Modes of Discourse - Smith Carlota (2003)
Modes of Discourse - Smith Carlota (2003)
Modes of Discourse - Smith Carlota (2003)
MODES OF DISCOURSE
In studying discourse, the problem for the linguist is to find a fruitful level
of analysis. Carlota Smith offers a new approach with this study of discourse
passages, units of several sentences or more. She introduces the key idea of
the “Discourse Mode,” identifying five modes: Narrative, Description, Report,
Information, Argument. These are realized at the level of the passage, and cut
across genre lines. Smith shows that the modes, intuitively recognizable as
distinct, have linguistic correlates that differentiate them. She analyzes the
properties that distinguish each mode, focusing on grammatical rather than
lexical information. The book also examines linguistically based features that
appear in passages of all five modes: topic and focus, variation in syntactic
structure, and subjectivity, or point of view. Operating at the interface of syntax,
semantics, and pragmatics, the book will appeal to researchers and graduate
students in linguistics, stylistics, and rhetoric.
Modes of Discourse
MODES OF
D I S C OURSE
T HE L OCA L STRUCTURE
OF T E X TS
CA RL OTA S . S M ITH
University of Texas
Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo
-
isbn-13 978-0-511-06906-2 eBook (EBL)
-
isbn-10 0-511-06906-5 eBook (EBL)
-
isbn-13 978-0-521-78169-5 hardback
-
isbn-10 0-521-78169-8 hardback
Introduction 1
ix
x Contents
References 294
General index 314
Index of names 318
Preface
This work would not have been possible without many kinds of support that I
have received from individuals and institutions. I am grateful to them all. The
New York Community Trust has supported much of my research on discourse.
It also funded three small conferences on discourse at the University of Texas
which advanced the work. I received a Faculty Research Award from the Uni-
versity of Texas Research Institute in 1994, which enabled me to pursue this
project. During that period I spent some time as a Visiting Scholar at the Maison
Suger of the CNRS in Paris. I was the beneficiary of a Dean’s Fellow award
from the College of Liberal Arts in 1998.
Parts of this work have been presented at conferences and colloquia. I
benefited greatly from the discussions that followed, as well as the presen-
tations themselves. They include three conferences on discourse structure
at the University of Texas; an International Round Table on The Syntax of
Tense and Aspect at Université de Paris, 2000; a symposium on Information
Structure in a Cross-Linguistic Perspective at the University of Oslo, 2000;
a conference on Linguistics in the Next Decade at the Academia Sinica,
Taipei, Taiwan, 2000; a Linguistics Colloquium at the University of Siena
in 1998; an invited lecture series at the City University of Hong Kong in
1998.
I would like to thank the members of a seminar on text structure that I taught
at the University of Texas in the Fall of 2001: Behrad Aghei, Robert M. Brown,
Pascal Denis, Q Wan Kim, Christian Rathmann, Brian Reese, Dong-Rhin Shin,
Cholthicha Sudmuk, and Jiun-Shiung Wu. Their questions and comments on
an earlier version of this manuscript were extremely helpful. I owe a special
debt to Keith Walters, who read the entire manuscript and gave me many valu-
able suggestions on content, presentation, and relevant material. I also thank
Pascal Denis, my research assistant during the critical stages of manuscript
preparation; he asked penetrating questions and provided very useful technical
advice. Finally, I thank the people with whom I have worked at the Cambridge
xiii
xiv Preface
University Press in the publication of this book, especially Neil Smith for
shocking, useful comments on an earlier version of the manuscript; I thank
Leigh Mueller, who did the copy-editing, for her careful work and good humor;
and I thank Jackie Warren for shepherding the book through the publication
process.
Introduction
This book is a partial answer to the question: what can close linguistic analysis
bring to the understanding of discourse? Discourse studies have focused on
pragmatic factors such as genre expectations, discourse coherence relations, and
inference. In part this has been a natural reaction to earlier, rather unsuccessful
attempts to apply the techniques of linguistic analysis beyond the sentence.
The current emphasis also follows from increased understanding of the area of
pragmatics, and of the role of context in language use and interpretation.
It has sometimes seemed, though, that nothing at all is conveyed by linguistic
forms, while everything is due to pragmatics or lexical content. I attempt to
right the balance here, at least in part. I propose a local level of discourse, the
Discourse Mode, which has linguistic properties and discourse meaning. I posit
five modes: Narrative, Report, Descriptive, Information, and Argument.
The Discourse Modes are classes of discourse passages, defined by the enti-
ties they introduce into the universe of discourse and their principle of progres-
sion. The discourse entities are essentially aspectual. They include the familiar
Events and States, and some less-familiar categories. The Discourse Modes
grew out of my work on aspect and tense. In studies of situation types in dis-
course, I noticed interesting differences between passages of different types.
Investigating further, I arrived at the Discourse Modes. If I am right about their
contribution to discourse, they make it clear that temporality is one of the key
sub-systems in language.
I characterize the modes by their linguistic features, that is, grammatical
forms with consistent interpretations. The linguistic features of the modes are
covert categories in the sense of Whorf (1956). They are not overtly marked
but they have characteristic patterns of distribution, and of interpretation. These
properties are subtle, but they are demonstrably part of a person’s knowledge
of language. The emphasis throughout this book is on grammatical rather than
lexical features of discourse.
The modes are, therefore, linguistic categories. I was curious to know whether
they would be related to anything in the field of rhetoric. When I looked at the
1
2 Introduction
This book studies discourse passages from a linguistic point of view. Discourse
is made up of sentences, and through linguistic analysis we have learned a good
deal about them. The perspective of linguistics, however, can’t be used directly
to study an entire discourse. Novels, histories, arguments, and other types of
discourse are activities with their own character and conventional structure.
Receivers draw on discourse knowledge to construct interpretations.
The first problem for the linguist interested in close study of discourse, then,
is to find a fruitful level for analysis. Larger units are organized primarily
by convention and expectation. I will work more locally, at the level of the
passage. There are intuitive differences between the passages of a discourse.
People recognize passages of several kinds, namely Narrative, Description,
Report, Information, and Argument. The intuitions are linguistically based: the
passages have a particular force and make different contributions to a text. They
can be identified by characteristic clusters of linguistic features. I shall say that
a passage of text with certain features realizes a particular “Discourse Mode.”
The Discourse Mode is appropriate for close linguistic analysis, because at this
level linguistic forms make a difference. Discourse Modes appear in texts of all
types of activity, or genres. I use the terms “discourse” for spoken and written
material, “text” for written material.
The Discourse Modes constitute an interesting level of text structure. I ana-
lyze them in two ways. I first discuss the differences between text passages of
each mode. I then look at passages in terms of subjectivity and surface structure
presentation, features that the modes have in common. Much of the analysis is
formalized in the framework of Discourse Representation Theory.
Part I of this book discusses the Discourse Modes and lays out the context
for the inquiry. Part II presents the linguistic characterization of the modes,
emphasizing the differences between them. Part III discusses subjectivity and
surface structure presentation across modes. Text passages are thus considered
from complementary points of view in the second and third parts of the book.
The different analyses are brought together in Part IV.
7
8 The study of discourse
Section 1.1 of this chapter introduces the Discourse Modes; 1.2 outlines the
approach to texts and analysis that I take in this book; 1.3 presents the main ideas
to be developed later, with examples of passages analyzed for different kinds
of information that they convey; 1.4 concludes with summary characterization
of the modes and brief comments on the importance of temporality for human
beings.
1. Persuasive discourse is not listed separately. All genres and modes of discourse may have a
persuasive component.
2. The texts were chosen to provide a variety of examples. They include short stories, novels,
books, articles from journals and newspapers. They were analyzed intensively by the author.
Appendix A provides a list of the texts and significant fragments from the ones most often
used.
1.2 Approaches to the study of texts 9
cheese-wire to check for air bubbles, then slammed the pieces together much
harder than usual. A fleck of clay spun off and hit her forehead, just above her
right eye.
(2) In the passenger car every window was propped open with a stick of kindling
wood. A breeze blew through, hot and then cool, fragrant of the woods and
yellow flowers and of the train. The yellow butterflies flew in at any window,
out at any other.
(3) Near a heavily fortified Jewish settlement in the Gaza Strip, an Israeli soldier
and a Palestinian policeman were wounded as Palestinian protests for the
release of 1,650 prisoners degenerated into confrontations. Israeli military
officials say they are investigating the source of fire that wounded the soldier.
(4) Thanks to advanced new imaging techniques, the internal world of the mind
is becoming more and more visible. Just as X-ray scans reveal our bones, the
latest brain scans reveal the origin of our thoughts, moods, and memories.
Scientists can observe how the brain registers a joke or experiences a painful
memory.
(5) The press has trumpeted the news that crude oil prices are three times higher
than they were a year ago. But it was the $10 or $11 price of February 1999,
not the one today, that really deserved the headlines.
In a different game, calling out the same word would have different force. A and
B might be archaeologists investigating a site, for instance, and A might call
out a word – column, brick – to convey to B what he has found. To interpret A’s
utterances, we have to understand the language game being played: the activity
and the role that language plays in it. Wittgenstein glosses the term “language
game” as referring to “the whole, consisting of language and the actions into
which it is woven.”3
Knowing the language game, or genre, requires knowledge of an activity
as a whole. This knowledge is not conveyed by linguistic forms. The global
structure of a discourse is rarely if ever stated explicitly. People understand
discourse with different kinds of information, including what is conveyed by
linguistic forms. They use general information about genre and principles of
communication, and specific information about a particular case. There are
some differences among genres. Scientific articles and textbooks often lay out
the specific relations between their parts, whereas literary genres tend to be less
explicit.
3. R. Rhees, in a Preface to The Blue and Brown Books, says that Wittgenstein introduced the
notion of language games “in order to shake off the idea of a necessary form of language . . . He
is insisting that . . . understanding is not one thing: it is as various as the language games
themselves.” The Blue and Brown Books were dictated in 1934–35 and published in 1958.
1.2 Approaches to the study of texts 11
4. The syntactic surface structures that I use are based on such works as Culicover (1997) which
are in the Principles and Parameters generative framework. I do not take a position on types of
movement rules or the mechanisms that trigger movement.
There is no level of Logical Form in this approach: the semantic interpretation is developed
in the Discourse Representation Theory framework.
12 The study of discourse
Text progression: there are several principles of text progression among the
Discourse Modes. In Narrative, situations are related to each other and dynamic
Events advance narrative time. In Reports, situations are related to Speech Time
and time progresses forward and backward from that time. In Description,
time is static and the text progresses in spatial terms through the scene de-
scribed. The Information and Argument modes are atemporal and progress by a
metaphoric path through the domain of the text. Text progression is discussed in
Chapters 5 and 6.
Subjectivity: I distinguish “subjective” sentences from others on the basis of
a set of grammatical forms. All forms of subjectivity convey access to mind –
either the mind of the writer or a text participant – through communication,
mental state, perception, and perspective. For each subjective expression a
Responsible Source must be identified. The main predicate of a sentence may
indicate communication, mental state, evaluation. The arguments of the predi-
cate may indicate perspective with deictic pronouns and reflexives. Modals, ad-
verbials, parentheticals indicate evaluation and evidentiality. Subjective forms
appear in passages of all the Discourse Modes. Subjectivity is discussed in
Chapter 7.
Surface structure presentation: presentational features organize the informa-
tion in a sentence, usually into topic and comment, focus and background.
These features appear in all text passages. I develop an integrative approach,
drawing on current linguistic insights and traditional Prague School views.
Presentational information depends on syntactic surface structure, the linear
and grammatical position of phrases. I will be particularly interested in pre-
sentational progression, which tracks the shifts from one topic to another in
the sentences of a discourse.5 The topic phrase gives the referent that a sen-
tence is about. The main criteria for identifying the topic phrase are salience,
coreferentiality, and continuity.6 See Chapters 8 and 9 for discussion.
Presentational structure is also known as “information structure”; I prefer the
term “presentation” because texts convey other kinds of information besides that
of topic, focus, and associated notions such as familiarity status.
5. The notion of presentational progression is unlike the shifting of attention in reading a text,
studied in psycholinguistics and artificial intelligence. The processes involved in understanding
are beyond the scope of this discussion.
6. Local continuity looks for a topic phrase that is coreferential with the topic phrase immediately
preceding. Global continuity looks for a topic phrase that is coreferential with other phrases in the
context. These factors are recognized in other approaches to local relations between sentences
such as Centering Theory, which ranks local continuity above global continuity (Walker et al.
1998). See Chapter 6 for discussion.
14 The study of discourse
Each E in this passage advances the narrative: the clauses express bounded
Events. State sentences such as 2a, 3a–b, and 4a–b do not advance narrative
time.
Now I add forms of subjectivity. They indicate access to mind, of either the
author or a participant. There is only one such form in this passage, a verb with
an implicit experiencer argument, given in bold.
The verb recall implies an experiencer (recalled to someone). Since the passage
is in the first person, participant and narrator are the same. We infer that the
narrator perceives the room according to the description in sentences 3 and 4.
The first person pronouns woven into the passage do not convey subjectivity in
the intended sense of access to mind.
Finally, information about surface presentational progression is added. The
topic phrases of each clause, in italics, provide the steps of progression through
the passage.
The topic phrases are subjects in S1, 2b, 3a, 4c, and the clauses of 5, 6, and
7. This is the most common position for topics. Topic phrases are discussed
16 The study of discourse
in Chapters 8 and 10. S3b and 4a–b are non-canonical structures without topic
phrases; see Chapter 9.
The next example is in the Report mode. Reports are similar to Narrative
in the situations they introduce: Events and States, and sometimes General
Statives. They have a different principle of progression, however. In the Report
mode, situations are related to the time of the report, Speech Time, rather than
to each other. The text progresses as time changes. The linguistic cues to change
are tensed verbs, modals, and adverbs that convey temporal information. In (9)
the adverbials and tensed verbs are underlined.
The time talked about moves back and forth from past to present, with one
modal future (“could become”) and one past perfect (“had taken”). Both modal
and perfect clauses are stative.
Subjective and presentational features are added in (10). The topic phrases
are italicized; subjective features are in bold.
The passage has deictic and evaluative subjective features. The deictics indicate
the time and place of the reporter (“now,” “here,” “tonight”), in addition to their
locating function. The evaluative “clear” implies an evaluator (clear to someone)
and the modal “could” suggests access to a mind. The Responsible Source is
the author, since no plausible text participant is available. The topic phrase is
the subject in all but two clauses of this passage.
The next example is Information, an atemporal mode. The situation entities
introduced include a significant number of facts and propositions, and gener-
alizing statives. They do not involve particular situations located at a time and
place. Therefore text progression in this mode cannot be based on temporal
or spatial location. Passages in the atemporal modes progress by metaphorical
motion through the semantic domain of the text. Motion, or lack of it, depends
on metaphorical changes of location. We track location in this sense by iden-
tifying a Primary Referent in each tensed clause in a passage, and considering
the location of the primary referents.
The Primary Referent is semantically central in the situation expressed. In
Events, the Primary Referent is what moves or changes. In States, the Primary
Referent is located or characterized; or emergent, dependent on the State for
existence. The Primary Referent of a clause usually coincides with the argument
that has the thematic role of Theme/Patient. Criteria for determining Primary
Referents are discussed in Chapter 6.
The fragment in (11) is an Information passage. It introduces Generalizing
Statives, except for S2b which refers to a Fact. These situations are typical
of the Informative mode. In addition, the Primary Referent phrases are shown
with underlining for each tensed clause. In S2 the extraposed clause is Primary
Referent for the main clause, indicated by the underlining of “S” which precedes
the clause. Ge = Generalizing Stative. Within the extraposed clause the Primary
Referent is also underlined.
(11) Information a: situations and Primary Referents
1aGe When people try to get a message from one individual to another in the
party game “telephone,” bGe they usually garble the words beyond recognition.
2aGe It might seem surprising, then, bFact that mere molecules inside our cells
constantly enact their own version of telephone without distorting the relayed
information in the least.
3Ge Actually, no one could survive without such precise signalling in cells.
4aGe The body functions properly only because bGe cells communicate with
one another constantly. 5Ge Pancreatic cells, for instance, release insulin to tell
muscle cells to take up sugar from the blood for energy. 6aGe Cells of the im-
mune system instruct their cousins to attack invaders, bGe and cells of the
18 The study of discourse
nervous system rapidly fire messages to and from the brain. 7aGe Those
messages elicit the right responses only bGe because they are transmitted
accurately far into a recipient cell and to the exact molecules able to
carry out the directives. 8Ge But how do circuits within cells achieve
this high-fidelity transmission?
The subjective forms in S2 are predicative, deictic, modal, adverbial. They are
part of the main sentence, though they do not involve either topic or Primary
Referent phrases. The concentration of subjective forms in this sentence, the
second of the article, conveys subjectivity which can be maintained with fewer
subjective forms later. S8 is in question form, directly invoking author and
reader. This pattern of subjectivity is fairly typical of informative prose. The
author is not a participant but can be glimpsed from time to time.
Next, information about presentational progression is added, with the topic
phrases in italics:
1.4 Conclusion 19
1.4 Conclusion
Summarizing, I give below a brief characterization of the modes, listing the
main properties of each
The entities differ in abstractness and temporality. The most specific are situ-
ations which are located in the world at a particular time and place. General
Statives – Generic and Generalizing sentences – are also located, but they
express a pattern of situations rather than a specific situation. Facts and Propo-
sitions, the most abstract entities, are not located in the world. Because of these
differences, information about the domains of time and space, or the absence
of it, is a revealing feature in a text.
The notion of “predominant entity” is flexible. Entities predominate when
there are relatively many of that type, or if they are highlighted in the text by
syntax and/or position in a passage.
Discourse conveys several kinds of information. Underlying a story, historical
account, or argument is information about situations and participants, time
and place, continuity, text progression of two kinds, point of view. Part of the
complexity of a text comes from its multiple linguistic cues to inter-related
meanings, expressed simultaneously. This book explores how some of these
meanings arise.
I have emphasized that temporal factors are important for the modes. The
point is supported by empirical findings which show that people notice tem-
porality in texts. Faigley & Meyer (1983) did an experimental study in which
readers classified texts. In three experiments, subjects were presented with a
varied group of texts and asked to sort them “according to type.” The subjects
were identified as high- and low-knowledge readers, graduate students and
1.4 Conclusion 21
undergraduates respectively. They did not receive special training for the ex-
perimental tasks.
When genre and subject matter were controlled, temporality was the feature
that explained the results. The temporal and aspectual information of a text
correlated with the subjects’ classifications. All subjects put texts into three
classes, identified by Faigley & Meyer as (a) narrative, (b) process-description,
(c) definition–classification. Temporality was recognized on a continuum,
Faigley & Meyer suggest. Passages with many events (narration) are at one
end and passages with many statives are at the other (description, classifica-
tion). In the middle are passages with unspecified time, often with modals such
as should, would, could, etc.
This work confirms the importance of temporality that we have arrived at on
a linguistic basis. The conclusions of Faigley & Meyer go beyond temporality
as such: they claim that there is a cognitive basis for text types if genre is
controlled. Their notion of “text types” is that of traditional rhetoric. Although
traditional text types are not defined in linguistic terms, they are remarkably
close to the Discourse Modes arrived at independently here, as I show in 2.4
below.
Time is one of the key factors that affects behavior, memory, and thinking.
We are only dimly aware of the “biological clocks” in the brain that synchronize
body functions with day and night and track the passage of time. Recent work
has led to understanding of how the body keeps time through circadian rhythms,
or “body time” (Wright 2002). However, we do not yet understand very much
about “mind time.” Mind time deals with the brain mechanisms for organizing
time, and the consciousness and perception of time (Damasio 2002). Time
is currently under study in anthropology, biology, neuroscience, philosophy,
physics. That time plays a role in so many aspects of human life may partly
explain its importance in cognition and discourse.
Example sources in this chapter (page nos. are given only for examples from books):
(1) Peter Robinson, A Necessary End, New York: Avon Books, 1989, p. 182.
(2) Eudora Welty, Delta Wedding, New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1945, p. 1.
(3) Barak fights on many fronts. New York Times, May 20, 2000.
(4) Mapping thoughts and even feelings. New York Times, May 20, 1999.
(5) Robert Mosbacher, Cheap oil’s tough bargains. New York Times, March 13, 2000.
(6–8) Oliver Sacks, The Man who Mistook His Wife for a Hat, New York: Harper &
Row, 1970, p. 11.
(9–10) After a victory, Ethiopia looks toward other fronts. New York Times, May 20,
2000.
(11–13) John Scott & Tony Pawson, Cell communication. Scientific American, June
2000.
2 Introduction to the Discourse
Modes
22
2.1 The entities introduced in texts 23
situation types are aspectual in nature; they are discusssed in detail in Chapter 4.
I recognize three classes of situation entity: situations, General Statives, and
Abstract Entities. Situations consist of Events and States. Events differ from
States in the feature of dynamism. Events are dynamic, with successive stages
that take time, while States are static. Example (2) gives simple sentences that
express situations:
The subject or object complement clauses refer to abstract entities. They are
not spatially or temporally located in the world, although the situations they
refer to may be located.
Complement clauses refer to Facts and Propositions. There are, of course,
many sentences that express Facts and Propositions directly. They cannot be
distinguished linguistically, and are therefore beyond the scope of this discus-
sion. This sense of “proposition” should not be confused with the general use
of the term, in which a Proposition is the sense of a sentence, the content that
it expresses.
The class of non-dynamic entities is varied: it includes States, General Sta-
tives, and abstract entities. The Discourse Mode passages in which these entities
predominate are not organized temporally. The feature of dynamism is essential
to the temporal advancement of narrative passages, as I show below.
2. This oversimplifies somewhat: adverbials can give an explicit bound that is less than the full
run-time of an event.
3. Narrative sequence is the default, in this view. Departures from the default are usually signaled
by adverbials or other cues. Another approach takes sequence as one type of “discourse rela-
tion” and change of scale, causation, etc., as different discourse relations; see Chapter 11 for
discussion.
2.2 Text progression in the temporal modes 27
they have an Event verb constellation and the perfective aspectual viewpoint,
conveyed by the simple verb form, e.g. “Mary walked.”4 Event sentences with
the progressive be+ing, a type of imperfective viewpoint, convey ongoing
Events, e.g. “Mary was walking.” Ongoing events and states are unbounded.
These points are discussed in Chapter 4.
The examples below illustrate passages of the Narrative Discourse Mode;
each has sentences of bounded and unbounded Events. The bounded Events
advance narrative time, marked with arrows →:
(5) Narrative passages
a. 1 → I slipped outside into a shock of cool air and → ran down the pier.
2 Several small boats were rocking lazily to and fro in the water. 3 → I
unfastened the rope to one, → paddled out toward the “Republic,” → then
hauled myself hand over hand up a rope ladder to the topgallant bulwark,
over onto a broad empty deck.
b. 1 → When I got to Harry’s Waldorf Towers apartment, they were winding
up the meeting downstairs. 2 → Harry appeared about a half-hour later, →
greeted me warmly, → went immediately to the telephone.
In (5a) the bounded events of S1 and S3 advance narrative time; in (5b) the
when-clause of S1, and the events of S2, advance the narrative.
Unbounded situations – ongoing events and states, including perfects – do
not move time. In the fragments above, ongoing events are expressed in S2 of
(5a) and the main clause of S1 in (5b). We interpret the unbounded situations
as simultaneous with a time previously established in the text.
The preceding passages are from novels; (6) offers an example of a completely
different type of narrative. The passage is from a book of detailed history and
analysis concerning events in the Middle East during and after the First World
War.
(6) → Townshend became aware in the autumn of 1918 of rising peace sentiment
and, like Newcombe, → he decided to give Events a push.
When Townshend learned that the Talaat ministry had fallen, → he arranged
an interview with the new Grand Vizier, and on → 17 October went to the
Sublime Porte carrying some notes that he had sketched out to indicate the
sort of peace terms that might be asked by Britain. His notes suggested that
Britain would be willing to leave the Ottoman Empire in possession of Syria,
Mesopotamia, and perhaps even the Caucasus, so long as these regions were
allowed local autonomy within a restructured empire that would resemble a
confederation of States.
4. The interpretation of perfective sentences is slightly different for the types of events known as
Activities: they are focused as a bounded unit. The unit need not coincide with the endpoints of
the Event; see Chapter 5.
28 Introduction to the Discourse Modes
The perfective event clauses and time adverbials advance the narrative.
Inference can also advance narrative time. When a narrative changes place,
the reader often infers that there has been a change in time. The fragment in
(7) illustrates, from a novel. Banks’ activities and perceptions are recounted in
the first paragraph. In the second paragraph another person appears in another
place, there. We infer that time and place have moved, and that Banks has
arrived at his destination.
(7) 1 Banks dropped Richmond off at a pub near the West Pier and carried on
along Marine Drive, parking just beyond the closed fun-fair. 2 He buttoned up
his raincoat tight and walked along the road that curved around the headland
between the high cliff and the sea. 3 Signs on the hillside warned of falling
rocks. 4 Waves hit the sea-wall and threw up spray onto the road.
5 Tony Grant was already there, leaning on the railing and staring out to the
point where sea and sky merged in a uniform grey. 6 He wore a navy duffle
coat with the hood down.
The paragraph break at S5 suggests a change of direction, and the adverb already
conveys Banks’ expectation that he was to meet Tony Grant. Readers of this
passage in the novel know that Banks had a destination, which supports the
inference of advancement.
Tense is usually unchanging throughout a narrative; conventionally, past is
the narrative tense. Tense in this mode actually conveys continuity rather than
temporal location. The inferences of temporal advancement are based on as-
pectual information – the dynamism of bounded Events in sequence – and to
explicit time adverbials. These points will be explicated in Chapter 5.
(8) Description
a. We were in an impressive and beautiful situation on a rocky plateau. It
was too high for grass, there was very little earth and the place was littered
with boulders, but the whole plateau was covered with a thick carpet of
mauve primulas. There were countless thousands of them, delicate flowers
on thick green stems. Before us was the brilliant green lake, a quarter of a
mile long, and in the shallows and in the streams that spilled over from it
the primulas grew in clumps and perfect circles.
b. An example of this kind of diversity is Eleventh Street between Fifth and
Sixth Avenues in New York, a street admired as both dignified and interest-
ing to walk on. Along its south side it contains, going west, a fourteen-story
apartment house, a church, seven three-story houses . . . a three-story apart-
ment house with a candy and newspaper store at street level. While these
are nearly all residential buildings, they are broken into by instances of ten
other uses. Even the purely residential buildings themselves embrace many
different periods of technology and taste, many different modes and costs
of living. They have an almost fantastic array of matter-of-fact, modestly
stated differences: different heights at first-floor levels, differing arrange-
ments for entrances and sidewalk access.5
These descriptive passages introduces states and events of different kinds. Time
doesn’t advance, at least not significantly.
In passages of the Description mode the reader progresses spatially from
one part of a scene to another. For instance, in the first sentences of (8a) we
tour the rocky plateau from the boulders to the flowers; then to the lake and
its subsidiary streams, following the gaze of the describer. In (8b) the passage
progresses along the buildings of Eleventh Street.
Typically in description there is a locative phrase with scope over the material
that follows, as in these examples. I also assume a tacit durative time adverbial
for descriptive passages. When there is a change of time in description, there is
also a change of scene. The information that tense conveys is anaphoric: the time
of description is that of a time established earlier in the text. The Description
mode is discussed further in Chapter 5.
5. The sentence listing the buildings on Eleventh street is too long to repeat here: it continues for
most of a page along these lines: “a five-story house, thirteen four-story houses, a nine-story
apartment house, five four-story houses with a restaurant and bar at the street level, a five story
apartment, a little graveyard, and a six-story apartment house with a restaurant at street level;
on the north side, again going west . . .”
30 Introduction to the Discourse Modes
(9) Report
a. 1 A week that began in violence ended violently here, with bloody clashes
in the West Bank and Gaza and intensified fighting in Southern Lebanon.
2 Despite the violence, back-channel talks continued in Sweden. 3 Israeli,
Palestinian and American officials have characterized them as a serious and
constructive dialogue on the process itself and on the final status issues.
4 News accounts here say that Israel is offering as much as 90 percent of
the West Bank to the Palestinians, although it is difficult to assess what is
really happening by the bargaining moves that are leaked.
b. 1 At his news conference here, even before he took questions, Schroeder
implicitly challenged the official US explanation for the bombing of the
Chinese embassy in Belgrade – that target analysts relied on a faulty street
map – by renewing his demand for a formal NATO inquiry into the bombing.
2 Diplomats say that Schroeder, who just returned from China, was angry
that a trip he had long planned to herald his chairmanship of the European
Union was transformed into an official apology for the embassy bombing.
The Primary Referent is usually the grammatical object in sentences with tran-
sitive verbs, and subject in sentences with intransitive verbs. Primacy is deter-
mined by event structure, and does not change with shifts of word order and
syntax. So, for instance, the Primary Referent is object in the active sentence
(10a) and subject in the corresponding passive (10b). The Primary Referent
corresponds to the thematic argument role of Theme or Patient in most cases;
see Chapter 4 for discussion.
How a domain is organized in the text can affect progression. There are several
conventional principles for domains: for instance, they may be organized by
hierarchy as in plant and animal taxonomies. Conventional organizing principles
include causal relations, chronology, and geography. Example (11), for instance,
has a geographical organization (cited in Olman 1998):
(11) 1 Cats also spin a story about how creatures adapt to the world they live in.
