Justice Community Dialogue IR
Justice Community Dialogue IR
Justice Community Dialogue IR
Editorial Board
Steve Smith (Managing Editor)
Thomas Biersteker Chris Brown Alex Danchev Phil Cerny
Joseph Grieco A. J. R. Groome Richard Higgott
G. John Ikenberry Caroline Kennedy-Pipe Steve Lamy
Michael Nicholson Ngaire Woods
78 Richard Shapcott
Justice, community and dialogue in international relations
77 Philip E. Steinberg
The social construction of the ocean
76 Christine Sylvester
Feminist international relations
An unfinished journey
76 Kenneth A. Schultz
Democracy and coercive diplomacy
75 David Houghton
US foreign policy and the Iran hostage crisis
74 Cecilia Albin
Justice and fairness in international negotiation
73 Martin Shaw
Theory of the global state
Globality as an unfinished revolution
72 Frank C. Zagare and D. Marc Kilgour
Perfect deterrence
71 Robert O’Brien, Anne Marie Goetz, Jan Aart Scholte and Marc Williams
Contesting global governance
Multilateral economic institutions and global social movements
70 Roland Bleiker
Popular dissent, human agency and global politics
69 Bill McSweeney
Security, identity and interests
A sociology of international relations
68 Molly Cochran
Normative theory in international relations
A pragmatic approach
67 Alexander Wendt
Social theory of international politics
Richard Shapcott
The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom
http://www.cambridge.org
Introduction 1
1 Beyond the cosmopolitan/communitarian divide 30
2 Community and communication in interpretive
theories of international relations 53
3 Emancipation and legislation: the boundaries of
conversation in poststructuralism and the critical
theory of IR 95
4 Philosophical hermeneutics: understanding, practical
reasoning and human solidarity 130
5 Philosophical hermeneutics and its critics 180
6 Towards a thin cosmopolitanism 209
Conclusion 233
Bibliography 239
Index 248
vii
Acknowledgements
This book would never have been completed, or even undertaken, with-
out the support, advice, encouragement and inspiration of the following
people and institutions (in no particular order).
The School of Australian and International Studies and the Faculty
of Arts at Deakin University granted me six months leave to complete
this project in 2000. The Faculty of Social Sciences and the Department of
Politics of the University of Bristol awarded me a university scholarship,
as did the Overseas Research Scholarship scheme, to undertake the PhD
thesis out of which this book evolved. I would be remiss were I not to
acknowledge the benefits I gained from teaching on Bristol’s Master’s
degree in World Politics. At Bristol I received the support and friend-
ship from the staff in general and the administrative staff – Veronica
Scheibler, Anne Jewell and Elisabeth Grundy in particular. In addition,
the Department of International Relations at the University of Keele pro-
vided me with a fertile, stimulating and welcoming environment for the
seven months in which I was a visiting scholar there in 1994 when crucial
early research was conducted. Alex Danchev, John Macmillan, Hidemi
Suganami and Chris Brewin all expressed interest and enthusiasm as
well as provided constructive input. Rosarie McCarthy, Peter Newell,
Matt Paterson and Jo Van Every all helped to make my transition to
English life easier and my time at Keele enjoyable. The Department of
Politics at Monash University also supported the early stages of my
investigation and awarded me an Australian Postgraduate Research
Award in 1993. The book also benefited from the time I spent at La
Trobe University, Australia, as a Post-doctoral Fellow in 1998. Steven
Slaughter of Monash University stepped in at the last minute to take
over my teaching responsibilities at Deakin; without this assistance the
book would have been a much longer time coming.
viii
Acknowledgements
ix
Acknowledgements
x
Introduction
1
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
2
Introduction
provide better resolutions than others none escapes the tension entirely,
including the ‘solution’ suggested by philosophical hermeneutics. For
this reason the development of an approach informed by philosophi-
cal hermeneutics should be understood as a contribution to the effort
to better accommodate this tension rather than a claim to have finally
resolved it.
3
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
4
Introduction
place once the philosophical ground work has been undertaken. That
said, as Gadamer and others emphasise, the meaning of the concepts
explored here are incomplete as long as they remain exclusively in the
abstract realm. Therefore this book should be seen as merely the first
step along the way of developing a thin cosmopolitanism informed by
philosophical hermeneutics.
4 As Molly Cochran has recently reminded us, all theory is normative theory. See
M. Cochran, Normative Theory in International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1999).
5
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
6
Introduction
8 See A. Linklater, Beyond Realism and Marxism: Critical Theory and International Relations,
2nd edn (London: Macmillan, 1990).
9 See the discussions in E. H. Carr, The Twenty Years Crisis (London: Macmillan, 1939) and
H. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace (New York: Alfred
A. Knopf, 1954).
7
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
substantive moral life is possible only within the state, and the interstate
realm is portrayed as the realm of necessity possessing a different and
restricted morality, the morality of states (the chief virtue of which is
prudence).
The account of community presented by the rationalists holds a some-
what different place for culture. In the works of Wight, Bull and Watson
the existence of a certain degree of shared cultural inheritance pro-
vides the conditions of possibility for an ordered society of states.10
However, for Bull and others the presence of major cultural difference
within the modern universal society of states raises the possibility for
a decrease in world order and an increase in conflict. Amongst the
tasks of international society then, is the mediation of cultural differ-
ences and the identification of shared interests or goals across cultural
boundaries.11
As the discussion in chapter 2 demonstrates, cosmopolitans have also
identified cultural heterogeneity as an obstacle to progress in the interna-
tional realm. Where they tend to differ from Realists is in the aspiration
to transcend these differences and either to replace or incorporate them
in a universal community. For this reason cosmopolitanism has often
been identified as hostile to the existence of diverse societies and value
systems. While a full discussion of the place of culture in IR theory is
beyond the scope of this investigation it is possible to suggest from this
brief overview that the question of cultural difference is central to the
question of community in IR.
The task of this book is to contribute to the development of alterna-
tive understandings of the relationship between community and cul-
tural difference in the international realm. It addresses both parts of the
question: is moral community possible beyond the state or the particular
community and, if so, what are the characteristics of that larger com-
munity? In answer to the first part, it argues that a morally inclusive
but ‘thin’ cosmopolitanism capable of doing justice through recognition
is possible. In answer to the second, it argues that such a community
should embody the values of communication and the characteristics of
dialogue in which recognition of differences can occur.
8
Introduction
9
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
10
Introduction
11
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
12
Introduction
of identity in turn rests on, and is mediated through, the shared qual-
ity of language. Because human identity is shaped and constituted
linguistically (though not exclusively so) it is capable of articulation
through language; in other words, it can be communicated. This being
the case, recognition becomes a dialogical task to be achieved through
understanding the ‘other’ in conversation. For this reason the work of
Gadamer is used to demonstrate how the dialogical character of un-
derstanding constitutes an act of communication between differently
constituted agents. The major task proceeding from these insights is to
theorise the nature of a good dialogue in which justice to difference is
achieved. Linklater’s work contains one theorisation of the nature of
good inclusive dialogue and, to date, represents the most consistent at-
tempt offered in international relations to think through the meaning
of inclusion in a universal dialogue. The work of David Campbell and
other poststructuralists has also contributed to a serious effort to think
through the relationship of ‘self’ to ‘other’ in the international context.
However, as is noted in chapter 2, this has not, for a variety of reasons,
involved sustained reflection on the meaning of dialogue and conversa-
tion. The aim of this work is to contribute to the project of thinking about
the nature of communication and dialogue in an international context
and, in particular, about what a universal community in which justice
to difference is achieved might look like.
However, before proceeding further down this track one important
task needs to be undertaken. The best means for understanding the im-
portance of communication as an ethical/moral relationship is to com-
pare it to its alternatives. It is only when having examined the ways in
which communication differs from certain other modes of interaction
that it is possible to understand both how communication provides a
superior form of self/other relation and what exactly is involved in com-
municating. For this reason the discussion below turns to the work of
Tzvetan Todorov and his now classic discussion of self/other relations
in The Conquest of America.16 The principal task performed by this dis-
cussion is to elaborate on the ways in which communication is related
to both knowledge and belief. While it says little about what ‘good’ dia-
logue itself might consist of, Todorov’s reading of the encounter between
Europeans and the occupants of the Americas provides an essential
service by making the argument for communication over and against
its alternatives of assimilation and coexistence.
13
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
17 The meeting of the Spanish and the Indians in the years after 1492 is of interest to this
investigation for several reasons. The inhabitants of the Americas, indeed the Americas
themselves, had no place in the Christian cosmology prior to 1492, and were truly ‘other’.
Thus, upon encountering them, the Europeans had to interpret this new phenomenon and
decide how it might fit their old cosmology. It can be argued that this encounter began
the process of decentring the European identity. The difficulties and problems involved
in such a decentring are a necessary step towards communication. For another read-
ing of this encounter see B. Jahn, ‘The Power of Culture in International Relations: The
Spanish Conquest in the Americas and its Theoretical Repercussions’ (San Diego: paper
presented at ISA Annual Conference, April 1996). See also D. Blaney and N. Inayatullah,
‘Prelude to a Conversation of Cultures in International Society? Todorov and Nandy on
the Possibility of Dialogue’, Alternatives, 19 (1994), 23–51; C. Brown, ‘The Modern Require-
ment?: Reflections on Normative International Theory in a Post-Western World’, Millen-
nium: Journal of International Studies, 17.2 (1988), 339–48; C. Brown, ‘Cultural Diversity and
International Political Theory: From the Requirement to “Mutual Respect” ’, Review of In-
ternational Studies (2000), 26, 199–13 and, W. E. Connolly, ‘Identity and Difference in Global
Politics’, in J. Der Derian and M. J. Shapiro, International/Intertextual Relations: Postmodern
Readings of World Politics (Lexington, 1989).
18 Todorov’s account is not without its critics. While the following argument draws heavily
on Todorov it is an interpretation and application of ideas found in Conquest of America
and not a wholesale endorsement of his position. The purpose of this discussion is merely
to use his categories to pursue a certain line of thinking.
14
Introduction
First of all, there is a value judgement (an axiological level); the other is
good or bad, I love or do not love him, or as was more likely to be said at
the time, he is my equal or my inferior (for there is usually no question
that I am good and that I esteem myself). Secondly, there is the action
of rapprochement of distancing in relation to the other (praxeological
level): I embrace the other’s values. I identify myself with him, or else
I identify the other with myself, I impose my own image upon him;
19 Todorov himself does not use these terms, I have adapted them for my own purposes.
Todorov uses the terms enslavement, colonialism and communication, conquest, love
and knowledge to describe various manifestations of similar phenomena. See Todorov,
Conquest of America, pp. 169, 185.
15
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
16
Introduction
17
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
Cortés does not communicate, in the sense intended here, with the In-
dians because his evaluation of them as inferior remains and is unaf-
fected by his knowledge, thereby ruling out communication from the
beginning.28
Assimilation
In the case of the Spanish priest and Bishop Bartolomeo de Las Casas,
probably the principal advocate of the Indians’ equality in the sixteenth
century, the relationship between knowledge and evaluation becomes
more complex. Las Casas’ relation to the Indians is that of assimilation.
This is a more complex relationship to the other than the ones discussed
earlier because although it allows for the possibility of equality, such
equality comes at the expense of identity.
Las Casas has his alter ego in the figure of the scholar, lawyer and
philosopher Ginês de Sepúlveda. Where Las Casas argues against the
policies of conquest and enslavement, Sepúlveda defends the wars
against the Indians as just on the grounds that the Indians are naturally
inferior. The two figures engaged in a debate at Valladolid in Spain in
1550, the content of which illustrates the category of assimilation. The
basic arguments were simple: Las Casas argued that the Indians were
the Europeans’ equals and should be treated as such, while Sepúlveda
argued that the Indians’ inferiority legitimated their destruction. Las
Casas’ position, however, is not as straightforward, nor as desirable,
28 Despite the ease with which Cortés undertakes the conquest and despite the general
Spanish assumption of superiority, the Spanish felt the need to provide some moral and
legal means by which they could justify the conquest and dispossession of the Indians.
The example of the requirimiento is the most famous illustration of this. The requirimiento
was a Spanish proclamation required to be read upon encountering Indians in the new
world. It presented the Indians with a history and explanation of how the Spanish came
to be laying claims to the new world. It suggested that the Spanish claim was Just and
God-given, and gave the Indians two alternatives: voluntary surrender and recognition of
Spanish legitimacy, or enslavement and war. The requirimiento illustrates the lack of choice
presented to the Indians. It paid lip service to moral discourse but was, in fact, an ulti-
matum, and one that was beyond the comprehension of those to whom it was addressed
(literally so because it was in Spanish!). The requirement is a parody of conversation, as it
implies that the Indians can partake in the discussion, while at the same time completely
ruling out the possibility of such a discussion and assuming the inequality of the other.
‘The Indians can choose only between two positions of inferiority: either they submit of
their own accord and become serfs; or else they will be subjugated by force and reduced to
slavery . . . (they) are posited as inferiors from the start, for it is the Spaniards who deter-
mine the rules of the game. The superiority of those who promulgate the requirimiento . . .
is already contained in the fact that it is they who are speaking while the Indians listen.’
Ibid., p. 148. For further discussion of the requirement see R. Shapcott, ‘Conversation and
Coexistence, Gadamer and the Interpretation of International Society’, Millennium: Journal
of International Studies, 23.1 (1994).
18
Introduction
Equality
Whereas Sepúlveda’s starting point is a premise of human inequality
and the ‘natural fact’ of hierarchy, Las Casas starts from the Christian
principle of equality. All humans are equal before God, because they
are equally capable of accepting God. Indians are human beings and
potential Christians and to wage war against them is wrong and a de-
nial of their fundamental humanity. Thus, Las Casas demonstrates their
equality by asserting not only how like the Spaniards they are, but how
like Christians. His argument for the Indians’ equality is premised upon
a Christian identity, the Indians’ ‘human nature’ is their ‘Christian na-
ture’. As Todorov points out, the universalism of Christianity implies
a fundamental lack of difference between all persons.32 In the case of
the Indians this is not only a matter of recognising them as human be-
ings capable of understanding and converting to Christianity, but also
of their particular predisposition toward it: ‘At no other time and in
no other people has there been seen such capacity, such predisposition,
19
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
and such facility for conversion . . .’33 They are so predisposed because
they already resemble and embody basic Christian qualities. According
to Las Casas, ‘[t]hese peoples considered in general, are by their nature
all gentleness, humility and poverty, without weapons or defences not
the least ingenuity, patient, enduring as none other in the world’.34 Las
Casas only sees those things he wants to see in the Indians, in par-
ticular those attributes he can interpret as essentially Christian, such
as humility and poverty. There are two important points to note from
this account: first, that all the Indians of the Americas bear these same
traits and, second, that all these traits are psychological states of mind.
The first denies any difference between the various Indian groups,
and the second is blind to social practices and behaviour that will en-
able knowledge of who the Indians are, that is, what they believe, the
reasons and meanings of their practices, and how they understand
themselves; again a form of denial of differences. Las Casas proceeds
to account for all differences as, in fact, similarities. For example, the
Indians’ disinterest in material wealth is in harmony with ‘. . . the di-
vine law and the evangelical perfection which praise and approve that
man be content with no more than what is necessary’.35 It is there-
fore seen as evidence of their essential Christianity. There is, then, a
major catch in Las Casas’ defence, the price of the Indians’ equality
is their identity; according to natural law, humans exist ‘without any
difference’.36
Las Casas attempts to demonstrate the Indians’ equality by min-
imising the differences that Sepúlveda, for instance, draws attention
to. Ironically, this means that Las Casas is, in many ways, even fur-
ther away from knowledge and communication with the other than
Sepúlveda. The Indians themselves never speak in Las Casas’ account;
they are certainly not present at Vallodolid, and we learn little or noth-
ing of them in the course of the debate. For all Las Casas’ love of the
Indians it is at the cost of knowing them. For all Sepúlveda’s hatred of
them he knows them better. Todorov asks ‘Can we really love someone
if we know little or nothing of his identity, if we see, in place of that
identity, a projection of ourselves or of our ideals?. . . Does one culture
risk trying to transform the other in its own name, and therefore risk
subjugating it as well?’37 The name for Las Casas’ relation to the other
is Assimilation.
20
Introduction
So far in this account we have seen the development of the nexus dif-
ference/inferiority, identity/equality. Sepúlveda believes the Indians
are different and, therefore, inferior. Las Casas believes they are equal
and, therefore, the same. While we may applaud Las Casas and sym-
pathise with his attempts to bring justice to the Indians by ending the
wars against them, the realm of practice reveals another layer to this
story. We know Sepúlveda wishes the Indians’ destruction and justifies
the wars against them, but what of Las Casas? What is the relation of
thought to practice in his case?
Las Casas supports the colonisation and occupation of the Americas;
what he rejects is the Conquest or, more correctly, its means and prac-
titioners: ‘Las Casas does not want to put an end to the annexations
of the Indians, he merely wants this to be effected by priests rather
than soldiers.’38 The Indians are potential Christians, they are equals
but they must be converted in order to achieve their full equality. Las
Casas, believing the Indians to be ripe for conversion, seeks the end of
the bloodshed but not the occupation.
According to Todorov, the difference between Las Casas and
Sepúlveda is the difference between two ideologies: Enslavement and
Colonialism.39 The move to Colonialism may be an improvement on
Enslavement, but it is not a recognition of the other’s being a sub-
ject ‘like oneself’, as the Indians still remain subjugated to the colo-
nial power. Las Casas’ defence of the Indians is only in the name of
Colonialism, and their continued subjugation. As in the requirimiento,40
the Indians only have a choice between two forms of subjugation
(though of course in reality they rarely even have a choice about
this).
Colonialism denies justice in the particular form that Todorov de-
sires, that of communication: ‘. . . if colonialism opposes enslavement,
it simultaneously opposes that contact with the other which I shall
simply call communication. To the triad understand/seize/destroy
corresponds this other triad in inverted order: enslavement/
colonialism/ communication.’41
38 Ibid., p. 171.
39 An ‘enslavement’ ideology reduces the other to the status of an object, to be bought or
sold. A ‘colonialist’ ideology recognises the other’s subjectivity but only to the extent that
‘the other is seen as a subject capable of producing objects that one can then possess’. Ibid.,
p. 176.
40 See note 28 above regarding the requirimiento. 41 Ibid., p. 177.
21
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
Coexistence
Before exploring Todorov’s notion of communication, there is one other
option, adopted by Las Casas in his later life and certainly prevalent
in discussions of cultural difference today, especially in IR. This is the
stance of tolerance, neutrality or coexistence.
Todorov argues that after the Valladolid encounter, Las Casas un-
derwent a change that gradually led him to a ‘perspectivist’ position.
At Valladolid, Las Casas had to find a way to make the seemingly
22
Introduction
23
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
now runs something like same, equal, tolerate.48 Equality becomes tol-
erance, neutrality and coexistence. The question that needs to be put
here is whether coexistence is enough, is this truly where justice to oth-
erness lies? The answer of this book is that it is not enough, and it is
to what lies beyond tolerance, coexistence and neutrality that it now
turns.
