Philip Kitcher The Ethical Project 2011
Philip Kitcher The Ethical Project 2011
Philip Kitcher The Ethical Project 2011
Philip Kitcher
Introduction 1
§1. The Shape of Things to Come 1
§2. Methodological Preliminaries 9
I. An Analytical History
1. The Springs of Sympathy 17
§3. Psychological Altruism: Basics 17
§4. The Varieties of Altruistic Reactions 25
§5. Some Dimensions of Altruism 31
§6. Maternal Concern 35
§7. Broader Forms of Altruism? 42
§8. Possibilities of Evolutionary Explanation 47
§9. The Coalition Game 57
2. Normative Guidance 67
§10. The Limits of Altruism 67
§11. Following Orders 74
§12. Punishment 87
§13. Conscience 92
§14. Social Embedding 96
viii Contents
Acknowledgments 411
Index 417
Moral conceptions and processes grow naturally
out of the very conditions of human life.
—John Dewey
Introduction
1
2 the ethica l project
2. Darwin himself made some first efforts to inaugurate this program in the early chap-
ters of The Descent of Man (John Murray, 1872). Thomas Kuhn proposed a similar under-
standing of the natural sciences as historical products (The Structure of Scientific Revolu-
tions [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962 and 1970]). I have followed their lead,
both for the sciences and for mathematics (in The Advancement of Science [New York: Oxford
University Press, 1993] and in The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge [New York: Oxford
University Press, 1983]).
Introduction 3
3. Charles Darwin, On the Origin of Species (facsimile of the fi rst edition), edited by
Ernst Mayr (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964), between 116 and 117.
4. See The Quest for Certainty, vol. 4 in John Dewey: The Later Works (Carbondale:
Southern Illinois University Press, 1988), 204; and Reconstruction in Philosophy (Boston:
Beacon Press, 1957), 147.
5. See Dewey and James Tufts, Ethics, 2nd ed. (New York: Henry Holt, 1932), 307– 9;
William James, Pragmatism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978), Lecture
VI.
6. The inversion of Hamlet stems from Nelson Goodman: Fact, Fiction, and Forecast
(Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, 1956).
4 the ethica l project
7. The considerations bluntly advanced here are elaborated at much greater length in
the last chapter of my Living with Darwin (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007).
Introduction 5
ing out the places where false belief has intruded. A secular renewal of
the ethical project requires constructive work, positive steps going
beyond brusque denial.8
Given these clarifications, I can now explain the structure of the fol-
lowing chapters. Part I, Chapters 1–4, elaborates an “analytical history,”
aimed at providing insight into the evolution of our ethical practice. It
provides a basis on which Part II (Chapters 5–7) can explore questions
about ethics: given this account of the origins and unfolding of ethics,
can we make sense of ethical truth or ethical knowledge? The history of
Part I and the metaethical account of Part II are then extended, in Part
III (Chapters 8–10), into a normative stance, an attempt to suggest how
we might best go on from where we are.
It is worth supplementing this bald characterization with a little more
detail. A “history of ethical practice” might take many forms, and the
one I offer may initially appear strange. Since I suppose our species to
have been engaged in the ethical project for tens of thousands of years, it
would be hopeless to offer a narrative showing how particular aspects of
ethical life have gradually emerged. Until the invention of writing (five
thousand years ago), the clues are fragmentary, far scantier than the fos-
sil record, whose poverty provoked Darwin’s lament.9 Primatology, an-
thropology, and archeology enable us to offer a plausible account of the
conditions under which our preethical ancestors lived, but many sub-
sequent steps are beyond our evidential grasp.
The analytical history starts by attempting to understand relevant
psychological capacities of the preethical ancestors, and, on that basis,
to portray the initial stages of the ethical project. Hominid social life was
akin to the contemporary lives of our closest evolutionary relatives: our
precursors lived in small groups, mixed by age and sex. For that, they
needed a capacity for psychological altruism. Yet the limitations of their
altruistic dispositions made living together tense and difficult. The first
ethicists overcame some of the problems by agreeing on rules for conduct,
8. See the closing pages of Living with Darwin, as well as “Challenges for Secularism,”
in The Joy of Secularism, ed. George Levine (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,
2011).
9. Darwin, Origin of Species, chap. 9, esp. 310–11.
6 the ethica l project
rules remedying a few of the recurrent altruism failures that had plagued
their group life. Very probably, they began with precepts about sharing
scant resources and not initiating violence.
Because the character of early ethical practices is so much simpler
than the forms of ethical life visible once written documents are avail-
able, it is important to show (Chapter 3), how a series of gradual steps
might have taken the ethical project from its relatively crude initial phase
to the complex articulation of rules and stories found in the first written
documents. Thereafter, it is possible to trace, although not with the
completeness one might hope for, how actual changes in ethical practice
have occurred. Chapter 4 considers a few examples from history (rather
than prehistory) with the aim of supporting two main theses. First, it is
hard to resist the recognition of occasional progress in the evolution of
ethics: perhaps ethical progress is rare, but there are transitions (like the
repudiation of slavery) in which it seems to occur. Second, even when
the records kept by people who participated in apparently progressive
ethical change are most extensive, moments of ethical discovery are elu-
sive: there are no analogs of episodes of scientific insight.
The history of Part I offers hypotheses about how the ethical project
actually began, and how, in recent history, it has actually gone. It also
addresses concern about the vast difference between the early stages of
the project and the rich practices found at the dawn of history by show-
ing how it would have been possible for the bare beginnings to evolve, by
gradual steps, into the complex systems discernible in the earliest texts.
Because the differences in these two modes of explanation need to be
clearly appreciated, the next section will address some methodological
preliminaries.
How can any history, however carefully focused and articulated, bear
on philosophical questions about ethics? One possibility, already illus-
trated by the example of religion, is that a historical account might un-
dermine current practice. Seeing where our approaches have come from
could breed skepticism and disillusionment. In those episodes of ethical
change most susceptible to analysis, the participants do not appear to
apprehend some previously unrecognized value, or to reason their ways
to some novel moral principle. Historical detail, to the extent it can be
provided, is inhospitable to philosophical theories about ethical truth
Introduction 7
(Chapter 5). Yet the history of Part I also reveals examples of ethical
progress. The metaethical perspective of Part II centers on trying to
reconcile these points.
A “mere change” view of ethical evolution, in which the history is
simply one damned thing after another, conflicts with the pull to charac-
terize some transitions as advances. Chapter 6 resolves the conflict by
seeking an account of ethical progress, one that abandons the idea of
progress as accumulation of (prior, independent) truth. If this appears a
strange idea, we should recall that, in some areas of human practice, prog-
ress does not consist in the increase of truth. Technological progress is
often a matter of discharging certain functions more efficiently or more
fully. Moreover, in line with the history of Part I, the initial ventures in
the ethical project are readily conceived as introducing a new—social—
technology, aimed at remedying disruptive altruism failures.
Amelioration of altruism failure was the initial function of ethical
practice. Yet the obvious differences between the pioneering ventures
and the complex codes present at the dawn of recorded history show
clearly that other functions have emerged. That is the way with technol-
ogy in general. People begin with a problem and achieve partial suc-
cesses in solving it. The successes generate new problems to be solved.
Chapter 6 attempts to anchor the concept of ethical progress in the dis-
charging of functions, originating with the problem of remedying fail-
ures of altruism, and understanding later functions as generated from
the solutions previously obtained.
It thereby paves the way for a concept of ethical truth. Ethical truths
are those acquired in progressive transitions and retained through an
indefinite sequence of progressive transitions. Pragmatic naturalism pro-
poses that some ethical statements—typically, vague generalizations, com-
mending honesty and disavowing violence, for example—are true. They
owe their truth to the role they play in ethical progress: “truth happens
to an idea.”10
To declare that our ancestors invented ethics is to deny that they dis-
covered it or that it was revealed to them. Pragmatic naturalism rejects
the idea of a special moment (long ago on Mount Sinai, perhaps) when
11. This idea, defended by some sociobiologists, is criticized in the fi nal chapter of my
Vaulting Ambition: Sociobiology and the Quest for Human Nature (Cambridge, MA: The
MIT Press, 1985).
12. For a forthright attempt to link human ethical practice to the altruistic tendencies of
other primate species, see Frans de Waal, Primates and Philosophers (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 2006).
10 the ethica l project
13. A view well articulated and defended by Marc Hauser: Moral Minds (New York:
Ecco, 2006).
14. Finally, pragmatic naturalism also rejects the thought that significant advances can
be made in understanding ethical issues by undertaking psychological, or neurological,
experiments in which subjects are asked to respond to abstract philosophical scenarios. It
is unclear what capacities are being fathomed in posing the questions: for questions and
concerns that would arise in everyday life are artificially excluded. Moreover, pragmatic
naturalism looks for an alternative to current ethical theorizing, rather than for an experi-
mental extension building on available options.
15. The locus classicus for this accusation is Stephen Jay Gould and Richard Lewontin,
“The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adapta-
tionist Programme,” Proceedings of the Royal Society, B, 205, 1979, 581– 98. In Vaulting
Ambition, I argued that storytelling vitiates much work in human sociobiology.
Introduction 11
How did our ethical ancestors move from those simple beginnings to
the complex forms of ethical life recognizable in the world of ancient his-
tory? No answer can claim to tell the actual story. Here pragmatic natu-
ralism must face the difficulty of discriminating a preferred story from
potential rivals. It is, however, committed to supposing some sequence
of transitions led—without revelations, without discoveries of the struc-
ture of values or the moral law, without any “spooks”—to an endpoint
enormously richer and more complex than the original practices. To an-
swer skeptics claiming that “real ethics” requires resources naturalists
cannot allow, some narrative needs to be given. It cannot be advertised as
a “how actually” explanation; instead it is a “how possibly” explanation.
Explanations come in many varieties, but for the purposes of this
book, these two types will suffice. A historical “how actually” explana-
tion aims to tell the truth about a sequence of events: if it is properly sup-
ported, rival options have to be eliminated by the evidence. A historical
“how possibly” explanation, by contrast, aims only to tell a story, con-
sistent with the evidence and with background constraints: its status is
not impugned by pointing out that there are other options (the more, the
merrier). A “how possibly” explanation is important because we some-
times wonder whether a chain of occurrences could have occurred, or
whether the occurrence of the sequence is permitted by a particular
theory. Opponents wonder, for example, if the processes countenanced
by Darwin and his successors allow for the evolution of the cell. Answer-
ing their doubts requires showing how Darwinian processes might have
produced the cell. It would be marvelous, of course, to be able to say
how the history actually went, but, given the temporal remoteness of the
events and the limitations of our evidence, modesty is required. In the
context of rebutting the skeptical challenge, modesty—settling for “how
possibly”—is enough.
Pragmatic naturalism can advance probable hypotheses about the
original state in which the ethical project began, and about the character
of the evolution of the project during recorded history. With respect
to the transformations that occurred between the early phases and the
practices of the ancient world, all that can be claimed is that these could
have happened without supposing processes or causes of kinds prag-
matic naturalism rejects. The history of Part I is self-conscious about the
Introduction 13
An Analytical History
chapter 1
1. There is a long tradition, stemming from Hume, Adam Smith, and Schopenhauer,
that places a capacity for sympathy at the center of ethics. In recent years, that tradition has
been renewed by phi losophers (Simon Blackburn, Ruling Passions [New York: Oxford
University Press, 1999]) and by primatologists (Frans de Waal, Primates and Philosophers
[Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007]). Although the approach I shall defend
overlaps with some of the themes of this tradition, it does not ascribe sympathy (or altru-
ism) so dominant a role. For explicit comparisons, see my discussion of de Waal, “Ethics
and Evolution: How to Get Here from There,” in Primates and Philosophers.
17
18 the ethica l project
2. Different anthropologists use different methods for estimating hominid group size,
some favoring direct comparisons with social groups in other species (either evolution-
ary relatives or primates with a similar ecology), others taking extant hunter-gatherer
bands as models or seeking correlations with mea sur able anatomical features (e.g., skull
size) and extrapolating from the results on hominid skulls (viewed as providing clues to
the relative increase in neocortex size). See Robin Dunbar, Grooming, Gossip, and the
Origins of Language (London: Faber, 1996); Steven Mithen Pre- History of the Mind
(London: Thames and Hudson, 1996); Christoph Boehm, Hierarchy in the Forest (Cam-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999); Clive Gamble, The Palaeolithic Societies
of Europe (Oxford, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1999); and Peter MacNeilage, The Ori-
gin of Speech (Oxford University Press, 2008). Although I am inclined to accept a relatively
small value (30–70), my conclusions would not be greatly affected were this increased to,
say, 80–140.
3. The original papers are W. D. Hamilton, “Genetical Evolution of Social Behavior,” I,
II, Journal of Theoretical Biology 7 (1964): 1–52; Robert Trivers, “The Evolution of Recip-
rocal Altruism,” Quarterly Review of Biology 46 (1971): 35–57; Robert Axelrod and William
Hamilton, “The Evolution of Cooperation,” Science 211 (1981): 1390– 96. Lucid and acces-
sible summaries are available in Richard Dawkins, The Selfi sh Gene, 2nd ed. (New York:
The Springs of Sympathy 19
Oxford University Press, 1993); and Robert Axelrod, The Evolution of Cooperation (New
York: Basic Books, 1984). I shall be exploring these important ideas in §8.
4. For discussions about behavioral altruism, I am indebted to Christine Clavien.
5. There are complications that I glide over here and that will be addressed more
thoroughly in treating the third type of altruism, the one pertinent to the examination of
ethics. After the presentation of that third notion, it will be easier to see how to charac-
terize behavioral altruism more exactly.
6. As the specification of psychological altruism will show, the account begins with
wishes. Interests come later (§21).
20 the ethica l project
Many people believe psychological altruism does not exist, even that
it is impossible. Often they are moved by a very simple line of reasoning:
when a person acts in a way that could be appraised as altruistic, he or
she acts intentionally; to act intentionally is to identify an outcome one
wants and to attempt to realize that outcome; hence, any potential altru-
ist is trying to get what he or she wants; but to strive for what you want is
egoistic; consequently, the potential altruist turns out to be an egoist
after all. The key to rebutting this argument is to distinguish different
kinds of wants and goals. Some of our desires are directed toward our-
selves and our own well-being; other desires may be directed toward the
welfare of other people. Desires of the former type are the hallmark of
egoism, but those of the latter sort are altruistic. So altruists are inten-
tional agents whose effective desires are other-directed.7
I shall develop this approach to psychological altruism further, by
giving a more detailed account of the character of other-directed desires,
and thereby bringing into the open some of the complexities of the con-
cept of altruism. In focusing on desires, I ignore for the moment the fact
that there are other psychological attitudes—hopes, aspirations, and
particularly emotions—that can be properly characterized as altruis-
tic. Attention to these other types of states will occupy us in the next
section. Because of the connection of desires with intentions and ac-
tions, altruistic desires have a certain priority. They are thus the topic
of the basic account.
The other-directed desires central to the defense of the possibility of
altruism are desires that respond to the altruistic agent’s recognition of the
impact of his or her actions on the situations of others. To be an altruist
is to have a particular kind of relational structure in your psychological
life—when you come to see that what you do will affect other people, the
wants you have, the emotions you feel, the intentions you form, change
from what they would have been in the absence of that recognition. Be-
cause you see the consequences for others of what you envisage doing,
the psychological attitudes you adopt are different. You are moved by the
7. This line of response surfaces in the eighteenth century in the famous series of ser-
mons given by Joseph Butler at the Rolls Chapel. Many subsequent writers have followed
Butler’s lead—as shall I.
The Springs of Sympathy 21
perceived impact on someone else. If your response leads you to act al-
truistically, that is because your desires have been affected.8
So far, that is still abstract and vague. I shall motivate the underlying
idea with a simple and stylized example and then offer a more precise
definition.
Imagine that you are hungry and that you enter a room in which
some food is spread out on a table. Suppose further that there is nobody
in the vicinity who might also be hungry and want all or part of the food.
Under these circumstances, you want to eat the food; indeed, you want
all of it. If the circumstances were slightly different, however, if there
were another hungry person in the room or believed to be in the neigh-
borhood, your desire would be different: now you would prefer the out-
come where you share the food with the other person. Here your desire
responds to your perception of the needs and wants of someone else, so
that you adjust what you might otherwise have wanted to align your de-
sire with the wants you take the other person to have.
This is a start, but it is not sufficient to make you an altruist. For you
might have formed the new want when you see that someone else will be
affected by what you do, because you saw profitable future opportunities
for accommodating this other person. Maybe you envisage a series of oc-
casions on which you and your fellow will find yourselves hungry in
food-containing rooms. You see the advantages of not fighting and of not
simply having all the food go to the first person who enters. You resolve
to share, then, because a future of cooperation will be better from your
point of view. For real altruism, the adjustment of desires must not be
produced by this kind of self-interested calculation.
I offer a definition of “A acts psychologically altruistically towards B in
C”—where A is the agent, B is the beneficiary, and C is the context (or
set of circumstances). The first notion we need is that of two situations
differing from each other in the recognizable consequences for others
(people or nonhuman animals). Let us say, then, that two contexts C and
8. You might be affected by another person’s predicament, and form an altruistic emo-
tion, but that might not generate a desire that issues in action. The most basic type of altru-
ism that is of ethical concern is a response to someone else that eventually expresses itself
in conduct.
22 the ethica l project
C* are counterparts, just in case they differ only in that, in one (C*, say)
the actions available to A have no perceived consequences for B, whereas
in the other (C) those actions do have perceived consequences for B. C*
will then be the solitary counterpart of C, and C will be the social coun-
terpart of C*. If A forms different desires in C* from those A forms in C,
the set of desires present in C* will be A’s solitary desires (relative to the
counterparts C and C*). Given these preliminary specifications:
(1) A acts on the basis of a desire that is different from the desire
that would have moved A to action in C*, the solitary
counterpart of C.
(2) The desire that moves A to action in C is more closely
aligned with the wants A attributes to B in C than the desire
that would have moved A to action in C*.
(3) The desire that moves A to action in C results from A’s
perception of B’s wants in C.
(4) The desire that moves A to action in C is not caused by A’s
expectation that the action resulting from it would promote
A’s solitary desires (with respect to C and C*).
Condition 1 tells us that A modifies his or her desires from the way they
would otherwise have been, when there is an impact—more accurately,
when there is a perceived impact9—on the wants of B. Condition 2 adds
the idea that the desire, and the behavior it directs, is more in harmony
with the wants attributed to B than it would have been if B were unaf-
fected by what was done. (It is possible to modify your desires in response
to the perceived wishes of another, but to do so in a way that diverges
from their perceived wants—that is spite.) Condition 3 explains that the
increased harmony comes about because of the perception of B’s wants;
it is not, say, some caprice on A’s part that a different desire comes into
play here. Finally, condition 4 denies that the modification is to be un-
9. I shall consider cases in which agents have mistaken beliefs later. For the time being,
I suppose that the parties get things at least roughly right.
The Springs of Sympathy 23
derstood in terms of A’s attempt to promote some desire that would have
been present in situations where there was no thought of helping or hurt-
ing B; this distinguishes A from the food sharer who hopes for returns on
future occasions when B is in the position of disposing of the goods.
Condition 4 requires that genuine psychological altruists be different
from Machiavellian calculators who aim to satisfy the wants they would
have in solitary situations (I shall sometimes refer to condition 4 as the
“anti-Machiavelli” condition).
Given this account of psychological altruism, it is now possible to
characterize behavioral altruism more carefully. Behavioral altruists are
people who look like psychological altruists. That is, they perform the
actions people with psychologically altruistic desires would have been
led to perform. In ascribing behavioral altruism, however, we do not sup-
pose any particular psychological explanation of the actions. Perhaps
they are indeed the products of psychologically altruistic desires, or per-
haps the actions are produced by quite different desires having nothing
to do with the satisfaction of the beneficiary—a desire for status, or for
feeling oneself in accordance with some socially approved pattern of con-
duct, or even a self-interested calculation. (We shall explore some
possibilities of behavioral altruism later; see §§7, 11.)
The stylized food example allows the introduction of an obvious con-
cept, one that will be important in future discussions, and that further
articulates the account of altruistic desires. The altruistic modification
of solitary desires can be more or less intense. I have spoken—somewhat
vaguely—of the altruist as aligning his or her wants with those attributed
to the beneficiary.10 That alignment is often a matter of degree, for
example, when there is a continuum of possibilities intermediate between
complete egoism (retaining one’s solitary desires in the social counter-
part) and complete subordination of one’s solitary wishes to those one
perceives the other to have (where one comes to want exactly what
one perceives the other as desiring). In sharing food, this is easily
10. For a more precise and formal discussion of many aspects of altruism, see my essays
“The Evolution of Human Altruism,” Journal of Philosophy 90 (1993): 497–516, and “Vari-
eties of Altruism,” Economics and Philosophy (2010): 121–148. As I shall note at various
places, there are several aspects of the account of altruism provided in this chapter that can
be treated mathematically, and these articles make a start on that.
24 the ethica l project
where vSoc measures my social desires, vSol my solitary desires, vBen the
measurements of desire I attribute to the beneficiary (you), and wEgo and
wAlt the weights given to my solitary desires and my attributions of desire
values to you (so that wEgo + wAlt = 1). The intensity of my altruism is rep-
resented by the size of wAlt —and hence inversely by the size of wEgo ; if
wEgo = 1 (wAlt = 0), then I am, at least with respect to you on this occasion,
a psychological egoist; if wAlt = 1, then I am a self-abnegating altruist; if
wAlt = 0.5 (= wEgo), then I am a golden-rule altruist.
We should not assume that all types of altruistic alignment with the
wishes of others can be conceived in this very simple way. Cases of shar-
ing show that a simple approach sometimes works, and the simple ex-
pression of social wants as weighted averages will be useful in explaining
and illustrating some of the ideas of later sections.
The Springs of Sympathy 25
11. The distinction between these two modes of altruistic emotional response—forms of
“sympathy”—was already clearly recognized by Adam Smith in Theory of Moral Senti-
ments, Knud Haakonssen, ed. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002).
26 the ethica l project
with the emotion the altruist supposes he or she would feel if placed in
the other’s shoes), and the alignment comes about because of the recog-
nition of the other’s feelings (or of the other’s situation); finally, it is not
caused by any background solitary emotion or solitary desire. Now,
whereas in the understanding of altruistic desire this last condition re-
sponds to a genuine worry—for we readily think people can form osten-
sibly other-directed desires on the basis of selfish calculations (I can
want to share with you because I think it will be good for me in the long
run)—the anti-Machiavelli condition seems odd and gratuitous in the
emotional case. It is natural to think, and it may even be true, that self-
directed psychological states simply have no power to generate emotions
toward others, that our emotional life is not under that sort of control.
Emotional responses, one may suppose, are caused by processes more
direct and automatic than the perceptions and cognitions figuring in my
analyses. Consequently, an account of emotional altruism parallel to the
analysis of altruistic desire will be at least incomplete, and perhaps even
radically misguided.
This is a serious challenge. To meet it, we shall have to consider, if only
briefly, the character of emotions. Without taking sides in unresolved
controversies, I shall argue that some kinds of emotional response can
be understood along the lines just sketched, while others cannot. An ac-
count of more basic altruistic emotional reactions, or “affective states,”
as I shall call them, provides a valuable supplement to the approach to
psychological altruism begun in the previous section.
Emotions involve changes in our physiology, and some students of
emotion have identified the emotion with the alteration in physiological
state. Others propose that there are important distinctions among emo-
tions that cannot be recognized without supposing those who feel the
emotions to have particular beliefs, desires, and intentions: specific forms
of awareness are required for guilt and shame, for resentment and indig-
nation, and for certain kinds of contentment and anger. A natural way of
responding to the findings of neuroscientists, psychologists, and anthro-
pologists is to suppose that many emotions are complex entities, perhaps
processes in which particular types of physiological conditions are ac-
companied by special kinds of cognitive and volitional states. When some-
one resents the insensitive remarks made by another, he or she undergoes
The Springs of Sympathy 27
12. Here I am much influenced by the thoughtful and ecumenical approach adopted by
Jenefer Robinson in the first three chapters of Deeper than Reason (New York: Oxford
University Press, 2005).
13. See Paul Ekman and Richard Davidson, eds., Nature of Emotion (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1994).
14. Since the role of social environments is central to my approach to our altruistic ten-
dencies and the character of the ethical project, my position would be strengthened if this
concession proves false.
28 the ethica l project
15. See Martin Hoff man, Empathy and Moral Development (New York: Cambridge
University Press, 2000).
The Springs of Sympathy 29
those giving rise to the behavior perceived or causing the sensations: A’s
observation of B’s facial expression produces neuronal firings that tense
the pertinent muscles and that result in A’s imitation of B; perhaps the
sound of another baby crying induces a pattern of neural activity that
mirrors that in the source of the crying and thus causes the originally
contented baby to cry.16 Mechanisms of this sort require a different ap-
proach to altruistic emotions.
Once we have the challenge clearly in view, however, it is not hard to
see how to liberate the account of altruism begun in §3 from its depen-
dence on cognition. The task is to provide a defi nition of “A feels an
altruistic emotion in response to B in C.” As before, we shall suppose
the notions of solitary and social counterparts. The conditions are as
follows:
16. William Damon, The Moral Child (New York: Free Press, 1998); and Hoff man, Em-
pathy and Moral Development.
30 the ethica l project
This account introduces clauses into the second and third conditions
in order to allow the possibility of altruistic emotions produced in
ways that bypass cognition. Although the fourth condition is retained, it
is highly plausible that Machiavellian manipulation of our emotional
lives is beyond our powers, and, if that is indeed so, this requirement is
redundant.
The analysis just given preserves a fundamental feature of my original
characterization of psychological altruism (§3): altruists have a particu-
lar type of relational structure in their psychological lives—when others
are around, the altruist’s desires, hopes, intentions, and emotions are
different from what they would otherwise have been, closer in some way
to those of the others, and the difference is produced by some sort of re-
sponse to those others, not by something enclosed within the self (calcu-
lations of future benefit, for example). What the more complex approach
to altruistic emotions adds is the possibility that the generation of the
response might involve some precognitive mechanism.
It is easy to overinterpret this last point. One might suppose that
affective states are always generated by some mechanism that does not
involve cognition—but, not only do I see no basis for holding so sweep-
ing a generalization, but it also seems belied by the fact that affective re-
actions are often founded in complex and explicit understanding (when
I see pictures of Jewish refugee children being greeted at English ports
by policemen and willing foster parents, I feel a complex mixture of
emotions, surely involving affective states, but these states are clearly
dependent on my conscious understanding of what the photographs
display). The causal relations among affective and cognitive states may
be quite various, and, while we await definitive accounts of them, it is
well to suspend judgment and to be open to many possibilities.
Nor should we suppose that noncognitive mechanisms are inevitably
involved in whatever altruistic responses occur in nonhuman animals.
Although questions about the extent of animal abilities to recognize the
wishes and thoughts of their conspecifics are much debated, there is no
reason to take an advance stand on these issues.17 I shall later defend the
17. For defenses of opposing views, see de Waal, Primates and Philosophers; and Derek
C. Penn and Daniel J. Povinelli, “On the Lack of Evidence that Non-human Animals Pos-
The Springs of Sympathy 31
thesis that some of our evolutionary cousins have altruistic desires (in
the sense of §3; see §7) and that similar capacities were shared by our
hominid ancestors.
egoists set wEgo at 1 and wAlt at 0. People for whom wEgo = 1 − ε, where ε is
tiny, are altruists in a very modest sense: they will act to advance the
wishes of others only when the perceived benefits to others are enormous
compared to the forfeits for themselves—they may suffer the scratching of
their finger in order to avoid the destruction of the world, but refuse larger
sacrifices. People for whom wAlt = 1, by contrast, are completely self-
abnegating. They abandon their own solitary desires entirely, taking on
the wishes they attribute to the beneficiary. In between, we find golden-
rule altruists, for whom wAlt = 1/2, who treat the perceived wishes of the
other exactly as they do their own solitary desires.
Even when averaging is not appropriate for representing altruistic de-
sires, there will often be a comparable notion of the degree to which one
has accommodated the perceived wishes of the other. Moreover, with
respect to altruistic emotions there is surely a similar concept. Notori-
ously, we can be relatively unsympathetic, even with those who are dear-
est to us, when we are preoccupied or distracted. At other times, we en-
ter fully into the feelings of friends and loved ones, even of strangers. It is
not obvious how to delineate the notion of intensity in the emotional
case as precisely as the food-sharing example allows, but the varying in-
tensity of altruism in emotional responses is uncontroversial. Notice,
however, that it should not be confused with the intensity of emotion:
intensity depends on the degree of alignment with the other’s feelings
(or with the feeling one would have had in the other’s situation), not
with the force of what one feels.
Most altruists, indeed probably all, lack a fi xed intensity of response,
applying with respect to all potential beneficiaries and all contexts.
There are many people to whom we would rarely make an altruistic re-
sponse: these people effectively fall outside the range of our altruism.
Even with respect to those to whom we are disposed to respond, there
are many contexts in which we do not take their perceived wishes or their
feelings into consideration (or into our own minds). For many, perhaps,
The Springs of Sympathy 33
we are prepared to offer limited forms of aid and support; for a few, we
are willing to sacrifice everything. Often our altruistic responses to some
are colored by indifference to others: parents who make sacrifices to help
their children obtain things the children passionately want frequently
do not take into account the wishes of other children (or the altruistic
desires of the parents of the other children).
Someone’s altruism profile typically shows a relatively small number
of people to whom the focal individual responds, frequently with signifi-
cant intensity, across a wide set of contexts. The beneficiaries lie at the
center of the range of altruism for the focal individual, and the scope for
these beneficiaries is wide. As we consider other potential beneficiaries
more distant from the center, the scope narrows (there are fewer contexts
in which the more peripheral people elicit an altruistic reaction) and the
intensity falls off, until we encounter people to whom the focal individ-
ual makes no altruistic response at all. Henceforth, I shall conceive of
the range of A’s altruism in terms of the metaphor of center and periph-
ery: the center is the select set of potential beneficiaries for whom A’s
response is relatively intense across a relatively wide scope of contexts; at
the periphery, the intensity of the response and the scope of contexts
narrow and vanish.
Someone’s character as an altruist is not fi xed simply by the factors so
far considered—intensity, range, and scope—because there are also sig-
nificant cognitive dimensions to altruism. A may make no response in a
particular context through failure to understand the consequences for
B; perhaps A does not differentiate the social from the solitary counter-
part. Often this is an excusable feature of our fallibility, for the impact on
the lives of others may be subtle; we may just not see that following some
habitual practice—buying at the most attractive price, or investing in
promising stocks—has deleterious consequences for people about whose
welfare we care. Evidently, however, acuity with respect to consequences
comes in grades, and we admire those who appreciate the intricate ways
in which others can be affected, while blaming those who “ought to have
seen” the damage they cause.
Similarly, there are degrees to which people are good at gauging the
desires of others. Almost everyone is familiar with the well-intentioned
person who tries to advance the projects of an intended beneficiary but
34 the ethica l project
19. Sigmund Freud, Civilization and Its Discontents (New York: Norton, 1961); Bernard
Williams, “Personhood, Character and Morality” in Moral Luck (Cambridge, UK: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1981); Peter Railton, “Alienation, Consequentialism, and the De-
mands of Morality,” in Facts, Values, and Norms (Cambridge, UK: University Press, 2003).
36 the ethica l project
20. There are many excellent sources for attributing complex cognitive states to nonhu-
man primates. See, for example, Dorothy Cheney and Robert Seyfarth, How Monkeys See the
World (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), esp. chaps. 3 and 8; Jane Goodall, The
Chimpanzees of Gombe (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986); C. Bachmann
and H. Kummer, “Male Assessment of Female Choice in Hamadryas Baboons,” Behavioral
Ecology and Sociobiology 6 (1980): 315–21; R. Byrne and A. Whiten, eds., Machiavellian
Intelligence (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1988), particularly the essay by Nicho-
las Humphrey (“The Social Function of Intellect,” 13–21).
21. Many, though not all, of the essays in Byrne and Whiten, Machiavellian Intelligence
(see n. 20), adopt this perspective. For a more pronounced articulation of the theme that
intelligence is a tool for calculating egoists, see James Barkow, Leda Cosmides, and John
Tooby, eds., The Adapted Mind (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992). In “The Social
Function of Intellect,” Nicholas Humphrey offers a broader vision (see esp. p. 23).
The Springs of Sympathy 37
dates for altruistic responses to the young are affective and immediate.
That would allow for altruistic emotions, even emotions that direct
behavior, but not necessarily for altruistic desires. To address this latter
concern, I shall begin with an example that involves serious cognition
and planning.
Primates roaming on the savannah sometimes encounter carcasses
that could serve as food. Imagine a female finding a carcass in the ab-
sence of her young. Instead of devouring it on the spot, she quickly sum-
mons her young. It is difficult to think of behavior of this sort as an
action driven by instincts or emotions. Apparently, the mother has to
recognize this as food she can share, and to prefer sharing to devouring
it entire. Perceiving the possibilities for her young, she forms a different
desire from the one she would have formed had they been out of range or
fully mature and dispersed. That desire underlies her efforts to summon
them to the scene before the food spoils or is taken by another animal.
On the face of it, this is an example of altruistic desires in the sense of §3.
One line of concern about attributing altruistic desires is that capaci-
ties for such wishes could not have evolved and been maintained under
natural selection. In settling this worry, we can use the tools supplied to
solve the problem of biological altruism. Suppose that food has decreas-
ing marginal value (in terms of promoting reproductive success), so that,
although eating a whole carcass has a higher effect, on fitness it is consid-
erably less than double the effect of eating just half. Assume that the
mother has a disposition to golden-rule altruism (or some approximation
of it) with respect to her offspring, and that there is just one of her young
in the vicinity. Then it is not hard to show that this disposition can be
favored by kin selection.22
The more difficult challenge asks whether all the conditions for psy-
chological altruism have been met. Perhaps the adjustment of desires to
accommodate the perceived needs of young is based upon “Machiavel-
lian” calculations. What form might these supposedly self-directed
processes take? Begin with a style of skeptical argument rarely made
explicit, but one underlying the conviction that references to psychologi-
cal altruism are exercises in sentimental self-deception. According to
this line of thought, the benefits to off spring, favoring the evolution-
ary success of altruism, undermine its genuineness. In the described
scenario, however, the mother must do something psychologically
sophisticated—she has to recognize this as an occasion for seeking out
her young—rather than simply exhibit some instinctive reaction. What,
then, is the alternative cognitive account that replaces the disposition to
adjust preferences with Machiavellian calculation? It strains credulity to
suppose mothers recognize the evolutionary advantages of sharing: only
a few very select primates could calculate the genetic gains and losses
(and those who do make their judgments in this way are, to say the least,
misguided). So if she calculates it will have to proceed via proxies,
through the attempt to attain selfish goals correlated with increases in
reproductive success. What could those be?
The most plausible answer is that maternal care proceeds from expec-
tations of future reciprocity—the child is expected to grow into a future
ally, maybe eventually a caregiver. Here, the consequences of the present
action would be represented in terms we can imagine being within the
mother’s conceptual repertoire, but we are supposing animal abilities to
abstract from present conditions and to envisage a very different future,
to overlook the weak juvenile and see a future strong ally. Even if we allow
such amazing foresight, problems remain. If dispositions to share with
young evolve under natural selection because of inclusive fitness consid-
erations, then the expectations of future aid ought not to be an accurate
guide to the kinds of behavior selection would favor—the alleged prox-
ies do not match up well with the variables (the gene frequencies) that
are the “ultimate currency” of evolution. From the standpoint of inclu-
sive fitness, mothers should provide some aid when there is very little
chance of reciprocity in the future (simply because, even without recip-
rocation, helping offspring is a good way to spread the genes), and they
should provide extra aid to offspring who can be expected to recipro-
cate. If the hypothetical calculation is to give values that correlate with
inclusive fitness, the perceived gains from reciprocity have to be inflated.
Why should mothers think their care will be remembered, or, if recalled,
it will trigger a disposition to repay? If sharing is based on the expectation
of returns, the young seem bad targets. Other, more mature, members of
the group would appear to be better prospects for future aid.
The Springs of Sympathy 39
23. In Unto Others (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), Elliott Sober
and David Sloan Wilson rightly regard this kind of skeptical response as the most impor-
tant challenge to the existence of psychological altruism. I think their way of dealing with
it is unnecessarily complex, and offer a simpler treatment. Nonetheless, we are in agree-
ment that the challenge can be met.
40 the ethica l project
25. Frans de Waal, Good Natured (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1996), 83.
44 the ethica l project
Jakie modified his wishes from what they would have been in Krom’s
absence, and he did so in light of his perception of her desires. He
aligned his wants with hers. Are there grounds for skepticism about his
altruism? If so, they must stem from concerns that the anti-Machiavelli
condition is violated. Perhaps Jakie expected some future reciprocation—
but that would be to impute to him a seriously misguided appraisal of
Krom’s future abilities to reward him (an appraisal quite at odds with his
clear social intelligence; Jakie understands Krom’s place in the troop).
Perhaps he aimed to impress others—but Jakie was surely aware that
the only other primate around was the (socially irrelevant) de Waal. Or
should we think Jakie not only feels glows and pangs, but has the cogni-
tive powers to perceive the present causes of their future occurrence?
Skeptics about altruism are often moved by the thought that an egoistic
story is less extravagant than a hypothesis introducing some ability to
identify with others. Here, however, skeptical hypotheses about glows
and pangs seem the truly extravagant options.
So we can broaden the domain of psychological altruism in the non-
human world, at least a little. This is important for understanding the
ethical project, because it allows us to attribute altruistic desires to ani-
mals before ethical considerations are on the scene. A central theme of my
approach to altruism is that there are preethical forms of altruism and
that these are realized in animals who have not yet acquired ethical prac-
tice. Yet caution is necessary. Besides the striking—and clear—cases,
there are many instances of primate behavior suggestive of altruism, in
which skeptical challenges are far harder to rebut. Observations of chim-
panzees and bonobos frequently inspire the interpretation that par-
ticu lar pairs form genuine friendships, that the mutual adjustment of
behavior signals an underlying modification of preferences and inten-
tions, prompted by recognition of the other’s wants. When the appar-
ently stable alliance breaks down, when a “friend” deserts a seemingly
close ally, there are two possible reactions: one can see this as revealing
that the parties were calculating all along, using one another to mutual
advantage (or apparent mutual advantage); or one can suppose it exposes
the previously unnoticed limits of altruism along one of the dimensions
(scope) distinguished earlier. Later in this chapter, my preferred expla-
nation of the evolution of psychological altruism will be used to support
The Springs of Sympathy 45
26. I ignore here the variety of ways in which opportunities for sharing arise, and, in
particu lar, the important point that subjects will sometimes give some of their assigned
money to “punish” participants who fail to share. For a more extensive discussion, see §11.
46 the ethica l project
27. For a concise and informative survey of these experiments, see John Sabini and
Maury Silver, Moralities of Everyday Life (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1982),
chap. 4.
The Springs of Sympathy 47
29. This approach stems from the important work of Robert Trivers, William Hamil-
ton, and Robert Axelrod. The Trivers-Hamilton-Axelrod approach has given rise to an
50 the ethica l project
extensive series of further investigations. See, for example, Alexander Harcourt and Frans
de Waal, Coalitions and Alliances in Humans and Other Animals (Oxford, UK: Oxford
University Press, 1992); Karl Sigmund, Games of Life (New York: Oxford University Press,
1993); and Ronald Noë, Jan van Hoff, and Peter Hammerstein, eds., Economics in Nature
(Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2001).
The Springs of Sympathy 51
C(ooperate) D(efect)
supposed that T > R > P > S, and that T + S < 2R.30 If the game is played
just once, defection (D) is a dominant strategy for both players, since
T > R and P > S. Rational actors in a socioeconomic interaction of this
form are expected to wind up with the noncooperative outcome of mutual
punishment, rather than achieving the reward for mutual cooperation—
which, if they could be assured of it, they would prefer (since R > P). By
the same token, if animals sometimes engage in interactions with non-
relatives, where the payoffs in units of reproductive success meet the
conditions of PD, natural selection would apparently favor strategies of
defection.
