Gáspár Miklós Tamás About Class
Gáspár Miklós Tamás About Class
Gáspár Miklós Tamás About Class
One of the central questions of social theory has been the relationship between
class and knowledge, and this has also been a crucial question in the history of
socialism. Differences between people – acting and knowing subjects – may
influence our view of the possibility of valid cognition. If there are
irreconcilable discrepancies between people’s positions, going perhaps as far as
incommensurability, then unified and rational knowledge resulting from a
reasoned dialogue among persons is patently impossible. The Humean notion of
‘passions’, the Nietzschean notions of ‘resentment’ and ‘genealogy’, allude to
the possible influence of such an incommensurability upon our ability to
discover truth.
All versions of socialist endeavour can and should be classified into two
principal kinds, one inaugurated by Rousseau, the other by Marx. The two have
opposite visions of the social subject in need of liberation, and these visions
have determined everything from rarefied epistemological positions concerning
language and consciousness to social and political attitudes concerning wealth,
culture, equality, sexuality and much else. It must be said at the outset that
many, perhaps most socialists who have sincerely believed they were Marxists,
have in fact been Rousseauists. Freud has eloquently described resistances to
psychoanalysis; intuitive resistance to Marxism is no less widespread, even
among socialists. It is emotionally and intellectually difficult to be a Marxist
since it goes against the grain of moral indignation which is, of course, the main
reason people become socialists.
One of the greatest historians of the Left, E.P. Thompson, has synthesized
what can be best said of class in the tradition of Rousseauian socialism which
believes itself to be Marxian.1 The Making of the English Working Class is
universally – and rightly – recognized to be a masterpiece. Its beauty, moral
force and conceptual elegance originate in a few strikingly unusual articles of
faith: (1) that the working class is a worthy cultural competitor of the ruling
class; (2) that the Lebenswelt of the working class is socially and morally
superior to that of its exploiters; (3) that regardless of the outcome of the class
struggle, the autonomy and separateness of the working class is an intrinsic
social value; (4) that the class itself is constituted by the autopoiesis of its
rebellious political culture, including its re-interpretation of various traditions, as
well as by technology, wage labour, commodity production and the rest.
Whereas Karl Marx and Marxism aim at the abolition of the proletariat,
Thompson aims at the apotheosis and triumphant survival of the proletariat.
The main difference between Rousseau and Marx is that Rousseau seeks to
replace (stratified, hierarchical, dominated) society with the people (a purely
egalitarian and culturally self-sustaining, closed community), while Marx does
not want to ‘replace’ society by annihilating ‘rule’ and the ruling class as such,
but believes that capitalism (one specific kind of society) might end in a way in
which one of its fundamental classes, the proletariat, would abolish itself and
thereby abolish capitalism itself. It is implied (it is sous-entendu) that the moral
motive for such a self-abolition is the intolerable, abject condition of the
proletariat. Far from its excellence – extolled by the Rousseauians – it is, on the
contrary, its wretchedness, its total alienation, that makes it see that it has
‘nothing to lose but its chains’, and that it has ‘a world to win’. In the Marxist
view it is not the people’s excellence, superiority or merit that makes socialism –
the movement to supersede, to transcend capitalism – worthwhile but, on the
contrary, its being robbed of its very humanity. Moreover, there is no ‘people’,
there are only classes. Like the bourgeoisie itself, the working class is the result
of the destruction of a previous social order. Marx does not believe in the self-
creation or the self-invention of the working class, parallel to or alongside
capitalism, through the edification of an independent set of social values, habits
and techniques of resistance.
Marx is the poet of that Faustian demonism: only capitalism reveals the social,
and the final unmasking; the final apocalypse, the final revelation can be reached
by wading through the murk of estrangement which, seen historically, is unique
in its energy, in its diabolical force.5 Marx does not ‘oppose’ capitalism
ideologically; but Rousseau does. For Marx, it is history; for Rousseau, it is evil.
Rousseau thought that we would have remained both more virtuous and much
happier were we bereft or at least rid of mediation. He knew it was too late, and
his recipes for a solution are famously desperate; they take essentially the shape
of a purge, ‘cleansing’, épuration. All Rousseauian socialist solutions (for this
reason extremely popular in peasant societies, that is, in societies with a still
strong cultural recollection of peasant experience and ideals) aim at
simplification. Simplification towards a more natural (or, with luck, a
completely natural) way of life. It is, after all, Karl Polányi’s famous thesis that
market societies are not natural, that they are the exception rather than the rule
in history.7 On the one hand, he resists the idea that capitalism is a natural order,
whose emergence was only prevented in the past by scientific and technological
backwardness and blind superstition; and he resists the idea that competitiveness
and acquisitiveness are ‘instincts’ characteristic of all societies, only repressed
in the past by chivalric and religious ‘false consciousness’ (and here he is of one
mind with Marxists in ‘historicizing’ competition and the market.) On the other
hand, Polányi regards non-market societies as ‘natural’ for being in the historical
majority. He believed that we should orient our social action towards a re-
establishment of what modern capitalism has falsified.
The other great Rousseauian socialist Marcel Mauss has shown that most acts
of exchange in the history of humankind were motivated not by a desire for
gain, but for ostentatious display and the satisfaction of pride.8 Yet another
Rousseauian socialist, Georges Bataille, one of the few truly prophetic geniuses,
has generalized Mauss’s point in drawing attention to society’s need for
unproductive losses, waste and destruction, which contradicts any notion of
utility.9 Sacrifice, he reminds us, etymologically means ‘the production of the
sacred’. The sacred is the result of unnecessary bloodshed. Non-genital and non-
reproductive sexuality has long been considered ‘a waste’. All these elements
have been classified under the rubric of ‘the irrational’, since only equitable
exchange conforms to the official idea of rationality which cannot, ever, account
for a surplus which appears as ‘savage’ or ‘illusory’. But then, bourgeois
society, in the guise of ‘representative government’, has always equated ‘the
people’ with the ‘irrational’. The apposite clichés (savage ‘crowds’, ‘masses’)
have been inherited from the late Roman republic.
In the famous Second and Third Maxims of Book IV of his treatise on
education, Rousseau says: ‘One pities in others only those ills from which one
does not feel oneself exempt’. And: ‘The pity one has for another’s misfortune is
measured not by the quantity of that misfortune but by the sentiment which one
attributes to those who suffer it’.10 These maxims are the kernel of a manifesto
for solidarity. Pray consider: Rousseau does not presuppose anything else but
bare humanity in any individual. This presupposition is purely personal,
subjective, psychological – available through introspection. It is based, as is well
known, on fear: fear of suffering, which we can understand in others as well.