Communication
What remains is the option of communication. In none of the scenar-
ios previously explored have we come across an instance of equality
leading to communication. Even Las Casas’ final position, coexistence,
forestalls and withholds from understanding and communicating with
the Indians. Coexistence denies any possibility of communicating or
judging across cultures. Equality here means autonomy but extends no
further. The other is both like me (equal) and unlike me (different) and
being unlike me I cannot engage with them. Put in terms of the iden-
tity/difference nexus Todorov offers us this formulation: ‘. . . we want
equality without its compelling us to accept identity; but also difference
without its degenerating into superiority/inferiority. We aspire to reap
the benefits of the egalitarian model and of the hierarchic model; we
aspire to rediscover the meaning of the social without losing the quality
of the individual.’49 To recognise truly the humanity of the other, to have
a relationship with them that meets this aspiration, one must communi-
cate, or at least attempt communication. Of course, communication and
conversation is itself problematic and requires more space than is avail-
able here to articulate fully and explore it. However, Todorov begins to
sketch the requirements of communication and it is with this that we
will leave this section.
Assuming, Todorov argues, that we want to have interaction between
cultures and go beyond coexistence, then such interaction must proceed
in the form of proposition, not imposition. Communication, therefore,
is opposed to assimilation as proposition is opposed to imposition:
The essential thing . . . is to know whether they [changes] are imposed or
proposed. Christianization, like the export of any ideology or technol-
ogy, can be condemned as soon as it is imposed, by arms or otherwise.
A civilisation may have features we can say are superior or inferior;
but this does not justify their being imposed on others. Even more, to
48 Both of these, of course, contrast with the view of Sepúlveda: different, inferior,
destroy/enslave.
49 Ibid., p. 249.
24
Introduction
impose one’s will on others implies that one does not concede to that
other the same humanity one grants to oneself . . .50
50 Ibid., p. 179.
51 ‘No one asked the Indians if they wanted the wheel, or looms or forges; they were
obliged to accept them. Here is where the violence resides, and it does not depend on
the possible utility of these objects. But in whose name would we condemn the unarmed
preacher, even if his avowed goal is to convert us to his own religion?’ Ibid., p. 181.
52 Ibid., p. 241.
25
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
Chapter structure
This discussion has provided a preliminary case for communication as
a model of self–other relations capable of providing a more just relation-
ship to difference, of fulfilling the requirement of justice as recognition.
The remainder of this book consists of an examination and evaluation
of approaches to justice and community in IR in terms of this typology:
annihilation, assimilation, coexistence and communication. In so doing,
it explores the relations between the axiological, epistemic and prax-
eological positions of a variety of thinkers and perspectives. The next
two chapters will attempt to assess the contributions of Normative IR
theories according to the degree to which they approximate, account
for, contribute to or embody the idea of communication.
Chapter 1 proceeds from this discussion to an assessment of the
so-called cosmopolitan/communitarian divide. An application of the
26
Introduction
27
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
28
Introduction
29
1 Beyond the cosmopolitan/
communitarian divide
30
Cosmopolitan/communitarian divide
31
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
4 See S. Mulhall and A. Swift, Liberals and Communitarians (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992); also
D. Morrice, ‘The Liberal–Communitarian Debate in Contemporary Political Philosophy
and its Significance for International Relations’, Review of International Studies, 26 (2000),
233–51.
32
Cosmopolitan/communitarian divide
procedural account, in which the qualities of the right are defined once
and for all time. Communitarianism, on the other hand, suggests that
the contextual and historical nature of human social life prevents such
an exercise from succeeding. Both liberalism and communitarianism
begin with premises relating to the nature of morality itself and only
then move on to positions regarding the scope of moral boundaries; in
particular whether morality is transcendental, or universal, or whether
it is contextualised and particular.5
There is an important qualifier that needs to be made here. Because
they are not concerned with boundaries per se very few, if any, commu-
nitarians argue that we have no obligations to others, or more correctly,
that community borders work as strict walls preventing expressions of
moral solidarity and action between peoples. Most accept that humans
on the whole are moral beings capable of treating each other morally
regardless of their particular origins or situations. What the definition
or expression of morality might consist of is disputed, in the sense that
we may have different obligations to those who do not belong to the
immediate community, but this is secondary to the charge that commu-
nitarians restrict moral actions to the domestic sphere entirely. Likewise,
many liberals, such as Rawls, accept that their theories presuppose con-
sensus and existent levels of community, and, therefore, cannot be ap-
plied unproblematically to the international realm.6
However, what does distinguish these positions are their conceptions
of selfhood and moral agency. Liberal and communitarian positions
begin with different conceptions of the moral self, and derive from them
different conceptions of community. What is at issue here is the nature of
5 This is what the framework suggests. What the participants themselves argue
is often different. Some communitarians, such as Charles Taylor, give more spe-
cific endorsement to the possibility of heterogeneous community. See C. Taylor and
A. Gutman, Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition (Princeton University
Press, 1994). See also his discussion of communitarianism in C. Taylor, ‘Cross-Purposes:
The Liberal–Communitarian Debate’, in N. L. Rosenblum (ed.), Liberalism and the Moral
Life (Harvard University Press, 1989). Taylor argues that the liberal/communitarian debate
runs together two issues which should be kept separate, namely ontology and advocacy.
It blurs the distinction between ‘the factors you will invoke to account for the good life’
and ‘the moral stand or policy one adopts’. Taylor, ‘Cross-Purposes’, p. 159. The two
are not necessarily related he argues and to conflate them is to conflate description with
prescription.
6 For instance see M. Walzer, ‘The Distribution of Membership’ in P. G. Brown and
H. Shue (eds.), Boundaries: National Autonomy and its Limits (New Jersey: Rowman and
Littlefield, 1981); J. Rawls, ‘The Law of Peoples’, in S. Shute and S. Hurley, On Human
Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures (New York: Basic Books, 1993); J. Rawls, Political Lib-
eralism (Columbia University Press, 1993).
33
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
the ‘selves’, or moral agents, that populate the moral community and the
relationship to otherness suggested by the different conceptions of the
self. Understanding these various levels will allow assessment of both
cosmopolitan and communitarian positions and a movement beyond
the divide at the level of boundaries.
34
Cosmopolitan/communitarian divide
35
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
Liberal–cosmopolitanism: Beitz
Liberal rights-based approaches, in one form or another, form the basis
of the most widely held interpretations of cosmopolitanism. Rights-
based approaches, for example, underlie the advocacy of international
human rights laws and of arguments for global redistributive justice.13
One of the most systematic and widely known formulations of the cos-
mopolitan position in recent times is offered by Charles Beitz who has
outlined a cosmopolitan philosophy derived from the work of John
Rawls.14
According to Beitz, a cosmopolitan morality must be universal: it
must consider the good of the individual and, therefore, of the species.
It is concerned ‘. . . with the moral relations of members of a universal
community in which state boundaries have merely derivative signif-
icance. There are no reasons of basic principle for exempting the in-
ternal affairs of states from external moral scrutiny. . . ’15 What defines
Beitz’s cosmopolitanism as liberal, in addition to its individualism, is the
commitment to universal and impartial principles. According to Beitz, a
cosmopolitan position is impartial because it ‘seeks to see each part of
the whole in its true relative size . . . the proportions of things are accu-
rately presented so that they can be faithfully compared’.16 Cosmopoli-
tan morality must also, therefore, remain neutral in relation to different
conceptions of the good. A cosmopolitan perspective cannot privilege
any one group in relation to any other or any group over any individual.
It must be non-perspectival, claims Beitz.17 In other words, cosmopoli-
tanism aspires to treat all individuals alike, regardless of their situation.
For Beitz, this aspiration comes closest to fulfilment in a Rawlsian so-
cial contract. The cosmopolitan quest for impartiality requires that ‘we
must . . . regard the world from the perspective of an original position
13 See for example H. Shue, Basic Rights (Princeton University Press, 1980).
14 C. R. Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton University Press, 1979)
and J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford University Press, 1972).
15 Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations, p. 182.
16 C. R. Beitz, ‘Cosmopolitan Liberalism and the States System’, in C. Brown (ed.), Political
Restructuring in Europe: Ethical Perspectives (London: Routledge, 1994), p. 124.
17 ‘By, “non perspectival”, I mean that a cosmopolitan view seeks to see each part of the
whole in its true relative size . . . the proportions of things are accurately presented so
that they can be faithfully compared. If local viewpoints can be said to be partial, then a
cosmopolitan viewpoint is impartial.’ Ibid., p. 124.
36
Cosmopolitan/communitarian divide
37
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
23 Ibid. 24 Ibid.
25 Ibid. 26 Ibid., p. 101. 27 Ibid., p. 104.
28 According to Benhabib this observation does not undermine the universalist project
altogether, instead it merely provides a corrective to it. Under the conditions of the
‘veil of ignorance’ it becomes impossible to know what ‘like’ might mean: ‘Without as-
suming the standpoint of the concrete other, no coherent universalizability test can be
carried out, for we lack the necessary epistemic information to judge my moral situ-
ation to be, like, or unlike, yours.’ Accordingly Benhabib argues a coherent universal-
ism must take into account the plurality of concrete others. Benhabib, Situating the Self,
p. 164.
38
Cosmopolitan/communitarian divide
39
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
40
Cosmopolitan/communitarian divide
36 O. O’Neill, ‘Ethical Reasoning and Ideological Pluralism’, Ethics, 98, July (1988), 714.
37 O’ Neill, Faces of Hunger, p. 37.
41
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
Communitarianism
If the cosmopolitan position appears biased too heavily in favour of the
generalised other, then the communitarian position appears to favour
the concrete other. At the level of agency, communitarians take the po-
sition of the concrete other as the starting point of their deliberations on
justice. As Walzer argues
42
Cosmopolitan/communitarian divide
43
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
44
Cosmopolitan/communitarian divide
goals, aims or versions of the good life. ‘The general function of interna-
tional society is to separate and cushion, not to act.’44 R. J. Vincent has
described this as the ‘egg box’ conception of international society.
For Brown, Terry Nardin has provided the best articulation of this as-
pect of international society.45 In establishing the nature of international
society Nardin makes a distinction between ‘purposive’ and ‘practical’
associations. Purposive association is concerned with pursuing common
and shared goals, such as a Trade Union might do. Practical association
concerns the relationship between those ‘. . . who are associated with one
another, if at all, only in respecting certain restrictions on how each may
pursue his own purposes’.46 This type of association covers those areas
concerned with the rule of law and standards of conduct, it is ‘. . . a set of
considerations to be taken into account in deciding and acting . . .’47 or, in
other words, the rules of engagement. Nardin himself draws on the work
of Michael Oakeshott for this distinction.48 The point is that Brown wants
us to see that in Nardin’s version ‘. . . the nature of international society
is such that all-inclusive association can only be practical’.49 Because the
rules of international conduct are premised on the lack of agreed com-
mon purposes, the type of conversation in this community is limited to
the terms of its continued existence. Nardin’s version of international
society is that of the ‘egg-box’. In such an association the objective is
merely to keep the various purposive associations apart; it has no role
in facilitating understanding or agreement on matters of substance. This
notion of ethics extends the possibility of shared values only so far as
the maintenance of minimal order. Moral relativism is tempered only
by need to manage diversity, to define rules of engagement and proce-
dure; to establish a secure cushioning environment, an egg box. Thus for
45
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
50 This approach corresponds with what is known as the pluralist interpretation of in-
ternational society. However, a solidarist interpretation is also available. The advantages
of the solidarist interpretation will be discussed in later chapters; all that needs to be
noted at this point is that the interpretation of the role of international society provided
by Brown and Nardin can be contested by a more cosmopolitan or solidarist reading, see
N. Wheeler and T. Dunne, ‘Hedley Bull’s Pluralism of the Intellect and Solidarism of the
Will’, International Affairs, 72 (1996), 1–17.
51 Walzer, Thick and Thin, p. 8.
46
Cosmopolitan/communitarian divide
47
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
57I have outlined the problems with Brown’s solution in Shapcott, ‘Conversation and
Coexistence’.
48
Cosmopolitan/communitarian divide
58 O’Neill’s position shows how cosmopolitans and communitarians ask different ques-
tions and how these influence their substantive positions. In this sense, the cosmopolitan
and communitarian positions provide useful and enlightening critiques of each other.
59 O’Neill, ’Ethical Reasoning and Ideological Pluralism’, p. 717.
60 Ibid.
61 A further problem with communitarian positions is that the position of coexistence
requires the establishment of some agreement whereby difference can be valued and
tolerance established, such as an ‘ethics of coexistence’, otherwise they lapse into an in-
coherent relativism. Such an agreement must in some sense be universal. Therefore at the
very least even an ethics of coexistence requires an expansion of the meaning of ‘we’ and
the development of some sort of universal ethic.
49
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
62 Ibid., p. 716.
50
Cosmopolitan/communitarian divide
Conclusion
This chapter has pursued the idea that the meaning of justice should
incorporate the idea of justice to difference, and that a relationship
premised on communication suggests a possible way of achieving such
an aim. It can be suggested here that an account of justice as communi-
cation remains universalist in aspiration, while at the same remaining
attentive to particularity. Phrasing this slightly differently, a commu-
nicative morality is universally inclusive of particular, situated agents.
In this regard, Young has suggested the possibility of distinguishing
between two senses of universalism. She argues that ‘[U]niversality in
the sense of the participation and inclusion of everyone in moral and
social life does not imply universality in the sense of the adoption of a
general point of view that leaves behind particular affiliations, feelings,
commitments, and desires.’63 A communicative morality aspires to the
51
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
52
2 Community and communication
in interpretive theories
of international relations
1 R. B. J. Walker, One World, Many Worlds: Struggles for a Just World Peace (Boulder: Lynne
Rienner, 1988), p. 166.
2 Ibid., p. 136.
53
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
Constitutive theory
This section provides a brief examination of the ‘constitutive’ approach
to international ethics, developed by Mervyn Frost.3 While Frost’s con-
stitutive theory bears much in common with the communitarian posi-
tion, it can be understood as an attempt to develop a more coherent
international application of it.4 Frost shares the communitarian posi-
tion that norms and ethical argument must occur within the language
we have available in any given social context; norms must be under-
stood within the particular embedded contexts that generate them. For
Frost, however, a ‘communitarian’ understanding of the constitution
of the ethical subject does not preclude the viability of international
norms such as human rights. A communitarian starting point does not,
3 M. Frost, Ethics in International Relations: A Constitutive Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1996). Originally published as Towards a Normative Theory of International
Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986).
4 Molly Cochran for instance categorises Frost as communitarian, and not without jus-
tification. However, it is argued here that Frost’s commitment to human rights places his
analysis somewhere outside this category. See M. Cochran, Normative Theory in Interna-
tional Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).
54
Community and communication
55
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
7 ‘All the debates about normative issues in international relations take place within a
common tradition of political theory – within what I have called the modern state domain
of discourse. Ibid., p. 83. Within this domain ‘there is widespread agreement on what
could be called the goals of modernisation. This includes the goals of technical advance,
industrialisation and the education of the populace which is necessary to support the
former two goals’. Ibid., p. 84.
8 Ibid., p. 79. According to Frost there are at least eighteen settled norms of the state do-
main of discourse. They are: (1) preservation of society of states, (2) sovereignty, (3) peace,
i.e. war requires special justification, (4) the anti imperialism norm, (5) action against impe-
rialism is considered good, (6) balance of power, (7) modernization, (8) patriotism, (9) col-
lective security, e.g. United Nations,(10) institutions of diplomacy, (11) international law,
(12) citizens, domestic priority, (13) democratic institutions are good, (14) human rights,
(15) non-intervention, (16) economic sanctions, (17) jus in bello, (18) economic coopera-
tion. See ibid., chapter 4.
9 See H. Bull, Justice in International Relations (The Hagey Lectures), (Waterloo: University
of Waterloo, 1983).
10 Frost, Ethics in International Relations, p. 84.
56
Community and communication
57
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
states that establishes their sovereignty, that is, their right to an exclu-
sionary realm. Frost argues that Bull, for instance, is, therefore, unable to
account for the importance of both of these norms. Frost also argues that
contractarian, order based, and utilitarian approaches are similarly inad-
equate. He asserts, contra Bull, that there is no such opposition between
the two norms of sovereignty and human rights. According to Frost,
Bull and others have misunderstood not only the nature of sovereignty
but also the nature of rights and the state discourse. He argues that a
constitutive understanding of the individual and the state, drawing on
Hegel’s philosophy of Right, effects the necessary reconciliation.
According to Frost the modern state should be understood as con-
stitutive of its citizens as rights holders and as free and equal citi-
zens. Individuality should be understood as something that is con-
stitutive and realised in the community in the form of the sovereign
state, not against it. Frost argues, against liberals, that the state is not
just an instrumental means of allowing individuals to compete and to
realise their rights and ends. It is instead constitutive of their individ-
uality. He, therefore, takes a Hegelian view of the state as the highest
form of community in which individuality is realised. The state sur-
passes the family and civil society as an institution in which individ-
uals are recognised and constituted. However, Frost does not posit a
strict division between inside the state and outside it. He understands
the state and the individual to be constituted in turn by embedded-
ness in an international society of states ‘. . . within the autonomous
state all individuals are constituted as free citizens, but for their citi-
zenship to be fully actualised their state needs to be recognised by
other states as autonomous.’12 The realisation of the individual can
only occur within a state which is a member of an international so-
ciety of states. The society of states itself rests on certain norms re-
garding the legitimacy of states and their internal and external obli-
gations. Thus an ethically defensible state must guarantee the liberty of
its citizens. It must be a state in which individuality and freedom are
realised:
12 Ibid., p. 151.
58
Community and communication
13 Ibid., p. 152.
14 For a more detailed discussion of this dimension see P. Such, ‘Human Rights as Set-
tled Norms: Mervyn Frost and the Limits of Hegelian Human Rights Theory’, Review of
International Studies, 26 (2000), 215–31.
59
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
60
Community and communication
17 For the purposes of clarity I will use the term poststructuralist to denote a broad
range of thinkers also sometimes referred to as postmodernist. There exists a great deal
of disagreement and dispute about the use of these terms in themselves and as applied to
particular writers both in the field of international relations and more widely. In particular
whether the works of Foucault and Derrida can be placed together under the name post-
structuralism without doing significant violence to either of them is at issue. My usage
follows what I perceive as the dominant usage of these terms in IR. Thus Richard Ashley,
R. B. J. Walker, William Connolly and David Campbell are more likely to refer to them-
selves as practising poststructuralist rather than postmodern IR (though Campbell himself
resists this categorisation). In following this usage I am also distinguishing between post-
structuralism as a strategy of reading and postmodernism as a term that delineates a par-
ticular historical epoch or movement, as has been suggested by Jean-François Lyotard. See
61
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
62
Community and communication
63
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
64
Community and communication
65
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
66
Community and communication
67
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
68
Community and communication
69
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
freedom not as fixed endpoints, universally and transcendentally defined, outside of time
or place but as continuing processes with flexible, contingent and particular meanings in
particular locations.
45 Ibid., p. 139.
46 It is important to note here that this ‘labor of self-making’ is not conceived of as a project
undertaken by individuals in isolation: ‘. . . Self making is not a private matter; . . . the
expansion of freedom cannot be equated with the expansion of sovereign powers’. Ibid.,
p. 392. Indeed the very ethicality of this notion of freedom lies in the recognition that
one’s own ‘labor of self making’ is carried out in the context of others attempting to do the
same, that ‘it is just at this point – where the differences between the ‘she’ of a locality and
the ‘ourselves’ who span localities are tested – that ethical considerations . . . arise’. Ibid.,
p. 393.
47 Walker, for example, argues that ‘[M]uch of the postmodern turn can be understood
as a series of attempts to reclaim or reconstruct or even finally to create some practical
space for, say, a Kantian concern with the conditions of the possibility of knowledge or the
meaning of autonomy in a world in which the secular guarantees of Reason and History
can no longer console us for the death of God’. Walker, Inside/Outside, p. 20.