Not, however, if the interactions are repeated. In an iterated prisoner’s
dilemma (IPD), players can adjust their strategies to the previous perfor-
mance of those with whom they interact. A strategy for IPD consists in a
choice of how to play on the first round, together with a set of preferred
responses to the various potential sequences of choices by one’s partner/
opponent. Suppose you know the interaction will be repeated but do not
know exactly how many times it will occur.31 Your strategy is specified
by saying how you will begin, and how you will act given any potential
history of choices by your partner.
Robert Axelrod investigated the success of various strategies em-
pirically, by inviting scholars to submit their preferred proposals for
playing IPD, and staging a computer tournament. In each round of
the tournament, different strategies were paired (as in a round-robin),
and then played a par tic u lar version of PD against each other for a
large number of iterations. 32 The winner was one of the simplest strat-
egies submitted, tit for tat (TFT), which begins by cooperating, an-
30. The second condition implies that, if the game is repeated, it is cooperatively better
for the players both to play C than to adopt a pattern of alternating C and D (so that, on each
occasion, one plays sucker and the other plays traitor, with alternation of roles).
31. This last stipulation is added to address the concern that it will always be prefer-
able to defect on the last round, that once that is a matter of common knowledge it will
be rational to defect on the penultimate round, and so on. There are complications here
that I shall not explore. For present purposes, it is enough to follow the standard
treatment.
32. For details, see Axelrod, Evolution of Cooperation. Note that the number of itera-
tions is close to two hundred, and that the payoffs in the game—the values of T, R, P, and
S—are the same in each iteration and in each round.
The Springs of Sympathy 53
33. For the important notion of evolutionary stability (of an evolutionarily stable strat-
egy), see John Maynard Smith, Evolution and the Theory of Games (Cambridge, UK: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1982). From the beginning it was apparent that there were indirect
ways in which populations of TFTs could be invaded. In such populations, variants that
invariably cooperate would be indistinguishable from the TFTs and could thus enter.
Once there were sufficiently many of them, the stage would be set for noncooperative strat-
egies to invade through exploiting the undifferentiating cooperators. (See my discussion in
Vaulting Ambition, [Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1985], 100–101.) Further research
revealed that combinations of noncooperative strategies can also invade (Robert Boyd and
J. P. Lorberbaum, “No Strategy Is Stable in the Repeated Prisoner’s Dilemma,” Nature 327
[1987]: 58–59).
54 the ethica l project
C D
C <9,9> <0,10>
>D <10,0> <1,1>
Interact
Opt out >5
34. The results summarized here were originally presented in Kitcher, “Evolution of
Human Altruism.” I should note that the strategy DC described here is characterized as
DA in the earlier paper (“discriminating cooperator” is a more accurate label than “dis-
criminating altruist”).
56 the ethica l project
35. See John Batali and Philip Kitcher, “Evolution of Altruism in Optional and Com-
pulsory Games,” Journal of Theoretical Biology 175 (1995): 161–71.
36. This result is derived in Kitcher, “Evolution of Human Altruism.” Note that quasi
altruists resemble behavioral altruists, although some behavioral altruists may not meet
condition 3 of §3.
The Springs of Sympathy 57
39. A valuable source for discussions of social life among the apes is Barbara Smuts;
Dorothy Cheney, Robert Seyfarth, Richard Wrangham, and Thomas Struhsaker eds., Pri-
mate Societies (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987).
The Springs of Sympathy 59
40. I shall tend to take chimpanzees, rather than bonobos, as the model for our hominid
past. This decision rests partly on a sense that many small human societies that live in en-
vironmental conditions closer to those of our ancestors appear to share the relative intoler-
ance for neighbors that is so marked in chimpanzee social life, and, more important, on the
hypothesis that psychologically altruistic tendencies are more prominent and pervasive in
bonobos than in the (common) chimpanzee. Hence I assume that if a compelling story
about the evolution of sociality and its roots in psychological altruism can be given for
chimpanzees, it would be easier to defend a similar account for bonobos. (Here I am in-
debted to a valuable conversation with Frans de Waal.)
41. See Richard Wrangham, “On the Evolution of Ape Social Systems,” Social Science
Information 18 (1979): 334– 68; “An Ecological Model of Female-Bonded Primate Groups,”
Behaviour 75 (1980): 262–300); “Social Relationships in Comparative Perspective,” in
Primate Social Relationships: An Integrated Approach, ed. Robert Hinde (Oxford: Black-
well, 1983); and “Evolution of Social Structure,” in Smuts et al., Primate Societies, 282– 96.
Wrangham bases his analysis on the hypothesis that the principal determinant of female
reproductive success will be her access to food and that the principal determinant of
male reproductive success will be the ability to copulate as frequently as possible with
60 the ethica l project
estrous females. So, for example, on his account, orangutans pursue their relatively soli-
tary lives because females can most efficiently forage for fruit by working alone, and males
have physical abilities to defend a territory including the smaller home ranges of several
females. I shall make no such specific assumptions. Instead, I abstract from the particulari-
ties of Wrangham’s discussion, offering a more general model of which his approach would
be a special case.
42. Wrangham, “Evolution of Social Structure,” 290. Compare Hobbes: “. . . the weak-
est has strength enough to kill the strongest, either by secret machination, or by confedera-
tion with others that are in the same danger with himself” (Leviathan, 82). Hobbes, how-
ever, would not have thought that this could apply to the brutes, because, without speech
“. . . there had been amongst men neither Common-wealth, nor Society, nor Contract, nor
Peace, no more than amongst Lyons, Bears, and Wolves” (Leviathan, 20). Hobbes under-
rated the lions and the wolves and knew nothing of the chimpanzees and the bonobos [New
York: Oxford University Press (World’s Classics) 2008].
43. Some primatologists have recognized the point in the context of their studies of par-
ticu lar societies. See, for example, R. Noë, “Alliance Formation Among Male Baboons:
Shopping for Profitable Partners,” in Coalitions and Alliances in Humans and Other Ani-
mals, ed. A. Harcourt and F. de Waal (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1992),
285–321.
The Springs of Sympathy 61
Without pursuing the technical details, I shall try to show how this pro-
cess might unfold.
Begin with a more benign version of the initial state, a Rousseauian
world that contains more than enough for everyone. As the population
expands, competition enters. Eventually, so long as the competition goes
on in the assumed way, some animals will not find the resources they
need to survive.
44. Note that the fitness values that occur in the payoff matrices for the games played by
community members, whether optional or compulsory, must reflect the consequences of
actions for the underlying alliances to which the animals belong. This recapitulates the
point made earlier that the structure of animal interaction cannot be understood in isola-
tion from the demands of the most fundamental game, here seen as the coalition game.
62 the ethica l project
the population. Selection thus favors variants of this type, even if the divi-
sions of the resources acquired are not even.
Plainly, several parameters must be set in developing versions of the
scenario I am envisaging, but it is possible to show that, given almost all
ways of choosing values for non-Rousseauian worlds, any population at
stage 1 will contain at least one pair of organisms who can increase their
fitness through coalition formation. That does not mean, of course, that
the disposition to team up must evolve: there might be no way to gener-
ate any such propensity. I shall suggest shortly that more basic capacities
for psychological altruism provide a way in which the successful vari-
ants might emerge.
Just as stage 1 would favor the emergence of pairwise coalitions, so too
the emergence of pairs puts pressure on animals who are working alone.
The gains of the animals who team up are obtained by dispossessing
those who would otherwise have done better. Any variation that equips
them with a disposition to pair with another animal will be favored. As
the population becomes full of coalitional pairs competing with one an-
other, the weakest pairs will do better if they are prepared to add single
members or merge with other pairs. Selection favors the variants who
unite with others at the size required by the actual escalation of coalition
formation.
Although the origination and escalation of coalition formation is easy
to understand, the termination of the process appears more mysterious.
The rationale, however, is a direct consequence of the fact that coalitions
have to travel together if they are to exert their joint power. No coalition
can visit more resources than a single individual. When the environment
is filled with large coalitions, coalition members who receive the small-
est shares may have no better option than to resume scrambling for re-
sources the large coalitions are not able to visit. The dynamics of the
process leads to a situation in which the habitat is partitioned into terri-
tories controlled by sizable coalitions, occasionally with a floating popu-
lation of individuals who live on the fringes.45
45. The announced results are not hard to derive analytically. They coincide with the
findings of some ingenious computer simulations designed by Dr. Herbert Roseman. See
his unpublished Ph.D. dissertation “Altruism, Evolution, and Optional Games,”2008 Co-
lumbia University.
64 the ethica l project
first toward young and then toward close relatives. The broadened pro-
pensities allowed for the formation of those loose coalitions found in our
evolutionary cousins. Far from being anthropomorphic, sentimental, or
self-deceiving, the hypothesis advanced here looks like the best explana-
tion of the form of sociality of our hominid past. It also explains why the
friendships of youth are so deep and enduring, both in human beings and
in other primates, and why newcomers are sometimes accepted into pri-
mate social groups when a resident animal has formed social bonds with
them in a shared past as juveniles together.47
Psychological altruism is the kernel from which ethical practice grows—
because it lies at the heart of the type of sociality our hominid ancestors
experienced. As we shall discover, however, the plant is far more elaborate
than the seed.
47. De Waal relates a striking instance, in which a relatively unprepossessing male (Ji-
moh) was accepted into a chimpanzee troop because of his prior association with two older
females in the group. See de Waal, Good Natured, 131–32.
chapter 2
Normative Guidance
67
68 the ethica l project
1. Arguments along these lines have been developed by Kristen Hawkes and her col-
leagues (see, for example, Hawkes, James O’Connell, Nicholas Blurton Jones, Helen Alva-
rez, and Eric Charnov, “The Grandmother Hypothesis and Human Evolution,” in Evolu-
tionary Anthropology and Human Social Behavior: Twenty Years Later, ed. L. Cronk, N.
Chagnon, and W. Irons [New York: De Gruyter, 1999]) and by Sarah Hrdy, Mother Nature
(New York: Pantheon, 1999), and Mothers and Others (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univer-
sity Press, 2009).
Normative Guidance 69
more often prevented, less time has to be spent in reknitting the social
fabric. The cumbersome peacemaking of our original hominids is re-
placed by a new device, one preempting rupture rather than reacting to
it, and in principle capable of operating in a wide variety of contexts.2
That device is necessary for what we think of as ethical practice. I shall
call it a “capacity for normative guidance.”
The previous chapter was at pains to defend attributions of psycho-
logical altruism and to rebut the skeptical insistence that sees Machiavel-
lian intelligence behind apparently helpful or kindly actions. Its account,
however, was entirely consistent with the thesis that the psychological
altruism of our hominid ancestors was limited. Recall two of the dimen-
sions of altruism: range and scope. An animal may be disposed to re-
spond altruistically to particular other members of its social group (“close
friends”) across a relatively broad set of contexts, and to respond to all
members of its social group in some contexts (banding together against
outsiders, for example), although there are occasions on which it would
act selfishly even toward its closest friends and staunchest allies. The
limited quality of chimpanzee-hominid altruism, in both range and scope,
set the stage for the emergence of normative guidance.
The limits of altruism are most starkly and spectacularly visible when
the selfish rewards for deserting erstwhile allies are extremely high—as
when a male has the opportunity to achieve dominance in the social group.
A study of “chimpanzee politics” in the colony at Arnhem (an environ-
ment allowing the animals to retain important features of their life in the
wild, but, at the same time, providing opportunities for systematic ob-
servation of them) revealed the ways in which three high-status males—
Yeroen, Luit, and Nikkie—related to one another and to the high-status
females, during times of transitions in power.3 Each male exhibited social
behavior readily interpretable as aimed at retaining dominance, achiev-
ing dominance, or, at worst, serving as the principal lieutenant of the
dominant male. In the early phases of the struggle, Luit aided the newly
have seen enough varied contexts in which two animals respond to each
other to assign them to each other’s range of altruism—until the animals
encounter a new type of context, in which an altruistic response would
require the forgoing of huge potential gains. The selfish action in that
context is a sign not that everything in the past has been opportunism,
but just that the altruistic disposition is incompletely pervasive. Even for
animals who are central to the range of the altruist’s altruism, there are
circumstances outside the scope of that altruism.
The conception of psychological altruism offered in §§3–5 reveals
what is occurring. Chimpanzees (and our hominid ancestors) have regu-
lar psychological propensities for making an altruistic response to an-
other member of their group, with the intensity dependent on salient
features of the circumstances. Even though an animal frequently displays
a tendency to accommodate the wishes and needs of a particular band
member—a “friend”—there are environments in which the intensity of
the altruistic response drops to zero. In those environments, altruism
suddenly vanishes. Friendship is “situation linked” because there is no
fi xed value of the intensity of the altruistic response depending solely on
the strength of the relationship.7 Even in the most committed mutually
altruistic relationships, circumstances offering one party the chance of a
huge advantage diminish the intensity of the response. When the stakes
are high enough, it disappears entirely.
The struggle for dominance presents in high relief contours visible in
more mundane settings. Every day in chimpanzee troops, members who
are not one another’s principal allies act in blithe indifference to their
fellows’ obvious plans. Attempts to obtain a valued object are blocked
or thwarted, requests to share food are turned down, appeals for aid in
conflict are ignored. The animals involved are not entirely indifferent to
one another, for they would band and bond together in the face of an
externally presented threat. Rather, the scope of their mutual altruism is
7. The approach adopted here has some kinship with Walter Mischel’s emphasis on the
failure of cross-situational consistency in people who have stable personality profi les. See
W. Mischel and Y. Shoda, “A Cognitive-Affective System Theory of Personality: Recon-
ceptualizing Situations, Dispositions, Dynamics, and Invariance in Personality Struc-
ture,” Psychological Review 102 (1995): 246– 68. I am grateful to George Mandler for the
suggestion that I explore Mischel’s work.
72 the ethica l project
8. In terms of the discussion of §9, the extremely limited altruism profi les displayed in
such cases express membership in different—and often competing—subcoalitions.
9. Because it is so banal, this phenomenon is rarely described in studies of chimpan-
zees. Even a few hours of observation will provide instances.
Normative Guidance 73
10. I draw the examples considered here, as well as the helpful Jekyll-Hyde metaphor,
from Thomas Schelling’s valuable discussion in Choice and Consequence (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1984), particularly chap. 3, “The Intimate Contest for
Self-Command.”
74 the ethica l project
Once, that was the predicament of our ancestors, too.11 They over-
came it through acquiring a mechanism for the reinforcement and re-
shaping of altruistic dispositions, and for the resolution of confl ict.
The evolution of that mechanism, the capacity for normative guid-
ance, was an important step in the transition from hominids to human
beings.
11. If our hominid ancestors lived in societies more akin to those of contemporary bono-
bos, then their situation would have been less tense than under a chimpanzee form of soci-
ality. The differences, however, are matters of degree, not of kind.
12. Eventually it also modified our ancestors’ emotional lives.
Normative Guidance 75
13. In the discussion of psychological altruism, where A’s own perspective is crucial to
the formation of the altruistic preference, I saw that preference as incorporating A’s percep-
tion of B’s wants. Here I imagine the command as requiring alignment with B’s actual
wants. There will be no discrepancy, when A has an accurate perception, and, for the time
being, I shall assume that mistakes are not made.
76 the ethica l project
14. Plainly, one can recognize commands and act in response to them in ways that have
nothing to do with psychological altruism. That will concern us later. For the time being,
normative guidance is tied directly to the reshaping of altruism.
Normative Guidance 77
The oversimple view supposes that cases of type a represent the most
fundamental (primitive) form of psychological altruism; cases b–d dis-
play responses that could emerge only from normative guidance.
Why should one think this? Underlying the view is an apparently
plausible line of argument: the adjustment of desire could result only from
the operation of an emotion or the outcome of a process of reasoning; prior
to the articulation of ethical practice, the only forms of reasoning available
to an agent (human or nonhuman) would have to be calculations of selfish
advantage; hence, preethical adjustments of desire based on reasoning
would fail the anti-Machiavelli condition; by the same token, the only
ways in which obeying commands could produce altruism involve the
recognition of reasons for modifying desire.
On the account of §3, all four types count as instances of psychologi-
cal altruism. The argument just outlined denies that the modification of
desire constitutive of psychological altruism could occur in cases b–d. To
assess it, consider the examples that occupied us in the last chapter.
Some of them fit easily into the simple view. Prominent instances of psy-
chological altruism among primates express an emotional reaction to the
plight of another animal: mothers’ immediate responses to the discom-
fort of the young, or Little Bee’s patience with her mother. It is far from
evident, however, that the example of Jakie and Krom can be so easily
assimilated. Further, as §6 argued, maternal concern is not always a
78 the ethica l project
deliberations.15 Beyond this general point, there are grounds for attrib-
uting a major directive role to emotions in some instances of normative
guidance.
Consider, first, the way in which the psychology of a normatively
guided individual can develop. Initially, a human being, a member of
one of those small bands in which our ancestors lived, is disinclined to
respond to the predicament of one of his fellows. Capable of normative
guidance, he obeys a command to make a behaviorally altruistic response,
and his reacting in this way generates in him an emotional response to
the beneficiary, a primitive feeling of sympathy (as in case c previously).
That feeling is reinforced by the beneficiary’s reaction to his behavior,
and, perhaps after a few further interactions, this person is able to en-
gage in the behaviorally altruistic conduct either on the basis of the origi-
nal process or through a full—psychologically altruistic—identification
with the other. An emotional change may thus be the direct product of
the commitment to following an imperative: as you come to endorse
the command to treat your brother in a particu lar way, your emotions
toward the brother are modified, and the new fraternal feeling gives
rise to the desire to treat him in ways you would previously have
avoided (or resisted). Initially, normative guidance operates to pro-
duce behavioral altruism, but it eventually issues in full psychological
altruism.
How is that first step taken? Must it be on the basis of reasoning—
perhaps through a Machiavellian recognition of the benefits of comply-
ing? Not necessarily. Endorsing the command can embody emotions,
sometimes emotions directed toward the commander: you may accept
it because you are afraid.
The point may provoke an obvious reaction. If the notion of norma-
tive guidance is liberal enough to allow for conformity grounded in fear,
acquisition of the capacity for normative guidance cannot be the decisive
transition to ethical practice. A dilemma seems to loom. If the ability
to follow commands, to obey rules and precepts, is the decisive step in
acquiring a genuinely ethical practice, then this special sort of ability
15. See Antonio Damasio, Descartes’ Error (New York: Putnam, 1994), and Marc
Hauser, Moral Minds (New York: Ecco, 2006).
80 the ethica l project
16. A prime source of this view is, of course, Kant, and the most sophisticated elabora-
tions of it are offered in the Kantian tradition of ethical theory. Yet Kant’s opponents, who
often protest the denigration of the emotions, share the emphasis on a distinctively ethical
point of view. I am proposing that we reject a precondition of their debates.
Normative Guidance 81
does not mark the transition to the “ethical point of view.” That is not
because there is some further move that does the trick awaited by the
critics, one that shows how a very special kind of normative guidance (a
special way of internalizing the orders, say) constitutes the “ethical point
of view,” but because the entire conception of the “ethical point of view” is
a psychological myth devised by philosophers. There are plenty of ways in
which human beings can be led to recognize and to conform to com-
mands. While it is undeniable that some kinds of causal processes make
ethical progress over others (in ways Chapter 6 explores), we should not
infer a binary distinction between those processes that constitute genu-
inely ethical motivations and those that do not.
Most of the people who have ever lived have embedded their ethical
practices in a body of religious doctrine, viewing the precepts to be fol-
lowed as expressions of the will of gods, spirits, or ancestors (or occa-
sionally as capturing the tendencies of impersonal forces). Fear, awe, and
reverence have been parts of the emotional backdrop to most of the
important decisions and deliberations these people have made, and
virtually all those decisions have been subject to felt concerns about
the attitudes of transcendent beings. The fact that these people have
presupposed massively false beliefs about the universe does not under-
mine their status as ethical agents. Neither should the fact that what they
want, intend, and do are partially caused by emotions of fear and awe.
To insist on an “ethical point of view” liberated from such emotions is
to reserve that point of view for a very small number of cool secularists.
Moreover, it is reasonable to worry that the alleged ethical point of view
is itself only available because of the perspectives previously adopted by
those no longer counted as full ethical agents. The ability to “revere the
moral law” probably depends, in the evolution of culture and in the de-
velopment of individuals, on prior emotions, simpler feelings of rever-
ence now written off as ethically primitive.
There are many different ways in which people can be led to behav-
ioral altruism through their commitment to obeying a command. They
may explicitly represent to themselves the consequences of disobeying,
and find those consequences unpleasant or frightening because of future
interference with their bodies, behavior, or projects. They may make no
such explicit representation, but be moved by fear, or respect for the
82 the ethica l project
and cognitive states can be entangled in both cases. The causes of psy-
chological altruism and of normative guidance are probably highly het-
erogeneous. There are many ways to be a psychological altruist and,
equally, many ways to undergo normative guidance. None of these latter
modes is especially privileged as definitive of an “ethical point of view.”
No doubt there are extreme cases. Someone who forms the wish to
help another, simply because he is commanded to do so and because he
recognizes that disobedience will bring painful punishment on himself,
is no psychological altruist and (at best) at a rudimentary stage of ethical
practice. At the other extreme, a person who has a general conception
of the wishes of others, who follows a rule because it is taken to promote
the desires of someone else, may be viewed as at least an approximation
to psychological altruism and as participating in a more advanced form
of ethical practice, despite the fact that the wishes, and even the situa-
tion, of some of those she aids are unknown to her, and even though she
has a standing desire to be the sort of person who contributes to the
satisfaction of others’ desires. Normative guidance, as explicated here,
applies to individuals of both types, generating behavioral altruism in
the one instance and something akin to full psychological altruism in the
other.
Given the diversity of causal possibilities, why would one want to take
a stand on which of them has to be realized in a genuinely ethical agent?
The “ethical point of view” emerges as a challenge for naturalism because
it opposes the idea of ethical agents as those sympathetic individuals
who respond to the needs of others. While superficially attractive, these
people suffer a defect that makes them less than fully worthy.17 Their
kindly emotions are unreliable: it is reasonable to fear that the mind of
“the lover of humanity” will sometimes be “clouded,” and that, under
17. The classic source for the reaction is Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals,
Mary Gregor, trans., (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1998, Akademie
pagination 398). This passage is often viewed as expressing an opposition to Hume, but I
suspect that Kant actually had Adam Smith in mind. Not only does Smith develop the no-
tion of sympathy much further than Hume did, but his Theory of Moral Sentiments (Knud
Haakonssen, ed. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2002) [unlike Hume’s
Treatise (Oxford, UK: Oxford university Press, 1978)] is a work Kant is known to have
read.
84 the ethica l project
such conditions, fellow feeling will no longer operate and the person will
act selfishly. Yet if we take the concern about reliability seriously,
“proper” motivation appears impossible. What basis is there for suppos-
ing that carefully restraining the passions and engaging in abstract moral
reasoning (of any of the sorts philosophers have commended) will prove
reliable? Can’t our faculties of reasoning sometimes be “clouded,” too?
Abstract reflection and reasoning are hardly more reliable than the
emotional responses dismissed as capricious. Many of the most horrific
deeds of the twentieth century were carried out in the name of abstract
principles.
As we shall appreciate later, reliability is the issue (§21)—the worry
about the “clouding of the emotions” expressed an important point. Yet
the search for a single type of psychological causation, invariably reliable
or at least always more reliable than its rivals, is foolishly utopian. Dif-
ferent ways of inducing people to modify their preferences and actions
through obeying orders have different merits and deficiencies. Normative
guidance would work better by taking advantage of the ways in which
different psychological processes are suited to different situations. Per-
haps normative guidance evolved in parallel fashion to familiar types of
organic change, where initially crude systems for producing some im-
portant outcome are supplemented with further devices: the organism
has a variety of ways of generating what is required and is thus buffered
against catastrophe.
Normative guidance almost certainly began with crude external or-
ders, followed out of fear; much normative guidance may have been
mediated by respect for the supposed commands of transcendent be-
ings, respect tinged with hopes and fears (§17). Out of those hopes and
fears have come quite other emotional resources for motivating obedience,
feelings of awe and respect, of social solidarity and of contentment in
acting jointly with others, of pride in one’s conduct and of responsibility
to one’s fellows. The history of modes of normative guidance embodies
certain kinds of progress, and attempts to act through following dictates
the agent sets for himself, considers, and endorses have often been
progressive with respect to earlier and cruder forms of psychological
causation. These differences, however, are matters of kind rather than of
degree. Some processes (perhaps processes involving an especially pure
Normative Guidance 85
18. See Thomas Nagel, The Last Word (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997),
chap. 6; also The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), chap. 9.
19. This is already to demonstrate something that is very important for economic re-
search, for it entails that models imputing utility functions that are increasing functions of
amounts of money, and of this alone, are unlikely to accord with the behavior of actual
agents (for whom other things are important). Indeed, for the project of advancing econom-
ics, any concerns about the ways in which the subjects come to the wants they express in
their actions are entirely irrelevant. What is far less clear is how these ingenious experi-
ments bear on philosophical concerns about altruism and its role in ethical practice. For an
illuminating presentation of the experimental work, see Ernst Fehr and Urs Fischbacher,
“Human Altruism—Proximate Patterns and Evolutionary Origins,” Analyse & Kritik 27
(2005): 6–47.
86 the ethica l project
20. Subjects whose primary motivation is to impress (or to avoid disappointing) the
experimenter are easily linked to the experimental subjects who were prepared to infl ict
pain on others.
21. This conclusion motivates the attitudes of the researchers who carry out these ex-
periments, who suppose the important concept is that of behavioral altruism. My account
Normative Guidance 87
§12. Punishment
To treat normative guidance in this way has an obvious presupposition.
Behind the disposition to follow orders, whether delivered externally or
from internalized commands, must stand practices of punishment. Un-
less there were sanctions for disobedience, fear could hardly be central
to the initial capacity for normative guidance. Conversely, when punish-
ment is present in a group, it can make possible the evolution of elabo-
rate forms of cooperative behavior (and much else besides).22
Can this presupposition be defended? The actual beginnings of the
ethical project have been seen as a transition from a state of limited psy-
chological altruism to one in which commands are followed out of fear.
The plausibility of that view would be undermined unless there were an
explanation of the possibility of punishment.23
Begin with chimpanzee societies in which a crude precursor of pun-
ishment is already present. Conflicts within these groups are often set-
tled through the interventions of a dominant animal.24 Here rank or
physical strength (or both as concomitants of each other) prevail, and a
dispute is settled—not always, of course, through the infliction of pain
or discomfort on the animal whose initial defection gave rise to the con-
flict. Allies who might have intervened to protect some of those who re-
ceive the rough discipline of the dominant animal anticipate the costs to
themselves and hold back.
of the ethical project also recognizes the important role of dispositions to psychological
altruism. Different concepts are needed in different forms of inquiry and there need be no
quarrel about which notion of altruism is the “right one.”
22. Here I rely on a brilliant essay by Robert Boyd and Peter Richerson, “Punishment
Allows the Evolution of Cooperation (or Anything Else) in Sizable Groups” (originally
published in Ethology and Sociobiology 13 [1992]: 171– 95; reprinted as Chapter 9 of Boyd
and Richerson, The Origin and Evolution of Cultures [New York: Oxford University Press,
2005]).
23. Here, it is important to recall the methodological points of §2. A hypothesis about
the actual origins of the ethical project is supported by evidence about the prior hominid
state, and recognition of familiar human capacities to address its social difficulties. That
hypothesis must be defended by showing that its presuppositions are compatible with the
constraints acknowledged by pragmatic naturalism.
24. Goodall, Chimpanzees of Gombe, 321– 22; and de Waal, Peacemaking Among
Primates.
88 the ethica l project
Punishment need not always take so dramatic a form and can be pres-
ent simply when animals recognize opportunities for cooperation with
one another. Once the basic dispositions to altruism toward nonrelatives
that underlie chimpanzee-hominid society are present, optional games
(§8) are available. There is a pool of potential partners who can be re-
cruited for joint ventures. Because of tendencies to bond with close
friends and allies, some kinds of defections in the ventures will be
tolerated—animals will not behave with the rigor of discriminating co-
operators, refusing invitations to joint activity, when the potential part-
ners are targets of psychological altruism and longtime allies. Neverthe-
less, as the ties are weaker and the history of interaction more limited, it
is to be expected that a strategy like discriminating cooperation will be
favored. The altruistic dispositions emerging from the coalition game
incline animals to give weight to benefits received by their allies, and
thus to increase the value attributed to outcomes in which the ally gains
and the focal individual loses; consequently, animals will be less rigor-
ous in dismissing their close friends as potential partners for interaction;
as the relationship becomes more distant, however, the deviation from
the basic structure of the optional game (for example, optional PD) is
much smaller, and the strategy favored will more closely approximate
discriminating cooperation, refusing further interaction on the basis of a
single defection.
That itself is a form of punishment. To deprive an animal of opportu-
nities for cooperative interaction is to force it sometimes to pursue sub-
optimal ways of meeting its needs. So long as there are occasions for
joint activity with others, allies who remain willing to enter partnerships
with the animal in question, the impact need not be severe. If the allies
are often unavailable, however, or if the refusal to interact spreads more
broadly, life may become quite difficult. Ostracism can be a serious
punishment.25
The practices just mentioned turn on the responses of individuals to-
ward actions by others, actions they do not like. Those individuals can
25. Social confi nement and exclusion are used as forms of punishment in small human
societies. For a vivid depiction of the effects, see Jean Briggs, Never in Anger (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1970).
Normative Guidance 89
effectively cause pain for the perpetrators, either through their strength
(or through force that is unchallenged because of considerations of rank)
or through refusal to interact (a response even the weak can usually man-
age). Social participation in these events is minimal: in the one instance,
bystanders behave as mere spectators because of the physical power (or
the rank) of the punisher; in the other, their attitudes or actions cannot
completely undermine the punisher’s success—they may continue to co-
operate with the animal whom the punisher has blackballed, but they
typically cannot compel the punisher to do so.26 More sophisticated sys-
tems of punishment emerge, as animals form social expectations about
the circumstances of punishment.
For an action to be a kind, even a crude kind, of punishment, rather
than simply another contribution to the melee, it is important that
bystanders not be drawn in. Thus, a first step in the direction of punish-
ment requires that other members of the group, even allies of the threat-
ened animal, should not intervene. There is a regularity—friends of the
animal(s) targeted in punishment let it proceed. The next stage couples
the mere regularity with an expectation, shared across the population,
that others will not interfere in such contexts. The expectation suppresses
resistance on the part of the target; the animal picked out expects others
not to intervene and merely suffers what happens. A further refinement
would be the existence of a regularity concerning the animals who carry
out the aggression: perhaps they are animals who bear a particular relation
to the context; perhaps they play a particular social role. Finally, there
arises an expectation about the identities of the animals who initiate ag-
gression. At this last stage, we have reached the systems of punishment
found in contemporary human societies (and in societies for which we
have historical records).
The actual evolution of punishment may have diverged from the
sequence of steps just envisaged; nor is it necessary to specify a point
26. In principle, just as there could be escalation of violence when some animals physi-
cally punish others, so too there could be escalation of noncooperation when a discrimi-
nating cooperator crosses another individual off the list of potential partners. In the former
case, obvious strength or recognition of rank stops the arms race; in the latter, the refusal of
A to play optional games with B is, I suspect, often not recognized and, when it is, does not
inspire B’s allies to forgo potentially valuable opportunities for cooperation with A.
90 the ethica l project
27. It is not hard to construct models allowing for the possibility of adaptive advantages
in initiating and refi ning systems of punishment. Those models serve the function of pro-
tecting the hypothesis of a gradual evolution of schemes of punishment against the charge
that they are idle fantasies, incompatible with Darwinian evolutionary theory. Yet, without
far greater knowledge of the ancestral environments, and hence of the values of pertinent
parameters, it would be unjustified to propose that any model of this sort picks out the ac-
tual course of the evolution of punishment. Modesty is appropriate here.
Normative Guidance 91
28. Once again, whether the capacity will be advantageous turns on the details of
the situation. If punishment carries even a small probability of serious damage, and if the
order-following variant is just slightly more likely to avoid the altruism failure, then the
expected gains in terms of staying intact and healthy can outweigh the loss of food that re-
sults from sharing. Once again, we cannot know whether this scenario is plausible; this is a
“how possibly” explanation.
92 the ethica l project
§13. Conscience
Two prominent Shakespearean figures present a view of conscience.
Richard III offers a conjecture about the origins of internal checks on
our conduct:
Hamlet, while using similar words, worries about the effects of con-
science on behavior, once the tendency for self-regulation is already
present:
29. Nietzsche’s complaint is most evident in the fi rst two essays of On the Genealogy of
Morality (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1994); similar themes are sounded
by Freud, in many later works, but especially in Civilization and Its Discontents (New
York: Norton, 1989), as well as by William James in his writings on the “strenuousness” of
the moral life (James “The Moral Phi losopher and the Moral Life” in William James Writ-
ings 1878–1899 (New York: Library of America, 595– 617).
30. Once again, the methodological points of §2 are relevant here.
Normative Guidance 93
too weak to overlay the “native hue of resolution.” They might lapse
into the altruism failures from which normative guidance promised
liberation.
As more sophisticated systems of punishment are elaborated, how-
ever, the ineffectiveness of remembered commands becomes costly both
for those who fail to be normatively guided and for other members of
their societies. Variant individuals, with a tendency to respond to modes
of socialization that reinforced the disposition to self-discipline, would
cooperate more thoroughly and encounter less trouble. This extension
of normative guidance involves both social innovations and psychologi-
cal changes in the individuals. On the social side, it requires practices of
training the young members of the group so that the prospects of flout-
ing a command become associated with emotions they find unpleasant.
On the individual psychological front, it consists in refinements of the
emotional lives of these individuals.
The Shakespearean suggestion that fear lies at the root of this process
of internalization need not be exclusive: other emotions might be avail-
able for recruitment to the cause of normative guidance. Imagine a social
group of early humans, able to issue and remember commands, but vul-
nerable to the flouting of those commands by individuals who think of
themselves as strong. An innovation in the training regimes customary
among this group, the practice of issuing orders to the young, promotes
an enduring fear: perhaps they are lured into violating one of the precepts
and then subjected to some extraordinarily harsh and memorable pun-
ishment; perhaps this occurs at an especially impressionable age. There-
after, even as they grow, those trained in this way remain haunted by a
sense of dread as they contemplate disobeying certain commands. Con-
science does make cowards of them. Yet, similar effects can be achieved
in different ways. If the young are induced to identify with some of the
orders current in their group, if they see obeying those orders as partly
constitutive of belonging to this distinctive social unit, they may feel more
complex reactive emotions—pride, perhaps, when they continue to carry
out the commands, shame or guilt when they do not. As these reactive
feelings attach to outcomes considered in prospect, they may substi-
tute for the raw fear of punishment, promoting the same types of coop-
erative behavior on a different basis.
94 the ethica l project
text, I do not think these exhaust all the possibilities; nor do I think they exclude one an-
other in the ways often suggested.
32. The point is eloquently expressed by Nietzsche in his critique of the “herd moral-
ity” based on ressentiment. How to foster forms of conscience that yield the important
benefits of internalization without deforming individuals is, of course, a question the ethi-
cal project continually has to decide.
33. One way of reading Freud’s Civilization and Its Discontents is to view him as claim-
ing that any way of achieving the measure of social cooperation required for civilization
will have to involve both prohibitions on a massive scale and pervasive negative emotions.
His claims rest on very particu lar ideas about our fundamental desires and drives.
34. This is obviously akin to the Hobbesian perspective on the constructive role of fear
that permeates Leviathan.
96 the ethica l project
35. Here my views are close to those of Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cam-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991).
36. See Christoph Boehm, Hierarchy in the Forest (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univer-
sity Press, 1999); Richard Lee, The !Kung San (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press, 1979); Raymond Firth We, The Tikopia (Boston: Beacon, 1961), Marjorie Shostak,
Nisa (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981).
Normative Guidance 97
ancestors lived like that until roughly ten to fifteen thousand years ago.
Consequently, more than three-quarters of the period through which
the ethical project has evolved was spent in social circumstances now
quite rare. Small societies reasonably fear the interference and preda-
tions of neighbors. Social cohesion is vital, and no adult can be margin-
alized in normative discussion. As the coalition game (§9) already re-
vealed, the hominid bands out of which early human societies grew
resulted from the partitioning of the physical environment through coali-
tion building. The stability of the partition depends on the approximate
balance among neighboring groups, and, where the groups are small, the
contribution of every member is necessary. Discussions that involve all
adults, that aim to answer to the needs of all adults, and that blur distinc-
tions of rank and ability were crucial to roughly the first forty thousand
years of the ethical project.37
Those discussions would have issued in agreed-upon rules for life
together—but not merely on that. Ethical codes are multidimensional:
besides explicit rules, they involve categories for classifying conduct,
stories that describe exemplary actions (both commended and frowned
upon), patterns of socialization, and habitual forms of behavior. At the
earliest stages, we should think of all these elements as accepted by all
members of the group. Around the campfires, they reached agreement
on precepts, on stories of model behavior, on ways of training the young,
on practices of punishment, on sanctioned habits, perhaps occasionally
on changes in the concepts hitherto employed. This form of socially
embedded normative guidance set the stage for the evolution of the ethi-
cal project.
Ethical codes can pronounce on their own amendment, fi rmly dis-
allowing any possibilities of change or welcoming revisionary discussion.
Perhaps at early stages, there was a common insistence on clear rules,
to be followed obediently and never to be modified. The difficulties of
37. My estimates here are speculative. I suppose that the ethical project began with the
acquisition of full language, at the latest fi fty thousand years ago, and that human societies
were small until, at the earliest, fi fteen thousand years ago. I conclude that the social egali-
tarianism observed in contemporary hunter-gatherers, and the kinds of social discussions
in which they engage, was central to the ethical project for at least the first thirty-five thou-
sand years.
98 the ethica l project
38. The type of view considered here is most clearly expressed by Marc Hauser. See his
Moral Minds (New York: Harper Collins, 2006).
Normative Guidance 99
approve, but they, the original agents, do not yet have these standards or
yet see a distinction between the behavior they used to exhibit and that
which they now perform. From our perspective they may be more just
than their predecessors, or kindlier perhaps, but this is not an assess-
ment they can make.
For them to initiate the ethical project they must come to see certain
types of behavior as exemplary or particular rules as commanding their
obedience. Could they derive any such recognitional ability from their
own dispositions and capacities, or from reflection on what they are
moved to do? How would they come to see one desire or action-prompting
emotion as different in status from others? They feel many kinds of sen-
timents (although the emotions available to them depend on the social
environments in which they live), but how do they ascertain which ones
belong to the “party of humanity”? 39 To identify something as a genuine
command, they need to distinguish commands from other pressures, and
the most evident possibility is to identify a source—a commander. Given
their environment, the only available source consists of their fellow group
members. If there were an explicit practice of discussing and formulat-
ing rules for the group, they would be able to draw the critical distinc-
tions. Nothing else in their psychology or in the ambient environment
can confer that ability on them. The ethical project can only begin, then,
when normative guidance is socially embedded.40
Even if there are dispositions to behave in ways we think of as ethi-
cally progressive—to refrain from violence, to share more, to comfort
the suffering, or whatever—these are merely “nice tendencies,” ways of
conforming to regularities (regularities the ethical project, once it gets
going, will approve), but they are not abilities to obey rules or precepts.
To be the beginnings of the ethical project they must be coupled to a
capacity to discern and be governed by rules and commands that re-
ceive some sort of authority. The ethical project requires normative
39. I borrow the phrase from Hume, Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals (In-
dianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1986), 77. It serves as a useful reminder of the fact that those who
believe in the existence of particu lar moral sentiments—or moral judgments—need to ex-
plain how agents are able to identify which ones these are.