There is no external or ‘objective’ measure for suffering, nor is there any need
for it; it is sufficient for us to have a feeling for the perils lurking around us in
order to have a feeling for the probable predicament of others. We pity others to
the extent of our understanding and sympathy for a situation we can imagine
ourselves to have been in, and to the extent of our picturing their feelings at such
a juncture. On this small foundation stone – a pebble, really – is the edifice of a
solidary community built.
To wish to put an end to imaginable and avoidable suffering is enough for the
construction of social justice, since fear and imagination are natural givens in
the human animal, but there is another hidden idea here, an idea even more
revolutionary. This we could call the rejection of any and all theodicy. The
church explains suffering by sin. How could a benevolent and omnipotent God
cause suffering and death? Only as a retribution for something inherent in all
humans but at the same time willed by all humans: the original sin of
disobedience. (Reductionist theories of human nature play the same role in
modern agnostic societies.) If we do not think that original sin is indeed inherent
in human nature, suffering is unnecessary; and vice versa, if suffering is felt and
understood in others, if then it can be counterbalanced by the succour of those
who may not be good but who have an instinctive distaste for the ominous threat
of visible misfortune in their environment – well, then the plausibility of original
sin seems remote.
Human nature being tantamount to liberty, our true nature is the source of the
liberty that is falsified and denied to us; hence the assumption that those
enslaved are morally superior to the slavers. Rousseau’s theory suggests that
there is a separate culture and a separate morality inherent in the people; a
culture and a morality that attracts the sympathy and the solidarity of all persons
of good faith.
Why (and how) could modern socialists mistake the abolition of caste for the
abolition of class? There are several reasons.
One is the oldest conundrum of the workers’ movement, to wit, the fact that
wherever successful proletarian movements or revolutions have taken place,
they triumphed not against capitalism, but against quasi-feudal remnants of the
old regime that, naturally, went against their self-understanding and their self-
image. All the endlessly complicated debates about class consciousness are
influenced by this primordial fact. This is also why Arno Mayer’s theory
concerning ‘the persistence of the old regime’ is so crucial to Marxist debates.16
What did this mean in terms of its struggle? In the nineteenth century there
had to be struggles against throne and altar, for universal suffrage, for the right
to organize and to strike; then national unity was re-forged in the Great War as if
the class struggle could be switched off at will; after that war the proletariat
liberated the miserable Eastern peasantry that had been kept in a servile
condition (this was the most massive historical achievement of the communist
regimes18); later it had to create Popular Fronts and Résistance alliances against
the fascist peril – there was always something that prevented proletarian politics
(in Marx’s sense), apart from heroic episodes by revolutionary minorities.
The reasons for this in post-1914 socialism seem self-evident: the need for
self-legitimation of the workers’ movement in view of its defeat but persisting
power, and its repeated contribution to bourgeois revolutions liquidating the
semi-feudal remnants of the old regime. A dispensation oriented to transcending
capitalism remained – and still remains – utopian, while the ‘secular’ triumph of
social democracy in the West and the transformation of the old regime into a
tyrannical state capitalism under Bolshevik rule in the East offered a vindication
for the movement, justified mainly by a puritanical and egalitarian system closer
to Calvin’s and Rousseau’s Geneva than to Marx’s classical Walpurgis
night.19 ‘Welfarism’ was not limited to the West: the Soviet bloc’s idea of
legitimacy was also a steady growth of income, leisure and accessible social and
health services. ‘Planning’ was a common idea of Mao’s Red China and de
Gaulle’s bourgeois and patriotarde and pompiériste France. Jacobinism was
common to both. The staatstragende community, the addressee of welfare
statism and egalitarianism, had to be defined somehow: it was the people,
offered equal dignity by ‘citizenship’.
All this has pre-modern accents. It seems obvious that for the creation of ‘a
people’ the annihilation of the upper classes would be necessary, as in
eighteenth-century France, where only the Third Estate became the nation and
where class relations had been ethnicized (the aristocracy: Nordic; the people:
Celtic, Gallic; cf. Norman blood in England, Varangians in Russia, etc.). Class
identity of this kind is definitely pre-socialist. Socialist movements had used it in
the past, creating enormous difficulties for themselves later. Its use succeeded
only where they could combine the specific demands of the usually small and
culturally (and sometimes ethnically) ‘different’ proletariat, with the general (or
‘bourgeois’) democratic enthusiasms of the usually peasant, provincial majority
led by the middle classes and journalistic opinion: for republic instead of
monarchy, universal suffrage, anti-clericalism (or laïcité), agrarian reform (i.e.,
redistribution of land), reduction of birth privileges, a citizen army, ethnic
minority rights, votes for women, and the like.
This perhaps explains why the origin of capitalism, especially English capi-
talism, is such an important political question or Kampffrage. The ‘Brenner
Debate’ was and remains decisive in this respect. But it is in the work of Ellen
Meiksins Wood that all the threads come together, and the theoretical and
political consequences are most clearly stated.25 Answering Anderson’s harsh
questions about ‘the “absent centre” of English social thought’, Wood insisted:
‘The individualism and ahistoricism of English social thought, its fragmentation,
have more to do, then, with the advance of capitalism than with its
inhibition’.26 She characterizes the parallel and contrast with continental Europe
thus:
This seems to be the very opposite of Perry Anderson’s view. But it is, at the
same time, another Marxian correction of E.P. Thompson’s Rousseauism. The
emphasis in Wood’s work on the separateness or autonomy of the ‘economy’
and ‘the economic’ points, rather promisingly, I think, towards a much-needed
Marxian political science. This autonomy of the economy may account for
peculiarities in English political culture that would, according to Perry
Anderson, explain the lack of a radical socialism in Britain, the substitution of
‘class culture’ for ‘class’ and the notorious (and idealized) absence of great,
salvific social theorems in the national culture. But the sudden modernization of
Britain under Thatcher and Blair yields surprising results, as Anderson himself
recognizes in another of his breathtaking surveys:
Nevertheless, the problem remains: part of the Left will see ‘class’ in cultural
and political terms, and this is indeed an effective aid to sustaining an opposi-
tional stance against ‘a rotten regime’ in the name and on behalf of a people
judged capable of achieving for itself a cultural and moral autonomy vouchsafed
by a working-class politics.29 The case of England is crucial for several reasons:
it is traditionally ‘the distant mirror’ of capitalism.30 It cannot possibly be
denied that the shift to culture in class theory was and is caused by the fate of
socialism (i.e., of the workers’ movement): to succeed only in the sense of
making capitalism more modern, democratic, secular and (perhaps) egalitarian
via cross-class alliances forces the workers’ movement to abandon the specific
proletarian calling envisaged by Marx. Western and Northern social democrats,
Eastern and Southern communists alike have replaced emancipation with
equality, Marx with Rousseau. Marxian socialism has never been attempted
politically, especially not by Marxists.31 Egalitarianism and statism (in
democratic and tyrannical versions) were the hallmarks of the main official
versions of socialism, everywhere.