2 Most landscapes hold wild cats indigenous to every continent except Aus-
tralia and Antarctica. 3 They live in forests, plains, mountains, deserts, snowy
steppes. 4 The margay, a small spotted cat of Central and South America, has
gymnast-like limbs suited to a life of tree climbing in the rain forest. 5 The
32 Introduction to the Discourse Modes
gray-white coat of the snow leopard melts perfectly into the rocky highlands
from Siberia through the Himalayas. 6 The slightly webbed front toes of the
fishing cat help it dive for prey in the rivers of tropical Asia. 7 The clouded
leopard, once found only in Asia’s pristine forests, has turned up in habitats
damaged by overgrazing and logging. 8 It has adapted to the careless hand of
man.
Olman points out that the examples distribute themselves across continents and
landscapes, following the rhetorical principle of Comprehensiveness. Under-
standing the way domains are organized is an interesting and difficult problem.6
Linguistic expressions for space and Primary Referents are discussed further
in Chapters 5 and 6.
(12) 1 Humpbacksi are found in every ocean. 2 Together with blue, fin, sei, Bryde’s,
and mink whales, theyi belong to the rorqual family of baleen whales. 3
Fully grown femalesj , whichj are bulkier than the males, can weigh 40 tons
and reach lengths of 50 feet. 4 Humpbacksi tend to favor shallow areas, often
quite close to shore, and theyi are among the most sociable of the great whales
and the most active at the surface, all of which makes themi among the easiest
to observe.
The Primary Referent is the subject NP in all but one clause in the passage:
“humpbacks,” “they,” “fully grown females,” “which,” “humpbacks,” “they.”
The last clause has a transitive verb and its object, the pronoun them, is the
6. This problem is well known in Artificial Intelligence, where knowledge bases must be organized
to allow searches from different points of view. See Porter et al. (1988), Acker & Porter (1994).
2.3 Text progression in the atemporal modes 33
2.3.3 Argument
An argument passage brings something to the attention of the reader, makes
a claim, comment, or argument and supports it in some way. Claims do not
have a particular linguistic form: they appear in all sorts of linguistic structures.
The assertion of something new, surprising, or tendentious may function as a
claim. For instance, one text I examined begins “The American high school is
obsolete and should be abolished.” In the context of current American life, this
is a strong claim. In linguistic terms the sentence is generic, referring to the
class of high schools. Determining when a sentence makes a claim is beyond
the scope of this discussion.
Passages in the Argument mode are concerned with states of affairs, Facts,
and Propositions. They differ in whether the author is strongly present or not:
we can think of the extremes as the argument and commentary poles. Texts near
the argument pole may not directly involve the author or audience; as in (13).
Sentences 1–2 have complement clauses referring to Facts, sentences 3–4 are
Generalizing Statives. The Primary Referents are underlined.
(13) 1 The routine transfer of power may not be the most dramatic feature of Amer-
ican democracy, but it is the most important. 2 It separates us [the United States]
from the majority of countries in the world, which have still not achieved it. 3
Conceding defeat and going home, or staying on in the minority and allowing
the winner to govern – these are not just the elements of good manners and
sportsmanship. 4 They are the core of patriotism.
(14) 1 It is likely that other new technologies will appear suddenly, leading to
major new industries. 2 What they may be is impossible even to guess at. 3
But it is highly probable – indeed, nearly certain – that they will emerge, and
fairly soon. 4 And it is nearly certain that few of them – and few industries
34 Introduction to the Discourse Modes
The first sentences have the same Primary Referent, so there is no progression.
At S6 the Primary Referent changes, with metaphorical motion from “other
new technologies” to the more abstract predictions the author is making (the
referent of “these”). When the primary is a quantified NP, as in S4 (“few of
them”), the relevant class is taken as primary.
This chapter began with an example of a passage that shifted from the Nar-
rative to the Information mode. Another example of a shift in mode, this time
from Argument to Narrative, is given in (15). The fragment is from the same
text as (13) above; the shift occurs at the second paragraph:
(15) I feel reasonably certain of the final verdict on the current impeachment affair
because I think history will see it as the climax of a six-year period marred by
a troubling and deepening failure of the Republican party to play within the
established constitutional rules.
It was on Election Night 1992, not very far into the evening, that the Senate
minority leader, Bob Dole, hinted at the way his party planned to conduct
itself in the months ahead: it would filibuster any significant legislation the
new Democratic President proposed, forcing him to obtain 60 votes for Senate
passage.
In the first paragraph the clauses refer to Facts and Propositions proposed by the
first-person speaker. There is a shift to narration in the second paragraph. The
clauses introduce Events, and the it-cleft construction signals that a narrative
is about to begin. It is a typical way of setting the scene in traditional tales (“It
was on a dark and stormy night that . . .”).
7. Hopper claims that foreground and background also differ in the familiarity status of subjects,
type of situation, and function. According to Hopper, there is a strong statistical tendency for
foregrounded Events to have familiar, animate subjects, to be punctual rather than durative, to
occur in sequence. In contrast, backgrounded situations tend to have less familiar subjects, to
be durative or stative, not to be sequential (1979:223).
36 Introduction to the Discourse Modes
(16) Narrative
a Harry did not want to run away. . . he kept snivelling and burst out, “But I
don’t want to!” “Yes, you do” I informed him . . . I kept my little brother awake
by telling him stories and then, already chilly in the night air, we sneaked from
the house, crept past the lit windows where our parents sat reading and ran off
down the road in the dark, the pillowcase with its loose tins banging against
my legs. b Harry was crying loudly now. c The bush was not then the domestic
bush it has become . . . And then something happened, the two dogs arrived,
to lick our hands and whine and jump around us. d We had not remembered
the dogs . . . we fled into our bedroom and into bed. We giggled and laughed
and shrieked with relief, and the dogs went quietly back to lie in their places
in the lamplight.
The italicized clause is off the static temporal line and involves another type of
entity. The main clause expresses an Event – the author had a particular thought –
and its complement is propositional.
The Report mode relates situations to Speech Time. One would expect that
narrative would be backgrounded in this mode, since it follows a different
pattern of tense interpretation, that of continuity. This expectation is borne out.
The example illustrates: there is a shift to narrative at S4.
(18) Report
1 The paradox is that the leaders of Ethiopia fought side by side with the
Eritreans to oust the military government of Mengistu Haile Mariam in 1991.
2.4 Foreground and background in text passages 37
2 For the first two years, the two governments were close friends, so close that
they never demarcated the border when Eritrea became independent in 1993. 3
a But tensions grew over personality clashes and economic rivalry, exploding
in May 1998 b when Eritrea claimed the Badme border region based on old
colonial maps. 4 Eritrea moved troops into the area. 5 a Ethiopia said it was
invaded, b and a war ignited that c has defied long peace talks and claimed
tens of thousands of lives on both sides.
The narrative fragment consists of the events of S4 and S5a–b; they are related
to the Event of S3a (“tensions grew”). The Report mode resumes at S5c, with
the present perfect. In this passage the narrative is subsidiary, backgrounded.
The atemporal modes progress metaphorically, and have the deictic pattern
of tense interpretation. Specific situations may be backgrounded. For instance,
the following Information passage consists of generalizing statives, except for
one clause, which is italicized:
(19) Information
The motifs [of the moulded pottery] include a large number of different flowers
and fruits including the chrysanthemum, which is not found in the carved
ware, both the flower and fruit of the pomegranate and melon gourds. To
these are added somewhat abstract foliage scrolls and a debased form of
key-fret, the only geometric motif in Ting decoration. There are proper fish
among aquatic plants and in lotus pools. Finally there are chubby infants,
wholly or partially naked. It seems unlikely that they were incorporated into the
decorative vocabulary much before the late twelfth century. The organization
of the surface [of the pottery] is similar to that of the carved ware.
(20) Argument
1 We in academia must figure out what is really critical to us and what we are
willing to give up.
2 Not all of these choices will be ours alone. 3 Our students, as well as our
governments, have changing expectations. 4 Information economies require
higher levels of education and more frequent education. 5 More of the new
student body may be part time, working and older. 6 I asked some students in
this new breed what relationship they wanted with their colleges. 7 They told
me that it should be like the relationship with a utility company, supermarket or
bank – their emphasis was on convenience, service, quality and affordability.
38 Introduction to the Discourse Modes
The question and answer of S6 and S7 are Events, one following the other. They
are unlike the entities expressed in preceding clauses, which are more abstract
and deictically organized. At S8 the Argument mode resumes with a general
prediction.
The examples show that with changes of entity there is a change from fore-
ground to background in passages of a given mode. The change is, in effect, to
a different mode. However, we tend to take one or two clauses merely as a shift
from foreground to background.
Summarizing, I have shown two ways in which material may be back-
grounded in text passages. They correspond to the distinctive characteristics
of the Discourse Modes. Situations are in the background if they do not ad-
vance the time of a passage in the temporal modes; or if they are of a different
type from those of the current Discourse Mode.
8. I thank Keith Walters for helpful discussion of this section. The definition in the text is from the
American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language, 3rd edition, Boston: Houghton Mifflin
Co., 1992.
2.5 Rhetorical and linguistic background 39
Aristotle taught that there are three aspects to persuasion: the truth and log-
ical validity of what is being argued (logos); the speaker’s success in con-
veying to an audience that he or she is to be trusted (ethos); and the emo-
tions that the speaker can awaken in the audience (pathos). In the Rhetoric,
persuasive oratory is organized into categories of political, legal, and ceremo-
nial (praise and censure). Classical rhetoric was further developed by Cicero,
roughly from 103 to 46 BC, and by Quintilian in the first century AD. After the
first century it was taught off and on in Europe until the end of the eighteenth
century.
There was a strong revival of classical rhetoric in nineteenth-century England.
Richard Whately’s 1828 Elements of Rhetoric presents itself as an adaptation
of classical rhetoric. Whately discusses the invention, arrangement, and intro-
duction of propositions and arguments. He teaches students how to find suitable
arguments to prove a point, and how to arrange them skillfully. Whateley gives
a typology of arguments (syllogisms, arguments from example, from testimony,
cause to effect, analogy); the appropriate use of arguments; the best arrange-
ment of arguments. Part II treats Persuasion, “influencing the will.” Whately’s
book was reprinted in 1963 and is still cited in discussions of rhetoric.
Modern rhetoric in the United States emphasizes the social and communica-
tive aspects of persuasive discourse (Lunsford & Ede 1984). Rhetorical texts
teach students the actual processes of planning, speaking, writing, in addition
to classic argumentation. For instance, Edward P. Corbett’s Classical Rhetoric
for the Modern Student, published in 1965 and still reprinted, offers rhetoric
as a system for finding something to say, learning how to select and organize
material, and how to phrase it in the best possible way. Corbett’s main topics
are discovery of arguments, arrangement of material, and style.
The text draws on a categorization of discourse types that is close to the
Discourse Modes of this book. Corbett recognizes “four forms of discourse:
Argumentation, Exposition, Description, Narration” (1965:32). They are not
defined or documented, but assumed as part of the toolkit of the rhetorician.
For instance, Corbett says that, in expository discourse, one can sometimes
organize according to a chronological scheme. But in argumentative discourse,
the speaker has to think about things like where to use the weakest argument
(1965:314). The notion of forms of discourse has a fairly long history in England
and America.
and rhetorical mode. Brooks & Warren distinguish two types of narrative, for
instance, according to the purpose of the text. “Expository” or “ordinary”
narration aims to give information, to explain (1958:110), while narrative
proper appeals to the imagination; there is a difference in intention, and thus in
method (1958:231). From the point of view of this book, “narrative proper” and
“expository narrative” are both of the narrative type, appearing in different
genres. Brooks & Warren’s comments can be interpreted as a recognition that
rhetorical mode differs from genre.
Many textbooks of composition used the approach of Bain and Genung in the
United States from about 1885 until the 1940s. After that expository writing was
emphasized in many rhetorical texts, to the exclusion of the other forms. There
was also a new emphasis on “process-oriented” teaching that emphasized the
writer’s intentions and methods, beginning in the 1960s (Connors 1997:251).
The rhetorical modes are found less often in texts today, mainly because they
did not help students learn to write, according to Connors; see Larson (1984)
for a different view.
The approach of rhetorical modes has been strongly criticized, especially as
a teaching technique. The pragmatic objection is that it is not effective with
students. Theoretically, people objected that it confuses purpose with mode:
“The categories [are] supposedly based on purpose or intention.Yet narrative
can scarcely be seen as an intention in the same sense as persuasion or exposition
might be. We can perceive widely varying intentions in different narratives such
as a fictional story, a factual report of Events, a scientific account of a sequence
of Events, and a narrative contained within an advertisement” (Britton et al.
975:5). There may be just such a confusion in Brooks & Warren’s treatment of
narrative.
Another point is that different rhetorical modes can be used in pursuit of a
single purpose. Faigley & Meyer comment, “an argument against slums might
well use descriptions of living conditions in slums, personal narratives of life
in slums, and evaluations of housing conditions in slums,” and go on to claim
that this criticism “refutes” the traditional modes (1983:308). But this is too
strong. The problem is rather a confusion between mode and genre. Moreover,
the experiments cited in their own work (mentioned above) give evidence that
the rhetorical modes have a cognitive basis.
There is indeed a certain confusion in discussions of the rhetorical modes.
We are told that they have a particular purpose or intention that determines
their character – which suggests that they function at the level of genre. Yet the
modes can be used to realize different purposes, in different genres. I think that
42 Introduction to the Discourse Modes
we can resolve the confusion by clarifying the distinction between genre and
mode. The rhetorical modes do not classify by purpose. Rather, they describe
texts at the more local level identified in this book as the passage.
The rhetorical Discourse Modes correspond nicely to the linguistically based
Discourse Modes of this book. One Discourse Mode, the Report, does not
appear in the traditional classification. The importance of Report as a Discourse
Mode may be due partly to mass communication, with the pervasive use of
newspaper, television, and now internet reports. Moreover, diaries and other
personal genres are taken seriously today and they often use the Report type of
organization.
Actual texts consist of more than one type or mode of discourse: this is an
uncontroversial point on which all agree.
9. Biber (1989) lists the genres studied as follows – examples of written genres from LOB corpus:
press reportage, editorials, press reviews, religion, skills and hobbies, popular lore, biographies,
official documents, academic prose, general fiction, mystery fiction, science fiction, adven-
ture fiction, romantic fiction, humor, personal letters, professional letters; examples of spoken
genres from London-Lund corpus – face-to-face conversation, telephone conversation, public
conversation, debates, interviews, broadcasts, spontaneous speeches, planned speeches.
44 Introduction to the Discourse Modes
10. For instance, Edward Smith (1985) looked for linguistic features correlating with four very
general text types identified by Longacre (1983/1996): Narrative, Procedural, Behavioral,
and Expository texts. He concluded that genre – purpose – isn’t conveyed by linguistic
features.
11. Discourse grammars use phrase structure expansion rules, producing hierarchical structures.
The grammar approach treats a discourse as one big sentence with hierarchically related parts.
Linguists and psychologists developed these grammars in attempting to model the processes of
discourse construction and discourse understanding. In principle, they believed, the units and
relations of a story grammar are psychologically real: “a higher level organization takes
place . . . strings of sentences combine into psychological wholes which account for . . . salient
facts about structure” (Rumelhart 1975:213). In the 1970s, some experimental evidence sup-
porting story grammars was found. Subjects remembered information, for instance, according
to the sub-units posited; but other, more general explanations for these results have been offered
(Garnham 1983, 1985).
According to Garnham, “The problem is to specify the way in which general semantic
definitions of syntactic categories could be used to compute the category of a proposition.
2.5 Rhetorical and linguistic background 45
the units of a story grammar and the linguistic units in which a story is real-
ized. For instance, the Reaction part of an Episode may be given by a phrase, a
sentence, several sentences, a paragraph, etc. Recognizing such a sub-part usu-
ally requires inference. But if this is true, we cannot specify a procedure for
going from the abstract “story grammar” to the actual story: no mapping pro-
cedure exists.12
Story grammarians have never noted this problem, let alone attempted to solve it” (1983:150).
Garnham suggests that psycholinguists’ findings are better explained in terms of referential
continuity and plausibility.
12. Apparent violations of a convention are interpreted with additional inferences that make them
plausible.
46 Introduction to the Discourse Modes
Instances of the same word may be coherent even if the two are not coreferential:
(22) a. Why does this little boy have to wriggle all the time?
b. Other boys don’t wriggle. Boys always wriggle.
c. Good boys don’t wriggle. Boys should be kept out of here.
Lexical items that appear in similar contexts have a cohesive effect. For instance,
in (23) the word “girls” is cohesive:
(23) a. Why does this little boy have to wriggle all the time?
b. Girls don’t wriggle.
“Girls” is related by complementarity to “this little boy” Halliday & Hasan note
that texts may have cohesive “chains” of related words:
candle . . . flame . . . flicker; hair . . . comb . . . curl; sky . . . sunshine . . . cloud . . .
rain.
13. The contribution of “cohesive factors” to literary texts was studied by Gutwinski (1976). She
examined texts by Henry James and Ernest Hemingway for cohesive ties. James and Heming-
way are considered to have different styles of writing, and Gutwinski found that their choice
of cohesive ties were different. James depended primarily on grammatical cohesion, especially
anaphora, whereas Hemingway used lexical cohesion almost exclusively. Gutwinski’s study
demonstrated that cohesion could be identified and that it contributed to literary
texts.
14. Hearst suggests that one can discover a text’s structure by dividing it up into sentences and seeing
how much word overlap appears among them. The overlap forms a kind of intra-structure;
fully connected graphs might indicate dense discussion of a topic, while long spindly chains
of connectivity might indicate a sequential account.
15. Halliday & Hasan also claim that cohesion distinguishes a text from an incoherent sequence
of sentences. In other words, cohesion is what distinguishes a coherent, well-formed text.
Arguments against this strong claim are given in Brown & Yule (1983), Blakemore (1988). For
discussion of the relation between cohesion and “coherence” see Stoddard (1991:13ff.) and
Sanford & Moxey (1995).
48 Introduction to the Discourse Modes
49
50 Text representation and understanding
Predicate Logic and Situation Semantics. All of these theories have an es-
sential pragmatic thrust: they take context as crucial for interpreting discourse.
They deal with both semantic and pragmatic reasoning and information.
Pragmatics concerns language as communicative action. What a person says
usually underdetermines interpretation, yet most communication is successful.
Pragmatics tries to account for this apparent paradox. Successful communi-
cation results from a tacit negotiation between speaker or writer and receiver,
based on shared assumptions about communication. Speakers try to give enough
information so that receivers can understand their intentions. In order to do
this, receivers must often work out the semantic and pragmatic meanings of a
communication.
The now-classical approach of Grice makes a distinction between the sem-
antic and pragmatic meanings of a sentence. Semantic meaning is conveyed
by linguistic expressions, while pragmatic meaning adds what a speaker im-
plicates and/or intends when uttering a sentence in a particular context. In
principle, sentence meaning is semantic, while speaker’s meaning is prag-
matic. Grice developed a theory of how intended meaning can be derived from
what is said (1975, 1989). He stated a set of basic assumptions, the coop-
erative maxims that underlie communication. Using these maxims and what
they know about the world, people calculate by inference the interpretations
intended in a text. In this view, semantic meaning is the input to pragmatic
meaning.
Pragmatic interpretations, or implicatures, are not logically entailed by what
is said. They can be cancelled, as Grice put it, by additional information. If I
say “John and Mary have two children,” you will probably infer that two is the
total number of children that they have. This is a conversational implicature. I
might go on to say more – possibly “indeed, they have four children” and this
would cause you to cancel your earlier inference. Entailments, truth-conditions,
and the conventional meanings attached to particular words cannot be cancelled
and therefore have a different status.
The division of labor between semantics and pragmatics seemed relatively
clear at one time; it is currently the subject of active debate.1 Complete sepa-
ration of semantics and pragmatics is difficult to maintain, because pragmatic
1. Kent Bach, for instance, proposes that “semantic meaning is the conventional meaning of lin-
guistic expressions, while pragmatic meaning is context-dependent, pertaining to utterances and
facts surrounding them.” In contrast, Levinson argues that conversational implicature plays a
role in assigning truth-condition, so that semantics and pragmatics are interwoven in most cases
(1999:168).
3.2 Types of inference 51
fill out explicit linguistic material with information which is essential for
understanding. Often, in talking and writing, the speaker or writer leaves out
what seems obvious, assuming that the receiver will recover it by inference. In
a detailed account such things must be made explicit.
Interpretation that goes beyond linguistic forms is an everyday part of
language understanding, not an exotic phenomenon. People tend to avoid
redundancy – for instance, relying on the receiver’s ability to interpret reduced
forms. A fully explicit and redundant text is not preferred and may even be
confusing. Consider the examples in (1):
(1) a. John and Mary went to the store and John and Mary bought two large
lobsters.
b. John and Mary went to the store and they bought two large lobsters.
c. John and Mary went to the store and bought two large lobsters.
(1b, c) are more natural and perhaps easier to understand than (1a), the
most explicit. If an unreduced sentence is used it tends to carry a special
meaning.4
Working out the intended referent of a pronoun often requires inference.
There may be more than one possibility. For instance, in the sentence “John
said that he was leaving,” “he” may refer to John or to another person; in a
specific context, one interpretation is usually preferred. In the second sentence
of “John saw Thomas. He was wearing a red hat,” the first natural interpreta-
tion of the pronoun referent is “Thomas”; but other information could override
this. In other cases, pragmatic knowledge about the world makes one interpre-
tation more plausible than another. Compare “Mary lent Jane a bicycle. She
asked her to be careful with it,” and “Mary lent Jane a bicycle. She thanked
her.” In the first sequence “she” would probably refer to Mary, whereas, in
the second, “she” would probably refer to Jane. Normally people use con-
text, inference, and world knowledge to choose the most plausible pronoun
referent.
Inferences are often needed to relate things to each other; one common
relation is part–whole, illustrated in different ways by the examples of (2):
4. One of Grice’s points is that flouting the maxims conveys a special meaning. The maxim of
quantity says that one should make one’s contribution as informative as required, and do not
make it more informative than required for the purposes of the communication. Sentences (1a)
and even (1b) would flout this maxim in most situations.
The additional meanings of unreduced conjunctions are explored by Levinson as examples
of “generalized conversational implicature” (2000:148). Levinson argues that generalized im-
plicature is distinct in kind from the implicatures of a particular utterance in context.
3.2 Types of inference 53
In (2aii), we infer that “the beer” is part of “the picnic supplies.” To understand
(2bii) we infer an event, a trip that is implicit in (2bi); the second sentence gives
details of that trip. To understand (2cii) one infers that the steering-wheel is
part of the car that Mary was driving (2ci) and one posits a car. Inferences like
those of (2) are known as “bridging” inferences. Bridging is an obligatory part
of comprehension, since the receiver must identify the intended referents for all
referring expressions. Experiments show that people make bridging inferences
like those above in the course of text understanding (Haviland & Clark 1974).
The inferences involve world knowledge, knowledge of the context, logical
entailments, and plausible reasoning.
Positing an entity that is not explicitly introduced in the discourse is a general
type of inference known as “accommodation.” The receiver infers the existence
of an entity if it is necessary to do so for coherence (Lewis 1979). In accom-
modation one accepts the information conveyed by a linguistic form whether
or not the form has an appropriate antecedent and adds an entity or presuppo-
sition to the common ground.5 For instance, the definite article the pragmati-
cally conveys that the referent of a NP is familiar, either known or identifiable
(see Chapter 6). Encountering a definite NP that is not familiar, the receiver
accommodates by taking the referent of the NP to be a known individ-
ual. Novels often exploit this convention by beginning with a definite NP
whose referent cannot be known to the reader. The experienced reader as-
sumes that the individual is to be added to the universe of discourse, and
waits for more information. The assumption that the referent of the N is
familiar is a pragmatic presupposition. In pragmatic presupposition one takes
information as uncontroversial in the context or common ground. There are
two main uses of the term “presupposition,” one “pragmatic” and the other
“semantic.”
Semantic presupposition is triggered by particular linguistic expressions: they
have the conventional meaning that information is known or presupposed. For
5. We understand that an entity is added to the common ground. Lewis discussed accommodation
in terms of presupposition: “if at time t something is said that requires presupposition p to be
acceptable, and if p is not presupposed just before t then presupposition p comes into existence,
ceteris paribus” (1979:172). See also Heim (1982).
54 Text representation and understanding
instance, “Tom stopped running” entails “Tom ran.”6 The contexts of semantic
presupposition include the complements of “factive” verbs (know, regret); the
clefted clause of cleft sentences (“It was the butler that stole the jewels”);
temporal adverbial clauses (“John left after calling his mother”). The informa-
tion in such contexts is treated as familiar, whatever its actual status for the
receiver.
The constructive view of language understanding has experimental support
from psycholinguistics. In a classic group of experiments, Bransford et al.
(1972) studied how people understood descriptions of situations that differed
slightly, as in sentences (3a) and (3b) below. The situations have somewhat dif-
ferent consequences. From (3a) a person can infer (3c), using spatial knowledge
of the world. In the situation described, if the fish swam beneath the turtles,
it swam beneath the log. Sentence (3b) does not support such an inference,
however, so that (3d) does not follow from (3b).
(3) a. Three turtles rested on a floating log and a fish swam beneath them.
b. Three turtles rested beside a floating log and a fish swam beneath them.
c. Three turtles rested on a floating log and a fish swam beneath it.
d. Three turtles rested beside a floating log and a fish swam beneath it.
In the experiments subjects were first presented with sentences like (3a) and (3b)
and asked to remember them. Later they heard a group of sentences containing
the originals and new, slightly different sentences – some of them like (3c) and
some like (3d). The subjects’ task was to say whether they had heard a sentence
before.
Subjects tended to “recognize” sentences that were consistent with the orig-
inal descriptions, with high confidence. In other words they tended to confuse
sentences like (3a) with (3c), but not to confuse sentences like (3b) with (3d).
Bransford et al. interpret the result as showing that “recognition was primarily
a function of the complete semantic descriptions constructed rather than a func-
tion of just that information specified by the linguistic input strings” (1972:205).
Results like these strongly support the mental model view of sentence repre-
sentation.
6. There are well-known tests for semantic presupposition. The best-known is negation. Semantic
presupposition is undisturbed by negation, as in (b), the negation of (a):
Both (a) and (b) carry the presupposition that Sam ran. Other tests include embedding under
modality, the antecedent test, the test for constancy under illocutionary force.
3.3 Mental models and representations 55
7. Not all agree with this classical view. In the approach of Connectionism, or Parallel Distri-
buted Processing, the mind is not symbolic but rather a network of simple processing units.
Connectionist cognitive modeling tries to understand the mechanisms of human cognition
through the use of simulated networks of simple, neuronlike processing units. This approach
is presented in McClelland & Rumelhart (1986), Bechtel & Abrahamsen (1991), and others.
A. Clark (1989) provides cautionary comments.
56 Text representation and understanding
states construction rules which take the sentences of a text as input and deliver a
representation as output. It does not try to account for the actual mental process
involved in understanding a text.
The model corresponds to the way some state of affairs might be, a mapping
from the DRS to the model and the world. The mapping is stated with rules
of functional application: they assign to sentences a denotation or meaning in
a model. It is impossible to include everything that is in the world in framing
conditions and models. Rather, the information in a sentence focuses on certain
situations, entities, locations, and times; the rest of the world is assumed. Thus
the models specified are partial models. In this book I work with conceptual
representations; the conceptual and truth-conditional levels are discussed in
Kamp (1981), Kamp & Reyle (1993).
8. Rules for calculating narrative progression in the DR Theory framework are proposed in Kamp &
Reyle (1993); they are somewhat different in detail from the rules given here.
58 Text representation and understanding
projection Aspect Phrase (AspP) for the simple and progressive verb forms.
The subject of a verb is directly dominated by IP; the direct object ap-
pears in the Verbphrase (VP) as sister to the verb. For simplicity, I ignore
higher projections and other projections that might appear in a more complete
structure.
The construction rules of the theory interpret the information in surface
syntactic structure and in the already-constructed DRS. Complex structures
and dependencies are modeled with sub-structures that are within the scope of
operators such as negation, quantifiers, modal subordination. The theory has
had notable successes in analyzing referential, scopal, and other phenomena.
For detailed accounts see the references in the text.
Rules of the theory applies to hierarchical surface structures with syntactic–
semantic features. The structures do not otherwise encode semantic informa-
tion: there is no level of Logical Form nor an associated semantic structure.9
The syntactic–semantic features are stated on the relevant syntactic node and
percolate to higher nodes in the syntactic tree. The features that I will use in
this introduction are NP number, gender, and case; verb class; aspectual view-
point associated with the simple verb form or the progressive; times and their
relations associated with tense morphemes. In discussions later other features
are used.
The rules account for the conventional meanings conveyed by a sentence,
abstracting away from lexical semantics. Structural constraints on interpre-
tation are modeled in a Discourse Representation Structure with embedded
sub-structures. Material within an embedded structure may not be accessible
as antecedent for anaphoric expressions.
As an introductory example, I show how entities for individuals and sit-
uations are represented for a discourse fragment, following the treatment of
Kamp & Reyle (1993). I then add tense and aspectual information. Consider (4):
(4) Mary read Ulysses. It fascinated her.