40. There are affi nities between the line of argument in this paragraph and Wittgen-
stein’s famous private-language argument (Philosophical Investigations §§243 ff.).
100 the ethica l project
41. Hauser (Moral Minds) uses the analogy, and supposes that there is an ethical coun-
terpart to “universal grammar.” For reasons given in the text, I am dubious.
42. The most systematic body of results comes from the work of Fehr and his associates;
see the reference in note 19. Hauser lucidly summarizes this.
43. The problem is exactly analogous to one that bedev ils many sociobiological and ge-
netic determinist claims—the difficulty of extrapolating a norm of reaction from a small
sample of cases. For diagnosis, see Kitcher, Vaulting Ambition: Sociobiology and the Quest
for Human Nature (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1985) and “Battling the Undead” in
Rama Singh, Costas Krimbas, Diane Paul, and John Beatty (eds) Thinking About Evolu-
tion: Historical, Philosophical and Political Perspectives (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 2001, 396–414).
44. See Colin Turnbull, The Mountain People (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1972);
Primo Levi, Survival in Auschwitz (New York: Touchstone Books, 1996); and John Sabini
and Maury Silver, The Moralities of Everyday Life (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press,
1982). Turnbull’s ethnography is controversial, but unless all his observations are thor-
oughly false, there would still be grounds for wondering about the hypothesis that our
predispositions make contrary norms impossible for us.
102 the ethica l project
Our tendencies to behavior are most likely quite plastic. Given the
hypothetical genomic change that underlies the supposedly broadened
altruistic tendencies, there would probably be a range of dispositions
to action across the (largely uncharted) space of social environments in
which people can live. If the conclusions drawn earlier (§11) about the
explanation of the behavior of subjects in experiments on sharing are
correct, propensities for conduct are likely to depend on the presence of
socially embedded normative guidance and the forms that guidance
takes. The weaker version of the biological hypothesis is implausible so
long as it insists on a specific type of emotional reaction available across
all environments and very particular ways in which that emotional reac-
tion is directed independently of the social milieu.
Far more plausible is the idea that, because of our evolved psychology,
not all attempts to inculcate norms will do equally well. Perhaps we do
have tendencies for emotional responses to types of actions, so that, in
the environments that prevail, following one norm might be uncomfort-
able for us (in the way experimental subjects feel discomfort as they are
following the experimenter’s order to inflict “pain”), while following an-
other might be accompanied by feelings of ease. To modify the linguistic
analogy, given those social environments so far created, some languages
might be more difficult to learn—and some sets of commands similarly
hard to follow. Human evolutionary history may have bequeathed to us
forms of blindness that make reliable compliance with some prescriptions
difficult. Without a proof of impossibility, pragmatism counsels societ-
ies to work hard at training their members to follow the precepts they
deem most important.
Our early human ancestors, equipped with a capacity for normative
guidance, were able to explore various possibilities for social exercise
of that capacity. Those explorations proceed along two dimensions, one
concerned with the ways in which the young are trained in the ethical
code, the other focused on the content of the code. Because we know, as
yet, so little about any biases with which our evolutionary past might have
equipped us, my account will attend to the more visible, social, features
of ethical exploration. To proceed in this way is not to conceive of human
beings as infinitely plastic, or (to switch images) as blank slates on which
societies can write what they please. The history of the ethical project,
Normative Guidance 103
45. A prime example is the case of cooperation in child care. See the references in note 1.
chapter 3
Experiments of Living
104
Experiments of Living 105
vision of which distributions are preferred and a rule enjoining the di-
viding of the spoils.1
Whether or not they would go as smoothly as just supposed, conver-
sations about sharing are readily imaginable. Equally, the discussants
might agree to aim at increasing the food supply, viewing each band
member’s wish to assuage hunger as something to be supported, or they
might all concur in repudiating acts that initiate violence. Socially em-
bedded normative guidance can begin the ethical project, but the pre-
cepts it is likely to generate appear simple and crude. How could the
project of these pioneers blossom into the ethical richness of contempo-
rary life? How did we get from there to here?
There is no serious chance of answering the second question, of de-
fending some narrative as providing the actual evolution of the ethical
project. The clues are too scanty. For the fifty thousand (or more) years
of the ethical project, we have written records only for the last five thou-
sand. Already, at the dawn of writing, elaborate systems of rules are in
place. Evidently, much happened in the Paleolithic and the early Neo-
lithic, leaving only indirect indicators of social change. Knowing the
starting point (the small bands of discussants) and the late phases (ethi-
cal life today and the historical records of the past few millennia), one
can identify what changes occurred, even if it would be folly to pretend
to know how they came about.
Here are some obvious modifications. By five thousand years ago, hu-
man beings had assembled in societies vastly larger than the groups in
1. I do not suggest that the rule agreed on need be the first choice of every band member,
nor that it take any specific form: perhaps it demands equal division, or equal division
among those who have gathered the resources, or division by subunits with special regard
to the needs of younger members. The point is both that there is pressure to agree on some-
thing, and that each of the discussants attempts to accommodate the views of others. This
last point is one way in which the approach I favor diverges from that taken by John Rawls
(A Theory of Justice [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971]). Instead of suppos-
ing that the discussants are rational egoists who consider the consequences for themselves
under conditions of (partial) ignorance, I take them to be psychological altruists, able to
refi ne that psychological altruism in contemplating a general problem that they face, who
deliberate using their knowledge of one another. Further differences lie in the facts that this
is no hypothetical contract, and that it is not directed at any “basic structure of society.”
106 the ethica l project
which the ethical project began. In those large settlements, the egalitari-
anism of the early phases had given way to complex hierarchies. Ethical
life had become entangled with religion. It had also come to address is-
sues beyond the conceptual horizons of the pioneers: citizens of the polis
who inquire into the good life inhabit a different world from those mak-
ing decisions about how to share scarce resources. New roles and in-
stitutions had emerged, generating precepts about property and about
marriage. In more subtle ways, an expansion of the notion of altruism,
beyond the concepts so far considered, permitted new ethical ideas
about human relationships.
There is no doubt that these changes occurred. Acknowledging the
difficulty of explaining how they actually happened leaves pragmatic
naturalism with a problem. Skeptics charge that the account of the ori-
gins of ethical practice works only by changing the subject—something
is shown to emerge, but it is not really ethics. Versions of the accusation
surfaced in the previous chapter: How did we acquire the “ethical point
of view”? How was the commanding voice internalized? How did a sys-
tem of punishment evolve? The questions gain force by sowing doubt
about any possibility of explanation in the terms pragmatic naturalism
permits. No available route leads from there to here.
Doubt is settled by telling a story meeting all the constraints. The
skeptic denies that something is possible, and an adequate response is
to provide a “how possibly” explanation (§2); claiming that this is how
things actually happened is not required. In the previous chapter, the
challenges were turned back by denying the need for any “ethical point
of view” (§11), by offering a scenario for the emergence of systems of
punishment, crude and more refi ned (§12), and by suggesting several
possible ways to build a conscience (§13). The goal of the present chap-
ter is to offer something similar for the rich features of the ethical life
apparently so far removed from the small groups of the pioneers. Not,
then, “how we actually got from there to here” but “how we might have
done so.”
Fundamental to the “how possibly” explanations to be developed
is the increased power of cultural transmission in a species that has
acquired language. The fi rst task is to consider this mechanism for
change.
Experiments of Living 107
2. The phrase is John Stuart Mill’s: see On Liberty [Oxford: Oxford University Press
(World’s Classics)], 1998 chap. 3.
3. I shall ignore issues about how far one must look into the future to achieve a reliable
measure for assessing success. Oversimplifying again, we can suppose that the relative
proportions in the first generation of descendants are preserved in subsequent iterations.
108 the ethica l project
4. Here there is further room for decision, for, if a code commands the obedience of a
smaller number of large groups, should it be counted as more or less successful than one
that is followed in a larger number of societies whose combined population is less? It is
important to appreciate the distinct possibilities, but, for the purposes of the current dis-
cussion, no decision about which is the real measure of cultural success is required.
5. The slogan was advanced in classic discussions of human sociobiology—see, for ex-
ample, Charles Lumsden and E. O. Wilson, Genes, Minds, and Culture (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1982). The details of the argument for thinking the slogan is
correct turn out to be much more complex than the simple presentation in the text sug-
gests, and controversial assumptions are required for its derivation [cf. the review by John
Maynard Smith and N. Warren, and chap. 10 of my Vaulting Ambition (Evolution, 6, 1982,
620–27)]. The most important rebuttal of the idea that cultural success and biological suc-
cess are likely to be coupled came from articulated accounts of the coevolution of genes and
Experiments of Living 109
culture. A seminal analysis was provided by Robert Boyd and Peter Richerson in Culture
and the Evolutionary Process (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985), and developed
further in several essays in their Origin and Evolution of Cultures (New York: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 2005).
6. For a succinct explanation of this important thesis, see Boyd and Richerson, Origin
and Evolution of Cultures, 8–11; more technical amplifications are provided in chaps. 1 and
2 of the same book.
7. Although the oversimplification I have adopted invites the thought that individual
rules are the atomic units transmitted in the history of ethical practice, the possibilities of
more subtle influences and modifications reveal that that is inadequate: a search for cultural
“atoms” must slice codes more finely. Moreover, there are good reasons for not thinking of
110 the ethica l project
For the first forty thousand years of the ethical project, small bands of
human beings regulated their lives by socially embedded ethical codes.
Faced with perceived difficulties the extant versions of their codes failed
to address, they tried new ideas. Sometimes, they interacted with other
bands, in whose practices they saw something to inspire revision of their
own rules. Eventually, some groups merged, and aspects of one or both
of the antecedent codes endured in the practice of the subsequent soci-
ety. Some bands simply died out, or dispersed, and their ethical prac-
tices withered with them, even though survivors may have brought fac-
ets of the previous code into the groups they joined. Sometimes new
arrivals, accepted perhaps as mates, brought novel ideas to the camp-
fire discussions, producing a synthesis previously envisaged by neither
of the (“parent”) groups. Processes of these general types (and probably
many more) combined to cause some kinds of rules to be prevalent, others
rare.
The most widely shared features of contemporary ethical codes prob-
ably emerged in many different ways. If human beings have evolved psy-
chological tendencies to acquire certain kinds of norms, a common rule
might reflect these propensities (subject to the qualifications of §14). A
rule might be the simplest response to a difficulty faced by all social
groups. A rule (or a preliminary version) might originate in a single group
and spread to others because it promises to satisfy widely shared de-
sires. Alternatively, groups failing to acquire the rule might suffer some
severe disadvantage, so that they had a tendency to die out or to be
taken over by outsiders. The features of the ethical codes transmitted to
us emerge from these sorts of episodes—and no doubt many more
besides.
cultural practices generally and ethical codes in particu lar as collections of discrete atoms
that can be shuffled and rearranged in novel combinations. Interactions among such al-
leged units may be crucial to the nature of the cultural practice, so that there is no stable,
practice-independent contribution a cultural “atom” generates. Perhaps only in the context
of an entire ethical code does a rule have specific meaning. See, for example, the writings of
Dan Sperber, in particu lar, Explaining Culture (Oxford: Blackwell, 1996). I have tried to
show the complexities of attempts to build serious theories of culture that mimic biological
evolution—theories of the transmission of “memes”— even at the level of kinematics; see my
“Infectious Ideas,” Chapter 10 of Philip Kitcher In Mendel’s Mirror (New York: Oxford
University Press, 2003).
Experiments of Living 111
8. The plausible assumption that rules directed at remedying altruism failures are likely
to promote the average Darwinian fitness of individuals as well as to enhance the cultural
competitiveness of the ethical practices realized in social groups enables me to sidestep
worries that the forces of cultural and Darwinian competition might tug in different direc-
tions. A more general account would explore the ways in which rules antithetical to average
Darwinian fitness might be supported because of their efficacy in cultural competition, but
my purposes here can be satisfied with far less. Boyd and Richerson, Origin and Evolution
of Cultures, provide the elements out of which the more general account can be fashioned.
Experiments of Living 113
retract their favors if the commands are broken. Spirits are associated
with particular places or particular animals and will wreak vengeance
on the group if rules are violated. There are hidden forces in nature,
with which people must align themselves to be successful, and to deviate
from the prescriptions is to endanger or destroy this alignment. Ethnog-
raphies testify to the popularity of the idea of unobserved enforcement
(typically, but not always, personified): as when informants tell of an “all-
father” who “from his residence in the sky watches the actions of men
[and] ‘is very angry when they do things they ought not to do, as when
they eat forbidden food.’ ”9
Once the idea of an unseen enforcer is in place, fear of punishment
can be embedded in a complex constellation of emotional responses.
Commands promulgated by elders can be identified with the wishes of
the gods or spirits (or with the tendencies of the impersonal forces affect-
ing human success). If the gods are local, they may be seen as prescrib-
ing particular rules for the group, rules that both express the favor of
the deities and constitute the identity of the band. Later phases of a
group’s ethical practice look back on an episode in which the ancestors
obtained the favor of a particular divinity and were also given the divine
command(ment)s.10 Crude fear of punishment is transmuted into more
positive emotions—awe, reverence—and the commands are welcomed
as a mark of the favor of an extraordinary being. Group members see the
rules as constitutive of who they are.
Religious beliefs, beliefs in some kind of “transcendent” reality, tied
to the origin and reinforcement of ethical prescriptions, are almost uni-
versal across known human societies—at least until recently. Why is this?
As noted (§16), there are many possible ways to succeed in cultural com-
petition, and the would-be explainer of the prevalence of any aspect of
9. Edward Westermarck, The Origin and Development of the Moral Ideas, 2nd ed.
(London: Macmillan, 1926), Vol. 2, 671; the entire chapter (chap. 50) is full of fascinating
examples of “Gods as Guardians of Morality.”
10. This conception is plainly present in the earliest versions of the Judaic tradition;
moreover, as the preambles to the legal codes of the ancient Near East make very clear, very
similar ideas appear in societies throughout Mesopotamia and Egypt. I conjecture that
these are simply written out versions of oral traditions that thrived and developed over tens
of thousands of years.
114 the ethica l project
11. Dewey favors an anthropological account along these lines, viewing it as the ultimate
source not only of religion, but also of philosophy and of science. See the opening chapters
of The Quest for Certainty vol. 4 of John Dewey: The Later Works (Carbondale IL: Univer-
sity of Southern Illinois Press). See also Pascal Boyer, Religion Explained (New York: Ba-
sic Books, 2001), and Daniel Dennett, Breaking the Spell (New York: Penguin, 2006).
Experiments of Living 115
the kill to the owner of the arrow, which, when combined with a wide-
spread practice of arrow sharing, effectively reduces differences in hunt-
ing yield.13 Violation of these conventions is regarded as a way of court-
ing bad luck. Under the circumstances of early human life, groups failing
to develop similar strategies would forfeit the advantages normative
guidance had brought.14 The societies visible in the first written records,
however, contain fine differentiation of rank and status. What might
have produced them?
Archeological evidence of early cities (Jericho, Çatal Hüyük) makes it
apparent that, by eight thousand years ago, human beings were able to
live in groups far larger than those present at the early stages of the ethi-
cal project.15 When a thousand or more people live within the walls of
the same city, strategies of peacemaking through face-to-face reassur-
ance are no longer applicable. There must be a system of agreed-upon
rules for forestalling potential conflicts and for dealing with people who
are relative strangers. Some extension of the prevailing injunctions to
cover transactions with individuals outside the small group of regular
associates must have been achieved substantially earlier. By fifteen thou-
sand years ago, at the very latest, bands of human beings were periodi-
cally uniting temporarily, for the deposits at some sites testify to a larger
association.16 Moreover, there is indirect evidence for peaceful intergroup
associations at earlier stages—and possibly even for the existence of
trade between different bands.
13. See Richard Lee, The !Kung San (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press,
1979).
14. For general discussion of the importance of egalitarianism, see Cristoph Boehm,
Hierarchy in the Forest (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), and for telling
examples see Lee,!Kung San. The case for a period of egalitarianism in human prehistory,
between the hierarchies of apelike hominids and those of the societies for which we have
historical records, is succinctly made by B. M. Knauft, “Violence and Sociality in Human
Evolution,” Current Anthropology 32 (1991): 391–428; see, in particular, the famous U-shaped
curve.
15. See James Mellaart, Çatal Hüyük (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1967).
16. See Clive Gamble, The Palaeolithic Societies of Europe (Cambridge, UK: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1999), chap. 8; Paul Mellars, “The Upper Palaeolithic Revolu-
tion,” in The Oxford Illustrated Prehistory of Europe, ed. Barry Cunliffe (Oxford, UK:
Oxford University Press, 1994), 42–78.
Experiments of Living 117
17. The hypothesis of Paleolithic trading networks was originally advanced by Colin
Renfrew and his colleagues, based on the discovery of obsidian tools at considerable dis-
tances from the nearest source. See C. Renfrew and S. Shennan, eds., Ranking, Resource,
and Exchange (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1982). The trade-network
hypothesis seems superior to the rival idea of long journeys undertaken by members of a
band, given the obvious problem of explaining how such journeys might be navigated.
118 the ethica l project
18. See Jean-Marie Chauvet, Eliette Brunel Deschamps, and Christian Hillaire, Dawn
of Art (New York: Harry N. Abrams, 1996).
19. The Egyptian Book of the Dead, trans. E. A. Wallis Budge (New York: Dover, 1967),
194– 98; also in James B. Pritchard, ed., Ancient Near Eastern Texts (Princeton, NJ: Prince-
ton University Press, 1969), 34–36.
Experiments of Living 119
20. There is even a Babylonian wisdom literature, dating to before 700 b.c.e. (possibly
to significantly before this period), in which the attitudes we associate with Christian ethi-
cal conceptions are articulated. It reads: “Unto your opponent do no evil / Your evildoer
recompense with good; / Unto your enemy let justice [be done].” Another text, of uncertain
date but possibly very early, offers the same theme: “Do not return evil to your adversary; /
Requite with kindness the one who does evil to you.” There is no reason to think that the
authors of these texts invented the idea. They, too, like the writers who borrowed the
120 the ethica l project
theme of forgiveness from them, probably drew on previous traditions. The ethical codes
of prehistory survive in these early texts, accompanied by regulations that deal with novel
problems.
21. Many prominent thinkers have been willing to advance views about law quite simi-
lar to my proposals about ethics: witness H. J. S. Maine, Ancient Law (Tucson: University
of Arizona Press, 1986); Benjamin Cardozo, The Growth of the Law (New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press, 1924); and H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford, UK: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 1961). Like Dewey, I take the kinship very seriously (as did Cardozo). For
encouragement to think about the development of law, I am indebted to Jeremy Waldron,
and I am also grateful to Sam Rothschild for valuable conversations.
Experiments of Living 121
22. It is worth noting that, even within traditions differentiating the ethical from matters
of law, religion, and etiquette, some voices speak differently. Pioneering secularists of the
past (Hume, Adam Smith) often seem to blur the distinction between morals and man-
ners: eighteenth-century accounts of moral sentiments surprise readers by grouping wit,
cheerfulness, and elegance with honesty and generosity. Even thinkers who allow for a
122 the ethica l project
separation between religious commands and the requirements of ethics do not always as-
sign priority to the ethical. Kierkegaard is famous (notorious?) for maintaining that the
greatness of Abraham, as “the knight of faith,” consists in his “suspension of the ethical.”
To suppose he can be refuted by declaring that it is constitutive of ethical maxims to take
priority over religious injunctions is no more convincing than specifying that your favorite
rule (or strategy) of nondeductive inference must be adopted because it is constitutive of
rationality. Better to try to understand why one, rather than the other, might be incorpo-
rated in our practices.
Experiments of Living 123
23. As envisaged by Adam Smith, Wealth of Nations (New York: Modern Library,
2000), book 1, chap. 1.
124 the ethica l project
24. In telling this story, I diverge from Smith, who appeals to an innate propensity to
“truck and barter.” Unlike Smith, I have also not assumed that the effect of the division of
labor must be greater productivity—some groups may settle for less work and more leisure.
See Smith, Wealth of Nations, book 1, chap. 2, esp. 16.
Experiments of Living 125
the pertinent tasks, while others never do, it will be important to ensure
that the users’ access to the needed implements is not impeded by the
activities of nonusers. These developments introduce an embryonic con-
ception of property.
Even though the basic resources of the group (food, materials for shel-
ter, and so on) are divided, the group as a whole owns the surplus. This
is to be used in hard times and to be available for exchange, and it will be
important to defend it against those who would take it. The rules allow-
ing for trade must specify that items brought by one trading partner are
not simply to be seized by others. Similarly, if the equipment required
for performing a particular task is to be available to one group member
and not to others, there must be rules allowing the user to keep it and
forbidding nonusers to interfere. Those rules will not yet permit the user
to transfer the items in question to anyone else he or she chooses—rather,
they insist that tools be passed on to the next performer of the task—but
they will protect a temporary power to employ the equipment. Commu-
nal property and a limited form of individual property have emerged.
discriminate those who have been unreliable in the past, and it may also
pay to choose individuals with particular physical traits.25 With devel-
oped division of labor, finer scrutiny became pertinent. Scrutiny starts
to perturb the egalitarian attitudes of the group—for some of the tasks
assigned can be carried out successfully by any of a relatively large sub-
group (they require no special talent or training), while others may be
difficult to fill well. Roles are more or less demanding, according as they
have more or fewer potential occupants.
Suppose a particular role—tracking, say—is both demanding in this
sense and requires extensive training and effort in performance. Good
potential trackers are rare, their skills need to be honed over a relatively
long time, and their tracking activities require searching attentively
through a broad area. The group inculcates stringent rules for learning
and performing this role. The solitary nature of the task, however, makes
enforcement difficult, and the bare idea of unseen enforcement may not
prove enough. A new idea is added: significant contribution of success-
ful tracking to the tribal stock is particularly favored by the entities who
are the source of the ethical code. Especially pleasing to the gods are
those with rare talents, who develop those talents to the full and use
them energetically in ser vice of the common good. In societies elabo-
rating the division of labor in this fashion, new human desires readily
emerge: people come to want the approbation, even admiration of their
fellows; they wish to enjoy the favor of the gods.
So elaborated, the code begins to advance a new conception of the
good human life. Its earlier forms identified the common good in terms
of basic desires, viewing human lives as going well when those basic de-
sires were met. Early stages of the ethical project introduced rules whose
intended effect was to improve the prospect of satisfying more of the ba-
sic desires and thus living better. Introducing the unseen enforcer con-
nected the rules with the wishes of a great being with special concern for
25. Consider a joint hunting venture. If two equally reliable partners are available, and
one is quicker than the other, that person may be a better bet for bringing home the game.
That can easily be offset by other considerations: if the slower individual is a longtime as-
sociate, and failure to interact on this occasion would prompt the person then to refuse
future invitations, the physical superiority of the rival candidate is better ignored.
128 the ethica l project
the group.26 Now the development and exercise of rare talent—in ser vice
of meeting the basic desires of members of the band—is seen as favored
by this being. Well-socialized group members want this sort of approval.
For the specially gifted, at least, to live well involves gaining the being’s
favor.
Once the broader idea of a good human life has been introduced as
an incentive for the rarely talented, it can be extended to others. Al-
though it is less important to encourage those who fi ll less demanding
roles, general diligence benefits the band. The myth that divine ap-
proval descends on those who fit themselves to their station and dis-
charge its duties with energy is a valuable extension of the idea of un-
seen enforcement. It detaches the rules enjoining development of talents
from their derivative status, as consequences of more general principles
about contributing to cooperative projects, and locates them in the
direct command of the unseen lawgiver. Perfecting one’s talents may
contribute to the success of the group, but it is required of each member
because it is the divine will.27
Cultural competition can favor an evolutionary transition from an
initial stage at which ethical codes are directed only at altruism failures
to more internally complex societies, with divisions of labor, prescrip-
tions for interactions with members outside the group, specific roles, rules
for carrying out those roles, and injunctions for behavior even when the
impact on others is not of central concern. At this stage in the ethical
project, continued discussion of the prevalent ethical code will some-
times need to consider the institutions of the group: prescribed pat-
terns of behavior focused on some domain of the band’s life. My “how
possibly” story concludes with the emergence and evolution of an insti-
tution presupposed by well-known ethical maxims: property.28
26. To keep things simple, I offer a version in which unseen enforcement is personified.
27. Once the injunction to develop talent has been detached from the consequences for
society, it can be maintained as a freestanding, self-regarding maxim, even when the idea of
a divine backing for it is abandoned. The attitude of the citizens of Plato’s Republic is,
presumably, one of seeing lives as good in terms of the perfection of talent—for this is what
the orga nization of the city aims to do— even though they have read the Euthyphro.
28. Both the seventh commandment and the tenth presuppose the institution of private
property.
Experiments of Living 129
29. Often, tools will be supposed to show a little, but only a little wear; there may be
occasions, however, when extensive per for mance involves considerable damage to a tool.
The point is that the extent to which this is to occur is not for the user to decide.
30. This is a standard conception in the history of political economy (developed by
Smith and by many others), and the thought that some kind of private property is a neces-
sary incentive for hard work occurs even in a thinker as worried about the notion as John
Stuart Mill (see Principles of Political Economy, Works [Toronto: University of Toronto
Press, 1963], 2:207, 2:225–26, 3:742–55).
130 the ethica l project
31. This is a nontrivial supposition, for one can imagine groups in which practices of
socialization rendered it quite repugnant.
32. My account echoes a famous Genesis story, the deal Jacob strikes with his father-in-
law, Laban. Similarly, the earlier discussion of saving surplus in good years, in preparation
for hard times, recalls the policies Joseph institutes in Egypt. Might we consider the myths
of ancient religions as embodying records of transitions in human prehistory retrospec-
tively seen as important forms of social and ethical advance?
Experiments of Living 131
33. Much later (in §62) we shall take up this institution with more critical eyes.
132 the ethica l project
34. A fully rigorous account would need further qualifications, since it is possible for
someone to acquire misleading information that subverts the modified wish. It would do
so, of course, by coming with another type of misconception or ignorance, from which yet
further knowledge could relieve the person. Perhaps the best way to approach the notion of
interests is to start with the idea of a remedy for ignorance, conceived as the clearing up of
misconceptions or a new piece of knowledge. An interest is a wish one would have, given a
remedy for current ignorance, and a wish that would survive any further acquisition of
knowledge provided the acquisition was supplemented with an appropriate remedy for ig-
norance. Whether this disposes of all the difficulties is not obvious. In any event, for our
purposes, the simpler approach of the text will do.
134 the ethica l project
35. Note that the imagined scenario does not involve any direct benefit for A; for A there
are only costs (use of time and energy, risk of harm from the resentful B*). In terms of the
approach of §9, we should take A and B to belong to a subcoalition that does not include B*;
B* is a more distant member of the band, in that the first subcoalition that includes A and
B* is bigger and more inclusive than the first subcoalition that includes A and B (and simi-
larly for B and B*).
Experiments of Living 135
you to act selfishly, you would perform the individually preferred ac-
tions, but you would forfeit what is primary for each of you—to wit, be-
ing together. Were both of you to act as psychological altruists, as so far
construed, the situation would be even worse: each would do the less-
preferred action and still not have the benefit of acting together. To escape
the bind, one of you has to be a different type of psychological altruist,
an altruist who adjusts wishes to align them with the other’s altruistic
desire.37
Although it is evident that the concept of higher-order altruism can be
abused, providing cover for people to pursue their selfish wants, the
anti-Machiavellian condition (§3) discriminates cases. Egoists simply have
their solitary wants, or see the simulation of an altruistic response to
others as a good strategy for achieving those wants (“Of course, if you
really want to help me by doing that, I don’t want to stand in your way”).
Psychological altruists reflect on their partners’ wishes, factor in their
own desires to promote those wishes, and, if they accept the altruism of
a partner, do so because they view it as based on a wish more central to
the partner’s life than any they would express by promoting the part-
ner’s nonaltruistic desires.38
Often-repeated interactions among people, in which altruistic re-
sponses are expressed by both parties, bring with them the possibility of
an importantly different form of higher-order altruism, one in which the
processes through which outcomes are reached become sources of happi-
ness for the participants. The original solitary value ascribed to an out-
come is sometimes negligible in comparison to the value that whatever
outcome is reached results from a serious process of mutual engagement
with the wishes of another person. Adjusting our actions to one another
can be more important for us than what those actions actually achieve.
138
One Thing after Another? 139
1. Characterizing what relativism actually claims, and assessing its credentials, turns
out to be a complex matter. For perceptive discussions of the cluster of problems here, see
Gilbert Harman, The Nature of Morality (New York, Oxford University Press, 1977); Mi-
chele Moody-Adams, Fieldwork in Familiar Places (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1997); and Carol Rovane, “Relativism Requires Alternatives, Not Disagreement or
Relative Truth” Blackwell Companion to Relativism, ed. S. Hales (Blackwell, 2011);
Rovane’s views about the claims of relativism are developed further in a forthcoming book.
140 the ethica l project
briefly at three examples challenging the mere-change view, but not pro-
viding insight into the processes underlying the apparently progressive
transitions: the transformation of the lex talionis in the ancient world,
the change from a heroic ethos in ancient Greece to the ideal of the citizen
of the polis, the emphasis on compassion introduced by Christianity.
For clearer ideas about how the participants made their decisions, we
shall need more recent cases.
2. James Pritchard, ed., Ancient Near-Eastern Texts (Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univer-
sity Press, 1950), 170, 175.
3. Ibid., 176.
4. Ibid., 185.
5. Of course, not all relatively ancient societies maintained the lex talionis. Nordic and
Saxon groups developed the notion of “wergeld,” a monetary payment compensating for
lives taken. In the ancient Near East, however, the idea that murderers must forfeit their
lives remained central. Witness the Hebrew Bible.
One Thing after Another? 141
lennia on, we may demur at the thought that this is the final word on the
matter, but it is hard to resist seeing the change as an improvement. We
envisage cases (the overwhelming majority?) in which the correspond-
ing relative knew nothing of the crime, cases where he or she was a child
or even a friend who mourns the victim. However that may be, if the rela-
tive was not involved in the killing, justice miscarries if the relative loses
his or her own life while the murderous relation goes free. Even if the
perpetrator is punished “through him or her,” that fails to support the
practice, for the relative cannot be treated as part of the machinery of
punishment, as if his or her life were not important to him or her as well
as to the perpetrator. When societies go after the criminal directly,
how can it not be a progressive step?
Great myths and poetry of early civilizations celebrate figures whose
recorded deeds express their devotion to an ideal of honor and greatness
overriding considerations that move later ethicists. Prominent examples
are Homeric heroes.6 We do not need to know if the Iliad has a historical
basis; the crucial question is whether the ethical attitudes expressed are
those prevalent in some Homeric past. One basis for supposing they are
is the improbability of oral presentations of a clearly defined ethical per-
spective, popular across many generations, if the ethical ideas failed to
reflect the actual outlook of the audience (or an audience hearers could
identify as part of their history).
One shift in the period between Homer and Solon replaced the em-
phasis on personal honor as the principal ethical end with the idea of
a contribution to the common good.7 The Homeric hero’s wartime life
was directed toward acquiring personal glory; his prowess might be
embodied in trophies (often given away in acts that simultaneously
marked the hero’s generosity and his previous exploits).8 To appreciate
6. Others include the noble warriors from German, Norse, and Japa nese traditions.
7. This is by no means the end of the idea of honor in Western ethical traditions. The
concept recurs again and again, in chivalric codes in the Middle Ages, in illuminating pas-
sages in Shakespearean plays, in standards for eighteenth-century gentlemen and ladies, in
the military ideals of affluent nations in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries.
8. For clear presentations of the central features of the heroic code, see Walter Donlan,
The Aristocratic Ideal in Ancient Greece (Lawrence, KS: Coronado Press, 1980), chap. 1;
Moses Finley, World of Odysseus (Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin, 1980); chap. 5; and Joseph
142 the ethica l project
the transition, juxtapose a passage from the Iliad with Thucydides’ later
“account” of Pericles’ funeral oration.9 Hector responds to various pleas
not to engage Achilles in single combat by affirming the demands of
honor. He knows his death would spell disaster for his city (and his fam-
ily), but he cannot accept the dishonor resulting from refusing the chal-
lenge.10 By contrast, when we read Thucydides’ “Pericles,” the common
good comes first. “Pericles” says of the fallen:
These words are meant to honor a group, not an individual, and they do
so by highlighting individual devotion to the good of the group.
Between the time recorded in the Iliad and the events commemorated
by Thucydides, Greek warfare had changed profoundly. Military ac-
tions were now dominated by the orga nization of armed troops into
the phalanx. (Men bearing heavy armor and a large shield were arrayed
shoulder to shoulder and marched forward together, presenting long
spears.) Success in battle depended no longer on the strength, endurance,
and skill of an outstanding individual—an Achilles, a Hector—but on
disciplined maintenance of one’s place in the line. Conduct routine in
the Iliad—Achilles’ refusal to participate, Hector’s rejection of the
counsels of prudence, Diomedes’ private treaty with his guest-relative
Glaukus—now appears selfish, irresponsible, capricious, and quirky.
The predominance of honor gave way to the virtues of moderation, self-
discipline, and loyalty.
Bryant, Moral Codes and Social Structure in Ancient Greece (Albany: State University of
New York Press, 1996), chap. 2.
9. Thucydides clearly warns that he reconstructs speeches by combining the sense of
what was said with the thrust of what it would have been appropriate to say (Peloponnesian
War [Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin Classics, 1972], 47).
10. See Finley, World of Odysseus, 115–17, for an excellent discussion of this episode.
11. Thucydides, Peloponnesian War, 148.
One Thing after Another? 143
12. Here it is worth recalling Mill’s insight that attention to the consequences does not
rule out self-sacrifice but simply demands that the sacrifice be worth something (John Stu-
art Mill, Works, Vol. 10 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1970), 217).
13. W. E. H. Lecky, History of European Morals from Augustus to Charlemagne (New
York: Braziller, 1955), 1:110. For Lecky’s advocacy of the idea of ethical progress, see also
vol. 1, 100–103, 147–50; vol. 2, 8–11, 73–75. The apparent relativism of Lecky’s formulation
is misleading rhetoric: he does not literally think that what is right (or wrong) has changed,
but that what is taken to be right (or wrong) is altered. This is plain from his confidence in
the Victorian values that have emerged.
144 the ethica l project
14. For an insightful discussion of issues about slavery, see Moses Finley, Ancient Slav-
ery and Modern Ideology (London: Chatto and Windus, 1980). Historians from Gibbon on
have noted the savagery of the confl icts among early Christian sects. A lucid account of the
Crusades is offered by Steven Runciman, A History of the Crusades, 3 vols. (New York:
Harper and Row, 1964–1967), see esp. his narrative of the massacres that attended the “tri-
umph of the cross” in Jerusalem, 1:286ff.).
15. As §18 noted, this theme is anticipated in Mesopotamian texts predating the Gospels
(see n. 20).
16. See Matthew 10:34–39 (also Luke 12:49–53), Matthew 18:21, and Acts 5:1–11.
17. I characterize the ideal in terms of preferences rather than interests because a Chris-
tian formulation in terms of interests would adopt a very special notion of the interests of
individuals, one that does not obviously translate into a judgment that the ideal would
mark a direction of ethical progress.
One Thing after Another? 145
18. The expansion of altruism in this way is hardly the exclusive province of Christian-
ity. As noted, the injunction to love and forgiveness, even toward enemies, appears in Baby-
lonian literature several centuries before Jesus, and the ancient world contained groups of
non-Christians (for example, Jews and Stoics) whose ethical codes extended the altruism
of prior traditions.
146 the ethica l project
19. The writings of Catherine MacKinnon serve as important reminders of what a sig-
nificant number of women (as well as some men) think remains to be done; see her Femi-
nism Unmodified (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987) and Towards a Femi-
nist Theory of the State (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989).
20. See J. Morrill, ed., The Oxford Illustrated History of Tudor and Stuart Britain
(New York: Oxford University Press, 2001), 97, for the account of Sir Edward Coke’s coer-
cion of his daughter; George Walker, although a Quaker, was given custody of his children,
despite the fact that his ex-wife, Ann, was Anglican—the law of Virginia ranked patriarchy
ahead of orthodoxy (see Julia Cherry Spruill, Women’s Life and Work in the Southern Colo-
nies [New York: Norton, 1972], 345); in 1889, Charlotte Angas Scott, a student at Girton,
obtained the highest score in the Mathematics Tripos at Cambridge, although she was not
able officially to register for a degree.
21. Many people would view the impact of women on life in the professions from which
they were so long excluded as a good thing. Within academic discussions, for example, in-
One Thing after Another? 147
and some view the second as more controversial. I take both as instances
of ethical progress.
How were the advances made? In the ancient examples it is impossi-
ble to identify psychological processes through which individuals, or
groups, made ethical discoveries. Here, however, there is material to
which investigators can turn in hopes of picking out the new perception
or new piece of reasoning that fueled ethical evolution. A sequence of texts,
retrospectively inspiring, leads from the writings of Mary Wollstonecraft
at the end of the eighteenth century, to the documents of the nineteenth-
century American feminist movement, to the classic essay co-authored
by John Stuart Mill and Harriet Taylor, to the fiction of Charlotte
Perkins Gilman and the social commentary of Virginia Woolf, to Sim-
one de Beauvoir, to Betty Friedan, Catherine MacKinnon, and their
successors.22
As with scientific revolutions, the triumph of a radically different per-
spective proves far more complex than might have been supposed.23
Once the revolution is over, the confident insistence on male privilege
seems monstrous in its blindness. How could Sir Edward Coke have tied
his daughter to that bedpost, or Sophie Jex-Blake’s father have hampered
clusion of women has sometimes fostered a more cooperative approach to research, and
established this as a rival model for the aggression of male-male competition.
22. Wollstonecraft, A Vindication of the Rights of Woman (New York: Modern Library,
2001); Alice Rossi, ed., The Feminist Papers (New York: Bantam, 1977); John Stuart Mill
(and Harriet Taylor, whom I include as coauthor here), On The Subjection of Women in Mill
On Liberty and Other Essays [Oxford: Oxford University Press (World’s Classics), 1998];
Charlotte Perkins Gilman, Herland (New York: Pantheon, 1979), and The Yellow Wallpa-
per (New York: Routledge, 2004); Virginia Woolf, A Room of One’s Own (New York: Har-
court, 1957); Simone de Beauvoir, The Second Sex (New York: Vintage, 1974); Betty
Friedan, The Feminine Mystique (New York: Norton, 1963); Germaine Greer, The Female
Eunuch (New York: Bantam, 1972); Catherine MacKinnon, Feminism Unmodified (Cam-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987), and Towards a Feminist Theory of the State
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989); Donna Haraway, Simians, Cyborgs
and Women (New York: Routledge, 1991); and bell hooks, Ain’t I a Woman (Boston: South
End Press, 1981). Although I mainly focus on Anglophone texts, there are many other im-
portant sources—for example, the response of Olympe de Gouges to the Declaration of the
Rights of Man and the Citizen, produced by the (male) leaders of the French Revolution.
23. The intricacies Kuhn discerned in major scientific debates (The Structure of Scien-
tific Revolutions [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962]) are even more apparent in
the ethical case.
148 the ethica l project
24. Late in Vindication, in chap. 9, Wollstonecraft does venture a little further, advert-
ing to the possibility that women may do some kinds of work (“keeping a little shop,” par-
ticipating in medical care). I read this as a clever signal to sympathetic readers (the ones
who have come this far with her), to the effect that the changes for which she officially cam-
paigns are only beginnings.