70
Community and communication
71
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
72
Community and communication
73
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
The larger ethical implication of this, however, is that the self is in effect
constituted by its responsibility to the other and, further, ‘one’s being
has to be affirmed in terms of a right to be in relation to the “other”.61
Ethics, then, is a response to the ‘call of the other’ and involves not a
struggle for one’s own freedom but a decentering of self in the face of
one’s responsibility to the ‘other’.62
According to Campbell, an understanding of Levinas’ ethics of re-
sponsibility undermines the principle of sovereignty, and indeed all ex-
clusionary practices, because such practices place limits on the extent of
responsibility, by restricting it to the nation-state or the particular com-
munity, gender, race or other grouping. Thus, for example, Campbell
argues ‘there is no circumstance under which we could declare that (the
war in the Former Yugoslavia) . . . was not our concern’.63 To take this
ethics seriously is to deterritorialise ethics completely.64 This condition
means that we cannot stop our moral duties at the water’s edge. Further-
more, it is an ethics that in acknowledging interdependence suggests we
have to resist assimilating the other into our world; and at the same time
we have to live for the other in all their alterity.
This transcendent and universal responsibility to ‘others’, accord-
ing to Campbell, suggests (at least) two further responsibilities. The
first is shared with the Foucauldian stream and consists of the project
of permanent critique of totalisation in the name of a single identity,
and thus is an act of resistance. The second suggests that the respon-
sibility to the other requires a politics and ethics that is oriented posi-
tively towards otherness; ‘. . . one in which its purpose is the struggle
61 Ibid., p. 460.
62 ‘Ethics redefines subjectivity as this heteronomous responsibility, in contrast to au-
tonomous freedom.’ Levinas quoted in Campbell, ibid., p. 463. Where Ashley and Walker
are concerned to foster, celebrate and respect difference, their ethical starting point is a
radical understanding of autonomy as resistance. For Campbell on the other hand, fol-
lowing Levinas, ethics begins with recognition of radical human inter-subjectivity which
requires a further recognition of responsibility.
63 Ibid., p. 462.
64 While Campbell is concerned to critique the exclusionary practices associated with
sovereignty he is also aware that sovereignty under certain circumstances provides the
best resource. Sovereignty might help the defence of pluralistic communities in Bosnia
for example. He argues ‘[W]e cannot be for or against sovereignty in such a circumstance;
instead, we have to be alert to sovereignty’s investments and effects in the light of our
responsibility to the Other. Only a critical attitude which enables flexible strategies which
are governed neither by abstract universals (and thus likely to further the conditions they
are responding to) nor by purely ad hoc ones (and thus unaffected by the ethical imperative
of responsibility), can hope to respond to our responsibility to the Other.’ Campbell,
D. ‘The Politics of Radical Interdependence: A Rejoinder to Daniel Warner’, Millennium,
25. 1 (1996), pp. 129–41, p. 141.
74
Community and communication
75
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
To be aware of this dilemma and yet at the same time to have to act re-
quires a ‘double contradictory imperative ‘an imperative that requires
an “interminable” experience and experiment of the impossible’.68 What
such a double gesturing, what an acknowledgement of the complex lines
of responsibility to otherness that exist in a condition of radical intersub-
jectivity, raises is the necessity of keeping lines of communication and
political action open and in continual flux. This reading of Derrida, for
Campbell, suggests that to do justice to the other, and to others, requires
a realm of contestation and negotiation in which differences flourish and
totalisation is resisted. It suggests that one’s duties can only be decided
through contestation and negotiation and the meaning and practices of
concepts such as democracy, identity, freedom, must also be continually
re-negotiated and questioned. Were there no need for decisions, there
would only be the implementation of programmes. However, the ‘het-
eronomous responsibility to the other’ requires that politics and ethics
cannot be reduced to a programme.
Campbell calls for an understanding of ethics and politics as a field of
contestation motivated by responsibility to otherness. The ethical dis-
position he endorses rejects the traditional modern ‘preference for de-
riving norms epistemologically over deciding them politically’.69 Thus,
our ethical responsibility to otherness must not be derived or decided in
advance of our engagement with the ‘other’. Instead the ‘way in which
our ethical responsibility has to be acted upon has to be contested and
negotiated’.70 In this, Campbell’s approach seems to resemble the ago-
nistic democratic ethics of Connolly: an ethos in which the responsibility
to otherness requires the critique of fixed standards of exclusion and of
judgement, the proliferation of multiple discourses and agents, and the
engagement with the ‘other’s’ particular alterity in some form of dia-
logue or communication.
Thus, Campbell’s approach contributes to a critique of the sovereign
state and, most importantly, the development of an ethical disposition
in which individual subjectivity is understood as ethically constituted
in its relationship to otherness. What this ethicality suggests is that, if
one understands oneself to be so constituted then, one’s relationship to
otherness cannot be premised on practices of superiority or indifference
but on respect and engagement. Respect and engagement suggests a
76
Community and communication
71 Indeed on another occasion I have suggested, following Taylor and Rengger, that the
poststructuralist emphasis on difference endorses the concept of ‘radical value incommen-
surability’ between inhabitants of different traditions and communities. See R. Shapcott,
‘Conversation and Coexistence, Gadamer and the Interpretation of International Society’,
Millennium, 23, 1, Spring (1994). The argument on that occasion suffered from a too-close
adherence to Taylor’s reading of Foucault. The present discussion can be understood as a
correction to that earlier suggestion.
77
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
writing are better or worse, more or less effective, and more or less
dangerous.72
78
Community and communication
74 ‘Indeed, because engagement with the world is necessarily “global” in its scope, but
the world is characterised by a multiplicity of agents, none of whom can single-handedly
bear the burden of global responsibility, the way in which our ethical responsibility is to
be acted upon has to be contested and negotiated.’ Campbell, Politics Without Principle,
p. 98.
75 Walker, One World, Many Worlds, p. 136.
76 Ibid., p. 134. Campbell likewise appears to endorse such a project, see his quote from
Derrida in Campbell, ‘The Deterritorialisation of Responsibility’, p. 476.
79
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
Critical theory
The 1980s saw the emergence of a critical theory of IR in part, and,
like poststructuralism, as a response to the re-articulation of Realism
in the work of Kenneth Waltz.78 Critical theorists such as Robert Cox,
Richard Ashley, Mark Hoffman, Andrew Linklater and Mark Neufeld
have all taken issue with Neo-Realism and its agenda.79 In particular,
they have argued that Neo-Realism provides an ahistorical account of
77 Walker, One World, Many Worlds, p. 135.
78 See K. Waltz, Theory of International Politics (Reading: Addison Wesley, 1979).
79 See R. W. Cox, ‘Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond International Relations
Theory’, in R. O. Keohane (ed.), NeoRealism and Its Critics (Columbia University Press,
1986); A. Linklater, Beyond Realism and Marxism: Critical Theory and International Relations
(London: Macmillan, 1990); A. Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community: Ethical
Foundations of the Post-Westphalian Era (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1997); A. Linklater, Men
and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations, 2nd edn (London: Macmillan, 1990);
M. Hoffmann, ‘Critical Theory and the Interparadigm Debate’, Millennium, 16. 2, Sum-
mer, 1987; R. K. Ashley, ‘Political Realism and Human Interests’, International Studies
80
Community and communication
the state and the states-system that was blind to the possibilities and
likelihood of change in the structure of international system. By focus-
ing on the reproduction of the states-system Neo-Realism ignored those
developments at work in the realms of class, production, and what Cox
called ‘social forces’ that would serve to generate structural transforma-
tion. Critical theorists, therefore, were concerned to develop a theory
that could investigate the possibilities for the transformation of world
politics.
Critical theorists have a particular normative concern with investi-
gating the possibilities for change that may bring about reductions in
systematic violence, inequalities of wealth and power and improvement
in the conditions of human existence. They are concerned both to under-
stand the present world order and to provide a normative critique of it.
Critical theory is informed by Marx’s 11th thesis on Feuerbach: ‘philoso-
phers have only interpreted the world in various ways; the point is to
change it’.80 Most importantly, critical theory is understood to be consti-
tuted by an interest in human emancipation, in expanding the realm of
human freedom. This commitment requires subjecting the social world
to rational scrutiny and in particular ‘to promote emancipation by pro-
viding enlightenment about the constraints upon human autonomy’.81
It is this interest that differentiates it from ‘traditional’, problem solv-
ing or technical theories, like Neo-Realism and Rationalism, which seek
to merely understand and contribute to the maintenance of the status
quo.82
Quarterly, 25. 2, June (1981) 204–36. M. Neufeld, The Restructuring of International Relations
Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994).
80 Quoted in Devetak, ‘Critical Theory’, p. 146. As Cox argues critical theory ‘ . . . allows
for a normative choice in favour of a social and political order different from the prevailing
order. But it limits the range of choice to alternative orders which are feasible transforma-
tions of the existing world.’ Cox, ‘Social Forces, States and World Orders’, p. 210. Critical
theory, therefore, is an immanent theory, it focuses on the tensions, contradictions and
possibilities within existing arrangements that may allow for or lead to transformation.
81 A. Linklater, ‘The Question of the Next Stage in International Relations: a Critical
Theoretical Point of View’, Millennium, 21.1 Spring (1992), 87.
82 Following Max Horkheimer, Robert Cox made a distinction between technical, prob-
lem solving theory and critical or emancipatory theory. Realism Cox argued is a technical
or problem solving theory while critical theory is emancipatory. See Cox, ‘Social Forces,
States and World Orders’. Linklater follows Habermas in making a threefold distinc-
tion between technical, practical and critical theory. According to Habermas the type
of knowledge acquired in any investigation is conditioned by the meaning contexts of
the type of enquiry, by the purpose, or interest, of the investigation: ‘The approach of the
empirical–analytic sciences incorporates a technical cognitive interest: that of the historical
hermeneutic sciences incorporates a practical one; and the approach of critically oriented
sciences incorporates the emancipatory cognitive interest . . . ’ J. Habermas, Knowledge and
81
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
Human Interests (London: Heinemann, 1972), (trans. Jeremy Shapiro), p. 308. Linklater ar-
gues that these interests have their representatives in IR theory: Realism, Rationalism and
Revolutionism (which he renames critical theory) correspond respectively to the Tech-
nical, Practical and Emancipatory cognitive interests. Furthermore Linklater argues they
‘ . . . form a sequence of progressively more adequate approaches to world politics . . . a the-
ory which analyses the language and culture of diplomatic interaction in order to promote
international consensus is an advance beyond a theory of recurrent forces constituted by
an interest in manipulation and control. And an account of world politics which seeks
to understand the prospects for extending the human capacity for self-determination is
an even greater advance in this sequence of approaches.’ Linklater, Beyond Realism and
Marxism. p. 10.
83 Ibid., p. 7. Neufeld’s inclusion of the search for ‘the good and just life’ into the definition
of the polis needs to be contrasted with Linklater’s acceptance of Habermas’ distinction
between matters of the good life and matters of justice.
84 Neufeld, The Restructuring of International Relations, p. 10.
82
Community and communication
83
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
ideal that every human being has an equal right to participate in di-
alogue . . . ’88
According to Linklater, the principal argument of discourse ethics is
that moral and political arrangements only gain legitimacy if they have
secured the consent of all those affected by them. Habermas’ defence of
universalism emphasises
the importance of answerability of all others; what it highlights is the
need for the destruction of all systematic forms of exclusion and the
pre-eminence of the obligation to develop global arrangements that
can secure nothing less than the consent of each and every member of
the human race . . . this notion of universal consent is the essence of ethical
universalism.89
For Linklater the principle of consent is the best means for both achieving
and defending the aspiration to universalism.
Discourse ethics is premised on Habermas’ reworking of Kant’s cat-
egorical imperative. Habermas argues, after Kant, that for morals to
be valid they must be universalisable: ‘. . . only those norms are ac-
cepted as valid that express a general will. As Kant noted time and
time again, Moral norms must be suitable for expression as “universal
laws” . . . Kant wants to eliminate as invalid all those norms that “contra-
dict” this requirement.’90 For this reason discourse ethics is classified as
a deontological theory which describes the ‘moral point of view’. It pro-
vides the procedures by which the validity of moral claims, understood
in the strict Kantian sense as those norms which are applicable to all, or
‘what everybody ought to do’, can be ascertained. Thus, Habermas sees
discourse ethics, resting on a principle of universalisation (U), as the cor-
rect re-working of Kant’s principle. Where discourse ethics differs from
Kant’s formulation is that, for Kant, universal applicability was the re-
sult of private reasoning on the part of the philosopher. Discourse ethics
on the other hand ascertains the validity of norms in a process of dis-
course and argumentation between genuine, concrete, situated agents.
Discourse ethics reworks the categorical imperative from a monological
84
Community and communication
there are no valid grounds for excluding any human being from dia-
logue in advance. No system of exclusion passes this moral test unless
its constitutive principles can command the consent of all, in particular
those to be excluded from the social arrangement in question.93
85
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
86
Community and communication
have worked over time and how they have been replaced by the adoption of ever more
universalistic perspectives.
99 A. Linklater, ‘The Achievements of Critical Theory’, in S. Smith, K. Booth and
M. Zalewski (eds.), International Theory: Positivism and Beyond (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1996), p. 286.
100 Linklater, ‘Citizenship and Sovereignty’, p. 86. 101 Ibid., p. 86.
102 Linklater, ‘The Achievements of Critical Theory’, p. 286.
103 Linklater, ‘Citizenship and Sovereignty’, p. 86.
104 The topic of the postconventional agent is dealt with in more depth in the following
chapters. For Linklater ‘the widening of the sense of who counts as amoral person or
moral equal and the willingness to be bound by universalisable norms are, arguably, the
two main features of the more advanced moral codes’. Linklater, ‘The Problem of Com-
munity’, p. 142.
105 Linklater, ‘The Achievements of Critical Theory’, p. 285.
87
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
106 In this his understanding of the Aristotelian project’s application to international re-
lations is different from Neufeld’s.
107 Ibid., p. 292.
88
Community and communication
The issue for the universalist is not to replace customary moral differ-
ences with a single universalised moral code but rather to find the right
balance between the universal and the particular. The aim is to defend
moral inclusion and equality without positing a single human identity
89
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
90
Community and communication
91
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
wider than the state but which does not merely reproduce the practices
of sovereignty at a larger level. Citizens of post-Westphalian states
can have multiple loyalties and identities as well as being subject to a
variety of authorities situated at a trans-and sub-state level. Again the
aim of such developments is to strike a balance between the universal
and the particular, between cosmopolitanism and communitarianism.
This section has attempted to outline the most important elements of
the contribution to the project of community in international relations
from a critical theoretical perspective. It argued that the constitutive
interest of a critical theory of international relations in emancipation
has resulted in a defence of universal community informed by dis-
course ethics and the development of post-Westphalian communities.
This form of universal community is, according to Linklater, able to
meet the communitarian criticism of cosmopolitanism and provide a
universal defence of difference while at the same time developing a
substantive conception of global community. Indeed, one of the goals of
cosmopolitan democracy as understood by Linklater is the protection
and inclusion of minority and sub-national groups in the global cos-
mopolis. The extent to which Linklater has been successful at this will
be examined in the following chapters.
Conclusion
This chapter has provided an account of constitutive, poststructuralist
and critical theoretical approaches to the problem of community in IR
and has argued that in different fashions these perspectives provide an
advance on liberal cosmopolitan and communitarian perspectives. The
works presented here all contribute significant steps towards transcend-
ing the cosmopolitan/communitarian divide and in beginning to chart
what might be called a communitarian path to cosmopolitanism. In a
variety of ways these approaches address the cosmopolitan question:
‘what kind of community can we construct?’ In so doing, they can all
be seen to be motivated, in different ways and to different degrees, by
the standpoints of both concrete and generalised others. They are all
concerned with articulating different possibilities of community that
neither exclude those outside the boundaries of the sovereign state nor
achieve inclusion at the price of a universal homogenous identity. The
primary importance of these perspectives lies in their emphasis on the
centrality of communication and dialogue in allowing a more ethical
and equal relation to concrete others. All three perspectives appear to
share the contention that a more satisfactory ethical relation to otherness
92
Community and communication
93
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
concrete ‘others’. In this way, these theories move beyond the limitation
of the cosmopolitan/communitarian divide.
Having made this move, however, the question that is raised again
is ‘of what does communication consist?’ In this regard, this chapter
suggested that Linklater’s application of discourse ethics to the cos-
mopolitan project provided an account of communication that was more
fully developed than the poststructuralist alternative. Discourse ethics
consists of a rigorous attempt to provide the answer to the question
‘of what does communication consist?’ The principal achievement of
Linklater’s critical theory has been to introduce a model of conversation
between participants inhabiting potentially radically different contexts
but who are nonetheless conceived of as equals. In so doing, Linklater
has provided the most detailed and systematic account of what a dis-
cursively based community concerned to do justice to difference might
consist of.
Despite these advantages significant problems remain. The succeed-
ing chapters argue that the openings for communication provided by
poststructuralism and critical theory do not exhaust the meaning of
‘good’ conversation. Furthermore, it is argued that the resolutions of the
tension between community and difference offered in them can still be
improved upon. Specifically significant assimilatory potential remains
in both poststructuralism and in Linklater’s account of discourse ethics,
which require further examination. A preliminary assessment suggests
that both perspectives contain tensions between a practice of enlighten-
ment (or emancipation) and a practice of communication. While this
tension may be both productive and restrictive in the long run, it
nonetheless raises the following questions: ‘Does the project of universal
emancipation and the creation of a community of self-determining au-
tonomous beings require the universalisation of a particular “postcon-
ventional” agency?’ and; ‘To what extent does the creation of a universal
principle of conversation require more substantive transformation of
individuals and communities that is itself a process of assimilation rather
than communication?’
Finally, by introducing a model of conversation Linklater gives the
discussion a different focus. Linklater’s introduction of discourse ethics
directs attention beyond the issue of boundaries and towards examina-
tion of the meaning of communication itself. The next two chapters take
up this task and introduce a model of conversation which provides both
an alternative and a complement to discourse ethics.
94
3 Emancipation and legislation:
the boundaries of conversation
in poststructuralism and
the critical theory of IR
In the previous chapter it was argued that both critical theorists and
poststructuralist writers in IR shared the goal of a non-exclusionary and
communicative relationship to difference. A reading of the works of
Linklater, Ashley and Walker, and Connolly suggested that communi-
cation, as an act of recognition which did justice to difference, was a
common element of both. In addition, it was also suggested that post-
structuralism (in at least one variant) and critical theory came to focus
on the issue of communication as a consequence of a commitment to
the possibilities for human freedom. However, it was also suggested
that Linklater’s appropriation of Habermasian discourse ethics pro-
vided the most sophisticated treatment of the nature of communica-
tion and conversation in IR. Because it is premised on the principle of
universal consent, discourse ethics provides a more just relation to dif-
ference through the formula of an unconstrained dialogue. This allows
a more just orientation towards difference because no agent, no matter
what their particular cultural starting point might be, is to be excluded
from dialogue in advance: conversation is exemplified in the principle
of equality in dialogue without requiring (uniform) identity. Stemming
from this principle, Linklater argued that discourse ethics recognises
the need for a universal and unconstrained dialogue in order to pursue
consensus and agreement on questions of justice and inclusion. The task
left to discourse ethics was the setting out of the nature of procedures
necessary to ensure such communication. Discourse ethics, Linklater
argued, provided the basis for a ‘thin’ conception of cosmopolitan com-
munity in which the demands of universalism and particularism could
be reconciled.
