Problems of The Plane Representation of Space Geometry Figures
Problems of The Plane Representation of Space Geometry Figures
Problems of The Plane Representation of Space Geometry Figures
“KNOWING” VS “SEEING”.
PROBLEMS OF THE PLANE REPRESENTATION OF
SPACE GEOMETRY FIGURES
ABSTRACT. There is necessarily a loss of information when moving from a geometrical object
to its drawing. but pupils (even sixth graders) frequently have the illusion that they can, thanks
to a drawing sufficiently sophisticated and close to the object. make a representation of it in
which there is no ambiguity at all.
Similarly, when ‘reading’ a drawing, they tend to regard the properties of the drawing as
properties of the object itself. To illustrate this ‘knowing vs seeing’ conflict, two examples.
studied in three French sixth classes, are given one of ‘coding’, the other of ‘decoding’ a
drawing. They show clearly that it is necessary, at high school level, to make the rules for
drawing space geometrical figures explicit, these rules being not the concern of more or less
‘hazy’ conventions, but of projective geometrical properties.
geometry
2D 3D
properties of the representation appear only thanks to the reader’s good will
(restitution of the meaning ). Actually, such a restitution could not take place
without a connivance between the author of the representation (the transmit-
ter) and its reader (the receiver), it being possible only because of a common
geometrical culture. This connivance is concerned in the first place with the
nature of the objects represented, which belong to a restricted number of
types, constituting, so to speak. a reference stock of archetypes (point,
straight line, triangle, circle, plane, pyramid, cylinder . . .), any representa-
tion can then be linked to an -assembly” of such archetypes. This is partic-
ularly evident with computer-created images: for instance. a straight line or
a circle are most exceptionally represented by a drawing which can really
stand visually for what it is supposed to represent, not so much because of
the thickness of the line. as of the ‘thrust faults’ it shows. And, nevertheless,
in a great majority of cases, it is correctly identified.
On the other hand. some figures are not representable, because they are
unlimited (straight line, plane ... ): thus no concrete realization can give an
accurate account of them. The - impossible - representation of such figures
is traditionally replaced by that of a conventional limited part (segment for
a straight line, rectangle for a plane ... ). considered as taking the place of the
whole (geometrical metonymy ). Of course, this can be a source of ambiguity:
for instance, in plane geometry, does a representation. rightly identified as
being that of a segment, really represent a segment. or rather a straight line?
Thus, even at level 1, close to the original. the representation appears
insufficient by nature, like a metaphor in a way, and the necessary interpreta-
tion made by the receiver to give it a meaning might well be improper. Of
course, the weight of tradition helps to lessen such a risk but, on the one
hand it is sometimes insufficient, and on the other hand we shall come back
to that point later on it can be a source of other types of problems.
* level 0 level 2 : This is about drawings representing space figures. The
relationship between a geometrical object and its representation is even
‘hazier’ than in the case of plane geometry, and it often becomes difficult to
guess, from the drawing. some properties of the 3D figure itself. For in-
stance, in Drawing 1A (level 1). representing a square and its diagonals, the
perpendicularity of these can easily be conjectured, on the contrary, in Draw-
ing 1B (level 2). representing a regular pyramid with a square base, the
diagonals of that base and the perpendicular height, it is much less evident
to imagine that the height is perpendicular to the diagonals: one must first
bring to mind a close representation, of the ‘model’ type (and even make it),
if one wants to get to it. unless one is familiar enough with the properties of
3D objects.
82 BERNARD PARZYSZ
Drawing 1.
Drawing 2
and three points. A, B, C, in space. For each of these three points tell, from
the drawing, whether it is in the plane P or out of it, or if the drawing does
not allow to decide”. For the 109 pupils involved, the results were as follows:
Point A 81 0 28
Point B 0 78 31
Point C 1 63 45
Drawing 3
‘KNOWING’ VS ‘SEEING’ 85
right angles, etc. Only 18 pupils out of 88 did so, only two of them in a
sufficient way for determining the accurate nature of the represented figure.