150 the ethica l project
central to their lives, to “find their own good in their own way.”25 They
call for social experimentation, both as a means for providing the young
with potential models from which they can assemble their individual
conceptions of how to live, and as the proper expression of what people
want, not to be confined unless it does harm to others.26 Later, when the
desires of educated women to participate in public life—and, in some
cases, to change the character of public life—have become even more
widespread, Woolf documents the ways in which those desires continue
to be resisted.27
Why does confinement continue? Woolf’s own quotations from the
oppressive men who rein in their daughters reveal the structure of con-
servative thought. Suppose the step recommended by Wollstonecraft is
taken: a society of educated women contains wives and mothers who
discharge their roles with unprecedented success. Not only would broad-
ening the activities of educated women require new arguments, but, ac-
cording to the case already made for educating women, it would likely be
counterproductive. If the emphasis is firmly on improving the conduct
of wives and mothers, pitching women into the public world appears a
bad idea, one likely to produce weakened marriages and neglected chil-
dren. Conservatives protest the Millian insistence on the primary value of
individual development, on formulating freely one’s own plan of life—by
appealing to higher, divinely prescribed, goals for human existence, by
emphasizing the health and flourishing of individuals or of society—but
they can even adapt their reasoning to the framework their opponents take
for granted. Desires are to be honored only if they do no harm to others.
If women are given access to public life, they will do harm—their hus-
bands and children will suffer. Women’s desires for time-consuming ca-
reers, for prominent positions in society, are viewed as altruism failures.
25. See John Stuart Mill, On Liberty[Oxford: Oxford University Press (World’s Clas-
sics), 1998], chap. 1.
26. John Stuart Mill, On the Subjection; plainly the essay reinforces and is reinforced by
the central ideas of On Liberty.
27. Virginia Woolf, A Room of One’s Own (New York: Harcourt, 1957), and especially
Three Guineas (San Diego: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1966). A crucial move in the latter
is the suggestion that public life be transformed by the pressure of women who form a “so-
ciety of outsiders.”
One Thing after Another? 151
28. Arguments of this kind survive into the present. Their persistence is a product of
the continued inability to solve broader problems about the provision of public goods and
the education of the young. Resolution is hard because the issues are so entangled. See
Chapter 10 (§60).
29. The line of reasoning attributed to conservatives here is still present in many societ-
ies, and in many corners of societies that officially endorse women’s entitlement to seek
demanding careers. Because the problem of combining work and family life remains un-
solved, for a large number of women and for a smaller number of men, issues about refram-
ing the institution of marriage remain. These combine with other questions about the
forms of the division of labor in contemporary societies, about the pressures that division
of labor exerts, about the distribution of resources, and about the provision of public
152 the ethica l project
goods. The resultant entanglements make debates among conservatives and reformers
even harder to resolve. Where women’s lives are able to combine demanding work and fam-
ily most smoothly, this is frequently achieved at the cost of deferring the burden to other
women whose choices are far more restricted (women of lower socioeconomic status who
serve as caregivers or housekeepers). Wollstonecraft’s assumption of the presence of ser-
vants in the domestic arrangements she envisages is not quite the anachronism it initially
appears—nor is Woolf’s reliance on the idea that someone else will do the shopping and the
cooking. (I am indebted to Martha Howell for presentations on Wollstonecraft that have
helped me to see these aspects of her problem more clearly.)
One Thing after Another? 153
30. The “more or less” enters here as a reminder of the difficulties already remarked (n.
29), of the fact that special social circumstances are needed for the combination to work
smoothly. See §60.
31. I think it can be opposed only by arguing that the notion of ethical progress cannot
be given a clear sense. I am grateful to Edie Jeff rey for reinforcing my conviction that this
example is indispensable for any account of ethical progress, and for giving me good advice
about how to investigate it.
154 the ethica l project
32. In The Problem of Slavery in Western Culture (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press,
1966), David Brion Davis provides an illuminating account of all these apologist strategies
and their relationship to ancient and medieval thought.
33. John Saffi n, “A Brief Candid Answer to a Late Printed Sheet Entitled The Selling of
Joseph” (1701), in Against Slavery: An Abolitionist Reader, ed., M. Lowance (New York:
Penguin, 2000), 16.
One Thing after Another? 155
The State of your Negroes in the World, must be low, and mean, and
abject; a State of servitude. No Great Things in this World, can be
done for them. Something, then, let there be done, towards their
welfare in the World to Come. . . . Every one of us shall give account
of himself to God 34
34. Cotton Mather, “The Negro Christianized: An Essay to Excite and Assist That Good
Work, Instruction of Negro-Servants in Christianity,” in Lowance, Against Slavery, 19.
35. Davis, Problem of Slavery, 218; see also 211–22.
36. Lowance, Against Slavery, 17.
37. See Mary Eastman, Aunt Phillis’ Cabin: Or Southern Life As It Is, excerpted in Low-
ance, Against Slavery, 296–300.
38. See Charles Montesquieu, Spirit of the Laws (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1989), for Montesquieu’s famous remark that Africans cannot be humans
156 the ethica l project
because if they were it would follow that we (Europeans) are not Christians. His ironies
were unappreciated. For some uncomprehending reactions to Montesquieu, see Davis,
Problem of Slavery, 403. It is also worth noting that one of Montesquieu’s most important
arguments against slavery imagines that the roles of slaves and masters are determined by
lot; for what seems to be an anticipation of Rawlsian appeals to ignorance of social position,
see the addenda to Spirit of the Laws.
39. Arthur Lee, An Essay in Vindication of the Continental Colonies in America, from a
Censure of Mr. Adam Smith in his “Theory of Moral Sentiments” (“Printed for the author”
London, 1764).
One Thing after Another? 157
40. Thomas Jefferson, Notes on the State of Virginia, in The Portable Thomas Jefferson,
ed. Merrill D. Peterson (New York: Penguin, 1975), 186ff. It is interesting to ask how the
man who wrote these words conceived his relationship with Sally Hemmings.
41. Cited in the “General Introduction,” to Lowance, Against Slavery, xxiv. Perhaps, as
the editor notes (xxv), Lincoln was simply bowing to political pressure.
42. The writings and speeches of Frederick Douglass are notable examples of this
last strategy. In his “General Introduction” to Against Slavery, Mason Lowance tells an
158 the ethica l project
interesting story of one of Douglass’s presentations: “Once during the opening moments of
a lecture in London, an audience expressed hostile disbelief in his past as a chattel slave
because his oratory and elocution were so powerful. (It was well-known that slaves were
held in illiteracy and ignorance as a means of control.) Without speaking another word,
Douglass promptly stripped off his shirt and turned his fl ayed back to the incredulous
audience to show the scars of his floggings” (Against Slavery, xxx).
43. Excerpts from Some Considerations appear in Lowance, Against Slavery, 22–24; see
also John Woolman’s Journal (New York: Citadel, 1961).
One Thing after Another? 159
never seems to have been some perception of the ethical standing, the
worth of the slaves; what troubled Woolman was the conflict between
the institution and his Christian duty.
The early pages of the Journal explain how the sixteen-year-old Wool-
man “began to love wanton company,” how a period of self-indulgence
was punctuated by ever-longer intervals of remorse, and how eventually
he “recovered” and came back to “live under the cross”.44 As his own
ability to resist temptations increased, he began to be troubled by the
backslidings of others, and to be “uneasy” when he did not remonstrate
with them; uncharitably, we might describe the twenty-three-year-old as
a bit of a busybody. The first (mentioned) concern about slavery arose
when he was asked to perform a task:
behavior and capacities, one that might persuade others to see them as
people. Similarly, the concern with his own spiritual standing, evident
in the hesitations over the bill of sale, is omnipresent. When he discloses
his discomfort, to his master and the purchaser (and to his readers), he
claims an inconsistency between Christianity and slavery. The nature of
that inconsistency is alluded to by the characterization of the woman as
a “fellow creature.”
What led Woolman to draw up the document? He clearly saw it as an
action commended by his duty of obedience (the Christian servant obeys
his Christian master), and yet he knew slaves often suffer (that was surely
the initial cause of his “trouble”). He temporarily suppressed doubts—
the buyer was elderly and a Friend, qualities likely to prevent sexual and
other forms of abuse. As he reflected, however, he recognized his par-
ticipation in an institution prone to inflict suffering on “fellow-creatures,”
and, although the chances of serious abuse in this case seemed remote,
they were not zero. Once the document had been signed and the woman
“conveyed,” there was no guarantee she would not be maltreated. He
would have been partly responsible.
Perhaps I overinterpret the passage. But this reading accords with
Woolman’s subsequent discussions of his growing opposition to slavery.
He is constantly concerned that he is infected by living among those who
support themselves by slavery—interested, too, in saving them from cor-
ruption.47 At times the spiritual plight of slave owners troubles him, and
his reprimands have the character of the sober young man who inter-
vened to save his acquaintances from “wantonness.” Moreover, more thor-
oughly than his predecessors, he takes seriously the Christian apology for
slavery, quoting scripture to rebut the characterization of slaves as inherit-
ing the curse laid upon Ham, and urging priority for the official aim of
redeeming these “lost people”:
as inflicted on real people. Finally, the men and women routinely bought
and sold are no longer anonymous, no longer undifferentiated “fellow
creatures,” but fully, individually, and equally, human.
similar people for whom all these problems are overcome. It is hard not
to view that as ethical progress.
From an older perspective, one still surviving in some societies and in
some groups even within countries that have made the transition, any
tolerance of “deviant” sexuality is a sign of corruption, a mark of ethical
decay. That perspective relies on two major claims, emphasized differ-
ently in different versions. First, homosexual desires are genuinely devi-
ant, unhealthy eruptions within degenerate people, who should be en-
couraged to suppress them in favor of more salubrious (heterosexual)
inclinations. Second, these desires—or, at least, the expression of them
in homosexual behavior—are forbidden by divine command. Accepting
same-sex preference rests upon establishing facts about the prevalence
of homosexual desires and about the consequences of expressing them,
as well as undermining the thought that satisfaction of these desires is
forbidden by the deity.
As in the case of women’s aspirations, discussed in §24, the normality
of the desires is difficult to recognize in a society where they are seen as
deviant. When homosexual acts count as a form of vice, when those who
engage in them are reviled, mocked, and even prosecuted, the society
will lack reliable statistics about same-sex desires and their behavioral
expression. There will be little public knowledge of the character and
consequences of homosexual relationships. Finally, those relationships
will be profoundly and adversely affected by pressures to keep them hid-
den: not only will men and women struggle to find ways of meeting po-
tential partners, forced to seek love furtively in squalid places, but they
are also likely to absorb the social condemnation of what they do, feeling
shame and guilt even while they achieve some temporary satisfaction.
All this supports a public image of homosexual activity as infrequent,
deviant, insalubrious, and stripped of all positive traits associated with
the expression of love.
In part, this picture was rectified through the scientific study of sex-
ual behavior, from sexologists of the late nineteenth century to psycholo-
gists and sociologists of later decades.50 Whether or not its methods and
50. Even studies of sexual behavior that regard homosexuality as defective can play a
liberating role—just as Wollstonecraft’s apparently limited plea for female education
opened the way to broader expression of women’s aspirations. Freud’s recognition of
164 the ethica l project
data were completely reliable, Kinsey’s famous report played a large part
in undermining the repudiation of homosexuality as deviant.51 If men
and women were engaging in homosexual contact at the rates Kinsey
claimed, the effects of the behavior could hardly be so terrible.
Also important was a related shift in ethical practice, acceptance of
the wrongness of treating private consensual homosexual acts as crimi-
nal offenses. Against the background assumption that the law should
intervene only to prevent conduct causing harm to others, increased
understanding of facts about homosexuality induced many countries
to repeal their (frequently harsh) statutes.52 These legal steps neither
modified the common evaluation of homosexual acts as immoral (as
vice) nor removed the stigma associated with homosexuality. 53 To de-
clare oneself a homosexual was an act of great bravery when same-sex
acts were criminal, and it continued to require courage even after le-
galization, when “only” scorn and derision remained. Coming out was
still hard to do.
Yet, just as consciousness-raising was crucial to full public recogni-
tion of the prevalence and extent of women’s aspirations for public
roles, so acts of coming out presented a different picture of homosexual-
ity. Individuals who had previously seemed “normal” and “respectable”
suddenly exposed the “darkness” and “squalor” of their private lives.
widespread homosexual wishes, even though associating them with incomplete develop-
ment, modified prevailing ideas about their frequency.
51. Alfred C. Kinsey, Wardell B. Pomeroy, and Clyde E. Martin, Sexual Behavior in the
Human Male (Philadelphia: W.B. Saunders, 1948); Staff of the Institute for Sex Research,
Indiana University, Alfred C. Kinsey, Wardell B. Pomeroy, Clyde E. Martin, and Paul H.
Gebhard, Sexual Behavior in the Human Female (Philadelphia: W.B. Saunders, 1953);
E. O. Laumann, John H. Gagnon, Robert T. Michael, and Stuart Michaels, The Social Or-
ganization of Sexuality (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994).
52. This depends on a prior ethical shift, adoption of the Millian conception of law
(classically expressed in On Liberty). During the 1960s and 1970s, that conception com-
bined with increased factual knowledge to produce a cascade of liberalizing reforms in
European countries and in some parts of North America (Canada and some states in the
United States, with Illinois leading the way). Denmark (1933) had taken the step much
earlier, and, interestingly, the focus on the private may have inspired France (which had no
antihomosexuality law) to institute a law against public displays of homosexual affection.
53. As Mill so clearly sees (in On Liberty) the effects of social stigma can be just as con-
fi ning as those of the criminal law.
One Thing after Another? 165
54. This transition can be traced in newspaper responses to the nascent Gay Pride
movement; see in particu lar the reports in the New York Times, in the immediate aftermath
of Stonewall and in subsequent years.
166 the ethica l project
55. I simplify. Some religions suppose transcendent beings are impersonal and lack
wills. In these instances, one should speak of prescriptions to “align” oneself with the tran-
scendent forces. Adopting more circumspect language here would be clumsy and obscure
the lines of argument.
56. In Plato’s Euthyphro, the divine source is represented as plural— ethics is a matter of
what the gods love—and Socrates has a preliminary bout with Euthyphro in which he takes
advantage of the possibility of the gods having divergent tastes. This is a flourish on the
main line of reasoning.
57. Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, a good English translation is that of
Mary Gregor (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998) (Akademie pagination 408).
One Thing after Another? 167
58. Leviticus 18 and 20 suggest different punishments for the “lying together.” Simi-
larly, there are variations in what Canaanites are to expect, although, at best, only the
young women will survive.
168 the ethica l project
59. See a posthumous essay of David Lewis, “Divine Evil” (in Philosophers without
Gods, ed. Louise Antony [New York: Oxford University Press, 2007]; I completed this es-
say from an outline left by Lewis at his untimely death). The essay considers various pos-
sible ways for Christians to avoid supposing their God causes suffering on an infi nitely
vaster scale than any of the world’s most celebrated human evildoers.
One Thing after Another? 169
other than the will of some greater being? Abstract philosophical sub-
stitutes are hard to grasp, or to fit to prominent examples of ethical
advance.60 So, for all its fl aws, the picture of the divine commander
survives.
Understanding the ethical project, its origins, its evolution, and the
historical episodes supporting a conception of ethical progress can free
us from the choice between unconvincing philosophical abstractions
and problematic religious foundations. Showing that will be the work of
the rest of this book.
60. The next chapter will defend this claim. I suspect that many people have an incho-
ate appreciation of it.
pa rt t wo
A Metaethical Perspective
chapter 5
173
174 the ethica l project
1. Even Lecky’s (Victorian) study of a long period in the history of ethics concentrates
more on theoretical ideas than on the actual practices of groups of people. For the ancient
world, the writings of Kenneth Dover (Greek Popular Morality in the Time of Plato and
Aristotle [Oxford: Blackwell, 1974] and Greek Homosexuality [Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1978]); Moses Finley (World of Odysseus [New York: Viking, 1978]); Wal-
ter Donlan (The Aristocratic Ideal in Ancient Greece [Lawrence, KS: Coronado Press,
1980]); and Joseph Bryant (Moral Codes and Social Structure in Ancient Greece [Albany:
State University of New York Press, 1996]) point in appropriate directions, as do the dis-
cussions of Peter Brown, The Body and Society (New York: Columbia University Press,
1988) and Jerome Carcopino, Daily Life in Ancient Rome (New Haven: Yale University
Press, 2003), on the Roman world. I know of no sources for other places and later periods
(collectively) as good in elaborating the ethical lives of ordinary citizens. Many historical
works offer particu lar insights, but, without a focus on transitions in practice, ethical
change is hard to study seriously. Hence my (amateur) efforts in the previous chapter.
Troubles with Truth 175
agree in repudiating chattel slavery. They are repelled by the buying and
selling, the harsh treatment, the division of families. Because they judge
ethical progress to have been made when slavery was abolished, they do
not want to go back.2 When they contemplate the world before the rein-
troduction of slavery and the world after slavery returned, they prefer
the earlier state to the later (in this respect, at least).
A first, very simple, subjective criterion for progress can be based on
these reactions: a change in an ethical code is progressive just in case
those who live after the change prefer life in the later world to life in the
earlier one. Is the subjective criterion adequate as an account of ethical
progress? There are ample reasons to worry. Desires expressed in attri-
butions of ethical progress are purely contingent. Were the individuals
who make these judgments to be placed within a rival tradition, one
making different transitions in ethical practice (typically transitions run-
ning counter to those actually preferred), they would be likely to en-
dorse incompatible judgments of progressiveness.3 Human beings may
be malleable enough to be brought—by the right, or the wrong, systems
of training—to issue radically different verdicts on the same situations.
Even when many different traditions agree in their modifications of ethi-
cal practice and retrospective endorsements, history might easily have
gone differently, so consensus judgment is thoroughly contingent.
The skeptic issues a challenge: “You can call this ‘progress’ if you
like, but this is no more than a way of comforting yourself; you have
socially shaped preferences for the kind of life you now lead, in contrast
to the lives your forebears led; you dignify these preferences with a label,
but it is nothing more than an honorary title, masking the contingencies
of the events and of your retrospective judgments.” If things are as the
challenger says, there are two possibilities. Either nothing more can be
done to elaborate or defend the subjective criterion, and it is useless for
2. Or, at least, without the publicly tolerated institution of the seventeenth and eigh-
teenth centuries. They may also be indignant about contemporary practices (illegal prac-
tices) of human trafficking—and believe that stronger measures, both legal and ethical, are
needed to combat them.
3. In fact, actual people who lived through progressive transitions made incompati-
ble assessments. Not all those who lived through emancipation preferred the world it
produced.
176 the ethica l project
4. Here, there are obvious connections with ideas of classical pragmatism, specifically
to the account of truth often attributed to Peirce in Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel,
eds., The Essential Peirce, vol. 1 (Bloomington: University of Indiana Press, 109–123) and
apparently also present in James. In the ethical context, the idea surfaces in Jamesian refer-
ences to “the last word of the last man.” William James, “The Moral Phi losophers and the
Moral Life,” in The Will to Believe and Other Essays (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1979).
Troubles with Truth 177
cal practices needs explanation. Should this notion be tied to the actual
course of human history, or should it be understood in terms of some
idealization of our future? The actual past includes occasions on which
apparently progressive ethical transitions have been reversed—for ex-
ample, episodes in which par tic u lar groups have been protected by
the ethical code, only later to be excluded again. To judge the inclusions
as progressive is to diagnose the reversals as events of terrible social
blindness. At some periods in human history, people—socially blinded
people—have preferred to live in a world produced by a regressive transi-
tion, and there are potential causes that induce social blindness in any
group. What guarantees the absence of these causes in the limit of the
extension of our ethical practices? Understanding the criterion in terms
of the actual course of human history, it cannot be expected to judge
progress correctly.
Again, there is an obvious remedy. Require the preferences to be sta-
ble, in the limit, in a history that proceeds under “ideal” conditions: a
transition within ethical practice is progressive if and only if, in a future
proceeding from the transition and modifying practice under ideal con-
ditions, there is a stage after which the preference for life after the transi-
tion is never reversed. This version is superior to any previously consid-
ered, but it contains, at its core, an unexplained notion, that of the ideal
conditions these futures must satisfy. The ideal conditions depend on
certain kinds of perturbing forces being absent, the variety of causes
producing the forms of blindness of our ethical past. Historians are di-
vided on how to account for socially induced ethical blindness, even in
the most well-studied episodes.5 Because we understand so little of ear-
lier modifications in ethical practices, let alone the potential causes of re-
gressive steps in it, the causal factors diverting the past course of ethical
evolution from the ideal state cannot be specified. Nor can we hope to
identify further factors possibly affecting our descendants. Our only
purchase on the idea of the ideal unfolding of ethical practice is through
5. There is a large and sophisticated literature devoted to questions about how German
citizens could have avoided seeing what was done to the “outcasts” under the Nazi regime,
but it is hard to draw from it any defi nite cata log of all the perturbing forces potentially at
work.
178 the ethica l project
the distortion of human preferences: the perturbing forces are just those
leading people to prefer to live in the world produced by a regressive
transition. That specification of the “perturbing forces” would make the
subjective criterion quite hopeless. Transitions count as progressive just
in case the worlds they produce are preferred by people unperturbed by
forces generating misjudgments about progressiveness.
Even in its best version, the subjective criterion is not good enough. It
reduces to banal circularity. Furthermore, it introduces epistemological
problems. We judge the transitions of the last chapter as progressive. Are
we committed to a prediction about the future course of ethical evolu-
tion, actual or ideal? If progress was made, preferences for life after
slavery or life with greater female equality will be shared by our descen-
dants—so long as they are not “improperly swayed” by unspecifiable
forces. How can we assess that? The judgments of progress are grounded
in aspects of the episodes themselves, not because we anticipate the
eventual stability of human desires (assuming no “perturbations”). Any
confidence we have about the future, if it proceeds “properly,” rests on
thinking there is something about the transition to which people who
come after us will continue to respond (insofar as their vision is not dis-
torted). Their desires, like ours, are secondary, symptoms of the pro-
gressiveness of the transitions, not constitutive of it.
straints play a role in the larger changes of the Paleolithic and early Neo-
lithic? I offer blunt answers, to be defended more carefully in this and
the two following sections: the transitions recorded in the historical
record, as well as those hypothesized for the prehistoric past, are best
conceived as “local adaptations,” not episodes of ethical discovery.6 The
changes appear to be responses to difficulties of the social situations in
which individuals and groups find themselves. “Moments of ethical in-
sight” are elusive. My first aim is to show these answers to be prima facie
plausible.
The historical figures who figure in ethical transitions, the vast ma-
jority of them unidentifiable as individuals, do not start from some situ-
ation in which they lack ethical convictions, follow a process of reason-
ing or observe some facet of reality, and thereby arrive at a well-grounded
belief in an ethical judgment. Actual historical agents (and their prehis-
toric counterparts) were born into societies and socialized from early
childhood. They acquired practices of expressing ethical evaluations,
an extensive repertoire of ethical concepts, and dispositions to accept a
body of ethical statements, most of which they never questioned. For
the revisionary historical actors who stand out relatively clearly—Mary
Wollstonecraft, John Woolman—what occurs is a change in ethical con-
viction: ethical beliefs transmitted within the society and shared by ev-
erybody around are rejected in favor of claims incompatible with them.
The psychological processes these people seem to undergo differ rad-
ically from the forms of evidence conjured in typical philosophical
accounts of ethical justification. There are no special abstract forms of
reasoning, nothing reported as a moment of “perception” or “intuition.”
Reformers take up the ethical project as framed in their culture, making
proposals on the basis of empirical information they find salient.7 In light
of the background ethical views inculcated in the society, women act
well by performing particular tasks as wives and mothers, while black
6. Here I recapitulate themes presented in a pregnant passage from John Dewey, Hu-
man Nature and Conduct (Amherst NY: Prometheus Books, 2002) 103.
7. Their justificatory achievements and the limits of what they can support will become
fully clear only after the account of ethical method in Chapter 9. For the time being,
though, I emphasize only the differences from the views of those who treat ethics in terms
of conformity to external constraints.
180 the ethica l project
8. Here the loci classici are Thomas S. Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chi-
cago: University of Chicago Press, 1962 and 1970) and N. R. Hanson, Patterns of Discovery
(Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1958). The example of the pendulum is
Kuhn’s, and seems to me one in which his invocation of a “gestalt switch” is most
convincing.
Troubles with Truth 181
9. This position has been most clearly and precisely articulated by Nicholas Sturgeon;
particularly valuable is his exchange with Gilbert Harman. See Nicholas Sturgeon, “Moral
Explanations,” in Morality, Reason, and Truth, ed. David Copp and Dean Zimmerman
(Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 1985), and Gilbert Harman, “Moral Explanations
of Natural Facts,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 24 (1986): 57– 68. In the following text,
I use an example extensively discussed in this exchange.
182 the ethica l project
10. In the version where your evaluation depends on appreciating your own emotional
response, there is an intermediate step, but the process from perception to judgment re-
mains relatively direct.
Troubles with Truth 183
subatomic world, and so on. The history is long and complex, but our
confidence in the quick judgments of the technicians who observe tracks
in bubble chambers would be radically undermined if we thought it
could not be told.11
Back to your horrified witnessing of the tortured cat. Like the techni-
cian at the bubble chamber, you make an immediate judgment—“There’s
a positron!,” “That’s wrong!”—and you do so by exercising socially in-
culcated psychological dispositions. To view you in this way is not yet to
cast doubt on the thesis that you are making contact with some external
constraint and thereby arriving at new ethical knowledge. Sustaining
the thesis, however, requires a story about the historical background to
your belief, and to the dispositions (“techniques”) instilled in you, one
similar to the tale told for the detection of the subatomic world. Recon-
structing history requires tracing a justified route—disclosing processes
of reasoning, perception, intuition, or whatever—that led from the stage
at which people looked on at squirming animals with indifference (mak-
ing no ethical judgments about the actions producing the writhings) to
the stage at which the judgments (“That’s wrong!”) became firmly ac-
cepted and the young became socialized to have propensities for making
such judgments.
This particular ethical change did not figure in the catalog of the last
chapter. Its history is obscure—even the epochs and societies within
which it occurred cannot be identified.12 We can, however, consider
ethical revolutions for which we have historical evidence, and inquire
11. Historians and phi losophers of science have paid great attention to this example, so
it is reasonable to claim confidence here. See, for example, the writings of Mary-Jo Nye
(Molecular Reality [London: McDonald, 1972]), Wesley Salmon (Reality and Rationality
[New York: Oxford University Press, 2005]), Ian Hacking (“Do We See Through a Micro-
scope?” in Representing and Intervening [Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press,
1985]), and Peter Achinstein (“Is There a Valid Experimental Argument for Scientific Re-
alism?,” Journal of Philosophy [2002] vol 99 pp. 470–495).
12. I suspect it is very ancient. An obvious conjecture is that it occurred fi rst in connec-
tion with domestic animals—but that is no more than a conjecture. Some thinkers will
maintain, with considerable reason, that the “revolution” of responding to nonhuman
animal suffering is still far from complete. (A classic is Peter Singer, Animal Liberation
[New York: Random House, 1975]). As we shall see, ethical conclusions about nonhuman
animals raise difficulties for my own approach. For discussion, and an attempt at resolu-
tion, see §47.
184 the ethica l project
13. It is also a good case for present purposes because it is one principal defenders of the
idea of contact with external ethical constraints typically cite. Woolman is preeminent
among early abolitionists for explaining the circumstances leading to his new ethical
stance.
Troubles with Truth 185
he ponders what to do—slaves are often beaten, female slaves are often
sexually coerced, concern for the spiritual development of slaves is rare.
He is suddenly asked to do something that makes him, if only tangen-
tially, complicit with these common features of the slave-owning insti-
tution, and, for a young man so sensitive to his spiritual temperature,
even that tangential involvement promotes unease. This psychological
explanation fits the record we have far better than any (nebulous) pro-
cess through which some (mysterious) external constraint manifests
itself.
It is instructive to contrast the historical sources available in the ethi-
cal case with those in another instance in which philosophers want to
explore possibilities of new (disputed) knowledge. In The Varieties of
Religious Experience, William James canvasses the reports of those
who acquired a new belief about “the transcendent,” and his discussion is
fully based on particular episodes in which people “saw” something strik-
ingly new. Whatever scruples we may have about the reliability of the
processes James’s subjects underwent, reports of this kind are, in prin-
ciple, the right kind of material from which a defense of new religious
knowledge might be drawn. Historical documents describe the experi-
ences and their apparent power. In the repudiation of chattel slavery,
records of any similar experiences, moments of sudden revelation, are
entirely absent.
If progressive ethical inquiry increases conformity with external con-
straints, the absence of episodes in which such constraints are recog-
nized, even if only dimly, is thoroughly perplexing. When we reflect on
other examples of ethical revolutions considered in the previous chapter,
there is simply no evidence of times and places at which some sense of
these constraints modified ethical practice, allowing for the institution
of reliable techniques for everyday “observation” (ways of cultivating
psychological dispositions enabling people to “see” particular states and
actions as good or bad, right or wrong). For some transitions, the idea is
absurd. Greek replacement of the ideal of heroic courage with that of
solidarity has far more to do with the technology of fighting than it does
with any moment of insight disclosing the ethical flaws of the Homeric
hero or the virtues of the hoplite. Nobody would insist on moments of
ethical insight, analogs to the scientific observations perturbing preva-
186 the ethica l project
lent ideas about nature, if the grip of a background picture of ethics were
not so powerful as to make it appear that such moments have to have
occurred.
So far, a prima facie challenge for the thesis that ethics is a form of in-
quiry responding to external constraints. Defenders of the thesis must
explain how those external constraints play some substantive role in the
evolution of the ethical project. Otherwise invoking them is idle, a piece
of comforting rhetoric easily excised. Yet the issue should not be left
there, with a pointed invitation to tell a different narrative or to interpret
the history of Part I differently from ways so far suggested. Diagnosis of
the flaws of popular philosophical views is intended to fashion a better
approach to ethical progress. Hence, the problems just posed should be
examined more deeply, to reveal how serious the challenge is.
14. Anthropologists recognize cases in which the name of the group substitutes for the
vocabulary used to recommend or command actions. For the purposes of this chapter, it
does not matter whether the predicates used are “good”/“bad,” or “right”/“wrong,” or
“virtuous”/“vicious,” or even the names applied to a specific group and to those it counts
as outsiders.
Troubles with Truth 187
15. This last possibility would then need to be elaborated with some alternative account
of the external constraints, supplemented with a proposal as to how these constraints are
recognized either by participants in episodes of change or by the clever folk who come later.
16. My The Advancement of Science (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), as cor-
rected by Science, Truth, and Democracy (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001), pro-
vides an approach of this type. Other accounts are possible, for example, approaches con-
ceiving progress as problem solving. Those would be closer to the perspective I shall
eventually take in the ethical case.
Troubles with Truth 189
17. Here I rely on the Tarskian account of the truth of logically simple sentences of first-
order languages (sentences that do not contain connectives or quantifiers). I abstract from
issues about tense.
18. Alfred Tarski “The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages,” in Logic, Seman-
tics, Metamathematics (Oxford University Press, 1956), 152–278; in his important essay
“Tarski’s Theory of Truth,” Journal of Philosophy (1972), Hartry Field shows how Tarski
generates the notion of truth from the notion of reference. The correspondence theory I
espouse does not assume, with Field’s article, that it is possible to reduce the notion of ref-
erence to some physicalist basis. See my essay “On the Explanatory Power of Correspon-
dence Truth,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (2002): 346– 64.
19. There is a line of thought, descending from Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolu-
tions, that denies this claim. For defense, see my The Advancement of Science and Science,
Truth, and Democracy. See also my “Real Realism: The Galilean Strategy,” Philosophical
Review 110 (2001): 151– 97, and “On the Explanatory Power.”
190 the ethica l project
ple and irreducible may turn out to be complex and reducible, however,
not because subsidiary conditions are consciously noted, but because
the explanation of their detection involves unconscious apprehension
of those conditions. If color properties apply to macroscopic objects in
virtue of the disposition of those objects to scatter light of particu lar
wavelengths, our detection of these color properties will be explained in
terms of our ways of responding to the characteristic patterns of scatter-
ing.20 A realist approach to ethical truth may thus suppose the proper-
ties marked out by ethical predicates (“good,” “wrong,” and so forth) are
simple and irreducible or complex and reducible; with respect to the
latter alternative, the subsidiary conditions may be consciously noted, or
unconscious apprehension may play a role in detection.
Much more could be said about these options, but brief explanations
are sufficient for refining the challenge of §29. Consider next the possi-
bilities for constructivism. The very simplest version of a constructivist
approach to ethical truth takes the reference of ethical predicates (“wrong,”
for example) as simply a matter for conventional determination. Any
group, or maybe even any individual, can decide, on any grounds or on
none, to apply the predicate so it picks out any set of objects, states of af-
fairs, or events. This is the Humpty Dumpty theory of ethical truth—with
respect to the key ethical vocabulary, we, collectively or individually, are
always the masters—and it allows any ethical transition whatsoever to be
“progressive” from the viewpoint of those who make it, or, since all can
be assimilated, abandons any contrast between progress and regress. It
capitulates to the mere-change view.
More interesting versions of constructivism suppose there are condi-
tions on the processes through which the reference of ethical predicates
is determined. The set of events marked out as wrong consists of those
events acquiring a special status if particular procedures were followed.
20. I do not suppose this is the correct account of color properties. It is a popu lar one,
and hence useful for introducing an option a realist about ethical truth may try to exploit.
The example may inspire some to retract the supposition that the property of being an ap-
proximately straight line counts as simple and irreducible: perhaps the only such proper-
ties are geometrically more basic, or perhaps there are no such properties at all. I need not
quarrel with such reactions. Since I shall conclude that realist truth about ethics cannot be
sustained in any of its guises, it is best to be inclusive about the possibilities allowed.
192 the ethica l project
So, for example, there might be some form of reasoning each individual
can undergo that divides actions into a number of types; or there might
be some hypothetical social process, in which groups of people can en-
gage, generating distinctions among events; or there might be some ac-
tual social process either generating or revising such distinctions. Kant
and his successors pursue the first option, claiming there are processes
of reason, available to all rational beings whatever their social and physi-
cal environments, yielding conclusions about the status of actions. Social
contract accounts of the traditional kinds develop the second, suggesting
that ethical distinctions among actions derive from the deliberations
people would make under ideal conditions. The third is developed in the
next chapter, and, since the present focus is on rival perspectives, fur-
ther consideration of it is postponed till then.
Both realists and constructivists have several ways of developing the
thesis that ethics is governed by external constraints. All the alternatives
so far reviewed adopt the framework of truth as correspondence. One
rival approach deserves a mention. Instead of considering the structure
of truth, how the truth of statements arises (what makes truths true), one
may adopt a functional account, seeking to understand what we aim at
in various areas of inquiry.21 For descriptive statements about the physi-
cal world, from common sense to refined science, a correspondence ac-
count seems to deliver both structure and function. By contrast, applying
a correspondence theory of truth to mathematics appears problematic,
precisely because it requires us to suppose the existence of a realm of
abstract objects, whose properties are ever-more precisely and more
completely described by the mathematical statements accepted, and be-
cause the ways in which mathematical statements come to be accepted
make it utterly mysterious how mathematicians are gaining access to that
realm. The great figures in the history of the subject, those to whom we
attribute the most significant advances, respond to earlier problems by in-
troducing new notation, often inspired by attempts to carry out symbolic
manipulations on a broader scale. They seem to be expanding the lan-
21. The distinction is drawn in Michael Dummett’s important essay “Truth” (reprinted
in his Truth and Other Enigmas [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978], 1–24).
Dummett does not use the terms I employ to mark the distinction.
Troubles with Truth 193
Debates about borderline cases are irrelevant for present purposes. For
the issues about ethical truth and progress turn on examples where the
distinction between the ethical and the factual is quite uncontroversial:
it is a fact that educated women do certain things; “Slavery is wrong” is
an ethical statement.)
If the denial of fundamental innovations were sustained, realists
could dismiss a large part of the challenge outright, for there would be a
uniform account of progressive ethical transitions. Once the ethical
project was begun, each generation inherited a body of established ethi-
cal beliefs, indeed ethical truths, from which people drew false conse-
quences because the most general and basic ethical truths were con-
joined with incorrect factual statements. Wollstonecraft discerned the
truth about women’s behavior under conditions of education, and Wool-
man recognized the psychological effects (on slaves and slave owners
alike) of chattel slavery. They made ethical progress by replacing false-
hood with truth.
Realists would still have to explain how the entire project was started,
how, in the dim mists of the Paleolithic, small human groups arrived at
all the fundamental concepts and principles required to yield, with dif-
ferent factual premises, the divergent conclusions adopted by rival tradi-
tions at distinct epochs. Although nobody should deny the significance
of new factual knowledge in the progress of our ethical practices, it is
hard to view the proposed story as explaining the entire evolution of
ethics—can we really suppose the origins were ethically rich enough to
allow the explanation envisaged? In denying ethical novelty, the account
assumes a collection of elaborate ethical principles was not only avail-
able for Wollstonecraft and Woolman to work with, but present at the very
beginning. The history of Part I took the initial institution of socially
embedded normative guidance, undertaken in response to the fragile
and tense hominid society it transcended, to be relatively crude and
limited—to comprise principles about sharing and the like. To suppose
ideas about roles, expanded altruism, and the good life were already part
of the Pleistocene package strains credulity. Furthermore, at the dawn
of written history, societies made important transitions not easily assimi-
lated to the story: the refi ned conception of the individual figuring in
the reformulation of the lex talionis, the reshaping of the concept of
courage, the acceptance of the policy of forgiving your enemies.
Troubles with Truth 195
of trade question those views, effectively because they do not find any-
thing strong enough to counterbalance the perceived pain relief and de-
sire satisfaction.
Do the pioneers or their interlocutors have any articulated account of
the good and the right, clearly held in view, an account showing the
exact circumstances under which desire satisfaction and relieving
pain contribute to goodness or rightness? Apparently not. Woolman
and Wollstonecraft are aware of contentions about valuable goals achieved
by permitting the sufferings of slavery and not responding to female de-
mands for education—and they actively and specifically oppose those
contentions. They express their own assessment of what is gained and
what is lost, but they do not operate with any independent understand-
ing of goodness and rightness beyond those available in the formulations
of their opponents. They are catalysts of a renewed social exchange, a
conversation of the sort that initiated the ethical project, and the proper-
ties of goodness or rightness can be seen as fixed through such exchanges.
It is even harder to imagine how the early champion of neighborly exchange
could appeal, either in his own thinking or in his efforts to persuade, to
some reduction of goodness or rightness sanctioning his proposed mod-
ification of the code.
The point can be illuminated by focusing on another example. The
modification of the lex talionis relieves one form of pain but substitutes
another of the same kind: in either version, someone’s life will be trun-
cated. Perhaps that fact is itself ethically problematic, but the substitu-
tion of perpetrator for daughter surely looks like ethical progress. We
know nothing about the people who proposed and argued for the change.
Yet, on the realist account, there must be some connection between facts
about suffering and mortality, and ethical properties, that differentiates
the cases in which daughter and perpetrator suffer and die. If the inno-
vators and those whom they convince are to apprehend the rightness of
making the transition, they have to recognize that connection. How? We
can dimly recognize the form of the explanation realists want, but we
have no idea about how to give it substance. By contrast, it is easy to sup-
pose that the ancient societies in which the transition occurred were en-
gaged in frequent debate, that many voices participated, and that eventu-
ally continuing the old practice became socially problematic. Conversation
198 the ethica l project
within a social group replaces the nebulous contact with some external
standard.
The realism just considered supposes some externally fi xed connec-
tion between the sorts of things ethical innovators apprehend—things
the examples reveal them as recognizing in perfectly straightforward
ways—and fundamental ethical properties. The challenge is to say what
the connection is, to explain how it could be apprehended, and to sup-
port the hypothesis of actual (albeit dim) apprehension. I now turn to
what seems the most promising realist position.