These are also the key elements of the contemporary popular image of
socialism, and the key elements of the colourful pop ideology of the ‘new social
movements’ as well, aiming at righting injustice by enlarging and radicalizing
the idea of equality and trying to impose this idea on the bourgeois states and
international financial organizations they despise (they themselves do not wish
to take power; theirs is an étatisme by proxy). The ‘statism by proxy’ of the new
social movements (we won’t vote for you, we won’t smash your power through
revolution, but we want you to draft bills and pass acts of parliament and UN
and EU resolutions that we deem useful and edifying), in spite of their many
beauties and quite a few successes, is still statism, experimenting with a radical
idea of equality of all living beings, hesitating between straight reformism and
utopian self-sufficiency and exodus.
For most of history, humanity was not thought to have been co-extensive with
humankind. Women, slaves, foreigners, children were almost invariably
excluded everywhere, but so were people who had to work for a living
(banausoi), people who had become retainers in a chieftain’s retinue, persons
exercising trades that were ideologically considered repellant or religiously
taboo, people with physical deficiencies, whole nations subjugated in war,
persons belonging to another religion or denomination, persons without
property, enemies of the state, members of ‘inferior’ races, and so on. These and
many others were not supposed to share with the rest the prerogatives of full-
fledged human beings. There was resistance to this state of affairs among some
Stoics, Cynics and Epicureans, the early Christians and some medieval heretics,
some Buddhists and other assorted riff-raff. But on the whole the title of ‘man’
(let alone of ‘citizen’, which is still limited by nation-states33) was a prerogative
circumscribed by criteria of excellence, hence the absence of an idea of equal
and universal rights and obligations.
Caste or ‘estate’ is a whole life, with dimensions capitalism has since nullified.
Let me quote a few words from the greatest authority on the caste system:
… the lot of the Shudras is to serve, and … the Vaishyas are the grazers
of cattle and the farmers, the ‘purveyors’ of sacrifice … who have been
given dominion over the animals, whereas the Brahmans-Kshatryas have
been given dominion over ‘all creatures’.… [T]he Kshatrya may order a
sacrifice as may the Vaishya, but only the Brahman may perform it. The
king is thus deprived of any sacerdotal function …. The Brahman
naturally has privileges …. He is inviolable (the murder of a Brahman is,
with the murder of a cow, the cardinal sin), and a number of
punishments do not apply to him: he cannot be beaten, put in irons, fined,
or expelled ….34
The contrast with modern capitalist society could not be more obvious: each
caste (or estate) is a complete way of life, embodying a cosmological principle.
Caste is a differential system of privileges, endowments and ‘gifts’ which
represent a model of the social world, based on a philosophical doctrine
concerning human functions and a scale of values, embodied by various closed
groups whose commerce with one another is a function of their respective rungs
on the ladder of human values, religiously determined. All this is strengthened
by a well-entrenched system of prejudices. The English word villain,
French villain, has its origin in the late Latin villanus, villager, peasant.
‘Ignoble’ originally means a person devoid of noble rank. The
Hungarian paraszt, ‘peasant’ originates in the Slav stem prost, ‘simpleton’, etc.,
all signs that contempt and deference did not need excuses. Medieval ditties
made fun of hunchbacks, beggars, cripples, fat people and, simply, the poor.
Explanations for the ill-fate of some were, apart from social theodicy, racial and
warlike. The upper castes were (in the whole Indo-European area) supposed to
be fair, the servants, the aborigines, the slaves, the foreigners, swarthy.35
The target of egalitarian rebellion was always this ascription and adjudication,
i.e., doubt concerning just deserts, and ambiguity of the idea of ‘God’s children’
and the radical distinctions regarding dignity (and the sheer scope of human life)
inherent in caste society. The complaint that kings and barons are not chivalrous
and gallant, that monks and nuns are not sagacious and chaste, is perennial. For
the rebels, the world is turned upside down, merit trampled underfoot, while
crime is rewarded with honours and plenty. Virtue, unlike moral goodness or
intelligence, adheres to caste, not to persons or to humanity as such. What is
virtue for one caste, is not for another. Pride is good in one, humility in another.
Achilles, the greatest warrior, is incomprehensible apart from his semi-divine,
princely heroism which coexists with extreme prickliness and sensitivity and a
morbid preoccupation with slights and with the insufficient deference shown to
him by equals whom he was bound to consider inferiors – a universal type
encountered in ancient epics. Heroism is very much a matter of bodily integrity
and beauty, athleticism, elegance, sexual glamour and a pronounced distaste for
being ‘dissed’. Heroism is play and display; all this is allowed under the
disquieting but glorious threat of death on the battlefield, the untimely deaths of
rich young men.36
If it is true, and I think it is, that Marx’s theory does not purport to be a theory
of human nature as such, but a theory of capitalism, then the immortal words
of The Communist Manifesto, according to which ‘[t]he history of all hitherto
existing society is the history of class struggles’, must be false. Class is unique
to capitalist society. Class is, first of all, a structural feature of the system;
belonging to a class is a condition legally and, quite often, socially, open to
anybody. This openness of class as a contingent social position is what makes
capitalism great and gives it the aura of Mephistophelian liberation through ever
‘more extensive and more destructive crises’, as the Manifesto also puts it. In
order to achieve this gigantic ‘creative destruction’ (an expression of
Schumpeter’s inspired by Bakunin) there was a need to unleash the forces of
individual freedom – a freedom, that is, from a legally and coercively enforced
classification of human beings into groups of birth and status.
Addressing class as such is, intuitively, very difficult.
The distinction between castes could not be farther away from this portrait of
the worker who may be alienated and exploited, but certainly is no stranger to
capital; on the contrary, he is one of its ‘moments’, one of its structural features.
This is clearly not something anybody could abolish by decree or by law. If the
worker is a feature of capital, the worker can change capitalism into something
else only if he or she changes himself or herself, in an extra-moral sense.