The purpose of this chapter is further to advance the case for a
‘thin’ cosmopolitanism by examining the nature of good conversation
95
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
96
Emancipation and legislation
97
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
4 What Hutchings’ discussion of the legislative function of freedom raises is the difficulty
of grounding the idea of reason outside of itself. If reason cannot be grounded in the
way that its advocates would like, as Hutchings argues, then it must be a practice as
vulnerable as any other. As a result, the legislative and judicial power of reason has its
universality undermined. Reason, therefore, must appeal to its persuasive faculties rather
than ontological or metaphysical grounds. According to Hutchings, Ashley and Walker, in
adopting a register of freedom, likewise claim some sort of grounding for it and, therefore,
are appealing to its legislative faculty.
98
Emancipation and legislation
5 As Ashley and Walker argue ‘. . . any understanding of disciplined ethical conduct that
would aspire to cast all activities in the clarifying light of sovereign centre of universal
judgement – in the light of some given consensus, for example, or some canon for the
production of consensus – ironically depends on the exemption of certain activities from
the critical, juridical light to which it would refer . . . A universalistic ethical system, so
understood, always depends upon a reach of activity that exceeds the system’s ethical
grasp . . . we cannot represent, formalise, or maximise deterritorialized modalities of ethi-
cal conduct. We cannot evoke a juridical model, define the good life and lay down the code
crucial to its fulfilment, as if bespeaking some universal consensus formed according to
rules of discourse already given, without at the same time covertly imposing a principle
of territoriality that these modalities refuse to entertain.’ R. K. Ashley and R. B. J. Walker,
‘Reading Dissidence / Writing the Discipline: Crisis and the Question of Sovereignty in
International Studies’, International Studies Quarterly, 34 (1990), 367–426, pp. 390–1.
99
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
100
Emancipation and legislation
the past, and past forms of injustice, and the need to shape a universal
normative trajectory for the future.’7 In particular, poststructuralists par-
ticipate in this project in so far as they offer a politics of radical autonomy
in which the destabilisation of sovereign identities and subjectivity is
linked to an ethics of critical freedom. Furthermore, poststructuralists
follow Foucault in depicting enlightenment as the questioning of limits.
Freedom is found in the questioning and removal of limits previously
seen to be final and absolute. In particular, they share the aspiration to
subject all ‘given’ limits and truth claims to critical scrutiny and aim, as
a consequence, according to Foucault, to ‘separate out, from the contin-
gency that has made us what we are, the possibility of no longer being,
doing, or thinking what we are, do, or think’.8 According to Devetak, this
orientation towards limits requires ‘. . . the “permanent reactivation” of
the critical attitude’.9 While critical theory and poststructuralist inter-
national relations may offer differing interpretations of the meaning
of enlightenment and autonomy, they nonetheless partake in a similar
project by adopting a legislative practice oriented towards increasing
the realm of freedom, however, so defined, or problematic, its meaning
may be. Both endorse freedom understood as critique and offer it as the
grounds for the exclusion of other modes of thought and speech.
While Ashley and Walker resist a developmental or teleological ac-
count of freedom and enlightenment they nonetheless find themselves
engaged in a similar practice with similar problems to those facing crit-
ical theory. By theorising in ‘a register of freedom’ Ashley and Walker’s
account of freedom also ‘. . . take[s] on the explicit status of a Kantian reg-
ulative idea as a standard of judgement’.10 For Ashley and Walker, free-
dom, therefore, inevitably functions simultaneously as both an emanci-
patory and a legislative ideal. In this sense and to this degree (and only to
this degree) Ashley and Walker’s account of practice is complicit in a po-
tentially unequal relationship between self and other. This is so because
from this position the other remains to be enlightened or emancipated
101
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
from something like their immaturity (in the Kantian sense) and it is
this which governs the orientation of the poststructuralist self towards
the other. The poststructuralist practice of disturbance also suggests the
goal of the creation of a community (or communities) populated by
beings who share a similar self-understanding, that of reflexive post-
structuralist individuals. Poststructuralism suggests that those who do
not share this assessment of themselves as unfree are in need of enlight-
enment and, therefore, should be the subject of further critique or more
correctly, should engage in more reflective self-critique. The poststruc-
turalist account of freedom, like critical theory, suggests the expansion
of the realm of those agents who understand themselves in a certain
manner, that is, as postsovereign, reflexive, critical individuals. For this
reason, despite both the aim of inclusion, and the recognition of the mul-
tiple meanings of freedom and communication with ‘concrete’ others,
poststructuralist accounts of IR retain the potential for assimilation and
prescription in the domain agency.
This aspect of poststructuralist thought comes through most clearly
in Ashley and Walker’s account of communication. For them communi-
cation does not have the same requirements for entry or participation as
discourse ethics, they have no intention of developing a uniform model
of conversation between post-conventional beings and furthermore, are
not concerned with the development of ‘thick’ universal norms. The
poststructuralist account of developing a ‘universal moral trajectory’
suggested by Devetak (above) appears to go only so far as the thin prin-
ciple of inclusion. Thus while Ashley and Walker engage in a project
of enlightenment, communication itself does not appear to be limited
exclusively to enlightened agents. The pursuit of universal freedom in
terms of a recognition of the arbitrary and historical nature of subjectiv-
ity is not an essential component of the ability to converse. Rather, the
poststructuralist account of conversation is directed only at questioning
the practices and beliefs which serve to prevent different agents from
conversing with each other.
Ashley and Walker explicitly raise the question of how to engage
ethically with those who do not share their self understanding or who
‘in their specific marginal sites’ comprehend the meaning of freedom
differently. They ask, ‘how is it possible to pursue and expand the realm
of freedom and at the same time be sensitive to others?’:
If, in the process of testing limitations, one assumes that one’s local
strategic situation is a paradigm for the struggle for freedom wherever
102
Emancipation and legislation
it unfolds, then one is all too likely to be impatient with other’s labors
in other strategic situations . . . one is all too likely to be insensitive to
the ways in which one’s own conduct, one’s way of questioning lim-
itations – might ramify beyond one’s locality and threaten to deprive
others of the cultural resources by which they reply to the problems of
freedom in other equally difficult strategic settings.11
103
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
104
Emancipation and legislation
105
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
106
Emancipation and legislation
and
[D] Only those norms can claim to be valid that meet (or could meet)
with the approval of all affected in their capacity as participants in a
practical discourse.17
15 See D. C. Hoy and T. McCarthy, Critical Theory (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), p. 54.
16 J. Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action (Cambridge: Polity, 1990),
p. 65.
17 Ibid., p. 66. 18 See ibid.
107
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
108
Emancipation and legislation
109
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
concerning the good life are amorphous and do not lend themselves to
the same kind of formal study.’26 Personal conceptions of the good life
and of what it means to be a good person, Habermas suggests, can be
equated with aesthetic preferences or tastes in that they are not suscep-
tible to rational argument. It is not possible to argue rationally about
personal tastes as they are merely a matter of preference and individ-
ual constitution. For Habermas, as Benhabib puts it, ‘[A]ll other moral
matters as pertain to the virtues, to normal emotion, to life conduct
are questions which belong to the domain of “ethical life”. They are
non universalisable and non formalisable.’27 The resolution of conflicts
between different conceptions of the good and their general validity
as ought statements cannot be subjected to the unforced force of the
better argument and discursively redeemed. Thus ‘ethics’ as distinct
from ‘morality’, the ‘good’ as distinct from the ‘right’, are not suscepti-
ble to ‘rational’ argumentation in the same sense. Those matters which
are not rationally redeemable in this way have no place in discourse
ethics.
However, by excluding questions of the good and orienting conversa-
tion exclusively towards the telos of consensus Habermas is unnecessarily
restricting and legislating the topics of possible conversation. In so do-
ing, not only is the nature of conversation unnecessarily narrowed but
the likelihood of excluding radical difference is heightened. This dimen-
sion is revealed if we return to the concerns of both communitarians and
gender oriented thinkers.
The communitarian and feminist arguments describing the limits of
impartialist theories were discussed in chapter 2 in terms of the issue of
agency. Many of these arguments have also been made in slightly dif-
ferent form against discourse ethics. In particular, it has been claimed
that discourse ethics like other ‘neutral’, ‘impartial’ accounts of the right
actually presupposes fairly ‘thick’, but disguised, accounts of the good.
Mark Neufeld argues, following Charles Taylor, that deontological the-
ories, including discourse ethics, are caught in a self-contradiction in
relation to the good; ‘they postulate not just first order goods, under-
stood as desires or wants (for example, the individual purposes of states)
but also higher order goods that stand qualitatively above others’.28 By
this he means that deontological theories are not neutral mediators be-
tween different conceptions of the good but also embody and advocate
110
Emancipation and legislation
111
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
For agents facing these sorts of questions the issues ‘what ought I to do’
and ‘what sort of person should I be’ are inextricable from each other, as
it would be difficult to answer one without having an idea of how one
should answer the other. Furthermore, the solutions to these problems
are not necessarily to be formulated in terms of universal maxims or
subject to universal validity tests. The questions are concerned with
what ‘I’ as a specific individual ought to do in ‘this’ specific situation and
not with what it is universally right to do, that is, with what everybody
ought to do. While these obligations and concerns are not necessarily
subject to a Universalisation test they do help to constitute the moral
realm in the everyday experience and reflect the most obvious sorts of
moral problems faced in everyday life.
The problem with Habermas’ theory, according to Benhabib, is that
its focus on the generalised other is gendered and excludes the concerns
and capacities associated with women’s experiences of moral life.
The qualities associated with ‘femininity’ are relegated to the private
realm. Benhabib argues that ‘[T]he restriction of the moral domain to
112
Emancipation and legislation
113
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
36 ‘Every person who accepts the universal and necessary communicative presupposi-
tions of argumentative speech and who knows what means to justify a norm of action
implicitly presupposes as valid the principle of universalisation . . . ’ Habermas, Moral
Consciousness and Communicative Action, p. 86.
114
Emancipation and legislation
good from that viewpoint.37 As such he has not modified those ele-
ments of the model of conversation which are exclusionary as outlined
here.
Turning the discussion from Habermas to Linklater’s use of discourse
ethics in the context of a critical theory of international relations several
points should be made. In so far as Linklater’s account of moral conver-
sation is different from Habermas’ it can be addressed separately.
Linklater’s use of discourse ethics has not been uncritical and in The
Transformation of Political Community he clearly states how he thinks
discourse ethics can be modified in light of the comments of its crit-
ics. Linklater accepts the claims of both Benhabib and others such as
Neo-Aristotelians that discourse ethics needs to take into account the
hermeneutic skill of understanding and application at a much earlier
stage than acknowledged initially by Habermas.38 Indeed he goes fur-
ther than Habermas to accept that a hermeneutic perspective is nec-
essary not only in terms of applying universal principles to particular
situations but it also aids in reflecting on different understandings of
the universals themselves.39 Benhabib’s critique of Habermas, Linklater
argues, indicates ‘engagement with the particularity of others is essen-
tial whenever agents become involved in any dialogue about whether
there are any universal principles which ought to regulate their social
interaction’.40
According to Linklater, the development of an account of universal
dialogic cosmopolitanism does not need to be harnessed exclusively to
Habermas’ understanding of discourse ethics. For this reason Linklater
has had little to say regarding Habermas’ ‘grounding’ of discourse
ethics nor some of Habermas’ other larger philosophical claims as they
have little bearing on his own project. Linklater has turned to discourse
ethics primarily because it relates moral universalism to the principle
of discursive inclusion. Therefore, while many significant differences
remain between discourse ethics and its critics, dialogic universalism as
a larger project is not necessarily fundamentally undermined by these
criticisms. Rather Linklater argues it can accommodate many of them
37 He has, however, acknowledged that a relationship between these two does exist and
that one does indeed presuppose the other. See J. Habermas, ‘Justice and Solidarity’, in
M. Kelly (ed.), Hermeneutics and Critical Theory in Ethics and Politics (Cambridge: MIT Press,
1990), pp. 32–52.
38 For a suggestion of the manner in which discourse ethics can be made inclusive of ‘con-
crete others’ see A. Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community: Ethical Foundations
of the Post-Westphalian Era (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1997).
39 Ibid., esp. pp. 94–5. 40 Ibid., p. 95.
115
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
116
Emancipation and legislation
117
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
natural powers and forces and believe that social distinctions have
their origins in nature or confront men as naturally sanctioned . . . But
this is an alienated form of consciousness for what men are unaware
of at this level of social organisation . . . is the fact that it is their cul-
tural framework which endows nature with authority over them: it is
they themselves who have conferred social power and meaning upon
natural phenomena.41
41 A. Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations, 2nd edn (London:
Macmillan, 1990), p. 145.
42 Ibid., p. xii. Linklater expands on this point thus: ‘At this level of self consciousness, it
would be necessary to accept the Kantian proposition that not to allow others to promote
their self development is not to recognise their humanity, the capacities which differen-
tiate them from the natural world. To understand the relationship between history and
self-knowledge . . . is to require acceptance of the Marxian claim that man should elimi-
nate from his environment those obstacles to the further development of his distinctively
human powers. With these understandings it becomes essential for men to determine
what each individual owes the other members of his species by virtue of their common
humanity, their equal status as free beings. They must seek satisfaction as self determining
beings, as progressive beings with fundamental obligations to all other members of their
species.’ Ibid., p. 198.
118
Emancipation and legislation
119
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
120
Emancipation and legislation
121
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
52 Not only does this account exclude those not engaged in the philosophical discourse of
modernity but it also attributes reason as a property specific to that discourse, non modern
forms of reasoning are not understood to be fully rational.
53 There is a sense in which in a strict logical form this three level analysis makes sense,
in that only those capable of reflective discourse can engage in reflective discourse. How-
ever, because discourse ethics is tied to specific historical–philosophical cultural for-
mation it makes claims beyond those of strict logic and instead becomes engaged in
quasi-anthropological statements regarding human capacities. Put simply as Hoy notes
‘Habermas believes that an evolutionary theory of the development of rationality struc-
tures allows the anthropologist to criticise the practices of a less developed culture.’ Hoy
and McCarthy, Critical Theory, p. 204. The nature of the relationship between postconven-
tionality and modernity is complex and ambiguous. Habermas and Benhabib have both
made it clear that postconventionality is not tied to an account of human development
at the societal level. That is, it is quite possible that those inhabiting pre-modern epochs
in human history might exhibit the capacity to reflect critically upon their own and their
societies practices and to do so in light of an abstract universality. However, despite this
dimension discourse ethics is still troubled by an equation of reflexive thought with uni-
versality which forms the basis of its potential for exclusion, and the tension between its
goals of inclusion and universality.
122
Emancipation and legislation
123
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
59 A. Linklater, Beyond Realism and Marxism: Critical Theory and International Relations
(London: Macmillan, 1990), p. 4.
60 A. Linklater, ‘The Question of the Next Stage in International Relations: a Critical
Theoretical Point of view’, Millennium, 21. 1. Spring (1992), p. 87.
61 According to Linklater ‘discourse ethics reconceptualises the emancipatory project and
retrieves the universalistic position within a compelling account of the historical develop-
ment of species-wide moral competences’. A. Linklater, ‘Citizenship and Sovereignty in
the Post-Westphalian State’, European Journal of International Relations, 2. 1, March (1996),
77–103, p. 86.
62 Thanks to Michael Janover for this formulation.
63 Critical theory’s emancipatory project is open to a presumption of superiority, and,
therefore, inequality, on behalf of the ‘emancipated’ towards the ‘unemancipated’. It
should be emphasised here that it is the practice of emancipation, and not the idea of
freedom per se, that creates the opening for the assimilative relations between self and
other. The telos of emancipation presupposes a condition of unfreedom for both self and
other: The task then, is to liberate or emancipate both from this condition. In itself, this
formulation understands both as equal in their need and capacity for emancipation. How-
ever, potential inequality arises when ‘one’ recognises one’s own unfreedom and capacity
for freedom and simultaneously sees that the other does not recognise themself in this
manner. As a result, the enlightened agent might engage with the unenlightened agent
124
Emancipation and legislation
for the purpose of reducing their ignorance. The presupposition is that the other is less
free and in need of enlightenment because they do not share the same self-understanding.
The assimilationist resonances of this argument can be evoked if we remember Las Casas’
argument that Indians were worthy of inclusion on the grounds that they were capable
of becoming Christians.
64 According to Linklater this vision is not excessively assimilative of otherness, indeed,
he argues, only an interest in emancipation can provide an adequate account of universal
moral community. Linklater argues that it is a commitment to freedom that prevents
the unjustifiable exclusion of the radically different from the realm of moral obligation.
However, as this discussion indicates the critical theoretical ability to deliver in relation
to ‘radical’ difference is in doubt.
125
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
126
Emancipation and legislation
127
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
128
Emancipation and legislation
Conclusion
This chapter has attempted to demonstrate the manner in which the
approaches to communication supplied by critical theory and post-
structuralism in IR are problematic. It has been suggested that the
Foucauldian strain of poststructuralist IR and Linklater’s critical theory
share a commitment to ‘theorising in a register of freedom’. Following
Hutchings it was suggested that as a result both these approaches could
be identified as being subjected to what she referred to as the Kantian
paradox of limitation and legislation. This paradox manifests itself in
a dynamic which both encourages free communication and yet simul-
taneously appears to provide restrictions on it. In drawing attention to
these possible problems in this fashion the purpose has not been to re-
ject either the value of freedom or the goal of a universal community
in which all are free. Nor has the intention been to suggest that either
the Kantian paradox or the tension between community and difference
can be escaped completely. Rather the intention has been to indicate
the ways in which a certain definition of the meaning of freedom, espe-
cially when equated with the enlightenment ethos of critique, can affect
the possibility of communication between radically different actors. If
this chapter has succeeded in drawing attention to this dimension of
the project of a thin dialogic cosmopolitanism then the next challenge
becomes how to conceive of a universally inclusive dialogue in which
all are free to speak, which reduces the potential for assimilation and
exclusion detailed here. The next chapter offers one suggestion as to
how this might be achieved.
129
4 Philosophical hermeneutics:
understanding, practical reasoning
and human solidarity
130
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
It was suggested that this model contains the potential for a ‘thicker’
cosmopolitanism than suggested by Linklater’s reading. This chapter
presents the case for advancing a model of dialogue informed by philo-
sophical hermeneutics and which entails a ‘thinner’ and thereby more
inclusive vision of cosmopolitan community. Philosophical hermeneu-
tics provides an alternative basis for thinking about conversation and
the nature of a polis in which matters are decided through words and
persuasion. The argument below is that the theory of understanding pro-
vided by philosophical hermeneutics supplies an account in which the
goal of justice to difference through recognition in conversation might
be more closely actualised. Philosophical hermeneutics provides the
resources for such an account because of its orientation towards under-
standing, practical reasoning and the achievement of solidarity through
dialogue.
The case for philosophical hermeneutics consists of several parts.
The first requires analysing the model of conversation central to the
hermeneutic account of understanding. Philosophical hermeneutics is
a philosophy of understanding rather than a theory because it asks the
question: ‘what does it mean to say we have understood something?’
or, rather, ‘what is the meaning of understanding?’ From this question
conclusions are drawn about the nature of human ‘Being-in-the-world’
(Dasein) and these conclusions have significance for understanding the
possibility of developing a universal communication community. The
discussion begins by briefly outlining the nature and context of the philo-
sophical hermeneutic theory of understanding. It presents Gadamer’s
case for the ‘ontologisation’ of hermeneutics through the recognition
of the linguisticality of all understanding, and then moves to discuss
the depiction of understanding as a dialogical ‘fusion of horizons’.