According to that position, ethical properties are conceived by anal-
ogy with colors, and colors identified with dispositional properties of
objects: redness, for example, is a disposition to cause us to enter certain
neuropsychological states (triggered by the impinging on our retinas of
light of particular wavelengths).22 Goodness and badness, rightness and
wrongness, apply to actions (say) in virtue of the tendency of those ac-
tions to generate reactive emotions, feelings of approbation and repug-
nance, for example. A great advantage of this account is its license of
justified ethical assessment without any complicated cognition (backed
by some unspecified process). You see the torturing of the cat, you feel
the repugnance, and your reaction both prompts and justifies your ethi-
cal judgment.
The reactive emotions that figure in this proposal are not merely af-
fective states available to be triggered across a wide range of social envi-
ronments. If they were, it would be impossible to account for the phe-
nomena we are attempting to understand, cases of progressive ethical
change (where in similar environments people react quite differently to
the same events). Instead, the reactive emotions—approbation, gratitude,
resentment, repugnance—involve cognitive and volitional states con-
22. Working out the details of any such account of color properties is itself a large task,
but I shall simply suppose that it can be done. Many contemporary thinkers have been at-
tracted to the thesis that ethical properties of things, states of affairs, actions, and patterns
of behavior can be treated analogously. The version offered by John McDowell (“Values
and Secondary Qualities,” in his Mind, Value, and Reality [Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1998]) is, in my judgment, the best, precisely because it is sensitive to the
thought that the responses in the individual are shaped by the culture in which he or she
grows.
Troubles with Truth 199
nected, in ways nobody yet knows how to specify (§4), with affective
states. What reactive emotions are available to an individual, the extent
to which a person is sensitive to such emotions, and the entities trigger-
ing the emotions are all subject to social shaping (§4).
It is important to appreciate this triple dependence on the environ-
mental conditions, including the social environments, in which we find
ourselves. Features of the ambient environment at the time at which we
encounter some occurrence affect whether we have an emotional reaction
to it, and what form that reaction takes. Features of the developmental en-
vironment, the surroundings in which we learn and grow, shape the ways
in which our emotional reactions are directed. Even more fundamentally,
that developmental environment affects our emotional repertoire. For, al-
though there may be some physiological responses relatively invariant
across regimes of socialization, the emotions pertinent to ethical assess-
ment are more complex than any such affective reactions, having socially
shaped cognitive components. No realist approach to ethical properties
that ignores these three modes of environmental influence can be ade-
quate, for the simple reason that certain types of environments can pro-
duce reactions strikingly at variance with one another. Realists need a
distinction between types of environments, proposing that particular re-
actions of people who have been socialized in normal developmental en-
vironments, and who find themselves in normal ambient environments,
signal the goodness (say) of the states of affairs to which they respond.
A full version of this form of realism has to suppose an external stan-
dard fixing some environments as the pertinent class in which specified
reactive emotions suffice for specified ethical properties—the fact that in
some situations (death camps, the near-starvation conditions of the Ik)
people fail to respond to acts of cruelty does not affect the ethical proper-
ties of those acts. Let us concede that the specification can be provided,
and the realist can even explain why the “normal” environments are
privileged.
Consider, now, the ethical innovator. At last we appear to have an ar-
ticulated, and convincing, account of how that innovator responds to
the external constraints on ethics. An ordinary experience produces a
strong reactive emotion, say, a violent feeling of repugnance against
some form of behavior tolerated by the surrounding community. The
200 the ethica l project
23. The examples I offer here recapitulate the most famous versions of constructivist
approaches, the first evident in Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (Mary
Gregor, trans.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), and the second attribut-
able to Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), and
his successors [most obviously T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1998)]. I do not think any of these constructivists succeeds
in providing a completely clear and precise account of the processes envisaged—Kant’s
critics, for example, have rightly complained that his appeals to “contradictions” and his
implicit restrictions on the types of principles of action (maxims) permitted are vague and
loose. The challenge I am presenting, however, to integrate the account of ethical truth
with the evolution of the ethical project can be more accommodating and can concede to
constructivists successes so far not achieved.
202 the ethica l project
24. I defend this unpopu lar assessment in The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge (New
York: Oxford University Press, 1983), chaps. 1–4.
25. The very simplest versions emerge in the early writings of A. J. Ayer and Charles
Stevenson, although there are previous sources of inspiration in Hume. Both Ayer and
Stevenson articulate the position with increasing sophistication, and there are intricate
debates about the adequacy of the proposed semantic treatment for all contexts. A well-
developed version of the view is provided by Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990).
204 the ethica l project
26. Here I echo the language used by Gibbard, whose version of noncognitivism is the
best I know.
27. Many noncognitivist writings accept the relativist conclusion (or are uninterested in
resisting it). There are hints of a more progressive view in Gibbard’s Wise Choices, but, for
all its attention to many details of noncognitivism, I have not been able to draw from that
work any clear account of ethical progress.
Troubles with Truth 205
28. Most popu lar is “intuition,” a term Frege rightly saw as overused. It stands to Kant’s
credit that he attempted to give the notion of intuition some clear content. See Kitcher,
Nature of Mathematical Knowledge, chap. 3.
206 the ethica l project
the various revolts against it. Detailed biographical research would ex-
plain Moore’s forthright dicta about value—and the attractions his views
held for his contemporaries.
Equally for Kant. His brilliant account of ethics in terms of Pure Prac-
tical Reason can be understood as a reaction to the moral law as com-
manded from on high. Attracted by ideals of autonomy and repelled by
the thought of subjection to a divine commander, Kant solves his con-
flict with a perennially popular account of ethics by placing the lawgiver
within, elaborating his revisionary theory in a framework of powerful—
but purely hypothetical—faculties. Kant can be assimilated to the great
innovators in the history of the ethical project. He responded to the state
of ethical practice he found in the Prussia of his day in an especially in-
genious way, but there is no reason to think he transcends the predica-
ment of his fellow pioneers.
Theorizing about the ethical project has been hampered by assuming
there must be some authority in ethics, some point of view from which
truth can be reliably discerned. Philosophers have cast themselves as
enlightened replacements for the religious teachers who previously pre-
tended to insight. But why credit any individual participant in the project
with such special authority? Ethics may simply be something we work
out together (Chapters 6 and 9). If latecomers improve on previous efforts,
their success might be based, not in occupying some privileged epis-
temic vantage point, but on study of the history of the project as it has led
up to the practices of their day.29
We can now see why attacks on the idea of the divine commander fail
to dislodge the idea (§27). The alternatives seem so mysterious. Ironically,
supposing ethical truths are claims a deity endorses and reveals does
29. Dewey is optimistic that ethics can fi nd its own analog of scientific method [see, for
example, chaps. 10 and 11 of Dewey, The Quest for Certainty, vol. 4 of John Dewey: The
Later Works (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1984)]. I share the hope that
a properly informed understanding of the ethical project and its evolution might lead our
successors to pursue it more sure-footedly. That will depend, however, on more systematic
studies of changes in ethical practice (whose absence I lamented—§28). It would be foolish
to suppose the historical cases inadequately sketched in Part II can do anything more than
reorient discussions of ethics so as to prepare eventually for synthetic understanding and
improved ethical practice.
208 the ethica l project
Possibilities of Progress
1. Here I follow the reliabilism pioneered within epistemology by Alvin Goldman, Epis-
temology and Cognition (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987). There are well-
known problems of saying exactly what kinds of reliability are at stake in securing justifica-
tion or knowledge; these are lucidly presented by Robert Brandom, Articulating Reasons
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000, chap. 3); solving these problems
209
210 the ethica l project
requires pragmatic judgments, dependent on the values endorsed. Those problems will
not be addressed here, since the task is to understand how appeals to truth and justification
in ethics might be reconceived in terms of the notion of ethical progress.
2. The parenthetical characterizations connect the permuted picture with the pragma-
tist tradition, the first with Peirce, C.S. Peirce “The Fixation of Belief” in Nathan Houser
and Christian Kloesel, eds., The Essential Peirce, vol. 1 (Bloomington: University of Indi-
ana Press, 2009) 109–123 the second with James, William James The Meaning of Truth
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978), 169.
Possibilities of Progress 211
saying there are pairs of codes such that the transition in one direction is
progressive (and, in the opposite direction, correspondingly regressive).
Looking at the codes of the past, we are concerned to evaluate them
because of the possibility of going back. Fundamental to our assessment
is the question whether a particular transition, one reversing the actual
course of history, would be progressive. Faced with the codes of actual
rival people, we are interested in possibilities of shifting to their commit-
ments, or of constructing from the elements of their current code and the
elements of ours a new amalgam. We ask whether the change to their code,
or to the amalgam, would be progressive. Similarly for codes we envis-
age. What concerns us is the possibility of a progressive transition.
In fact, it is better to approach these decisions by starting with the no-
tion of progress rather than that of truth. Thinking in terms of truth
narrows the focus. For truth applies to statements, so we are led to con-
ceive the decision as one about descriptive counterparts of rules of the
alternative code. There are other components of ethical codes—concepts,
exemplars, habits, emotions, modes of inducing compliance—and im-
provements to our own practice could occur in each of these respects. A
rival code whose rules agree with ours might do substantially better
at preventing relevant forms of blindness. Thinking in terms of progress
responds more directly to the practical choices we face.
Attending to contexts of comparison, in which issues of progress
arise, poses an obvious question. Is it right to take the overall progres-
siveness of an ethical transition as fundamental, or should we think in-
stead of changes as progressive in particular respects? Historical changes
often seem to involve losses as well as gains. Rejecting the glorification
of the Homeric hero in favor of social solidarity impresses us overall as
progressive, but we may want to concede something to Nietzsche’s nos-
talgia for lost creativity, daring, and freedom. On balance we can talk of a
progressive transition, but that is because we can weigh the relative impor-
tance of the aspects with respect to which progress occurs. So, it might
be suggested, the fundamental notion is that of a transition progressive
in certain respects: judgments of overall progress are made by adding the
weights of the progressive respects and subtracting the weights of the re-
gressive respects. Sometimes the sum can be done, and we can talk con-
fidently of a progressive (or a regressive) transition, but there will be
212 the ethica l project
3. Issues about justification and knowledge, and how these notions apply to historical
actors, will occupy us briefly at the end of this chapter.
4. This is the empiricist strategy pursued by Hume in his second Enquiry [Enquiry
Concerning the Principles of Morals (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1986)], a strategy in accor-
dance with his understanding of Newtonian method. (On this topic, I have been helped by
Matthew Jones.)
214 the ethica l project
these transitions and then declaring any ethical change progressive just
in case it occurs on the list would plainly be unsatisfactory. That would
fail to allow for future progressive transitions. More important, the skep-
tical challenge (§28) would arise again, in the pointed form of asking
why anyone should care about ethical progress, if it is just a matter of
making one of the officially designated transitions. We want an account
of ethical progress isolating common features of the favored transitions,
features revealing why we might be concerned to make ethical changes
of this particular kind.
Chapters 2 and 3 offer only an infinitesimal fragment of the envisaged
list. Yet their constituent examples are often in line with the most popu-
lar idea about ethical progress: insofar as they have attended to ethical
progress, historians and philosophers have singled out a particular kind
of movement as constitutive of advances. They have talked of “the circle
expanding” or “the expanding circle.”5
The proposal is motivated by a striking feature of some progressive
transitions in the history (and prehistory) of ethical practices. In the rel-
atively recent examples of the abolition of slavery and the recognition of
women as equal participants in public life, individuals who had previ-
ously not been brought within the purview and protections of ethical
precepts routinely applied to others (white men) became recognized as
full people, as proper subjects for the application of principles hitherto
applied on a restricted scale. Slave owners were committed to precepts
forbidding certain kinds of behavior toward full people: full people were
not to be permanently separated from their families; they were not to be
bought and sold. Before the ethical change, black men and women did
not count as full people; after it they did, and old proscriptions now
applied to them too.
Earlier examples reinforce the idea. A prominent Gospel message de-
nies that boundaries of aid and compassion embrace only the local group.
Even in prehistory, interaction with other groups, temporary fusion of
5. The former phrase is used by W. E. H. Lecky in his History of European Morals from
Augustus to Charlemagne (New York: Braziller, 1955); the latter is the title of Peter Singer’s
book-length attempt to identify ethical progress, The Expanding Circle (New York: Farrar,
Straus, Giroux, 1981).
Possibilities of Progress 215
smaller bands into larger units, negotiation, and trade become possible
when some rules were extended to cover outsiders.
Reflections of this kind inspire a straightforward theory about ethical
progress. Ethical codes begin by increasing the scope of altruism within
a group (enlarging the set of contexts across which members are pre-
pared to respond altruistically; §5); they progress by further expansions
of scope and by expansions of range (the set of individuals toward whom
altruistic responses are made; §5). Progressive transitions occur exactly
when the modified code contains precepts enjoining altruism of wider
scope or greater range than the code it replaces.6
There are difficulties. Not all our paradigms of progressive ethical
change fall under the envisaged rubric. Consider the modification of the
lex talionis. Here there is a shift from inflicting suffering on individuals
specially related to the perpetrator to punishing the person who did the
deed. The transition does not begin with a class of people initially pro-
tected by an ethical precept and another class of people not so protected,
and transfer some of the latter individuals to the protected class. Initially,
anyone is vulnerable to harm, provided he or she stands in a particular
relationship to the crime—being the son or daughter of someone who
killed the son or daughter of another person; after the transition, anyone
is vulnerable to harm if he or she stands in a different particular relation
to the crime (being the doer of the deed). No circle is expanded; one
circle is replaced by another.
Sometimes, what changes is not the group attitude toward a particu-
lar individual or class of individuals, but the group attitude toward the
desires those individuals have. Consider the withering of vice (§26). With
some strain, you could say there are two classes of people, those with pref-
erences solely for sexual activity with members of the opposite sex and
those who sometimes want to engage in intercourse with a member of the
same sex; before the change, there is toleration (an altruistic response?)
of the desires of the former class, but toleration is not extended to similar
desires of the latter class; after the transition, toleration extends to both.
6. As I read Singer, he is attracted by a theory of this sort (although possibly not one
so extremely rudimentary); at an early stage of my own thinking about ethical progress, I
was too.
216 the ethica l project
Quite apart from the issue of whether talk of altruism is really illuminat-
ing (or appropriate) here, the crucial step consists not in gathering per-
sons under a protective umbrella from which they were previously ex-
cluded, but in recognizing their desires as worthy of expression.
Inclusion and exclusion apply to desires, not people.7
Attention to some changes that must have occurred in prehistory re-
inforces these conclusions. During the Paleolithic, our human ancestors
modified their ethical codes to require individuals to use their talents for
the benefit of the group, they introduced roles and role-specific prescrip-
tions, they added requirements for development of talent, they came to
appreciate the higher forms of altruism that play a role in human rela-
tionships, and, in doing all these things, they developed a richer concep-
tion of human life and of the human individual.8 Among the members of
the earliest societies to have left written records are at least some who
have a conception of what it is to live well, far more elaborate than any
present in the groups that began the ethical project: for well-born Baby-
lonians and Egyptians, a life satisfying the basic desires felt by their dis-
tant ancestors would not be good enough.9 To be sure, aspects of their
understanding of what is good constitute no advance at all (their eager
acquisition of gaudy luxuries); others are simply regressive (desires to be
7. Defenders of the “expanding-circle” proposal might reply that they allow for exten-
sion of scope as well as of range. Yet the example is importantly different from central in-
stances in which an ethical advance consists of increasing the collection of contexts in
which people are willing to help one another (for example, by commanding the response,
even when the costs for agents would previously have inhibited addressing the other’s
plight). Failure of response arises not from the burdens of altruism but from the character
of the desire. Precisely because of what the other person wants—sexual relations with an-
other man or another woman—there is condemnation, assault, punishment, even murder.
Progress does not consist in expanding any circle but in recognizing facts that normalize
desires.
8. In citing these changes I do not presuppose my “how possibly” explanations of them,
but simply that these transitions occurred. That is a simple consequence of the difference
between the initial stages of normative guidance and the practices present at the dawn of
history.
9. Whether it would be enough for the distant ancestors themselves is a question to be
considered. One might well attribute to them desires for cooperation and for making con-
tributions to joint projects. If so, the seeds of a richer notion of living well are already
present.
Possibilities of Progress 217
10. In many cases, people have to make decisions about what factors are most important
to them, trading reliability against cost, or speed against ease of use. Here, as in the ethical
case, we can recognize progress in particu lar respects. Sometimes it is possible to talk of
overall progress, but sometimes not.
11. Here I adapt ideas from a seminal discussion by Larry Wright (“Functions,” Philo-
sophical Review 82 [1973]: 139–68). There are long and intricate discussions of how to elabo-
rate Wright’s “etiological” approach to functions, but details are not pertinent to present
purposes. The version of the account I favor, and that underlies my general claims about
Possibilities of Progress 219
functions here, is given in my essay “Function and Design,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy
18 (1993): 379–397.
12. This is an important insight of Robert Cummins (“Functional Analysis,” Journal of
Philosophy 72 [1975]: 741– 65). I amend Cummins’s original account by requiring that the
causal contribution relate to some function of the whole system (and thus there must be a
prior notion of overall function). For defense, see my “Function and Design.”
220 the ethica l project
13. For more detail about the differences between this approach to functions and that
taken by etiological theories, see my “Function and Design.”
Possibilities of Progress 221
14. To conceive the problem background in this way is to introduce familiar ideas from
ethical theories. The emphasis on endorsability has obvious connections to universalizing
principles and can be viewed as echoing a Kantian idea; the focus on the most urgent de-
sires has kinship with Rawls’s different principle; see also T. M. Scanlon, “Preference and
Urgency,” Journal of Philosophy 82 [1985]: 655– 69.
224 the ethica l project
failures have occurred. One way for A to “remedy” the failures of altru-
ism would be for her to form a desire that responds positively to B’s
manifest wish—to join the attack on B*. Often that would be to intensify
social conflict. Some forms of positive responses to the desires of others
are contaminated because what the other wants to do is to initiate inter-
ference with the expression of the desires of a third party. Societies with
rules supporting such interference are likely to fan the flames of social
conflict; societies directing altruism away from contaminated desires, and
toward the wishes of the targets of the interference, will probably dimin-
ish the tensions. They will develop a system of punishment directing
retribution toward those who initiate aggression.
So we can indicate another class of altruism failures to be remedied,
those in which the desires of victims to be protected go unsupported. As
with the earlier effort at more exact characterization in terms of urgent,
endorsable desires, this too is incomplete. Societies that fasten on actions
initiating aggression, take altruistic responses to the desires those actions
express to be contaminated, and institute rules for remedying altruism
failures toward the targets of aggression make a large first step toward
solving the problem of social confl ict. There will, however, be occa-
sions for further refi nement. Excluding contaminated desires is not the
whole story.
The large hope of ethical systems is to formulate an overarching ac-
count of fundamental ethical properties (goodness, rightness) or a collec-
tion of basic principles sufficient to adjudicate all cases. Those who share
the hope will believe that the function of ethics can be specified exactly
by latecomers in the evolution of our ethical practices. To the extent they
accept the framework in which I have posed the issue, they will seek an
exact representation of the problem background and a precise character-
ization of the altruism failures to be remedied. I view the situation differ-
ently. We latecomers know more about the problem background than
the pioneers who developed ethical systems partially responsive to it: we
can see how rules directing altruistic responses toward urgent endors-
able desires and away from contaminated desires are likely to dimin-
ish social tensions and confl icts. Codes incorporating those rules have
taken a first step, but they leave room for functional refinement. Ex-
trapolating from whatever progress can be discerned in the past, we
Possibilities of Progress 225
other hand, the wishes of servants are satisfied, and this is done through
rules encouraging the masters to respond to those wishes. Now the dis-
tinction between masters and servants lacks the significance it appeared
to possess, and, again, we have a recognizable system of ethics with an
odd means of ensuring compliance.
Consider yet another scenario. Social harmony is achieved because,
in the cases that would have generated conflict, some parties just do not
want whatever it was that caused a quarrel. If we focus the idea by imag-
ining the original experiments of living, the previously contested items
will be basic necessities, and the fantasy consists in supposing that some
members of the group do not want the resources they need to keep them
going. The other members respond to their abstemious wishes, and they
wither and die. In this instance, however, although a certain class of
altruism failures may be remedied, an extreme type of altruism failure
remains—for those who profit from the resources their unfortunate com-
rades forego fail to take any steps in the direction of paternalism. As the
plight of the ascetics becomes ever more dire, identification with their
actual wishes, rather than with the wishes they would have had if they
clearly perceived the consequences for themselves, ceases to be a form
of altruism.
Imagine a last variation on the theme. Social tension within the group
is decreased by expelling some of the members.15 There are two main
possibilities. Perhaps those expelled are the primary causes of social trou-
ble: they sometimes benefit from the altruism of other group members
but consistently fail to make altruistic responses themselves. Ending the
practice of interacting with them genuinely would remedy the altruism
failures by which the band has been beset and so would fulfill what has
been identified as the original function. If these are the circumstances,
however, the account of the original function is not challenged, since
there is no basis for describing the envisaged expulsion as regressive—it
is of a piece with prevalent societal practices of sequestering trouble-
makers. On the other hand, if those driven out are only marginally more
likely than their fellows to lapse from psychological altruism, excluding
15. I am grateful to Christian Nimtz and Boris Hennig for forceful presentation of this
possibility.
228 the ethica l project
become real options. These societies can address social tensions in the
brutal ways the scenarios propose. When they do so, they cannot be
conceived as fulfilling the original function of ethics and thus making
ethical progress—for, to recapitulate, they do not remedy altruism fail-
ures. Nevertheless, these societies do raise an important question for the
approach to ethical progress I am developing. Does the original function
of ethics continue to bind those who come later? The question brings home
the important fact that there are two sides to questions about ethical
progress, only one of which has as yet been considered. The facet under
study, here, as well as in Chapter 5, concerns whether one can make
sense of some notion of ethical progress integrable with the narrative of
Part I. Even given success in that venture, however, it would not follow
that progress, understood in the preferred way, would have any force
on later participants in the ethical project. Is “progress” of this sort
something we should aspire to make? Do the functions our ancestors
attempted to fulfill matter to us?
These important issues will occupy us in Chapters 7–9. So far, they
are merely registered—but their turn will come. For the moment, it is
enough to note the circumstances in which the problem background orig-
inally arose, the situations of our fi rst human ancestors with their
uneasy social lives; these are very different from those in which many
latter-day participants in the ethical project have lived (during the past
ten thousand years). The project began in small, egalitarian societies,
in which people with limited tendencies to psychological altruism lived
together. Feeling the tensions of their social lives, they had no success-
ful options except to address the (unrecognized) cause—and ethics was
born with the function of remedying altruism failures. That original
function is refined and gives rise to further functions, in ways we shall
now explore.
the idea of the enforcer counts as a major progressive step along one
dimension, even though it creates obstacles to progress of other types.
This is an important general point: advances in the social technology
that is ethics can shape the way in which further ethical progress be-
comes possible or impossible.
Introducing myths about unseen powers is not the only way in which
our ancestors have improved the techniques of promoting compliance.
As previously noted (§§17, 21), the thought of the enforcer can serve as a
conduit to association of a far richer set of emotions with the ethical code.
Initially, rules are followed out of fear. Later, once the belief that the com-
mandments express the divine will is entrenched, fear of the unseen
power can become awe, respect, even love and gratitude, so, still later,
following the code appears an act of reverent obedience, a gesture of re-
spect and love. The imagined wrathful countenance of a punitive deity
gives way to joy in the prospect of conforming action to shared ethical
rules. People may even describe themselves as acting out of respect for
the moral law, a law they suppose the deity to have inscribed on their
own hearts.16 In my account, these steps count as ethically progressive,
not because they eventually take us to some wonderful place—the privi-
leged “ethical point of view”—but because the multiplication of poten-
tial motivations increases the reliability of compliance to the ethical code.
They are refinements of the original function of promoting social har-
mony through eliminating altruism failures.
Exactly similar points apply to the extension of human sympathy. So-
cially embedded normative guidance first replaces altruism failures with
behavioral altruism, but, as remarked (§§11, 21), continued interactions
16. Kantians will probably not approve of this way of viewing the stance they identify
with a special ethical point of view. They are likely to suppose a decisive break between the
crude and inadequate ethical systems relying on divine commands and the supposedly a
priori unfolding of the moral law. It is, however, completely opaque to me how one could
arrive at correct ethical principles a priori, even if they were (in what sense?) “within,” and
it is worth considering whether Kant’s ethical innovations can be—and should be—viewed
as the recombination of elements from earlier traditions: the idea of divine command ap-
proaches that ethical principles are prescriptions not grounded in good consequences for
human beings, the suggestion of natural law theories (e.g., Aquinas) that the law is written
within our hearts, a long-standing philosophical celebration of reason and a corresponding
suspicion of emotion.
232 the ethica l project
with people, each responding to the other’s desires, can generate sympa-
thetic emotions. You begin the regular work of helping because that is
prescribed, but, as you continue, and as others react to your help, the
responses occur from different causes. This, too, is a progressive shift—
and again not because it attains a special “ethical point of view” in which
mutual sympathy holds sway, but because an increase in the potential
sources of compliance makes fulfilling the original function proceed
more reliably.
People with enlarged sympathies, with respect for the ethical code and
for those who have made conspicuous sacrifices to follow it, are more
likely to comply than those deficient in one of these respects. For them,
failure to respond to the socially approved desires of others opposes
several distinct psychological dispositions. They are not perfect, and,
on occasion, all the mechanisms for leading them to behavioral altruism
fail. Failure occurs more readily as societies grow, as the ethical project
introduces more distinctions and divisions, assigns status differentially,
and makes some members of the large society invisible to others. Even as
some developments in the project buttress old mechanisms and introduce
new ones, they simultaneously make psychological altruism of certain
types more difficult—sympathies expand, but only as far as the limits of
a group with which the higher-order altruist identifies him- or herself.
Transitions progressive in some respects are regressive in others
and even block off further ethical advances. In changed social cir-
cumstances, inherited modes of socialization encourage some forms of
altruism failure.
A second mode of ethical progress consists in integrating the code
with the system of punishment. Normative guidance emerges in a con-
text in which a rough system of punishment is already present (§12), and
it builds on psychological capacities for avoiding behavior that provokes
punishment. In part, the introduction of ethics substitutes prevention for
punishment. It does so by combining specification of commands with
the threat of punishment if they are broken. The systems of punishment
found in chimpanzees inflict harm on individuals who have done certain
things. An ethical code must approach such raw reactions to behavior
more self-consciously. Implicit in any endorsement of punishment is a
suspension of altruistic response: at least some of the desires of the indi-
Possibilities of Progress 233
vidual who has performed the rule-breaking action do not count; they
are not to be accommodated in dealing with him. The perpetrator wants
to avoid all the harm others in the group intend to visit upon him, but
this is not an occasion for responding to his desire. Integrating the ethi-
cal code with a system of punishment requires some things resembling
altruism failures not to be remedied, because, as we would ordinarily
say, the rule breaker has made some of his desires forfeit.
The ethical code connects with the system of punishment through
three questions: When? Who? How? The first issue is addressed by ap-
pealing to the prescriptions of the code: retribution is to occur just when
one of these rules is broken. The second is the translation of the earlier
raw reaction into the social practice of normative guidance: we look to
the individual(s) who did the action that broke the rule. For the third,
the ethical code must itself pronounce, declaring which kinds of harms
are to be inflicted. It must decide what accommodations with the desires
of the perpetrator are to be made. As noted, his desire to avoid all harm
is not to be the basis of an altruistic response; in carrying out the punish-
ment, ignoring that desire is not an altruism failure to be remedied. That
does not mean, however, that the code must be indifferent to everything
the rule breaker wants.
The original function of the code is to remedy altruism failures caus-
ing social discord, and that is achieved if punishment and the threat of
punishment decrease the frequency with which failures occur. Setting
some of the perpetrator’s desires outside the scope of altruistic responses
expresses a commitment to this function: if those desires are ignored, he
and others will be less likely to engage in future rule-breaking behavior.17
In many situations of rule breaking, other members of the group are
compelled to choose the target of their altruistic response, forced to de-
cide whether to align their desires with one person or another. The ap-
paratus of punishment makes this decision for them by distinguishing
between perpetrator and victim. In ignoring the desires of the perpetra-
tor and attending to the desires of the victim, one prominent—and readily
17. Here my functional approach to ethical progress aligns itself with views of punish-
ment that are forward-looking, that view punishment as a means to prevent future harm.
The raw reaction of a desire for revenge is transmuted into a piece of social technology.
234 the ethica l project
of the lex talionis using the “corresponding relative” as a vehicle for ret-
ribution is likely to inspire protests and reactions from those who sym-
pathize with the people targeted. In its early form, the law introduces
altruism failures instead of remedying them and, in doing so, destroys
rather than promotes social harmony. The modified version confining
discipline to the perpetrator can thus be seen as a refinement of the origi-
nal function of ethics.
Another important aspect of ethically mediated punishment deserves
consideration. The initial stages of ethical experimentation had to oper-
ate with a conception of rule breakers, and it is overwhelmingly probable
that they introduced the idea in the most straightforward fashion, think-
ing of perpetrators as people whose behavior violated rules. The func-
tion of punishment is to decrease the future occasions on which similar
altruism failures occur, and realizing that function depends on delibera-
tors’ ability to recognize in advance when a potential action is at odds
with the code. As prescriptions and the concepts involved in them become
more complex, it is apparent that there are episodes in which people
unwittingly break rules. Inflicting harm on those who tried to honor the
code is likely to sap the motivation to comply, since dedicated efforts still
lead to trouble. Acknowledging human limitations, incomplete knowl-
edge, and life histories yielding a distorted perspective makes progress
in fulfilling the original function. Breaking the rules is forgiven when
violators convince others they were doing their best to comply.
The extent to which an ethical code should take account of our limita-
tions of knowledge and the environmentally caused distortion of our
sympathies is something on which the code itself must pronounce. The
strategy of conceding something to human frailty is a progressive step in
the evolution of ethics. Our understanding of how to make such conces-
sions remains incomplete. Too rigid an insistence on the fact of rule vio-
lation proliferates altruism failures by weakening the motivation to try;
too easygoing an approach multiplies altruism failures by undermining
the rules themselves. The challenge, for our predecessors and for us, is to
operate in the space between these extremes and to sharpen the concept
of an excusable offense. Because of the variety of ways in which human
effort can fall short, our progress remains incomplete—we continue to
work out the extent to which we excuse human imperfection.
236 the ethica l project
18. With respect to this last example, as §32 noted, the altruism failure consists of an
attitude toward certain types of desires (desires for fulfi llment of same-sex love) that the
progressive transition modifies.
Possibilities of Progress 237
That is the starting point for a process leading, a very large number of
generations later, to societies with a far richer conception of living well.
My “how possibly” explanation links the two by starting with divisions
of labor (§19). Dividing the labor helps satisfy endorsable desires; speci-
fication of roles and assigning people to roles on the basis of talent refine
the social technology. In the process, new desires emerge: people find
some roles more attractive than others. The conception of the good life
expands, as members of the society view living well not just as meeting
the needs identified at the beginning—it is no longer enough to have a
full belly and a warm, safe place to sleep.19 Additionally, living well in-
volves attaining roles one wants and having the chance to choose one’s
roles.
The original problem remains constant throughout this process. Eth-
ics must continue to promote social harmony through remedying altru-
ism failure. Now it must do so on an expanded field of desires. If the
means to satisfy the endorsable desires present at earlier stages have be-
come available, it is in principle possible to solve the older problems (al-
though, in practice, that may not be done because of violations of the
code). The residual problem is to address social tensions caused by al-
truism failures with respect to desires that the (in principle) successful
solution has generated. Ethical principles are also required to respond
to conflicts within the individual’s expanded repertoire of desires, and
in this sphere, prescriptions for character development emerge.
This is a story about the generation of functions, where the notion of
generation is that discerned in the biological and technological examples.20
To make the structure explicit, consider the following sequence:
19. So simple a menu of basic desires was probably never sufficient to the idea of the
good life, even at the beginning. But this elementary formulation suggests the appropriate
contrast.
20. The account is a story—a “how possibly” explanation. It was originally provided to
show how ethical evolution could have led by gradual steps from the original form of the
ethical project to the complex practices recognizable in the ancient world. It is used here to
illustrate the notion of functional generation with respect to ethics, and also to show how a
challenging example—the emergence of richer notions of the good life—can be seen as
proceeding by locally progressive steps. Neither of these purposes requires my story to be
an account of actual history.
240 the ethica l project
In cases that exemplify this sequence, I shall say that P0 generates P1,
and that F0 generates F1. A function for ethics is anything resulting from
the original function (the remedying of altruism failures) by a finite num-
ber of steps of functional generation, that is, from a finite number of it-
erations of the sequence 1–4.21 The narrative of the last paragraph identi-
fies responding to the endorsed (elementary) desires of all group members
as a function of ethics, introducing and elaborating the division of labor
as a function of ethics, specifying roles as a function of ethics, and ulti-
mately endorsing an expanded set of desires as a function of ethics.
(Those identifications would be preserved, even if my “how possibly”
story is not historically accurate, given the minimal assumption that the
steps leading to the richer conception of the good life involved group
responses to antecedent problems.)
People need not always be aware of their problems. Proliferation of
mechanized vehicles might give rise to a period during which traffic was
unregulated. Some of the population, people unaffected by the accidents
befalling others, might see no difficulty in the status quo. The same can
occur with the ethical project. The evolution of ethical practice can give
rise to codes whose shortcomings and burdens are felt by only a few.
When that occurs, the first task of would-be reformers is to make the
problem apparent to all members of the society. That may occur through
verbal presentations—as with Woolman and Wollstonecraft—or through
the exerting of pressure from people whose voices have not previously
been heard. In the earliest phases of the ethical project, however, when
groups are small and everyone can make his or her particular perspective
known, the problems generated are visible. Stratified societies create
21. At risk of being unnecessarily explicit: this specification counts the original function
as a function, since it is obtainable from itself by zero steps of functional generation.
Possibilities of Progress 241
22. Whether this is so requires deeper scrutiny of their lives than I can offer here. I do
not endorse the conclusion that they were better at discharging some functions, but simply
recognize this as a question.
Possibilities of Progress 243
23. I borrow the term from Isaac Levi (The Enterprise of Knowledge [Cambridge, MA:
The MIT Press, 1982]), who deploys it to make a kindred point about the importance of
local (“myopic”) standards.
24. The method is specified by the first formulation of the Categorical Imperative, in
which potential maxims are to be scrutinized to see if they can be willed without contradic-
tion. Ethical truths are just statements that record the results of the process—thus, if
“Make a promise not intending to keep it” fails the test, then “Promise breaking is imper-
missible” constitutes an ethical truth. I shall not try to work out the intricacies of this
theory, since its procedure seems so indeterminate. A more plausible constructivist approach
can be derived from Rawls, who can be read as viewing ethical truths as expressing the
246 the ethica l project
decisions arrived at in the original position. There are well-known difficulties in specifying
which version of the original position is privileged (and why).
25. See Peirce, “The Fixation of Belief,” and James, Pragmatism (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1978). In connection with ordinary statements about the physi-
cal world, as well as scientific statements, I regard James’s development of the thought as
compatible with a correspondence theory [see my “Scientific Realism: The Truth in Prag-
matism” forthcoming in Wenceslao Gonzalez (ed), Scientific Realism and Democratic Soci-
ety: The Philosophy of Philip Kitcher, (Rodopi, Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of Sci-
ence) and “The Road Not Taken,” to appear in German in a volume edited by Marcus
Willaschek, celebrating the centennial of William James’ Pragmatism (Suhrkamp].
26. As with many generalizations in other areas, it is hard to state these with any great
precision. This has sometimes inspired authors to think of ethical precepts as analogous to
Possibilities of Progress 247
27. The pluralism envisaged here is close to that defended by Isaiah Berlin. One impor-
tant feature of it is the recognition by each of the rival traditions of the values taken as fun-
damental by the other— each feels the tug of what the other does so well. (I am grateful to
Chris Peacocke for emphasizing to me this crucial facet of Berlin’s pluralism, and thereby
prompting me to make my acceptance of it explicit.)
250 the ethica l project
30. Few people in the history of the ethical project have offered progressive proposals,
and few have had the insight into possibilities of altruism failure achieved by the three fig-
ures whose status I have (briefly, unsympathetically, and coldly) evaluated. One of the wise
sayings attributed to the most wide-ranging of these reformers is that judgment is danger-
ous. Those whose contributions to the ethical project are infinitesimal in comparison (as
mine are) should acknowledge that.
31. John Dewey and James Tufts, Ethics, 2nd ed. (New York: Henry Holt, 1932). In the
original, the sentence is italicized.
252 the ethica l project
Naturalistic Fallacies?
1. This is very clearly argued by Richard Joyce in The Evolution of Morality (Cam-
bridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2006). Some of the following discussions present points akin
to those made in this informed and well-argued book, but, since my pragmatic naturalism
diverges from Joyce’s approach in important respects, the formulations are sometimes
different.
253
254 the ethica l project
2. David Hume, Treatise of Human Nature, 3.1.1. (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1978).
3. The notion of “essential occurrence” is developed by writers on logic from Bolzano
on and is especially clearly worked out by W. V. Quine (Philosophy of Logic [Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1970], 80–81). Counterexamples to the thesis that statements es-
sentially involving ethical vocabulary cannot be derived from factual statements were of-
Naturalistic Fallacies? 255
6. For social Darwinism, see the classic study by Richard Hofstadter (Social Darwin-
ism in American Thought [Boston: Beacon, 1955]). The most prominent versions of the
sociobiological inferences come in E. O. Wilson, On Human Nature (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1978), and in Michael Ruse and E. O. Wilson, “Moral Philoso-
phy as Applied Science,” Philosophy 61 (1986): 173– 92. For extended critique, see the fi nal
chapter of my Vaulting Ambition: Sociobiology and the Quest for Human Nature (Cam-
bridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1985) and “Four Ways of ‘Biologicizing’ Ethics,” in Concep-
tual Issues in Evolutionary Biology, ed. Elliott Sober (Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books,
The MIT Press, 1994).
7. As the discussion of method in substantive ethics, to be presented in Chapter 9, will
reveal, the sense in which ethical proposals are justified is rather special and involves a col-
lective procedure. For the moment, the complications of this method are ignored, and I shall
operate with a blanket notion of justification that figures in naturalism’s commitment.
Naturalistic Fallacies? 257
from history reveal the premises as partly normative and partly factual.
Wollstonecraft’s premises are (1) women ought to be capable of wifely
and maternal behavior (in line with the prevalent ethical code), and (2)
educated women are more likely to have these capacities. She infers that
women ought to be educated (§24). Her inferences are not touched by
Hume’s challenge.
Merely making this observation is no more satisfactory than appeal-
ing to the fact that the inferences Hume criticizes are hard to circum-
scribe. To say that “from the beginning” human beings (human beings)
have been committed to normative judgments would only release natu-
ralism from Humean suspicions if all subsequent inferences could be
assimilated to the pattern discerned in some of my examples (for exam-
ple, those that figure in the reasoning of Wollstonecraft and Woolman).
Unfortunately, if you suppose all modifications of ethical practice in-
volve logical inferences from previously adopted ethical judgments and
factual statements (typically newly discovered), ethical innovation will be
viewed as an illusion. Clear-eyed champions of the Humean challenge
would wonder how, if there were never any novelty in ethics, it was pos-
sible for human ethical practice to achieve, at the beginning, a strong
enough collection of normative premises, and to do so in a justified way
(§31). If pragmatic naturalism is to scotch concerns about its reliance on
illicit inferences, more will have to be said.