First, one has to take into account the psychological needs of opposition to any
system one was brought up in. All social systems – through mythologies,
patriotic chronicles, traditions and the like – pretend and, indeed, must pretend
that they are natural, and that their failings are due to inherent clashes within
human nature, and that unhappiness all too obviously caused by impersonal
factors is somehow retribution, either visited upon people because of their
imperfections, or because of some fatal breakdown in the system itself caused
by ingratitude, impiety or the inscrutable decree of a higher force of some kind.
Blaming the system will always appear as an easy pretext for failing to blame
oneself, dissatisfaction being always regarded as a weakness of the unsuccessful,
of the insufficiently noble or the insufficiently insightful – in short, of the
Thersites of this world. People have to be on a solid moral footing if they are to
dare to say ‘no’. Thus, it seems necessary to establish that there is an innate
excellence residing in those who have been held by the ruling order to be
inferior, and that the inversion of the established moral order or moral hierarchy
happens to be both the superior truth and a satisfactory motivation for its
reversal. The oldest rhetorical tricks can be employed here:
Blessed be ye poor: for yours is the kingdom of God. Blessed are ye that
hunger now: for ye shall be filled. Blessed are ye that weep now: for ye
shall laugh. Blessed are ye, when men shall hate you, and when they
shall separate you from their company, and shall reproach you, and cast
out your name as evil, for the Son of man’s sake…. But woe unto you that
are rich! For ye have received your consolation. Woe unto you that are
full! For ye shall hunger. Woe unto you that laugh now! For ye shall
mourn and weep. Woe unto you, when all men shall speak well of you!
For so did their fathers to the false prophets. But I say unto you which
hear, Love your enemies, do good to them, which hate you, Bless them
that curse you, and pray for them which despitefully use you.38
The moral order is reversed, but even the threat of that reversal is turned
upside down, for those who would suddenly find themselves at the bottom of the
moral heap will be forgiven and saved. This sums up nearly all revolutionary
manifestoes we can think of. The scary flip of the moral coin is made
unthreatening – even the frightening curse, ‘ye shall mourn and weep’ is made
good – by the invocation of universality: ‘love your enemies’. But the right to
forgive will be conferred upon those who did not have the power to forgive, and
thus to condemn, before. Power is being taken away and given anew, this is why
the Son of Man is also called the Lord.
A second reason why the retreat from socialism to egalitarianism has been the
rule is the need for a trans-social or meta-social foundation for the possibility of
a change which might reduce or even obliterate injustice and domination. This is
(intuitively) the suppleness, the plasticity, the flexibility, the malleability of
human nature and the randomness of intellectual, aesthetic or physical
endowment, distributed capriciously among all ranks, races, creeds and
provinces. In other words: a belief in the possibility of equality without
upsetting too much the shape of society which – even if equality of income,
opportunity, status and access to political power were achieved – would still
contain elements of domination, either by government (tempered by law) or by
various social hierarchies of command and control in the workplace, education
and family, as well as a continuing social division of labour.
On the other hand, this ever-recurring retreat makes good psychological sense.
It is well-nigh impossible to wage a battle to the death (which revolution,
however slow and gradual, necessarily is) if there is no sense that it is fought on
behalf of people who deserve sacrifice, whose cause is morally superior
because they are superior to the foe. The anti-luxury ideas of Rousseau and his
countless ideological forebears declare ‘the great and the good’ to be
superfluous. This notion may be plausible (although still unpleasant) in the case
of caste society, but in the case of class society, Marx is adamant that
This is not consonant with the millenary voice of rebellion. That voice, on the
contrary, tells us that ‘we was robbed’, the thrifty by the thriftless. That honest
toil was not paid in full, owing to the superior coercive power of the mighty.
That ascribing a necessary ‘productive’ role to the ruling classes is pernicious
‘ideological’ mendacity. All value is created by the workers – this is Lassalle’s
view, and not Marx’s.45 All official and triumphant ‘socialist’ art from Soviet
social realism to Latin American muralists glorifies proletarian might, sinews,
purity, work and victorious confrontation with the puny and unclean enemy –
unlike the few works of art truly inspired by a Marxian vision, from George
Grosz and Gyula Derkovits to the more extreme avant-garde. These latter
creations are almost invariably dark and pessimistic. Their problem was
succinctly summarized by Georg Lukács thus: ‘[T]he objective reality of social
existence is in its immediacy “the same” for both proletariat and bourgeoisie’.46
EPILOGUE
Our argument has established that revolutionary mobilization in the past was
almost invariably aimed at the economic, social, cultural, racial, legal, religious,
racial, sexual and intellectual humiliation inherent in ‘caste’; it was an
egalitarian mobilization against aristocratic orders of variegated kinds. It is true
that ‘democracy’ in practice never meant the effective rule of the lower orders,
albeit their influence has increased from time to time (never for long, though),
but it alleviated a burden we neglect too easily. Equality of dignity, the principle
of civic rights and liberties (even if most often honoured in the breach), shifted
the struggle for emancipation to new levels, both more profound and more
intractable.
Let’s not forget that bourgeois liberty, i.e., modern (liberal) capitalist class
society, was not quite safe until very recently. It should not be forgotten, either,
that this element played an important role in the anti-fascist struggle (not
understood by purely and uncompromisingly proletarian radicals like Amadeo
Bordiga and some, by no means all, left communists). An explanation is here in
order. Fascism and National Socialism are constantly interpreted, not without
justification, as instances of ‘reactionary modernism’, as a sub-species of
twentieth-century revolutionism, etc., initially in order to stress their not
negligible parallels and similarities with ‘communism’, especially Stalinism,
often under the aegis of the (untenable) ‘totalitarianism’ dogma. However
justified and novel these approaches were, they contributed to the (all too
frequent) neglect of the obvious. Southern and Catholic fascism wanted to
introduce the Ständestaat (always translated as ‘corporate state’ but literally
meaning ‘the state of estates’, a sort of new caste society), based on the theories
of Othmar Spann, Salazar and others, all inherited from Count Joseph de
Maistre, the Marquis de Bonald and Don Juan Donoso Cortés, with a mix of the
‘elite’ theories of Vilfredo Pareto and others. There were variants of the same
neo-feudalism in Nazism, too, with racist and sexist elements of ‘arischer
Männerbund’ (Aryan male fraternity) and similar pseudo-historical nonsense,
very much in vogue then among fashionable people like Carl Schmitt and others
of his ilk.
What all this verbiage amounted to was a quite serious attempt to re-introduce
caste society, that is, human groups with radically different entitlements and
duties (against uniformizing and levelling, ‘mechanistic’ conceptions of
egalitarian liberalism and socialism and bourgeois individualism): the Führ-
erprinzip in all occupations (witness Heidegger’s infamous ‘Rektoratsrede’, i.e.,
commencement address); vocational groups dissolving classes (e.g., steel-
workers would have meant, in the future, Krupp and Thyssen as well as the
steel-workers proper); untouchables (Jews and other condemned races), and so
on. The fascists were quite serious in wanting to go back to before 1789, as they
(or at least their predecessors) had been announcing loudly since the 1880s.