This shows that it is not so evident for the pupils, even at such a level, that
the drawing cannot , by itself, substitute for the object.)
We studied the productions of the 88 pupils (30 and 33 in the two low-
sixth classes, and 25 in the sixth class), taking a special interest in the three
following points:
- Position of the image of the base with regard to the edges of the sheet.
- Shape of the image of the base.
- Position of the image of the top with regard to that of the base.
1. Position of the image of the Base with Regard to the Edges of the Sheet
The results are recorded on the frequency polygons of Drawing 4 (the two
lower-sixth classes are called 1S1 and 1S4, and the sixth class is called TD1).
Drawing 4.
86 BERNARD PARZYSZ
They show that the first case represents at least the three quarters of the total
number, which is not so surprising (it provides the object with a ‘base’), and,
when the quadrilateral is a parallelogram, it corresponds to the position of
the object in “perspective cavalière”, as it is called in French (that is, an
oblique parallel perspective, in which a reference cube has two sides parallel
to the projection plane. this type corresponds in fact to the ‘classical’ repre-
sentation of a cube, drawn backward from one face).
We have distinguished:
S. square
D: diamond ( ≠ square)
R. rectangle ( ≠ square)
P: parallelogram ( ≠ diamond, ≠ rectangle)
T: trapezium ( ≠ parallelogram)
X: other quadrilaterals
Drawing 5.
being square, the ideal thing would be to represent it by a square, but such
a picture of a pyramid is much less satisfactory, visually speaking. owing to
a lack of ‘relief’. On the contrary, representing the base by a parallelogram
preserves nothing but the parallelism of the sides. but the perspective effect
is much more convincing. Between these two opposite poles, we find the
diamond which. although preserving the main part of the visual advantage
of the parallelogram. keeps moreover the equality of length of the four sides.
Hence its success (39 per cent).
More precisely, the diamond presents both an advantage and an incon-
venience:
- inconvenience : the ratio of ‘reduction’ in the receding direction equals 1,
and then tends to make the square look too elongated in depth.
- advantage : the conservation of the equality of length for the four sides.
Therefore, the pupils who choose the ‘plain’ parallelogram stand on the
‘seeing’ side (they “present in order to see”), while those who prefer the
diamond stand more on the ‘knowing’ side (the “make known”). The latter
attitude corresponds in fact to the illusion that one can. thanks to a drawing
sufficiently sophisticated and close to the object, and to it alone, make a close
representation of it, without any ambiguity. In the present case, pupils would
have come to an optimal result. and in a more economical way, by the
drawing of a parallelogram. the oblique sides of which being shorter than the
horizontal ones (“present in order to see”), provided an indication of
the equality of length of the sides should have been added, for instance, with
88 BERNARD PARZYSZ
We have distinguished:
A: image of the top on a vertical line passing through the intersection of the
diagonals of the quadrilateral (this case corresponds to the ‘classical’
representation).
B: image of the top on the perpendicular bisector of the ‘lower’ side of the
quadrilateral.
C: image of the top on the perpendicular bisector of the ‘upper’ side of the
quadrilateral.
X: other cases.
Remark : The cases A. B and C are not exclusive of one another. In particu-
lar, in a ‘front’ view in parallel perspective, the three conditions are realized
simultaneously (Drawing 6 ). In such a case, we gave the priority to A over B
or C.
The frequency polygons in Drawing 7 show a clear predominance of case
A (about half the total number), which generally corresponds to the classical
representation. But we must also notice the non-negligible frequency of case
B (20 to 25 per cent), which was not expected initially. and which appeared
only at the examination of the productions.
This type of representation corresponds rather (but not inevitably in a
systematical way) to another priority in the construction of the representa-
Drawing 6
‘KNOWING’ VS ‘SEEING’ 89
Drawing 7
tion: instead of beginning by drawing the base. one represents first a lateral
side (as an isosceles mangle), and the rest follows. This is to be paralleled
with the classical drawing of a cube in “perspective cavalière” (a drawing
which all pupils of that level are familiar with): you start by drawing a
square. then draw the receding lines and complete.
