Scientists and Electromagnetic Waves: Maxwell and Hertz: Maxwell, An English Scientist
Scientists and Electromagnetic Waves: Maxwell and Hertz: Maxwell, An English Scientist
An electromagnetic wave exists when the changing magnetic field causes a changing
electric field, which then causes another changing magnetic field, and so on forever.
Unlike a STATIC field, a wave cannot exist unless it is moving. Once created, an
electromagnetic wave will continue on forever unless it is absorbed by matter.
With this oscillator, Hertz solved two problems. First, timing Maxwell's waves. He
had demonstrated, in the concrete, what Maxwell had only theorized - that the
velocity of radio waves was equal to the velocity of light! (This proved that radio
waves were a form of light!) Second, Hertz found out how to make the electric and
magnetic fields detach themselves from wires and go free as Maxwell's waves.
His investigations, reported weekly before the Académie des Sciences, established
the new science of electrodynamics.
He was also first person to develop measuring techniques for electricity in order to
perform his experiments. Ampère built an instrument utilizing a free moving
magnetized needle (a compass) to measure the flow of electricity. The later
refinement of this instrument is known as galvanometer.
Michael Faraday is probably best known for his discovery of electromagnetic induction, his
contributions to electrical engineering and electrochemistry or due to the fact that he was
responsible for introducing the concept of field in physics to describe electromagnetic interaction. But
perhaps it is not so well known that he also made fundamental contributions to the electromagnetic
theory of light.
In 1845, just 170 years ago, Faraday discovered that a magnetic field influenced polarized light – a
phenomenon known as the magneto-optical effect or Faraday effect. To be precise, he found that
the plane of vibration of a beam of linearly polarized light incident on a piece of glass rotated when a
magnetic field was applied in the direction of propagation of the beam. This was one of the first
indications that electromagnetism and light were related.The following year, in May 1846,
Faraday published the article Thoughts on Ray Vibrations, a prophetic publication in which
he speculated that light could be a vibration of the electric and magnetic lines of force.
physics.
Oersted was the elder son of an apothecary, Søren Christian Oersted, and his wife, the former
Karen Hermansen. The demands of his father’s business and his mother’s superintendence of a
large family forced his parents to place Hans Christian and his younger brother, Anders Sandøe,
with a German wigmaker and his wife while they were still young boys. It was there that Oersted
learned German by translating a German Bible and speaking with the couple. The brothers’
intellectual abilities were soon apparent, and neighbors did what they could to stimulate and
educate them. In this way they picked up the rudiments of Latin, French, and mathematics. When
Oersted was eleven, he began to serve as his father’s assistant in the pharmacy, thereby gaining a
practical knowledge of the fundamentals of chemistry.
This was not much formal education; but when the two brothers arrived in Copenhagen in 1794,
they were able to pass the entrance examination for the university with honors. At this point they
parted intellectual company; Anders went on to become a jurist and Hans Christian pursued a
career in natural philosophy. The most important of Oersted’s courses for his intellectual
development was that offered on Kant and the critical philosophy. Oersted became a passionate
Kantian and defender of Kant’s philosophical views, which were to be of fundamental
importance to his scientific development. They were even to be the agent that led him to his most
important discovery, electromagnetism.
After a brief stint as the manager of a pharmacy, Oersted set out in the summer of 1801 on a
journey that was to complete his scientific education. The scientific world was in ferment over
the recently announced discovery of the voltaic pile (1800), and Oersted eagerly pursued
information relating to galvanism and its relation to chemistry. A small voltaic battery of his own
invention gained him entry to others’ laboratories, and he gathered knowledge and ideas as he
visited Berlin, Göttingen, and Weimar. Again the influences at work on him were twofold. At
Göttingen he was given an introduction to Johann Ritter, who was then publishing on the
chemical effects of current electricity. Ritter focused Oersted’s attention on the forces of
chemical affinity and their relationship to electricity. Ritter’s highly unorthodox ideas on matter
and force also stimulated Oersted to develop his own concepts. At Berlin he attended lectures
on Naturphilosophie and met such Naturphilosophen as Henrik Steffens and Franz von Baader.
He read Schelling and heard Friedrich Schlegel. As a result he developed his philosophical
insights by comparing his own metaphysics with those of the Naturphilosophen.Since both
Oersted and the Naturphilosophen drew their inspiration and basic ideas from Kant, it is no
coincidence that Oersted’s later philosophy closely resembled Naturphilosophie.
Oersted was saved from the extravagances of a Schelling by his basic respect for empirical fact.
Nevertheless, during this trip it was his philosophical penchant that dominated, for although he
was suspicious of Schelling’s system-building, he swallowed as fact what were only wild
guesses by Ritter and the Hungarian chemist J. J. Winterl. Indeed, it was as a defender of Winterl
and Ritter that Oersted made his scientific debut in Paris.
The result was disastrous. Winterl’s “system” rested on two archetypal substances—Andronia
and Thelycke—the essences of acidity and basicity. From these Winterl developed a chemistry
of conflicting opposites which, because of its philosophical beauty, completely seduced Oersted.