Since pre-modern and aristocratic memories were still alive in Central and
Southern Europe, the modernist-egalitarian impulse against fascism was quite
strong, and since this impulse was carried by the Left, and since the murderous
attack of fascism and Nazism was directed against them and the liberal
bourgeoisie and intelligentsia, small wonder that Popular Fronts were born and
were quite sincere in their fight against the revival of an oppressive past, and
against an anti-egalitarian and anti-Enlightenment obscurantism. This fight was
pre-socialist in its historical and ideological character, but unavoidable (and one
has to admire the gall of Horkheimer and Adorno in disregarding this aspect
altogether).
But since the rather recent global triumph of capitalism, egalitarian mobi-
lizations against caste, although still the dominant form (viz. battles against
poverty, for jobs, against local and global discrimination, for gender and racial
equality, for fairness for the indigenous or ‘first’ peoples, and so on) appear
insufficient because inequality (if still a pertinent term at all) has different causes
from those it had in the past. When in the vast literature of the disillusioned Left
we read about the irrelevance of class, the vanishing proletariat, we can still see
the unconscious amalgamation of caste and class. Since the immanent, intra-
capitalist fight for equality led by socialists possessed by the ‘false
consciousness’ of fighting against alienation and exploitation, has ended; since
the historically forced synthesis of these two aspirations has been dissolved
through the final evanescence of the remains of aristocratic order, deference and
birth privilege; since the ‘socialist’ states have reverted to capitalist type, as a
result of the successful conquest of agrarian aristocratism by ‘communist’
parties;53 it is for the first time that pure capitalism makes an appearance.
That said, on a global plane capitalism appears in the stark, unforgiving light
of its final triumph. It is completely, utterly, absolutely itself. It is like Rome
being perfectly realized in Byzantium. We reconstruct Roman society from the
legal documents written later and elsewhere, in which Roman law was
generalized and synthesized by people culturally remote from Latium but who
nevertheless understood, and what is more, lived and experienced ‘Rome’ in its
unadulterated Roman ‘haecceity’ as Romaioi. Balzac and Dickens might not be
able to understand the completed ultra-capitalism of today, but we see that we
are the accomplished heirs of their characters.
As far as we are aware, only direct (coercive) social domination was ever
overturned by popular revolt. As the experience of so-called ‘real socialism’
shows only too clearly, a change in legal ownership (of the means of production)
from that of private citizens or their associations to that of the state or
government means as little (for the workers) as the passage of a company from
ownership by a family into that of a pension fund. The ‘expropriation of the
expropriators’ did not end alienation. The illusion that capitalism was ever
defeated is linked to the non-Marxist idea of an anthropological turn away from
‘artificial’ society (the anarchy, wastefulness and inefficiency of the market,
self-destructive individualism, greed and assorted social pathologies, etc.) to true
human nature where people will act (not work) creatively after their hearts’
desire. This is, again, Rousseau, not Marx – or at least not the mature Marx – the
analyst of bourgeois society.56 Marx’s historicism is thorough and radical. He
did not describe the human condition when describing capitalism; indeed, his
description is meant as a refutation of any such idea, and this refutation is
pursued throughout his oeuvre. As Postone puts it: ‘The “essence” grasped by
Marx’s analysis is not that of human society but that of capitalism; it is to be
abolished, not realized, in overcoming that society’.57
Neither value nor labour are perennial qualities of human existence, nor is
class. Class, in contradistinction to ‘caste’, is not a framework for a whole life or
a Lebenswelt. This is why the disappearance of the cultural identity of the old
working class does not change the fundamental character of capitalism one whit.
Class, not being a human group with common interests and common moral and
cultural values such as, say, solidarity and contrariness, but a structural feature
of society, is not an actor. Contra E.P. Thompson, it is a ‘thing’.58
Class is that feature of capitalist society which divides it along the lines of
people’s respective positions in relation to reification/alienation, i.e., their
degree of autonomy vis-à-vis subordination to commodities and value. The
concomitant differences in wealth, access, etc., could, in principle, be remedied
by redistribution and mutual ‘recognition’. But greater equality of this kind
(which may appear as a utopia right now, but there are very strong forces
pushing towards that utopia which is well within the realm of possibilities) can
achieve better consumption, but not better ‘production’ – that is, not unalienated
labour. Equality, arrived at through redistribution, does not and cannot preclude
domination and hierarchy – a hierarchy moreover that, unlike in aristocratic
systems, does not build upon a cosmology and a metaphysics that could effect a
reconciliation with reality (and what else is reality than servitude and
dependence?).
No doubt the cruelty, craftiness, low cunning and high logistics used in the
expropriation of surpluses goes on as always, but the enemy is less and less a
culturally circumscribed bourgeoisie as described in Benjamin’s Arcades
Project,59 but a capitalism without a proletariat – and without a bourgeoisie – at
least, without a proletariat and a bourgeoisie as we know them historically, as
two distinct cultural, ideological and status groups not only embodying,
but representing ‘socialism’ and ‘capitalism’.60 It is this representation which
happens to be obsolete, and perhaps it was secondary to begin with, in spite of
its mobilizing force which makes the blood flow faster when listening to
the Marseillaise or the Internationale (curiously, both were played at East Euro-
pean demonstrations at the beginning of the twentieth century).
Some people mistake the absence of identifiable cultural and status groups on
either side of the class divide for an absence of class rule. But this is false. The
capitalist class rules, but it is anonymous and open, and therefore impossible to
hate, to storm, to chase away. So is the proletariat. Legal, political and cultural
equality (equality here only means a random distribution of – very real –
advantages and privileges) has made class conflict into what Capital makes it out
to be. Class conflict is dependent on the extraction of surplus, and it is not a
battle between two camps for superior recognition and a better position in the
scheme of (re)distribution. That battle goes on still, to be sure, but it is
essentially the battle of yesteryear. The bourgeoisie is by now incapable of
autonomous self-representation; the representation of its interests which is taken
over more and more by the state. Since the state represents, and looks after,
capitalism, the old-style self-representation of the working class is moribund,
too, but the state is not supplanted – as was the case, at least symbolically, in the
past – by political institutions of counter-power. Thus revolutionary proletarian
movements, although they now barely exist, are cast into the outer darkness.