This metaphor demonstrates that for philosophical hermeneutics, un-
derstanding is conceived not as a purely private, subjective, act but
rather as a dialogical, communicative and intersubjective one. Philo-
sophical hermeneutics conceives of understanding as a communicative
act, between equal but differently situated agents, in which self and
other achieve recognition through dialogue. It is this dimension which
provides the basis for an alternative model of dialogical community
which preserves the strengths and cancels some of the weaknesses of
those discussed in previous chapters.
The philosophical hermeneutic conception of the nature and pur-
pose of conversation has much in common with discourse ethics but
nonetheless provides an alternative model that avoids some of the
131
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
132
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
133
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
134
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
12 Ibid., p. 139. In order to make this claim Gadamer employs an expressive view of lan-
guage. One of the main elements of expressivism is that language is not simply a tool
for understanding to be manipulated at will. Instead, it is the expression of being-in-the-
world [Dasein]: ‘. . . words and language are not wrappings in which things are packed
for the commerce of those who write and speak. It is in words and language that things
first come into being and are [for us]’. Heidegger quoted in Palmer, Hermeneutics, p. 135. If
language is the location of understanding and is thus constitutive of our experience it can
never be transcended in the sense of achieving an extra linguistic or objective understand-
ing. The attempt to reproduce the objectivity of the natural sciences in the social sciences
through the manipulation of an objective language is thus limited by this embeddedness.
To use or manipulate language can only be done through language because language is
always present in any attempt to understand Language. For another account of expres-
sivist views of language, see C. Taylor, ‘Language and Human Nature’, in M. Gibbons
(ed.), Interpreting Politics (New York University Press, 1987).
13 H. G. Gadamer, Philosophical Hermeneutics (Berkeley: University of California Press,
1977), p. 4.
14 Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. 474.
15 In this sense we are always in a position of less than complete knowledge or under-
standing. Gadamer argues ‘It is the medium of language alone that, related to the totality
of beings, mediates the finite historical nature of man to himself and to world.’ Ibid., p. 457.
135
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
16 Ibid., p. 300. Gadamer’s concept of effective history derives from his critique of the
nineteenth-century historicist school. Historicists argued that the past could be under-
stood ‘in its own terms’ and, therefore, it was not possible to judge one period by the
standards of another. Gadamer argues that such a project requires an objectification of the
past which is both impossible and which prevents actual understanding. Historicism does
not recognise the manner in which the Historian unknowingly projects the understanding
of the present onto the past. In so doing, it presupposes a clear distinction between past
and present. This Gadamer denies: ‘there is no pure seeing and understanding of history
without reference to the present. On the contrary, history is seen and understood only and
always through a consciousness standing in the present’. Palmer, Hermeneutics, p. 176. The
present at the same time ‘. . . is seen and understood only through the intentions, ways
of seeing and preconceptions bequeathed from the past.’ Ibid., p. 176. The past, Gadamer
argues, can never be fully objectified as it is always operative within us and in ways in
which we are not aware: we can never make our own position in history fully transparent
to ourselves. Gadamer calls this the principle of effective history (Wirkungsgeschichtliches).
Effective historical consciousness (Wirkungsgeschichtliches Bewusstein) is the consciousness
of ‘. . . being exposed to history and to its action, in such a way that this action upon us
cannot be objectified because it is part of the historical phenomenon itself’. P. Ricoeur,
Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences: Essays on Language, Action and Interpretation (ed.
Thompson, J. B.), (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), p. 61. Thus we can
never have complete knowledge of the efficacy of history: ‘. . . effective history still deter-
mines modern historical and scientific consciousness; and it does so beyond any possible
knowledge of this domination’. Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. xxxiv.
17 Ibid., p. 302. 18 Ibid., p. 272.
136
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
19 Ibid., p. 302.
20 The philosophical hermeneutic emphasis on situatedness and tradition is compatible
with Richard Rorty’s philosophy which emphasises the inescapability of thinking from
‘where we are now’, i.e. from where we are situated historically, culturally and linguisti-
cally, as distinct from thinking from outside history in some Archimedean vantage point.
137
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
138
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
139
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
The concern with the Sache liberates us from the attempt to psycholo-
gise and relativise understanding. According to Gadamer, to be open
to the other’s truth claims is to be open towards what it is the other
communicates. To understand ‘. . . means, primarily, to understand the
content of what is said, and only secondarily to isolate and understand
another’s meaning as such’.32 Furthermore, it does so by enabling us to
28 ‘. . . a person trying to understand a text is prepared for it to tell him something . . . ’ Ibid.
Although Gadamer uses conversation as a metaphor for what happens in understanding
a text there is, for him, no major difference between studying a text, understanding a
work of art or engaging with another person in dialogue. Gadamer argues that all such
encounters are dialogical in one form or another. For this reason Gadamer refers to the
relationship between an interpreter and a text as an I–Thou relationship. Hence also the
many references to texts in the quotations provided here.
29 Ibid., p. 361. 30 Ibid., p. 367.
31 D. C. Hoy and T. McCarthy, Critical Theory (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), p. 189.
32 For Gadamer this is the essential similarity between understanding a text and reach-
ing understanding in a conversation ‘. . . the chief thing that these apparently so different
situations . . . have in common is that both are concerned with a subject matter that is
placed before them . . . this understanding of the subject matter must take the form of
language . . . the way understanding occurs . . . is the coming-into-language of the thing
itself’. Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. 378. Gadamer here shares with Paul Ricoeur and
140
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
Jacques Derrida the emphasis on separation of a text from its author’s intention: ‘. . . the
understanding of tradition does not take the traditionary text as an expression of another
person’s life, but as a meaning that is detached from the person who means it, from an I or a
Thou’. Ibid., p. 358. Gadamer’s appeal to truth and the Sache suggests, on first reading, that
he is referring to some sort of correspondence notion of truth and understanding. How-
ever, such an interpretation would be inaccurate. The purpose of Gadamer’s account of
historicity and linguisticality of all understanding is to move away from such endeavours
while simultaneously resisting the obvious relativist implications of such a move.
33 Ibid., p. 385.
34 ‘The acceptance of the other certainly does not mean that one would not be com-
pletely conscious of one’s own inalienable Being. It is rather one’s own strength, espe-
cially the strength of one’s own existential certainty, which permits one to be tolerant . . . . it
(hermeneutic understanding) does not concern abandoning and extinguishing the self for
the sake of universal acceptance, but rather the risking of one’s own for the understanding
and recognition of the other.’ H. G. Gadamer, ‘The Future of the European Humanities’,
pp. 193–208, in D. Misgeld and G. Nicholson, Hans-Georg Gadamer on Education, Poetry and
History (Albany: SUNY, 1992), pp. 206–7.
141
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
35 C. Taylor, ‘Connolly, Foucault, and Truth’, Political Theory, 13. 3, August (1985), 377–85,
p. 382.
36 Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. 271. Understanding is, therefore, not a matter of our
correctly grasping an unchanging tradition. Instead it is as much a creative transforma-
tive act in which the historical tradition is transformed once again: ‘understanding is to be
thought of less as a subjective act than as participating in an event of tradition, a process of
transmission in which past and present are constantly mediated’. Ibid., p. 290. The expe-
rience of change allows or forces us to see things differently, it means our interpretations
and understandings of the world transform over time with exposure to new circumstances
and it is this which creates the possibility of understanding.
37 Ibid., p. 271. ‘Just as the individual is never simply an individual, because he [sic]
is always involved with others, so too the closed horizon that is supposed to enclose a
culture is an abstraction.’ Ibid. What Gadamer means here is not that cultures have not
historically been isolated, temporally and spatially, from others, for example the Aztecs
from the Spanish prior to 1492, but their isolation does not necessarily constitute a wall.
38 Ibid., p. 271.
142
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
143
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
144
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
45 Ibid., ‘. . . a hermeneutically trained consciousness must be, from the start, sensitive to
the text’s alterity. But this kind of sensitivity involves neither “neutrality” with respect
to content nor the extinction of one’s self, but the foregrounding and appropriation of
one’s own fore-meanings and prejudices’. Ibid., p. 269. Of course none of this is to say that
having prejudices exposed is a guarantee that they will be ‘overcome’.
46 Palmer, Hermeneutics, p. 208.
47 Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. 379. ‘this understanding of the subject matter must take
the form of language . . . the way understanding occurs . . . is the coming-into-language of
the thing itself.’ Ibid., p. 378.
145
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
question, that would imply that they were already in possession of that
which is to be understood, that is, the meaning of what is being said.
Following this, the interpreter also comes to see the historical text as an
answer to a certain question, and in order to appreciate how something
is an answer one must also understand the question which it answers.48
This dimension of conversation is integral to the process of coming to
see the truth in what the other has to say. Understanding something as
an answer also means understanding it as a valid answer, that is coming
to see that it answers a question.49 It is in the sense of understanding
how a statement, text or law is an answer to a question, that we see its
truth and learn from it.
The process of question and answer goes further than this, however,
for the interpreter must also acknowledge the question that they them-
selves are attempting to ask and answer. It is the question which, in
the case of history or a text for example, has prompted one’s own en-
quiry. This dimension of understanding refers again to the questioner’s
own situatedness; the question that is asked is one that is formed in the
context of the tradition and prejudices that the questioner brings.
Furthermore, in attempting to understand, one also acknowledges the
question that one is being asked by the text:
the voice that speaks to us from the past – whether text, work, trace –
itself poses a question and places our meaning in openness. Recon-
structing the question to which the text is presumed to be the answer
itself takes place within a process of questioning through which we try
to answer the question that the text asks us.50
48 Kögler puts this clearly ‘according to Gadamer understanding a question can mean
nothing other than posing the question oneself. If a text is understood as an answer to a
question, it is related back in a productive way to one’s own questioning; that is to one’s
own problem situation. Only when a text is conceived in terms of a question can a dialogue
be set into motion in such a way that the other’s as well as one’s own views can be treated
as substantive and potentially true views.’ H. H. Kögler, The Power of Dialogue: Critical
Hermeneutics After Gadamer and Foucault (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1996), p. 122.
49 This does not mean that understanding requires us to see all answers as correct
answers. On the contrary understanding involves endeavouring to discover if and how
what is being understood answers the question.
50 Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. 374.
146
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
147
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
148
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
149
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
The importance of agreement lies not so much in its content nor its
achievement itself but, rather, that in being open to encountering truth
one sees the other as an equal. According to Gadamer: ‘[T]he experience
of the Thou also manifests the paradox that something standing over me
asserts its rights and requires absolute recognition; and in that process is
“understood”. But . . . what is so understood is not the Thou but the truth
of what the Thou says to us.’59 Understanding, therefore, is oriented by
the possibility of reaching an agreement concerning the meaning (not
necessarily its moral rightness or universal validity) of a subject matter
of conversation between fully equal participants.60
Socratic conversation
For Gadamer the ultimate model of conversation embodying this
approach is the Socratic dialogue which presents a model of hermeneu-
tic conversation/understanding in at least three senses: first: it is a
conversation the purpose of which is to seek truth. It is not an argument
in which the aim is to win through demonstrating the other’s weakness:
‘[T]o test the assertions of the other person, one does not try to weaken
them but rather to strengthen them, that is, to find their true strength
in the subject itself.’61 In a Socratic dialogue the manner of proceeding
150
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
62 Ibid., p. 363.
63 ‘Reaching an understanding in conversation presupposes that both partners are ready
for it and are trying to recognise the full value of what is alien and opposed to them. If this
happens mutually, and each of the partners, while simultaneously holding onto his own
arguments weighs the counter arguments, it is finally possible to achieve – a common
diction and a common dictum.’ Ibid., p. 387.
64 See chapter 2, ‘Socratic Knowing and Not-Knowing’, in H. G. Gadamer, The Knowledge
of the Good in Platonic–Aristotelian Philosophy (Yale University Press, 1986).
151
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
Phronesis
Philosophical hermeneutics is, Gadamer emphasises, a practical phi-
losophy. Gadamer sees Aristotle’s discussion of phronesis, or practical
wisdom, as illustrative of a process of reasoning that is essentially
hermeneutic. If Philosophical hermeneutics as a practical philosophy
begins with an understanding of knowledge as interpretative, situated
and intersubjective, then the concept of phronesis illustrates the under-
standing of reason as a contextualised practice. The virtues associated
with Socratic conversation and a dialogic engagement with others in a
spirit of openness are characteristic of the exercise of phronesis, according
to Gadamer. Therefore in order to understand the nature of Philosophi-
cal hermeneutics it is necessary to understand Gadamer’s interpretation
of the meaning of phronesis. Furthermore, phronesis represents an alter-
native to a practice of emancipation dedicated towards the creation of
a realm of suitable agents and has direct relevance to the task of devel-
oping a thin cosmopolitan community.
152
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
153
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
154
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
155
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
156
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
157
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
158
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
159
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
86 H. G. Gadamer, ‘Interview: The 1920s, 1930s and the Present: National Socialism,
German History and German Culture’, pp. 135–53 in Misgeld and Nicholson, Hans-Georg
Gadamer, p. 152.
87 Gadamer, Reason in the Age of Science, p. 87.
88 For Gadamer this task is directed primarily against what he sees as the replacement
of practical reason with techne in the political and social decision making of modern
technological societies.
89 In its ultimate form then Gadamer sees the task of hermeneutics as contributing to
‘. . . the rediscovery of solidarities that could enter into the future society of humanity’. Ibid.,
p. 87. ‘. . . I ask whether in foreign civilisations that are now being drawn technologically
over into the ambit of European–American civilization – China, Japan, and especially
India – Much of the religious and social traditions of their Ancient cultures does not
still live on under the cover of European furnishings and American jobs, and whether
whatever lives on may not perhaps bring about an awareness out of necessity once again
of new normative and common solidarities that let practical reason speak again.’ Ibid.
160
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
together for better or worse and that it has to solve the problems of its
life on this planet’.90 In other words, one of the goals of philosophical
hermeneutics is to increase human understanding and solidarity across
the globe and across cultural divides as a contribution to the develop-
ment of a thin cosmopolitan community.
The vision of cosmopolitanism that might be informed by philosoph-
ical hermeneutics is, therefore, obviously different from the thick vision
presented by liberals, such as Beitz, where universality is privileged
over particularity, homogeneity is endorsed and otherness denied. It
also does not fall prey to the criticisms which often confront discourse
ethics, including that conversation is necessarily oriented towards a fi-
nal consensus and agreement. Instead philosophical hermeneutics sug-
gests a multicultural cosmopolitanism in which, through conversation,
various cultures and individuals learn to ‘experience the other and the
others, as the other of ourself, in order to participate with one another’.91
A part of this of course is also to learn to ‘live with the other, as the other
of the other’.92 It is this ‘learning to live and participate’ with others
which is, for Gadamer, the meaning of solidarity.
161
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
162
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
163
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
164
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
again can be shaken.’ But Gadamer’s understanding of freedom is not the same as Kant’s
and his philosophy can be understood as an attempt to avoid or at least relax the tension
identified by Hutchings.
99 Dallmayr, Beyond Orientalism, p. 168. 100 Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. 571.
101 If there is a moment of assimilation in philosophical hermeneutics then it occurs in
the argument that all humans possess reason as a consequence of being linguistically and
historically situated. Thus philosophical hermeneutics does not escape the assimilationist
moment altogether. However, it can be argued that it reduces that moment significantly.
165
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
166
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
167
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
103 For Habermas moral rightness is analogous though not identical with truth.
See J. Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action (Cambridge: Polity,
1990), pp. 58–60.
104 This is an important qualification which Linklater has emphasised in his latest writ-
ings, where he is at pains to point out the open-ended and possibly inconclusive nature of
genuine dialogue and which serves to bring the approaches of critical theory and philo-
sophical hermeneutics closer to each other. See Linklater, The Transformation of Political
Community.
168
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
169
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
enlightenment in which all can learn. In this respect the other is seen as
a dialogic equal in discourse ethics and philosophical hermeneutics and
both, therefore, involve a high degree of communication.
However, despite these commonalities, substantial differences remain
over the exact meaning and emphases placed on all these common
elements, in particular, the concepts of agreement, truth and learning.107
These differences in turn can be traced to the more significant point of
departure regarding the ultimate purpose or telos of conversation. As
a result of being motivated by the goal of understanding philosophi-
cal hermeneutics is able to preserve some of the strengths and cancel
some of the weaknesses of the discourse ethics model. Philosophical
hermeneutics preserves the strengths of the discourse ethics model in
those areas outlined above where there is a commonly held position.
Philosophical hermeneutics preserves the strengths of conversation ori-
ented towards truth, of openness towards others, of the possibility of
agreement, and on the goal of universal inclusion. However, it cancels
out some of the weaknesses of discourse ethics on these issues as well.
In particular, three areas can be identified in which the goal of under-
standing provides a more inclusive and less exclusionary approach to
conversation: the goal of inclusion, the right versus good, openness to
others and the possibility of learning.
Superficially at least philosophical hermeneutics and discourse ethics
share the belief that conversation requires ‘understanding directed to-
wards agreement’. However, further examination reveals more pro-
found differences on the significance of agreement and its relation to con-
versation. In particular, the Habermasian model involves a thicker and
107 Both approaches share a view that open dialogue and the ‘reversibility’ of perspec-
tives are essential to being open to the other’s point of view. In discourse ethics this was
classified as being open to the possibility of learning and was the achievement of the post-
conventional agent. However, such learning, for Habermas and apparently for Linklater, is
really only of one type: learning regarding that which can be universalised. Linklater gives
further support to this when he argues that discourse should proceed in the attempt to
assess which principles, both in the west and in other societies, have transcultural validity
or appeal. This search would involve a conversation which sought to discover only those
beliefs in other cultures which are capable of universalisation. These appear to constitute
a predisposition towards what counts as learning in this situation. In this fashion, and
because it asserts that all normative claims seek universal redemption, discourse ethics
appears to discount the very possibility of ‘particular’ learning. Discourse ethics, there-
fore, delimits in advance the possible scope for understanding and, therefore, for hearing
the voice of the other. The self is closed off to the particularity of the other and their truth
because the other becomes merely a source of verification (or not) of universalisable norms.
Learning for philosophical hermeneutics is not associated with a developmental process
as it is for Habermas and Linklater. Instead it merely involves acquiring an awareness of
different possibilities of being and a gaining of experience (Erfahrung).
170
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
108 G. Warnke, ‘Walzer, Rawls and Gadamer: Hermeneutics and Political Theory’, in
K. Wright (ed.), Festivals of Interpretation: Essays on Hans-Georg Gadamer’s Work (Albany:
SUNY, 1990), p. 156. It is important to emphasise that to have agreed or understood in this
sense is to have ‘experienced’ (erlebnis) the other’s position or horizon and not merely to
have recovered their self-understanding.
171
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
172
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
173
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
174
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
175
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
176
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
177
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
Faced with the ‘other’ who resists or does not share its consciousness
or understanding, a position informed by philosophical hermeneutics
is able to keep the question of justice open and in dialogue. Because of
this it is possible to remain open to what the other has to say because
the other’s difference does not prevent them from being perceived as an
equal in conversation. This account resists the traditional dynamic of IR
in which the lack of a thick homogenous cosmopolitan community can
only mean the perpetuation of exclusive and self-interested communi-
ties and, instead, contemplates the nature of moral action in the absence
of a universal kingdom of ends. In the absence of a final universal con-
sensus or completed community of emancipated beings there is instead
the task of living together in difference, a task which requires a medi-
ation of means and ends, universal and particular and the pragmatic
development of wisdom and understanding in which differences and
agreements are worked through.