One thing that can, and should, be said immediately is that not all
cogent inference is deductive. From Hume himself on, no sophisticated
devotee of the challenge has believed that the inferences leading from
factual premises to normative conclusions have to be cast in a form re-
vealing them as deductively valid. Naturalists can avail themselves of
nondeductive modes of inference. Pragmatic naturalism can plausibly
suppose that some modifications of ethical practice proceed through a
search for reflective equilibrium: given the normative judgments currently
accepted, one looks for principles subsuming them and perhaps jetti-
sons particular normative judgments that do not accord with candidate
subsumptive principles.8 Recognizing this possibility (and others akin
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), and fully explicit in A Theory of Justice
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), is well suited to a dynamic understand-
ing of ethical justification. Interestingly, Rawls’s source for the appeal to reflective equilib-
rium, Nelson Goodman, deployed the idea as part of a naturalistic solution to his own
“new riddle of induction” (see the fi nal chapter of Fact, Fiction, and Forecast [Indianapo-
lis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill, 1956]). I shall discuss the credentials of appeals to reflective equi-
librium at greater length in Chapter 9.
9. Here I draw on my reconceptualization of a reliabilist approach to justification. See
§§32, 39.
Naturalistic Fallacies? 259
Divide the problem into parts. Start with the pioneers, those who be-
gan ethical practice. They belonged to a tense society, in which altruism
failures constantly produced social conflict. If their newly introduced
rules address the problem underlying the original function of ethics (they
fulfill the function of remedying altruism failures), they take a progres-
sive step. Despite my emphasis on the sporadic character of ethical prog-
ress (episodes of “sleepwalking” might occur with significant frequency),
the codes introduced by groups successful in cultural competition dis-
charged this function. It is implausible that their success was entirely
accidental. The first ethical deliberators surely perceived clearly some
sources of trouble—failures to share, unprovoked aggression, and so
forth. Almost certainly, the rules they formulated to address their prob-
lems were imperfect, but they were an advance over the unregulated
state in which they suffered social tension. Imagine, for example, early
ventures in regulating alliances and mating, rough-and-ready delinea-
tions of “the elementary structures of kinship,” adjusting the conduct of
group members so it became more frequently behaviorally altruistic and
less likely to provoke trouble. We cannot suppose that deliberators who
recommended progressive transitions were entirely clear about what
they were doing—they were not in the position of later analysts who can
identify functions and show how they would be promoted by proposed
changes—but the successes of these early ethicists did not emerge from
blind guesswork either. In the beginning, the successful pioneers made
ethical progress through processes (diagnosis of prevalent social prob-
lems, joint deliberation) likely to generate progressive transitions.
Their successors expanded the conceptual framework to introduce
ideas (of good, of right, of virtue—or of what it is to be “one of us”) en-
abling them to express descriptive counterparts of the rules previously
adopted. They have a rule enjoining or forbidding a class of actions, and,
within the expanded framework, they declare that actions in this class
are right or are wrong (what members of the group do, or avoid). If adopt-
ing the rule was based on deliberation likely to generate progressive
transitions, promulgating the rule is justified—and so derivatively is ac-
ceptance of its descriptive counterpart.
Turn now to the subsequent modifications. As emphasized (§§36–37),
the evolution of ethics brings new functions beyond the original one.
260 the ethica l project
10. In making the particu lar claim about honesty, I offer no judgment about whether the
line of reasoning that counts as SJ-justified would have been available to our predecessors.
It is possible (but not obviously correct) that SJ-justification requires explicit articulation
of a pragmatic naturalist perspective. If so, it does not detract from the WJ-justification I
take to be present throughout the history of ethics.
Naturalistic Fallacies? 263
11. The quoted phrases are from Mill, who favors explaining the “sanction of ethics” in
sociopsychological terms. See Mill, Works (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1970)
10:229, 228.
12. Mill is inclined to the latter explanation: see Works 10:230. In accordance with
the discussion of §14, I recommend framing the questions in terms of interactions be-
tween genotype and environment, and remaining open about the precise contributions
of each.
Mill offers an eloquent formulation of the picture he views as most plausible. Our coop-
erative social existence arouses this feeling, and it is given direction by the community
around us:
The smallest germs of the feeling are laid hold of and nourished by the contagion of
sympathy and the influences of education; and a complete web of corroborative as-
sociation is woven round it, by the powerful agency of the external sanctions.
(Works 10:232)
As I read him, he tries to address the question of the authority of ethics (the “sanction of
morality”) by appealing to something like the account of normative guidance and of con-
science offered in §§11–13.
264 the ethica l project
13. The quoted phrase is from Dewey, who extends Mill’s sociopsychological approach.
He confronts what is supposed to be a great difficulty:
It is said that to derive moral standards from social customs is to evacuate the latter
of all authority. Morals, it is said, imply the subordination of fact to ideal consider-
ations, while the view presented makes morals secondary to bare fact, which is
equal to depriving them of dignity and jurisdiction. (Human Nature and Conduct,
79)
Dewey claims that the worry rests on a “false separation,” the supposition that cultural
practices are merely “accidental by-products” (ibid.). Here he recapitulates the point made
in his summary of his ethical perspective, that “moral conceptions and processes grow out
of the very conditions of human life” ( John Dewey and James Tufts, Ethics, 2nd ed. [New
York: Henry Holt, 1932], 343). This prepares the way for his answer to the challenge. After
arguing that, strictly speaking, no view of the “origin and sanction” of moral obligation can
provide what some people seek for the authority of ethics, he suggests that, in “an empirical
sense” there is a simple answer: “The authority is that of life” [Human Nature and Con-
duct, (Amherst NY: Prometheus Books, 2002), 80–81; see also 98, 232, 326]. My approach
to the objection that naturalism loses the authority of ethics will endeavor to articulate
what I take Dewey to have had in mind.
14. Some of Mill’s formulations make him vulnerable to the charge that he has changed
the topic in this way. Yet that accusation is a little unfair, since the discussion in Utilitari-
anism, in Mill On Liberty and other Essays [Oxford: Oxford University Press (The World’s
Classics), 1998], does make some efforts to show how the conditions of community life will
orient our subjective feelings (conscience) in particu lar directions—specifically in leading
us to view our own preference and perspective as one among many. It is easy to see, how-
ever, how my emphasis on processes of socialization provokes the complaint.
Naturalistic Fallacies? 265
15. For discussions of this theme, see chaps. 5 and 6 of my Science, Truth, and Democ-
racy (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001).
266 the ethica l project
16. This is to overcome the “separation” of which Dewey was suspicious, and to recon-
nect the standards of inquiry with human life.
Naturalistic Fallacies? 267
17. Kantians will incline to the latter formulation, resisting any suggestion of an inde-
pendent ethical reality to which our judgments should conform. Their approach to objec-
tivity emphasizes constructions taken to have a priori validity, and they will argue that
pragmatic pluralism can supply only contingent—second-rate—constraints.
268 the ethica l project
18. The notions of progress and justification that figure here can be construed accord-
ing to either of the conceptions that figured in the last section, as weak or strong. The
strong concepts provide a close analog of the split between conformity to local authority
and the recognition of ethical truth, on which critics want to insist, but the weak concepts
mark another important distinction, one accommodating our fallibility and the historical
contexts in which we fi nd ourselves.
Naturalistic Fallacies? 269
19. I shall not attempt any fi ne distinction between skepticism and nihilism: my focus
will be on a range of questions that might be covered with either label. Egoists will be con-
sidered as skeptics/nihilists who view ethics as a constraint on their personal (solitary—§3)
desires.
20. As we shall see, discussion of the comparative issue leads to a deeper challenge, one
already identified at the end of the last chapter. I am indebted to an anonymous reader who
recommended being explicit about this.
Naturalistic Fallacies? 271
Even this basic differentiation allows various ways of reading the skepti-
cal query.
Nonnaturalistic approaches to ethics clearly suppose that the skeptic
is raising a question about some true ethical precept. Nobody thinks a
skeptic who inquires why he or she should conform to the injunction to lie
whenever one feels like it deserves any more than correction about what
ethics commands. So a very straightforward reading of the challenge
would adopt b as indicating the precepts with respect to which skepti-
cism is to be addressed. That formulation, however, might seem to un-
derestimate human fallibility. We know we do not have any ultrareliable
access to the rules that would be adopted in any indefinite sequence of
progressive modifications, and so, perhaps, we should take ourselves as
reasonably conforming to the rules our best justifications single out
as likely to have the status assigned in b—and take skeptical questions to
be directed against c. Or we might go further, viewing our individual
selves as unlikely to improve on the wisdom of the tradition in which we
stand, and modestly disclaiming our own abilities to make judgments
about future progressive modifications. Consequently, we might take
the rules adopted in our current code as the best available candidates for
b, supposing the skeptical challenge focuses on a. Even formulating the
skeptical worry turns out, ironically, to involve a judgment about the
allowances we ought to make for our acknowledged fallibility.
As before, it is not enough to point to inexact or problematic formula-
tions of an objection. However you circumscribe the queried rules, the
challenge can be posed with respect to examples. Consider any likely
candidate, and imagine the demand directed at it: given that injunctions to
honesty (say) emerge as stable elements in all progressive traditions, why
should that provide grounds for compliance? Skeptics want to know
why a sequence of progressive transitions, conceived as addressing the
functions of the ethical project, should deliver rules to be obeyed, even
when the rules in question seem overwhelmingly likely to be maintained
in all future progressive modifications of current practice.
What conditions should an answer to the skeptical question meet?
One thought is that, to be satisfactory, a response should silence the skep-
tic. Given the response, nothing can be said to continue the skeptical
challenge. Plainly, that sets the standards of success very high, and, in
272 the ethica l project
21. The “open-question” argument, in just this form, is usually attributed to Moore. But
a close reading of what Moore actually says reveals a much more complex and rather differ-
ent line of reasoning. For good discussion, see Joyce, The Evolution of Morality (Cam-
bridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2006). Whatever the merits of the interpretation of Moore,
the familiar objection is an important one.
22. As has frequently been observed, the conception of discrete orbits is at odds with
the principles of electromagnetism. Another interesting example is the concept of the rigid
body in relativistic dynamics.
Naturalistic Fallacies? 273
irrationality’ will pose difficulties for me. Nor am I much moved by the
thought of rules hypothetically ideal people (supposedly better than me)
in some fictional situation would agree to. Why should I be bound by
what they would decide? There is no argument for thinking the pur-
poses I care about would be ill served by flouting any such precepts.”
Orthodox Kantians or contractarians may think this alleged reply is
incoherent, tacitly self-undermining, or something like that. Yet however
hard they struggle to reveal the skeptic’s irrationality, they do not render
him speechless—he can cheerfully wave away the gloomy descriptions of
his state by pointing out how well he is able to pursue the things that
matter to him. Silencing is hard to do.
Maybe, though, the skeptic’s answers have exposed something wrong
with him: he has failed to meet ideal conditions of rationality. If that is
so, the criterion for a successful reply to the skeptic is modified. He does
not have to be silenced; one must merely have an account of why his re-
sponses are problematic. Given this understanding, however, pragmatic
naturalism can do just as well as the allegedly superior nonnaturalistic
approaches. Where Kantians and contractarians see failures of ideal
rationality, pragmatic naturalism diagnoses an inability to appreciate
how central the ethical project is to human life. Pragmatic naturalism
will begin answering the challenge by pointing out that the achievement
of normative guidance was central to the origin and development of fully
human society, that ethics served an important original function, and
that progressive shifts in ethical practice consist in fulfilling that func-
tion, and those generated from it, more effectively. Once again, the skep-
tic speaks: “Why should I be bound by the rules emerging from ‘pro-
gressive transitions’ in this ‘project’? No matter how they have helped
discharge the functions you identify, I can manage perfectly well by flout-
ing them. There is no compelling motivation for me to continue in any
ethical tradition.” Pragmatic naturalists will want to insist that desires
the skeptic wants to satisfy by breaking the rules have been made possi-
ble only by the project he rejects, that he fails to understand how the ori-
gin and evolution of ethical practice have framed his life, giving him the
options he wants to pursue. That insistence will not silence the skep-
tic—it will be no more effective than appeals to practical reason or charges
of irrationality. Yet it fares no worse as a diagnosis of the skeptic’s
274 the ethica l project
mistake: he wants to reject something that has made his envisaged way
of life and his preferred choices possible.
This judgment can be elaborated further and defended by consider-
ing some familiar characters from the history of philosophical ethics.
Thrasymachus challenges Socrates, suggesting that ethical principles
(more exactly, the claims of justice) are put forward to advance the inter-
ests of those in power.23 He views ethical practice as a device employed
to keep weaker members of the society in line and refuses to go along.
Pragmatic naturalism credits Thrasymachus with an insight and faults
him for an error. The insight: in many ethical traditions, rules are intro-
duced or emended by a powerful minority, supposedly especially good
at recognizing the will of the unseen enforcer, and the precepts of the
social practice can be arbitrary and oppressive (§§35, 26). The error is to
overlook the fact that pragmatic naturalism diagnoses the oppressive
injunctions as stemming from regressive transitions. Functional ethical
practice is not a tool for asserting the will of the strong and mighty, but
rather grounded in attempts to take into account the desires of all mem-
bers of a society. The original function of remedying altruism failures
acknowledges the wishes and aspirations of all. Thrasymachus can be
enlisted as an ally and invited to continue in the evolving project of eth-
ics by responding to places at which it is dysfunctional. He is wrong in
his characterization of the project as a whole.
A different challenge comes from a later figure, the “sensible knave”
who pops up in the final paragraphs of Hume’s Enquiry Concerning the
Principles of Morals.24 Knave does not offer any general theory of what
ethical practice is and how it has gone wrong—he simply wants his own
plans not to be constrained by it. He has egoistic (solitary) desires con-
travening some of the ethical principles in force, and, where he can get
away with it, he would prefer to satisfy those desires, instead of conforming
23. See Plato Republic Book 1. Socrates replies with a convoluted and unconvincing se-
quence of questions that eventually reduce Thrasymachus to silence. Later, Glaucon and
Adeimantus present the challenge in a milder form, eliciting a far more sophisticated and
interesting account of justice. Whether an adept real-life counterpart of Thrasymachus
would really be rendered speechless by either version of the response is highly dubious.
24. David Hume, Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals (Indianapolis, IN: Hack-
ett, 1983), 81.
Naturalistic Fallacies? 275
to attain would not be available to him. Knave replies that this is all past
history. He is grateful so many of his predecessors went along with the
codes in force and modified them in the progressive ways that have made
contemporary society possible—although he hints that there have prob-
ably been a few of his sort before, people who have quietly made use of
the obedient docility of their fellows. Now that ethical practice has made
a rich and complex society possible, he can take advantage of that fact
and pursue his egoistic goals.
Knave cannot be silenced. Yet pragmatic naturalism can offer a diag-
nosis of what he is doing. He wants to take advantage of the products of
social evolution without acknowledging the functions that have made
those products possible. He wants to operate within a society without
feeling that sympathy to others, that altruistic response to their desires,
whose evolution has formed that society. Being human, we tell him, con-
sists in participating in this project through which altruism failures are
remedied and further ethical functions generated and fulfilled. He shrugs
his shoulders, unmoved by this rhetoric. Yet the diagnosis seems no worse
than that offered by the major rival approaches to ethics. Indeed, one
way of elaborating the notion of practical rationality might suppose that
the knavish incoherence consists in making an exception of oneself while
simultaneously relying on the ethical practice that sustains human coop-
eration, a reading that would erase the differences between the naturalis-
tic and nonnaturalistic alternatives.26
The third and last troublemaker is a Nietzschean persona, the “free
spirit.” Unlike Thrasymachus, free spirit does not want to provide a gen-
eral characterization to convince everyone to view ethics as oppression.
Unlike knave, free spirit is not concerned only with himself and with his
ability to use institutions presupposing the ethical project to advance his
own solitary ends. Free spirit writes for his peers. They are oppressed,
confined, by ethical practice; how matters stand with the rest, with the
herd, is of no concern to him.
26. Pragmatic naturalism does point out a kind of “contradiction” in knave’s attitudes—
and Kantian-inspired approaches might identify this as the crucial failure of practical ratio-
nality. If so, the accounts would be not only on a par, but also almost identical. The residual
difference would lie in the ability of pragmatic naturalism to point to the failure of sympa-
thy knave exhibits.
Naturalistic Fallacies? 277
The charge leveled by free spirit is so far ambiguous. Free spirit might
be rejecting the ethical codes actually developed (or developed in a par-
ticular tradition), seeing these as failing to fulfill important human func-
tions, and, on this basis, demanding a “revaluation of values.”27 Viewed
in this way, free spirit is a reformer, a participant within the evolution of
ethics, not someone who rejects the rules it would deliver if it were to
proceed progressively. He calls attention to particular places—possibly
quite fundamental places—at which he takes the historical development
of ethics to have been regressive. Assuming we can reach agreement with
him about whether the pertinent modifications refine the functions of
ethics, there will be no difficulty.28 For, if the transitions turn out to
be progressive after all, he will acknowledge the rules. If they do not, we
shall not insist on his acknowledgment of the rules actually generated,
and he will honor the prescriptions resulting from progressive replace-
ments of the dysfunctional precepts.
Free spirit may want more, however. He asks why he should care
about the specific recommendations emerging from those transitions
pragmatic naturalism counts as progressive. His question is best met
with another: what alternative does he have in mind? To conceive of the
historical evolution of ethical practice, taken as a whole, as oppressive
is vacuous, unless one can do more than wave vaguely in the direction of
unarticulated possibilities. The more limited version of free spirit, who
is willing to acknowledge the functions of ethics and who clamors for
27. I think most of Nietzsche’s many-sided polemic against “morality” can be inter-
preted in this way. So understood, he turns out to be an interesting and insightful ally of
the pragmatic naturalist project. The derogatory remarks about “English” genealogies,
and the attacks on the value of altruism, [see the early sections of Genealogy of Morals,
Friedrich Nietzsche On the Genealogy of Morality (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2007)], are fundamentally attacks on the thesis that a historical understanding of the
emergence of contemporary ethical ideas must vindicate those ideas. Instead, Nietzsche
wants to use history in the interests of reform—with the aim, one might say, of advancing
the ethical project. That is entirely in accord with pragmatic naturalism, which is receptive
to the thought that increased historical understanding might expose regressive transitions
and open up new possibilities for us. I am grateful to Jessica Berry, whose insightful com-
ments and questions in response to a lecture I gave at Emory University have led me to view
Nietzsche as less of a threat and more of a fellow traveler.
28. The next section will begin to scrutinize this assumption.
278 the ethica l project
Understanding that the task is not to quell the sociopath with some
brilliant philosophical formula helps us see more clearly what the trou-
blesome characters really represent. We should envisage the skeptical
challenge as posed by ordinary people, whose socialization is reason-
ably effective and who feel the tug of ethical commands. They have a
tendency to conform but also want to know why they should be glad to
have this disposition. The troublemakers are devices for giving sub-
stance to this worry, personae with which the skeptical questioner can
vicariously identify but for whom following through on the identification
would be psychologically disastrous. The skeptical question is not a de-
mand to be talked into complying (typically, disobeying the rules is not
a live option), but a request for reassurance. The questioner needs to feel
at home with his or her ethical propensities.
We can now see why certain approaches to ethics, particularly the
nonnaturalistic Kantian and contractarian varieties, seem appropriate
replies to skeptical challenges. They provide reassurance by delineating
an ideal of rational thought and behavior, more or less thoroughly articu-
lated, so people who already feel the ethical tug can identify a mistake
deviants would be making. These philosophical replies cannot (to repeat)
silence deviants or bring sociopaths to heel. But they succeed at a more
modest task.
So too does pragmatic naturalism. To the extent people who wonder
whether they should be glad to have ethical dispositions can be satisfied
with explanations invoking practical rationality, they should be (at least)
equally content with the pragmatic naturalist account. For that account
places ethical practice at the center of our humanity, viewing ever-more
refined attention to altruism failures, ever-increased recognition of the
wants of others, as preconditions of the kinds of lives we live and the
kinds of societies we have. Although one may challenge parts of the ethi-
cal practices we have inherited, there is no escaping the ethical project.
The only social alternative we know is that of our hominid ancestors and
our chimpanzee contemporaries, an alternative from which the intro-
duction of ethics originally liberated us. That reply should be reassurance
enough.
In a justly famous image, Otto Neurath specified our epistemological
predicament, comparing us to sailors who must constantly rebuild the
280 the ethica l project
31. Otto Neurath, “Protokolsätze,” Erkenntnis 3 (1932–33): 206; translated and re-
printed in Logical Positivism, ed. A. J. Ayer (New York: Free Press, 1959), 199–208, 201.
Quine made the passage famous by using it as the epigraph for his influential book, Word
and Object (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1960).
Naturalistic Fallacies? 281
32. There is plenty of room for reform here—for challengers might uncover points at
which regressive precepts or institutions have been introduced. Pragmatic naturalism is by
no means committed to the vindicating (“English”) genealogies, of which Nietzsche com-
plained. See On the Genealogy of Morality.
Pa rt T h r e e
A Normative Stance
chapter 8
285
286 the ethica l project
societies, but by fulfilling the functions of ethics as they have so far emerged.
The project is something people work out with one another. There are
no experts here.
From this perspective, normative ethics requires continuing efforts to
decide how to live together in a common world. Each generation renews
the project, going on from the point reached by its predecessors. The tasks
facing normative ethics are those of deciding what should be retained,
what modified and how—also to resolve how those decisions are made.
If we are like sailors, repairing our ship at sea, we must determine which
planks to leave in place and which to move—and our efforts have to be
coordinated. The normative ethicist’s role is not to offer the grand plan
but to help the coordination.
Pragmatic naturalism assigns philosophers the task of facilitating dis-
cussion of how we should continue the project of living together. Philos-
ophy makes proposals. (That is itself a proposal.) Given the approach to
progress offered in Chapter 6, one type of proposal should identify the
problems, unsolved and partially solved, to which ethical practice has
responded: call this the diagnostic proposal. Another type of proposal,
the methodological proposal, should offer suggestions about how pro-
posals are to be adjudicated, about the rules of the continuing ethical
conversation. (That does not close off the possibility of reverting to the
classical vision of normative ethics, since one possible conversation is a
monologue: we could decide to listen to the advice of a sage.)
Philosophical proposals can be more or less informed, more or less
articulated and supported. In light of Parts I and II, we can identify the
functions of ethics and try to use factual knowledge to find ways in which
those functions could be more effectively discharged. If there were only
a single function, or if there were no danger that fulfilling the distinct
functions that have emerged would involve choices among them, the im-
portance of deliberation would recede, or even vanish. Ethics could
become a fully empirical discipline, whose task was to discover the ways
of satisfying a single function or a harmonious set of functions. Because
the pursuit of local progress gives rise to functional conflict (§§37–38),
the ethical project cannot be turned over to a group of specialists who
can work on finding ways to fulfill a function (or compatible functions).
A first proposal: we have little alternative to recapitulating the original
Progress, Equality, and the Good 287
1. Here I allude to a famous remark of Richard Rorty (see the closing passages in Phi-
losophy and the Mirror of Nature [Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979]). I sus-
pect I assign a larger role to philosophical midwifery than Rorty would allow.
288 the ethica l project
the package to have a coherence its (skeptical) rival lacks. I begin by pre-
senting a useful framework for diagnosis.
2. Mill, Works, J.S. Mill, Collected Works (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1970),
10:111, from the essay “Bentham.”
3. Mill, Works, 10:217.
4. The most spectacular examples of ungrounded deontology occur in invocations of
the divine will to prohibit (or command) human actions (§§26, 35).
290 the ethica l project
5. Perhaps one might claim that the difference in value is explicable because of the atti-
tudes people would have: their pleasures would be less in the causally unsystematic world.
Then grant them the illusion of thinking the causal relations are as they normally are. The
difference in value persists.
292 the ethica l project
There is a very general reason for worrying about almost all the as-
sumptions generating utilitarianism from consequentialism. Utilitarian-
ism derives from consequentialism by a series of reductionist moves. We
aim to compute the values of the worlds that would flow from our envis-
aged actions. We reduce the problem to one of summing the values of the
lives of a class of individuals; we reduce it further by considering only
sentient individuals and further still by ignoring most of these and con-
centrating on those we suppose immediately affected by the actions un-
der scrutiny; we reduce the problem of measuring the values assigned to
the individual lives by decomposing those lives into a sequence of mo-
mentary states; now we assign values to those states by reducing the
aspects we consider to the intensities of pains and pleasures; having
reduced the problem in this way, we can start summing, and arrive at the
measure utilitarians commend. Any or all of the reductions could be
questioned. For there is no reason to think the value of a world will al-
ways consist in the sum of the value of the lives of the individuals we
consider one by one—distribution might be crucial. Further, we have no
reason to suppose that the value of an individual life can be generated by
summing the values of momentary states (or even longer experiences
that occur in people) taken in isolation from one another.
Consider an alternative view of the value of individual lives. It starts
by taking a valuable human life to be one directed by the free choices
of the person whose life it is, as something given coherence by an in-
dividual conception of the good.6 However pleasurable a sequence of dis-
jointed experiences (even a repetitive sequence) might be, it would fall
short unless it had certain global properties. Valuable lives exhibit a
plan.
Similar holistic considerations apply to social states. Rather than
thinking the valuable social state is one in which the total sum of plea-
sure over pain in the population is high, we might conceive a group of
people pursuing a wide diversity of projects for their lives, who are none-
theless bound together in relations of dialogue, joint action, and mutual
6. As Mill claims throughout On Liberty and other Essays [Oxford: Oxford University
Press (The World’s Classics), 1998]. This essay shows his enormous debt to the Greek
thinkers he studied from childhood on.
Progress, Equality, and the Good 293
9. Bernard Williams makes some perceptive remarks that anticipate this line of re-
sponse in his contribution to J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism: For and
Against (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1973), sec. 2.
10. So one might say that the idea of the unseen enforcer is unproblematic for ethical
progress when the deliverances of the commander are grounded in the prior understand-
ing of the good. Things go astray only when the practice of commanding takes on a life of
its own.
Progress, Equality, and the Good 295
11. Here I am imagining societies as defi ned recursively. One might try to block the
conclusions by demanding that any two members must engage in social interaction, or by
raising the standards for social interaction. I shall discuss the issue of how to demarcate
societies more extensively below. For the moment, the recursive approach will help to fi x
ideas.
296 the ethica l project
of achieving the “higher” goods. When the most valued social positions
go to those who have performed outstandingly on the tasks assigned by
an educational system, people often fail because of their inability to sat-
isfy basic needs (hungry, ill-sheltered children do not always concen-
trate, children who go to decrepit, dangerous schools do less well on the
exams devised to test them).
Functional conflict underlies social tensions but is not itself perceived.
In practice, the conflict is settled by overriding the original function of
the ethical project, and that suppression is thoroughly institutionalized.
Equipped with an account of the ethical project and its evolution, we can
be more reflective. Dynamic consequentialism sees our normative task
as beginning from respecifying the good. That specification cannot be
achieved without reflecting on roles and institutions—ethics is social.12
The development of a richer repertoire of emotions for responding to
the actions of others, especially the negative sentiments of indignation
and revulsion provoked by injustice and cruelty, underlies current ways
of securing compliance to our codes. People living in a state of blatant
inequality, people whose basic needs are unmet, are often not persuaded
that there has been no real injustice or cruelty. Indignation and revul-
sion easily reinforce the anger and frustration that would have been felt
by their ancestors under similar circumstances. If the amplified emo-
tional reaction is held in check, it is only because the injunction against
initiating violence is powerfully enforced: asymmetries in wealth and
power are used to threaten those inclined to protest with even direr con-
sequences for themselves and their loved ones. (This kind of coercion
figured in the scenarios about dictatorial rule—§34; impossible though
it may have been among the small bands of the Paleolithic, it is readily
contrived within contemporary societies.)
Were we to consider the entire human population as a single society,
the extent and range of inequality would be enormous. Each day, thou-
sands of people die or become disabled through lack of the resources
12. The phrase is Dewey’s, chosen as title for the last chapter of Human Nature and
Conduct (Amherst NY: Prometheus Books, 2002). The point encapsulated in the phrase
recapitulates themes in Foucault and Marx, themes often beyond the horizons of contem-
porary ethical discussions.
Progress, Equality, and the Good 297
13. The annual reports of the World Health Orga nization provide (sobering) data. See
James Flory and Philip Kitcher, “Global Health and the Scientific Research Agenda,” Phi-
losophy and Public Affairs 32 (2004): 36– 65, for a small selection from the statistics.
298 the ethica l project
miserable if she feels there is no chance of recovery (you know her well;
she is sensitive and liable to be crushed by dreadful news). She asks
you point-blank what the doctors have said. You are well prepared and
know you can convince her. Lying would avoid the bad consequences of
telling the truth.14
These examples have to be carefully constructed if they are to call
into question the universal goodness of truth telling. The potential de-
ceiver must be clearheaded, must have thought through the options, and
must have understood that there is no honest alternative to the decep-
tion. The officer at the door cannot be fobbed off with an evasive answer,
nor will your loved one be satisfied with even the most adroit attempt to
change the subject. This means the lie will probably have to be premedi-
tated and its expression carefully prepared—in general, conditions we
take to intensify the wrongness of a misdeed.
14. Thinkers inspired by Kant may claim that allowing any exceptions undermines the
practice of answering questions, or perhaps that it violates the integrity of the speaker, or
perhaps that the good requires that people always act in nonmanipulative ways. When the
odds are set very high, as they are in the case of the officer at the door, none of these replies
succeeds. The lie to the Gestapo officer is not going to undermine any important human
practice, even if all householders in similar situations behave in the same way. If the lies are
discovered, the investigating officials are likely to be more skeptical of what they are told
and hence may investigate more thoroughly—and that will have to be countered in future
practices of asylum granting—but these refugees will have been saved. The example of the
seriously sick illustrates the point very well. Those who are extremely ill know that people
who care about them will be inclined to spare them bad news. Knowledge of that sort does
not undermine any practice of questioning and answering but simply means they are more
suspicious than they would otherwise have been about what their loved ones tell them.
Many deontological traditions, religious as well as philosophical, have taken the bad-
ness of deception to consist in the corruption of the liar—in effect, they offer an account of
the good that gives priority to purity of heart and suppose telling a lie, even to promote
otherwise good ends, compromises this purity. Religious teachers and leaders have been
advised to respond to questions by discovering ambiguous or evasive or misleading (but
not outright false) answers or to take oaths with a private “reservatio.” Faced with the offi-
cer at the door, householders who spend time trying to discover a tricky way out are not so
much worthily protecting themselves from corruption as irresponsibly putting others at
risk. Even if the chances the officer will penetrate the cleverly evasive reply are slim, the
damage done by arousing his suspicions is too great to justify the maneuvers. Further, why
should we suppose that those who concentrate their effort on shielding vulnerable victims
they have taken in are somehow less pure than people whose first thoughts are divided be-
tween the threats to the refugees and their own rectitude?
Progress, Equality, and the Good 301
15. It is interesting to speculate about the length of time for which altruistic lying has
been possible—perhaps there are occasional analogs of the examples I have used that could
have arisen for the small groups of the Paleolithic—but it seems evident that concentrations
of power and advances in certain kinds of knowledge (medical knowledge, for instance)
generate clear cases with increased frequency.
302 the ethica l project
16. Mill’s treatment of the permissibility of lying appreciates these points. Convinced
that “all moralists” would allow for breaches of the prohibition against lying, he points to
just the cases I have used: “when the withholding of some fact (as of information from a
malefactor, or of bad news from a person dangerously ill) would preserve someone (espe-
cially a person other than oneself) from great and unmerited evil, and when the withhold-
ing can only be effected by denial” (Works, 10:223). He cautions, however, that not every
good consequence is sufficient to allow for lying, since we also have to take into account the
costs that permitted deception will entail: “inasmuch as any, even unintentional, deviation
from truth, does that much towards weakening the trustworthiness of human assertion,
which is not only the principal support of all present social well-being, but the insufficiency
of which does more than any one thing that can be named to keep back civilization” (Works,
10:223).
Progress, Equality, and the Good 303
17. That is, if A and B meet the interaction criterion, and if B and C do so as well, A and
C belong to the same community, irrespective of whether they also interact above the
threshold; the community consists of all the people who can be related to any of its mem-
bers through a chain whose adjacent members interact at a frequency above the threshold.
The minimal notion of interaction is one in which the behavior of one affects the choices
available and the prospects of success of the other.
304 the ethica l project
18. In framing the ideas that follow I have been helped by some acute observations and
questions from Erika Milam. There are also links to the framework proposed by Dewey in
The Public and Its Problems (Athens OH: Swallow Press, 1985).
Progress, Equality, and the Good 305
bers, can grow healthily. All extant ethical traditions count this as an
endorsable desire. Today, the actions of people in some areas of the
world interfere with the realization of such desires. Practices of com-
merce, agriculture, industry, and even medical research in affluent
countries decrease the probability that people in poorer regions will
be able to nurture healthy children.19 All members of our species face
the common problem of avoiding (further) environmental changes
that would dramatically disrupt human lives: global warming will,
almost certainly, make many heavily settled areas uninhabitable and
will leave many others vulnerable to extremities of weather that will
challenge available technologies of shelter. We urgently need a concep-
tion of the good that considers the desires of all people and that will
guide attempts to treat the problems engendered by a thoughtless indus-
trial past.
Causal interaction binds the entire human population together. The
altruism failures in that large community are dangerously magnified ver-
sions of those that prompted the first ventures in ethics. Pragmatic natu-
ralism’s proposal about the good gives priority to the continually more
extensive network of causal relations linking us all. It does not follow
that there is no place for more fine-grained partitions. There are issues
on which a local community could progressively elaborate a conception
of the common good by concentrating only on the desires of its members
and on remedying the altruism failures arising within it. The areas in
which this should occur, however, must be distinct from those covered
by more wide-ranging conceptions (ultimately by that conception that
takes the entire human population as its province): where there are seri-
ous consequences for distant others, there must be an attempt to respond
to them.20 Moreover, the local community’s explorations in this regard
are properly constrained by the vague central themes adduced as the
19. Commercial practices interfere with the supply of basic goods to the poorest areas of
the world; agriculture subordinates the task of feeding the hungry to considerations of
profit; industry squanders resources and neglects long-term energy needs; medical re-
search has, until quite recently, conspicuously neglected the problems of the poor.
20. Plainly, this proposal has links to Mill’s famous “harm principle” (On Liberty); even
more directly, it connects to Dewey’s reformulation in the opening chapter of The Public
and Its Problems.
306 the ethica l project
best candidates for ethical truth. Nevertheless, the pluralism already ac-
knowledged (§38) is recapitulated in the idea of domains in which pro-
gressive elaboration of the conception of the good can proceed through
responses to the desires present in a local community (one that is a
proper subset of the human population).
An important objection: focusing on the global human population
draws the boundary too narrowly. Other things—nonhuman animals,
or parts of the biological or inorganic environment, or human artifacts—
have ethical standing. I shall take the case of nonhuman animals as central
to the objection.
Ethical traditions disagree about the extent to which our conduct to-
ward nonhuman animals should be regulated. Almost everyone agrees,
however, that people should not arbitrarily inflict pain on mammals and
birds (igniting cats is usually viewed as cruel) and that pet owners should
attend to the needs of the animals they have acquired. Some hold that
farmers should not breed mammals and poultry under conditions of close
confinement that distort the animals’ normal patterns of development
and normal metabolic functioning; these critics often hold that consum-
ers should not buy and eat animals bred in these cruel ways. Yet others
suppose the entire practice of eating nonhuman animals—whether birds
and mammals, or all vertebrates, or all invertebrates into the bargain—
is wrong. A similar range of positions applies to using nonhuman animals
in medical experimentation.
The aim here is not to consider which position, if any, would be ad-
opted in a progressive transition from the current state of ethical prac-
tice, but to address the concern that no view of any of these types can
be reconciled with the framework of pragmatic naturalism. It suffices to
focus on the most minimal rules governing conduct toward nonhuman
animals, like the proscription of torturing mammals. What ethical func-
tion would be discharged by introducing any such prohibition into ethi-
cal practice?
It is worth recalling part of the history of ethical experimentation. For
a long period in the ethical project, human groups were very small; out-
siders were not covered by any of the protections afforded by the rules of
the band. The scope of the rules was extended when peaceful exchanges
with neighbors effectively created something akin to a broader society.
Progress, Equality, and the Good 307
“The circle expanded.”21 What occurs here is first that a set of interac-
tions takes place with people who have previously usually been avoided,
and second that failures to respond to some of their desires count as al-
truism failures. My “how possibly explanation” (§19) showed a way of
making that extension. Interactions are set up in an attempt to discharge
an ethical function (satisfying the endorsed desires of members of the
local group through trade), and the expansion of the rules fulfills an-
other function (the original function of remedying altruism failures;
some of the desires of the erstwhile outsiders correspond to endorsed
desires of group members, and not responding to these comes to count
as an altruism failure).
Is anything similar available in the case of nonhuman animals? Ap-
parently so. Just as the late Paleolithic witnessed first occasions of tran-
sient association among neighboring groups and later increases in band
size, so, at the very end of this period, people began to set up more regu-
lar patterns of association with some kinds of nonhuman animals. The
practice of domestication creates something like a society, one including
some nonhuman members. That practice refines the ethical function of
satisfying the endorsed desires of all. Yet, because the animals newly in-
cluded differ in some important properties from the people across the
river, obvious questions arise. Does this expansion really create any-
thing like a society? If so, to what extent can the rules adopted within
the local group be carried over to the new members?
In a minimal sense, a broader society is created simply in virtue of
recurrent patterns of interaction. Human beings feed their domestic ani-
mals, breed them, work them, and consume some of their biological
products. These interactions need to proceed in ways permitting a long
series of repetitions. Yet, because of asymmetries in power, that might
simply be done by brute force. If the “society” is simply constituted by
regular patterns of interaction, its stability requires no more than human
skill in confinement and handling.
21. As §33 observed, this is a prominent mode of ethical progress. Peter Singer’s title
“The Expanding Circle” expresses his conviction that this is the dominant mode of ethical
advance, and he argues that this expansion should bring nonhuman animals within the
scope of our ethical precepts.
308 the ethica l project
22. Hume saw this point clearly and drew a harsh conclusion. See Enquiry Concerning
the Principles of Morals (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1983), 25–26.
Progress, Equality, and the Good 309
23. The justification of blood sports would thus have to show that the hunted animals
are threatening in some way (foxes attack livestock) or that the activity of hunting serves
some important human purpose (plays an indispensable role in the maturing of young
men). I am extremely dubious that any such attempt at justification accords with reflection
on the conceptions of the good that have come down to us.
310 the ethica l project
potential discounting factors for risk and future possession) or have at-
tempted to analyze the common good without presupposing the compa-
rability of subjective experiences.24 One social situation is said to be su-
perior to another just in case there is no individual whose preference
satisfaction is diminished and at least one whose preference satisfaction
is enhanced. This perspective has been the starting point for some of the
most brilliant and illuminating work in theoretical social science and in
social and political philosophy of the past century.25
Existing consequentialist theoretical traditions offer conceptions of
the good in three distinct forms:
24. Lurking behind all this are methodological ideas that have sometimes played a use-
ful role in inquiry (through connecting hypotheses with potential tests and observations)
but that have often hardened into restrictive dogma (most evident, perhaps, in some kinds
of behaviorist psychology). Significant parts of economics and social theory remain in the
grip of sclerotic operationalism, even though its philosophical credentials have long been
subject to important critiques.
25. Kenneth Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values (Hoboken, NJ: Wiley, 1951);
Amartya Sen, Collective Choice and Social Welfare (San Francisco: Holden-Day, 1970);
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971).
26. It is worth reflecting on the extraordinary combination of a very crude basic mea-
sure of goodness (number of survivors) with the excessively refi ned concentration on
wildly contrary-to-fact hypothetical examples (trolley problems) so evident in some philo-
sophical fashions.
Progress, Equality, and the Good 313
32. Much of the time, Mill endorses this proposal, thinking of human progress as
making the good life ever more widely available. This is evident in the famous phrase
from On Liberty, “the permanent interests of man as a progressive being,” as well as in
the closing pages of the System of Logic, John Stuart Mill, System of Logic (London:
Longmans Green, 1959). It is crucial to the egalitarian concerns of Principles of Political
Economy.