The truth about class is, therefore, that the proletariat had, historically, two
contradictory objectives: one, to preserve itself as an estate with its own
institutions (trade unions, working-class parties, a socialist press, instruments of
self-help, etc.), and another one, to defeat its antagonist and to abolish itself as a
class. We can now see that the abolition of the working class as an ‘estate’, as a
‘guild’, has been effected by capitalism; capitalism has finally transformed the
proletariat (and the bourgeoisie) into a veritable class, putting an end to their
capacity for hegemony. Class hegemony of any kind (still quite vivacious and
vigorous in Gramsci’s time) was exactly what was annihilated. Class as an
economic reality exists, and it is as fundamental as ever, although it is culturally
and politically almost extinct. This is a triumph of capitalism.61
But this makes the historical work of destroying capitalism less parochial, it
makes it indeed as universal, as abstract and as powerful as capitalism itself.
What political form this may take, we don’t know.62 Nevertheless, it is now
truly the cause of humanity. There is no particular, local, vocational, ‘guild’ bias
to this cause, nor is any possible. The truth of class is of its own transcendence.
The proletariat of the Manifesto could stand outside because it could lose
nothing but its chains. No one is outside now – although not in the sense of
Antonio Negri: nation-states and classes continue to exist, and they do determine
our lives.63
The question is, could there be a motivation for a class that exists in
deprivation – and is now even deprived of a corporate cultural identity – to
change a situation which is dehumanizing and dangerous, but not humiliating to
the point of moral provocation?
We don’t know.
What is certain is that the last flowers have fallen off the chains. The working-
class culture which inspired so much heroism and self-abnegation is dead. That
culture was modernist in the sense of taking aim at hierarchy and trying to
achieve a secular, egalitarian and rights-based society. This the working class
mistook for socialism. It is not. It is capitalism. Capitalism could be itself only if
and when aided by socialist delusion.64 We are now free of this delusion. We
see the task more clearly.
NOTES
5 To quote the perhaps most famous words in the modern history of ideas: ‘All
fixed, fast-frozen relations, with their train of ancient and venerable
prejudices and opinions, are swept away, all new formed ones become
antiquated before they can ossify. All that is solid melts into air, all that is
holy is profaned, and man is at last compelled to face with sober senses his
real conditions of life, and his relations with his kind’. Karl Marx and
Friedrich Engels, The Communist Manifesto [1847], ed. by Gareth Stedman
Jones, London: Penguin, 2002, pp. 222-3.
6 In an essay written but never published in English, and available only in
Hungarian translation: ‘Jean-Jacques Rousseau’ [1953], in K.
Polányi, Fasizmus, demokrácia, ipari társadalom, Budapest: Gondolat, 1986,
pp. 244-258.
8 The Gift, London: Routledge, 1970. Cf. the chapters ‘Don, contrat, échange’
and ‘Sources, matériaux, textes à l’appui de “l’Essai sur le don”’, in Marcel
Mauss, Oeuvres 3, présentation de Victor Karady, Paris: Les Éditions de
Minuit, 1969, pp. 29-103. Paul Veyne has also demonstrated how in the
ancient Greek city-states, this kind of display became a
system, euergetismos, the system of ‘good works’ whereby the richest
aristocrats had been forced by the community to sacrifice large chunks of
their wealth for public purposes (military, naval, religious and athletic) in
exchange for honours, but under pain of confiscation and exile, in lieu of
taxation. Honour was equated with giving up, not amassing,
wealth. Civisme meant sacrifice. See his Bread and Circuses, London:
Penguin Books, 1990, an abridged version of Le Pain et le cirque, Paris: Les
Éditions du Seuil, 1976.
9 See his The Accursed Share, New York: Zone Books, 1991. Cf. Georges
Bataille, ‘The Notion of Expenditure’, in Bataille, Visions of Excess, ed. by
Allan Stoekl, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993, pp. 116-
129; for background see his ‘The Moral Meaning of Sociology’, in
Bataille, The Absence of Myth, ed. by Michael Richardson, London: Verso,
1994, pp. 103-112. On war as play, he spoke in a radio interview (on
Nietzsche) with Georges Charbonnier on 14 January 1959, see Bataille, Une
liberté souveraine, ed. by Michel Surya, Paris: Farrago, 2000, p. 130.
10 Emile, or On Education, ed. by Allan Bloom, New York: Basic Books, 1979,
pp. 224, 225.
11 E.P. Thompson, Witness Against the Beast: William Blake and the Moral
Law, New York: The New Press, 1993, pp. 109-110. Rousseauian socialism
was often attracted to counter-cultural intermundia, far away from official
‘polite’ culture. Bataille, the alleged ‘crazed pornographer’ is a case in point,
see his texts from the 1930s anti-Stalinist left subculture, L’Apprenti sorcier,
ed. by Marina Galletti, Paris: Éditions de la Différence, 1999; cf. Laure: Une
rupture, ed. by Anne Roche and Jérôme Peignot, Paris: Éditions des Cendres,
1999 (letters of Laure, Bataille, Boris Souvarine, Pierre Pascal, Simone
Weil). The subversive potential of demotic or popular culture was shown to
great effect by Robert Darnton; see his The Great Cat Massacre, New York:
Vintage, 1985, and particularly The Literary Underground of the Old
Regime, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1982. It is small wonder that
it was he who pointed out the parallels between the clandestine literature of
pre-revolutionary France and the underground samizdat literature in Eastern
Europe (of which this writer was a modest practitioner), see R.
Darnton, Berlin Journal 1989-1990, New York: W.W. Norton, 1991 It is
pretty characteristic that defeated Marxian socialists would retreat to the
‘antinomian’ stance and discover the ‘authentic’ proletarian culture, like
Jacques Rancière in his The Nights of Labor, Philadelphia: Temple
University Press, 1989. It is significant that Rancière was Louis Althusser’s
comrade-in-arms and ends up as an ally of E.P. Thompson.
12 This does not mean, of course, that Rousseauian socialists are averse to faux-
naïf appeals to reason. See, for instance, P.-J. Proudhon, Les Confessions
d’un révolutionnaire, 1849, ed. by Daniel Halévy and Hervé Trinquier, Paris:
Éditions Tops, 1997, p. 141.
13 At the same time, Rousseau would extol the merits of a music rooted in a
parochial community, necessarily based on the cadences of an ethnic
language. As in Rousseau, ‘Lettre à d’Alembert’ [1758], in Jean-Jacques
Rousseau, Oeuvres complètes, V, Pléiade edition, Paris: Gallimard, 1995, p.
15.
