The Problem of Epistemology
The Problem of Epistemology
The Problem of Epistemology
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Duke University Press and are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The Philosophical Review
1 This article connects itself with the previous paper on " Psychology, Episte
mology, and Metaphysics," which appeared in the second number of this journal.
2 Enquiry, section 12.
504
1 Obviously on such a hypothesis the designation " cognitive " applied to the states
is no longer appropriate, since they have ceased to be the instruments of knowledge.
pass over into him. At no point can the real world, as it were,
force an entrance into the closed sphere of the ideal; nor does
that sphere open at any point to receive into itself the smallest
atom of the real world, qucd real, though it has room within itself
ideally for the whole universe of God.
A critical Realism must start then with the acknowledgment
of this fact. This is the truth which both Locke and Kant had
got firm hold of. It is the basis of Locke's hypothetical Dual-
ism, and, so far as our present argument ig concerned, Kant's
relativistic phenomenalism with its inferential background of
things-in-themselves is substantially a similar theory with the
sceptical suggestions of Lockianism unfortunately emphasized.
From Locke and Kant as centres the epistemological specula-
tions of modern philosophy may be conveniently viewed. Now,
unquestionably, the transcendence of the real does give scep-
ticism its opportunity. Scepticism takes up its position in the
gap thus apparently made between the ideal and the real, and
asks how we know that we know the real things, what assur-
ance have we that the world of real things is as it appears to
us to be, nay, in the last resort, what assurance have we that
there is a world of real things at all. This sceptical insinua-
tion requires to be fairly met, for, however little it avails to
shake our practical certainty, the theoretic possibility of such
a doubt lies in the very nature of the case. So long as the
knower and that which he knows are not identical, so long is it
possible that his knowledge may not be true, i.e. may not cor-
rectly render the nature of what is. Hence a succession of
attempts to dispense with the otherness or transcendency of the
object known. Thus we find Berkeley inveighing against this
"groundless and absurd notion " as "' the very root of scep-
ticism." I The arguments used by sceptics in all ages, he says,
depend on the supposition of external objects.2 The temptation
accordingly is to abolish the independent world of real exist-
ences altogether, and to manipulate our perceptions or ideas
in such a way as to make them stand in its place. This is
the plan we find adopted by Berkeley partially, and in more
thorough-going fashion by Hume. Berkeley and Hume have