The figure in (5) gives a simplified syntactic tree representation of the first
sentence of this fragment. In the figure, PN = proper name; ø = zero, associated
9. Logical Form is a semantic level in Principles and Parameters theory and related theories; it is
irrelevant to DR Theory, which provides semantic interpretation.
Syntactic surface structures developed in other syntactic frameworks are also appropriate for
the construction rules of DR Theory. Kamp & Reyle (1993) use the syntactic framework and
representations of Gazdar et al. (1985). The framework is convenient because it is explicit and
has a carefully worked out way of dealing with syntactic–semantic features.
60 Text representation and understanding
in the tree below with the perfective viewpoint; the E subscript on the verb is a
feature classifying it as an event verb.
NP I'
N' I AspP
PN tense Asp' VP
Mary past
Asp V'
Ø V NP
read N'
PN
Ulysses
PN PN
3.4 Analysis of text passages in DR Theory 61
For the sentence structure in (5) the rule applies first to the configuration in
(6ai). The third condition of (b) results in an intermediate structure “x read
Ulysses,” not given here.
The next constituent considered here is the VP; I return to the other nodes
later in dealing with aspect and tense information. Rule (6aii) applies to the VP
configuration, licensing the entity y as Ulysses (“reads y”). The highest NP and
the VP together license a situation entity e and a condition that characterizes it;
and the syntactic structure is deleted. The complete rule is not given here; see
Kamp & Reyle (1993) for details.
The resulting partial DRS is given in (7): e introduces the event of Mary’s
reading. The information in the DRS consists of the discourse entities, listed at
the top, and the conditions, displayed below.
x y e
1. x = Mary
2. y = Ulysses
3. e: read (x,y)
The figure in (7) follows the standard format for DRSs: a two-tiered box that
encloses the entire structure; embedded structures are represented by sub-DRSs,
which have the form of embedded boxes.
The tree structure for the second sentence of fragment (4), It fascinated
her, is like the first except that the NPs are pronouns. For each pronoun, a
new discourse referent is entered into the top part of the DRS, together with
conditions that identify it. Pronouns may be interpreted as coreferential with
an antecedent discourse referent if they agree in gender and number. I assume
that the construction rules include a mechanism for agreement. In (8), there is
a partial DRS for both sentences of (4); lines 4 and 5 provide that the pronouns
are coreferential with their antecedents, the discourse referents x and y. The
entity at the top is s, the situation of Mary’s being fascinated by Ulysses, a
state.
62 Text representation and understanding
x y u v e s
1. x = Mary
2. y = Ulysses
3. e: = read (x,y)
4. u=y
5. v=x
6. s: fascinates (u,v)
In (8) the antecedents of the pronouns are available for coreference and there
are no other possibilities, so that the DRS identification is licensed.
In some cases the structure of the DRS makes an NP inaccessible as an an-
tecedent for coreference. When an NP is within the scope of a general quantifier
or negation, for instance, it cannot serve as antecedent to a pronoun. For in-
stance, the sequence “John doesn’t own a car. It is red” is ill formed because
the NP a car is in the scope of negation and cannot function as an antecedent
for the pronoun it. The sequence “The elephant is a gentle beast. He is run-
ning away from danger” is ill formed for similar reasons. The first sentence is
generic, while the second expresses a specific event and the pronoun refers to
a specific elephant. This kind of inaccessibility is represented in a DRS with
embedded structures. NPs are discussed more fully in Part II; the DRT treatment
of coreference is discussed in Kamp & Reyle (1993).
The rules can also be stated with labeled bracketing. The rules can “see” the
relevant configuration, as well as features on NPs, verbs, etc. These features are
needed anyway in a grammar of the language. Example (9), for instance, gives
a labeled bracket version of the rule above.
The structural description appears on the left side of the arrow; it corresponds
to the tree structure in (6). Here only the information relevant to a particular
rule is given; variables a, b represent other material in the sentence. The rule
specifies the relevant phrase structure nodes and, for the NPs in question, the
PN feature; the dots represent the actual proper names. On the right side of
the arrow is the interpretation, in this case entities x and y to be entered into
the DRS with the proper name as specifying condition. Rule (a) recognizes the
subject of a sentence, corresponding to the configuration in (6ai) above. Rule
3.4 Analysis of text passages in DR Theory 63
(b) recognizes the direct object; it corresponds to (6aii) above, though it is more
specific. For the fragment in (7), the dots in rule (9a) represent the proper name
Mary; the dots in rule (9b) represent Ulysses. The rules in (9) result in the same
DRS as those of (6). I will use rules like (9) throughout the book.
Now we add rules that interpret the aspectual and temporal information of
fragment (4), repeated here:
Aspectual information gives the class of the situation entity and the aspectual
viewpoint. The sentence “Mary read Ulysses” licenses an Event entity in the
DRS, because of the E feature on the verb and the proper names in subject
and object position; see Chapter 4 for discussion. The E feature on the verb is
visible to the rule, as in (10):
This rule adds the entity e at the top of the DRS and a condition which specifies
that the entity e is an Event, perhaps of a certain class.
The aspectual viewpoint of the sentence is perfective, because it has the
simple verb form rather than the progressive auxiliary. Example (11) indicates
very roughly how this interpretation is made. The rule focuses on the simple
verb form and the Event verb; it licenses a viewpoint condition in the DRS.
The rules (10–12) add more information to the DRS, as shown in (13). Discourse
entities for times are added at the top, t1 and t2. Line 4 specifies that the situation
entity is an event, line 5 specifies that the viewpoint is perfective; the next two
lines characterize the times, and line 8 locates the event entity at t2.
(13) Partial DRS for “Mary read Ulysses.”
x y e t1 t2
1. x = Mary
2. y = Ulysses
3. e: read (x,y)
4. e = Event
5. View(e) = Perf
6. t1 = SpT
7. t2 < t1
8. e at 12
The Discourse Modes introduce situation entities into the universe of discourse,
and have different principles of text progression. The information is conveyed by
forms of aspect and temporal location. The two are complementary. Temporal
location locates a situation in time, while aspect specifies the internal temporal
structure of the situation. This chapter is devoted to aspect; temporal location
is discussed in Chapter 5.
The understanding of aspect is the key to the analysis of Discourse Modes,
because the situation entities are aspectual in nature. The Discourse Modes
characteristically introduce different types of situation entities. Passages of
the Narrative and Report modes primarily involve Events and States. The
Description mode primarily concerns States and ongoing Events. The Infor-
mation mode primarily has General Statives; the Argument mode primarily has
Abstract Entities, Facts and Propositions, and General Statives. After a brief
introduction to aspectual systems, this chapter discusses the concepts of situ-
ation entities and their linguistic correlates, and how aspectual information is
encoded in Discourse Representation Theory.
Section 4.1 introduces the two components of aspectual systems and dis-
cusses Event and State situation types, including shifts of one type to another;
4.2 discusses General Statives; 4.3 discusses Abstract Entities; 4.4 discusses
the linguistic correlates for the three major classes of situation type; 4.5 covers
aspectual information in Discourse Representation Structures.
67
68 Aspectual information
Both are relevant to the Discourse Modes. Situation entities realize different
situation types, while viewpoints focus all or part of a situation. Together they
determine the boundedness of situations, which is essential for temporal pro-
gression in the Narrative mode. Situation type indirectly classifies situations
into the major categories of Event and State situations, statives, and Abstract
Entities. In previous work I have used the term “situation type” for situations
and General Statives. I now extend it to include abstract entities as a separate
class.
Situation types are idealizations of situations, semantic concepts organized
according to their internal temporal properties. They are conveyed by the com-
posite of the verb and its arguments, the “verb constellation.” Verb constella-
tions of each class have distinctive distributional properties. Because of these
properties, the situation types are covert linguistic categories which are tacitly
available to the speakers of a language.
The aspectual viewpoint of a sentence is like the lens of a camera. It focuses
on all or part of the situation expressed by a sentence, making the focused infor-
mation visible. Only visible information is available for semantic interpretation.
Viewpoint is important for calculating advancement in the temporal Discourse
Modes, because it is one of the factors that determines whether a situation is
bounded or unbounded.
Viewpoint and situation type constitute closed “closed systems,” within
which a choice must be made from a few possibilities. There are two main
viewpoints in English, marked morphologically as in most languages. The
simple verb form is “perfective,” focusing events with bounds (“Mary made
a desk”). States are unbounded in the perfective, however (“John knew the
answer”). The progressive verbal auxiliary is an “imperfective”: it applies only
to events.2 The progressive focuses an open interval, without endpoints: an inter-
nal interval of a durative event (“We are building a sandcastle”) or a preliminary
interval of an instantaneous event (“He is winning the race”). Both are taken as
ongoing events. Progressive viewpoints appear in many languages. Other imper-
fective viewpoints, for instance the French imparfait, apply to states as well as
events.
The information given by a viewpoint depends on the type of situation entity
it focuses. Each class of verb constellation and aspectual viewpoint has an
associated temporal schema, and viewpoints focus all or part of the temporal
schema. The relationship between situation type and viewpoint is modeled by a
2. There is a marked use of the progressive with stative verb constellations, often found in informal
speech, e.g. “I’m loving this walk.” Such sentences present states as events (Smith 1997).
4.1 Aspectual categories 69
Associated with each situation type is a schema that represents its temporal
properties. The temporal schema of Events includes either a single point or an
initial and final point, depending on the feature of duration. The final endpoint
is natural or arbitrary, depending on telicity. The schema for a State does not
have endpoints: changes into and out of a state are events in their own right
and not part of the state. For simplicity I will sometimes call a verb constel-
lation or sentence by the situation type or temporal feature with which it is
associated – for instance, an “event” or “dynamic” sentence.
The visible span of the viewpoint inherits the properties of the entire situation
schema.3 This correctly provides that we know the situation type of a sentence,
independent of whether the viewpoint makes visible all or part of the situation.
3. For Activities the precise statement is more complex. Activities are focused by the perfective
viewpoint with implicit temporal bounds which may, but need not, coincide with their endpoints.
In other words, the temporal boundedness of the viewpoint does not require that an activity
terminate.
The perfective viewpoint focuses a segment that is implicitly bounded. If the activity continues
after the implicit bound, the continuation constitutes another temporal segment. The point is
delicate but important for understanding the contribution of Activities to discourse. Assertions
of continuation may felicitously be made, as in the examples below. The second conjunct of
4.1 Aspectual categories 71
4.1.4 Coercion
There is a standard, basic-level set of associations between situations in the
world and idealized situation types. In choices that depart from the standard,
the speaker uses derived situation types (Smith 1995a). They are shifted by rule
from the basic-level types through a mechanism widely known as “coercion,” a
term due to Moens (1987). No additional situation types are needed to account
for coercion: derived situation types fall into the same classes. Shifts in situation
type are triggered by material in the context, often by adverbials. For instance,
“Mary knew the truth” is a state sentence. With the adverbial suddenly, as
in “Suddenly Mary knew the truth,” the sentence expresses an event, that of
Mary coming to know the truth. Another example is the perfect: in the perfect
construction dynamic sentences shift to states, e.g. “We have (already) eaten
each sentence asserts that another segment, or temporal unit, follows the unit presented in the
first conjunct (Smith 1999b).
4. States and other static situations are homogeneous, with a uniform part structure. They have the
sub-interval property: when a state holds for an interval, it holds equally for any smaller interval
of that interval. Progressives, too, have this property.
In a view that I have characterized as the “strong mereological” approach, states, progressives
and Activities all belong to the one global semantic category because of their homogeneity. For
discussion see Smith (1999) and the references therein.
72 Aspectual information
dinner.”5 Derived situation types include the basic verb constellation and the
triggering adverbial.
Adverbials of duration and completion can also trigger a shift in situation
type. Telic verb constellations become atelic with a simple durative adverbial,
as (3) shows:
(3) a. Mary wrote a letter.
b. Mary wrote a letter for an hour.
The understanding of (3a) is that Mary wrote and completed a letter; that of
(3b) is that she was engaged in the activity of letter-writing, but that she did
not actually complete a letter. The shift in understanding is due to the different
aspectual values of the verb constellation and the adverbial: durative adver-
bials are atelic. Example (3) illustrates a consistent pattern in coercion. If there
is a clash in value between the verb constellation and an adverbial or other
form external to it, the external value overrides. This pattern is formalized in
Section 4.4 as the Principle of External Override.
The progressive is often treated as an instance of coercion. In this approach
the progressive is an operator that applies to events and produces states as a
derived situation type (Vlach 1981, Kamp & Reyle 1993). The treatment has
the advantage of formally unifying progressives and static situations. But there
is a disadvantage: progressives are not entirely like states.6 For discussion see
Smith (1983, 1995b).
I now turn to the two other major classes of entities. They are all static in
nature and thus form a super-class with States.
5. The “perfect” construction is formed with the verbal auxiliary have and a participle. In English
there are past, present, and future perfects.
Perfects are semantically states: one piece of evidence is that they do not advance narrative
time. The perfect affects temporal location as well as aspect; see Comrie (1976), Kamp & Reyle
(1993), Michaelis (1994).
6. The differences between them are significant: (a) progressives cannot be taken as inchoatives,
whereas states can be; (b) progressives are dynamic, whereas states are not; (c) progressives and
statives have different co-occurrence properties with adverbials as noted in Glasbey (1998).
4.2 General Statives 73
Sentences like these are studied in depth in the articles in Carlson & Pelletier
(1995).
Generic sentences refer to kinds rather than individuals: in (4b) the subject
NP denotes the entire class of lions, not a particular lion or lions. Definite NPs
(the lion) and bare plurals (lions) are the main types of NP that are used as kind-
referring. Indefinite NPs, both mass and count, can be used in a “taxonomic”
reading, as in “The World Wildlife Organization decided to protect a (certain)
large cat, namely the Siberian tiger,” an example from Krifka et al. (1995).
Generalizing sentences express regularities, not particular facts. Such sen-
tences often have a frequency adverbial (sometimes, always, never). There are
a number of special forms which lead to the general reading, e.g. used to, the
agentive -er suffix, the middle voice, present simple tense with an Event verb
constellation. Kind-referring NPs can occur in a Generalizing sentence, as in
“Potatoes are served whole or mashed as a cooked vegetable.” The characteri-
zation and examples above are due primarily to Krifka et al. 1995; they use the
term “characterizing” for the class that I call Generalizing sentences.7
Generic and Generalizing sentences are static: they have no dynamism. They
are derived by coercion from verb constellations that express specific situations
at the basic level of categorization. For instance, the verb, object argument,
and adverbial of examples (3c, d) above – “speak French”, “feed the cats” –
standardly express specific events. In context with a definite NP subject, simple
viewpoint, and present tense, however, they have the generalizing interpretation.
Similarly, Generic sentences may have event verb constellations, as in “The lion
eats meat.” Verb constellations that express states at the basic level also appear
in General Statives, as in “have a bushy tail.”
7. Two additional properties of Generic sentences are noted by Krifka et al. (1995): Generic sen-
tences with the indefinite article don’t express accidental properties. For instance, “polyphonic”
is an intrinsic property of “madrigals,” but “popular” is an accidental one. The sentence “The
madrigal is polyphonic” can be taken as generic or particular. But with the indefinite article,
only the ascription of an intrinsic property is acceptable: “A madrigal is polyphonic” is fine, but
#“A madrigal is popular” is odd. This is a slightly different version of the characterization by
Krifka et al.
Kind-denoting NPs in Generic sentences are only plausible with a nominal that refers to a
well-established kind. Thus, “The Coke bottle has a narrow neck” is fine but #“The green bottle
has a narrow neck” is odd (indicated by #), on the generic reading.
74 Aspectual information
General Statives are spatiotemporally located in the world: they hold at par-
ticular intervals and places, though these coordinates may not be specified in a
given sentence.
Since propositions are the mental states of the particular individuals who hold
them, they have subjective features. Propositions are referentially opaque: they
do not accept substitution of a different expression with the same referent.
4.4 Linguistic correlates of situation entities 75
In other constructions the pro-verb do appears with both event and state verb
constellations. For instance, in verb-ellipsis constructions such as “John knows
Greek and Mary does too,” “do” is a pro-verb for the State “know Greek.”
76 Aspectual information
8. Telicity is not expressed directly in language at the level of a general distributional property,
although it is an important conceptual property of Events for human beings. There seem to be
no linguistic correlates of it per se. The syntactic evidence for a telic Event turns on the notion
of completion, which involves the interaction of duration and change of State.
Verbs and adverbials of completion (finish, in an hour) contrast with verbs and adverbials of
simple duration (stop, for an hour). Telic verb constellations are compatible with completion; in
contrast they are odd with forms of simple duration, requiring a special derived interpretation. In
contrast, atelic verb constellations are odd with forms of completion, as the examples illustrate:
These contrasts are semantically based: the notion of completion is intrinsic to a telic Event,
irrelevant to an atelic Event. Other tests for telicity involve verbs such as stop, finish, verbs of
time take and spend with sentential complements. Take is compatible with telic verb constel-
lations, spend with atelic verb constellations. The property of duration also has adverbial and
verbal linguistic correlates; see Smith (1997).
4.4 Linguistic correlates of situation entities 77
9. The complement forms of English include the substantive with -ing, as in “The collapsing of
the Germans,” “John’s cooking of the dinner,” “Mary’s analyzing of the situation.” These forms
have all the properties of substantives; they are not preferred when a morphological substantive
is available such as collapse, analysis.
4.4 Linguistic correlates of situation entities 79
The complement of (10a) refers to an Event, that of (11a) refers to a Fact. Thus
in the clearest cases complement form and predicate classes together fall into
distinct distributional patterns.
However, other patterns are less clear. Certain verbs and predicates are
flexible, allowing several kinds of complement. Among the flexible classes
are epistemic predicates such as be unlikely and psychological verbs such as
surprise, horrify. The complements of such predicates may be a substantive,
gerundive, or a that-clause:
These tests are quite effective. Peterson found that essentially the same proper-
ties support the distinction in such varied languages as Arabic, English, French,
German, Hebrew, Hindi, Kannada, and Marathi. On the basis of this data,
Peterson (1997) argues that the categories are universally linguistic as well as
conceptual.
There are some difficulties in actually applying the tests because not all sen-
tences have the form stipulated. It is often necessary to “normalize” a sentence,
to construct a version of the sentence which fits the substitution template.10
Normalization can be unreliable. Moreover, it’s not always clear when a com-
plex nominal has an underlying clausal structure and when it is just what it
seems to be, a nominal. Abstract nouns, for instance, are arguably often propo-
sitional. In many cases they seem intuitively to involve a proposition, and they
occur with predicates that allow sentential complements.
When are we justified in substituting a clause for an abstract noun or com-
plex nominal? In some cases the substitution requires little change, in other
cases several are needed, changes that are on the borderline toward reinterpre-
tation. The examples of (17) illustrate with sentences from texts in this study.
They require increasingly drastic changes in complement form to arrive at a
normalization.
(17) a The routine transfer of power may not be the most dramatic feature of
American democracy, but it is the most important.
a’ (The fact) that power is routinely transferred may not be the most dramatic
feature of American democracy, but it is the most important.
b The national outpouring after the Littleton shootings has forced us to con-
front something we have suspected for a long time: the American high
school is obsolete and should be abolished.
b’ (The fact) that there was a national outpouring after the Littleton shootings
has forced us to confront something we have suspected for a long time: the
American high school is obsolete and should be abolished.
c But it was the $10 or $11 price of February 1999, not the one today, that
really deserved the headlines.
c’ The $10 or $11 price of February 1999, not the one today, really deserved
the headlines.
c” But that the price was $10 or $11 in February 1999, rather than the one
today, really deserved the headlines.
In (17a, b) normalization turns the subject nominals into verbal clauses. For
(17c), however, more changes are needed. The original is a cleft sentence. The
restatement of (17c’) removes the cleft, and (17c”) gives a that-clause version
which is arguably the same semantically as (17c). Normalizations like this
are often necessary for carrying out the tests proposed by Peterson. Sentence
(17c) illustrates the kind of problem that can arise when trying to produce
sentences of the right form for the substitution tests. One must decide when the
transformation results in a sentence that is appropriately close to the original
sentence, and when the result is too far from the original.
Moreover, some classes of predicates don’t give the right results with these
tests, as Peterson himself points out. The troublesome classes include verbs of
communication and conjecture (e.g. tell, say, show, indicate, guess, predict,
estimate), which are ambiguous between Fact and Proposition readings but
permit indirect question substitution. The substitution test predicts that propo-
sitional complements exclude the substitution of indirect questions, as in (15)
above. Emotive verbs such as regret, resent, deplore are also counter-examples:
they don’t take indirect questions (∗ “I resent who won the race”), but are
expected to do so since semantically their complements denote facts.11
Nevertheless the substitution tests are useful and I will assume that, together
with distributional classes of predicates, they can usually distinguish comple-
ments referring to Facts and Propositions.
There is also a quantification test that distinguishes between types of entities.
Asher shows that quantifiers such as everything, something, can be used in
sentences that express entities of the same class. But they are odd if the entities
are of different classes (1993:33). Consider (18):
(18) a. Everything that happened took an hour.
b. Everything that John believes is true.
c. #Nothing John believes takes an hour.
Example (18a) involves Events, and the sentence is good: the main clause
expresses an Event and the complement clause refers to Events. Similarly, (18b)
expresses and refers to Propositions. But (18c) is odd, even uninterpretable,
11. These verbs are known as “factive” verbs. They presuppose the truth of their complements.
Thus, the truth-conditional status of the complement remains under question and negation, e.g.
“Did you resent John’s winning the race?” “I don’t resent John’s winning the race.” Peterson
extends the term “factive” to include a wider range of Abstract Entity complements.
82 Aspectual information
because it expresses an Event and refers to a belief. The belief context and
temporal location context are not satisfied by the same kind of entity.
12. This independence is one of the basic ideas of the two-component theory. One argument for it
is that the span of a viewpoint does not necessarily coincide with the span of a situation type.
For instance, the progressive of an instantaneous Event focuses a preliminary interval that is
not part of the Event itself: “He was reaching the top”. There are additional viewpoints in other
language that have similar properties.
Another argument is that the viewpoint of a sentence does not obscure its situation type.
The situation type of a sentence is available to the receiver whatever its viewpoint. Consider
a sentence with the progressive viewpoint “Jane was walking to school.” Receivers of this
sentence know that only part of the Event is visible, and what sort of Event it is. They know
the nature of the final endpoint, although it is not semantically visible and may not occur.
4.5 Aspectual information in DRSs 83
Verbs are assigned intrinsic aspectual features in the lexicon. The intrin-
sic value of a verb is determined by its value in a simple verb constellation
with obligatory arguments. Simple constellations have the minimum number
of countable arguments that a verb allows. For instance, the verb walk may
appear in intransitive atelic sentences such as “Mary walked,” and in telic sen-
tences such as “Mary walked to school.” Since it is atelic and durative in the
simpler constellation, walk is assigned the intrinsic features [Atelic] and [Dur].
The essential aspectual feature of NP arguments is whether they are count-
able or uncountable. Proper names are countable; pronouns depend on their
antecedents. Common noun NPs are countable when they appear with deter-
miners forming a specific or definite NP, e.g. an apple, those apples, 3 apples.
Common nouns are either count or mass. For instance red and flour are mass
nouns at the basic level, while dog and apple are count nouns at that level.
Most nouns can appear as members of both categories. The notions of standard
and marked choice are relevant to the multiple categorization in nouns, as they
are for verb constellations. The analysis of apple as a mass noun and flour as
a count noun is similar to that of the shifted and derived categories of verb
constellations.
As an introductory example, consider the compositional analysis of an Event
sentence that expresses an Activity. In (10), line (i) gives the sentence, line (ii)
its surface structure feature analysis, and line (iii) the compositional rule. The
rule registers the verb features [Atelic, Durative] and the compatible feature of
the complement. VCon = verb constellation; NP = NounPhrase, V = Verb,
PP = prepositional phrase, Loc = location, Dir = directional.
The output of the rule is a situation entity of the Activity type, as indicated
on line (iii). The term [Activity] represents the complex of temporal features –
[Dynamic], [Atelic], [Durative] – that characterize the Activity situation type.
I give below a few compositional rules that are slightly more general. They
interpret the situation type of a clause by composing the aspectual feature val-
ues of its constituents. The rules specify only relevant parts of the sentence. For
instance, rule A below composes a simple Activity verb constellation with an
atelic verb and a subject or other argument. Sentences with such verbs are atelic
whether or not the subject NP is quantized: “Susan laughed” and “People
laughed” are both atelic. Therefore the rule does not specify a feature for the
subject NP. The feature of the object NP is slightly more complex, due to the
variation that exists among verbs, but I shall ignore the problem here. Examples
4.5 Aspectual information in DRSs 85
indicate the type of case covered by each rule. Abbreviations: Ct = count, NCt =
non-count, Prt = particle, Adv = adverbial, PP = prepositional phrase, Tel =
telic, Atel = atelic, Dur = durative, Cmp = completive, ( ) = an optional
constituent.
Activity:
A. Atelic verb and compatible (atelic) complement:13
Accomplishment:
D. Telic verb and countable argument:
The feature stated in this output is entered as a condition on the entity [e]
in the DRS (recall that “Accomplishment” and other situation type labels are
shorthand for clusters of features).14
Derived situation types are also interpreted by compositional rule. Recall that
they are triggered by adverbials or other information in the context. The output
13. There is some variation among atelic verbs.The transitive verb in this example, push, allows
a specific NP – “Susan pushed a/the cart”; but other verbs become telic with a specific NP as
direct object, for instance “walk,” as in “Susan walked the dog.”
14. The features characterize the situation entity by associating it with the class of Accomplish-
ments. The account of situation types with compositional rules can be explicated in terms of
semantic processes, as in Krifka (1989).
86 Aspectual information
of the basic-level compositional rules, together with the feature values of the
adverbial (or other form), provide the input to the derived-level rules.
The trigger for a shift in situation type is usually a clash between feature
values. Typically the temporal feature of an adverbial clashes with the corre-
sponding feature in the verb constellation, as in example (3b) (“Mary wrote
a letter for an hour”). The verb write is telic with a quantized object. In this
sentence the verb constellation has the aspectual feature [+Telic], while the
adverb is a simple durative, with the aspectual feature [−Telic]. The adverb
feature value determines the shifted interpretation by a general principle that
I call the External Override Principle. The coercion rule for interpreting this
sentence is sketched in (20). The verb constellation is already interpreted by
a basic-level compositional rule as telic (only the relevant features are stated).
The rule interprets the combination of the adverbial and verb constellation, with
the output an atelic derived verb constellation (DVCON):
The rule shifts the telic verb constellation, an Accomplishment, to an atelic de-
rived verb constellation, an Activity. The feature value of the adverbial overrides
that of the basic-level verb constellation.
The Principle of External Override holds for many derived situation types.
The principle can be stated as an alpha rule, sketched in (21). The input to
the rule is a verb constellation with a situation type value, and an adverbial
or other form. The situation type value is represented by a cluster of temporal
features (a,b,f); feature f has a given value, symbolized as α. The adverbial
also has feature f, but with the value β. The output of the rule is a derived verb
constellation with the feature value of the adverbial:
The output of the rule is the derived situation type value, which will be entered
in the DRS as a condition on the situation entity.
Information in the context of a sentence may trigger coercion, a shift of
situation type. For instance, a generic or habitual sentence may be within the
scope of an operator in a preceding sentence. The time and space adverbials
of the Description mode are similar. They have scope over the clauses of the
description and may trigger situation type shifts. See Chapter 5, 5.3.5.
Situation type information is represented in a DRS with a situation entity
and conditions that characterize it. For instance, (22) presents a partial DRS for
4.5 Aspectual information in DRSs 87
“Mary read a book.” A compositional rule will interpret the situation entity as
an Event. The type of event, Accomplishment in this case, is not included here;
identifying an event is sufficient for Discourse Mode interpretation. Individual
entities x and y represent Mary and a book; the entity e represents the Event.
The entity e is introduced into the top section of the DRS; the conditions on
lines 1–2 specify further.
x y e
1. e: = read (x,y)
2. e ∈ {Event}
3. x = Mary
4. y = a book
The curly brackets in line 2 indicate that the entity e belongs to the concept of
an Event with the intensional properties of that concept.15 Partial DRSs will be
developed further, with additional information, in later sections of this book.
The label [General] stands for the features [Static, Generalizing, Durative]. All
states are durative. This rule ignores the case of used to, a special verb form
that conveys a past pattern of events in English. The form could be added as
an optional feature of the input verb constellation. The rule in (23) does not
15. The temporal properties of a situation entity concept are intensional; they are realized as the
situation unfolds in time. The DRS account of aspectual information follows Smith (1997); it
differs in certain respects from that of Kamp & Reyle (1993).
88 Aspectual information
16. Whether there are two lexical entries for think in its different senses, or one is more basic than
the other, is a question about the lexicon and compositional rules generally. The difference in
dynamism between the verb constellations NP thinks that S and NP thinks about NP can’t be
attributed to the complements. That-complements appear in some verb constellations that are
dynamic (“John was saying that he will leave early”) and about-PPs appear in some that
are static (“The book is about the war”).
4.5 Aspectual information in DRSs 89
The first rules interpret sentences with verbs that clearly involve reference to
Facts; if they have an object complement, it is a that-clause. The rule specifies
the class of Fact predicates (Fact); the main sub-classes are noted above in
4.3. The complement may have the form of a that-clause or gerund; other
possibilities are ignored here. comp = complement; Ger = gerund.