14 ‘… the Savage lives in himself; sociable man, always outside himself, is
capable of living only in the opinion of others and, so to speak, derives the
sentiment of his own existence solely from their judgment’. Jean-Jacques
Rousseau, The First and Second Discourses, ed. by Victor Gourevitch, New
York: Harper Torchbooks, 1990, pp. 198-9.
16 Arno Mayer, The Persistence of the Old Regime, New York: Oantheon,
1981.
17 See the classical statement about the oligarchical tendency in (mainly
socialist) political organizations: Robert Michels, Political Parties [1915],
London: Macmillan, 1968, cf. Carl E. Schorske, German Social Democracy
1905-1917, New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1972, esp. pp. 88-145.
18 See G.M. Tamás, ‘Un capitalisme pur et simple’, La Nouvelle Alternative,
60-61, March-June 2004, pp. 13-40.
19 ‘Meta’-capitalist transcendence had to stay utopian in order to be able to fall
back on moral rather than historical criticism. This amounted to a transition
from Hegel to Kant, which, as Lukács well demonstrated, is a certain sign of
defeat. The philosophical manifesto of the 1918 German revolution shows
this clearly in its theologizing metaphysical rhapsody: see Ernst Bloch, The
Spirit of Utopia, Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2000, pp. 237-8.
21 See the series of superb and gloomy reports in Perry Anderson, English
Questions, London: Verso, 1992, pp. 48-104, 121-192, 193-301.
This réquisitoire of English decadence and philistinism has many parallels in
Matthew Arnold, Culture and Anarchy [1869], ed. by Samuel Lipman, New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1994.
22 This, perhaps necessary, tactic of the socialist movements was criticized
very early on. See the important essay of the greatest Hungarian Marxist
before Lukács, Ervin Szabó (an anarcho-syndicalist), ‘Politique et
syndicats’, Le Mouvement Socialiste, 1909, t. 1, pp. 57-67; cf. Ervin
Szabó, Socialism and Social Science, ed. by J.M. Bak and G. Litván,
London: Routledge, 1982. The clearest statement of the problem as regards
Bolshevism is to be found in Herman Gorter, Open Letter to Comrade
Lenin [1920], London: Wildcat, n.d. [1989], cf. Herman Gorter, ‘Die
Ursachen des Nationalismus im Proletariat’ [1915] and ‘Offener Brief an den
Genossen Lenin’ [1920], in A. Pannekoek and H. Gorter, Organisation und
Taktik der proletarischen Revolution, ed. by Hans Manfred Bock,
Frankfurt/Main: Verlag Neue Kritik, 1969, pp. 73-87, 168-227.
23 Ervin Szabó attributes the 1848 revolution in Hungary to a class conflict
between landed gentry and landed aristocracy; see his ‘Aus den Parteien und
Klassenkämpfen in der ungarischen Revolution von 1848’, Archiv für die
Geschichte des Sozialismus und der Arbeiterbewegung, 1919, pp. 258-307
(fragment from a larger work in Hungarian, this latter considered a classic).
25 She was even able to appropriate the dividends of the most blatantly
conservative work of historiography which, during the Thatcher decade,
declared the bankruptcy of the plebeian school in history initiated by the
CPGB Historians’ Group in the 1950s: see J.C.D. Clark, English Society
1688-1832, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988. Clark proves
himself to be the scourge especially of E.P. Thompson, in ‘a tract for the
times’ quite enjoyable in its acidity and its fashionably anti-snobbish return
to those supremely unfashionable writers, Sir Lewis Namier and Sir Herbert
Butterfield; see esp. pp. 141-161, 258-276.
27 Ibid.
30 There is a book, sadly overlooked, in spite of its many merits, which
analyses the political aspect of Marx’s picture of England: David MacGre-
gor, Hegel, Marx, and the English State, Toronto: University of Toronto
Press, 1996, especially strong on contracts and the Factory Acts; cf. David
MacGregor, The Communist Ideal in Hegel and Marx, Toronto: University
of Toronto Press, 1990.
31 The only exceptions are the failed revolts of Left Communists, Council
Communists, anarchists and anarcho-syndicalists. It is only they who ever
tried to elaborate a Marxian political project. See [Philippe Bourrinet], The
Dutch and German Communist Left, London: ICC, 2001 and the numerous
and voluminous works of Hans Manfred Bock. There is a recent re-edition of
Anton Pannekoek’s Workers’ Councils [1948], ed. by Robert Barsky,
Oakland: AK Press, 2003.
39 I tried to demonstrate, long ago, that this is an illusion: G.M. Tamás, L’Oeil
et la main, Geneva: Éditions Noir, 1985 (original
Hungarian samizdat edition: 1983).
41 It is quite astonishing to see the power of the old landed interest until the
Second World War in the westernmost state of Europe; see David
Cannadine, The Decline and Fall of the British Aristocracy, New Haven:
Yale University Press, 1990, with highly instructive appendices. The data
first collected by W.D. Rubinstein are inventively and entertainingly
interpreted. The book bolsters some of the Anderson-Nairn claims, albeit
belatedly. The peasant question was raised by Karl Kautsky; the debate raged
in Germany, Austria-Hungary and Russia; there was also an interesting
contribution from Rumania, by Constantin Dobrogeanu-Gherea on ‘the new
serfdom’; later, the criticism of Lenin, Trotsky and the October
Revolution from the Left was frequently based on the need of the ‘socialist
revolution’ to distribute land to the peasants, creating thereby petty
entrepreneurial capitalism in agriculture, that had to be ‘liquidated’
subsequently by the centralizing re-distributive state in a violent self-
repression of the revolution or, according to the Stalinists, the liquidation of
phase I of revolution by phase II (‘collectivization’ through massacre and
famine).
42 Cf. Perry Anderson, ‘The Notion of Bourgeois Revolution’. The historical
points are discussed in Ellen Meiksins Wood’s illuminating book, The Origin
of Capitalism: A Longer View, London: Verso, 2002, esp. pp. 95-146. Apart
from its striking originality, it contains an excellent survey of recent
controversies, around Perry Anderson’s Passage from Antiquity to
Feudalism [1974], London: Verso, 1992 and Lineage of the Absolutist
State [1974], London: Verso, 1979, and the Brenner Debate (see The
Brenner Debate: Agrarian Class Structure and Economic Development in
Pre-Industrial Europe [1976], ed. by T.H. Aston and C.H.E. Philpin,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988). There is a sharp attack on
Ellen Meiksins Wood and Robert Brenner by Ricardo Duchesne in ‘On the
Origins of Capitalism’, Rethinking Marxism, 14(3), Fall 2002, pp. 129-137,
which for lack of specialist expertise I cannot appraise, but as an outsider, I
am not wholly convinced. Central and East (including Russian) experience
seems to me to bear out Meiksins Wood’s contentions, as far as I can judge.