Conclusion
This chapter has demonstrated the position of philosophical hermeneu-
tics on knowledge and conversation. The argument made for philo-
sophical hermeneutics can be summarised as follows. A hermeneutic
conversation provides a relationship to otherness that is concerned with
understanding. It argued that the concept of conversation as one ori-
ented towards truth and understanding provides an orientation towards
the other which neither denies difference nor assimilates it. In particular,
it was argued that the hermeneutic model of a conversation provided
an account of communication that recognised equality without it im-
posing identity and that recognised difference without it degenerating
into inferiority. In this sense, it was argued that Gadamer’s formulation
of conversation as an engagement with otherness directed by an open-
ness to ‘truth’, provided a model of a relationship to difference that was
able to escape the categories of assimilation and coexistence. It depicted
the relationship between self and other as a relationship between equals
oriented towards mutual understanding and towards the truth of a sub-
ject over which they are engaged. The motivation for and condition of
this conversation is provided by human finitude. Thus, the hermeneu-
tic concept of the self–other relation is informed and fundamentally
structured by the recognition of finitude. The search for understand-
ing does not rule out the search for universal consensus or agreement
and it is possible that conversation oriented towards understanding
178
Philosophical hermeneutics and solidarity
179
5 Philosophical hermeneutics
and its critics
The principle that all are free can never again be shaken.1
The account presented in the previous chapters argued for the princi-
pal contributions of philosophical hermeneutics to the development of
a thin cosmopolitanism. However, philosophical hermeneutics is not
without its critics, nor its own limitations and exclusions. Therefore, in
order to build the case for a philosophical hermeneutic approach it is
necessary to engage with these critics. Out of this engagement a bet-
ter sense of the requirements of a cosmopolitanism encompassing the
principles of communication can be determined and the case for a thin
cosmopolitanism made stronger. This chapter examines the principal
criticisms of philosophical hermeneutics and uses them to help formu-
late a more complete account of conversation.
The most relevant criticisms made against philosophical hermeneu-
tics generally fall into two types. Perhaps the most longstanding, and
common, of these arguments is that philosophical hermeneutics is es-
sentially conservative. This charge is usually, but not exclusively, made
from a critical theoretical perspective. Critical theorists also often make
the related assertion that philosophical hermeneutics suffers from a
form of philosophical idealism and is dismissive of, or blind to, material
conditions which contribute to the formation of horizons of meaning.
Philosophical hermeneutics has also been subjected to criticism from
poststructuralists such as Jacques Derrida who charge that its arguments
are embedded in a metaphysics of the will and, more importantly, that
it privileges continuity over discontinuity and closure over disruption.
1 H. G. Gadamer, Reason in the Age of Science (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1981), p. 37.
180
Philosophical hermeneutics and its critics
This chapter engages with the relevant dimensions of these claims, be-
ginning with critical theory, before proceeding to those problems iden-
tified by Derrida.2 The chapter concludes by rearticulating a model of
conversation and an understanding of community which is informed by
philosophical hermeneutics, critical theory and poststructuralism and
identifying those elements which might form the basis of a common
perspective.
2 The discussion in chapters 3, and 4, has focused on the ‘Foucauldian’ stream of post-
structuralist thought which has been evident in international relations. The introduc-
tion of Derrida at this juncture serves to bring in another dimension of poststructuralist
thought and one which provides for a deeper engagement with the concerns of philo-
sophical hermeneutics. In addition, as the focus here is on the limitations of philosophical
hermeneutics it is necessary to address the concerns arising at its ‘origins’ so to speak,
i.e. that is in the philosophical realm. In this realm Habermas is the best representative of
critical theory and Derrida of poststructuralism.
3 For details of this debate see. J. Habermas, ‘A Review of Gadamer’s Truth and Method’
(trans. T. McCarthy and F. Dallmayr), in B. R. Wachterhauser, Hermeneutics and Modern
Philosophy (Albany: SUNY, 1986). J. Habermas, ‘The Hermeneutic Claim to Universality’,
in M. Gibbons, Interpreting Politics, pp. 174–202, and H. G. Gadamer, ‘Reply to My Critics’,
in H. Bleicher, Contemporary Hermeneutics: Figures and Themes (London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1980), also chapters 1 and 2 of H. G. Gadamer, Philosophical Hermeneutics
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1977).
181
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
182
Philosophical hermeneutics and its critics
183
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
184
Philosophical hermeneutics and its critics
185
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
186
Philosophical hermeneutics and its critics
187
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
18 See also for instance the oversimplified contribution by Caputo in D. P. Michelfelder and
R. E. Palmer (eds.), Dialogue and Deconstruction: The Gadamer–Derrida Encounter (Albany:
SUNY, 1989).
19 See ibid. For an interesting and illuminating discussion of the relationship between
Derrida and Gadamer see also F. R. Dallmayr, Beyond Orientalism: Essays on Cross Cultural
Encounter (Albany: SUNY,1996); and D. C. Hoy, The Critical Circle (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1978).
188
Philosophical hermeneutics and its critics
189
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
this particular case, the search for meaning and truth, even understand-
ing, is a continuation of the metaphysics of presence.21
Derrida’s particular problem with Gadamer, it would seem, is
Gadamer’s continuation of the project of the ‘hermeneutics of Being’
which, he argued, Heidegger later abandoned. Returning to his question
to Gadamer, this particular charge relates to interpretation of Heidegger
from different periods and in particular, to Heidegger’s interpretation
of Nietzsche. Derrida criticises Heidegger’s reading of Nietzsche and
argues instead that Nietzsche did more to disrupt metaphysics than
Heidegger’s search for Being. Derrida sees Nietzsche as going further
in destroying metaphysics than Heidegger, precisely because Nietzsche
reveals meaning as ‘the will to meaning’. That is, he reveals meaning to
be nothing other than the play of power without any hidden essence,
or truth, to conceal or to be revealed. Nietzsche, like Gadamer, remains
within a metaphysics of the will but does more to reach out of it because
he emphasises the arbitrary and the disruptive. Derrida wants to argue
that Heidegger, Nietzsche and others are still caught by metaphysics,
but he also wants to argue that it is an aporia that can’t be escaped; so
he therefore acknowledges that he can’t escape it either:
[T]here is no sense in doing without the concepts of metaphysics in
order to shake metaphysics. We have no language – no syntax and
no lexicon – which is foreign to this history; we can pronounce no
single destructive proposition which has not already had to slip into
the form, the logic, and the implicit postulations of precisely what it
seeks to contest.22
In his question to Gadamer, Derrida can be understood as reminding
Gadamer that philosophical hermeneutics is also caught in this aporia.23
21 Derrida’s critique of Metaphysics is, according to Bernstein, a critique of ‘the history of
the search for a series of substitutions of center for center by which we seek a “reassuring
certitude”, a “metaphysical comfort”, . . .’, R. Bernstein, The New Constellation (Oxford:
Polity, 1991), p. 175. Metaphysics is dangerous because ‘. . . it also (always) establishes
ethical–ontological hierarchies in which there is subordination and violence . . . (Derrida’s)
critique, his protest against metaphysics is primarily ethical–political. It is the invidious
and pernicious tendency toward hierarchy, subordination and repression that informs his
rhetoric and tropes.’ Ibid. p. 175.
22 J. Derrida, Limited Inc. (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1988), p. 183.
23 As David Hoy puts it ‘Hermeneutics may not think of itself as a version of metaphysics,
but the hermeneutic desire to decipher the univocal meaning of the text may mirror
the desire of metaphysics for a complete and comprehensive account of the meaning
of everything, for the truth of the whole and the unity of the world.’ Hoy, The Critical
Circle, p. 56. As Gadamer himself puts it, ‘. . . in taking up and continuing hermeneutics
as philosophy, [I] would appear at best as the lost sheep in the dried up pastures of
metaphysics’, H. G. Gadamer, ‘Letter to Dallmayr’, in Michelfelder and Palmer, Dialogue
and Deconstruction, p. 94.
190
Philosophical hermeneutics and its critics
191
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
Thus meanings and words are not, in Rorty’s phrase ‘the mirror of
nature’ nor the representation in language of something else. But the
relationship of words to each other is not overdetermined by tradition,
or by one particular context. Instead, Derrida is suggesting an ability of
meanings to become detached from certain contexts and attached to new
ones. Thus Derrida emphasises the infinite flexibility of language and the
limits of tradition to determine the context of meaning. Disrupture and
undecidability emphasise, exacerbate and encourage this dimension of
192
Philosophical hermeneutics and its critics
193
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
194
Philosophical hermeneutics and its critics
195
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
196
Philosophical hermeneutics and its critics
37 A. Linklater, Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations, 2nd edn (London:
Macmillan, 1990).
38 To appreciate the full extent of Linklater’s engagement with poststructuralism see A.
Linklater, The Transformation of Political Community (Cambridge: Polity, 1997).
197
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
39 Linklater, Men and Citizens, p. 216. 40 Bernstein, The New Constellation, p. 11.
41 Ibid., p. 57.
198
Philosophical hermeneutics and its critics
199
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
Or, in another vein, he states ‘[I] am concerned with the fact that the dis-
placement of human reality never goes so far that no forms of solidarity
exist any longer. Plato saw this very well: there is no city so corrupted
that it does not realize something of the true city . . .’45 The Stimmung of
philosophical hermeneutics, therefore, is one of ‘good will’ and open-
ness towards the possibilities of the other, be it a text, an individual, the
past or a culture. In this way it balances critical theory and poststruc-
turalism by presenting an account of understanding that emphasises
the possibilities for the exchange of meaning and mutual comprehension
between different agents. The pursuit of a conception of universal com-
munity which does justice to difference requires both these moments.
It requires both the awareness of discontinuity and misunderstanding
and the possibility of continuity and understanding. Indeed, it is the
interaction between these two moments which makes for productive
conversation and the possibility of learning.
200
Philosophical hermeneutics and its critics
201
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
202
Philosophical hermeneutics and its critics
Lectures in 1993. There, Lyotard emphasised that ‘all human beings have
an equal right to take part in dialogue and to “establish their community
by contract” using “reason and debate” ’.47
Likewise, a commitment to open dialogue and to certain rules of en-
gagement in conversation, can be seen in Derrida’s writings. In particu-
lar, in the afterword to Limited Inc., which is subtitled ‘Towards an Ethic
of Discussion’, Derrida suggests how discussion can or should be con-
ducted. This piece aims ‘to serve as an invitation to others, in the course
of a discussion that is both open and yet to come’.48 Indeed the value
of an open dialogue informs much of Derrida’s work, and helps us un-
derstand the aim of deconstructive readings, which is the identification
and recognition of the role of violence in communication and discus-
sion. The recognition of violence, he argues, will not necessarily remove
it entirely, but may nonetheless serve to make for a less violent discus-
sion. The afterword draws attention to that aspect of his work which is
directed towards identifying the violence in academic discourse:
[T]he violence political or otherwise at work in academic discussion or
in intellectual discussions generally, must be acknowledged. In saying
this I am not advocating that such violence be unleashed or simply
accepted. I am above all asking that we try to recognise and analyze
it as best we can in its various forms: . . . And if as I believe violence
remains in fact (almost) ineradicable, its analysis and the most refined
ingenious account of its conditions will be the least violent gestures,
perhaps even nonviolent, and in any case, those which contribute most
to transforming the legal ethical–political rules: in the university and
outside the university.49
In this way, there is evidence to suggest that Derrida also appeals to the
Socratic ideal of a nonviolent discussion, in which all participants aspire
to speak and to be heard without violence. His focus is on the violences
which accompany any mode of expression. This aim appears to be com-
patible with the goal of envisioning a form of inclusive conversation that
allows all to speak and be heard free from violence. Therefore, there is in
Derrida’s work a commitment to an idea of communication as freedom
and justice to difference, through openness in dialogue, even if at the
same time he problematises the rules of any particular dialogue. In this
way Derrida asks: what does it mean to speak freely and what obstacles
are put in the way of free thought and discussion?
203
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
50M. Foucault, ‘Polemic, Politics and Knowledge’, in P. Rabinow, The Foucault Reader
(London: Penguin, 1984), pp. 381–2.
204
Philosophical hermeneutics and its critics
and that understanding involves being open to the possibility that one
might learn from the other, that they may have a truth to communi-
cate in regard to a common matter of discussion, are all components
of a model of dialogue which seems to have broad support from a
variety of perspectives, including those which are critical of the philo-
sophical hermeneutic project. In this way, the criticisms of philosophical
hermeneutics discussed here do not necessarily amount to an opposi-
tion to the possibility of developing a thin dialogical cosmopolitanism
based on its model.
Conclusion
The recreation of the Aristotelian polis on the global scale is a common
aim of philosophical hermeneutics and critical theory. Habermas and
Gadamer share an understanding that the chief virtue of the Greek polis
was the aspiration to develop a realm in which discussion, persuasion
and argument could occur free from the threat of violence. However,
proceeding from this general recognition, larger differences emerge re-
garding what counts as good discussion and what the discussion should
be oriented towards. Habermas, we have seen, has sought to redefine the
meaning of good conversation in terms of a universal communication
community, in which discussion relates only to principles of obligation.
Although the meaning of justice was debated in the Athenian polis and
problematised by its philosophers, the deontological account given by
Habermas would be largely alien to them. In contrast, the account of
conversation oriented towards understanding and associated norms of
practical reason provided by Gadamer would, on first glance, appear
to be more familiar to its ancient Greek predecessors. To this extent,
philosophical hermeneutics suggests a form of neo-Aristotelianism.
However, the form of this return to Aristotle provided by Gadamer,
is not one which refutes the goal of a universal communication
community. On the contrary, philosophical hermeneutics is explicitly
universal in scope and ambition. Philosophical hermeneutics, Gadamer
argues, seeks to create a universal realm in which practical reasoning
or phronesis can work again. The virtues of the Aristotelian polis, and
the virtue of practical reasoning, he argues, are the most appropriate
for the challenges facing the culturally and normatively fractured
international realm. Philosophical hermeneutics, Gadamer suggests,
is essential to the expansion of human solidarity and the expansion of
‘we’ feeling. In this way, philosophical hermeneutics shares a concern
205
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
206
Philosophical hermeneutics and its critics
51 J. Habermas, ‘Justice and Solidarity’ in M. Kelly (ed.), Hermeneutics and Critical Theory
in Ethics and Politics (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990), pp. 32–52, p. 47.
207
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
208
6 Towards a thin cosmopolitanism
This enquiry began with the words of Paul Ricouer, who suggested that
a genuine conversation between the cultures of the world, which was
not an act of violence or assimilation, has yet to take place. This book
has taken the development of a model of such a conversation as its
motivating goal. It has argued that if such a ‘genuine’ conversation of
cultures and civilisations is to occur, then Gadamer’s account of philo-
sophical hermeneutics provides an appropriate model of how it might
proceed. Having outlined the meaning of philosophical hermeneutics
and its contribution to our understanding of communication, the task
of this chapter is to chart the implications of the preceding argument
for the nature of political community and ethical action in international
relations.
This chapter begins, in a preliminary fashion, to outline a more com-
plete account of the philosophical hermeneutic contribution to the cos-
mopolitan project. The principal insight to draw from this discussion is
that the essential task of a thin cosmopolitanism is to enable a genuine
conversation between different cultures and civilisations. Cosmopoli-
tanism, then, is reconstituted, or re-imagined, as a vehicle for inter-
cultural conversation. This chapter also argues that the philosophical
hermeneutic account leaves open the possibility that thicker cosmopoli-
tan communities may develop.
The chapter is divided into two sections. The first offers some gen-
eral reflections and provides a broad brushstroke sketch of what the
1 B. Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origins and Spread of Nationalism,
2nd edn (London: Verso, 1991), p. 6.
209
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
thin dialogic cosmopolitanism might look like, and how it might be re-
lated to contemporary trends and, in particular, to the apparent moves
towards a more solidarist interpretation of international society. The
second section of the chapter explores in more detail how the approach
developed in this book might contribute to thinking about human rights.
A thin cosmopolitanism informed by philosophical hermeneutics sug-
gests understanding the issue of human rights as both a political and
philosophical issue. It also suggests that conversation and dialogue have
an important place in any resolution of both these aspects.
The chapter concludes with the suggestion that communicative ethics
do not exhaust the scope for thinking about justice and ethics in IR, but
rather, provide a starting point for the development of more concrete
practices of ethical engagement.
210
A thin cosmopolitanism
211
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
212
A thin cosmopolitanism
us not to close the door to communication too early, and the task of
practical reasoning directs us towards inquiring into the conditions in
which actions and beliefs enable or disable communicative responses.
Such reflections form only part, and a preliminary part, of the
meaning of communication between equals in a thin cosmopolitan
community. The goal of inclusion also requires reflection on how the
political/institutional channels of communication between differently
situated actors can be opened and explored. The first thing to note about
such a task is that opening the channels of communication between
individuals and political communities requires that the divisions and
differences between them are not seen as absolute. It requires pursu-
ing the argument that communal and individual rights to autonomy
and independence need to be negotiated, and must take into account
the effects of these claims on those excluded from them. It means un-
derstanding claims to independence and autonomy as intersubjective
claims between equals, and not unilateral and non-negotiable ones car-
ried out in isolation. It means understanding claims to sovereignty as
non-absolute and contingent. A commitment to creating a communica-
tive community requires understanding the boundaries between com-
munities as negotiable and flexible. It requires a willingness to question
arrangements which exclude outsiders from dialogue or which unjusti-
fiably restrict communication. In this sense, this ‘thin’ cosmopolitanism
is, therefore, subversive of the sovereign state’s exclusive claim to com-
municative legitimacy. At the same time, however, it is not necessarily
subversive of the maintenance of a relatively bounded community. In-
stead, what makes this ‘thin’ community cosmopolitan is the refusal to
identify the state as the only representative voice, or form, of bounded
community. Such a principle constitutes a cosmopolitan community in
only the thinnest possible sense.
A thin cosmopolitanism is, therefore, consistent with the creation of
multiple channels of communication between its members. It is con-
sistent with the creation of ‘global civil society’ and the supplement-
ing of interstate discourse with intersocietal discourse as the medium
for intercommunal communication. In turn, this requires reflection
on the communicative dimension of policy-making in international
institutions, non-governmental organisations (NGOs), and states. It re-
quires the incorporation of dialogical relations into all such bodies,
ensuring that policies, practices and procedures are oriented towards
achieving maximum communicative input from all affected by their
actions. It requires that international institutions and NGOs reflect on
213
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
the relations between themselves and those whose interests they advo-
cate, and those who are excluded from their self-definition. An exam-
ple, though perhaps a difficult one, is in the area of emergency relief
and humanitarian aid. In such situations a communicative relationship
suggests that it is vital for aid agencies and other institutions to commu-
nicate with those whom they wish to provide relief and aid to. This, in
turn, requires that the beneficiaries of aid be seen not merely or only as
victims in need of rescue, but as dialogical equals who have a say in the
arrangements which govern the distribution of aid and humanitarian
relief. It is especially vital that the loss of agency, which is arguably expe-
rienced by refugees and the victims of natural disasters, not be replicated
or compounded by the very agencies seeking to remedy the situation.4
214
A thin cosmopolitanism
for human community is, to a certain extent, beside the point. Recog-
nising where we are now involves recognising that the institutions of
international order have in the past, and will in the future, play a role
in maintaining and expanding the human conversation. Therefore, any
attempt to engage in the transformation of human community, so that
it might approximate a thin cosmopolitanism, can start from the cur-
rent situation which involves the existence of an international society
of which states are the primary members. If the development of inter-
national society suggests a process of cultural interaction, allowing the
development of minimal, universal principles, then it is possible to con-
ceive that a ‘thin’ cosmopolitanism may develop out of that process.