This rule will interpret sentences, “I know that Mary refused the offer,” and “I
resent Mary’s winning the race.”
The main classes of fact predicates with subject complements are evaluative
and psychological verbs. Both classes are flexible, allowing complements of
all types. That-clause and gerundive complements refer to Facts in the context
of these predicates. The rule specifies that the main verb be of the class of
situations, correctly allowing both State and Event main verb constellations;
psychological verbs like surprise may be dynamic. Eval = evaluative verb.
Other subject complement forms are ambiguous: they also have a situation
(Event or State) interpretation with these predicates, as noted above. The sit-
uation interpretation of these predicates is sketched in (27). Substantive com-
plements are NPs, as provided in the rule. The linguistic expressions after the
predicate of interest are unspecified (X). Subst = substantive complement;
Psych = psychological verb.
except for the specification of the verb class, here Epist = epistemological verb,
Log = logophoric verb.
x y e I ti t j
1. e: = read (x,y)
2. e ∈ {Event}
3. {Viewpoint (I,e) = Perfective}
4. ti,j ∈ I
5. ti = I(e), tj = F(e)
6. t ∈ I, t ≥ ti , t ≤ tj
7. x = Mary
8. y = a book
17. This follows the treatment of viewpoint in Smith (1997). In another DRT approach, viewpoint
might be treated as a trigger for a sub-DRS in which all or part of the situation is visible (Patrick
Caudal p.c.).
4.5 Aspectual information in DRSs 91
The viewpoint concept is set off with curly brackets to indicate its special
status.
The progressive viewpoint focuses an interval of an Event that does not
include its endpoints. This is modeled formally by providing that the interval
[I] includes only times after the initial endpoint of e and before the final endpoint
of e.18 The partial DRS for a progressive sentence is given in (31):
(31) Partial DRS for “Mary was reading a book.”
x y e I ti tj
1. e: = read (x,y)
2. e ∈ {Event}
3. {Viewpoint (I,e) = Imperfective}
4. ti,j ∈ I
5. t ∈ I → t > I(e), t < F(e)
6. x = Mary
7. y = a book
These DRSs are still incomplete because they do not include information about
tense.
The aspectual information that is encoded in a DRS identifies a situation
entity for each clause. This information is essential to determining the enti-
ties introduced in text passages. Viewpoint information specifies whether an
Event is bounded or unbounded, which is essential for calculating temporal
advancement.
18. This statement covers the basic progressive meaning which focuses an internal interval of a
situation. It does not account for cases where the progressive focuses an interval before a single
point, as in “They were reaching the top.”
5 Temporal and spatial progression
Time and space are pervasive in human experience and in language; they are
essential in understanding the Discourse Modes. Text progression depends on
both domains. The temporal modes progress with changes in time and space,
while the atemporal modes progress with metaphorical changes of location
through the text domain. This chapter discusses text progression in the temporal
modes; the atemporal modes are considered in Chapter 6.
The principles for temporal progression are essentially pragmatic, depending
on inference about how situations are related to each other and to times. Tense is
interpreted in three different patterns. After discussing progression in the modes,
I provide the linguistic account that underlies the analysis, and implement it in
Discourse Representation Theory. There is a distinct grammatical sub-system
for talking about time in English, consisting of tense and time adverbials. The
system is a closed one: choice of tense and type of adverbial is limited to a
small set of alternatives. In contrast, spatial information is conveyed by lexical
means that do not constitute a grammatical sub-system, except for a very few
deictic adverbials.
Section 5.1 discusses temporal interpretation in the temporal discourse
modes; 5.2 introduces the sub-system of temporal location in English; 5.3 imple-
ments the interpretations in Discourse Representation Structures; 5.4 discusses
space, and how it differs in linguistic expression from the temporal domain; 5.5
gives the forms and linguistic features of the temporal location sub-system.
92
5.1 Sentences in context 93
different discourse patterns challenges the traditional idea that tense is deictic;
it also provides a needed supplement to accounts that deal only with narrative
advancement.1
In narrative passages bounded events advance narrative time. I will use the
term Reference Time for the advancing time of a narrative: with each bounded
event, Reference Time advances. The notion of Reference Time is explained
in 5.2 below. Narrative has the Continuity pattern of tense interpretation. In
Description, there is a full Anaphora pattern: time is static, the same as a previ-
ously established Reference Time. Tense is interpreted as Deictic in the other
Discourse Modes – Reports, Argument, Information – and in texts generally.
Deictic tense is oriented to Speech Time; this is the default pattern, as in tradi-
tional accounts.
In this section the different patterns will be demonstrated in some detail, and
principles proposed to account for them.
In the fragment, narrative time advances with perfective event sentences and
fails to advance otherwise. I consider the example in detail.
The narrative of (1) conveys a series of events in sequence, E1 (put on apron),
E2 (took a lump of clay), etc. There is one State, expressed in sentence 2 (clay
was wet), which we understand to hold at the same time as the preceding event,
and perhaps to extend before and after it. The diagram in (2) gives a time line
for the passage; E indicates an event, S a state; SpT is Speech Time:
1. The need for more than one pattern of tense interpretation is recognized in Caenepeel & Moens
(1994) and Caenepeel (1995). They note that some contexts evoke a narrative interpretation,
while others are deictic.
94 Temporal and spatial progression
All these situations are temporally located at a time prior to Speech Time,
following narrative convention. Otherwise the information conveyed by
tense is simple continuity. The past tense is not interpreted deictically: if it
were, the events would be related to Speech Time rather than to each other.
Nor do we interpret the past tense as expressing a series of events successively
prior to one another. The continuity function of tense holds for narratives in the
present or future as well as the past.
The interpretation can be expressed in two general principles that hold for
narrative passages. As a narrative advances it establishes a set of different Refer-
ence Times. In clauses that express bounded events, Reference Time advances.
In clauses of states and ongoing events, the time is the previously established
Reference Time. This is an anaphoric interpretation, limited in narrative to cer-
tain types of situations. The two patterns are set out in (3). When tense is past,
as in many narratives, we take it that Reference Time (RT) is prior to Speech
Time (SpT).
Temporal adverbials also advance narrative time, of course. This brief account
does not consider the relative past tenses, past perfect and future-in-past. They
locate situations before and after the current time established in the text. Similar
principles are stated by Kamp & Reyle (1993) in a slightly different approach.
The continuity pattern also occurs in procedural discourse.
Narrative continuity depends on semantic and pragmatic factors. The inter-
pretation of bounded Events is based on semantic, aspectual information: the
class of a verb constellation and the perfective viewpoint. The past-tense mor-
pheme conveys that a situation is prior to Speech Time (in simple sentences;
for other cases see 5.5 below). The sequential narrative interpretation itself is
pragmatic, and can be cancelled by additional information. Situations may be
5.1 Sentences in context 95
The passage consists of bounded events and states; there are no ongoing events.
The bounded events advance time, here supported by adverbials.
2. Shifts in level of detail are common, as in “We went on a long trip last summer. First we traveled
to India.” The second sentence is at a finer level of detail than the first. The inference of shift is
triggered by the adverb “first” and based in world knowledge. There may be other interpretations
of how sentences are related, more abstract and/or rhetorically based. Such interpretation is
usually triggered by additional information in the context. Discourse relations are discussed
briefly in Chapter 11.
96 Temporal and spatial progression
(6) 1 On the big land below the house a man was ploughing and shouting admoni-
tions to the oxen who dragged the ploughshares squeaking through the heavy
red soil. 2 On the track to the station the loaded wagon with its team of sixteen
oxen creaked and groaned . . . 3 A group of children walked to school. 4 On
the telephone wires the birds twittered and sang.
coerced to atelic, undergoing a shift of situation type. This is part of the general
phenomenon of coercion discussed in Chapter 4. Recall that sentences with a
telic verb constellation and a durative time adverbial are atelic. For instance, in
“Mary read a book for an hour” there is no sense that Mary completed the book –
on the contrary. The durative time adverbial overrides the telicity of the verb
constellation.
Similarly, “A group of children walked to school” in (6) is atelic under the
scope of the tacit durative adverbial of description. The actual duration of such
an adverbial is determined by context. The assumed duration is the time in
which the perceiver scans the scene and becomes aware of its properties, or
simply a period during which the situation is expected to hold.
In Description, the anaphoric pattern of tense interpretation holds for all
situations. There are coercion effects due to the tacit adverbial of duration: telic
events shift to atelic. Limited and Full anaphoric patterns of interpretation are
pragmatic, depending on the notion that what is conveyed is a static description
of a scene.
The passage begins with a future time, indicated by “will” and the for-adverbial;
at S2 the temporal location shifts to the present (“has postponed”), and then to
another future State. S3 shifts to the past event (“decided”), with a past tense
and time adverbial. The events of S4 (“took heat,” “called”) are also located in
the past relative to Speech Time. They need not occur at the same time as the
event of S3. The diagram in (8) gives a time line for this passage in terms of
Reference Time (RT) and Speech Time (SpT).
(10) Information
1GE Surprisingly, tunnels are among the most ancient engineering feats. 2GE
The earliest were very likely extensions of prehistoric cave dwellings. 3E The
Babylonians, in the twenty-second century BC, built a masonry tunnel beneath
the Euphrates River that connected the royal palace with a major temple. 4GE
3. For instance, the subject of S5 is interpreted as a Proposition. The subject nominal “the low
price” is normalized as clausal, That the price of oil was low. The clause then meets the criteria
for a Proposition.
5.2 Introduction to the temporal system of English 99
In the Deictic pattern situations and deictics are oriented to Speech Time.
Summarizing, three patterns of tense interpretation have been demonstrated
for non-first clauses of text passages. (I assume that the first sentence of a pas-
sage is interpreted by the default deictic principle.) Tense conveys Continuity,
Anaphora, or Deixis. Each Discourse Mode has a different pattern:
convey information about time. English has two tenses, past and present. The
modal auxiliary will standardly conveys Future time.4 Tense is obligatory in the
main clause of a sentence. There are complex tenses, the perfect (“Mary has
arrived”) and the embedded future (“Mary would leave soon”). Temporal adver-
bials are optional. Locating adverbials specify times (“Mary called at noon”), as
do clausal time adverbials (“John left when Mary arrived”). Adverbials anchor
either to Speech Time or to a time specified in the linguistic context. The discus-
sion below focuses on tense, although adverbials are included in the summary
of the system in 5.5.
The temporal expressions form a closed system, a limited domain from which
one of a few possibilities must be chosen. Tense in independent sentences is
deictic, anchored to Speech Time. Tense locates the situation in a clause by tac-
itly invoking two times: the time of the situation expressed, which I will call Sit-
uation Time; and Speech Time. Present and past tense, and future will, indicate
that Situation Time is respectively simultaneous with, before, or after Speech
Time. In complex sentences the anchor may be a time other than Speech Time.
There is a third time conveyed by tense, a temporal perspective time. Every
tensed sentence takes a temporal perspective or standpoint, known as “Ref-
erence Time,” following Hans Reichenbach (1947). Reichenbach presents
strong arguments for the notion of Reference Time, which I assume here.5
The centrality of the speaker implies an organizing consciousness that provides
a standpoint “from which the speaker invites his audience to consider the Event”
4. The modal will has present tense, correspondingly the modal would has past tense and has a
future-in-past meaning. Would is also a conditional form, not discussed here. Enç (1991) shows
that will is a modal not a tense. Will with strong stress conveys volition or requirement, as in “I
WILL go”; “Bill WILL go.”
5. There are three main arguments, for the notion of Reference Time, two of them due to Reichen-
bach himself. The first involves perfect sentences. Consider the difference between a simple
past and a present perfect sentence. Both present an Event that takes place before Speech Time;
they have the same truth conditions, yet they contrast in conceptual meaning.
(i) a Mary arrived. past
b Mary has arrived. present perfect
In both sentences Situation Time (the Event of arriving) is Past.
The notion of Reference Time gives us a way of understanding such contrasts. In past
tense sentences, both situation and temporal standpoint are in the past; in present perfect
sentences, the situation is past but the temporal standpoint is present. In the perfect, RT is
equal to Speech Time. The perfect has an additional aspectual component of stativity, noted in
Chapter 2.
Another argument for Reference Time comes from the relations between situations. The con-
text of a clause gives information that locates situations relative to one another. They occur
in sequence, or overlap. Using the notion of Reference Time, we can say that overlapping
5.2 Introduction to the temporal system of English 101
(Taylor 1977:203). In sentences with the basic tenses, Reference Time is the
same as Situation Time. The reader will recognize the term Reference Time
from the earlier discussion of text progression.
situations share Reference Time and those in sequence do not. This accounts nicely for the
difference between the examples in (ii).
Thus the notion of RT provides a locus for relating situations in a principled manner, explicated
in a DR Theory framework in Hinrichs (1986).
A third argument for RT concerns the phenomenon of shifted deixis. As is well known, some
deictic adverbials such as now, in 3 days, etc., which normally anchor to the moment of speech,
can anchor to a Past (or Future time):
(i) Mary sat down at the desk. Now she was ready to start work.
In such contexts the shifted now suggests Mary’s perspective. The notion of RT is the anchoring
point for this perspective. These arguments show that Reference Time is indispensable to an
understanding of the temporal information conveyed in sentences. Reichenbach and others use
the term Event Time for what I call Situation Time. The system as Reichenbach stated it must
be modified and extended (Smith 1980, Comrie 1985, Hornstein 1990, Kamp & Reyle 1993).
I will assume these adjustments. The account given here is similar but not identical to that of
Kamp & Reyle (1993).
6. There are future perfect sentences in which the situation must precede RT but need not precede
SpT, e.g. in “The Prime Minister will have burned the documents by Thursday,” as noted in
connection with (14) above.
102 Temporal and spatial progression
The tenses in (14b–d) are “relative” tenses because they depend on another
clause for interpretation: the main clause provides the anchor RT for the
embedded clause. Temporal adverbials, if they appear in a clause, specify
RT.
This relational information is the semantic meaning of a tense, associated
with the tense morpheme in the lexicon. In multi-clause sentences, one clause
may be dependent temporally on another, as in (14d).7 Formally, the tenses
have two semantic features, A and B, which give the relation between times
associated with a given tense. The features provide what Kamp & Reyle call
the “two-dimensional theory” of tense. The A feature relates Reference Time
to Speech Time; the B feature relates Reference Time to Situation Time.
Tense interpretation interacts with aspectual information. Recall that the per-
fective viewpoint focuses events as bounded, while the progressive focuses
events as unbounded. States are also unbounded. The property of boundedness
is crucial for the way aspect relates to temporal location. Bounded events are
totally included in the Situation Time, whether it be a moment or an interval
(e ⊆ SitT); unbounded events and states overlap or surround it (e 0 SitT). For
instance:
We understand the event of (15a) as taking place within SitT, here an interval.8
The ongoing event of (15b) overlaps SitT: it holds at an interval that includes
the SitT interval. For concreteness I give a semi-formal statement for the two
sentences.
7. There are several possible relations between the temporal information of a main clause and other
clauses in a sentence. Tenseless complements and adjuncts share the time of the matrix clause.
Tensed complements may be dependent on a time established in the main clause for either RT
or SitT. In the former case, an adverbial in the dependent clause may specify the time of SitT.
The past perfect and future-in-past would typically appear in a complement clause, as in (13d).
Relative clauses may be temporally dependent or independent of the main clause. See Smith
(1981), Ogihara (1989).
8. By convention, SpT is an instant. I will assume that RT and SitT may be moments or intervals,
depending on adverbial and situation information in the sentence. Both are needed in a semantic
account of the temporal system (Kamp & Reyle 1993:501).
5.2 Introduction to the temporal system of English 103
Due to this constraint, all simple present tense sentences express unbounded
situations. Almost the same notion is called the “punctuality constraint” in
Giorgi & Pianesi (1997:163).9 There are well-known exceptions, notably per-
formatives (“I christen this ship the Queen Elizabeth”) and sports-announcer
reports (“Now Jones throws the ball to third base”) and narratives entirely set in
the present. Another type, less well-known, appears in literary and many other
9. I thank Nina Hyams for pointing out the similarity of Giorgi & Pianesi’s constraint to the one
stated here. The Bounded Event Constraint is realized differently across languages. In Russian,
for instance, the perfective present conveys Future time reference. In French the present is
imperfective in meaning. The Bounded Event has consequences for temporal interpretation in
languages without tense; see Smith & Erbaugh (2001).
104 Temporal and spatial progression
In these cases the lower clause does not advance narrative time. Main and
complement clauses have the same Reference Time. There are two other re-
lations between main and complement clause. The complement may receive
its Reference Time from the main clause, or the complement may relate tem-
porally to Speech Time. The determining factors are the tenses and modal
will of main and complement clause, although adverbials also contribute to
interpretation.
When the main-clause verb expresses communication, the complement
clause indicates a previous event or overlapping open situation. The examples
illustrate: in (19a) an ongoing event is expressed in the complement, (19b) is a
variation in which the complement clause has a bounded Event.
(19) a. When I got to Harry’s Waldorf Towers apartment, his secretary said they
were winding up the meeting downstairs. Harry appeared about a half-hour
later, greeted me warmly, went immediately to the telephone.
b. When I got to Harry’s Waldorf Towers apartment, his secretary said Harry
(had) left. Harry appeared about a half-hour later, greeted me warmly, went
immediately to the telephone.
10. The literary examples can be seen either as Generalizing Statives, or perhaps as stage directions
that are invoked afresh each time the work is read. I thank Robert Brown for bringing these
examples to my attention.
5.3 Tense interpretation in DR Theory 105
NP I'
tense Asp'
Asp VP:e
ø
put on her apron
This sentence has past tense, the perfective viewpoint, the participants Mara,
her apron.
Information arises as follows: the IP is associated with a situation entity e,
and with a tense. The situation entity is interpreted by compositional rules. The
tense licenses the introduction of three times in the DRS, and conditions stating
the A and B features associated with it. The AspP is associated with the perfec-
tive or imperfective viewpoint, depending on whether the verb has the simple
form or an auxiliary; the participants appear in the highest NP and the VP, and
percolate to the top of the tree. This discussion focuses on temporal location
information.
The temporal location construction rule for sentences like (21) is given in
(22). The statement covers only simple tenses but could be extended to the
perfect tenses and the future-in-past. I include an optional temporal-locating
adverbial.
t1 t2 t3 x y e d
1. e: put on (x,y)
2. t1 = SpT
3. t2 < t1
4. t2 = d
5. t1 = SpT
6. d = at noon
7. e ⊆ t3
8. x = Mara
9. y = her apron
Tense is deictic in this single sentence. The tense features are on lines 3 and
5: the A feature for past tense is t2 < t1 ; the B feature t2 = t3 . Line 7 specifies
that the event is included in the Situation Time interval, since the viewpoint is
perfective. Other information is omitted, for simplicity.
The DRS above illustrates the deictic interpretation of tense, which as the
default applies to single sentences. I now consider temporal information in text
passages. Temporal interpretation requires construction rules and principles for
temporal advancement. I will concentrate on the latter.
11. Shifted deictics sometimes appear in narrative, e.g. “Mary had been working all afternoon; she
was tired now.” The decitic now is anchored not to Speech Time but to the Past time of the first
clause. See Chapter 9. Shifted deictics are not dealt with here.
5.3 Tense interpretation in DR Theory 109
principle advances narrative time with bounded events, and/or time adverbials.
I’ll work through the principles with the narrative fragment of (1), repeated
here as (24):
The principle applies when a clause and its immediate context have event and
state entities, which will be notated as entities of type e.
The first part of the rule for continuity is a contextual constraint that looks
at a clause and the immediately preceding context for the appropriate en-
tities. The times and entities of a clause are associated by letter subscript;
recall that clauses themselves do not appear in the DRS. The relevant en-
tities are of type e, events and states; the entity of the clause being pro-
cessed is subscripted with “n” for times tn . The entities of preceding clauses
are identified as n−2, n−1, and associated with temporal entities tn−2 and
tn−1 in the DRS. The principle applies to non-first sentences of a narrative
passage:
The condition requires that the clause being processed have an entity of type
e; that preceding clauses have entities of the same type; and that there are no
deictics. Thus in (23), clause 1a is first, so the condition is applicable to clause
1b: it is clause n, with an entity of type e; the preceding clause 1a has times
tn−1 and an entity of type e. Advancing in the passage, clause 1c will be clause
n and clauses 1a and 1b are clauses n−2, n−1 respectively. Both have entities
of type e so the rule applies.
The Continuity Principle provides for an advancement of RT with bounded
events. The principle has the form of a rule which advances the narrative from
one Reference Time, RTx , to a later time, RTy , indicated by the symbol >:
This rule applies to the passage in (24). The first application is to clause 1b:
the rule says that the RT of “[she] took a lump of clay from the bin,” RTy , is
later than the RT of the first clause: RTy > RTx . RTy is the updated Reference
Time. The rule applies in the same fashion to the next clause, “[she] weighed
off enough for a small vase,” and so on.
The full Continuity Principle also has a clause providing that a temporal
adverbial can advance narrative time, stated in (27):
The Limited Anaphora Principle applies under the same conditions as the pre-
vious principle, but only to State and unbounded Event entities:
These principles are stated for clear cases that do not require inference. Adverbs
of the locating type advance narrative time for all situations.
I illustrate the principles in a DRS for a narrative fragment of three sentences;
the first two introduce Event entities into the universe, the third introduces a
State. The times introduced by the sentences are subscripted a–c. The situations
e are numbered 1, 2, 3; e1 and e2 are Events, e3 is the State. The entities appear
at the top of the DRS.
The individual and situation entities are introduced by compositional rules like
those stated in Chapter 4. The rules provide the conceptual aspectual infor-
mation that classifies the entities as Events and States, and the viewpoint as
perfective in each clause. This information licenses the conditions on lines 4
and 11 that an event is included in t3 , or SitT (perfective, bounded); or on line
18 that it overlaps t3 , or SitT (unbounded simple State). The tense interpretation
is the result of a calculation within the DRS.
This DRS provides two RTs (t2 ) for the three sentences: the first is specified
as prior to SpT on the deictic interpretation, line 2; the second follows the first
by the principle of advancement, line 9. The third RT is equal to the second
by the Principle of Limited Anaphora, line 16. The events are included in the
intervals of t3 (SitT), lines 4 and 11; the State overlaps t3 , line 18. Again, other
aspectual information is omitted.
as well. The entities in a descriptive passage are states, ongoing events (in the
progressive) or atelic events. The time adverbial triggers coercion of telic events
to atelic events, as in Chapter 4. After the appropriate entities are entered into
the DRS, the principle of Full Anaphora applies.
The compositional construction rule for Description applies to the first sen-
tence of a descriptive passage. The sentence has an initial adverbial of space
which locates the scene. The rule constructs a tacit durative time adverbial.
The adverbial introduces an entity mt into the DRS and triggers a condition
identifying it as a durative amount, here unspecified. The entity mt follows
Kamp & Reyle’s account of durative adverbs (1993). The durative adverbial
serves as a coercion trigger for this sentence and subsequent sentences of the
passage.
(30) Construction rule: first sentence of a Description passage
In a clause n with temporal entities tn : the situation entity in n is unbounded
or atelic, of type e:
S[Adv [Loc] + e + tense] →
t1n , t2n , t3n ; A, B; adv, mt
The locating adverbial introduces an entity adv into the DRS and triggers a
condition locating the situation at that place.
Non-first sentences do not require a special construction rule for temporal
interpretation: they introduce times in the usual way. Coercion rules will apply
as usual. They must have access to the unspecified adverbial of duration in
the context. Non-first sentences of Description fall under the Full Anaphora
Principle of tense interpretation because of the entities they introduce and the
DRS context in which they are interpreted. The DRS must contain a space
adverbial and a durative time adverbial without amount specification, which
have the relevant sentence in their scope. I invoke here a general principle of
discourse continuity: between the initial Descriptive sentence and the sentence
in question, the context must not contain a time or space adverbial, or a bounded
event. These would interrupt the continuing scope of the Description passage.12
The Full Anaphora Principle is stated in (31).
(31) Full Anaphora Principle
In the context of temporal entities tn of the DRS, if the situation entities
associated with tn−2 and/or tn−1 are unbounded or atelic, and locating and
temporal conditions obtain:
12. Recognizing changes in continuity, when scope is interrupted, is discussed further in Chapter
7. Stating the possibilities in detail is quite complex: for instance, description typically has
space adverbials that fall within the scope of the initial space adverbial, so that one does not
want to block every space adverbial in descriptive contexts.
5.3 Tense interpretation in DR Theory 113
The diagram in (32) presents a DRS for the simplified first three sentences
of the Descriptive passage in (5a) above. The passage occurs in a narrative
context. By the principle of limited anaphora the first RT is the same as the
preceding RT. The times introduced with each clause are notated with subscripts
“a”–“c.”
The first clause introduces a state; the next two situations are perfective
Activities. In this context they are bounded, but the bounds do not coincide
with the initial or final endpoints of the events. The notation of inclusion (lines
11, 17) applies to the bounded units focused by the perfective viewpoint. The
duration of the states is greater than or equal to the amount mt of the tacit time
adverbial (lines 4, 12, 18).
t1a t2a t2a−1 t3a e1 x adv mt t1b t2b t3b e2 y t1c t2c t3c e3 z w
(33) 1 A week that began in violence ended violently here, with bloody
clashes in the West Bank and Gaza and intensified fighting in Southern
Lebanon. 2 Despite the violence, back-channel talks continued in Swe-
den. 3 Israeli, Palestinian and American officials have characterized them
as a serious and constructive dialogue on the process itself and on the
final status issues. 4 News accounts here say that Israel is offering as
much as 90 percent of the West Bank to Palestinians, although it is dif-
ficult to assess what is really happening by the bargaining moves that are
leaked.
S1 has an RT prior to SpT, indicated by the past tense. S2 is also in the past
tense. The event expressed, of continuing talks, is not related to the event of S1
in any direct way. The present perfect tense of S3 shifts RT from the Past to
SpT. The rest of the passage proceeds in the same fashion.
No additional construction rules or principles for calculating advancement
are needed for the Report mode. The deictic principle is applied anew for each
clause. I analyze formally a simplified version of this rather complex fragment.
The simplification does not substantially affect the temporal advancement of
the text.
t1a t2a t3a e1 x t1b t2b t3b e2 y z t1c t2c t3c e3 u v w t1d t2d t3d e4 s t
1. t1a = SpT
2. t2a < t1a
3. t2a = t3a
4. e1 ⊆ t3a
5. x = week
6. e1 : end (x)
7. t1b = SpT
8. t2b < t1b
9. t2b = t3b
10. e2 ⊆ t3b
11. y = back-channel talks
12. z = in Sweden
13. e2 : continue (y)
14. t1c = SpT
15. t2c < t1c
16. t2c = t3c
17. e3 ⊆ t3c
18. w = officials
19. u=y
20. v = serious dialogue
21. e3 : characterize (w,u,v)
22. t1d = SpT
23. t2d = t1d
24. t2d = t3d
25. e3 O t3c
26. s = Israel
27. t = 90 percent of the West Bank
28. e4 : offer (s,t)
rocks spilling down toward the right side. To explain its spatial structure would
involve all three dimensions and more than one orienting perspective.
In contrast, the temporal domain is one-dimensional. Because of its relative
simplicity, the possible temporal relations between entities can be enumerated
and calculated. In linear time any two events have exactly one out of thirteen
qualitatively distinct relationships to each other, ignoring orientation (Allen
1983). If we add orientation, there are twenty-six possible relations between
objects, Freksa (1992) has calculated. Nothing so simple as this is possible for
space.
People engage directly with space by volitional action, whereas their inter-
action with time is often involuntary.13 The role of volition brings out a crucial
difference between the domains. Events involving space are agentive, usually
following an active choice by the agent. One decides to cross the street, hang
a picture, take out the garbage, deliver a message. The passing of time is often
parasitic on facts about particular events: crossing a narrow lane takes less
time than crossing a wide boulevard. Again, maintaining rather than changing
a given state of affairs is often voluntary; the passage of time is concomitant, a
secondary effect of the decision to maintain the state. The contrast is not perfect:
there are a few cases in which time is directly and volitionally involved in an
event, e.g. one may deliberately walk or hold one’s breath for a long or a short
time.
Languages typically have rich verbal resources for talking about space. Spa-
tial information is encoded directly in many verbs. For instance, in verbs like
hang the spatial factor makes an essential contribution. English has a set of many
prepositions which also convey spatial information. There only a few temporal
verbs (pass the time, take an hour, spend an hour, and the aspectual verbs begin,
start, etc.).
Most verbs with a strand of temporal meaning involve projected situations and
attitudes. Classes of verbs with a temporal component include verbs of Future
Having (advance, guarantee, owe, etc.), verbs of Future Situation (propose,
plan, arrange for, etc.); verbs of Wish and Desire (want, covet, need, yearn,
etc.); verbs of Future Events (predict, expect, foretell, etc.); verbs of Future
Prevention (preclude, prevent, etc.); and verbs of Past Events (resent, realize,
etc.). Levin (1993) provides detailed lists.
Strikingly, the main factor for these verbs is modality, not time. They involve
attitudes, plans, or factive meanings, many with a discrepancy between the
current state of affairs and other states of affairs. They are only indirectly
temporal. There are few temporal analogues to verbs with spatial meanings,
which are directly concerned with space – traversing it in various ways, direc-
tionality, spatial configuration.