43 This is what Andrew Levine fails to see in his interesting book, A Future for
Marxism? Althusser, the Analytical Turn and the Revival of Socialist
Theory, London: Pluto, 2003. It is quite ironical that the two authors who in
the nineteen-seventies tried to recreate a pristine left theory, Louis Althusser
and G.A. Cohen, should be Mr Levine’s heroes in a book which accepts
egalitarianism (in John Roemer and others) and ‘normative’ political
philosophy (in the later G.A. Cohen) as an egress for wayward Marxism
without any further ado. Andrew Levine’s contention that G.A. Cohen and
others have brought Marxism into the ‘mainstream’ is rather extraordinary.
Imagine a system of beliefs that has influenced the lives of hundreds of
millions of people on four continents, taught around nocturnal camp-fires in
dozens of civil wars and hundreds of trade union institutions, debated by
dozens of revolutionary or reforming governments, brought into the
‘mainstream’ of a tiny and transient chapter in the history of thought,
analytically styled political philosophy. Academic myopia often beggars
belief. Whatever analytical remains from analytical Marxism is rather the
‘period piece’ feel, a combination of Oxford flippancy and Cambridge
philistinism, besides a commendable striving for clarity. Being ‘no-
nonsense’ and ‘tough-minded’ and ‘anti-bullshit’ is more a question of style
than anything else. Just as nobody takes seriously Spinoza’s Euclidean
pretensions or Hobbes’s aspirations to be ‘scientific’, and just as this does not
prevent us from appreciating their work, the ‘analytical’ style of a certain
Marxian writing, however secondary, does not preclude its insights from
being illuminating or useful. But it is strange, passing strange that an
eccentric manner should be considered ‘mainstream’ while the grand
tradition of post-Renaissance European social philosophy – of which
Marxism is, of course, a part – should be seen as marginal. Andrew Levine
also speaks about the ‘insularity’ of French academic philosophy, which
reminds one of the famous English headline, ‘Fog over Channel, Continent
cut off’. Marxists used to be internationalist revolutionaries, didn’t they?
45 In the draft programme of German social democracy you could find the
sentence: ‘Labour is the source of all wealth and all culture’. To which, Marx
responds: ‘Labour is not the source of all wealth. Nature is just as much the
source of use-values (and what else is material wealth?) as labour, which is
itself only the expression of a natural power, human labour power. This line
can be found in any children’s primer and is correct in so far as
the implication is that labour requires certain means and materials. However
a socialist programme cannot allow a bourgeois phrase like this to conceal
the very circumstances that give it some sense’. ‘Critique of the Gotha
Programme’, in Marx, Later Political Writings, pp. 208-9.
48 I spoke about this problem à propos Fichte (the Rousseauian and Kantian
revolutionary genius) in ‘Fichte’s “Die Bestimmung des Gelehrten”: A
Sketch’, Collegium Budapest Workshop Series 12, Budapest: Institute of
Advanced Study, 1997, passim, and in ‘From Subjectivity to Privacy and
Back Again’, Social Research, 69(1), Spring 2002, pp. 201-221.
50 ‘In order to place ourselves firmly within the field of articulation, we must
begin by renouncing the conception of “society” as founding totality of its
partial processes. We must, therefore, consider the openness of the social as
the constitutive ground or “negative essence” of the existing, and the diverse
“social orders” as precarious and ultimately failed attempts to domesticate
the field of differences’. So write Chantal Mouffe and Ernesto Laclau in
their Hegemony and Socialist Strategy [1985], London: Verso, 2001, pp. 95-
6. Wood’s response is rather cruel: ‘After much theoretical huffing and
puffing, has not the mountain laboured and brought forth – pluralism? The
alternative – which always lurks menacingly in the background – is a
doctrine according to which some external agency, somehow uniquely and
autonomously capable of generating a hegemonic discourse out of its own
inner resources, will impose it from above, giving the indeterminate mass a
collective identity and creating a “people” or “nation” where none existed
before. The sinister possibilities inherent in such a view are obvious’. The
Retreat from Class, p. 63. (Two remarks here: I think more highly of
Mouffe’s and Laclau’s talents than Meiksins Wood does; and I think the
‘sinister possibilities’ are already quite obvious in Gramsci’s
Machiavellianism. The end result, though, is indeed pluralism and
egalitarianism of ‘recognition’ of the contemporary NGO variety.)
53 See G.M. Tamás, ‘Un capitalisme pur et simple’. There is an earlier, non-
socialist essay by the same author, with some realization of this problem, cf.
G.M. Tamás, ‘Socialism, Capitalism and Modernity’, in Larry Diamond and
Marc F. Plattner, eds., Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy Revisited,
Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1993, pp. 54-68; see also
my ‘Victory Defeated’, in Larry Diamond and Marc F. Plattner,
eds., Democracy After Communism, Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins
University Press, 2002, pp. 126-131.
58 See Thompson’s famous preface to The Making (p. 11): ‘…class is a rela-
tionship, and not a thing…’.
60 About this the best Marxian (or any kind of) analysis is by Robert Kurz in
his largely untranslated books and his periodicals (Krisis, its lighter Austrian
counterpart, Streifzüge, and now Exit). He is the thinker closest to Moishe
Postone I know of. I believe he is the most original thinker on the German,
and perhaps European, Left nowadays. He deserves to be more generally
known.
61 The intellectual history of the highly interesting and important discussions
(chiefly among Marxists) on class as a problem of political philosophy is
summarized (and an original solution thereof is attempted) on a very high
theoretical level by Stephen A. Resnick and Richard D. Wolff, Knowledge
and Class: A Marxian Critique of Political Economy, Chicago: The
University of Chicago Press, 1987. It is a thousand pities that I cannot argue
with it here.
62 A starting point in envisaging the future function of the class-in-itself would
surely be the imposing work of Erik Olin Wright, the greatest authority on
class today. There are continuing sociological investigations about this: see
the innovative work of Stanley Aronowitz and Michael Zweig. None of the
above makes their kind of valuable work superfluous, quite the contrary.
63 On the debate concerning the new imperialism, see G.M. Tamás, ‘Isten
hozta, Mr. Bush’, Élet és Irodalom (Supplement), 22 April 2005.
64 ‘Revolutionary theory is now the sworn enemy of revolutionary ideology
– and it knows it’. Guy Debord, The Society of the Spectacle [1967], §124,
New York: Zone Books, 1995, p. 90.