Such a transformation, however, requires moving beyond international
society as it is currently conceived.
In order to understand this progression an examination of the his-
torical contexts of inter-cultural communication and an understanding
of the current international order is required. Samuel Huntington has
argued that the possibilities of inter-cultural conversation are virtually
non-existent.6 Instead, in the future, different cultures and civilisations
will (almost inevitably) continue to clash and engage in violent and un-
equal relations. For Huntington, the near total incommensurability of
the major civilisational groupings guarantees a future of conflict and a
withdrawal from understanding. This incommensurability stems, he ar-
gues, from the fact that these clashes will be between different identities.
In the future, conflicts will no longer be over what a person believes, but
over who they are. In the dimension of identity, according to Huntington,
there is no room for negotiation or accommodation.
Despite Huntington’s assertions, there exists enough evidence to sug-
gest that culturally different societies have, over the course of history,
been able to come to agree on certain principles and engage in a prac-
tice of mutual coexistence, if not always of understanding. According
to Bull, Wight, Watson and others, different civilisations and societies
have been able, through the institutions of international society and
over time, to come to share certain understandings and norms and even
identities.7 For writers, such as the early Bull, these norms have princi-
pally been restricted to the norms of sovereignty and non-intervention
215
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
and, on occasion, extended further to include the rules for both Jus in
bello and Jus ad bellum. Some, such as Mervyn Frost, as seen in chapter 2,
have argued that the norms of international society now exceed those
minimal goals of mere coexistence and incorporate thicker values such
as the recognition of universal human rights. Bull’s comments on the
need for international society to be more inclusive of the ‘third world’s’
demands are often cited in this regard.8
This suggests that international society can be understood as an arena
in which states have not only negotiated their interests but also one in
which different societies, cultures and civilisations are able to engage
with each other in relative equality. Bull and Watson’s investigation
into the expansion of international society demonstrates this point. The
establishment of international principles of order has involved a pro-
cess of inter-civilisational learning and dialogue, though not necessar-
ily a conversation between equals. It is certainly true that the norms
and principles of international society have been and continue to re-
flect the norms and values of the most powerful societies, and it is true
that the norms of international society were spread through the use of
force and unequal conversations. However, it is also true that appeal
to international society has also been a means by which some com-
munities have in turn attempted resistance to assimilation, and have
attempted to articulate their resistance to the dominance of the most
powerful.9 In articulating their claims in this way, these communities
are acknowledging the necessity and desirability of maintaining chan-
nels of communication. Furthermore, as Bull’s comments on the ‘revolt
against western dominance’ suggest, international society has in recent
decades come to be seen as a forum in which those subject to western
dominance now pursue their equality. Thus, while acknowledging the
deeply assimilatory history of this encounter, it is nonetheless possible
to conceive of the institutions of international society as having served
the purpose of maintaining international political order while allowing
a greater intercivilisational conversation of humankind to emerge.
Furthermore, to proceed from ‘where we are’ requires an acknowl-
edgement of the existing tension between pluralist and solidarist forms
of international society. Starting from ‘where we are’ means starting
from an international society in which pluralist and solidarist tendencies
8 See H. Bull, Justice in International Relations (The Hagey Lectures), (University of
Waterloo, 1983) and H. Bull, ‘The Third World and International Society’, Yearbook of World
Affairs (1979), 15–31.
9 Again see Bull’s discussion of ‘The Revolt Against Western Dominance’ in Bull, ibid.
216
A thin cosmopolitanism
exist, and in which non-state actors claim an important role, and struggle
to be recognised.
A pluralist interpretation of international society emphasises its role
in providing order between disparate political communities who lack
consensus amongst them, regarding substantive conceptions of the good
life and morality. This is the ‘egg-box’ conception of international soci-
ety discussed in chapter 1. However, in the period since the end of
the Cold War, international society has arguably moved in what Bull
labelled a solidarist, or interventionist, direction.10 Specifically, the in-
ternational order in the 1990s has been characterised by a number of
circumstances which have challenged international society to develop
and uphold some minimal standards for state behaviour which go be-
yond merely the mutual recognition of sovereignty, and which require
its members to act together to enforce these standards. Such a move goes
beyond the pluralist principles of coexistence. To move in a solidarist
direction necessarily involves a shift away from the foundational prin-
ciple of sovereignty. This is so because the central feature of solidarism
is a commitment to the principle of consensus rather than consent. The
principle of consensus means that international society can act against
recalcitrant or criminal states when there is an ‘overwhelming major-
ity, a convergence of international opinion’.11 The shift to a consensus
interpretation of international law has an impact upon the norms of in-
ternational society because it suggests that something like ‘the will of
the international community’ can, under certain circumstances, over-
ride the sovereignty of states. This is a demotion of sovereignty from its
status as a ‘primary goal’ to a somewhat secondary one.
The move to a more solidarist international society suggests the need
to develop new means for assuring the legitimacy of international law
and of international society in general, through the establishment of a
genuine international consensus on the values underlying solidarism. If
the shift to a solidarist international society replaces a consent-based in-
ternational law with a consensus based one, then that consensus must be
10 See H. Bull ‘The Grotian Conception of International Society’, in H. Butterfield and
M. Wight (eds.) Diplomatic Investigations (London: Allen and Unwin, 1966) and also Bull,
Anarchical Society; also N. Wheeler and T. Dunne, ‘Hedley Bull’s Pluralism of the Intellect
and Solidarism of the Will’, International Affairs, 72 (1996), 1–17.
11 Richard Falk quoted in Bull, The Anarchical Society, p. 148. This is opposed to the prin-
ciple of consent in which international law is upheld only by states willing to do so, i.e.
international law requires the consent of those affected by it. For a discussion of the norm
of consent see Christian Reus-Smit, ‘The Constitutional Structure of International Society
and the Nature of Fundamental Institutions’, International Organisation, 51. 4, Autumn
(1997).
217
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
218
A thin cosmopolitanism
A variegated cosmopolitanism
The previous discussion has outlined some of the implications of a com-
mitment to inclusion, through dialogue, to current understandings of
international society and international institutions. This section turns to
a discussion of the broad features of a thin cosmopolitanism informed
by philosophical hermeneutics and constituted by the goal of dialogi-
cal inclusion. In other words, this section addresses the question ‘what
might such a thin cosmopolitanism look like?’
The first and most important answer to this question is that the pri-
mary characteristic of such a thin cosmopolitanism is that it does not
prescribe the ‘thick’ moral content of the community prior to dialogue
between those concerned. Instead, it allows that content to be filled in
by the participants themselves. It is in this manner that the cosmopolita-
nism community is ‘thin’, because it does not prescribe the thick norms
associated with other forms of cosmopolitanism, such as the model ad-
vanced by Beitz and discussed in chapter 1. In this way the thin cosmo-
politan informed by philosophical hermeneutics shares a similar goal to
that outlined by Linklater. A thin cosmopolitanism is a form of dialogical
universal moral community where the moral content and norms which
govern the relations between its members are the product of discursive
engagement between the members themselves, and are not delivered
by philosophic fiat or acts of ‘monological reasoning’.12 Likewise, such
a realm is one in which norms are not simply imposed by the strongest
over the weakest, and do not necessarily reflect the thick norms of any
219
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
220
A thin cosmopolitanism
221
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
15 An example of this might be the use of modern media and political institutions by
certain indigenous groups, such as the Yanomani of the Amazon and the Penan of Borneo,
to articulate their claims to a wider universal audience. These claims are largely claims
to a form of self-determination in relation to a dominant state, but also include a claim to
resist the intrusion of certain aspects of modernity into their relatively bounded societies.
In this way, these people both exploit and resist ‘modernity’.
222
A thin cosmopolitanism
difference should take into account the possibilities for different types of
relations between communities, states, societies and the universal com-
munity. Where thicker universalism is aspired to, the hermeneutic ac-
count would require it to be the product of ‘genuine’ conversation. What
this would mean is that, rather than the expression of any particular cul-
ture, any thicker universal agreements must be just that, the result of
inclusive conversation. Such agreements may be a fusion of a number of
positions, or the creation of something new that is not unique to any cul-
ture. It may even be possible that one culture or society has been able to
persuade the others of the universal merit of a given norm, for example
freedom from torture, or even the concept of human rights. What is cer-
tain is that the participants in the conversation must be open to the possi-
bilities for learning from others, and any substantive agreement should
reflect that learning. The argument of this book has been that the model
for such a conversation is provided by philosophical hermeneutics.
By way of further comparison, this thin cosmopolitanism can be dif-
ferentiated from the account of cosmopolitan conversation provided
by Charles Taylor. In ‘The Politics of Recognition’16 Taylor argued that
the fusion of horizons resulting from a conversation between different
cultures will not only aid mutual understanding but also create the cat-
egories whereby we can judge their relative contributions and worth.
Taylor argues that, in order to ensure equal recognition, the ‘starting hy-
pothesis with which we ought to approach the study of any other culture
[should be that] all human cultures that have animated whole societies
over some considerable stretch of time have something important to say
to all human beings’.17 While Taylor’s formulation captures much of the
essence of the argument for recognition, and draws upon philosophical
hermeneutics, there is nonetheless something troubling in his hypoth-
esis that suggests a type of conversation different from that consistent
with the thin cosmopolitan conversation being described here.
The goal of discovering the contribution of different cultures would
seem to be another variation on the idea that there is something to be
learnt from them in understanding. The problem is that, for Taylor, not
only should we start with a presumption of worth, but the purpose of
conversation is to endeavour to assess that worth. The purpose of un-
derstanding, therefore, is not merely coming to an understanding, but
an assessment and judgement, in terms of an unspecified contribution to
16 C. Taylor, ‘The Politics of Recognition’, in C. Taylor and A. Gutman, Multiculturalism:
Examining the Politics of Recognition (Princeton University Press, 1994).
17 Ibid., p. 66.
223
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
224
A thin cosmopolitanism
take the international order, and inform thinking about certain types of
actions and institutions. This section offers an exploration of how a
commitment to communicative inclusion might contribute to thinking
about questions of human rights.
If there is one issue in international relations today which most di-
rectly speaks to the concerns of a thin cosmopolitanism it is the idea
of universal human rights. The pursuit of universal human rights and
their institutionalisation as an international norm since the end of the
Second World War are of central importance to the goal of creating a
thin cosmopolitan community for several reasons. First, it is the clearest
expression of a moral universalism which goes beyond the morality of
states, evident in the international realm today. As such, the incorpora-
tion of human rights into the norms of international society is, whether
states perceive it this way or not, a commitment, however thin, to the
idea of universal community of humankind. The commitment to hu-
man rights suggests that states, as well as individuals, have obligations
and duties to humankind that are superior to the obligations they have
to maintain order, or that individuals have to their states. Second, the
norms of universal human rights, in a sense, underpin most other nor-
mative developments in international society, including the shift from
a pluralist to a solidarist understanding. Third, human rights are also
a key focus for debates regarding the rights to cultural difference and
diversity. Just what human rights are, where they have their grounding
and how they can be defended as universal, are central philosophical
questions which have arisen alongside, and as part of, the usual po-
litical objections to universal moral projects. In this way, they can be
seen as a paradigm case for how a communicative approach can inform
moral debates in international relations. Finally, any conception of thin
cosmopolitanism must be informed by some sense of universal human
right to participate in dialogue. However, such a commitment must be
accompanied by a recognition that it must itself be defended argumen-
tatively and established discursively. The discussion below offers an
attempt to think through how to proceed in this vein.
In a recent contribution the moral philosopher Bikhu Parekh has pro-
posed an important and viable approach for thinking about human
rights in international politics, which is largely consistent with the ap-
proach to community outlined in this book.18 Parekh’s argument begins
225
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
226
A thin cosmopolitanism
227
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
23 In their comments on Parekh’s argument Dunne and Wheeler suggest that it suffers
from a prior assumption of that which it seeks to achieve, i.e. a universal sense of the
228
A thin cosmopolitanism
human. But this point runs the risk of absurdity if taken too far. In order to have a dialogue
about human rights two things are necessary. The first is that there is something called the
human to which these rights refer. What the definition of the human is may differ across
cultures and individuals but the concept at least must be present and there must be some
minimal recognition of the subject matter as having something in common for all. This is
the opening of Socratic dialogue.
24 In such a conversation a number of further questions arises. Instead of asking are
human rights universal in the abstract, we can ask two further questions: can universal
agreement on human rights be achieved and which human rights might be capable of
such a consensus? Thus for instance there may be universal agreement that human rights
are universal in the sense that everyone deserves the right to life but there may not be
universal agreement on the proposition that everyone deserves free universal health care.
229
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
25 K. Booth, ‘Three Tyrannies’, in Dunne and Wheeler, Human Rights in Global Politics.
230
A thin cosmopolitanism
231
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
the issue of universal human rights. They are not proposed as the defini-
tive or even the right approach to addressing these issues. Instead, they
should be understood as an attempt at a thinking through of possi-
ble implications. The philosophical hermeneutic model of conversation
and the thin cosmopolitan ethics informed by it do not necessarily have
the solution to all problems associated with human rights and moral
universalism. However they do provide a means which is consistent
with the aspirations, central to the project of achieving human rights, of
universalism and the recognition of difference.
232
Conclusion
Justice is like the pre-original, anarchic relation to the other, and akin
to the undecidable. It represents the domain of the impossible and the
unrepresentable that lies outside and beyond the limit of the possible
and the representable.1
233
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
234
Conclusion
2 P. Ricoeur, History and Truth (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1966), p. 283.
235
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
236
Conclusion
3 See R. Epp, ‘The English School on the Frontiers of International Society: A Hermeneutic
Reflection’, Review of International Studies, 24, Dec. (1998), 47–53.
237
Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations
238
Bibliography
239
Bibliography
240
Bibliography
241
Bibliography
242
Bibliography
243
Bibliography
Beyond Realism and Marxism: Critical Theory and International Relations, London:
Macmillan, 1990.
‘Rationalisation Processes and International History’, in Hoffman, M. and
Rengger, N. J. R. (eds.), Beyond the Inter-Paradigm Debate: Critical Theory and
International Relations (forthcoming).
‘The Problem of Community in International Relations’, Alternatives, 15 (1990),
135–53.
Men and Citizens in the Theory of International Relations, 2nd edn. London:
Macmillan, 1990.
The Transformation of Political Community: Ethical Foundations of the Post-
Westphalian Era, Cambridge: Polity Press, 1997.
‘Citizenship and Sovereignty in the Post-Westphalian State’, European Journal
of International Relations, 2. 1 (1996), 77–103.
‘Transforming Political Community: A Response to the Critics’, Review of
International Studies 25. 1 ( January 1999), 165–75.
Lyotard, J. F. The Postmodern Condition, A Report on Knowledge (trans., Bennington,
G. and Massumi B.), University of Minnesota Press, 1984.
Macintyre, A. After Virtue, University of Notre Dame Press, 1984 (2nd edn).
Macmillan, J. and Linklater, A. (eds.), Boundaries in Question: New Directions in
International Relations, London: Pinter, 1995.
Madison, G. B. The Hermeneutics of Post-Modernity: Figures and Themes,
Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1988.
Mapel, D. R. ‘The Contractarian Tradition in International Ethics’, in Nardin, T.
and Mapel, D. R. (eds.), Traditions, pp. 180–200.
McInlay, P. F. ‘Community and/or Difference: Gadamer on Sensus Communis.’
Paper presented at APSA Conference, New York, Hilton, 1–4 September
1994.
Michelfelder, D. P. and Palmer, R. E. (eds.), Dialogue and Deconstruction: The
Gadamer–Derrida Encounter, Albany: SUNY, 1989.
Misgeld, D. ‘Poetry, Dialogue and Negotiation: Liberal Culture and Conserva-
tive Politics in Hans-Georg Gadamer’s Thought’ in K. Wright (ed.), Festivals
of Interpretation, pp. 136–60
Misgeld, D. and Nicholson, G. Hans-Georg Gadamer on Education, Poetry and
History, Albany: SUNY, 1992.
Morgenthau, H. Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace,
New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1954.
Morrice, D. ‘The Liberal–Communitarian Debate in Contemporary Political
Philosophy and its Significance for International Relations’, Review of Inter-
national Studies, 26 (2000), 233–51.
Mueller-Vollmer, K. The Hermeneutics Reader, London: Basil Blackwell, 1985.
Mulhall, S. and Swift, A. Liberals and Communitarians, Oxford: Blackwell, 1992.
Nardin, T. Law, Morality and the Relations of States, Princeton University Press,
1983.
Nardin, T. and Mapel, D. R. Traditions of International Ethics, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1992.
244
Bibliography
Neufeld, M. ‘The Right and the Good in International Ethics’. Paper Presented
for the ISA Annual Convention. San Diego, April. 1996.
‘Interpretation and the “Science” of International Relations’, Review of Inter-
national Studies, 19 (1993), 39–61.
‘Reflexivity and International Relations Theory’, Millennium, 22. 1 (1993),
53–76.
The Restructuring of International Relations Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1994.
Oakeshott, M. On Human Conduct, Oxford University Press, 1975.
O’Neill, O. Faces of Hunger, London: Allen and Unwin, 1986.
‘Ethical Reasoning and Ideological Pluralism’, Ethics, 98, July (1988), 705–22.
‘Justice and Boundaries’, in Brown, C. (ed.), Political Restructuring, pp. 69–88.
‘Justice, Gender and International Boundaries’, British Journal of Political
Science, 20 (1989), 439–59.
‘Transnational Justice’, in Held, D. (ed.), Political Theory Today, pp. 276–304.
Ormiston, G. L. and Schrift. A. D. (eds.), The Hermeneutic Tradition: From Ast to
Ricoeur, SUNY, Albany, 1990.
Palmer, R. Hermeneutics: Interpretation Theory in Schleiermacher, Dilthey, Heidegger
and Gadamer, Northwestern University Press, 1969.
Parekh, B. ‘Non-ethnocentric Universalism’, in Dunne, T. and Wheeler, N. (eds.),
Human Rights, pp. 128–59.
Rabinow, P. The Foucault Reader, London: Penguin, 1984.
Rabinow, P. and Sullivan, W. M. Interpretive Social Science, A Reader, University
of California Press, 1979.
Rawls, J. A Theory of Justice, Oxford University Press, 1972.
Political Liberalism, Columbia University Press, 1993.
Rengger, N. J. ‘Going Critical: A Response to Hoffmann’, Millennium, 17. 1
(1988), 81–9.
‘Culture, Society and Order in World Politics’, in Rengger N. J. and J. Bayliss
(eds.), Dilemmas, pp. 85–106.
‘Serpents and Doves in Classical International Theory’, Millennium, 17. 2
(1988), 215–25.
‘Incommensurability, International Theory and the Fragmentation of
Western Political Culture’, in Gibbins J., Contemporary Political Culture,
London: Sage, 1988, pp. 237–50.
Rengger N. J. and J. Bayliss (eds.), Dilemmas of World Politics, Oxford University
Press, 1992.