These points may explain an otherwise odd fact about spatial and temporal
phrases and coercion. In coercion, an adverbial triggers a shift in the aspectual
value of a basic-level situation type. For instance, a basic-level Activity clause
denotes a non-specific atelic event which is not explicitly bounded (35a). When
a prepositional phrase is added, the resulting clause denotes a bounded, specific
event (35b–c):
(35) a. They walked. (no explicit bound)
b. They walked for three miles. (bounded)
c. They walked for an hour. (bounded)
In these examples the spatial and temporal PPs function in the same way,
providing an explicit bound to the event. With other prepositions, however, there
is a difference between the contribution of the spatial and temporal adverbials.
Compare (36a–b): the spatial PP adds the component of telicity, the temporal
PP does not:
(36) a. They walked to school. (telic: change of state)
b. They walked until noon. (bounded)
In (a) the event involves arrival at a new location, a change of state. But we
don’t think of (b) this way: we do not conceive of an event of walking-until-noon
as an arrival, or as involving a new state. There are grammatical correlates to
this conceptual difference. Sentences like (36a) pass tests for telicity, whereas
sentences like (36b) do not.14 The grammatical and conceptual differences show
that a spatial bound constitutes a telos whereas a temporal bound does not.
Although every concrete entity has a spatiotemporal location, we have seen
that there are important differences between the domains of time and space.
These differences give an explanation for the fact that aspect and temporal
location can be expressed linguistically through a closed system, while spatial
location cannot.
The main clause of (38a) is past; the complement clause, with present tense,
orients to SpT, not a time simultaneous with the main clause. In (38b), main
and complement clause both have past tense; the complement clause indicates
the same time as the main clause, not a time anterior to it.15 The sequences
15. The complement clause may have a relative tense, which conveys a SitT other than RT; the
perfect indicates that SitT precedes RT (a), the future-in-past that SitT follows RT (b):
a. John said that Mary had left.
b. Mary said that John would leave.
Neither of these cases advances narrative time.
A very different view of the relation between main and complement clauses is presented
in S. Thompson (2001), which argues that the main clauses of traditional analysis express
speaker stance toward the content of the clause. The discussion focuses on examples from
conversational English.
120 Temporal and spatial progression
16. The sentence below illustrates this possibility. Assume that it is uttered on a Tuesday, which is
two days after last Sunday:
Bill confessed last Sunday that he would resign in a week.
The complement clause has the same RT as the matrix, the Past time of “last Sunday”; the
adverbial in a week specifies a time following, a time that is in the future of the RT and of the
time of speech. The interpretation is shown below:
In (40a), the tense indicates RT which precedes SpT; in the second sentence of
(40b), the tense continues the RT which is previously established. In (40c) the
adverbial specifies RT prior to SpT, whereas in the complement of (40d) the
adverbial specifies SitT. These interpretations are made by construction rules
using feature information.
Auxiliary have has the relational value of anteriority with the same flexibility.
It may contribute to either RT or SitT: thus have indicates SitT in (41), and RT
in (42).
(42) a. Last Sunday John left the country. On Friday he had closed his bank account,
and had rented his house; at his office, he had emptied all the drawers and
shelves; then he (had) told his staff to take a holiday, and (had) made his
final arrangements.
b. auxiliary have: RT2 < RT1
These clauses involve three different times: t1 , RT > t1 , SitT < RT (the latter
indicated by auxiliary have). Note that sentence (43c) involves four times alto-
gether, since the main clause sets a Past orientation time for the complement. A
Role Feature limits the role of will to RT. The proposed features are summarized
in (44).
122 Temporal and spatial progression
123
124 Referring expressions in discourse
Elaborating these ideas, I give criteria for determining the Primary Referent
of clauses that express situations of different kinds. Example (2) deals with
event clauses; states are discussed directly below. The example sentences are
taken from an Argument passage in this study; the Primary Referent expressions
are italicized.
There is some overlap among the criteria: a referent which undergoes a change
of state (a) is often causally affected by another participant (b) and changes
in some way (d). However, there are cases for which all four criteria are
needed.
The domain of states requires more discussion. The Primary Referent in state
sentences can often be determined with the localist principle: the entity whose
location is asserted is the Primary Referent. By the localist principle, all cases
in which a property is ascribed to an entity are locational. Positional sentences
are basic, with x is at y the prototypical state. But the principle is not always
easy to put into practice. When two entities are involved, it may not be clear
which one is the Primary Referent. In other cases the metaphorical extension
is delicate. Additional criteria are needed to supplement the general localist
principle.
Criteria for determining the Primary Referent of states are listed in (3). Fol-
lowing the list is a discussion of how they apply to the main classes of states,
and to special problematic cases. The examples are from texts in this study;
Primary Referent expressions are italicized.
More specific criteria are applied before the general. Criterion (d), for instance,
holds of the subject in any state sentence.
I distinguish three classes of state: states of location, including position and
possession; mental states of thought, belief, feeling, perception, communica-
tion; states of composition and identification, and property ascription. The cri-
terion of literal and metaphorical location nicely applies to the first two classes.
Consider first states of location. With positional states, the located entity is the
Primary Referent (underlined): for instance in “The lamppost is on the corner,”
the Primary Referent is “the lamppost.” For states of possession, the possessed
entity or concept is the Primary Referent and its metaphorical location is the pos-
sessor, as in “John has a book,” “Mary has an idea.” Mental states, the second
class, fall under the rubric of extended possession. The contents of mental states
are possessed by the person who holds them, as in “John likes strawberries,”
“Mary thinks that Lee is here.”
Compositional and identificational states can be analyzed with the criteria of
dependence and possession. For example:
In (4a–b) the concepts denoted by the predicative NPs are the Primary Referents;
they depend for their existence on the subject NPs.2 In (4c) the referent of “eight
people” is the primary, by possession.
The third criterion applies in location sentences when one entity is located
in relation to another, known as Figure–Ground sentences. Consider (5):
2. The NPs in these examples are predicative: the sentences have only one referent. They can be
conjoined with adjectives: “Mary considers John competent in semantics and an authority on
unicorns” (Partee 1987:119). In uncertain cases, the possibility of conjunction with an adjectival
predicate is a good test for the function of an NP. By this criterion the post-copula NPs in (3b–c)
are predicative. The subject NP of (3d) is also predicative: there is only one referent in the
sentence, the kilns at Tao-chu in Shensi. The formulation of this criterion is similar to a criterion
for Theme role in Dowty (1991).
6.1 Atemporal text progression and Primary Referents 127
The sentences seem symmetrical: if John is near Harry, then surely Harry is
near John. But in fact one entity functions as the Ground for locating the other,
the Figure. To show this we look at different types of cases, following Talmy
(2000). For (5 a–b) either NP is plausible as the subject: “John is near Harry,”
and “Aunt Mabel resembles Harry” are good sentences. Often, however, the
alternative realization is semantically peculiar. The alternatives of (5c–d) are
peculiar (indicated by #):
(6) a. # The house is near the bike.
b. # The mountain is near the house.
Pairs like this show that factors other than location play a role in what makes
an acceptable Figure. (6a–b) are odd because a bike is not a plausible reference
point for locating a house, nor is a house plausible as a reference point for
locating a mountain. Although the relation between the referents is apparently
symmetric, one is usually more appropriate than the other as Ground.
The relative size and stability of the referents determine what is appropriate as
Figure and Ground. These are points about the world, not about the grammar.3
In Figure–Ground sentences the subject phrase gives the Primary Referent. An
alternative structure is inversion (“Near the house is a bike”). Nothing quite
like the active–passive alternation exists for sentences with the copula. The
non-canonical existential there construction has the same constraint, strikingly.
For instance, “There is a bike near the house” is good, whereas # “There is a
house near the bike” is odd indeed. Inversions and existential there sentences
are discussed in Chapter 9. I think that the evidence is strong that the notion
of Figure is semantically based in these cases (pace Dowty 1991). Yet, since it
appears in subject position, the Figure conflates semantic event structure and
pragmatic presentation.
3. Talmy lists the main factors: the Ground is usually (i) more permanently located; (ii) larger;
(iii) geometrically more complex; (iv) more familiar/expected; (v) of lesser concern or rele-
vance; (vi) more immediately perceivable; (vii) more backgrounded once Figure is perceived;
(viii) more independent (Talmy 2000: I, 315).
Almost identical criteria are proposed by Polinsky in a discussion of Figure and Ground in
Tsez, a language of the Caucasus, that belongs to the Nakh-Daghestanian family (1996). She
argues that Figure and Ground involve the interface between conceptual structure and syntactic–
semantic structure. The similarities suggest that the Figure–Ground distinction may be coded
similarly in many languages.
128 Referring expressions in discourse
Primary Referent. The criteria given have been used successfully to identify
Primary Referents in an informal study.5
There is a syntactic notion of prominent argument that may seem related to
Primary Referent. It is not: the two are quite distinct. The “prominent argu-
ment” relates syntactic structure to argument structure. For instance, Grimshaw
(1990) claims that the subject is prominent syntactically because of its position
as an external argument. The Agent and Cause roles that are typically realized
by subjects are also prominent, according to Grimshaw, in argument struc-
ture and event structure respectively. The subject is also regarded as prominent
in Speas (1990), who makes a different proposal. For Speas, thematic roles
originate in positions in lexical conceptual structure. The syntactic realization
corresponds to a thematic hierarchy, and follows the Universal Thematic As-
sociation Hypothesis (UTAH) of Baker (1988). Prominence in the thematic
hierarchy corresponds to syntactic prominence, Speas suggests; Agents are as-
sociated with the prominent subject position. In contrast, the Primary Referent
proposed here is associated with the outcome or motion of a situation, not the
agent/cause.
In determining the Primary Referents in a text I proceed on a clause-by-
clause basis. For clauses with a sentential complement, the Primary Referent is
decided as usual. If the event or state expressed by the complement is the Primary
Referent, the internal Primary Referent is noted as another level of structure. In
complex sentences each clause is treated separately, see Chapter 9.
5. An informal study ascertained that the criteria can be applied. The members of a seminar on
this material were given two texts and asked to identify the Primary Referent of each clause.
They agreed in most cases.
130 Referring expressions in discourse
thanks to the massive cost overruns and steadily growing complaints of mis-
management and corruption. 3 Overshadowed by scandal, the work itself –
whose scale and ambition are truly mind-boggling – continues almost as a
matter of course.
4 The heart of the project is an eight-to-ten-lane highwayi . 5 Iti is be-
ing built below ground to relieve the legendary traffic pressure caused by
Boston’s two major arteriesi , whichi converge downtown awkwardly near
the harbor, skyscrapers, and historic buildings. 6 Threading 35 lane-miles
of tunnel through Boston’s 3-D maze of subway lines and building founda-
tions, all without drastically disturbing the normal routines of surface life, is
an engineering planj thatj borders on the fantastic. 7 In some places the tunnels
are 120 feet deep. 8 The first two frequently asked questions on the project’s
official Web site are “What are you building?” and “Are you nuts?”
9 Surprisingly, tunnels are among the most ancient engineering feats.
The first two sentences have “headlines” and “news fare” as Primary Referents:
there is little change in metaphorical location from one to the other. At S3
the Primary Referent is “the work itself,” at Sentences 4 and 5 “the highway,”
and, at the relative clause, the relative pronoun referring to “Boston’s major
arteries.” At S6 the fantastic nature of the plan is primary, at S7 “the tunnels” is
Primary Referent; S8 has no distinguishable Primary Referent; at S9 “ancient
engineering feats” is primary. This sequence corresponds quite well to one’s
intuition of progression in the text, I think.
The reason for each choice of Primary Referent is listed very briefly in (9).
For sentences with more than one clause, the clauses are lettered a, b, etc.:
(9) Justification of choices of Primary Referents in (8)
S1) referent dependent on the situation for existence
S2) referent dependent on the situation for existence
S3) referent that moves/changes in the Event
S4) referent dependent on the situation for existence
S5) a, subject NP, referent come into being
b, relative clause, referent located
S6) referent dependent on the situation for existence
S7) referent has a property ascribed to it
S8) equational, no single Primary Referent
S9) referent dependent on the situation for existence
be identified by semantic and syntactic factors that relate event structure and
argument structure. I will not try to state them here, so that this construc-
tion rule is something of a promissory note. The enterprise, however, does not
seem hopeless. There is general agreement as to which argument realizes the
Theme/Patient role, although people do not agree on how to state principles of
argument selection. By hypothesis, then, an argument in the surface structure of
a clause has a semantic–syntactic feature that codes Patient/Theme information
from Event structure.
The construction rule identifies the argument with the Theme/Patient feature
(T/P) as Primary Referent. The information about Primary Referent will appear
as a condition on the entity in the Discourse Representation Structure. I state
the rule below and illustrate for the first sentence of (8), simplified:
(10) Primary Referents in the DRS
a. Construction Rule
[. . . a [+T/P]. . . . . . .] → a = Primary Referent
The rule applies to the sentence “The project made headlines over the past
months,” as shown below. The NP “headlines” is the Primary Referent since it
is the direct object of a transitive change-of-state verb (notated as Vt for telic),
and results in the DRS shown in (11b). In (11a), the input to the rule is a surface
structure with an NP subject, a transitive verb (Vt ), as NP object specified as
[+T/P]. “X” and “Y” indicate irrelevant material.
(11) a. IP [NPVP X[Vt NP [+T/P] Y]] → NP = PriRef
b. The project made headlines over the past months
t1 t2 t3 x y e d
1. e: made (x,y)
2. t1 = Sp T
3. t2 < t1
4. d = over the past months
5. t2 = d
6. t2 = t3
7. e ⊆ t3
8. x = the project
9. y = headlines
10. y = Primary Referent
The sentence is first in the DRS, with the deictic interpretation of the past
tense that locates the situation before SpT. The adverb specifies t2 , RT.
The event is perfective in this version of the sentence and included in t3 ,
SitT.
132 Referring expressions in discourse
The Primary Referent is the first step in determining atemporal text progres-
sion. The next step, more daunting, requires additional pragmatic calculation.
Recall that atemporal text progression occurs when metaphorical motion has
taken place. I suggested that metaphorical motion proceeds on analogy with
space, through the semantic terrain of a text. We know from the discussion in
Chapter 5 that spatial information is not conveyed by a grammatically closed
system. Morever, often the metaphorical motion in question will be only indi-
rectly spatial. To fully understand these matters we needed a way of accessing
and organizing many kinds of general information. We do not have a formal
account of how such calculations might be made at present. Perhaps the wide-
ranging approach sketched in Asher & Lascarides (1998) would eventually be
able to handle them.
The factors that determine text progression of atemporal text passages are
not grammatically signalled. Therefore the presentational aspect of such texts,
and the discourse relations that organize them at a more abstract level, take on
more importance. In the Information and Argument modes, discourse relations
may be an important part of atemporal text progression; see Chapter 11 for
some discussion.
6. Closed systems were extensively studied by linguists of the Prague School. Roman Jakobson,
for instance, discussed the meanings of their terms as conveying positive and negative values,
symmetry, and contrastive information (1957). I have proposed a somewhat different approach
6.2 Referring expressions 133
Referring expressions are closed systems, and pronouns are an important sub-
system. There is a very limited set of possibilities in English. Some findings
from other languages are pertinent to understanding the uses of English pro-
nouns. As a background for the discussion I make brief comments about noun
classifiers in Mandarin, proximate–obviative pronoun systems, and switch ref-
erence systems.
The forms of closed systems are often obligatory at the level of the sentence,
so that the grammar would predict that they appear in all relevant syntac-
tic contexts. It turns out, however, that extra-grammatical factors affect their
appearance.
In a study of noun classifiers in Mandarin Chinese, Erbaugh (1986) makes
this point quite dramatically. Classifiers (CLs) are a closed set of morphemes.
They appear in principle in NPs when a noun is preceded by a numeral or a
demonstrative, e.g. yiwei lao xiansheng (an old CL gentleman), yi pi ma (one
CL horse); there are two types, general and sortal classifiers. Erbaugh’s study
of classifiers in spoken Mandarin showed that sortal classifiers did not always
appear in such contexts.
Sortal classifiers were not predictable on a grammatical basis, Erbaugh found:
their use depended on genre, familiarity, and discourse structure.7 In relatively
formal speech situations and narratives, classifiers were most frequent. They
tended to appear in NPs that introduced new scenes or characters at event
boundaries. In casual conversation they introduced new topics or new concrete
objects, but they did not occur often. Erbaugh’s work shows these are used in
discourse according to extra-grammatical factors, although they are in principle
obligatory at the sentence level.
Similarly, certain types of pronouns are used to convey discourse meanings.
Proximal–obviative systems have contrasting pronominal morphemes with a
referential meaning. They signal whether a subject NP is coreferential with
a nearby antecedent. The proximate morpheme indicates coreference with a
nearby NP; the other obviates this reference, indicating as antecedent a less
to closed systems which distinguishes between semantic and pragmatic information (C. S.
Smith 1991). Semantic information is associated with a linguistic form in the grammar of a
language, while contrastive information about that form is part of the pragmatic knowledge of the
speaker.
7. Erbaugh showed films and asked subjects to narrate the story, using the “Pear Stories”. She also
collected examples of informal narratives, conversations, letters. There are additional subtleties
in the use of classifiers: for instance, Chu notes that the general classifier can be used instead of
“a specific one to express a casual attitude” (1983:17).
The Sino-Tibetan languages, including Mandarin, tend to have measure classifiers and special
classifiers. Mandarin also has a general classifier ge which may appear with any noun at all.
134 Referring expressions in discourse
proximate NP.8 The NPs are usually third person and animate. Systems of this
kind are found in Algonquian languages such as Fox, Plains Cree, Blackfoot.
The notions proximate and obviative have discourse interpretations. The no-
tion “proximate” is often metaphorical: proximate forms tend to be used for
characters of importance in the discourse. There are several patterns.9 In nar-
rative with a consistent central character, the proximate form is often used to
refer to that character throughout. Proximate forms are also used at the boundary
of a discourse unit, for instance the beginning of a new episode. More generally,
“proximate” is predictable, neutral, unmarked. “Obviative” is marked and con-
veys a referent that is special in some way. The extended, metaphorical distinc-
tion between proximal and obviative explains many uses of English stressed
and unstressed pronouns, and simple and reflexive pronouns as well.
Another type of system, known as switch reference, has a pronominal mor-
pheme on the verb which indicates whether the subjects of main and dependent
clauses are the same or different. The Same Subject morpheme (SS) in principle
indicates that the subjects are the same; the Different Subject (DS) indicates that
they are not. Switch reference morphemes are obligatory at the level of sentence
grammar, like noun classifiers. Also like noun classifiers, the morphemes do
not appear in every relevant context, and they usually have discourse meanings
beyond the referential. Switch reference morphemes are primarily used to con-
vey information about temporal and other relations between the situations in
the main and dependent clauses. Languages with switch reference systems in-
clude West African languages, American Indian languages, Papua New Guinea
languages.
The main use of switch reference is to indicate semantic relations between
situations. Often switch reference morphemes function as temporal connec-
tives. In temporal sentences the SS morpheme conveys that the situations in
dependent and matrix clauses are simultaneous, the DS morpheme that they are
sequential.10 These morphemes may also indicate logical or epistemic relations
8. Obviation refers to a form indicating the less salient of two third persons “to obviate con-
fusion,” according to Voegelin & Voegelin (1975:385). Hopi, Algonquian languages, Hokan
languages, Yup’ik Eskimo, and many others have contrasting forms which indicate coreference
and non-coreference between NPs in certain syntactic environments (Jacobsen 1967, Voegelin
& Voegelin 1975). The term “obviation” was proposed by Cuoq.
9. See for instance Frantz (1966) on Blackfoot, Wolfart (1973) on Plains Cree – all Algonquian
languages. Goddard (1990) and Thomason (1994) discuss Fox. Both Frantz and Wolfart note
that the proximate form has the pragmatic use of indicating a referent which is familiar, the
current topic of the discourse: currently in focus, in the sense of discourse focus.
10. When the referential and non-referential meanings of switch reference morphemes clash, the
non-referential meanings override. This leads to what Stirling calls “aberrant” uses of the
6.2 Referring expressions 135
6.2.2 Pronouns
Across languages pronouns take many forms: there are null pronouns, clitic
pronouns, strong pronouns, stressed and unstressed pronouns, reflexive pro-
nouns, possessive pronouns. Some languages have special pronoun forms with
specific functions. For instance, there are pronouns that convey reference to an
antecedent subject of consciousness, known as “logophoric.” Not all types are
available in all languages. If a language doesn’t have a pronoun form with
a dedicated function, other forms may be pressed into service to fulfill it.
There are no specifically logophoric pronouns in English, yet the subject-of-
consciousness meaning may be conveyed with the English reflexive pronoun. In
what follows I will consider stressed and unstressed pronouns, reflexives, null
morphemes. In aberrant DS cases, the morpheme appears when clauses differ in time, place,
or some other situation parameter, even though they have coreferential agentive subjects. The
examples below illustrate for time. The clauses have the same subject in all three examples. The
SS morpheme is grammatical in (a) but ungrammatical in (c); the DS morpheme is grammatical
in (b).
Example (a) is a typical case of Switch Reference: the second clause has the SS morpheme
and is not differentiated in tense from the first clause. In (b) the clauses have different tenses
and the second clause has the DS morpheme. The ungrammatical (c) is like (b) except that
the second clause has the SS morpheme. What this contrast shows is that having coreferential
subjects is not a sufficient condition for the SS marker in Lenakel: the clauses must have the
same tense as well. Stirling interprets this and similar examples as showing that the SS marker
is primarily used to convey that Events are closely related.
136 Referring expressions in discourse
pronouns, and possessive pronouns. Reciprocal and relative pronouns are not
discussed.
When used felicitously, pronouns refer to entities that are already known or
established in a discourse. The antecedent for a pronoun is mainly determined
by pragmatic factors.
11. I assume the grammatical constraints on possible pronoun reference as stated in Government
Binding Theory. The main constraint is that a pronoun may not be coreferential with an an-
tecedent that is higher in the structure of the same clause, a c-commanding antecedent (Chomsky
1981).
Non-referring uses of pronouns include quantifier contexts in which pronouns are variable
rather than referring expressions (“Everyone that has a donkey likes it”). These sentences are
known as “donkey sentences.”
12. One can construct examples which have a sentence-internal referent for the stressed pronoun:
Although [hisj colleagues]i think that theyi understand Johnj , HEj doesn’t think that
theyi do.
The pronoun in the main clause must be stressed, because the NP “his colleagues” sets up a
contrast set suggesting the focal interpretation of the pronoun. The example shows that the
6.2 Referring expressions 137
In this context the antecedent for “he” in (12c) is “Dad,” the referent of the
pronoun in the preceding sentence. Context may also affect the interpretation
of a stressed pronoun. In the context of (13a) the pronoun in (13b) is taken as
coreferential with “John”:
(13) a. Johni insists that Tomj and Billk abstain from drinking on the job.
b. After all, when HEi works, Johni doesn’t drink.
information for focal reference can be presented in more than one way; I shall not explore the
possibilities here.
138 Referring expressions in discourse
In (14a), the reflexive has no overt antecedent and is taken to refer to the
speaker of the sentence. Here and in other contexts, the reflexive alternates
with the ordinary pronoun form so that use of the reflexive represents a choice.
Reflexives that function similarly appear in other languages, e.g. Dutch zich,
Icelandic sig.
Locally Free Reflexives (LFRs) may also convey “empathy,” suggesting the
viewpoint of the antecedent in the situation expressed, as Kuno points out
(1972, 1987). The empathy meaning arises for LFRs in contexts that do not
directly express communication or mental state, as in (15):
13. Hagège compared the African languages with Latin and Japanese. Typically logophoric pro-
nouns are third person in subject position, but some languages are more flexible (Stirling 1993).
Some languages have a special pronoun form for non-subject cases, including the West African
languages Igbo, Gokana, and Ewe (among others).
The term “logophoric” has a general and a more specific use. Very generally, a logophoric pro-
noun attributes a connection of some kind between a pronoun and its antecedent, a connection
that is not licensed by the grammar, that is, the constraints of the Binding Theory (Reinhart &
Reuland 1993).
14. Cantrall (1969), Ross (1972) noticed that when they alternate with ordinary pronouns, reflexives
convey the consciousness or point of view of their antecedent. Sources of the examples: Ross
1970 (a); (b), is quoted in Zribi-Hertz (1989); c–d, Reinhart & Reuland (1993).
Other cases of LFRs include “My husband and myself would like to invite you to dinner”
(Keith Walters, pc).
6.2 Referring expressions 139
According to Kuno, these reflexives indicate the point of view or “camera an-
gle” of their antecedent: the speaker thus empathizes with that person. Neither
example falls under Binding Theory principles. In (15a) the reflexive and its
antecedent are not coarguments of the verb; (15b) is a “picture noun context” –
picture nouns have been problematic for the Binding Theory (Reinhart &
Reuland 1991).
Locally Free Reflexives may also indicate emphasis, contrast, or intensifi-
cation. The clearest cases of emphasis have strong stress, conveyed by capital
letters in this example from Zribi-Hertz (1989):
(16) Joycei is just holding herself together . . . Heri defenses are well inside
HERSELFi , not where mine are, outside in clothes, hair, etc.
Baker observes that the antecedent to the LFR “himself ” in this example, Sir
Willliam Lucas, cannot be explained as a subject of consciousness, empathy,
or contrast; but that the antecedent is prominent in the discourse. Discourse
prominence, according to Baker, is due to a character’s role as Agent or Patient,
of high importance or rank, or the primary topic of concern.15 A similar inten-
sive use also occurs with the [NP+reflexive] form, e.g. “The president himself
opened the door,” found in British and American English.
This section has identified several interpretations of Locally Free Reflex-
ives, in addition to their referential meaning. In the logophoric meaning, the
antecedent of the LFR is responsible for the thoughts, feelings, or sayings ex-
pressed in a clause. The empathy use implies the point of view of the antecedent.
15. Baker’s account is based in part on Ross (1970), Moyne (1971) on reflexives, and a suggestion
of Ferro (1993) that “self” may function as a focus marker. According to Baker, in American
English the difference between intensive and non-intensive contrast has been neutralized.
140 Referring expressions in discourse
The emphatic use highlights the antecedent of the reflexive, and the contrast use
involves explicit or implicit comparison with another entity. The intensive use,
typical of British English, both contrasts and highlights. Recall that LFRs can
always be replaced by an ordinary pronoun, since they are not subject to gram-
matical constraints. They represent the choice of the writer and carry special
meanings.
The situations in these sentences are tightly bound by their syntax. I will refer to
such clauses as “condensed clauses,” following Jespersen (1940). Condensed
clauses appear in argument and adjunct positions.
Sentences with condensed clauses present situations as a single syntactic
unit. The semantic meaning mirrors the syntactic presentation, as in (19):
(19) Searching with insatiable curiosity for underlying explanations, both did far
more than discover new facts or solve circumscribed problems, such as the
structure of DNA: they synthesized knowledge from a wide range of fields and
16. There are also lexically determined null subjects, as in the following examples. The possibilities
depend on the verb.
a. Mary wanted ø to win the race.
b. Mary wanted herself to win.
c. Mary wanted John to win.
d. Mary tried ø to win.
e. ∗ Mary tried herself to win.
f. ∗ Mary tried John to win.
Note that there is a close relation between the situations in main and complement clauses.
6.3 The familiarity status of referring expressions 141
created new conceptual frameworks, large parts of which are still accepted
today.
This fragment, presented as a unit, contains two condensed clauses and two full
clauses, both with conjoined VPs.
Strikingly, condensed clauses with null pronouns in English appear in almost
the same syntactic environments as the Same Subject morphemes of switch
reference systems. They use the two closed systems that allow anaphoric de-
pendence, tense and referential expressions. Condensed clauses have the effect
of presenting situations as tightly bound, just as the corresponding Switch Ref-
erence cases do. This semantic discourse effect follows from the syntax.
Choices from the closed system of referring expressions also convey infor-
mation about the familiarity or unfamiliarity of the referent.
(20) I saw a cat. The cat was sitting on a fence, watching a bird.
142 Referring expressions in discourse
The new entity in (21a) “a guy I work with” is quite different in status from
“Noam Chomsky” in (21b), as Prince points out. The former is Brand-new.
The latter is Unused, familiar – to the linguist at any rate – but not necessarily
active. The proper name can refer successfully only if the receiver is already
somewhat familiar with its referent.
The category of “familiar” entity can also be made more precise, Prince
shows.18 An NP with the definite article may refer to an entity actually available
in the discourse context; or to an entity that is readily inferrable in the context.
Example (22) illustrates:
entities tend to have the definite article, as in the example. Definite possessives
can also be taken as familiar if their possessor is familiar, as in “A man came
in. His daughter was with him,” from Barker (2000).
The simplest adequate account has three main classes of familiarity status,
classified as New, Evoked, or Inferrable (E. Prince 1981). Inferrable entities
arise from background knowledge and a trigger in the text, as the referent
of “the driver” in (22) is triggered by the mention of “a bus” in the pre-
ceding sentence. Prince’s categories are based on the assumption that writ-
ers choose forms based on their understanding of receivers’ knowledge and
expectations.
Evoked entities are familiar, usually coreferential with an entity already in-
troduced in the text. The distance between the entity and its antecedent may
be great or small. The antecedent may be in the same or a preceding sen-
tence, in which case the entity is already in the focus of attention, present in
the consciousness of the receiver. The antecedent may also be relatively far
away.