33. Thus, Mill’s emphasis on choosing one’s own plan of life takes precedence over the
very specific ways in which, as an extraordinarily educated man, he conceived of his own
life as obtaining point.
34. Mill’s writings make this advance in many places. The most well-known occur in
On Liberty, particularly in chaps. 1 and 3.
316 the ethica l project
human beings struggle to satisfy their basic desires, 35 the young will be
invited to draw on the ways of living of many different predecessors to
formulate a conception of what matters for them.
This embryonic account of the good life will be developed a little fur-
ther (§50). The immediate task is to see how an account of this sort could
remedy the inadequacies of the conceptions of the good so far consid-
ered. Taking the notion of the good life as central, understood in the
ways just outlined, preserves the insight offered by conception D, while
rejecting the massively false presuppositions of the various religious
articulations of it. The holistic assessment of lives is primary, and positive
evaluation depends on there being a structure, freely adopted by the in-
dividual and, subsequent to that, on the kinds of satisfactions of desire
figuring in conception C, and tacitly in conceptions A and B as well.
This possibility arises only at a particular stage in human develop-
ment—it requires progress beyond the conditions dominant in the early
phases of the ethical project (§20). There are preconditions, some mate-
rial, some social, for any state in which holistic evaluation can come into
play. When life and health are constantly threatened, it is difficult, if not
impossible, to explore possibilities to fashion one’s own life pattern.
People must be able to interact peacefully with one another (and with
outsiders). Furthermore, if their life projects are to have serious chances
of success, they will need not only the toleration of those around them
but also active cooperation with their fellows.
Consider an imaginary social state: Utopia. In this state, each mem-
ber of the human population has a serious chance of living a good life, a
life in which the person can recognize a number of different possibilities
for living, can make a free choice of a project informed by that recogni-
tion, and realize a significant number of the plans, intentions, and desires
central to that project; moreover, the chances of living such lives are equal
across the population. Where the conditions of human life allow no seri-
ous chance of bringing about Utopia, it cannot figure in the theory of the
good. The good evolves, and this is an ideal available to us, but not to
our ancestors.
35. A condition Mill characterizes as the “puerile” condition of mankind; closing para-
graphs of System of Logic.
Progress, Equality, and the Good 317
36. Some small societies in the contemporary world have preserved the emphasis on
equality, but they lack any serious possibilities for achieving the richer versions of the good
life available to some members of other societies.
318 the ethica l project
37. See, for example, Jeff rey Sachs, The End of Poverty (New York: Penguin, 2005).
Progress, Equality, and the Good 319
38. See Amartya Sen, Development as Freedom (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press,
1999), esp. 217ff.
320 the ethica l project
would impoverish the lucky few who actually happen to enjoy richer
prospects for their lives, in a quixotic venture of trying to satisfy every-
one’s most basic needs. That worry has been allayed by limiting the size
of the human population. Can Malthusian restraint be achieved with-
out threatening the quality of the lives of individual people and fami-
lies? Quite reasonably, the skeptic insists that begetting and rearing
children is central to many people’s conceptions of what matters most
to them: consequently, confining the human population to the proper
bound directly and dramatically reduces the chances for good lives.
There are two ways to articulate the objection. One contends that, in a
population already at or below the proper bound, maintaining that popu-
lation size would significantly limit the quality of human lives. A more
modest version argues that any possible route to a population below the
proper bound requires diminishing the quality of life for the generations
traversing that route.
Although family life is central to many people’s conceptions of their
lives, it does not follow that limiting family size must interfere with their
prospects for a good life. As an elementary consequence of the biology
of reproduction, in a world where no couple produced more than two
children, the human population could not increase (and would almost
certainly decline). Thus, the stronger objection can be sustained only if
an ethical restriction of family size to two children excludes the oppor-
tunity for a good life. Plainly, smaller families are vulnerable to contin-
gent events that might diminish the quality of the lives of their members—
because of the impact of the death or disability of children. Nonetheless,
larger family size offers no guarantee against such contingencies, nor
can it necessarily relieve the pain accompanying the death of a child:
children are not intersubstitutable. 39 The most skeptics can rightly
conclude is that an ethical constraint on family size might lower some
people’s chances for a good life, through increased susceptibility to
hostile fortune. In worlds where the human population is maintained
at or below the proper bound, however, an equitable distribution of
39. It should be recognized, however, that the loss of all one’s children, as in cases
where all are killed in war, does strike people as especially tragic. That reinforces the
thought that smaller families are more vulnerable to the whims of fortune.
Progress, Equality, and the Good 321
40. The seminal work here is part 4 of Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford, UK:
Oxford University Press, 1984). Parfit’s brilliant posing of the problem has inspired many
efforts to solve it.
Progress, Equality, and the Good 323
subordinate dimension are relevant only insofar as they affect the pos-
sibility of doing well on the primary dimension. The formal approach
fits the progressivist and egalitarian aspects of pragmatic naturalism’s
conception of the good. The initial conceptions of the good are di-
rected at obtaining high values on the continuous dimension; later, high-
enough values can be achieved for all to make richer considerations of
living well come into play; thereafter, the good is achieved by realizing
the opportunity for all human beings to have a chance at a good life, and,
beyond that, by trying to increase the number of those who succeed in
living well.
42. In shaping the conception, and in the formulation given here, my debts to Mill, and
secondarily to Dewey, should be apparent.
43. One might think that our freedom in this regard is always enhanced through the
articulation of further possibilities, so that, the more “experiments of living” someone can
conceive, the more the choice is autonomous. As a matter of psychological fact, I doubt that
this is correct. Too many options can be overwhelming. It remains true that radically new
potential ways of living can show us opportunities that had previously been beyond our
horizons, so that Mill’s plea for further experiments remains cogent.
326 the ethica l project
One par tic u lar way in which some religions have distorted our
conception of the human good is by allowing for possibilities of valu-
able lives detached from other people. Solitary communion with tran-
scendent beings (or with the universe), exemplified by hermits who
live in remote places or those who pledge themselves to silence, is
viewed as one way of living a good life. The source of the value here is
surely the attunement of the individual psyche to the transcendent,
and when the myths about the transcendental realm are abandoned,
the idea that lives can be made significant in this way should go too. It
is equally important to repudiate secular ways in which this distort-
ing idea continues to manifest itself. Some of the most militant oppo-
nents of the world’s religions commend participation in the project of
understanding the natural world as an especially valuable way to live.44
Although there is an important insight here, it needs to be carefully
understood. The great discoverers achieve two things: they enjoy private
states of recognizing hitherto uncomprehended aspects of nature, and
they facilitate the understanding of others. The states of understand-
ing, while superior to the momentary satisfactions of the hermits (be-
cause based on genuine achievement rather than on illusion), are not
the primary determinant of the value of the discoverer’s life. Instead,
value accrues through the contribution to understanding on the part
of others.
To take this perspective is to emphasize the centrality to the good life
of our relationships with other people and of our contributions to their
lives. Refined theoretical contemplation has its place among the catalog
of factors that promote the good life precisely because of its potential to
promote the value of good lives. Consequently, the life of the priest or
scientist, the doctor or nurse, the teacher or social organizer, the tireless
participant in the maintenance of community and family, become valu-
able in similar ways, through the various human relationships the per-
son’s actions sustain. The emphasis on individual freedom, on the abil-
44. This is prominent in the writings of Richard Dawkins, Unweaving the Rainbow
(Boston: Houghton Miffl in, 1998). But the idea is very old—Aristotle’s fi nal chapter of the
Nicomachean Ethics, (Terence Irwin trans. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1999) sounds a similar
theme.
Progress, Equality, and the Good 327
45. Thus Dewey advances on the Millian formula from On Liberty, when he opens The
Public and Its Problems by posing the issue in terms of the freedom from coercion of joint
projects.
328 the ethica l project
obtains its significance from effects on, or more exactly contributions to,
the lives of others. We miss also the important point that, independent of
any large-scale public success, lives may be interlocked in mutual depen-
dence and mutual contribution and thus be genuinely and completely
worthwhile.
From the moment at which the issue of how to live well surfaced
among the ancients, it has been vulnerable to three types of major error.
The hedonist mistake is to decompose our lives into sequences of mo-
mentary experiences and measure value by the balance of pleasures and
pains. The individualist mistake, prominent in some religious traditions
but also retained in some versions of secularism, proposes that some
particular nonsocial condition of the individual—the receipt of divine
grace, the making of great discoveries, the amassing of wealth—is the
major source of value. The elitist mistake, already evident in the restric-
tion of the question to the male aristocrats of the polis, is to suppose that
something very large and uncommon is a precondition of a life’s going
well. By contrast, in the approach I have taken, good lives are in princi-
ple available to almost all members of our species.46 Philosophers tend
to talk grandly of “life projects,” as if the good life required both a type
of intellectual reflection and an exalted focus that can be managed by
only a select few. Instead, I offer a schematic account of the good life that
celebrates the ordinary. Although in almost all places at almost all times,
people have been coerced or led into lives that should not be counted as
worthwhile, what they have lacked are certain basic forms of freedom,
everyday awareness of possibilities, not exceptional resources or un-
usual talents. Moreover, in many times and places, ordinary people whose
lives are permeated by actions with and for others have sometimes, if not
often, lived well.
I have pointed only to aspects of the good life: freedom of choice, lack
of deontological encumbrance (most evidently the distortions of reli-
gions), joint activity and reciprocal relationships with others. To indi-
46. The exceptions are those whose cognitive and emotional possibilities cut them off
from fully developed relationships with others. This is, I believe, why we fi nd prenatal ge-
netic testing for some sorts of traits a merciful way of proceeding. I have discussed these
questions in more detail in the later chapters of The Lives to Come (New York: Simon and
Schuster, 1996).
Progress, Equality, and the Good 329
Method in Ethics
330
Method in Ethics 331
is interrupted, and you must decide if the maxim has sufficient force to
suspend it.2 Deliberation need not lead to any modification—for the
code, as it stands, may give a clear directive; it may, for example, pro-
nounce on the importance of giving aid to people in the predicament you
see before you, assigning that priority over the role-associated duties.
Yet though episodes of this sort need not lead to ontogenetic change,
they can do so.
Imagine your habitual performance is interrupted, and you are brought
to think about how to go on. You canvass the code you presently endorse,
but there is no unambiguous result. Perhaps there are conflicting vague
maxims with no clear priority. Reflecting on other facets of the code, and
emotionally reacting to the situation, you introduce a priority, perhaps
making one or both of the maxims more precise than they previously
were. The judgment about what to do remains stable in the aftermath of
your action. As you explain what you have done to others, particularly
to those your action affected, their reactions do not prompt a change of
mind. From this point on, the claim about relative priority and the some-
what sharpened maxim(s) belong to your code.
Other types of ontogenetic change do not begin with thoughtful de-
liberation. Your ethical code contains no prohibition against speaking
in a par ticu lar way to members of a par ticu lar class. You are accus-
tomed to talk that way, until one day your remarks are met with protest.
Somebody affected by your words shows you, convincingly, how pain-
ful it is for him, and, in appealing to the authority of the code, you feel
your response is feeble. Suddenly and unexpectedly, you are moved to
sympathy with a person whom you have previously seen under the
shadow of a label, and your regret about what you said translates into a
resolution not to repeat such phrases. You have modified your ethical
code by inserting a prohibition where there was none before. The inter-
actions that fuel changes like this are dim echoes of the original ethical
discussions.
For most people all the ontogenetic changes made in ethical codes, and
for all people most of the ontogenetic changes made in ethical codes,
2. See Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 2002),
52ff., 103–5.
Method in Ethics 333
are normal changes. 3 Given the ethical resources she has, an agent faces
a puzzle, and the ontogenetic changes she makes are the products of her
efforts to solve the puzzle. One cannot, of course, speak of a “solution”
to a puzzle, without some standard of correctness: what makes life hard
for the agent is the sense that there is some way of going on that is right
and others that are not. People do not seek “mere change.” Although
ethical lives are largely matters of following the precepts and patterns of
our ethical codes, they are also—and importantly—ventures in trying to
improve those codes, by recognizing and solving puzzles that arise for
us. As individuals, we solve puzzles by making progressive shifts in the
codes to which we subscribe. Normal ethical change consists in attempts
to find a way to amend or extend the code, one refining the functions at
which it is directed.4 Puzzles arise within an ethical practice in which
a particular set of functions is to be discharged; a solution to a puzzle
modifies the code so that some of these functions are better served and
none is worse served. Puzzle solving occurs only when there is no func-
tional conflict (§36). Revolutionary change, by contrast, is marked by the
presence of functional conflict.
How can normal phylogenetic change occur? Perhaps as the product
of uncoordinated ontogenetic changes (although this would be highly
unlikely at early stages of the ethical project). Imagine most people encoun-
ter a type of situation where the ethical code they endorse fails to provide
clear counsel; through these encounters, they amend their codes in simi-
lar ways; in the next generation, the lore passed down from parents to
children absorbs the modifications, and, because the amendments are so
similar, the parental advice is reinforced in wider socialization. Yet if a
type of situation arises frequently, challenging individuals to articulate
their ethical code through puzzle solving, a public response can occur.
Especially when people respond differently, ethicists—including social
critics, religious teachers, and individuals with intimate knowledge of
5. Appeal to religious texts is highly unlikely to satisfy this constraint on public ethical
discussion, since there is no positive correlation between the deliverances of those texts
and the refi nement of major ethical functions. In fact there is probably a negative
correlation.
6. A classical discussion of this method is given by John Rawls, A Theory of Justice
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 18–19, 42–45.
Method in Ethics 335
7. Many of the “thought experiments” beloved of analytic ethics provoke serious doubt
whether responses express any socially inculcated skill. The situations are too remote from
the mundane situations in which ethical judgment is exercised. I am grateful to Gerd
Gigerenzer for discussion of this point.
8. This was probably so for some codes considered in Chapter 6: the Greek honor code
and the Puritan code defending slavery seem systematically blind to the bungling of the
original function of ethics.
9. One carried out with great skill in the writings of some phi losophers, for example,
John Rawls, Thomas Nagel, and Peter Singer.
336 the ethica l project
at rules all could accept. It will be useful to have a term for these condi-
tions: call them the circumstances of mutual engagement. Mutual en-
gagement was well-suited to finding a solution to the social problems
generating the ethical project. Acquainting group members with the
needs and difficulties of their fellows, giving them equal status in the
conversation, and aiming at solutions everyone can endorse constitutes a
good strategy for coping with the altruism failures manifested in social
tension.
Chapter 8 proposed to renew the original function of ethics and scale
up the initial conception of the good. Likewise, our ethical method, for
use in cases of revolutionary change, can scale up the original method of
the fi rst ethicists. We should seek a notion of mutual engagement as
well suited to the renewed ethical project as the original version of mutual
engagement—the deliberations among band members—was to the origi-
nal venture. We need an analog of those constructive conversations out
of which the earliest rules for conduct emerged.
On the face of it, this suggestion must appear ludicrous, for any
actual conversation among all affected individuals—that is, among all
human beings—is impossible. Public ethical deliberation, however, can
proceed by attempting to simulate a conversation of the pertinent kind.
Faced with functional conflict, so revolutionary change is in order,
public contributors to ethical discussion are judged by their ability to
ground their proposals in mutual engagement: that is, to introduce the
considerations and lines of reasoning that would be brought forward to
achieve consensus were the entire human population to participate,
under conditions of mutual engagement, in a conversation about the
regulation of conduct. The italicized phrase is crucial here. An ethical
discussion seeking to replicate the conversation that would occur if the
entire human population were simply brought together in some vast
arena would be a useless exercise in cacophony. Because of their exist-
ing dispositions to psychological altruism, limited though these were,
because of the pressures on the group and the perceived need for joint
action, the original ethicists were forced into mutual engagement with
people who lived beside them every day. For us, however, mutual en-
gagement is not automatic (except with respect to small subsets of the
human population). If the proposal about ethical method is to have
Method in Ethics 341
10. As we shall see in the next section, this is too crude as it stands. But the crude ver-
sion will help to bring out the potential problem of circularity.
342 the ethica l project
11. This is a major theme in Dewey’s writings; see, for example, chaps. 9 and 10 of The
Quest for Certainty John Dewey: The Later Works, vol. 4 (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illi-
nois University Press, 1984).
Method in Ethics 343
12. Dewey emphasizes the comparison. See, for example, Quest for Certainty.
13. For the moment I focus on what may appear to be the implausible thought of perfect
consensus. Later, this requirement will be relaxed.
344 the ethica l project
I postpone issues about how one might apply any such standard, through
testing (confirming, refuting) claims that replication of an ideal delibera-
tion has been achieved.
Now to the concept of mutual engagement that lies at the heart of
these standards. The conditions of mutual engagement are partly cogni-
tive and partly affective (and in this they resemble the dimensions of
psychological altruism, §5). The first cognitive condition eliminates any
erroneous factual beliefs from the ideal conversation:
This condition seems innocuous and well motivated, for it appears that
consensus achieved on the basis of error would be problematic—a group
of intensely altruistic people would arrive at quite peculiar conclusions if
they assumed that extremely severe pain has all sorts of wonderful con-
sequences for sufferers. (KE) entails that the aspirations and wishes the
participants form, and the premises from which they reason, must be
thoroughly secular. They cannot announce that certain actions are re-
quired or forbidden, or certain elements characteristic of the highest
good, on the grounds that there is a transcendent being who commands
us in the relevant ways or who offers us an infinitely valuable immortal-
ity. Positive beliefs in transcendent beings, and in the arrangements such
beings make, are errors that cannot be permitted to distort the ideal
conversation.14
14. Unlike some contractarian writers (Rawls, Scanlon), I exclude appeals to literalist
readings of religious texts not because they introduce reasons not all participants share,
but because they are simply false. (KE) embodies the idea that false beliefs will distort the
Method in Ethics 345
15. Here I draw on ideas present in the eighteenth- century sentimentalist tradition,
notably in Smith’s theory of moral sentiments. I have explored the mirroring metaphor,
as he develops it, in “The Hall of Mirrors,” Proceedings and Addresses of the American
Philosophical Association 79, no. 2 (2005): 67– 84. As with the original discussion
of psychological altruism in §§3– 5, my formulations of conditions here incline to a
position that attributes conscious recognition of the states of others. It is possible, how-
ever, that human beings sometimes engage with the feelings of those around them in
more automatic ways (perhaps through the activity of mirror neurons). The account of
mutual engagement is easily amended to permit any mechanisms of this sort to play a
role.
16. The notion of a solitary desire was introduced in §3. Notice that I am not distin-
guishing A’s perception of B’s solitary desire from B’s solitary desire itself, since, under the
cognitive conditions of the ideal conversation, A has an accurate understanding of B’s
desires.
Method in Ethics 347
17. Since we are concerned here only with solitary desires, the relevant constraint from
(KC) is that the participant would continue to desire what he or she actually does, if the
participant knew all the consequences for him- or herself.
18. This is effectively to construct an analog of the “ideal spectator,” but one informed
by extensive factual knowledge. It articulates further the synthesis of the methodological
ideas of Smith and Dewey I propose in “The Hall of Mirrors.”
348 the ethica l project
19. This apparently optimistic thought about possible consensus will be modified
in §55.
Method in Ethics 349
plaint about revolutionary ethical change would insist that there is noth-
ing for ethical discussion to do when functional conflict arises, that
spoken or written words can be only the expression of an attitude others
are free to reject. By contrast, there is plenty to be said, much that can be
done to expose factual errors and false presuppositions, disharmonies
with background features of the prevalent ethical code, and, most im-
portant, shortcomings in accommodating the wishes of classes of other
people—failures of mutual engagement.
In the next sections, I attempt to show how this approach to ethical
method might sometimes manage to achieve consensus (and also con-
sider appropriate conclusions when consensus proves unreachable). First,
however, I acknowledge the considerable idealizations introduced and
examine how, given our limited perspectives, actual ethical discussions
might be assessed.
20. Here I suggest a parallel to Kuhn’s claims that normal science may break down as
repeated efforts to solve puzzles fail, so what appeared as a puzzle becomes seen as an
anomaly.
350 the ethica l project
products of labor along roughly egalitarian lines will interfere with mo-
tivation to work, and consequently with production. These claims
about the effects of general types of social arrangement—types includ-
ing a wide variety of possible implementations—are sometimes sup-
ported by assuming psychological generalizations, sometimes but-
tressed by mentioning a handful of specific historical cases.21 The
psychology invoked is simplistic, and the sample of instances ludi-
crously small. A genuine test of rival ethical proposals, with their vari-
ant conceptions of the consequences for people who live in quite differ-
ent situations, requires either further work in relevant social sciences
or a direct experiment.
Some hypotheses about the consequences of social arrangements
could be confirmed or disconfirmed through indirect investigations.
Without attempting to create conditions under which economic incen-
tives, claimed to be crucial for motivation to work, were absent, one
might aim for a general theory of human motivation, testing it in labora-
tory experiments or in existing social situations, and then deriving
from it some conclusion about likely behavior under hypothetical egali-
tarian conditions. When that strategy is considered more thoroughly,
however, it seems unlikely to resolve the question: any combination
of laboratory and field studies would be inadequate to the full range
of possibilities for realizing an egalitarian ideal. If that is so, the only
chance of replacing our— ethically crucial—ignorance about conse-
quences is to bring about the conditions egalitarians envisage and see
what happens. Rational ethical debate may require further experiments
of living.22
21. Adam Smith and John Stuart Mill disagree about the first issue (Smith holding that
increased rates of production will translate into increased economic benefits for all, Mill
maintaining that distribution is not an immediate effect of increased productivity), but they
are united on the second. Smith, Wealth of Nations (New York: Modern Library, 2000), bk.
1, chap. 8; Mill, Works, 2 [Principles of Political Economy (Toronto: University of Toronto
Press, 1970), bk. 2, chaps. 1–2]. With respect to this latter question, both appeal to a simple
generalization about human motivation. Contemporary critics of egalitarianism are fond of
mentioning the prominent instances in which they take egalitarian ideas to have been ap-
plied, and they conclude from a few failures that all ways of implementing egalitarian
ideals are doomed.
22. Mill envisages this possibility, and it is emphasized even more strongly by Dewey.
352 the ethica l project
23. With respect to egalitarian experiments, there is a tendency to overlook some of the
small societies that achieved partial success (Robert Owen’s Lanark colony), or that were
set at a disadvantage because of relations to other communities (the Diggers and Levellers
in Britain, the Israeli kibbutzim).
24. Hume is rightly criticized for the parochialism of his remarks that we can reconstruct
the wishes of temporally and spatially distant people by considering our acquaintances—
but it is far from obvious that anyone (including Hume’s critics) really avoids partiality on
this issue.
Method in Ethics 353
25. Here I am indebted to discussions with Moira Gatens and to her illuminating work
on imaginative knowledge in philosophy and literature.
26. Perhaps the most striking instance is the description of the life of Jo, the crossing
sweeper in Bleak House. But there are many others.
354 the ethica l project
27. For details, see chap. 7 of my Advancement of Science (New York: Oxford University
Press, 1993).
Method in Ethics 355
about crucial issues, problems that have highest priority, involve the
same sort of “balancing” as that found in the schematic account of
extended mirroring. In the scientific cases, we are often confident that
some proposals for “balancing,” some claims about the truly crucial prob-
lems, are defensible and others are not. Our contemporary views about
the evolution of life do not resolve every issue in the domain, and yet
considerations of the “balance” of successes and failures demonstrate
how vastly more successful these views are, in comparison with the posi-
tions invoked as challenges to them; it is no less reasonable to judge that
Darwinism solves a huge number of significant problems that its rivals
do not, than it is to prefer a clean, well-maintained car to a rusty clunker
whose only virtue is its fetching hood ornament. “Balance” resists pre-
cise definition in the scientific case, and that should caution us against
demanding more in the ethical sphere.28
I have tried to counter the impression that any search for method to
deal with revolutionary change is hopeless. We cannot tell how far we
can get until we make a serious attempt at a complicated and taxing ven-
ture (one requiring considerable pooling of ideas and recognition of
alternative perspectives). Yet it is worth considering, in advance, not only
the cases in which consensus can be reached, but also those in which it
cannot.
28. The earliest efforts to specify methods of scientific confirmation were schematic and
imprecise. More specific formulations emerged from attempts to put those preliminary
conceptions to work. Thoughts about method coevolve with discoveries about the natural
world. I envisage a similar process in the ethical sphere: attempts to elaborate the method
will yield more precise versions of it.
356 the ethica l project
situation may thus be one of functional conflict, and, for both traditions,
the confl ict may be resoluble in alternative ways. Because there is no
ultimate resolution here, because we can envisage a progressive sequence
of changes, proceeding indefi nitely without convergence, it would be
wrong to require a method for revolutionary change always to achieve con-
sensus. Even an ideal conversation should sometimes leave participants
with alternatives.
Furthermore, even along the route to full consensus, even with re-
spect to ethical debates allowing eventual resolution, there are likely to
be intermediate stages at which agreement cannot be forced. Conse-
quences hard to predict might be recognized through direct ethical ex-
perimentation. To carry out such experiments is, in effect, to fragment
a previously united community (although the fragmentation is initially
conceived as an intermediate step toward resolution of a debated ques-
tion). As such experiments are envisaged, how they are to be conducted
will itself be a matter for ethical reflection, and the considerations in-
volved here are the same as those figuring in appraisal of the relations
among rival ethical traditions. For in both instances, questions arise
about the extent to which consensus must be sought or difference toler-
ated. These questions may be focused by asking when a single commu-
nity debating a question of revolutionary change can properly allow
division into two subgroups that adopt alternative answers.
Imagine a discussion, under the conditions of mutual engagement,
that has given rise to two rival parties whose differences cannot cur-
rently be resolved. Perhaps this comes about because there are facts
about the consequences of the alternative proposals espoused by these
parties, facts not determined by the available body of knowledge, and
because the only way members of the society can envisage settling these
facts is the route of direct experimentation. Or perhaps it is the product
of different ways of extended mirroring, the result of alternative concep-
tions of how to balance the desires of group members (desires conform-
ing to the cognitive and affective conditions of §53). Each party regards
the other as espousing an incorrect (or an inferior) modification of their
shared current ethical practice. They recognize, however, that no com-
pelling ways of showing the mistake (the inferiority) are at hand, nothing
can be done to show the factual error (fi rst case), nothing can be said
Method in Ethics 357
29. The treatment of honesty in §46 argued that there are exceptional instances and that
the core truth is thus vague. One can envisage rival ethical traditions proposing different
more precise versions of it, but abandonment of it would be ruled out by the method sug-
gested here.
Method in Ethics 359
her socialization and education have elicited her wants. If she were to
see clearly how her options have been narrowed from the beginning, if
others who care about her were to understand how there were alternative
possibilities for her, the desires held by her and by them would be quite
different. The actual desires owe their presence to a pervasive error, the
mistaken belief that the existing processes of socialization are non-
coercive. Consequently, there is a failure of mutual engagement: in effect,
those who have led her to her present state have engaged not with her but
with their preconceived image of her. Only in the case of people who,
under alternative schemes of socialization, would remain entirely un-
concerned by thinking their choices had been narrowly foreclosed from
the beginning can one suppose that the desire is uninfected by error.
There may be such people, but we have every reason to think that they
are rare.
Discussion of such cases exposes an important facet of the limits of
tolerance, one best illustrated by considering the permissibility of ethi-
cal experiments. The last section envisaged groups, moved by an egali-
tarian ideal, trying out their preferred versions of it. If those who sign
on to the experiment are coerced, either through the overriding of their
present desires or through prior socialization that has narrowed their
choices, the experiment will not accord with the conditions of mutual
engagement. At times, however, people voluntarily resolve—by our every-
day standards of voluntary choice—to undertake this kind of venture.
There is a danger they will coerce others, in particular their children. The
forms of coercion making the examples of confining social practices sub-
ject to ethical critique may be absent in the first generation, but they can
easily emerge thereafter. Do all ethical experiments under mutual engage-
ment have to be short-term?
To avoid that conclusion the education and socialization of the young
must carefully preserve options. The experiment should allow children
to choose from as wide a range of alternatives as those available to their
peers, whose parents and teachers are not part of the experiment. The
experimenters must recognize and tolerate their children’s opting out—
and, perhaps, others’ opting in. As a result, some possibilities for living
(forms of family relationships) may be distorted, a distortion to be recog-
nized if the probative value of the experiment is to be properly assessed.
360 the ethica l project
30. Whether it will also justify outside pressure to amend the practices, or even the use
of force, is a further question, one that would have to be settled by looking carefully at the
details in individual instances. To justify ethical criticism is not yet to warrant particu lar
ways of translating the criticism into action.
31. That is, he concedes the story as I have narrated it. The challenger, shortly to be
identified as a version of Nietzsche, might prefer an alternative account, one viewing the
emphasis on cooperation as a late corruption [see the first essay of Friedrich Nietzsche On
the Genealogy of Morality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007)].
Method in Ethics 361
32. The challenger may even flaunt this rejection, comparing the masses whose desires
are ignored or crushed to lambs that serve as prey for stronger, “nobler” beasts. See the fa-
mous image from Genealogy of Morality, essay 1, sec. 13.
362 the ethica l project
33. One way in which my conclusion here might be resisted would be to argue that set-
ting bounds on the population is incompatible with major components of worthwhile lives.
This line of reasoning was already considered in §49, in confronting a form of skepticism,
and I rely on the response developed there.
Method in Ethics 365
have to ascribe low weight to the wishes of the Diminished, and exactly
the same problem would arise. Thus, the only way for extended mirror-
ing to generate the inegalitarian desires is for a failure of primitive mir-
roring to occur somewhere among the class of the deliberators—and
that means that the discussion cannot satisfy the conditions of mutual
engagement.
Application of the method of §53 is likely to yield pragmatic natural-
ism’s conception of the good, as the provision for all of serious, and
roughly equal, chances for worthwhile lives. Further, the conception
of human relationships as central elements in worthwhile human lives
can be viewed as in harmony with the method’s insistence on the con-
ditions of mutual engagement. Yet the conclusion should not be over-
stated. Any rehearsal of an ideal conversation must appeal to psycho-
logical assumptions about human reactions, and these can be falsified
by actual reactions to the line of reasoning people are supposed to
adopt. In advance of those reactions, a tentative conclusion: pragmatic
naturalism’s proposal about the good coheres with its view of ethical
method.
Turn now to the challenger’s position. The challenger’s conception of
the good sees the development of the few as crucial and the lives of the
many as unimportant. There are special people—call them “free spirits”—
supposed to be capable of a form of human existence superior to any
attainable by the rest. A world is good to the extent that it allows for the full
development of the free spirits; what happens to the others is irrelevant.
This conception is evidently incompatible with the conception offered
in Chapter 8, and the incompatibility descends from a difference about
the functions the ethical project is to discharge. The egalitarian concep-
tion is embedded in an attempt to take the original function as primary,
to see ethics as continuing to be directed at remedying altruism failures
(and to view ethical method as an attempt at mutual engagement). Its ri-
val views the original function of ethics as a trigger that eventually led to
enhanced possibilities of human living. Whereas the egalitarian concep-
tion attempts to integrate the emergent possibilities with the original
function (through the focus on equal opportunities for worthwhile lives),
the challenger takes the emergence of the richer possibilities to be a turn-
ing point, after which the original function can be forgotten, in favor of
366 the ethica l project
34. As Plato already did. The thought of concentrating on biological heredity is central
to his way of providing different courses of education for differently talented people [Re-
public (trans Grube) (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1992)]. Yet Plato understands that this will at
best be an approximation: golden children can emerge from leaden parents, and golden
parents can produce baser offspring.
368 the ethica l project
When the ethical community becomes the entire species, all the in-
volved parties can no longer sit down together and discuss potential
modifications to a shared code. Socialization of the young can no longer
stop with transmitting the code as it has been passed on, leaving its fur-
ther evolution to conversations in which they will engage with one an-
other. At least some people in each generation, perhaps the entire cohort,
need to understand what the ideal of mutual engagement is and how
they might exemplify it. The proposals of the last two chapters call for
further proposals about ethical education.
The cognitive conditions on mutual engagement require recognition
of the predicaments of others. In many affluent societies, the general idea
of learning about people who live under very different circumstances
receives official approval, but, for serious ethical discussion, it deserves
more systematic emphasis. Young people need to acquire vivid knowl-
edge of a range of lives lived by their fellows. They should be conscious
also that their power of vivid representation reveals only a sample of the
actual forms of contemporary existence. When they reflect on proposals
for action, they should be aware of how those proposals would be felt by
people whose situations are very different from their own. If they eventu-
ally conclude that nothing can be done to improve the predicaments of
the less fortunate, they should do so with an intimate understanding of
how the neglect would be experienced. The aspirations of others should
be present in their own psychological lives.
Education should also foster an ability to satisfy the affective condi-
tions of mutual engagement. Besides a general encouragement of empa-
thy, potential deliberators need an ability to shape altruistic responses
along the lines of the inherited ethical code, to recognize endorsable and
contaminated desires, insofar as these have been discriminated. They
should have practice in mirroring, in contemplating an outcome from
various angles. They should become aware of the value of higher-order
altruism. All these skills can be developed by simulating the early phases
of the ethical project. Children can learn, from early in their lives, how to
work out a life with others, to find their way to rules all can accept—and
they can experience the joys of fluent cooperative interactions according
to those rules, as they attune their own conduct to that of their peers.
Although some issues, most notably the custody of our planet, arise at
a specieswide level, others can be negotiated by smaller groups, and these
372 the ethica l project
1. The secular humanism I defend cannot be a purely negative position, one that stops
with the declaration that religion is bunk. For elaboration of the point, see the closing
pages of my Living with Darwin (New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), as well as
some further essays [“Beyond Disbelief” in Russell Blackford and Udo Schüklenk (eds)
Fifty Voices of Disbelief (Oxford: Blackwell, 2009), “Challenges for Secularism” in George
Levine (ed) The Joy of Secularism (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2011), and
“Militant Modern Atheism” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 28, 2011].
Renewing the Project 373
2. See James Flory and Philip Kitcher, “Global Health and the Scientific Research
Agenda,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 32 (2004): 36– 65.
376 the ethica l project
3. To cite just one example, techniques for genetically manipulating crops might dra-
matically increase the sustainable food supply in the parts of the world most subject to
famine, if agricultural companies were less concerned to secure an indefi nite return of
large profits by modifying plants so poor farmers could not harvest their own seeds.
Renewing the Project 377
of the proper modes of sharing scarce resources, like access to the best
schools and universities, proceeds by guesswork.
That said, the ways of considering the issue adopted by educational
institutions and by policy advisers are not entirely bad. Instead of trying
to draw conclusions from abstract philosophical principles, they typi-
cally proceed by involving a number of people who represent different
points of view. Procedures of this sort can be regarded as an approxima-
tion to pragmatic naturalism’s method—even though they fall far short of
the ideal conditions of mutual engagement. There are obvious ways of
improving them: the population of those represented in the conversation
could be far more varied and far less skewed toward the affluent than is
currently the case; the deliberators could make far greater efforts toward
understanding rival perspectives; and they could benefit from experi-
ments to resolve questions currently answered by guessing.
Issues about scarce medical resources seem simpler. A society com-
mitted to offering health care for all its citizens must consider the ways in
which a budget of medical resources is to be divided up. Focusing on
giving equal opportunities for a worthwhile life inspires the proposal
that preventative procedures promoting health in childhood and matu-
rity are more important than late rescue efforts enabling old people to
hang on for a few weeks or months at greatly reduced capacity. Accept-
ing that proposal would reshape the character of medical expenditure in
the United States, in which, at present, half of the money spent on a
person’s health is expended in the last years of life.5 One might even go
further, proposing that, for some elderly patients, the principal task of
medical care is to ease the process of dying. A good death is, for many
people, a component of a good life.
Public appreciation of that fact would mark a salutary shift in our ethi-
cal life. In many hospitals, many doctors quietly appreciate that preserv-
ing life is not a fundamental goal. A more basic aim is to help lives realize
the projects to which those who live them are committed. Many active,
passionate, and thoughtful people reflectively view an envisaged future
state of lingering in a state of dementia, or subject to a condition in which
5. See, for example, Berhanu Alemayehu and Kenneth Warner, “The Lifetime Distri-
bution of Healthcare Costs,” Health Ser vices Research 39 (2004): 627–42.
Renewing the Project 379
6. See George Bernard Shaw, The Doctor’s Dilemma (New York: Penguin, 1956), in
which a doctor has a newly discovered cure in a quantity sufficient to save one patient—and
there are two potential recipients.
380 the ethica l project
who have already been able to realize many of their aspirations before
the current misfortune. If the lives of many others are bound up with
the patient’s continued existence (as with parents of young children, or
people whose work contributes to the welfare of many others), it is ap-
propriate to give the patient more weight. The ideal doctor—or the ideal
committee of medical planners—would thus attend to the various ways
in which patients’ failures to survive would affect the future quality of
lives, both their own and those affected by their presence in the world.
Ideally, there would be a process of mirroring, in which the possible
futures for an inclusive group of people were surveyed, out of which a
decision could come.
So far, however, no attention has been paid to the past. If the alcoholic
scores more highly on the future-oriented measures than his or her tem-
perate counterpart, he or she will qualify for the single available liver.7
Can the recommended form of consequentialism be sensitive to the
thought that the carelessness of a patient’s earlier life is pertinent, that
people who neglect their health, or even actively cause their own medical
problems, are less worthy as recipients of corrective treatment? It can. A
commitment to equal sharing of scarce resources must consider whether,
in the initial distribution, everyone received the same. In the original
context of food sharing, for example, if the portion given to one member
of the group were to spoil quickly, our first ethical ancestors would likely
try to make up the lack, perhaps by having the others contribute from
their own allotted shares, viewing this as producing the equal distribu-
tion they had aimed at, but failed to achieve, in the first place. Similarly,
a person whose liver has failed because of a genetic defect was not
granted an equal portion of the resource healthy liver, and a commit-
ment to equality (equal opportunity for a worthwhile life) has to take ac-
count of this fact.
An ideal distribution of the scarce medical resources would attend to
the variety of forward- and backward-looking factors, balancing them in
7. In practice, of course, the alcoholic’s past excesses may diminish his or her future
prospects, and thus reduce his or her score on the forward-looking measures. But to ex-
clude the alcoholic in this way would respond to the future consequences of his or her be-
havior, not to the behavior itself. Many people would maintain that, even if this yields an
acceptable result, it does so in the wrong way.
Renewing the Project 381
some alternative might have been a little better, and that many would
have been equally good, provided the superior possibilities would have
been hard to appreciate in the time available for decision. Reflections on
everyday life are pervaded by concessions to our limitations.
The mundane character of ethical deliberation and ethical judgment
is easy to overlook and takes for granted so much that might be exam-
ined and questioned. Talk of ethics gravitates too quickly to striking
cases, often to cases both striking and artificial. The reality of everyday
ethical life, however, consists in attempts to use and extend the collec-
tion of resources previously acquired, and, in doing this, there is no
single answer an ideal system of ethics might in principle supply, nor do
we judge ourselves and others from the perspective of any such system.
Against the background of what we already have, an ethical code that
presupposes institutions, roles, facets of the good life, and ways of allow-
ing for human limitations, each of us considers what to do, and, retrospec-
tively, appraises his or her own conduct and the deeds of others. Judgment
turns on a number of obvious questions: Is the conduct in accordance
with the general prescriptions of the code? Does it discharge the duties
associated with the agent’s role(s)? Does it appreciate opportunities for
contributing to welfare that go beyond those roles? Does it exhibit too
much thought or too little? Are any lapses understandable as consequences
of human limitations affecting (almost) all of us? Answers typically allow
a significant range of plans of action to count as permissible, even praise-
worthy, applications and extensions of the code.
