5, ii(n.n), ments
12, 13, 26, 31, 31(21.40), 58. 60, Jung-Srilling, Heinrich, 131 f.
67. 70-79, 86-96, 120fi.,123 L,
248 f.; letter of 1772 to, 12 t. Kästner, A. G., 179(11.1)
Hillmer, G. F., 213 Kant, J. H., 31, 185
Hume, David, 13, 2S, 41 f., Kanter, J. J., 47, 50
I22(n.i), 135, 196(^1) Kant's family and genealogy, 31,
Hutcheson, Francis, 36, 36(^4) 185, 236 f.
Kant's health, 77, 88, 177, 211,
Ideality, 196. See also Space and 251 £
time Kierkegaard, S., 6(11.5)
Ideas of reason, 134, 142, 149, 180, Kiesewettcr, J. G. C. C., 31, :6i-
230 65, 172ff.,206 f., 209 5., 252 f.
Inaugural dissertation: Jh: Form Knobloch, Charlotte von, 4 (n.2)
and Principles of the Sensible Kraus, C. I. 90, 91. 93
and Intelligible World, 5. 10, Kritik der praktischer, Vernunft.
58-76.. 94, 109 See Critique of Practica Reason
Inner sense, 75, 130 Kriti\ der reinen Vernunft. See
inquiry into the Distinctness of Critique of Pure Reason
the Fundamental Principles of Kritik der Urteilskraft. See Cri-
Natural Theology and Morals, tique of Judgment
An, 8 Kroner, Richard, 28 a. :
Intuition, 52, 141 ff., 180 f., 184,
190 f.; intellectual, 19; pure, Lambert, J. K.. 4, 4(^3), 5, 10,
125, 141, 184, 246. See also 43-53. 58-67, 76. 86, 96-98,
Space and dme 3 ; . 17
Intuitive reason or understanding, Laplace, Marquis Pierre Simon
7, 156, 230 de, 4Ö(n.6)
Lavater, J. C., 14, 79-82
Jachmann,}. B., 134 ff. Lehmann, J. H. I., 31
Jacobi, F. H., 2:, 22, 22(11.23), Leibniz, Baron Gottfried Wilhelm
i2o(n.i), 123, X24(a-3)> 157^ von, 7, 11, 12, 13, 17, 19, 28, 51,
228 64, 109(11-4), 124(11.3), 148 t,
Jacobi, Maria Charlotte, 4(11.2) 152, 154, 177
Jakob, L. H., 29, 124! Lessing, G. E., 7, 22, 23, 86, 120
Jesuits, 17, 114 (n.i)
Jews, 27 n., 107 f., 136, 212. For Lichtenberg, G. C., 172
Kant's usual attitude, see his Lindbiom, J. A., 236 f.
letters to Herz and Mendelssohn Lindner, J. G.. 4(n.a)
Index • 257
Locke, John, 52,143 Nicolai, C. F., 7, 8
Love, 24 ff, 188 ff. NIcolovius, F., 31
Noumea a, 13
Maimon, Salomon, 26,133 t , 151-
56, 175 ff., 196 ff., 212 Objects, 16, 30, 7t, 103 a., 106,183
Malebranche, Nicolas, 72. On a Discovery according to
Marburg, University of, 122 (n.i) Which All Critique of Pure Rea-
Marital and extramarital relations, son Is Supposed to Be Obviated
Kant's views on, 23f., 115-18, by an Earlier One, 19, 142 n.
235 £. On the Common Saying, "That
Mathematics, 8, 11, 52£., 62-66, May Be True in Theory but Not
128-31, 135, 140,145 f., 148,155, in Practice," 208 (n.2)
166-69, 179 On the First Ground of the Dis-
Meiners, Christoph, 7, 122(0.1) tinction of Regions in Space, 11
Mendelssohn, Moses, 3 a. 4, 7, 3, (n.12)
9, 1 0 , 1 5 , IÖ, 2 1 , 2 2 , 5 4 - 5 7 , 6 7 - Only Possible Proof of the Exist-
70, 76, 86, 87, 96, 103, i o 5-8, ence af Gad, 5, 44, 46
i2o(n.i), 123 f., 124(0.3) Ontology, 125, 182
Metaphysical Foundations of Nat- Opus postumum, 31, 99 n., 252
ural Philosophy, 49, 49 n., 119,
170 Pantheismusstreit, 21 ff.
Metaphysics, 8, 9, ro, n , 29, 31,44, Paton, H. J.. 12(0.13)
48 ff-, 55» 57,59> 62, 64 £, 71, 95- Phenomena, 65; and noumeru, 61
97, 106, 125, 139, 144, 179, 182 Phenomenology, 59, 66
Metaphysics of Morals, 4(0.2), 59, Philanthropin, 15, 83-85
119, 132, 200, 207, 238 Platner (or Plattner), Ernst, 78,
Metaphysik, der Sitten. See Meta- 126
physics of Morals
Plato, 72, 143
Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der
Pleasure, 60, 68, 78,127
Naturwissenschaft. See Meta-
Plessing, F. V. L., IJ, 23 f., 1 1 3 -
physical Foundations of Natural
18
Philosophy
Mind and body, relation of, 56 f., Positing (Setzen), 241 ff.
79. See also Spiritual sub- Pre-established harmony, 39, 73,
stances 154
258 Index
Reecard, G. C-, 44, 86 Seile (Sell), C. G., 94, 162 £.