It is to be noticed that, even in the case of a pyramid, this representation is
quite accurate, from a perspective point of view: it is enough to place the
pyramid so that the reference lateral side is frontal.
The compromise between the representation of ‘what is seen’ and that of
‘what is known’ can be expressed here in the following manner (which is
described usually by ‘mixture of perspectives’; but this expression is not quite
true in the present case):
The ‘mixture of perspectives’ would consist of imagining the pupil as
drawing first the fore side of the object, seen from the front (isosceles tri-
angle) but, becoming aware of the evident lack of relief of his drawing, he
would then transform it by a change of ‘point of view’. However, it
seems more likely to think that, from the beginning, the pupil has in mind
the representation as a whole: if he draws an isosceles triangle, it is not
because he wants to represent the pyramid seen from the front, but rather
because this element seems important to him for the identification of the
represented object: it is a matter of knowledge to be presented. Thus, there is
no interference between two perspectives, but integration of a knowledge into
a (unique) perspective, as when one represents the base of the pyramid by a
diamond.
Besides, let us notice that a representation like that of Drawing 6 preserves
the isosceles shape of two lateral sides, and that of Drawing 1A does so for
90 BERNARD PARZYSZ
the four sides! (In addition to that, these four isosceles triangles are admit-
tedly right-angled. which could not be the case for any pyramid.)
We can see now what proportion of the pupils have represented the pyra-
mid in the ‘classical’ way. This corresponds, let us remind it, to the following
characteristics:
2° P or D: base represented by a parallelogram (possibly a diamond);
3° A: top on the vertical line passing through the centre of the image of the
base.
On the whole there are 33 drawings out of 88 belonging to this type, that
is 37 per cent. the proportion varying from 27 (1S1) to 48 per cent (1S4),
according to the classes.
From that we can conclude that, even if the classical representation be-
longs to these pupils’ competence (they are able to recognize a regular pyra-
mid on a drawing completed with graphic indications), their performance is
not on the same level. for some of their productions hardly evoke a regular
pyramid (Drawing 8 ), even if they are perspectively accurate. For these
pupils. there is actually no conscious and deliberate choice of a perspective,
as well as a position of the object which “presents in order to see” (and
therefore can he used as a ‘support’ for thinking and reasoning), but a use -
more or less important and more or less empirical - of perspective effects,
with a concern for preserving some properties of the object.
Let us go back to the general case. the necessity for managing at best the
‘seeing’ vs ‘knowing’ conflict has led gradually the users of geometry to make
choices which, by reoccurring. have ended in constituting the “tradition”
which we alluded to above. As we said then. there are ‘classical’ drawings,
which can he traced ‘vertically’ from the eighteenth century to nowadays, as
well as ‘horizontally’, from one text-hook to another. That tradition has a
positive side: it allows us to recognize, at first sight, the object in question.
But it has a negative side too, insofar as it might well he restricting: the
pupils. accustomed to drawing a given figure in a given position (for
instance: the cube), lose sight of the ’why’ of that precise representation and
almost don’t think up any others. It is so for the regular tetrahedron,
traditionally represented in “perspective cavalière” with a horizontal side
(Drawing 9A ), and which should sometimes he of greater use if it is inscribed
in a cube (Drawing 9B ).
To conclude, we think that all this shows clearly. the necessity of working,
at least at high school level, on the very principles of the plane representation
of space figures, so its to manage to master them. and not to he a slave of
stereotyped drawings, which have finally lost a great part of their operating
power (cf. Vladimirskii, 1978).
‘KNOWING’ VS ‘SEEING’ 91
Drawing 8.
Drawing 9.
92 BERNARD PARZYSZ
BIBLIOGRAPHY