The everyday practice of ethical judgment might itself be judged from
a more extensive perspective. Is there occasion for modifying the code
itself, the prescriptions it offers, the institutions and roles it presup-
poses, its conception (tacit or explicit) of the good life, its recommenda-
tions about the proper extent and the proper occasion of deliberation, its
ways of accommodating human frailty? Stepping back and judging all
aspects of our code at all times is plainly impossible. Decisions about
what to do next have to be made, and they cannot await protracted scru-
tiny of everything we have inherited. Equally, failing to raise questions
about the various features of our codes, about the ways we answer the
questions on which everyday judgment turns, is the unthinking devotion
to routine our mundane practice condemns. While most of our ethical
384 the ethica l project
life consists in using the ethical resources we have to deal with novel sit-
uations, our current ethical code—with its appreciation of the dangers of
thinking too little as well as those of thinking too much—requires us to
probe its constituent resources. How does the conception of the good (in
terms of equal opportunity for the good life) bear on institutions and
roles we normally take for granted? How does the method of delibera-
tion (in terms of ideal mutual engagement) affect the principles we try to
apply? Are we too slack in allowing people to steer by their routines, and
not to engage, more frequently, in attempts to mirror the attitudes of
others? Is the practice of everyday judgment itself too comfortable?8
Almost certainly, contemporary members of affluent societies (philoso-
phers included) are often caught up in the unexamined life. Operating by
habit, we narrow the horizons of ethical concern, so the plight of many
people becomes invisible to us—hence the tolerance for worldwide in-
equalities, even those as glaring as those just considered (§58). Routine
inclines us to consider a restricted range of options, among which we seek
one as good as any rival. Often, everyday ethical judgment involves prob-
lems to which there are many adequate solutions. The challenging exam-
ples, those able to jar us into considering reform, are occasions on which,
given the resources of the ethical code, there appears to be no available
solution. Ethical dilemmas are not the principal part, or even a very large
part, of ethical life—at least, not for those who live comfortably.9 Their
value lies in causing us to pay attention.
Dilemmas can be more or less isolated, or conversely more or less sys-
tematic. Systematic dilemmas are those that can erupt for different people
8. Although we have seen (§27) why ethics cannot be founded on the will of the deity,
there is an important question about the positive impact of embedding ethics within reli-
gion. William James argued that a connection between ethical precepts and ideas about
powers transcending the human makes ethics properly “strenuous” (“The Moral Phi loso-
pher and the Moral Life,” in The Will to Believe [New York: Dover, 1956], 211). For all the
problems of that connection, one might maintain that, as a matter of fact, the discipline of
religious participation provides structures that encourage people to examine their conduct
more closely and thus prevent certain types of slackness. If this is so, secular societies re-
quire substitute ways of fostering self-examination. (The example of Socrates, whose refer-
ences to deities are peripheral to his probing interrogations, shows us that uninstitutional-
ized surrogates are possible.)
9. They are surely more prominent in the lives of those who live in want.
Renewing the Project 385
under a range of contexts, and if this is the case, a proper diagnosis may
require us to understand accepted institutions or roles as responsible.
Suddenly, the background to our habits needs examination. The well-
brought-up conversationalists imagined in §57 might be less dependent
on these occasional provocations, more constantly attuned to the possi-
bility of habit-induced myopia.
provide for their children and make the envisaged opportunities avail-
able. Yet to keep their job they are required to frustrate their central
purpose. Sometimes, even when the children are sick or distressed,
they must be left with overburdened caregivers or sent from school to
after-school activities because parents cannot leave the workplace to
provide support and comfort. The internal logic of examples like these
is that a chosen role (child rearing) requires a secondary role (working)
that sometimes can be pursued only at cost to performance in the pri-
mary role.
The second class of cases involves women who hope to combine
career satisfactions with responsible motherhood. In many of these in-
stances, more options are available: the aspiring lawyer, doctor, busi-
nesswoman, or researcher has enough disposable income to purchase
better substitutes for her own presence. If, however, the career goals are
to be realized, the same squeeze is felt in a different place. Maybe a ten-
hour workday can be managed, if sufficiently hefty expenditures on
child care secure nurturing and stimulating environments for the grow-
ing children. Career advancement, even career maintenance, may de-
mand even more. Ten hours at the desk, in the hospital, on the road, or
at the bench is not sufficient. The childless—and some of the fathers—
are able to devote more time and energy, and they are likely to receive
the most prized opportunities. Eventually, perhaps, the career of the
promising young woman stagnates—she has put in “only” her ten-hour
days, leaving for a few hours with the children as others remain—and as
she recognizes stagnation, even the ten-hour day becomes unbearable.
Here, the logic of the situation is that a life centered on filling two roles,
both viewed as important and neither prior to the other, is constantly
affected by their competing demands.
Given luck in the form of sufficiently favorable circumstances, women
(and men) who fall under these types may stagger through, achieving
something they retrospectively identify as satisfactory. The parent for
whom work is simply a means to support the children sees them happily
launched on lives they have chosen; the parent who hopes to combine
career and family reaches a similar goal while also managing a satisfying
professional life (perhaps the career could have gone farther without the
“distractions” of the family, but it has gone far enough). With great good
Renewing the Project 387
fortune, women and men can feel even that they have discharged both
roles to the best of their abilities: their child raising has gone as well as it
would have done, even given more “investment” in family life; their
career has gained whatever rewards10 it would have garnered, even if full-
time efforts had been devoted to it. Yet the most successful ways of bal-
ancing may require squeezing out other roles, limiting the range or depth
of friendships, for example.
If we compare the women and men who strive to combine family and
professional life, and who constantly feel these dilemmas, with the class
of men (and a smaller number of women) who either pursue careers
single-mindedly or else rely on another (a spouse or a partner) to take
care of the family responsibilities, successes, especially at the highest
levels, will be found predominantly in the latter group. These people,
after all, do not require great good fortune to achieve what they might
have attained with maximum effort—for maximum effort is just what
they devote. Even among the most egalitarian communities in the afflu-
ent world, the sex ratios in the two groups are different: more women
than men find themselves confronting serial dilemmas, generated by
clash of roles; more men than women are freed from those serial dilem-
mas because they can depend on someone else to discharge the poten-
tially clashing role. Hence, an imbalance in performance will persist.
The most spectacular successes in public life will typically be achieved
by men rather than by women, even though opportunities are, supposedly,
now equal.11
The recurrently arising dilemmas stemming from clashes among
domestic and public roles give rise to two distinct ethical problems. The
more obvious of these is that which confronts the individual agents as
they must make their everyday decisions. So long as the demands of the
confl icting roles are not too severe, these people can resolve the sequen-
tial predicaments by judicious accounting. Those who stagger through
to success typically do so by keeping a running tabulation of their
10. These need not be matters of salary, or public honors, but the sense of having made
a contribution to an important enterprise.
11. For a brilliant summary of the manifold ways, many of them small, in which equality
is undermined, and of the large cumulative effect of apparently minute differences, see
Virginia Valian, Why So Slow? (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1998).
388 the ethica l project
12. The “how possibly” account of §20 proposed particu lar problems as giving rise to
specific roles. Even if that account is historically inaccurate, the more general thesis that
roles and institutions respond to problems would not be falsified.
390 the ethica l project
13. This is a point that has been emphasized in feminist analyses for decades. It is elo-
quently made, for example, by Virginia Woolf. See Three Guineas (San Diego: Harcourt
Brace Jovanovich, 1966).
Renewing the Project 391
14. Here, I consider only the toleration of violence in warfare. Concealment, even dis-
honesty, is allowed in some commercial and political contexts. For preliminary analysis,
see my “Varieties of Altruism,” Economics and Philosophy 26 (2010): 121–48.
392 the ethica l project
15. See the essays collected in P. A. Woodward, ed., The Doctrine of Double Effect
(Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2001), for lively debate about this
issue.
Renewing the Project 393
16. The bombing of Dresden was probably inspired by the need of the Western Allies to
satisfy Stalin’s demand for action. The official claim was that this act would break the Ger-
man morale (in odd neglect of the fact that the Blitz had only stiffened British resistance to
Hitler). Those who crafted the policy knew that Dresden had become a sanctuary for many
people from Eastern Europe who were fleeing the advancing Russian army.
17. My formulation here is intended to allude to Isaac Levi’s pioneering work on this
topic. See his Hard Choices (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1985).
394 the ethica l project
life).18 Part of the ethical task was to frame rules for dealing with aggres-
sive interactions once they had broken out. Even more crucial was the
formulation of rules for preventing conflicts from erupting in the first place.
Egalitarian arrangements were essential at those early stages because the
group could not manage without the ser vices of any of its members and
because failing to attend to the needs of any member would lead to defec-
tion or outright conflict.
Pragmatic naturalism treats the contemporary world as a scaled-up
version of this initial stage in our ethical life, one in which our inherited
social technology is inadequate to the expanded field on which conflict
has emerged. Huge inequalities between groups that have become aware
of one another’s relative situations inspire the have-nots, when they can,
to wrest what they lack by force. When the economic differences become
highly skewed, the most disadvantaged often outnumber those who live
in comfort, and, when they are able to band together, they have sufficient
chances of success to make aggressive action pay. As technology produces
weapons that can be used to inflict massive destruction, great numbers
of people are no longer needed. Armed with atomic bombs, even in crude
and “dirty” versions, small groups of disadvantaged people can threaten
to take hundreds of thousands of lives. Our predicament exacerbates
that faced by our human ancestors—as if, in their small bands, each
member, even the weakest, had access to tools that would realistically
threaten the life of any four or five others the person selected. The chal-
lenge to amend our ethical practice so as to forestall situations provoking
such threats is more urgent than the fragile social life that inspired the
origin of ethics.
The egalitarian approach to the good addresses that challenge as our
ancestors did when they tackled their problems: they introduced rules
for sharing, and so should we (§58). But this is only part of the difficulty
we face. Not all human conflict arises out of the protests of those hitherto
18. As recognized in §10, the evolution of hominid behavior after the split with the com-
mon ancestor of human beings and chimpanzees may have broadened or intensified the
original tendencies to psychological altruism. See, for example, the proposals made by
Sarah Hrdy about cooperative parenting (Mothers and Others [Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2009]). Despite these steps, there remained plenty of limitations of homi-
nid altruism and resultant tensions within hominid societies.
Renewing the Project 395
deprived. Human history and the human present are full of wars sparked
by religious differences. Equally, some of the most brutal hostilities re-
sult from the ambition of megalomaniacs who succeed in inspiring oth-
ers. To address all the factors generating conflict in the global society to
which we now belong, egalitarianism must be combined with secular-
ism, at least to the extent of undercutting the military enterprises of
zealots who would impose their conception of the divine will by force.
If we could achieve a world in which there were no economic causes to
invade others, and in which any religious exhortation to conflict was
viewed as illegitimate, if not absurd, two of the major sources of warfare
would be dammed up.19
Even though we can hope to reverse the biblical (and Malthusian)
dictum that the poor will always be with us, the same is surely not true
for megalomaniacs and psychopaths. Their power to generate wars would
be radically diminished if they were deprived of their two major means
of securing support: through rallying those who suffer from various forms
of inequality and through invoking a divine mission. Pragmatic naturalism
does not suppose that the pacifist project of working to eliminate war is
unrealistic, and that we have to settle for articulating the precise condi-
tions under which various kinds of lives should be traded. It can draw
inspiration from the thought that our first ethical ancestors learned how
to solve the problem in the small—and also from the more recent fact that,
on a continent dominated, through centuries, by fierce wars among neigh-
bors, Eu ropean states have entered into relationships that are broadly
(if insufficiently) egalitarian and secular. To many who look at their ac-
complishments, the hostilities of the past seem no longer possible. It is
not entirely utopian to think their achievement could be more broadly
emulated.
A package of proposals is required. In a world constantly scarred by
acts of violence, it is necessary both to find ways of removing the causes
of conflict as speedily and as thoroughly as possible, and to institute
rules for responding to the brutality that continues to occur. Pragmatic
19. Achieving that kind of world might also enable us to address a third source of
confl ict—the shadow of the past, with its recurrent, often escalating, violence between par-
ticu lar groups.
396 the ethica l project
naturalists do not think there are magic wands to be found and waved,
but there may be coordinated proposals that would both take steps to-
ward the diminution and eventual eradication of violence and supply
directives for coping with the imperfect precursors of the goal state. Its
optimism derives from the hope that we can learn about the causes of
social conflict and find strategies for enlarging human sympathies.
20. Hume makes the point eloquently; Inquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals (In-
dianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1983), 28.
Renewing the Project 397
with what they own, or property is held in common, and only the group
is permitted to make decisions about how it is used.21 Nobody should
endorse any such dichotomy. Conceptions of property lie on a contin-
uum. At one pole are those conceptions that subordinate all decisions
about the use of an item of property to the group (impossible in anything
but the very simplest society); at the other are conceptions that sub-
ordinate all decisions about the use of an item of property to the individual
(subject to legal constraints: owning a gun does not give you the right to
shoot somebody). Between these poles lie a host of positions that specify
two kinds of contexts, one where the individual owner’s will holds sway,
another where the community judgment is decisive.
An institution of property consists in a set of rules about how one may
acquire it, and a set of rules about what one may then do with it, without
intervention from others. In the Anglo-Saxon world, the dominant insti-
tution derives from a seminal discussion by Locke.22 Primarily focused
on the example of land, Locke famously proposed we acquire property
by “mixing our labor” with it—that is, making use of it in some way—
and we are entitled to acquire anything previously unclaimed by others,
subject to two provisos: first, we take no more than we can make use of,
and second, we leave as much and as good for others. Once the property
is acquired, however, we are entitled to do what we want with the entities
we own, given that we do not break any law by doing so. In particular,
we are allowed to give our property to anyone we want, so there can be
unlimited transfer across generations. The stage is set for arguments that
egalitarian distributions must be transitory.
This conception is incoherent because of the asymmetry between its
account of the acquisition of property and its relaxed attitude toward
property transfer. When property is acquired, the provisos constrain.
That accords with egalitarianism: initial distributions of property
must allow all to have approximately equal shares. Transfer does not
21. This oversimplified conception underlies the polarized rhetoric that emerges in
some political discussions: advocates of communal property think of (private) property as
theft; contemporary conservatives sometimes view taxation as a form of theft.
22. Second Treatise on Government (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1980). For contempo-
rary exposition and defense, see Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York:
Basic Books, 1974).
398 the ethica l project
23. In discussing these points, I have been helped by conversations with Rohan Sud.
Renewing the Project 399
More than a century ago, Mill argued for a proposal of this kind.24
His reasoning was double sided. In addition to the more obvious con-
cern that children born to poor parents should be provided for, he wor-
ried about the effects on the recipients of dynastic wealth.25 Instead of
offering enhanced opportunities for choosing and pursuing a person’s
own life project, acquiring a very large fortune can prove limiting, sap-
ping the desire to exert oneself. Whether that psychological generaliza-
tion holds, there is an important point behind it. If what is fundamen-
tally valuable is not wealth per se, but the opportunities wealth brings,
history reveals many worthwhile human lives that began in far from wealthy
circumstances, as well as children of the extremely rich who lost their
way. Pending more detailed analysis, it is not obvious that leaving one’s
children a fortune is more likely to bring them a worthwhile life than
providing them with the means (protection, nurture, material necessities,
educational opportunities) to discover their own way.
Does the proposal wrongly curtail human freedom? “What I have
earned is mine, and I have the right to do what I like with it. When that
right is abridged, I suffer a loss of freedom.” The protest begs a crucial
question. For the issue is what it should mean to say that something is
“mine,” and one cannot choose by fiat from a continuum of possible posi-
tions. If it would be ethically progressive to introduce a modified concep-
tion of property, amending the asymmetry infecting Locke’s proposal, the
claim of right lapses.
Behind the protest stands one plausible thought. If we should aim for
a world in which all people enjoy a serious and approximately equal
opportunity for leading worthwhile lives, it is important to consider
whether the modification, one that appears to enhance the opportunity
for some, does so by interfering with the life projects of others. Is the re-
vised conception of property hostile to certain ideas about the worth-
while life, which it eliminates as possibilities for people?
What might these views about worthwhile lives be? Here are the cen-
tral possibilities:
24. Principles of Political Economy (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1970), Works,
2:218–27, 3:755–57.
25. Principles of Political Economy, Works, 2:221.
400 the ethica l project
26. It is important to be mindful here of Mill’s point about the need for solitude (Works,
3:756). Public resources can be shared without introducing such dense crowds that enjoy-
ment of them becomes impossible.
Renewing the Project 401
The second vision sees value accruing not from the toys one has, but
from the activity of accumulating them (already a positive step). Lives of
this sort are not threatened in any way by the envisaged modification of
the conception of property. For the duration of a person’s existence, the
activity of accumulation is allowed to go undiminished (subject to what-
ever taxes are levied before the intergenerational transfer). If there is to
be any frustration of the accumulator’s plan, it must result from the cen-
trality of a further desire: to give what has been amassed to a younger
heir. Assuming the desire is directed toward the perceived interests of
the heir, the thought must be that bequeathing the wealth increases the
opportunities for the heir to live a worthwhile life. Yet, under the egali-
tarian conception, serious chances are already available. Only if the
life envisaged for the heir were one of consumption—after the pattern of
vision 1—would the inheritance be necessary. It would be strangely
schizophrenic for someone to hold the active work of accumulation
worthwhile for himself, whereas a life of passive consumption would be
suitable for another. If the life envisaged as valuable were one of active
accumulation, it would be counterproductive to provide great wealth for
the young.
Vision 2 is more promising as an account of a worthwhile life than is
vision 1 because it emphasizes the work of achievement rather than the
material goods garnered. Material goods are important bases for most
activities around which valuable lives are pursued, but those required
are typically not the expensive and the rare. A world in which all were
given serious (and equal) opportunities for living valuable lives would be
one in which anxieties about accumulating wealth for one’s heirs would
evaporate.
27. In each of these formulations, I give only the bare bones of the scientific account of
the options made available by biotechnology. The intention is to draw attention to impor-
tant features without drowning readers in technical details.
404 the ethica l project
28. Similarly, the mutant embryos used by Christiane Nüsslein-Volhard in her brilliant
investigations of the genetics of development in fruit fl ies belonged to the species Drosoph-
ila melanogaster. For an account of this work, see Peter Lawrence, The Making of a Fly
(Oxford: Blackwell, 1992).
Renewing the Project 405
sex, say, or relatively short stature.29 Here, any wish to terminate the
pregnancy would have to be defended against charges that it embodies
a frivolous view of what matters in human lives, and, in general, we can
expect the defense to prove inadequate. Hence, pragmatic naturalism
frowns on termination in these instances. Finally, there are genetically
identifiable conditions with respect to which the probability of worth-
while life is significantly diminished. Down syndrome (strictly speaking
a chromosomal abnormality) covers a wide range of possible courses of
life. On the one hand are children (and occasionally adults) whose mental
retardation is severe and whose physiological problems cause difficulty
and pain; on the other are people who achieve significant things. Although
great strides have been made in providing environments allowing people
with Down syndrome to develop more fully, we still lack knowledge of
the distribution of phenotypes across the kinds of environments we can
provide. Prospective parents cannot even calculate the chances that
their child with Down syndrome will have the opportunity for a worth-
while life. Under this situation of extreme uncertainty, it is hard to blame
them for choosing termination—even though, in the future, we might ar-
rive at more refined understandings that would change our perspective.
With respect to the third question, it is important to ask why repro-
ductive cloning might appeal. We can distinguish two types of cases: there
are circumstances in which cloning would provide a unique opportunity
for two people to conceive a child with a close biological relationship to
both of them;30 alternatively, someone (or some pair of people) may want
a child with the genetic material of an admired individual. With respect
to the latter case, the conception of the good tells against the use of re-
productive cloning. If children should be provided with opportunities
for a worthwhile life, and if having a worthwhile life involves making free
decisions about what is most central, there are serious concerns about
parental pressures that appear to be implicit in the idea of having a child
29. A caveat is necessary here. There are plainly environments in which characteristics
like these do interfere with the possibility of having a worthwhile life. The primary ethical
imperative in such instances is to do something about the crippling environments.
30. Consider, for example, two lesbians who have no biological relatives who propose to
have a child by inserting the nuclear DNA of one into an enucleated ovum from the other,
and reintroducing the embryo into the second woman’s uterus.
406 the ethica l project
with this splendid DNA.31 To want a child with the phenotype of some-
one one admires is already to set one’s own ideas about what matters
ahead of those the child might choose for him- or herself—the same sort
of coercion James Mill inflicted on his son. By contrast, when reproduc-
tive cloning would be a unique means to biological continuity, matters
cannot be settled so simply. It is worth asking whether people should be
so wedded to biological continuity with those they rear that they resort
to such technologically delicate ways of achieving it. Under conditions
where mammalian cloning requires the use of a very large number of ova
to obtain a single birth, a couple with a desire for children should choose
some more reliable method, even if biological continuity is sacrificed.
These are only preliminary answers to issues about the uses of bio-
technology. Answers ought to be constrained by the broader commitment
to egalitarianism. Sophisticated forms of reproductive technology are
currently available to a minority of the human population, and we should
ask if the costs of making them available to all would be worth the benefit.
Even if one were to conclude that some instances of reproductive cloning
would be permissible, providing opportunities to all those who would
want them might be incompatible with satisfying more urgent medical
needs: biomedical research might use its resources more profitably. The
nonaffluent world has higher priorities. Conversely, there might be in-
creased pressure to engage in genetic testing and early termination of
pregnancies because providing appropriate environments for children
born with various disabilities could not be carried through on too large a
scale—without using genetic tests to reduce the population of the dis-
abled, maintaining good environments for children with particular gene-
tic conditions would draw resources away from meeting the needs of many
other children. Adding these points about the background commitments
of the view of the good does not end the discussion but merely reveals
reasons for possible modification of the initial answers.
Yet a principal concern about those answers, whether in their original
form or modified, is that something is lost in substituting the bare bio-
31. Prospective parents who aim to replicate someone they admire also have radically
misguided views about genetic contributions and are victims of a crudely mistaken genetic
determinism.
Renewing the Project 407
32. This point is made with great eloquence by Ronald Dworkin in Life’s Dominion
(New York: Knopf, 1993). Dworkin’s discussion of issues about the “ends of life” in that
book is an exemplar of the wide-ranging canvassing of different points of view that I see as
the proper form of ethical conversation. Very few writers on ethical topics, whether reli-
gious or philosophical, have offered so sensitive and insightful a treatment of any contem-
porary ethical question.
33. The point here is akin to one affecting the “two-sphere” approach to trade. Sus-
pending maxims fostering altruism toward others within a particu lar sphere (between
buyer and seller) might erode responsiveness to others more broadly. Talking clinically
about embryos might similarly promote a more callous attitude toward (for example) chil-
dren with severe disabilities. Once again, there are psychological facts to be explored.
34. This is particularly true in Germany. The German translation of my book on ethical
consequences of genomic research (The Lives to Come [New York: Simon and Schuster,
1996]; Genetik und Ethik [München: Luchterhand]) aroused far more controversy than its
Anglo-American original.
408 the ethica l project
§64. Summing Up
Tens of thousands of years ago, our remote ancestors began the ethical
project. They introduced socially embedded normative guidance in re-
sponse to the tensions and difficulties of life together in small groups.
They were equipped with dispositions to psychological altruism that
enabled them to live together, but the limits of those dispositions pre-
vented them from living together smoothly and easily. Out of their nor-
mative ventures have emerged some precepts we are not likely ever to
abandon, so long, at least, as we make ethical progress, the vague gener-
alizations that embody ethical truths. Besides those core themes, we
have also inherited a conception of the good that includes confl icting
elements, as well as providing for us a far richer conception of human life
than any the first ethical pioneers could have apprehended. Our ethical
task is to decide how to go on.
The three preceding chapters recommend renewing the project by
emulating the early phases and expunging some of the distortions intro-
duced in later transitions. Pragmatic naturalism’s normative stance con-
sists in an egalitarian conception of the good, focusing on equal opportu-
nity for a worthwhile life, and a method for ethical discussion in terms of
409
410 the ethica l project
1. See Dewey, Democracy and Education (New York: Free Press, 1966), 328; The Quest
for Certainty, vol. 4 of The Later Works (Carbondale, IL: University of Southern Illinois
Press1984), 204.
Acknowledgments
I entered ethics by the back door. In the early 1980s, as I tried to become
clear about the pitfalls of human sociobiology (“pop sociobiology,” as I
uncharitably called it), it seemed important to assess the famous claim
that the time had come for ethics to be removed from the hands of the
philosophers and “biologicized.” The final chapter of my book Vaulting
Ambition criticized sociobiological proposals to provide ethics with a
biological basis. Yet, as I reflected, I was not entirely satisfied with my
own response. The negative arguments seemed sound, but I imagined
the complaint of an aggrieved biologist: “You have found fault with ef-
forts to reconcile ethics with a Darwinian picture of life, but do you have
any positive view to offer? Is any of the available philosophical concep-
tions satisfactory?” I had no good answer to this complaint, and, around
1985, I set myself the task of finding one.
The present volume is my attempt to complete the task. It has taken a
long time, and a very large number of people have helped me. My views
have evolved in ways I would not have anticipated. Along the way I have
found myself increasingly at odds both with efforts to carry forward the
program Darwin outlined in The Descent of Man, and with the standard
perspectives from which contemporary philosophers pursue ethical and
metaethical questions. I have often worried that the book I have tried
so many times to write would please nobody.
411
412 Acknowledgments
During the many years I have been thinking about this project, there
have been several people who have helped me on a number of occasions.
Conversations with Allan Gibbard have invariably been wonderfully
instructive, and I am delighted that he decided to spend a sabbatical
leave in New York City. Isaac Levi has shaped my thinking in many
ways, most likely more than either of us could enumerate. Interactions
with Frans de Waal, both on the occasion of his Tanner Lectures at
Princeton and during a visit to Emory have enlightened me greatly about
crucial facets of primate behavior. Chris Peacocke has been a splendidly
open-minded interlocutor and a constructive critic. Continuing discus-
sions with John Dupre, Michael Rothschild, and Elliott Sober have been
illuminating and always enjoyable.
My debts to my students at Columbia, especially those who have taken
my seminars on evolution, altruism, and ethics, are extensive. Particular
thanks go to current and former graduate students: Dan Cloud, Laura
Franklin-Hall, Michael Fuerstein, Jon Lawhead, Katie McIntyre, Heather
Ohanesen, Herb Roseman, and Matt Slater; also to some truly brilliant
undergraduates: Lauren Biggs, Leora Kelman, Jonathan Manes, Howard
Nye, Michael Roberto, Sam Rothschild, and Rohan Sud. Many thanks
to Jon Lawhead for preparing the index.
The penultimate draft, prepared in 2008–9, was somewhat longer
than its predecessor—and considerably longer than the final version. I
am extremely grateful to two perceptive and constructive readers for
Harvard University Press who gave me excellent advice—in particular to
make it shorter. It helped that their thoughts coincided completely with
those of the person who has always been my best reader, Patricia Kitcher,
to whom I owe more than I can say.
Lindsay Waters has been a helpful and supportive editor. He has had
to wait a long time, and I appreciate his patience.
My thinking about these topics began before our sons were teenagers,
and that is reflected in the nickname the book in progress still bears.
Charles continues to ask me how “Nice Monkeys” is going—even though
I have told him many times that it is no longer much about nonhuman
animals, that the relevant nonhuman animals are apes, not monkeys,
and that part of the point is that they are not particularly nice. For many
years, I have been entertained, enlivened, challenged, and informed
Acknowledgments 415
417
418 Index
boundaries, 120, 190, 214, 303, 306, 309 compromise, 241, 244, 260, 272, 300,
Boyd, Robert, 53, 87, 109, 112 336
Brownian motion, 182 computer simulation, 52, 56, 63
brutality, 31, 47, 60, 118, 143, 161, 166, 225, conscience, 40–41, 92– 93, 112
229, 278, 307, 395 consensus building, 175, 334–335,
340–344, 348–360
consequentialism, dynamic, 288–294,
calculus, 234, 293 311–313
callousness, 46, 393 constructivism about truth, 190–192,
Canaan, 154, 167 201–203, 245
Carcopino, Jerome, 174 contractarianism, 273, 279, 344
Cardozo, Benjamin, 120 conversation. See discussion; mutual
caregiving practices, 38, 152, 385–386, engagement
389–390 cooperation: discriminating, 12, 55–57,
causation: between affective and emotional 88–89, 174; noncooperation, 52–53, 85,
states, 27–30, 77–78, 80–84; of ethical 89; nondiscriminating, 55
regression, 177–178; in functionalism, Crusades (Christian), 144
219–220; role in evaluating ethical facts, Cummins, Robert, 219
291–294; as a way of demarcating ethical
communities, 302–305
Cheney, Dorothy, 36, 58 Darwin, Charles: Darwinian evolution, 12,
children, and altruistic behavior, 40–42, 36, 90, 107–109, 111–112, 114, 123, 138,
132 213, 219–220, 237–238; coevolution of
citizenship, 106, 128, 140, 145–147, 149, 162, genes and culture, 108–109; social
165–166, 174, 177, 212, 375, 378, 382, 390 Darwinism, 255–256, 258
civilians, 392–393 Dawkins, Richard, 18, 326
cloning. See bioethics deliberation about norms, 111–115, 130–135,
coalition game, 57– 66, 88, 96– 97, 228 143, 259–261, 286, 308–313, 331–332,
cognition: role mediating ethical judg- 340–345, 372–384
ments, 25–30, 37–39, 75–80, 198–200; in Dennett, Daniel, 114
animals, 39–45, 50, 56, 78–80 deontology, 289, 294, 298, 300, 302, 314,
Coke, Sir Edward, 146–147 325, 328
collective: construction of ethics, 2, Descartes, Rene, 205
191–192, 204–205; use of resources, de Waal, Frans, 9, 17, 30, 43–44, 50, 57,
123–124, 318–323; acceptance of an 59– 60, 66, 69–70, 87, 189
ethical code, 234–237, 256 Dewey, John, 3, 114, 120, 179, 207, 251, 264,
colonial, 109, 154 266, 304–305, 327, 342, 347
colonies, 43, 69–70, 146, 153–156, 352 Dickens, Charles, 353
combat, 142, 175, 249, 392–393 discussion: ideal, 96–100, 104–108, 111–112,
commitment, 74–75, 79, 81, 96, 121, 151, 339–341; among groups, 270–272,
195, 200, 211–212, 233–234, 247, 256, 281–282, 285–288, 296–298, 302–329,
280, 324, 331, 352, 373, 380, 388, 331–338, 342–354, 356–360, 363–369,
390–391 394–396; contemporary, 370–373,
communal resources, 125, 129–131, 242, 397 377–378, 383–385, 388–391, 394–396,
compassion, 140, 143, 160, 174, 214 402–404, 406–410
competition: for resources, 60– 62, 248, disobedience, 81–82, 93, 111, 279
255, 350, 375, 390; cultural, 107–115, dispositions, 36–38, 63– 65, 67, 69–74,
128–131, 169–170, 259 78, 87–88, 91, 93, 98–100, 102, 108, 131,
Index 419
145, 161, 179, 183, 185, 191, 198, 204, 217, 226–227, 230, 234–235, 243, 247,
228, 232, 263, 278–279, 303, 335–336, 295, 302, 315, 356–360
340 expertise (ethical), 8, 285–287
divine commander, 111–115, 119–121, explanations, 12–13; how possibly, 60–74,
127–128, 163, 166–170, 207–208, 78–80, 87– 94, 99–103, 104–107, 111–115,
230–231, 241, 260, 289, 294–298 122–131, 135–137, 216n8, 223–229,
divinity, 2, 4, 8, 113, 115, 119, 121, 128, 131, 236–237, 239–242; 242–245, 307–308;
148–150, 163, 165–170, 207–208, how actually, 105–106, 117–119, 173–178,
230–231, 260, 285, 289, 298, 311, 313, 213–229, 294–296, 374–381; evolution-
328, 372–373, 395 ary, 107–110, 114, 213–214, 237–240
division of labor, 117–118, 122–131, 151n29,
239–241, 243–245, 294–295, 327–329,
350–352 Faustian bargains, 41
dominance, 59, 69–71, 228 Fehr, Ernst, 85, 101
Dummett, Michael, 192 feminism, 146–148, 152, 390
Foot, Philippa, 247, 278
forgiveness, 120, 144–145
early friendships, 64– 66 Fossil record, 5, 18
ecology, 59, 319 Foucault, Michel, 296
economics, 23, 50, 65, 85, 312, 391 Freud, Sigmund, 34–35, 92, 95, 163
education, 146, 149, 193–197, 317–319, 324, friendship, early friendships, 64– 66
359, 371, 375–377 function, etiological approach to, 218, 220
egalitarian commitments, 96– 97, 106, functional confl ict, 241–245, 247–249, 252,
115–116, 122–123, 127, 217, 248, 297, 321, 260–262, 281–282, 286–288, 296,
324–325, 351–352, 359, 364–366, 373, 333–334, 337–353, 355–356, 360–369.
377, 389–390, 393–397 See also progress; pluralism (ethical)
egoism, 19–20, 23–24, 31–32, 34, 36, 40,
44–45, 105, 136, 230, 274–276
Egypt, 11, 113, 118–119, 130, 216–217 Galileo, 148, 181, 189
elitism, 314–315, 328 generosity, 121, 136, 141
emotions, 36–37, 49, 76–85, 93– 95, genetic determinism, 27, 50, 114, 406
98–102, 198–204; nature of, 25–32, genetic testing, 380, 402–406
78–79, 198–201 Gibbard, Alan, 96, 203–204
empathy, 31, 34, 144, 250–251, 345, 371 Gilgamesh, 118
enforcer (divine), 111, 113–115, 119, 127, 131, Goldman, Alvin, 209
169, 217, 226, 230–231, 241, 260, 274, Goodall, Jane, 42
294, 297–298 Goodman, Nelson, 3, 258
environmentalism, 305, 310, 321 Gould, Stephen, 10
equality, 11, 85, 96, 115, 157, 178, 248, 285, government: autocratic, 148; democratic,
287, 289, 291, 293–295, 297, 299, 301, 146, 188–189, 265
303, 305, 307, 309, 311, 313, 315, 317–319,
321, 323–325, 327, 329, 339, 341, 364,
380, 385, 387, 389, 396 habits, 97, 331–332, 381–385
ethical point of view, 80–85, 106, 231–232 Hacking, Ian, 183
eugenics. See bioethics Hamilton, William, 18, 49
evolution. See Darwin, Charles Hamlet, 3, 92, 94
experiments: psychological, 45–46, 85–86, Hammurabi, code of, 118–119
101–102; of living, 104–137, 150–153, 213, Harman, Gilbert, 139, 181
420 Index
Nagel, Thomas, 85, 335 74, 79–81, 90–91, 96–98, 100, 102, 104,
naturalism: pragmatic naturalism (general 112–114, 216–218, 221–223, 225, 228–229,
discussion), 3–13, 225, 246, 256–258, 231, 236–238, 242–243, 251, 258, 261,
268–270, 281–282, 317–324, 362–369; 275, 278–279, 287, 294, 296, 316, 380,
nonnaturalism, 8, 269–271, 273, 276, 393–395; chimpanzee, 11, 17–18, 36,
279; counternaturalistism, 281 42–44, 47, 57, 59–60, 64–74, 87–88, 90,
Nazi, 139, 177, 255 222, 228, 232, 251, 278–279, 393–394;
Neurath, Otto, 279–280 bonobo, 17–18, 44, 47, 57, 59–60, 64–65,
neuroscience, mirror neurons, 28–30, 43, 68, 74; baboons, 36, 60; Arnhem
346 chimpanzee colony, 43–44, 49, 69–70,
Newton, 205, 213 77–78, 189; gorilla, 58; gibbon, 58, 144;
Nietzsche, Fredrich, 92, 95, 143, 211, orangutans, 58, 60
276–278, 282, 360–361 primatology, 5, 17, 36, 57, 60
nihilism, 269–270 primitive vs. civilized, 242–245, 248
noncognitivism, 30, 201–205 Prisoner’s Dilemma: defection strategy,
normative: guidance, 67– 69, 74–87, 51–55, 67– 68, 83, 87–88, 162, 379–380,
90–103, 111–112, 123–125, 131–137, 394; tit-for-tat strategy, 52–53; iterated,
221–223, 230–234, 409–410; conclusions, 52–54, 56, 58, 64; optional, 54–58,
191–192, 253–259, 338 60– 65, 88– 90, 126–127. See also
Nozick, Robert, 397 coalition game
progress: ethical, 6–8, 81, 99–100, 138–170,
173–206, 209–213, 338–342, 391–395,
obedience, 84, 99, 108–109, 111, 160, 167, 402–407, 409–410; technological, 7,
231, 264, 289 218–220, 238–242, 288; atomism about,
objectivity in ethics, 139–140, 209–212, 210–212, 363
243–245, 267, 312 properties, ethical properties as disposi-
tions, 198, 204, 263
144, 297; judaism, 145, 165, 176, 206, 230, 232, 264, 278– 279, 333, 359,
254– 255, 299, 301 371
resentment, 26, 134, 198, 204, 308, 324 sociobiology, 9–10, 36, 87, 101, 108,
Richerson, Peter, 87, 109, 112 255–256, 258
Robinson, Jenefer, 27 sociopathy, 279
roles (evolution of), 68–71, 89, 106–110, spirituality, 154, 158, 160, 184–185, 313–314
115–116, 125–131, 146–151, 216–217, stem cells, 1. See also bioethics
239–245, 247–249, 295, 331–332,
382–391
Roman empire, 143–145, 174–175 Tarski, 189, 246
Roseman, Herbert, 63 Taylor, Harriet, 147–152, 293
Rousseau, J., 61– 63, 149 technology: progress in, 7, 218–220,
Rovane, Carol, 139 238–242, 288; ethics as a social
technology, 221–241, 262, 394; ethical
challenges of, 401–408
Sabini, John, 46, 101, 331
Scanlon, T.M., 201, 223, 344
Schelling, Thomas, 73 unseen enforcer, 1. See also divine
Schopenhauer, Arthur, 17 commander
secularism, 4–5, 81, 121, 161–162, 287, utilitarianism, 272, 290–294, 311–314,
325–328, 344, 372–374, 395, 402–408 322–323
Sen, Amartya, 312, 319 Utopia, 84, 316–318, 324–325, 339, 395, 397
sexual behavior: polygamy, 143; hetero-
sexuality, 162–163, 165; homosexuality,
162–165, 174; incest, 255 value (dimensions of), 323–324
Seyfarth, Robert, 36, 58 violence: rape, 140, 234; warfare, 142, 174,
Singer, Peter, 183, 214–215, 307, 335 391–392, 395; coercion, 146, 162, 185,
skepticism (ethical), 12–13, 35–56, 65– 69, 226, 228, 296, 317, 327–328, 359–360,
106, 247, 270–273, 279–282, 287, 318–321 363; genocide, 169, 392
slavery: abolition, 143, 153, 157–158, 161,
184, 187, 200, 214; and christianity, 143,
154–155, 160–161 Wilson, E.O., 39, 108, 256
Smith, Adam, 17, 25, 83, 121, 123–124, 156, Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 99
346, 351 Wollstonecraft, Mary, 147, 149–150, 152,
Smith, John Maynard, 53, 108 163, 179–182, 184, 193–197, 202, 240, 250,
Sober, Elliott, 39, 256 257
social: cohesion, 9, 97, 287–288, 292, women, rights of, 140, 145–153, 179–180,
334–336, 341–342, 353, 362, 365–367; 193–196, 212, 214, 236, 250, 256–257,
asociality, 55, 61; blindness, 176–177, 293, 318–319, 358, 385–389
211–212, 335; fragmentation, 228, 356; Woolf, Virginia, 147, 150, 152, 390
nonsociality, 328 Woolman, John, 158–161, 179–182, 184,
socialization, 93– 94, 97, 101, 107, 126, 193–197, 200, 202, 240, 250, 257
130–132, 148, 151–153, 182, 199, Wrangham, Richard, 58– 60