The French chemists, however, were scornful; and Oersted was blasted in the Annales de chimie
et de physique. It was a valuable lesson. Henceforth, Oersted tended increasingly to hold his
philosophical enthusiasms in check at least until he had some evidence for their plausibility. The
lesson was driven home by his championing of Ritter’s work. To his dismay, he discovered that
many of the experimental results his friend reported in the journals were, like Winterl’s
Andronia, mere figments of his imagination. The pain of having made a scientific fool of himself
taught Oersted the critical attitude necessary for the successful pursuit of scientific knowledge.
There is a unity in Oersted’s scientific work that is rarely found in the results of someone whose
researches ranged from the forces of chemical affinity, electromagnetism, and the
compressibility of fluids and gases to the new phenomenon of diamagnetism. This unity was
drawn from Oersted’s philosophy, inspired by his reading of Kant. Most Kantian scholars today
would insist that Oersted totally misread Kant and came to conclusions to which Kant would
have objected. That charge is probably correct; but what is important is that Oersted, and a
number of other philosophers and scientists of the time, misread Kant in the same way.
Basically, what Oersted thought Kant was saying was that science was not merely the dis-covery
of Nature; that is, the scientist did not just record empirical facts and sum them up in
mathematical formulas. Rather, the human mind imposed patterns upon perceptions; and the
patterns were scientific laws. That those patterns were not arbitrary was guaranteed by the
existence of Reason. Human reason corresponded to the Divine Reason, for man was made in the
image of God. And, inasmuch as God had created Nature, it too shared in the Divine Reason.
Thus human reason, unaided, could construct the laws of nature by virtue of its congruence with
the Divine Reason. “Was der Geist versprecht, leistet die Natur” is a misquotation from
Schiller’s Columbus—“Mit dem Genius steht die Natur in ewigem Bunde, Was der Eine
Verspricht, leistet die andre gewiss”—that Oersted used more than once in The Soul in Nature. It
represents the basic position of Naturphilosophie.
Oersted’s reading of Kant led him to more than an attitude toward nature. It also gave him what
he felt was a firm metaphysical foundation for his beliefs. In a now neglected
treatise,Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaft (1786), Kant had abandoned some
of his agnosticism expressed in the antinomies in the Critique of Pure Reason. More particularly,
whereas in the Critique he had argued that it was impossible for reason to decide between an
atomistic or a plenist concept of matter, in the Metaphysische Anfangsgründe he came down on
the side of the antiatomists. He argued that we experience only force; that force manifests itself
in matter as the force of attraction that defines the limits of a body and the force of repulsion that
gives a body the property of impenetrability. These two forces Kant called Grundkräfte(basic
forces). Other forces, such as electricity, magnetism, heat, and light, he hinted, were merely
modifications of the Grundkräfte under different conditions.
In 1800, however, Oersted’s ideas were only half-formed. He was far more au courant in
philosophy than he was in science. This is why his journey to Germany and France was so
crucial. It acquainted him with men who were at the frontiers of science and forced him to bring
his philosophical speculations down to earth.
The reentry was a difficult one. The “new” chemistry of Lavoisier and the other French chemists
left him unmoved because it turned its back on the very questions, such as elective affinity and
the true nature of acids and bases, that fascinated Oersted. Winterl’s system, on the other hand,
was just what he was looking for. Instead of some thirty-odd elements, defined only empirically
as the last products of a laboratory analysis, Winterl offered two fundamental and opposed
substances. Andronia and Thelycke could be viewed as materializations of theGrundkräfte and
chemistry could then, it was hoped, be seen as a Kantian science. Similarly, Ritter’s work in
electro-chemistry appeared to Oersted as a development of Kantian thought and all of a piece
with his own philosophy of forces. It was only when his philosophical theories and the empirical
facts refused to fit together in repeatable experiments that Oersted’s critical faculties were
awakened. It is significant that, at this point, he did not reject his philosophical faith. Instead, he
rejected the physical systems of Winterl and Ritter. His first real scientific achievement was to
create his own system, based upon his own experiments. The results appeared in German in 1812
and in a French translation in 1813. The title of the latter,Recherches sur l’identité des forces
chimiques et électriques, indicates its purpose. From theGrundkräfte, Oersted hoped to deduce a
system of chemistry that would be in accordance with the results of experiment.
It is important to stress that electromagnetism was not an effect to be expected according to the
orthodox, corpuscular theories of the day. Coulomb seemingly had proved in the 1780’s that
electricity and magnetism were two entirely different species of matter whose laws of action
were mathematically similar but whose natures were fundamentally different. The conversion of
one into the other was, literally, unthinkable. Hence, those who accepted Coulomb’s findings
simply did not look for a magnetic effect.