The forms of referring expressions differ in amount of coding material
and content. Thus the unstressed pronoun he is shorter and has less content
than a full NP such as the man or the man standing by the window. Expres-
sions that have the least information tend to be used when their antecedents
are nearby and/or salient in the text. For instance, if the antecedent of an
entity is nearby, a pronoun is commonly used to refer to it. When the an-
tecedent is further away, people tend to use referring expressions that are more
informative.
Drawing on these and other observations, Ariel (1990) gives a ranking of
referring expressions that links coding material, or amount of information,
and accessibility. Accessible referents are near, or easily found, in the text.
The rank of an expression correlates with how much information it conveys.
Null forms and unstressed pronouns are at the low end of the scale, with a
minimal amount of coding material. In the middle are demonstrative NPs (this
X, that Y) and stressed pronouns. At the high end of the scale are full names
and long definite descriptions. According to Ariel, each expression signals the
reader to search for an entity with accessibility indicated by its ranking on the
scale.
Evidence from text counts supports Ariel’s ranking. Pronouns are predom-
inantly used for short distances, anaphoric demonstratives are used in cases
of intermediate distance, and definite descriptions refer to antecedents that are
relatively far away (1989:70). Ariel notes that this conforms with the principle
of relevance proposed in Sperber & Wilson (1986). The correlation between
144 Referring expressions in discourse
The ranks are implicationally related. The implicational ranking relates a form
to all others that are below it on the hierarchy. For instance, if an expression of
rank 4 is licensed, so are expressions of ranks 1–3.
In using a particular form a speaker “signals that the associated cognitive sta-
tus is met and . . . that all lower, less restrictive statuses have been met” (Gundel
et al. 1993:184). The implicational relations may explain how people under-
stand expressions from the lower end of the scale used to refer to relatively
familiar entities. Such reference often appears in discourse when there is a
change of direction (see 6.3.2 below). Gundel et al. give similar rankings for
19. The hierarchy in (22) has a definite and indefinite use of the demonstrative this. In the definite
use, the NP is coreferential with an antecedent, as in the toy example below:
A man walked into the room. This man was wearing a red hat.
The indefinite use introduces a new element into the universe of discourse:
There was this guy I saw yesterday who was wearing a red hat.
The second use is common in speech and informal writing, as Keith Walters has pointed out
to me.
6.3 The familiarity status of referring expressions 145
the referring expressions of other languages. The rankings in (23) relate nicely
to Prince’s classes of familiarity status. Expressions from rank 6 to 3 are Evoked
or Inferrable; 1 and 2 are New.
The work reviewed above emphasizes the receiver rather than the text. There
is evidence that a text-based approach may be sufficient, even preferable, to
the receiver-based one. Prince (1992) looked at both approaches in a study
of referring expressions in a single written text. She asked whether hearer-
based or discourse-based categories were the most relevant and best predictor
of pronoun form. Comparing the cognitive status for the receiver and text status
of the entities, she found that the two overlapped in many cases. When they did
not overlap, “discourse-old” and “discourse-new” were better predictors of the
form of referring expressions than the corresponding categories “hearer-old”
and “hearer-new” (Prince 1992). The work of Birner & Ward (1998), discussed
in Chapter 8, also bears out this finding.
6.3.1.1 Continuity
Texts have referential continuity when each sentence refers back to entities
in the sentence that immediately precedes it, according to Sanford & Garrod
(1981). The simplest kind of continuity is conveyed by a chain of pronouns after
an entity is introduced. Example (24) is a constructed example from Kameyama
(1985):
(24) Maxi is a chemist. Hei is 30 years old, and hei lives in San Francisco.
The pronouns keep the entity at the same level of focused attention. If the chain
of pronouns is broken by an intervening sentence, the result can be odd and
difficult to interpret, as in (25), from Sanford & Garrod (1981).
(25) The little puppyi trod on a waspj . The puppyi was very upset.
Itj started to buzz furiously.
Examples like this have led people to seek the conditions for felicitous
continuity.
146 Referring expressions in discourse
The natural interpretation of (26a) has “Bill” as antecedent for the pronoun,
although both nouns in the first conjunct are possible.20 Strong stress on the
pronoun conveys the other interpretation unambiguously, as in (26b); it also
adds a sense of contrast. The principle of parallelism is very strong, overriding
the factor of proximity. For instance, “Tom” is nearer to the pronoun in (26a),
but the parallel interpretation remains. From a procedural point of view, par-
allel syntactic structures are an instruction to the reader to look for a certain
connection between them; the antecedent–pronoun link serves this function
(Blakemore 1988). Parallelism affects pronoun interpretation similarly in other
languages.
There are other patterns of continuity as well. General principles for conti-
nuity in discourse are stated in Centering Theory, which models connections
between referents in discourse (Walker et al. 1998).21 The theory works with
“centers,” semantic entities in an ongoing discourse model. The referring ex-
pressions of a sentence comprise a set of ranked forward-looking centers (Cf).
The highest ranked is a backward-looking center (Cb), which links the sentence
to previous discourse. The Cfs are potential backward-looking centers for other
utterances.
The notion of grammatical salience is the key to the ranking of centers.
Salience is determined by a hierarchy of grammatical relations: subject >
object > second object. The “preferred center” is the Cb. The Cb represents
20. The effects of parallelism can be increased or mitigated by the lexical properties of the main
verb. For instance, note the differences in the pairs below:
a. Frani won the money from Helenj because shei was a skillful player.
b. Frani won the money from Helenj because shej was a careless player.
c. Heleni punished Cathyj because shej confessed to shoplifting.
d. Heleni punished Cathyj because shei disapproved of shoplifting.
21. Centering Theory developed from a computational model of local attention and coherence,
where coherence was understood in terms of the links between sentences of short discourses
(Joshi & Weinstein 1981, Grosz & Sidner 1986, Walker et al. 1998: Ch. 1). Psychological
studies, e.g. Brennan (1995), Gordon & Chan (1995), give evidence that supports the model.
See also studies in Walker et al. (1998).
6.3 The familiarity status of referring expressions 147
(1987a:167). An illustrative example from Fox is given in (28). The change from
“she” back to “Susan” demarcates a new unit in the text, indicated graphically
by the paragraph indentation.
(28) The four flights up to her floor seemed longer than usual to Susani . Shei
paused on several occasions, because of a combination of physical fatigue and
mental effort.
Susani tried to remember if Bellows had said succinylcholine was among
the drugs found in the locker.
The choice of form, a full NP (Susan) at the beginning of the second paragraph
signals the functional structure of the narrative. Fox (1987b) documents similar
patterns in discursive prose. Similarly, Clancy (1980) observes that full NPs
are used at episode boundaries in narratives based on the “Pear Story” films, in
both English and Japanese.
These findings have experimental support from work in psycholinguistics. In
studies of production and comprehension, Vonk et al. (1992) looked at pronouns
and full NPs in text fragments. They found that when NPs were more specific
than necessary to recover an antecedent, the NPs had a discourse structuring
function. Pronouns were related to thematic continuity, full NPs triggered or
signalled shifts in theme.22 The authors interpret these findings as showing that
the full NP functioned as a signal to set up a new chain of information in the
discourse representation.
Other referring expressions have the same pattern: the fuller, more informa-
tive expression indicates a shift in the discourse. For instance, the pronouns
it and that differ. The pronoun it is neutral and that is deictic, indicating
non-proximate reference. In a study of oral apartment descriptions, Linde
(1979) found that the two appeared systematically according to whether their
referents were in the same or different discourse unit. It was used when
the referent was in the same unit; that when the referent was in a different
unit.
Another prediction of the linear continuity account is that a long gap between
mentions of a referent triggers a full NP. One might predict that pronouns,
22. These patterns also appear in other languages. In an oral Polish narrative with a main pro-
tagonist, reference was made with null pronouns when continuous and predictable. Null pro-
nouns are the Polish equivalent of unstressed ordinary pronouns. Overt pronouns appeared
when there was narrative discontinuity, changes in speaker perspective, and contrast between
foreground and background (Flashner 1987). Similarly Clancy (1980), in a study of spo-
ken English and Japanese narratives, found that people tended to use full NPs to mark dis-
course boundaries, point-of-view changes, and episode changes. See also the articles in Givón
(1979).
6.4 Referring expressions and DR Theory 149
which have little coding material, are not strong enough to access an antecedent
that is relatively far away. This prediction has been disconfirmed. In a study
of narrative, for instance, Fox found that pronouns are used for a particular
character over relatively long stretches of text “until another character’s goals
and actions are introduced, unless those goals and action are interactive with the
first character’s” (1987a:162). In sum, what matters is discourse continuity. In
texts with one central character, reference to that character may be made at any
time with an ordinary pronoun, even if there have been significant interruptions
(Whitaker & Smith 1985).
Similar findings have been documented for non-narrative English discourse.
Hinds (1977) examined the use of pronouns and full NPs in newspaper articles.
He found that the choice between them depended on the structure of the text.
Nominal and pronominal reference were sometimes used to convey different
degrees of prominence, with nominal reference indicating “semantically promi-
nent” information. Hinds found that nominal expressions tended to appear at
discourse peaks.
Summarizing, the form of a referring expression encodes the familiarity status
of a referent. In discourse, anaphoric expressions convey referential continuity.
Fuller expressions are used to convey discourse shifts, and expressions that
code unfamiliarity tend to appear at discourse boundaries.
23. The approach of Discourse Representation Theory was a significant advance over earlier theo-
ries such as the referential theory of indefinites and an alternative, the quantificational theory.
The discussion below necessarily omits many important points, among them varieties of
pronoun reference and plurals.
150 Referring expressions in discourse
introduces discourse referents that are coreferential with entities already there.
These classes correspond, more or less, to the distinction between new and
familiar referents. In some cases a referring expression has the form asso-
ciated with familiar referents, but the context does not contain an appropri-
ate antecedent. The receiver accommodates by assuming or inferring such an
antecedent.
Proper names and indefinite NPs license the introduction of new entities into
a DRS; pronouns and certain other NPs refer to entities that are already in the
context.24 In certain contexts coreference is impossible, as noted in Chapter 3.
The theory recognizes this by stating structural accessibility conditions. (This
notion of accessibility is different from accessibility based on distance in a text.)
In conversation, pronouns may refer to an entity in the context; they refer to
discourse entities in a written text.
Anaphora in the DRS is thus a relation that holds between a discourse entity
and a pronoun or other referring expression. This is the standard Discourse
Representation Theory account. The work on referential expressions discussed
above suggests that the standard account should be augmented slightly. Expres-
sions that refer to familiar entities should include NounPhrases with demonstra-
tive (that, this), and null pronouns which are interpreted by rule. Expressions
that introduce new identities should probably include referential indefinites
(“this N”), although it is not easy to distinguish them from nominals of the
same shape referring to “activated” referents.
Reflexive pronouns in syntactically bound contexts require additional con-
ditions, as Kamp & Reyle point out. Reflexives do not alternate with simple
pronouns in such contexts. To convey a coreferential meaning a reflexive form
must be used. For instance, in “Jane washed her,” “her” cannot be interpreted
as coreferential with the subject “Jane.” Coreference can only be expressed
with the reflexive “Jane washed herself.” These conditions are straightforward
in principle, although actually stating them is complex.
Locally Free Reflexives do alternate with simple pronouns and thus re-
quire a different treatment. Two questions arise, one specific to the class and
the other general to pronouns. The specific question is whether the special
quality of LFR should be encoded in the DRS. The mechanism for such en-
coding exists: a special feature could be introduced that would allow for the
24. Proper names are linked to entities in the world by an external anchor. The external anchor
for a discourse referent x is a function which maps x into some real individual a. The anchor
constrains the mechanism used for truth-conditional verification of a sentence (Kamp & Reyle
1993:248).
6.4 Referring expressions and DR Theory 151
(29) 1 The four flights up seemed longer than usual to Susani . 2 Shei paused on
several occasions.
3 Susani tried to remember if Bellows had found drugs in a locker.
25. In a more complete account of the pragmatics of discourse, pragmatic principles for contrastive
meanings might be stated. I proposed such principles for contrastive meanings in aspectual
viewpoint systems in C. S. Smith (1997).
152 Referring expressions in discourse
x y z u v s1 e1 e2
1. x = four flights
2. y = Susan
3. s1: seemed long (x,y)
4. z = she
5. e1: pause on several occasions (z)
6. z=y
7. u = Susan
8. u=y
9. v = Bellows
10. e2: try to remember (v
if
e3 a b c
1. a = Bellows
2. b = drugs
3. c = locker
4. e3: find (a,b in c)
5. a=v
The discourse entities are licensed by the proper names, pronouns, and Noun-
Phrases. In this case there is only one possible antecedent for the pronoun “she”:
Susan. The second instance of the proper name is taken as coreferential with
the first. This is a matter of pragmatic interpretation, indeterminate in the DRS.
In all Discourse Modes and genres, one finds passages that suggest a particular
voice. They convey a sense of subjectivity, a point of view toward propositional
information. “Point of view” is familiar as a literary term referring to presen-
tation of the mind of a fictional character in narrative. More generally, point
of view is “the perceptual or conceptual position in terms of which narrated
situations and events are presented” (G. Prince 1987:73). Linguists now use
the term for expressions of speech and thought, evidentiality, perspective, and
other indications of an authorial or participant voice. “Point of view” is used
almost interchangeably with “perspective” and “subjectivity.” I shall use the
latter term as more general. Subjectivity is conveyed by grammatical forms and
lexical choices.1
Three traditions come together in the area of subjectivity. One is deixis and
its linguistic expression. Deixis is a general term for the centrality of the here
and now in language. The study of deixis takes as basic the canonical speech
situation with Speaker and Addressee, and explores its linguistic ramifications.
The second tradition involves evidentiality, indications of the source and reli-
ability of information. Evidentiality is a relatively new term for the semantic
field of attitude toward knowledge, a kind of modality. Linguistic resources for
this vary strikingly across languages. Finally, subjectivity conveys the contents
of mind and personal perspective; here linguistic study is complemented by
a strong literary tradition. The area is a vast one and I intend this chapter as
an introduction, by no means a complete account. I will give the grammatical
underpinnings of subjectivity, the bare bones.
Subjectivity arises primarily in discourse contexts. It is expressed by gram-
matical forms at the sentence level: verbs and their complements, adverbials,
tense, modals, aspectual viewpoint, anaphors. Often a subjective form has scope
1. Some of the material in this chapter was presented at a symposium at the University of Oslo in
December 2000: “Information Structure in a Cross-linguistic Perspective.” I would like to thank
the audience for their questions and the discussion; I also thank Cathrine Fabricius-Hansen for
helpful comments.
155
156 Subjectivity in texts
express one’s own sadness, for instance, a person uses a subjective adjective
with a first-person pronoun; to report the sadness of another, a verb and a third-
person subject. What Kuroda noticed is that the subjective forms appear in third-
person narrative fiction, where they would not, strictly speaking, be expected. In
these fictional contexts the subjective forms directly render a character’s mental
state; they do not function as linguistic communication.2 Kuroda calls this use
the “non-reportive” style, distinguishing it from the “reportive” style typical of
communication (1973:384). Although lacking forms like these, English too can
convey expressions of mental state. In fact, there are English expressions that
correspond to Kuroda’s reportive and non-reportive styles. Banfield argues that
represented speech and thought, which are typical of fiction, are non-reportive
(1982:12). Subjectivity can also be expressed with deictic pronouns and verbs
of mental state. Lyons notes that English has distinct forms for “experiential”
and “non-experiential” expressions (1982:107).
In fact, English has ways of expressing subjectivity in sentences of all genres
and modes. The linguistic forms that convey subjectivity include verbs of mental
state and perception, modals and evaluative adverbs, and others discussed
below. Sentences that lack these forms are neutral or objective in our conven-
tional understanding, which posits a Responsible Source and a point of view
for every sentence. I do not have space here to explore competing views.3 The
force of the subjective and objective is unique in fictional narrative, however.
The fictional world of a story or novel can be known to the reader only from
the text. The functions of sentences with and without subjective elements reflect
this. Certain sentences of a fictional narrative are objective, in the sense that we
accept them as true information about the fictional world. These are sentences
2. Kuroda’s examples include sentences with the subjective adjective forms and third-person sub-
jects. The following, for instance, has the subjective adjectival form for “sad”:
Yamaderra no kane o kiite, Mary wa kanasikatta.
Hearing the bell of the mountain temple, Mary was sad.
Sentences like this are odd, even ungrammatical in isolation. In a narrative context they are
taken to express a character’s point of view directly.
3. This view has been developed primarily for narrative. For instance, Genette (1980) says that
strictly objective narration is impossible, and that all narrative is subjective, or “focalized,”
although in different ways. He makes an important distinction between the “one who sees,” (the
narrator), and “one who speaks.”
There is surely something right about the idea that the speaker/author is present in all genres,
cf. Palacas (1993). In an account that included expressive lexical items, one might want to posit
a Responsible Source for all cases.
The distinction between subjective and objective sentences may not hold for all languages.
Some languages have obligatory morphemes which code subjective information for evidentiality
in all sentences; see Willett (1988).
158 Subjectivity in texts
4. The view that only one Responsible Source in needed accords with much recent work. In her
discussion of narrative and represented speech, Banfield (1982) formulates syntactic principles
for attributing expressive elements to a unique subjectivity. Stirling (1993) takes a similar
approach in the Discourse Representation Theory framework. She posits a single Validator role,
7.2 Expressions of communication 159
In the next few sections I discuss the main types of expression that lead
to the interpretation of subjectivity: communication, mental states, evaluation,
perception and perspective. The examples of text passages come from texts in
this study.
which is associated with the appropriate sentient being. Speas and Tenny (2001) posit a single
interpretive role, the Evaluator, in a semantically based syntactic approach. In contrast Sells
(1987) argues that three roles are necessary to account for logophoric expressions; for discussion
see Stirling (1993). Sanders & Redeker (1996) also posit a single Responsible Source, using the
framework of cognitive linguistics.
5. The line between quoted and reported speech is sometimes difficult to draw, in a discussion of
real and constructed dialogue and quotation. Tannen (1989) notes that the context for quotation
and report always informs what is said. She claims that even seemingly “direct” quotation is
really “constructed dialogue,” primarily the creation of the speaker rather than the party quoted
(1989:99). I am grateful to Keith Walters for pointing out this book to me.
160 Subjectivity in texts
The deictics convey that the reporter has recoded all or part of what was said.7
In (4a) “tomorrow” relates the leaving to Speech Time rather than to the past
time of John’s utterance. In (4b) the clauses have different tenses. The sentence
6. Tense concord is also known as “sequence of tense.” Tense and person concord is required in
English, but not in all languages. Japanese and Navajo, for instance, do not have shifted person
markers nor tense concord in the complements of communication verbs; Russian does not have
sequence of tense, Amharic does not have sequence of person (Schlenker 1999).
7. Deictic adverbials vary: some can shift orientation to any deictic center, others are oriented only
to the here and now, as noted in Chapter 5. Tomorrow and yesterday are rigid adverbials that do
not shift.
7.2 Expressions of communication 161
conveys that John’s utterance about Mary’s pregnancy was made in the past;
and that the reporter relates the pregnancy to the time of speech. This type of
sentence is known as a “double-access” sentence; see Ogihara (1996), Abusch
(1997), Giorgi & Pianesi (1997).8
Verbs of communication are a distinct syntactic class. They allow a direct
object complement which expresses the actual communication and an indirect
object referring to the addressee (“X said Y to Z”). The class includes the verbs
say, ask, request, command, declare, confess, advise, insist, claim, shout, read,
sing, remark, observe, note, swear, promise, announce, pray, and many others.
Manner-of-speaking verbs such as shout, scream, whine, whisper, holler have
special properties (Zwicky 1971).
Given the close relation between them, we might attempt to derive indirect
speech from direct speech. However this approach cannot work. The argument
turns on two points: firstly, not all indirect speech reports have plausible coun-
terparts in expressions of direct speech; and secondly, the ambiguity between de
re and de dicto readings arises only for indirect speech (Partee 1973, Banfield
1982).
Communication in discourse may take the form of represented speech or
thought, which has some features of quoted and some of indirect speech. Rep-
resented speech maintains the syntax of actual, or quoted speech, but tense and
pronouns are shifted as in indirect speech; (5) illustrates:
(5) Represented speech and thought
1 He then took from his waistcoat pocket a little paper and glanced at the
headings he had made for his speech. 2 He was undecided about the lines
from Robert Browning, for he feared they would be above the heads of his
hearers. 3 Some quotation that they would recognize from Shakespeare or
from the Melodies would be better. 4 He would only make himself ridiculous
by quoting poetry to them which they could not understand. 5 They would
think that he was airing his superior education. 6 He would fail with them just
as he had failed with the girl in the pantry. 7 He had taken up a wrong tone. 8
His whole speech was a mistake from first to last, an utter failure.
After S1, the sentences have shifted tense and person. The narrator would
think of himself as “I,” would represent the future with “will,” the past with
“took.” The locutions of direct speech and thought are rendered directly, as in
Sentences 6–7.
8. Cathrine Fabricius-Hansen notes (p.c.) that the reporter is responsible for the temporal descrip-
tion but not for the claim. Example (4b) would not necessarily be false if Louise were not
pregnant at the time of the report, as is shown by the felicity of the following:
(i) John said that Louise is pregnant but in fact she isn’t.
It is the claim that John is reported to have made that would be false.
162 Subjectivity in texts
(6) Looking at the more severely affected countries, experts are wondering where
the saturation point will be. Where will the infection rate level off as most of
those engaging in riskier behavior fall prey: 30 percent? 40 percent?
(7) Those are rather windy thoughts, but I have had a hard time escaping them
the last few weeks as I’ve tried to make some sense of the Events surrounding
President Clinton, Congress and impeachment. What will people say about
all this 20 years from now? Will they quiz each other on the minutiae of the
Starr report, as they do on the contents of the Warren report? Or will posterity
simply conclude that one of the two political parties, having lost an election,
saw an opportunity to nullify it and proved too weak to resist the temptation?
You may find that a difficult question. I don’t.
The writer is the source of subjectivity in this text. The reader may also be
addressed directly, as in the last sentences of the fragment above.
In (8b), which expresses a belief, the main and complement clauses have
coreferential subjects. The coreference relation between subjects in clauses of
thought and communication triggers a logophoric interpretation, discussed in
Chapter 6.
The person who holds a belief is responsible for it. But belief sentences are
also reports by the writer and have the possibility of recoding. The writer’s
presence is sometimes suggested by evaluative expressions and epithets, which
are vague as to source. For instance, epithets such as “that fool,” “that idiot of
a doctor,” “a peach of a girl” can be ascribed to the believer or to the reporter,
as in (9):
(9) a. Sam thinks that his beloved cat should have only fresh fish.
b. Mary believed that that fool Kevin wanted to run the committee.
On one reading, the epithets “beloved cat,” “that fool” are part of the reported
beliefs. There is also a reading in which the reporter designates the cat as
beloved, Kevin as a fool. This reading is salient in (9b) because of the deictic
that.9
Sentences with clauses referring to propositions have an additional dimension
of subjectivity. Recall that propositions are subjective, ascribed to the person
holding them (Chapter 4). Clauses referring to Facts are not subjective in this
way. Nominals of communication and mental state are similar to verbs in sub-
jectivity. For instance, the interpretation of “Mary’s belief that John won the
race” is not significantly different from the corresponding tensed clause.
9. The interpretation is my own; Banfield claims that epithets in clauses of indirect speech and
thought are attributable only to the speaker (1982:54).
Epithets are lexical items whose full interpretation entails a reference to the speaker. In the
embedded clause of indirect speech, however, they only express the state and attitude of the
reporting speaker, according to Banfield, who suggests two classes:
a. Epithets: fool, bastard, etc.
b. Evaluative adjectives: the poor girl, that damned Faustus, etc.
Banfield claims that these forms constitute a well-defined, “non-classificatory” class that can
be distinguished with a lexical feature.
164 Subjectivity in texts
expressions are evaluative and evidential adverbs and adjectives, modals, and
parenthetical expressions. Attitudes are ascribed to participants in the text sit-
uation when they appear within the scope of subjective expressions.
Adverbs can be divided into classes according to their semantic relationship to
the situation and speaker/writer. One class gives the speaker’s attitude toward
what is said (frankly, honestly); another conveys the speaker’s evaluation of
the text situation (fortunately, surprisingly). Evidential adverbials express the
speaker’s commitment to a proposition (clearly, allegedly, seemingly, probably,
possibly); likely is an adjective of the same type. Adverbs like these can appear
in various positions in a sentence: they are also called “parentheticals.”
(10) a. Surprisingly, tunnels are among the most ancient engineering feats. The
earliest were very likely extensions of prehistoric cave dwellings.
b. Most of us don’t suffer as a result of Darwin’s having eventually attributed
too much scope to the process termed sypatric speciation than it actually
deserves. But a powerful man’s mistaken ideas about women have certainly
caused suffering.
c. The rest of the space was taken up by fancy notepaper, glass paperweights,
fluffy animals and fridge-door magnets shaped like strawberries or Humpty
Dumpty. In the back, though, the setup was very different.
(11) a. The predominant output was the white ware with transparent ivory toned
glaze which made the kilns famous. The other wares were a soft, dark
brown or dense black glazed type, a white ware and a group of lead glazed
earthenwares.
The kilns clearly specialized in the production of the porcellanous ware.
b. Sooner or later, oil prices are likely to drop. But prices at today’s levels
have their advantages.
The adverbs of (10a–b) and parenthetical of (10c) express attitude and evalua-
tion. The adverb and adjective of (11) express evidentiality; they are sometimes
called “speaker-oriented” forms. These expressions are attributed to the speaker
as Responsible Source. The adverbs are classified as Speech Act, Evaluative,
and Evidential adverbs by Cinque (1999). Cinque presents a semantically based
syntactic account of these expressions: he posits a syntactic projection for each
class according to their possible positions in a sentence.
Many evaluative and evidential adverbs have corresponding adjectives. They
differ in the Responsible Source, reflecting a different syntactic status. The
speaker is always the source for adverbs, which are external syntactically and
semantically to the sentence. Evaluative adjectives, however, function as the
main predicate. They are associated with an experiencer, explicit or implicit.
This allows more than one interpretation of responsibility; (12) illustrates:
7.4 Evaluative and evidential subjectivity 165
In (12a), we infer that the author is responsible for evaluating the situation
as surprising. But in (12b) the experts hold the evaluative attitude. Example
(12c), though vague, includes the author. The modal contributes to the inter-
pretation of subjectivity; modals are discussed below. The verbs seem, appear,
suggest have the same range of interpretation. The speaker is responsible for
the evaluation unless a text participant is explicitly mentioned. For instance, a
variant of (12c) has a sentence-internal interpretation: “For a big-city mayor to
be so at odds with his party seemed peculiar to the voters.” Another difference
between evaluative predicates and adverbials is that verbs and adjectives can
be questioned, whereas adverbs cannot. The related “psychological” verbs, e.g.
surprise, frighten, annoy, etc., are not subjective in the sense developed here:
they do not require that responsibility be ascribed to a mind.
Discourse salience, evidentiality, and “performativity” must all be consid-
ered in understanding evaluative predicates and adverbials, according to Nuyts
(1993). He suggests that evaluatives may be “performative” or “descriptive.”
When used performatively, the speaker/author is an active participant in the
evaluation. They are descriptive when they report evaluation that is part of the
text situation.
Evidentiality is the semantic domain of speaker commitment to what is said.
In English, evidentiality is expressed by adverbs and adjectives, as above; and
by verbs and modal auxiliaries.10 I will sketch here how modals fit into an
account of evidentiality. I cannot offer a full account here of the contribution of
modals to interpretation, nor of the domain of modality; I ignore conditionals
and the modal aspect of generics.
Strictly speaking, modality has to do with necessity and possibility: modal
forms express the necessity or possibility of a proposition. More abstractly, they
express a certain way the world might be, and involve a modal relation and a
10. Some languages have highly developed sub-systems for evidentiality, see Chafe & Nichols
(1986), Willett (1988), Dendale & Tasmowski (2001) for surveys. Kamio (1994) discusses
Japanese.
166 Subjectivity in texts
On the internal interpretation must functions like the modal operator of logical
necessity on the proposition; it does not express the position of the speaker. The
evidential interpretations can be paraphrased as “I (confidently) infer that Alfred
is unmarried” and “Alfred is obliged to be unmarried.” The two interpretations
correspond to the distinction between epistemic and deontic modality. The
epistemic interpretation ascribes confidence to the speaker. It is “subjective,”
qualifying the speaker’s commitment to the proposition that Alfred is unmar-
ried. The deontic interpretation in this sentence is “objective’: it indicates that,
according to the judgment of the speaker, there is a mathematically computable
chance that the proposition is true.
Subjective and objective modality differ in how the speaker participates in
the evaluation. For instance, on the subjective must reading of (13) the speaker
expresses commitment to an evaulation. The objective interpretation is a factual
assertion expressing the speaker’s judgment about content (Lyons 1982).
Three classes of modals are recognized in Verstraete (2001): internal, epis-
temic, and deontic. Internal modals concern ability and volition and pertain
directly to the proposition expressed. Epistemic modals are evidential and sub-
jective. Deontic modals may be subjective or objective, for instance, “Alfred
may be unmarried” is ambiguous between the speaker’s subjective assessment
and an “objective” assessment of circumstances. Such an assessment, although
objective, is due to the speaker and therefore also evidential.11
11. Subjective and objective evidentials are distinguishable by the criteria of behavior under in-
terrogation and in conditional contexts, and surface ordering, according to Verstraete (2001).