Receptivity, 183 Sensibility, 27, 29, 59, 97, 183, 297;
Rehberg, A. W., 166-69, 212(1^2), a priori, 109. See also Space and
2I N
3( -3) time
Reichardt, J. F., 94, 121 n. 123 Servants, Kant's attitude toward,
Reid, Thomas, 135
Reinhold, Karl Leonhard, 17, 18, Setzen. See Positing
10, 27 n., 28, 29, 126(11.4), I27 Shaftesbury, Anthony Ashley
136-50, 176 £., 177 ff., 1S0, Cooper, 3d Ear! of, :or.., 68
211 f., 217, 238, 253 Smith, Norman Kemp, I2(n.i3)
Religion, 6, 14, 15, 20, 21, 26 Snow, C. P., 5
(n.30), 79-82, 107 f., 131 f., 158, Soul, 9, 56 f.
186 f., 205, 217-20 Space and dme, 6, n, 52, 61-67,
Religion innerhalb der Grenzen 74-76, 125. 141. 163* 184, 193,
der blossen Vernunft. See Reli- 195, 196 ff.
gion within the Limits of Rea- Spinoza, Baruch, 21, 40, izß(n.i),
son Alone 15S
P.eiigior. within the Limits of Rea- Spiritual substances, 9 £., 55 ff.
son Alor.e, 14, 20, 178(0.2), Stäudlin, C. F., 205 £.
205 £., 200 n., 220. Stang, Conrad, 24,224 f.
Religious reacdon to Kant's phi- Streit der Faeultäten, Der. See
losophy, 17, 19, 20, 21, 1x3-14, Strife of the Faculties
i22(n.i), 163(11.4), 186 f., 206, Strife of the Faculties, I2(n.i4),
210 £., 217-20 2:7(n.i), 239(11.7), 249!
Representations, 30, 71, 151, 176 £.; Sufficient reason, principle of, 19,
content of, 183; objectivity of, 139-42,146 £.
191, 216, 228 Sulzer, J. G., 44, 57, 97
Reuss, Maternus, 24, 222 £. Swedenborg, Emanuel, 4(11.2), xo,
Richardson, J., 31 54, 57.160
Swift, Jonathan, 107
Scheiling, F. W. J., 29 Syncretism, 158
Schiller, Friedrich, 8, 31, 209, Synthesis (Zusammensetzung,
221 f. Verknüpfung), 26, 30, 44, 51,
Schlettwein, J. A., 226 n. 112, 129, 151, 169, r8i, 183, 191,
Schmid, C. F., 17,18 195, 214, 216, 232ff.,245-48
Schrepfer, J. G., 114 Synthetic a priori judgments, 13,
Schütz, C. G., 17,18, 26 E., 119 f., 106, 141 ff., 184. See also Ana-
234 ft. lytic-synthetic distinction; Math-
Schultz, Johann, 74, 99 a., 108-13, ematics
128-31, 208, 223, 227, 229-32 Synthetic unity, 198, 215. See also
Schulze, G. E. ("Aenesidemus"), Apperception
196,215
Schwärmerei (fanaticism, enthu- Teleology, 128, 208, 22X
siasm), 159/5., 221 Tetens, J. N., 96, 103, 107
Index • 259
Thing-in-itself, t6, 26, 27, 29, 30, Vleesehauwer, Herman J. de, 31
103 n., 195,2=3 =43 (n.35)
Tieftrunk, J, H., 26, 30, 238-50. Von dem ersten Grunde des Un-
Time, 62-65, 69 t., 75, 148, 198. terschiedes der Gegenden in
See also Intuition, pure; Space Raum. See On the First Ground
and rime of the Distinction of Regions in
Todes, Samuel J., 9 n. Space
Träume eines Geistersekers, erläu- Vorländer, Karl, 24, 24 a., 32
tert durch Träume der Meta- (11.42), 163(11.4)
physik- See Dreams of a Ghost-
Seer "Explained by Dreams of
Was heisst: Sich im Denken
Metaphysics
Truth, 144 onentiren? See What Is Orien-
Turnips, 31, 252 tation in Thinking?
Wasianski, E. A. C., 32
über den Gemeinspruch: "Das Weldon, T. D., 12(0.13)
mag in der Theorie richtig sein, What Is Orientation in Thinking?,
taugt aber nicht für die 21, 121 n., 123(0.2), 158 n.
Praxis." See On the Common Wieiand, C. M., iS(n.i9), 119
Saying, "That May Be True in (n.z), 120
Theory but Not in Practice" Will, 192
über die Buchmacherei (1798), 8 Windisch-Graetz, Joseph NIcolaus
über eine Entdeckung, nach der von, X5~(n.i)
alle neue Kritik der reinen WöUner, J. C., 103(0.4), 173
Vernunft durch eine ältere ent- Wolff (or Wolf), Christian, 17, 47,
behrlich gemacht u/erden soll.
51,62(0.3), 149.132, 179(0.:)
See On a Discovery According
Wolff, Robert Paul, 12 (n.:?), 64
to Which All Critique of Pure
(n-5)
Reason Is Supposed To Be Ob-
viated by an Earlier One Wolke, C. H., 14 f„ 33-85
Ulrich, J. A. H„ 18, i26(n.3) Woltersdorf, T. C. G., 173(3.:),
Understanding, spontaneity of, 210
71, 214 t, 228 t., 240-44 Women, Kant's attitude toward,
Untersuchung über die Deutlich- 25 f., 204. See also Kant's letters
keit der Grundsätze der na- to Maria von Herbert
türlichen Theologie und Moral. Wright, Thomas, 46(11.8)
See Inquiry into the Distinctness
of the Fundamental Principles Zedlitz, K. A. von, 8, 12, 91, 92,
of Natural Theology ar.d Mords 94
Zöllner, J. F., 163(0.3)
Verbinden. See Combine Zusammensetzung. See Combina-
Verknüpfung. See Synthesis ion; Synthesis
260 Index