For Oersted the situation was quite different. The Kantian doctrine of Grundkräfte led directly to
the idea of conversion of forces. All that was necessary was to discover the conditions under
which such conversions took place. The particular conditions for the conversion of electricity
into magnetism were deduced by Oersted from the nature of electricity. Electricity to him was a
conflict of the positive and negative aspects of magnetism, which conflict spread out in wave
fashion in space. When the electric conflict was confined in a rather narrow-gauge wire, the
result was heat. When the conflict was restricted still further by decreasing the diameter of the
wire, light was produced. So, Oersted suggested in his treatise on the identity of chemical and
electrical forces, the magnetic force should be produced when the electrical conflict is still
further confined in a very narrow-gauge wire. In 1813, therefore, he had already predicted the
existence of the electromagnetic effect. He was wrong, of course, on the conditions; and this
error, together with his increasing teaching duties in the years that followed, prevented him from
bringing his prediction to reality. The actual discovery was made in the early spring of 1820 and
may best be given in Oersted’s own words.
Electromagnetism itself was discovered in the year 1820, by Professor Hans Christian Oersted,
of the University of Copenhagen. Throughout his literary career, he adhered to the opinion, that
the magnetical effects are produced by the same powers as the electrical. He was not so much
led to this, by the reasons commonly alleged for this opinion, as by the philosophical principle,
that all phenomena are produced by the same original power. … His researches upon this
subject, were still fruitless, until the year 1820. In the winter of 1819–20, he delivered a course
of lectures upon electricity, galvanism, and magnetism, before an audience that had been
previously acquainted with the principles of natural philosophy. In composing the lecture, in
which he was to treat of the analogy between electricity and magnetism, he conjectured, that if it
were possible to produce any magnetical effect by electricity, this could not be in the direction of
the current, since this had been so often tried in vain, but that it must be produced by a lateral
action. This was strictly connected with his other ideas; for he did not consider the transmission
of electricity through a conductor as an uniform stream, but as a succession of interruptions and
reestablishments of equilibrium, in such a manner that the electrical powers in the current were
not in quiet equilibrium, but in a state of continual conflict.… The plan of the first experiment
was, to make the current of a little galvanic trough apparatus, commonly used in his lectures,
pass through a very thin platina wire, which was placed over a compass covered with glass. The
preparations for the experiments were made, but some accident having hindered him from trying
it before the lecture, he intended to defer it to another opportunity; yet during the lecture, the
probability of its success appeared stronger, so that he made the first experiment in the presence
of the audience. The magnetical needle, though included in a box, was disturbed; but as the
effect was very feeble, and must, before its law was discovered, seem very irregular, the
experiment made no strong impression on the audience [“Thermo-electricity,” in Edinburgh
Encyclopaedia (1830), XVIII, 573–589; repr. in Oersted’sScientific Papers, II, 356].
Oersted could not be sure that the effect was the one he had anticipated, and therefore he
deferred working on it for some three months. In July he resumed his researches and made
certain that a current-carrying wire is surrounded by a circular magnetic field. The results
appeared in a short paper, written in Latin, sent to the major scientific journals in Europe. The
“Experimenta circa effectum conflictus electrici in acum magneticam,” dated 21 July 1820,
opened a new epoch in the history of physics. From it followed the creation of electrodynamics
by Ampere and Faraday’s Experimental Researches in Electricity.
Oersted’s second major area of research involved the compressibility of gases and fluids. It may
be, as his biographer Kirstine Meyer implies, that he became interested in this problem by noting
inconsistencies in the experiments of previous investigators. There may also, however, be a
matter of theoretical importance involved. In all his experiments on compressibility, especially
the compressibility of fluids, Oersted was intent upon proving that the reduction in volume was
proportional to the pressure. If this were so, then the law of compressibility would provide a
smooth pv curve. The existence of incompressible atoms, occupying space, would force a
discontinuity in this curve if and when the point could be reached when the atoms were packed
tightly together. Oersted’s system of forces permitted continual compression, and it seems
plausible that his experiments on compressibility were intended to test the atomic hypothesis.
The results were inconclusive, but his apparatus and critical acumen in detecting sources of error
were of basic importance for later investigations of compressibility.
Oersted’s last scientific researches were on the phenomena of diamagnetism. He tried to account
for diamagnetic substances by assuming reverse polarity and reverse inductive effects in
substances that were repelled from, rather than attracted to, a magnetic pole. This work, in the
late 1840’s, was made obsolete by Faraday’s investigations, which showed that the concept of
polarity could not be applied to diamagnetics.
In his last years Oersted returned to his first love, philosophy. In a series of articles, published
together in The Soul in Nature, he considered the relation between beauty and science. He still
saw the hand of God in both. Beauty in art and music was the Divine Reason manifested in the
harmonies of sight and sound. “Spirit and nature are one, viewed under two different aspects.
Thus we cease to wonder at their harmony.” Oersted’s last work, The Soul in Nature, was left
unfinished when he died on 9 March 1851. It was intended to express, in final form, the faith that
had guided his entire scientific career.
The new speed of the waves as they pass propagate through the quartz is
The frequency of electromagnetic waves does not change when the medium through
which the waves are propagating changes. Since for electromagnetic waves
propagating through a dielectric medium, we have