Verstraete may not share my interpretation of objective modal interpretation as evidential. Nuyts
(1993) distinguishes subjective and objective evidentials by their availability for negation, and
other criteria. His work is based on a study of adverbial and adjectival expressions in a corpus
of Dutch discourse. He suggests that the English forms can be explained along similar lines.
7.4 Evaluative and evidential subjectivity 167
The following examples illustrate the classes: (14) has a modal of ability,
internal to the proposition. Sentence (15), repeating (12c), has a subjective,
evidential modal; the modals of (16) are evidential and ambiguous between the
subjective and objective interpretations.
(14) Gabriel went to the stairs and listened over the banisters.
He could hear two persons talking in the pantry.
(15) For a big-city mayor to be so at odds with his party would seem peculiar.
Except that it’s happening everywhere.
(16) a. In Belgrade, Yugoslav President Slobodan Milosevic . . . insisted . . . that the
details must be negotiated directly with the United Nations. That would ap-
pear to fall short of Western conditions for halting the eight-week bombing
campaign.
b. For the body to operate properly, it is crucial that diverse hormones and
receptors produce distinct effects on cells. To achieve such specificity, re-
ceptors must engage in somewhat different behavior.
c. Bass rumbles that could have issued from the lowest octave of a cathedral
pipe organ gave way to plaintive moans and then to glissandos like air
squealing out of a balloon when you stretch the neck taut. With the notes
building into phrases and the phrases into repeated themes, the song may
be the longest – up to 30 minutes – and the most complex in the animal
kingdom.
(17) Allied divisions over using ground troops in Kosovo burst into the open on
Wednesday when Germany’s chancellor declared that his country would block
NATO from fighting a land war.
Similarly, when a modal is within the scope of a mental State verb, the Respon-
sible Source is the subject of the verb.
Context is often essential in interpreting expressions of subjectivity: the
Responsible Source may be in a preceding sentence. For instance, a mental
state verb holds over subsequent sentences unless it is interrupted by another
subjective indicator or a change of time or place. Example (18) gives a simple
example, a variant of (12a); the evaluative was clear in S2 is in the scope of
believe of S1.
(19) 1 Sir Mark Sykes seems to have started worrying about the Syrian problem the
year before in the context of pledges he intended Britain to keep to her allies –
and her allies to keep to her. 2 His concern was that Syrians might not accept
the Sykes–Picot agreement and the terms outlined by Sir Henry McMahon
to the Sherif Hussein. 3 In 1917 he asked the Arab Bureau [of Britain] to
set up a meeting for him with Syrian Arab leaders in Cairo, apparently in
order to arrive at an agreement with them that would be consistent with the
secret accords with France and with the Hejaz – accords whose existence,
however, he could not reveal to them. 4 He claimed he had succeeded; in his
own hand he noted that “The main difficulty was to manoeuvre the delegates
into asking for what we were prepared to give them, without letting them
know that any precise geographical agreement had been come to.” 5 The
“precise geographical agreement” must have meant the Damascus–Homs–
Gana–Aleppo line that was to be the westward frontier of Arab independence
in Syria under the agreement with al-Faruqi in 1915 and with France in 1916.
6 But reports arrived from various quarters that the Ottoman government
might be planning to pre-empt Arab nationalism by granting autonomy to Syria
immediately. 7 That would leave Britain in the awkward position of sponsoring
the claims of King Hussein as against an indigenous Arabic leadership in
Damascus that threatened to be far more popular in the Syrian provinces.
The list in (20) summarizes the interpretation, giving the trigger for subjectivity;
the Responsible Source (RS), and the scope of the subjective expression. The
7.5 Perception and perspectival sentences 169
There are three candidates for the Responsible Source of the modal in the last
sentence. The first is the Author; the second is “reports,” Subject by extension,
though not a sentient being. On this reading the evidential is contained in the
reports and the scope of “reports” is S6 and S7. The third possible source for
“would” in S7 is Sykes, the Subject of the mental State verb “worry about” in
S1 of the fragment.
The entire fragment is concerned with Sykes’ worrying about a complex
situation. The verb “worry about” in S1 has uninterrupted scope through S7
because continuity is maintained. The fragment does not introduce a Respon-
sible Source that competes with Sykes, nor does it contain any deictic shifts
indicating a difference in the situation.
Evaluation may take other forms as well. Sentence connectives such as yet,
anyway, still, but, for instance, convey the author’s view of relations between
situations. There are also idiomatic forms, e.g. after all as in “So he is coming
after all! (despite our expectation to the contrary)” from Cinque (1999). Like
other lexical expressions, cases like this are beyond the scope of this discussion.
Compositional rules for subjective interpretations like those given above are
presented in 7.6.
7.5.1 Perception
Linguistic presentation of perception may be direct, contextual, or inferred. The
most straightforward cases are reports of direct perception, in which a verb of
seeing, hearing, etc., introduces a complement which expresses the percept, as
in (21):
(21) a. John saw that the sun was shining.
b. John saw Mary walk to school.
c. John saw Mary walking to school.
The subject of the first sentence is the perceiver; the second sentence conveys
what is perceived. Sentences that convey perception in this way are “perspec-
tivally situated” (Caenepeel 1989);13 they tend to occur in narrative contexts.
12. In a full account of direct perception sentences, one might distinguish perceivable situations
from those that can only be inferred, e.g. “Mary saw John thinking about the race.” Such
distinctions would help to separate the extended meanings of see, hear, feel from the meaning
of direct perception. The extended meaning of see would be something like “understand,”
“infer”, while that of hear would be “have been told that”; etc.
13. According to Caenepeel, perceptual reports or perspectivally situated sentences are always
stative (state or progressive event sentences, in our terms). She claims that events – that is,
event verb constellation with the perfective viewpoint – are impossible or awkward as perceptual
7.5 Perception and perspectival sentences 171
S2 in (23a) suggests Mary’s perspective. The tense of both clauses is past; the
complement clause has the deictic adverb now, which is normally anchored to
Speech Time; the situation is a state. S2 in (247b), however, is indeterminate
between the perspective of Mary and that of the narrator. Oppositions such as
perfective and imperfective often have the pragmatic function of marking what
is traditionally referred to as “point of view” in narrative (Fleischman 1991:26).
There are also contexts of inferred perception, when the situation implies a
percept due to our knowledge of the world. As with indirect perception more
than one sentence is needed. The examples in (24) illustrate:
(24) a. 1 I sipped my drink and nodded. 2 The pulse in his lean grey throat throbbed
visibly and yet so slowly that it was hardly a pulse at all. 3 An old man
two-thirds dead and still determined to believe he could take it.
b. 1 One night in November 1961, Alice went into the tub room to put some
clothes in her old wringer washing machine. 2 a When she turned on the
light, b there was a rat the size of a small cat sitting on the machine.
reports unless there is a contingency relation between the event and the focalizing sentence.
In a contingency relation, the situation of the perspectivally situated sentence is contingent on
the immediately preceding situation.
However, events are acceptable as perceptual reports in extended, continuous situations of
perception:
a. 1 John looked out the window. 2 Birds flew back and forth and the church bell tolled
loudly.
b. John looked out the window. Mary threw the ball to Sue and Bill played in the
sandbox. The neighbor’s dog arrived and trotted around the yard.
Of course, not all sequences with a verb of perception preceding a sentence of an unbounded
situation express a percept. The second sentence may indicate an entirely different situation:
c. John looked out the window. The children were playing quietly in a corner of the
room.
14. This is particularly clear in French: the imparfait past tense allows shifted deictics more freely
than the perfective past tenses (Banfield 1982, Smith 1991).
172 Subjectivity in texts
(25) a. Mary played in the sandbox. Huge storm clouds covered the sky. Was it
going to rain?
b. Mary was playing in the sandbox. Huge storm clouds were covering the
sky. Was it going to rain?
c. Mary was playing in the sandbox with her brother. Huge storm clouds were
covering the sky. Was it going to rain?
In (25a) the direct question is the only subjective element; in (25b) the pre-
ceding sentence has the progressive, which invites a subjective interpretation.
The example with the strongest subjective interpretation is (25c), which also
has a possessive phrase oriented to Mary. I do not have a formal account
of inferred perception. It depends on pragmatic factors as well as linguistic
form.
15. Cantrall was perhaps the first to note the perspectival use of the reflexive. Cantrall presents
many examples, among them the following sentences. Cantrall asks us to imagine that they
describe a photograph which portrays a group of standing women who have their backs to the
camera:
a. The womeni were standing in the background, with the children behind themi .
b. The womeni were standing in the background, with the children behind themselvesi .
In (a) the children are located from the perspective of the speaker; in (b) they are located from
the perspective of the women. As Zribi-Hertz notes, the sentences provide empirical evidence
that the reflexive is correlated with an “internal” point of view – that of a discourse protagonist
as opposed to the speaker (1989:704).
Examples like (27a) led Ross (1970) to suggest that all sentences have a higher clause in
underlying structure with a first-person pronoun and a verb of communication in the present
tense. The overt reflexive pronoun would be coindexed with the covert first-person pronoun.
Zellig Harris reached the same conclusion on a different basis (in Harris 1982), as Bruce Nevin
has pointed out to me.
16. Syntactically conditioned reflexives are obligatory in certain contexts; they are defined in
Government Binding Theory with the notions of c-command and locality of domain. The
Binding Theory requires that the antecedent c-command a reflexive if it is within the domain
of the relevant governing category (Chomsky 1981). The Binding Theory as stated has been
the subject of much critical comment. Reinhart & Reuland (1993) offer an extensive revision
in the same general framework.
174 Subjectivity in texts
Example (27b), with the reflexive, suggests the perspective of John as he pulls
the toy, (27a) does not. Other uses of Locally Free Reflexives are discussed in
Chapter 6.
According to Kuno (1987), the reflexives in these examples convey an “empa-
thy perspective” in which the reporter takes the perspective of another person.17
Empathy may be conveyed by other means as well. For instance, consider the
descriptions of the participants in “Accompanied by his son, the informant
went out to investigate.” The writer expresses empathy with the informant by
describing him independently and the son dependently, as Sanders & Redeker
(1996) observe.
Possessive pronouns may also suggest perspective, often of a participant. In
English this is due to the limited resources of the language. Possessive pronouns
have no reflexive alternant. There is only one form, with the potential for a
possessive, reflexive, or perspectival reflexive reading. The examples in (28)
show possessive pronouns suggesting the perspective of the antecedent: (28a)
is from Kuno (1987), (28b) from Hirose (2000):
(28) a. John criticized his brother.
b. Kazuo lost a book that he borrowed from a friend of his.
17. Perspectival LFRs have been identified in many other languages, among them Japanese, Scan-
dinavian languages, and Italian. Kuno (1987) offers a survey of perspectival and logophoric
phenomena across languages.
Hirose gives examples of two uses of zibun, perspectival and logophoric. The logophoric
involves access to consciousness, the perspectival does not; his term for the latter is “point of
view.” Hirose says that in the logophoric example (a) Kazuo is aware that he is shy, because he
says so. On other other hand in example (b), Kazuo does not have to be aware that the book he
lost is the one he borrowed from his friend. This is shown by the fact that (c) is not contradic-
tory (2000:1646). The examples are reproduced with Hirose’s abbreviations and translations.
TOP = topic, COP = copula, QUOT = quotative, STAT = stative, NOM = nominative case,
ACC = Accusative case, NEG = negation.
a. Kazuo wa zibun wa tereya da to itteiru
K. TOP self TOP shy.person COP QUOT say-STAT
Kazuoi says that hei is shy.
b. Kazuo wa zibun ga tomodati karita hon o nakusit
K. TOP self NOM friend from borrowed book ACC lost
Kazuoi lost a book that hei borrowed from a friend.
c. Kazuo wa zibun ga tomodati karita hon o nakusita ga, sono
K. TOP self NOM friend from borrowed book ACC lost but that
hon ga tomodati kara karita mono da to wa kizuite-it-nai. book NOM friend from
borrowed thing COP QUOT TOP realize-STAT-NEG
Kazuoi lost a book that hei borrowed from a friend but he has not realized that the
book is the one he borrowed from a friend.
Hirose says that “zibun” in examples like (b) and (c) conveys “point of view,” whereas in
(a) “zibun” is logophoric.
7.6 Formalizing the interpretation of subjectivity 175
In (29a) the deictic “three weeks ago” is anchored to the time of speech; there
is no subjectivity. But (29b–c) suggest the perspective of Mary, the sentence
subject, with deictics anchored to a past time.
The rather delicate interpretation of perspective can be partially accounted
for by compositional rules. Reanchored deictics can be recognized by rules
which look at the tense and deictic adverbial in a clause. If the two are not in
accord – for instance, a past tense and Speech-Time-oriented deictic – and there
is an appropriate Responsible Source, then the deictic is perspectival. Locally
Free Reflexives (LFRs) could in principle be recognized by a rule with access
to the principles of the Binding Theory. If a reflexive has no Binding Theory
antecedent, it is an LFR. However, it need not be perspectival: recall that LFRs
have other functions, noted in Chapter 6. I will not state a compositional rule
for perspectival LFRs.
The list is not complete but it gives a sense of the many and varied forms
involved. Among the forms ignored here are conditionals and counter-factives;
the subjunctive; conjunctions such as yet, anyway; verbs and PPs with a deictic
component such as come and go, toward and away from. Forms of comparison
and evaluation also indicate subjectivity (Hunston & Thompson 2000); since
they are conveyed lexically they are beyond the scope of this discussion.
The interpretation of subjectivity requires that a Responsible Source be iden-
tified. To account for subjectivity in Discourse Representation Theory, I write a
set of construction rules that introduce the Responsible Source as a conceptual
role. The rules associate this role with the appropriate individual entity, on the
one hand, and with a sub-structure of the representation on the other. The output
of the rule is encoded in the Discourse Representation Structure (DRS).
The construction rules recognize as Responsible Source either the Author
or the Subject, a sentient being in the text situation. When the Author entity
is needed, a special discourse entity is constructed by the rule. The Subject is
usually the subject of a sentence, but may also be the direct object or the object
of a preposition. In clauses with subjective forms the rules look for NPs that
have the feature [+human] in appropriate syntactic relation as candidates for
Subject. Most of the features of subjectivity are needed anyway in a grammar
of English, e.g. the noun feature [+human]; the verb classes of communication,
mental state, and perception; pronoun forms; modals; tense, etc.
Subordinate structures in a DRS model the relation between the Responsible
Source and the relevant material. The information in the scope of a subjective
form appears in a sub-DRS. This correctly identifies subjectively introduced
information, and provides a special status for it. The approach is consistent
with treatments of propositional attitude verbs and modality in Discourse Rep-
resentation Theory since the mid 1980s by Kamp (1985), Roberts (1987), and
7.6 Formalizing the interpretation of subjectivity 177
Frank & Kamp (1997). I also draw on the DR Theory account of logophoricity
in Stirling (1993). All of these analyses use subordination: material in the scope
of mental state verbs, modal operators, and other forms of subjectivity appears
as a sub-DRS. The mental space theory of Fauconnier (1985) takes essentially
the same approach.
Thus, for instance, a mental state verb will trigger a sub-DRS. The subject
of the verb is identified with the role of Responsible Source. This appears as a
condition in the DRS. The information in the complement of the verb is in a
sub-DRS that is associated with the Responsible Source.
Before introducing the compositional rules, I give two examples of DRSs
with expressions of subjectivity. The first DRS interprets a sentence with the
mental state verb believe and a complement clause: “Mary believes that John
won the race.” By rule, the main clause subject is interpreted as Subject and
Responsible Source; the resulting condition is entered in the DRS (lines 3, 4).
The contents of the belief appear in a sub-DRS associated with the verb. In
a belief sentence like this, individuals are independent of the sub-DRS. The
individual “John” therefore appears at the top of the DRS and as a discourse
referent a in the sub-DRS. In the sub-DRS a is identified with John as a con-
dition (line 6). The DRSs are radically simplified, including only the relevant
information.
x y e
1. x = Mary
2. y = John
3. x = Subject
4. x = RS
5. e: believe, x . . .
RS
a b e’
6. a = y
7. b = the race
8. e’: win (a,b)
In some other types of subjectivity all the individuals within the scope of the
subjective form are independently posited and thus appear at the top of the
DRS.
178 Subjectivity in texts
The next DRS interprets a sentence with a modal, for which the Author (A)
is Responsible Source (RS). The Author is introduced as a discourse entity at
the top of the DRS, and is interpreted as RS (lines 2 and 3).
x e A y
1. x = Mary
2. A = Author
3. A = RS
4. y = the race
5. e : Mary may. . .
RS may
a b e’
6. a = x
7. b = y
8. e’: win (a,b)
The material within the scope of the modal is within the sub-DRS, as in the pre-
vious example. However in this case both individuals in the sub-DRS, “Mary”
and “the race,” are posited independent of the modal operator. The formal inter-
pretation of the modal would also be included in a complete DRS. Additional
DRS interpretations of subjectivity will be presented in Chapter 10.
(33) Abbreviations
Animate NP picked out by rule = NPx
Referent of NPx, usually subject or experiencer = Subject
Speaker/Author = Author
Responsible Source = RS
Ability, obligation modal = Modc
Communication verb or nominal = V/Ncom
Evidential evaluative modal, verb, adverb, adjective V/Mod/Adj/Adve
Mental State Verb or nominal = V/Nme
Perception verb or nominal = V/Npe
The rules are listed below. Each rule has 3 parts: (a) a verbal statement of the
surface structure that the rule recognizes, with examples in italics; (b) the formal
rule itself – X, Y indicate optional additional material that is not relevant to a
rule; (c) a statement of the interpretation the rule makes.
Rule 5: ModalE
(a) V/Modale not in the scope of V/NCOM ; entity Author; Author = RS
The earth may be flat. Mary may be very clever. Mary may think that she
is clever.
(b) S[. . . NP V/Nm . . .] → Author; Author = RS (S)
(c) Rule 5 introduces the entity Author, and interprets Author as RS for the
sentence. The rule doesn’t need to know whether there is a potential Sub-
ject in the clause.
Rule 6: V/Modc
(a) NPx sentient being, subj verb/NP, Modalc, Subject = RS
John could not see the ship on the horizon. RS: John
(b) S[. . . NPx Modc[VP]] → (Modc(VP))
(c) Rule 6 interprets the modal as modifying the VP. Such modals are internal,
with no RS and without intertriggering a sub-DRS.
Rule 7: Evaluative/Evidential + Experiencer
(a) Subject (NPx), PP obj of V/Adje; Subject = RS
It seemed to John that Mary had left. That Mary left was surprising to
John.
It seemed an anomaly to John.
(b) S[NP . . . Adj/Ve. X PP[to NPx]] (Y) → NPx = Subject; RS = Subject
(S)
(c) Rule 7 interprets the NPx of a to-PP as experiencer subject and RS in the
context of an evaluative or evidential predicate.
Rule 8: Evaluative/Evidential
(a) Adj/Vex; no experiencer subject or PP; Author = RS
It is evident that the earth is flat. Evidently, the earth is flat.
(b) S[NP . . . Adj/Ve . . .] → Author; Author = RS (S)
(c) Rule 8 introduces the entity Author, and interprets Author as RS for the
sentence.
Rule 9: Evaluative/Evidential Adverbial
(a) Adverbe; entity Author; Author = RS
Obviously, the earth is flat.
(b) S[{Adve} NP {Adve} vp[X . . .] {Adve}] → Author; Author = RS (S)
(c) Rule 9 introduces the entity Author, and interprets Author as RS for the
sentence. The braces give the three main positions for adverbs of this class:
initial position; before the VP; final position. Only one position is filled,
so the braces mean “choose one.”
Rule 10: Contextually Licensed V/Mode, No Candidate NPx for Subject
(a) In the scope of V/Nm e in the context.
Darwin believed in the postulate of “blending inheritance.” It was
clear that the mother’s and father’s characteristics fused in their
offspring.
182 Subjectivity in texts
(5), (14), and (23) James Joyce. “The Dead.” In Dubliners, 1916; reprinted London:
Penguin Books, 1982, pp. 179, 182, 177.
(7) Alan Ehrenhalt, Hijacking the rulebook. New York Times, December 20, 1998.
(10a) Jim Collins. How it works. US Airways Magazine, Attaché, May 2001.
(10b), (12a) and (19) Jared Diamond. A tale of two reputations. Natural History, Febru-
ary 2001.
(10c) Peter Robinson, A Necessary End. New York: Avon Books, 1989, p. 181.
(11a) Margaret Medley, The Chinese Potter. London: Phaidon, 1989, Ch. 5.
(11b) Robert Mosbacher, Cheap oil’s tough bargains. New York Times, March 13, 2000.
(12b) Douglas Chadwick, Listening to humpbacks. National Geographic, June 1999.
(12c) and (15) Peter Beinart, The pride of the cities. New Republic, June 1997.
(16a) and (17) Kosovo strategy splitting NATO. New York Times, May 1999.
(16b) John Scott & Tony Pawson, Cell communication. Scientific American, June 2000.
(19) David Fromkin, A Peace to End All Peace, New York: Henry Holt, 1989, p. 329.
(24a) Raymond Chandler, The Long Goodbye, Boston: Houghton, 1964, Mifflin, p. 64.
(24b) J. Anthony Lukas, Common Ground, New York: Knopf, 1985, p. 149.
8 The contribution of surface
presentation
Sentences that differ in arrangement and sentence accent also differ in meaning,
although their propositional content may be the same. As Bolinger puts it,
discussing the difference between active and passive (1977:9):
The classical case is the passive voice. If truth value were the only criterion,
we would have to say that John ate the spinach and The spinach was eaten
by John are the same. They report the same event in the real world. The same
entities are present, in the same relationship . . . Linguistic meaning covers a
great deal more . . . [it] expresses, sometimes in ways that are hard to ferret
out, such things as what is the central part of the message, what our attitudes
are toward the person we are speaking to, how we feel about the reliability of
our message, how we situation ourselves in the Events we report, and many
other things.
The meanings that Bolinger talks about involve the way a text presents infor-
mation, its presentational structure.
Surface structure presentation instructs the receiver about how to organize
the information in a sentence. The sentences of a text are not undifferentiated
wholes, nor simple linear arrangements of words. I adopt the approach to pre-
sentation originally put forth by Prague School linguists and further developed
in recent years. This approach uses the notions of communicative dynamism,
topic–comment, and focus–background, to understand the internal organization
of sentences and how they are deployed in texts. Although “topic” is notori-
ously difficult, I hope to show that it contributes an important dimension to the
analysis of sentences and texts.
The writer’s choices of how to present material are influenced by assessment
of what is accessible to the receiver. The familiarity status of information is
a key factor. This notion was introduced in Chapter 6, where it was shown
that the forms of referring expressions used in a text tend to correlate with
familiarity of the referent. Familiarity status concerns whether information is
discourse-old or discourse-new, hearer-old or hearer-new. What is new to the
discourse needn’t be new to the hearer; but discourse-old is also hearer-old.
185
186 The contribution of surface presentation
1. The Prague School is a general term referring to a group of linguists in Central Europe who
worked in the structuralist tradition, first in the 1930s and early 1940s, later in the 1960s
and 1970s. Their ideas are enjoying something of a resurgence; see Hajičová et al. (1995),
Hajičová et al. (1998). The notion of topic and comment can be traced to Henri Weil, a French
classical scholar who published in 1840, to German scholars of the late nineteenth century, and
to Mathesius; see Firbas (1974) for discussion.
The approach presented here owes a great deal to the latter-day Prague School but is not
identical with it. I recognize both topic and focus phrases in most sentences, whereas the
traditional partition consists of focus and background.
188 The contribution of surface presentation
movement rules here.2 When a phrase is displaced to the end of the sentence
it becomes the focus phrase and receives the sentence accent, by the “ordering
principle” of Hajicová and Sgall (1987). Alternatively, another phrase may be
highlighted with a contrastive accent.
In the spoken language, prosody is an important cue to the topic and focus
phrases of a sentence. The intonation center, or sentence accent, occurs canon-
ically on the rightmost stressable unit of the sentence, the focus phrase.3 The
scope of the accent is indeterminate: it may be limited to a single phrase or
extend to larger constituents. I assume that prosodic structure is a reflex of
semantic and pragmatic information (cf. Gussenhoven 1983, Erteschik-Shir
1997, Steedman 2000, and many others). Prosody will not be discussed, since
this study is devoted to written texts.
The status of information as more or less familiar plays an important role
in presentation. The familiarity of a referent is often coded by morphology:
pronouns tend to have referents that are familiar and definite NPs to have iden-
tifiable referents. For discourse reasons a definite NP may be used for a referent
that is already familiar, as noted in Chapter 6.
The notions of topic and comment, focus and background, represent different
partitions of a sentence. Topic–comment recognizes a topic referent, what the
sentence is about; the rest of the sentence is comment. The focus–background
partition distinguishes the main contribution of a sentence in a focus phrase,
and the rest of the sentence functions as background for that focus. To cover the
full range of possibilities, both are needed. The apparent contradiction between
them is resolved with dual partitioning. I discuss each of these matters in turn.
2. Movement rules are implied by the notion of a canonical sentence order. Grammatical rules
that move phrases to non-canonical positions are essential to the approach of transformational
generative grammar.
3. The typical pitch contour of sentence accent is high and falling, written H∗ +L in Pierrehumbert’s
(1980) notation (an A accent in Bolinger’s system, 1972). Many sentences have a secondary
intonation peak, typically with a rising pitch contour, written L+H∗ (Bolinger’s B accent).
These notational systems do not bear on the question of how stress and intonation relate to the
syntactic and semantic components of the grammar.
8.2 The topic–comment partition 189
position, e.g. Hungarian and Mandarin Chinese; others have topic morphology,
e.g. Japanese and Korean.4 Topics in such languages may differ from topics in
English.
Subsequent sections discuss the notion of aboutness (8.2.1); the position of
topic phrases in sentences (8.2.2); sentences without topics (8.2.3); different
notions of topic (8.2.4); and determining sentence topic in texts (8.2.5).
The notion of aboutness organizes the information conveyed by a sentence.
We understand that a sentence says something about X, the topic referent. Thus
the topic determines how the truth of a sentence is assessed: we ask “Is it true
of X[topic] that Y?” The topic phrase is canonically the subject of a sentence,
as in (1):
(1) A. Beavers build dams.
B. Sue visited her cousin last week.
People tend to understand (1a) as saying something about the class of beavers
and (1b) as saying something about Sue, unless there is information to the
contrary.
The topic–comment partition mirrors the classic division of a sentence into
“subject” and “predicate,” also known as “theme” and “rheme.” The subject and
predicate are distinct syntactic constituents in traditional accounts. The division
determines interpretation: a sentence makes a comment about the subject ref-
erent, and the comment is expressed by the predicate. The topic of a sentence
indicates how the information it conveys should be added to the developing
mental model of the discourse.
The context of a sentence usually points to a particular topic interpretation.
The pairs in (2) present different contexts for the second sentence; in both
“Mary” is topic, the subject of immediate concern.
(2) a. i. What did Mary wear?
ii. Mary/she was wearing an enormous hat.
b. i. I saw Mary yesterday at the movies.
ii. Mary/she was wearing an enormous hat.
Questions and answers like (2a) are often used to demonstrate sentence topics.
The felicity of this pair contrasts with another in which Mary is not topic of the
second sentence, for instance a cleft sentence like “It was MARY who wore an
enormous hat.”
4. Studies show that languages with syntactic topics differ substantially from those without them;
cf. Li & Thompson (1976), Kiss (1986), Portner & Yabushita (1998), Vallduvı́ & Vilkuna (1998),
etc.
190 The contribution of surface presentation
Paraphrase can test and support the intuition that a given phrase is topic. With
paraphrase tests, one recasts a sentence with an explicit introductory phrase
and the putative topic phrase (as for, speaking of ). The result is felicitous if the
phrase in question is indeed the topic. For instance, supporting the intuition that
the (ii) sentences are about Mary, one can say “As for Mary, she was wearing
an enormous hat” and “Speaking of Mary, she was wearing an enormous hat.”
Both are reasonably felicitous. Another paraphrase test uses a verb of saying, as
in “He said about Mary that she was wearing an enormous hat” (Gundel 1974,
Reinhart 1982). There are well-known difficulties with paraphrases as actual
tests for topic; they are both too weak and too strong.5 Nevertheless the tests
can be helpful in illustrating and identifying the topic of a sentence.
8.2.1 Aboutness
The intuition of aboutness is often taken as primitive. Strawson and Reinhart,
however, offer useful discussions.
The notion of aboutness explains how the information of a sentence is un-
derstood and assessed in context, according to Strawson. Aboutness relates a
sentence to a matter of concern in the context: “We do not, except in social des-
peration, direct isolated and unconnected pieces of information at each other,
but . . . intend to give or add information about what is a matter of standing
(3) a. It’s no wonder that Carter is considering withdrawing the American athletes
from the Olympic games.
b. As for the Olympic games, it’s no wonder that Carter is considering
withdrawing the American athletes from them (because they are such a
farce).
c. As for Carter, it’s no wonder that he is considering withdrawing the Amer-
ican athletes from the Olympic games (because he is such a hard-liner).