Reus-Smit C. ‘The Constitutional Structure of International Society and the
Nature of Fundamental Institutions’, International Organisation, 51. 4
(Autumn 1997), 555–89.
Ricoeur, P. Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences: Essays on Language, Action and
Interpretation (ed. Thompson, J. B.), Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, Editions de la Maison des sciences de l’homme, Paris, 1981.
History and Truth, Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1966.
Risser, J. Hermeneutics and the Voice of the Other, Albany: SUNY, 1997.
245
Bibliography
Rosenblum, N. L. Liberalism and the Moral Life, Harvard University Press, 1989.
Schmidt, J. (ed.), What is Enlightenment?: Eighteenth-Century Answers and
Twentieth-Century Questions, University of California Press, 1996.
Shapcott, R. ‘Conversation and Coexistence, Gadamer and the Interpretation of
International Society’, Millennium, 23. 1 (1994), 57–83.
Sharp, Jane M. O. ‘Dayton Report Card’, International Security, 22. 3 (1997/8).
Shue, H. Basic Rights, Princeton University Press, 1980.
Shute, S. and Hurley, S. On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures, New York:
Basic Books, 1993.
Sjolander, C. T. and Cox. W. S. (eds.), Beyond Positivism: Critical Reflections on
International Relations, Boulder: Lynne Rienner, 1994.
Skinner, Q. (ed.), The Return of Grand Theory in The Human Sciences, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1985.
Smith, S., Booth, K. and Zalewski, M. (eds.), International Theory: Positivism and
Beyond, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Such, P. ‘Human Rights as Settled Norms: Meryn Frost and the Limits of
Hegelian Human Rights Theory’, Review of International Studies, 26 (2000),
215–31.
Sullivan, R. R. Political Hermeneutics: The Early Thinking of Hans Georg Gadamer,
The Pennsylvania State University Press, 1989.
Taylor, C. ‘Connolly, Foucault, and Truth’, Political Theory, 13. 3 (1985), 377–85.
‘Cross-Purposes: The Liberal–Communitarian Debate’, in Rosenblum, N. L.
(ed.), Liberalism, pp. 159–82.
‘Foucault on Freedom and Truth’, in Hoy D. C. (ed.), Foucault, pp. 152–83.
Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers Volume Three,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985.
‘Language and Human Nature’ in Gibbons, M. (ed.), Interpreting Politics,
pp. 101–32.
Taylor, C. and Gutman, A. Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition,
Princeton University Press, 1994.
Thompson, J. Justice and World Order: a Philosophical Enquiry, London: Routledge,
1992.
Thompson, J. B. Critical Hermeneutics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1981.
Todorov, T. The Conquest of America, New York: Harper, 1982.
Vincent, R. J. Human Rights and International Relations, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Wachterhauser, B. R. Hermeneutics and Modern Philosophy, Albany: SUNY,
1986.
Walker, R. B. J. Inside/Outside, International Relations as Political Theory,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.
One World, Many Worlds: Struggles for a Just World Peace, Boulder: Lynne
Rienner, 1988.
Waltz, K. Theory of International Politics, Reading: Addison Wesley, 1979.
246
Bibliography
247
Index
abstraction, 40–1 Ashley, Richard, 80, 93, 95, 99, 101, 102, 104
agency, 27, 39, 40, 60, 61, 93, 104, 105, 110, assimilation, 13, 15, 16, 18–19, 21, 34, 40,
121, 183, 202, 214 42, 61, 72, 77, 94, 96, 120, 126, 129,
communitarianism and, 42–3 139, 174, 178, 199, 202, 206, 209, 216,
conceptions of, 40, 41 222, 233, 234
cosmopolitan/communitarian divide communication and, 50, 196
and, 44 identity and, 22
discourse ethics and, 88–9, 116, 117, impartiality and, 38
122, 126 veil of ignorance and, 39
freedom and, autonomy, 120
ethics of, 100 claims to, 213
pursuit of, 120 human, 124
human, 34, 38, 69, 93, 119, 125 individual, 118
Kantian approach to, 40–2
philosophical hermeneutics and, Being, 135, 136, 138
161, 167 hermeneutics of, 190
relation to reason, 162, 166 truth of, 149
postconventional, 94, 122, 184 Being-in-the-world (see Dasein)
poststructuralism and, 100 Beitz, Charles, 4, 5, 9, 27, 32, 34, 39, 42,
reason and, 162 89, 219
agreement, 170, 177, 189, 191, cosmopolitan morality and, 36
195, 196 liberal cosmopolitanism and, 37, 161,
conversation and, 168, 173 221
fusion of horizons and, 149 Benhabib, Seyla, 88, 105, 106, 109–114,
philosophical hermeneutics and, 115, 128, 165, 167
168, 171–2 abstract other and, 69
understanding and, 25, 171 generalised and concrete other and,
universal, 173, 178 34–6, 42, 206
alterity, 15, 16 universalism and, 108, 111, 116, 127
anarchy boundaries, 32, 34, 210
sovereignty and, 65, 66 communication and, 201
annihilation, 15, 16, 17, 19, 22, 72, 139, communities and, 213
197, 233 dialogue and, 201
Aristotelian moral, 26, 33
phronesis, 152, 154, 157, 176, 186 philosophical hermeneutics and,
polis, 82, 160, 204, 208, 210, 218 201
art sovereign, 202
importance of, 148–9 sovereignty and, 65, 100
248
Index
Brown, Chris, 27, 30–1, 32, 34, 44, 45, 46, communication and, 31, 48
47, 57, 60, 214, 221 community and, 31, 46, 49, 78
Bull, Hedley, 6, 8, 56, 58, 237 concrete other and, 42
international society and, 215–18 critical theory and, 83
criticism of Rawls, 9
Campbell, David, 5, 13, 63, 64, 66, 73–75, difference and, 31, 46, 111
76, 79, 93, 104, 105, 211 discourse ethics and, 111
citizenship, post-Westphalian, see international relations and, 46
post-Westphalian citizenship justice and, 42–3
coexistence, 13, 15, 16, 22–24, 34, 47, 48, 60, other, generalised and, 43
72, 77, 137, 139, 157, 174, 178, 202, poststructuralism and, 77, 78
216, 217, 218, 221, 222, 224, 233, 234 self and, 34
communication and, 24–6 community, 2, 27, 33, 78, 90, 92–4, 99,
communitarianism and, 46 104, 105, 176, 222
discourse ethics and, 88 building, 176
ethics of, 44, 46 communication and, 131, 183, 204,
rules of, 48, 88 205–6
communication, 16, 27, 51, 73, 76, 77, 92, communitarianism and, 31, 46, 49, 78
93, 98, 106, 193, 195 conversation and, 3, 118
assimilation and, 50, 196 cosmopolitan, 3, 4, 82, 83, 86, 89–91, 93,
boundaries and, 201 95, 117, 131, 132, 152, 161, 177, 197,
coexistence and, 24–6 208, 220, 221, 231
proposition and imposition and, 25 definition, 3
colonialism and, 21–2 dialogical, 131, 189, 201
communitarianism and, 31, 48 difference and, 2, 3, 31, 60, 94, 96, 105,
community, 131, 183, 204, 205–6 122, 126, 129, 175
conversation model and, 28 discourse ethics and, 122
cosmopolitanism and, 31 discursive, 83, 86, 128, 175, 187
dialogical, 210 expansion of, 157
difference and, 26, 28, 93–94, 95, human, recognition by states, 6
211 individuals in, 59–60
discourse ethics and, 122, 126 international relations and, 6, 8, 53, 62,
domain of discourse in, 60 96, 198, 200
equality and, 26, 95, 124 cosmopolitan/communitarian divide,
ethics of, 51, 62, 80, 96, 127 30–1
freedom and, 71, 203 just, 202
justice and, 15, 26, 51, 95, 211 justice and, 43
inter-cultural, 215 moral, 6, 7, 32, 34, 46, 50, 118, 201, 214,
knowledge and evaluation and, 18 218, 219
philosophical hermeneutics and, 28, philosophical hermeneutics and, 137,
132, 167, 187–8, 193, 209, 233, 235 157, 174, 175, 176, 177, 199
poststructuralism and, 98, 102 political, 91
recognition and, 12–13, 28 poststructuralist approaches to, 62, 64,
settled norms in, 60 77, 79, 93, 98, 99
violence in, 203 phronesis and, 153
communicative sovereignty and, 65, 66
ethic, 210, 236 thick, 158
ethics, 128 thin, 174, 233
inclusion, 225 universal, 2, 7, 8, 83, 92, 105, 118, 131,
rationality, 121 132, 188, 200, 214, 220, 223, 233
communitarianism, 27, 33, 34, 47, Connolly, William, 65, 67, 68, 70–1,
92, 226 72, 75, 95
agency and, 42–3 consciousness,
coexistence and, 46 hermeneutic, 176, 199
ethics of, 44 postconventional, 119, 120, 122, 183
249
Index
consensus, 2, 95, 98, 106, 108, 120, 125, 127, philosophical hermeneutics and, 131,
128, 147, 148, 176, 178, 183, 191, 196, 137, 160, 161–3, 166–8, 169, 170–3,
202, 207, 217, 218, 228, 229, 231 179, 206, 208
purpose of, 105, 110 poststructuralism and, 102
consent, 86, 87, 107, 201, 218 prerequisites, 121
cosmopolitan community and, 86 purpose of, 103, 104, 105, 106–7, 108,
norms and, 108 124, 125, 126, 147, 169, 170, 171,
post-Westphalian citizenship and, 91 174, 175, 176, 206, 223, 224
universal, 108, 177 reasoned, 166
constitutive theory, 27, 52, 53, 54–57, recognition and, 12–13, 93, 202, 206
59–61, 93 self and, 88, 169
conversation, 3, 93, 105, 108, 110, 117, 119, self/other relationships and, 28, 50–1,
195, 197, 203, 206 88, 131, 147, 193, 200
agreement and, 168, 173 strategic, 169
as Kantian project, 122 subjectivity and, 72–3
as procedure, 127 truth and, 148, 178, 204, 206
coexistence and, 48 understanding and, 141, 147, 148,
community and, 3, 118 150, 151, 152–3, 167, 178, 179,
consent and, 87 205, 206–7
cosmopolitan, 168, 174, 208, 223 universal, 114, 120, 159, 166
cosmopolitan/communitarian divide universalism and, 108, 128
and, 39, 42 veil of ignorance and, 39–40
culture and, 25 cosmopolitan
difference and, 147, 178, 220 community, 3, 4, 82, 83, 86, 89–91, 93, 95,
discourse ethics and, 86, 88, 96, 117, 131, 132, 152, 161, 177, 197, 208,
105, 106, 116, 121, 127, 128, 162, 213, 220, 221, 231
171, 176 consent and, 86
dispute resolution and, 128 thick, 209
emancipation and, 83 thin, 213, 219, 230, 231
equality and, 26, 95, 124, 234 conversation, 168, 174, 208, 223
exclusion from, 123, 162, 166, 167, 176, democracy, 90, 91, 92
195, 208 ethos, 220
freedom and, 71, 120 morality, 36, 51
fusion of horizons and, 145 project, 85, 88, 94, 209
good, 95, 195, 205 cosmopolitan/communitarian divide,
hermeneutic, 141, 143, 145, 147, 27, 32, 52, 53, 59, 60
152, 175 agency and, 44
Socratic dialogue, 150–2 community and, 30–1, 48–9, 92
hierarchy in, 126 conversation and, 39, 42
identity and, 147, 148, 166, 178 justice and, 31, 34–42, 43–4
inclusion, criteria for, 120 morality and, 44
intercultural, 209 poststructuralist approaches to, 62,
international society and, 45, 209 77–80, 93–4
justice and, 15, 39, 128, 173 cosmopolitanism, 4, 5, 8, 27, 32, 34, 90,
language and, 147, 166 92, 161, 176, 197
model of, 28, 94, 98, 114, 115, 116, central propostion of, 7
138, 157, 158, 162, 167, 175, 233 communication and, 31
discourse ethics, 168, 206 community and, 31, 43, 82, 83
human rights and, 227–9, 232 concrete other and, 34, 35
Kantian, 97 critical theory and, 83
philosophical hermeneutics, 166–8, culture and, 7
170–3, 208 difference and, 12, 31, 197
moral, 46, 116, 127, 235 discourse ethics and, 89–90, 122,
other and, 88, 104, 120, 148, 161, 165, 168, 161, 197
170, 176, 178, 202, 210 generalised other and, 34–5, 42
250
Index
251
Index
252
Index
253
Index
254
Index
to difference, 10, 11–12, 14, 15, 43, 50, post-Westphalian citizenship and,
51, 76, 89, 94, 105, 131, 138, 156, 91–2, 221
177, 195, 197, 200–4, 208, 210, 218, logocentrism, 188, 189
219, 221, 224, 233
veil of ignorance and, 39–40 Marx, Karl, 81, 93
meaning, 190
Kant, Immanuel, 3, 39, 40, 84, 89, 97, 123 language and, 192–3
Kantian truth and, 191
approach to agency, 40–2 metaphysics, 189, 190–1, 192
critique, 97 of presence, 190
limitation and legislation paradox of, 97, modernity, 100, 109, 165
105, 106, 113, 116, 122, 129, 166, 208 discourse of, 122–3
model of conversation, 97 moral
morality, 41, 47 action, 3, 42, 113
project, 97 realism and, 7
conversation as, 122 boundaries, 86
universal kingdom of ends, 124 communication and, 26
knowledge, 16, 32, 42, 93, 152, 164, claims, 84, 107, 224
169, 171, 178, 182, 194 conversation and, 128
authoritative, 97 discourse ethics and, 120
communication and, 18, 135 validation of, 116, 126
equality and, 17 codes, 119, 120
finitude and, 137 community, 6, 7, 32, 34, 46, 50, 118,
hermeneutic, 137, 148 201, 214, 218, 219
moral, 153 consideration, 90
phronesis and techne and, 154–6 conversation, 46, 116, 127, 235
power and, 17 debates
international relations and, 225
language, 46, 50, 190, 191, 202, 235 deliberation
conversation and, 147, 166 monological account, 42
difference and, 184 development, 123
identity and, 13 conception of, 119
meaning and, 192–3 dialogue, 105
philosophical hermeneutics and, 184–5, judgement, 77, 224
193–4, 235 knowledge, 153
reason and, 162 life, 165, 171
understanding and, 193, 198 women’s experiences of, 112–13
universality of, 135 obligations, 6
learning, 170, 200 point of view, 32, 107, 109, 114, 128
inter-civilisational, 216 realm, 3, 38, 98, 111, 112, 113
linguisticality, 165, 166, 193–4, 235 reasoning, 37, 38
understanding and, 143, 164, relativism, 45
185, 208 responsibility, 104
Levinas (Emmanuel), 73, 74, 75, 104, theory
105 difference and, 10
liberalism, 48, 78, see also cosmopolitanism international politics and, 9
limitation and legislation paradox, see international relations and, 12
Kantian justice and, 9–10
Linklater, Andrew, 4, 5, 6, 9, 12, 13, 27, 32, maternal thinking and, 112
54, 80, 82, 83, 87, 93, 95–6, 99, 100, universalism, 41, 83, 115, 225
106, 117, 118, 119, 123, 129, 165, 197, validity, 84, 127
198, 200, 202, 214, 219, 220 universal, 106
discourse ethics and, 84–6, 88–90, 94, morality, 32, 110
105, 115–16, 126, 127, 130, 169 care and, 112
emancipation and, 124–5 communicative, 51
255
Index
256
Index
257
Index
258
Index
259
Index
260
CAMBRIDGE STUDIES IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
65 Daniel W. Drezner
The sanctions paradox
Economic statecraft and international relations
64 Viva Ona Bartkus
The dynamic of secession
63 John A. Vasquez
The power of power politics
From classical realism to neotraditionalism
61 Charles Jones
E. H. Carr and international relations
A duty to lie
60 Jeffrey W. Knopf
Domestic society and international cooperation
The impact of protest on US arms control policy
57 Randall D. Germain
The international organization of credit
States and global finance in the world economy
56 N. Piers Ludlow
Dealing with Britain
The Six and the first UK application to the EEC
55 Andreas Hasenclever, Peter Mayer and Volker Rittberger
Theories of international regimes
53 James N. Rosenau
Along the domestic-foreign frontier
Exploring governance in a turbulent world
52 John M. Hobson
The wealth of states
A comparative sociology of international economic and
political change
51 Kalevi J. Holsti
The state, war, and the state of war
50 Christopher Clapham
Africa and the international system
The politics of state survival
49 Susan Strange
The retreat of the state
The diffusion of power in the world economy
48 William I. Robinson
Promoting polyarchy
Globalization, US intervention, and hegemony
47 Roger Spegele
Political realism in international theory
46 Thomas J. Biersteker and Cynthia Weber (eds.)
State sovereignty as social construct
45 Mervyn Frost
Ethics in international relations
A constitutive theory
44 Mark W. Zacher with Brent A. Sutton
Governing global networks
International regimes for transportation and communications
43 Mark Neufeld
The restructuring of international relations theory
42 Thomas Risse-Kappen (ed.)
Bringing transnational relations back in
Non-state actors, domestic structures and international institutions
41 Hayward R. Alker
Rediscoveries and reformulations
Humanistic methodologies for international studies
38 Mark Rupert
Producing hegemony
The politics of mass production and American global power
37 Cynthia Weber
Simulating sovereignty
Intervention, the state and symbolic exchange
36 Gary Goertz
Contexts of international politics
35 James L. Richardson
Crisis diplomacy
The Great Powers since the mid-nineteenth century
34 Bradley S. Klein
Strategic studies and world order
The globl politics of deterrence
33 T. V. Paul
Asymmetric conflicts: war initiation by weaker powers
32 Christine Sylvester
Feminist theory and international relations in a postmodern era
31 Peter J. Schraeder
US foreign policy toward Africa
Incrementalism, crisis and change
30 Graham Spinardi
From Polaris to Trident: The development of US Fleet
Ballistic Missile technology
29 David A. Welch
Justice and the genesis of war
28 Russell J. Leng
Interstate crisis behavior, 1816–1980: realism versus reciprocity
27 John A. Vasquez
The war puzzle
24 R. B. J. Walker
Inside/outside: international relations as political theory
23 Edward Reiss
The strategic defense initiative
22 Keith Krause
Arms and the state: patterns of military production and trade
21 Roger Buckley
US–Japan alliance diplomacy 1945–1990
16 Charles F. Doran
Systems in crisis
New imperatives of high politics at century’s end
15 Deon Geldenhuys
Isolated states: a comparative analysis
14 Kalevi J. Holsti
Peace and war: armed conflicts and international order 1648–1989
13 Saki Dockrill
Britain’s policy for West German rearmament 1950–1955
12 Robert H. Jackson
Quasi-states: sovereignty, international relations and the
Third World
9 William Bloom
Personal identity, national identity and international relations
8 Zeev Maoz
National choices and international processes
7 Ian Clark
The hierarchy of states
Reform and resistance in the international order
6 Hidemi Suganami
The domestic analogy and world order proposals
5 Stephen Gill
American hegemony and the Trilateral Commission
4 Michael C. Pugh
The ANZUS crisis, nuclear visiting and deterrence
3 Michael Nicholson
Formal theories in international relations
2 Friedrich V. Kratochwil
Rules, norms, and decisions
On the conditions of practical and legal reasoning in international relations
and domestic affairs
1 Myles L. C. Robertson
Soviet policy towards Japan
An analysis of trends in the 1970s and 1980s