Reinhart formalizes her proposal for multiple potential topics in terms of pos-
sible pragmatic assertions. In a given context one assertion is selected from the
set.
The topic of a sentence affects truth-conditional semantic interpretation. A
definite NP triggers a presupposition of existence when it is the topic and subject
of the sentence, but not otherwise (Strawson 1964, Hajičová 1971):
Example (4a) presupposes that there is a king of France. Example (4b) has
no such presupposition, as standard tests such as denial and questioning show.
192 The contribution of surface presentation
The wide-scope reading for “at least two languages” is available for (5b) but
not for (5a). These phenomena are well known, but not always ascribed to
topicality.
Other evidence that sentence topics affect semantic interpretation comes from
work in formal semantics. In if/when sentences with adverbials of quantifica-
tion, the topic phrase determines which indefinites are bound by the adverbial
(Chierchia 1992).6 The notion of sentence topic is part of the interpretation of
quantifiers, according to Partee (1991) and Büring (1999). Topics are modeled
as a presupposed salient set of alternatives, arrived at by constructing implicit
questions by von Fintel (1994) and McNally (1998). In a study of Japanese,
Portner & Yabushita argue that topics affect semantic interpretation in comput-
ing entailments, implicature, and certain scopal phenomena (1998). Their work
is suggestive, though Japanese topics differ from English topics in more than
one way.
Sentence topics are often demonstrated with question–answer pairs. As in
(2a) above, the topic of a sentence is clear in the context of a particular question.7
The observation has been generalized as a basic organizing principle of texts.
Following this principle, one looks for the question that a sentence answers in
a given context. If no question actually appears in a text, the analyst constructs
an implicit question. For instance, van Kuppevelt uses implicit questions to
construct an interpretation “which does not differ in acceptability and coher-
ence” from a text without them (1995:116). He claims that the approach gives
an operational way of characterizing topics.
6. Chierchia (1992) integrates the treatment of NPs with the theory of generalized quantifiers. He
outlines the “proportion problem,” which concerns the scope of the quantificational determiner
in “donkey sentences” and conditionals, and the scope of quantificational adverbials in if/when
sentences.
7. The question approach to topic was used by Daneš (1974), as well as Vennemann (1975), and
others. For the latter two the topic is identified with one of the presuppositions defined by a
question.
8.2 The topic–comment partition 193
8. When subjects in experiments hear a series – of digits, syllables, words, a long sentence or
series of sentences – they tend to remember the material that begins and ends the series (Neisser
1967:222).
Brennan (1995) studied people’s choice of referential expressions. She found that speakers
mentioned entities as full NPs in subject position before referring to them with pronouns.
New entities tended to be introduced as full NP objects. Experimental subjects tended to use
pronouns to express the most salient entity in a scene. Brennan’s study was done in the context
of Centering Theory (see Chapter 6). Subjects’ behavior was taken as evidence for a Centering
Theory account of pronoun use, rather than a simple knowledge-based strategy. The latter would
predict that pronouns be used for all familiar entities.
Linguists who worked with this and related pragmatic notions include Firbas (1964), Hockett
(1958), Strawson (1964), Halliday (1967), Kuno (1972), Dahl (1974), Hajičová (1971), Daneš
(1974), Reinhart (1982), Davison (1984), Fries (1983), Vallduvı́ (1992), Lambrecht (1995),
Vallduvı́ & Engdahl (1996), and Erteschik-Shir (1997).
9. Cross-linguistic studies of voice are concerned with variations in such constructions as active
and passive, middle, anti-passive, inverse. Klaiman (1991) identifies other approaches to voice.
“Posttraditional linguistics” takes voice as being concerned with the mapping from logical to
grammatical structure, and not associated with participants or viewpoint. For Philippine and
Mayan languages there are “pragmatic voice” alternations which signal assignment among
nominals of a certain pragmatic status.
194 The contribution of surface presentation
is salient, the event or its result is prominent. The active–passive, and other
alternations, change pragmatic perspective, as Givón (1993) puts it. The per-
spective varies according to what aspects of a situation – cause, process, and
result – are prominent in a sentence. This view is reminiscent of Grimshaw’s
(1990) notion of aspectual prominence, and is different from the perspectival
notion of subjectivity discussed in Chapter 7.
There is a strong tendency for topic and subject to coincide in texts as well as
single sentences. The empirical correlation will be discussed and examplified
in Chapter 10. But the topic phrase is not always the sentence subject. To
show this, we need a context that clearly determines a given phrase as topic.
Example (6) illustrates: note the third clause of B’s answer. The example is
from Erteschik-Shir (1997):
(6) A. So tell me about the earth. What do you know about the earth?
B. It’s round, it’s a planet, the moon goes around it.
In the last clause of B’s answer, the topic phrase is the pronoun object of the
preposition.
The topic referent must be an individual of some kind: an entity or a concept.
In the case of sentential subjects, the referent is the event, state, or other entity
expressed by the subject clause. Sentences with quantified subject phrases have
no direct topic referent. In such cases, the topic is the domain of quantification,
the class referred to in the quantified phrase. For instance:
(7) a. All the humpbacks in a given region sing the same song, which is constantly
evolving.
b. No person could survive without precise signalling in cells.
The topic referent in (7a) is the class “humpbacks in a given region,” the topic
referent of (7b) is the class of “persons,” and so on.
Topic referents tend to be familiar or readily inferrable from the discourse
context. The topic referent, however, needn’t be familiar. Example (8) illus-
trates: the referent is identified by his connection to the speaker and is unknown
otherwise. The example is based on Prince (1981):
10. The definition is a translation from Mathesius. Most definitions of theme are derivable from
this one, according to Fries (1983).
8.2 The topic–comment partition 197
11. Topics in conversation can be derived, according to Keenan & Schieffelin. They claim that any
discourse has a single proposition which represents the discourse topic (1976:338). The listener
establishes the discourse topic by reconstructing the semantic relations between referents.
Chafe argues that discourse topics are aggregates of semiactive information that segment a
conversation into larger chunks than intonation units (1994:135).
For written texts, van Dijk suggests that a discourse topic proposition can be constructed
for the whole (1972:37). His account is based on an analysis of the propositions that underlie
the text. The result is a complex proposition that is entailed by the joint set of propositions
of the text. Van Dijk’s approach has been influential in text studies that focus on memory and
cognition. It is not relevant here because it departs immediately from the text in seeking the
underlying propositions. Moreover, construction of the propositional analysis is difficult at
best, as Garnham (1983) argues.
Discourse topics for several sentences at once have also been proposed. For instance, Asher &
Lascarides (1998) present the following sentence sequence:
I’ve just arrived. The camel is outside.
To make sense of the pair, Asher & Lascarides suggest that the receiver recovers the discourse
topic notion of “transportation,” which correctly links the sentences.
12. One type of limited topic is the “backward-looking center or Cb” of Centering Theory: see
the discussion in Section 6.4. The backward-looking center is defined in terms of grammatical
relations and pronouns. In many ways the Cb is a return to the two-factor notion of theme
proposed by Mathesius. Another limited topic is the operationally defined “Link” of Vallduvı́ &
Engdahl (1996).
198 The contribution of surface presentation
be the subject of a sentence in discourse, and the topic referent may be new.
Given these difficulties, the question arises as to whether the topic of a sentence
can be reliably identified. Both Smith (1991) and Vallduvı́ (1992) argue that
there is no structural or “operational” test for topic. I think that this is correct.
Yet I am committed to the position that intuitions about sentence topic are
mostly reliable, and that sentence topics have semantic and pragmatic effects
in discourse.
How then does one decide on the topic phrase of a sentence in the context
of other sentences? I suggest that the intuition of topic is based on a set of
cues. Subject position is the default; it may be overridden by other cues in the
sentence and its context. There is the possibility of tension between sentential
and discourse factors. Cues may reinforce each other, or one cue may override.
Occasionally cues conflict and the intuition of aboutness is weak. In actual texts
the topic phrase of a sentence is usually the subject phrase, as noted above.
Within a sentence, the subject position is salient because of its linear position,
the grammatical relation of subject, and the typical familiarity status. Also
relevant are accent and morphology; topic phrases do not bear sentence accent
except in the marked case of contrastive topics. Topic referents tend to be
familiar, and familiar referents tend to be coded with pronouns. Thematic role
is another factor. Agent and experiencer arguments tend to appear in subject
position, with some exceptions, e.g. the psychological verbs surprise, amuse,
annoy, which encode the experiencer as object.
Discourse factors may also affect the intuition of aboutness. One factor is
continuity. Topic phrases maximize local or global continuity. Local continuity
identifies as topic the phrase that is coreferential with an immediately preceding
topic phrase.13 Global continuity identifies a topic phrase that is coreferential
with other topic phrases in the context. Syntactic parallels in sentence structure,
and changes of direction in the text, are also relevant.
In context, and in sentences that depart from the canonical S-V-O structure,
these factors may not converge. Therefore they must be considered as potentially
separate cues to the topic of a sentence. Criteria for sentence topics are listed
in (12):
13. Local continuity is most highly ranked in Centering Theory. Other “strategies” are recognized
but considered less preferable, as Haihua Pan has pointed out to me.
8.2 The topic–comment partition 199
NPs with sentence accent or other focus cues are not candidates for topic. The
criteria usually function together, but in some cases they clash, as we will see.
When a sentence has more than one clause, the clauses are analyzed sequen-
tially in left-to-right order. This treatment is justified in Kameyama (1998); the
alternative is to take the main clause first.
In applying the criteria, the natural strategy is an additive one: the phrase to
which the largest number of these criteria applies is the topic. The topic phrase
must be integrated into the organization of the whole sentence. Recall that every
sentence has a focus phrase, canonically in the predicate.
The criteria and principles are applied to a text fragment in (13), part of it
already presented in Chapter 5. Topic phrases are italicized. The immediately
preceding sentence concerns a large project in Boston; the definite NP in S1
refers to working tunnels in that project. I give in (14) the cues used for deter-
mining each sentence topic; the letters before each cue refer back to the list of
criteria in (12).
(13) 1 In some places the tunnels are 120 feet deep. 2 In some particularly delicate
places the road-work passes within just a few feet of skyscraper founda-
tions or beneath construction projects. 3 The first two frequently asked ques-
tions on the project’s official Website are “What are you building?” and “Are
you nuts?” 4 Surprisingly, tunnels are among the most ancient engineering
feats. 5 The earliest [tunnels] were very likely extensions of prehistoric
cave dwellings. 6 The Babylonians, in the twenty-second century BC, built a
masonry tunnel beneath the Euphrates River that connected the royal palace
with a major temple. 7 The Egyptians, using copper-bladed saws, excavated
long passageways and intricate rooms inside soft-rock cliffs. 8 The Romans
built an elaborate network of above- and below-ground acqueducts to carry
water.
S7: (a) subject; (c) agent; (g) lexically related context (earliest); (h) parallel
S8: (a) subject; (c) agent; (g) lexically related context (earliest); (h) parallel
The topic phrases are all subjects; there are no non-canonical syntactic struc-
tures. The object NPs are the focus phrases in the last three sentences:
“a masonry tunnel,” “long passageways and intricate rooms,” “an elaborate
network.”14 These phrases pertain to the theme of the passage and might be
taken as topics. But topic–focus organization precludes such an interpretation:
the object NPs are focus phrases. The semantic notion of Primary Referent
applies to these NPs: they are the Primary Referents in their clauses. Each is
the result of the event expressed in the sentence. There is an interesting tension
in the passage between topical and semantic progression.
Although sentence topics can usually be identified, there are some un-
clear cases. They arise when the criteria for topics result in a clash. For
instance, consider clause 2b in the familiar fragment of (15); the first four
clauses are familiar from previous examples. Clause 2b has pronouns as subject
(“she”) and object (“it”), both are coreferential with material in the immediate
context.
(15) 1a She put on her apron, took a lump of clay from the bin and weighed off
enough for a small vase. 2a The clay was too wet, b so she wedged it with a
flat concrete tray, c which absorbed the excess moisture.
The subject pronoun of clause 2b realizes the agent role, and is in subject
position, so by the additive strategy “she” would be the topic phrase. Now
consider the two continuity principles. By local continuity, we take the object
pronoun “it” as topic because its referent is topic of the previous clause. The
global continuity principle looks at other sentences in the passage. S3 and S4
have “she” as topic phrase, so by global continuity “she” would be topic in S2b.
The sentence organization does not resolve the problem: the verb “wedge” is
the focused phrase. The most satisfactory analysis is simply to say that in clause
2b both pronouns are part of the background; see the next section below. In my
judgment the uncertainty of cases like this does not compromise the many clear
cases of sentence topics and the importance of the notion.
The cues to sentence topic are pragmatic in nature. Coreferentiality and lex-
ical relatedness are probably the most important, and neither can be stated in
a construction rule of Discourse Representation Theory. The other cues are
difficult to formalize as well. Therefore I do not give construction rules for
topic or presentational progression. I have argued that sentence topic is needed
for conceptual and truth-conditional calculations within the DRS; and for fur-
ther pragmatic interpretation. I assume that topic information must be part
of enriched Discourse Representation Structures that allow further pragmatic
interpretation.15
15. Recognizing sentence topics in a DRS does not necessarily provide for sentence topics as an
organizing factor of information in the common ground, or context set. Organizing potential is
one of Reinhart’s arguments for aboutness, and a feature of Vallduvı́ & Engdahl’s procedural
account of Links. I do not wish to make the stringent requirement that the context set be
organized in any particular way. Rather, I suggest that organization by topics is a potential
feature of organization in memory. It may be best not to limit information access, as Portner &
Yabushita (1998) point out. People are able to organize large amounts of information in multiple
ways, according to what question is being answered or what kind of task is involved. For
instance, research on word access shows that people can search their word memory by first
sound, alphabetically by first letter, according to taxonomic meaning, functional meaning, etc.
(Forster 1979). In the current theory the information that makes up the context set is structured
only in DRS terms.
16. There is an extensive literature on focus and sentence accent, especially contrastive focus.
Semantic analyses of focus operators are given in Rooth (1992) and Krifka (1991). Although
they differ in some respect, they agree on the points that I rely on here. See also Horn (1991),
Fauconnier (1985), and Bosch & van der Sandt (1999).
Stress and intonational highlighting mark focus in cases where the topic–focus articulation
cannot be read off the syntax; they also mark strong contrast or exhaustiveness.
202 The contribution of surface presentation
The accented NP is the focus in (16b); the VP predicate is the focus in (16c);
the entire sentence is focused in (16d). I use the terms “argument focus” and
“predicate focus” for the first two cases and the term “all-focus” for the third
(from Vallduvı́ 1992, Lambrecht 1994). Sentence (16d), which is all-focus, is
a thetic sentence. The notion of focus is a relational one, internal to a given
sentence. On the argument focus interpretation of (16b), for instance, dams is
the focus relative to the other information in the sentence.
Different focus interpretations arise in different contexts. The argument focus
reading of (16b) is natural in a discussion of what beavers build, or in answer
to a question about the building habits of beavers. The predicate focus reading
would be natural if one were discussing what beavers do. For the sentence
focus reading imagine the sentence uttered “out of the blue,” perhaps by a child
imparting a newly learned fact.
The focus of a sentence is its contribution to a discourse. The focus is a
matter of presentation in that it “reflects the speaker’s decision as to where the
main burden of the message lies” (Halliday 1967:204). The speaker presents
the focused material as relating to the background in the sentence. Standard
examples of focus–background structures in the literature are question–answer
pairs, where the question clearly determines a particular interpretation. Example
(17) is from Prince (1986):
The question provides the background for the answer, making it clear that the
focused phrase provides the contribution to the discourse. In the context of
the question the background is shared knowledge. Typically, the background
represents what is salient or inferrable in the discourse at the time of utterance,
or what the speaker assumes to be so.
This notion of focus should not be confused with other meanings of the term.
It is used for “center of attention” in psychology, computational linguistics, and
8.3 The Focus–Background partition 203
In (19a) the defeat has taken place: it is presupposed, part of the background.
Example (19b) has no such presupposition: the sentence is compatible with
a situation in which we were not defeated. The difference follows from their
background–focus structure, according to Hajičová & Sgall (1987). In (a) “our
defeat” is part of the background, whereas in (b) it is the focus phrase. There
17. If one assumes a three-valued logic, (18b) would have no truth value, as Neil Smith points out
(p.c.).
204 The contribution of surface presentation
is some difference of opinion about the source of these intuitions of truth and
falsity.
The semantic consequences of background–focus are further adduced by
Partee (1991). Partee relates the distinction to tripartite semantic structures
that represent the contribution of quantifiers and other operators to a sentence.
The tripartite structure consists of a Restrictor, Nuclear Scope, and Operator.
The Operator applies to the Nuclear Scope in the context provided by the
Restrictor. The Restrictor and Nuclear Scope in such structures correspond to
the background–focus distinction. The focused phrase of a sentence functions
as Nuclear Scope, and the background functions as Restrictor. This and other
interactions of focus and semantics are addressed in Hajičová, Partee & Sgall
(1998).
Focused material need not convey information that is new in familiarity status
to the discourse, or to the receiver. What is essential is that the focus add to the
receiver’s apprehension of the information, relative to the rest of the sentence.
The fragment (20) illustrates; consider the status of “sedimentation,” the focus
phrase in the last sentence (Daneš 1974:111):
The focus phrase “sedimentation,” far from being new, is fully recoverable
from the context, as Daneš notes. It has a unique function in this sentence,
however.
Examples of another kind also show that focused information need not be
new to the discourse; (21) is from Lambrecht (1994), (22) from Gundel (1999).
In each case the relevant example is B’s answer to A’s question:
(21) A. Where did Sami go last night, to the movies or to the restaurant?
B. Hei /Sami went to F [the restaurant ].
(22) A. Who called?
B. Pati said F [she i ] called.
Reference to the focus phrase referent appears in the same sentence (22), or
in the preceding question (21), so that it cannot be regarded as new. The focus
phrases supply information that completes the background open propositions,
which are [– called] and [Sam went to –]. Thus, focus–background is a sentence-
internal relation established for a particular sentence.
The main cues to focus are sentence accent and linear or syntactic posi-
tion. Position is particularly important in writing, where the only other cue is
8.3 The Focus–Background partition 205
The example is from Lambrecht, who comments that Holmes needn’t have
had alternative suspects in mind to utter the sentence (1994:287). The focus
is emphatic, adding strength to informational focus, but does not change the
interpretation of a sentence.
to the other alternatives (Krifka 1991, Rooth 1992). This type of interpretation
is set out schematically in (28):
(28) Focus structure of Sue danced with BILL
Background: Sue danced with –
Focus: Bill
Focus operator: strong stress
Alternatives: everyone, Mats, Manfred, Bill, etc.
Focalizing particles such as even, only, also, convey contrastive focus. These
particles trigger and contribute to contrastive interpretation; strong stress is not
needed in their presence. Different particles relate focus and background to
their alternatives in a particular way. For instance, only conveys that there is no
relevant alternative to which the background applies. Even conveys that there
are alternatives to the focused choice which are more probable, more expected,
than the one that actually appears.
Focus that involves clear alternatives is often exhaustive, or “identificational,”
according to Kiss: “Identificational focus . . . identifies the exhaustive subset
of the set [of potential candidates] for which the predicate phrase holds”
(1998:245). Kiss contrasts this type of focus with information focus, which
every sentence conveys. Information focus merely marks the nonpresupposed
nature of the information it carries, according to Kiss.18 By this criterion, some
sentences with contrastive meaning do not have identificational focus. For in-
stance, “Sue danced with BILL” does not necessarily mean that Sue danced with
no person other than Bill. In contrastive contexts, however, focus constituents
express identificational focus in English, according to Cohan (2001).
Phrases with strong stress tend to be focus phrases. Topic phrases, however,
may also be contrastive. The alternatives are often explicitly parallel, as in (29)
from Vallduvı́ & Engdahl (1996):
(29) Where can I find the cutlery?
a. the forks are in the CUPBOARD . . .
b. but I left the knives in the DRAWER.
Contrastive topics like these have the aboutness property, rather than the
semantic properties of focus phrases (Lambrecht 1994:291).
18. In Hungarian informational and identificational focus phrases are associated with different
structural positions. Kiss lists six differences between the two kinds of focus. The first is given
in the text. The next two differences are these: (2) the type of constituent that can function
as information focus is not restricted, but certain types of constituents cannot function as
identificational focus; (3) information focus does not, but identificational focus does, take
scope. The other differences are more technical (1998:248).
208 The contribution of surface presentation
(30) Contrast
a. Chimpanzees engage in what might be called “trickle-down” provisioning
of meat to females and their offspring. Only those females and their young
who are in the vicinity of the killsite when the meat is being devoured will
have a chance of gaining access to it.
b. There is another difference between intelligence and other traits. Height
and weight and speed and strength and even conversational fluency are
real things: there’s no doubt about what’s being measured. Intelligence is
a much murkier concept.
Analyzing this sentence into Focus and Ground, the discontinuous material
[“the president – chocolate”] is the Ground; the Focus phrase is “hates.” Within
the Ground, “the president” is Link, “chocolate” is Tail. The Link functions
as an instruction for updating the common ground, the locus of update “the
president,” with a further condition specified by the Tail (Vallduvı́ & Engdahl
1996:468–70).
8.4 Dual partitioning: representation of topic and focus 211
Simple intransitive sentences (e.g. “The girl fell”) are exhaustively partitioned
by Topic and Focus; others have a Link as well. All-focus, thetic sentences have
no Ground.
How does presentational structure relate to grammar and to the representation
of discourse? It is clear that presentational structure interacts with semantic
as well as pragmatic interpretation. Some theories have a level of syntactic
structure from which the semantic effects of focus are derived, with some
underspecification, as in the dependency grammar of Hajičová & Sgall (1987).
Erteschik-Shir (1997) proposes an informational level of grammar that affects
semantics and phonology. Combinatory Categorial Grammar has a level of
information structure which includes syntactic and prosodic information; in this
architecture there is no distinct level of surface syntax (Steedman 2000:126).
Others argue that a pragmatic component deals with the “information structure”
of topic and focus (Vallduvı́ 1992, Lambrecht 1994).
Since focus is associated with semantic operators, including negation, it is
directly relevant to truth-conditional representation. Some evidence is cited
19. In fact, the treatment of unstressed pronouns is problematic in this account. Vallduvı́ & Engdahl
(1996) assimilate them to null pronouns, treating both types as a single class. Although this
has a certain appeal for a general, cross-linguistic account, I do not think that it is correct for
English.
212 The contribution of surface presentation
above; see also Hajičová, Partee, & Sgall (1998). Rules and representations for
focus are beyond the scope of this work.
8.5 Conclusion
The notions of topic and focus organize the information within a sentence. The
topic phrase of a sentence gives the referent that the sentence is about; the
focus phrase gives the main contribution of the sentence to a discourse. Dual
patterning is needed to account for the full range of cases.
The familiarity status of information is a key factor in presentation, both
within and across sentences. Within the sentence, familiar information tends to
appear first; and topic referents tend to be familiar. Focus phrases may convey
informational, emphatic, or contrastive information.
In the next chapter I look at surface presentational factors in non-canonical
sentences, and discuss whether and how to represent them in Discourse Rep-
resentation Theory. The account of presentational progression is developed
further in Chapter 10.
Canonical sentences furnish the background for variation. I consider here struc-
tures that play off this background with different word orders and syntactic
structures. Non-canonical structures have special force, because of their fea-
tures and because they depart from the basic case. Writers choose structures. I
assume that choice is based on assessment, not necessarily conscious, of how
a structure affects interpretation in a specific context.
Sentence-internally, non-canonical structures highlight or downplay the
material in certain positions. Syntax may enhance connectedness between sen-
tences by placing information that is familiar to a discourse first in a sentence. A
given structure may allow or block a topic relation with the following sentence.
Changes in direction may be conveyed by sentences that lack such connection,
and by breaks in the syntactic pattern. Thus syntactic patterning affects the
organization and progression of discourse passages.
This chapter concentrates on non-canonical structures that affect topic and
sentence connectedness, the main factors of presentational progression. I draw
on discussions in the literature of a variety of constructions. Together they give
a sense of the different tools that the language makes available. I will also look
briefly at multi-clause sentences, and will discuss paragraphs as text units.
The interpretations involve inference. Semantic presuppositions are close to
the linguistic forms: they are triggered by particular structures, such as cleft
sentences and temporal clauses; and by particular forms such as the focus
particles “only” and “even.” Pragmatic presuppositions of familiarity status
and linking inferences depend on context, world knowledge, and convention.
Topics are determined by a combination of cues including syntactic position,
lack of sentence accent, and coreference. Most of these cues are pragmatic in
nature.
Section 9.1 introduces non-canonical constructions; 9.2 discusses non-
canonical constructions with arguments; 9.3 discusses adjunct preposing; 9.4
considers multi-clause sentences; 9.5 discusses paragraphs; 9.6 comments on
presentational information in Discourse Representation Structure.
213
214 Non-canonical structures and presentation
foods’ ” (1997:7). Here the relation between the referents is alternate members
of the poset. Another example: “I walked into the kitchen. On the counter was
a large book.” The first sentence with “kitchen” evokes the poset “elements of
a house,” ordered by the part-of relation; the referent of the preposed phrase
“the counter” is related to this set as part-of the kitchen.
If no salient poset can be inferred, there is no linking relation.1 The non-
canonical structure of preposing depends for felicity on poset linking. If a
sentence does not have a poset link to the context, preposing cannot occur. For
instance, in “I walked into the kitchen. On the jacket was a large book,” there
is no salient or inferrable poset that relates “kitchen” and “jacket,” and the
sequence is infelicitous (Birner & Ward 1998:19–20). The notion of “poset”
linking accounts for many inferred entities in the literature. I will use “poset link-
ing” as a technical term for this type of connectedness between the sentences of
a discourse. These examples show that the term “familiar information” includes
material that is either explicitly mentioned or inferrable in the context.
For each structure considered below, I discuss how it differs from the canon-
ical pattern; its topic potential; structure-based particulars, if any; and the role
of familiarity status in its use. The examples are from texts in this study.
1. The notion of posets is due to Hirschberg (1991) and has been further developed by Ward &
Prince (1991), Birner & Ward (1998).
A partially ordered set is any set defined by a transitive partial ordering relation R, a relation
which is either reflexive and antisymmetric, or irreflexive and asymmetric (Hirschberg 1991).
Ward & Prince give as an example of the first type the relation “is-as-tall-or-taller-than”; as an
example of the second the relation “is-taller-than.” The discourse entity is related to the poset
by a ranking in which the entity represents a lower or higher value, or alternate value.
In the terminology of Birner & Ward (1998), the linguistic material that is related to the
context is the “link” and the poset that relates link and prior context is the “anchor.” The relation
between link and anchor, the “linking relation,” is always a poset relation.
216 Non-canonical structures and presentation
The derived surface subject is often the topic phrase of a sentence. In fact, the
traditional function of the passive is to present as subject a phrase that would
canonically be in object position. There are two main reasons for using the
passive construction: “a greater interest in the passive subject . . . or to facilitate
the connection of one sentence with another” (Jespersen 1924/1965:168; see
also Creider 1979, Davison 1984).
The full passives in the texts of this study all have the surface subject as topic.
In most of them the topic phrase is linked to the prior context via a related poset.
There are several types of connectedness, as the examples in (1) illustrate.
(1) a. There were protests that Freud was unworthy of even being honored by
an exhibition. A corresponding exhibition on Darwin would have been
protested only by creationists.
b. Dynamite was something new, and it gave engineers their most powerful
tool for tunneling through hillsides that couldn’t be opened by digging from
above.
c. Despite the often cavalier attitude toward teaching in college, at least physi-
cists know their physics, mathematicians know and love their mathematics,
and music is taught by musicians, not by graduates of education schools,
where the disciplines are subordinated to the study of classroom manage-
ment.
2. A recurrent question is whether the length and complexity of a phrase – known as “heaviness” –
is a factor of importance in non-canonical constructions. The heaviness of the underlying subject
does not appear to be a determining factor in the use of a passive, as the following examples
show:
The peals of laughter which followed Gabriel’s imitation of the incident were interrupted
by a resounding knock at the hall-door.
He would only make himself ridiculous by quoting poetry to them which they could not
understand.
In the first example the surface subject is long and complex; in the second the postposed material
is long and complex. They are from the same text. To determine the importance of the factor of
heaviness would require a large, corpus-based study.
Hawkins (1994) argues that heavy phrases in sentence-final position are relatively easy for
receivers to understand; postponing them to the end of a sentence may be helpful for speakers
as well: cf. Arnold et al. (2000). Thus the heaviness of a phrase might lead to the use of a
non-canonical structure which would move it toward the end of a sentence.
9.2 Argument constructions 217
Using the notion of link developed above, Birner & Ward (1998) discuss the
familiarity status of passive surface subjects and by-phrases. They propose a
familiarity status requirement couched in relative terms: the subject referent
of a passive must be at least as familiar, in context, as the referent of the by-
phrase (1998:199). This requirement accounted for all full passives found in
an extensive corpus. It also accounts for most of the passives in this study.3
Birner (1996) compared the familiarity status of the subject and by-phrase NPs
in passives in an earlier corpus-based study. In that study too she found that the
surface subject referent was always as familiar as the by-phrase in the context.
Summarizing, the surface subject of a passive tends to be the topic phrase, and
has information that is relatively familiar in the context.
Psycholinguistic experiments have often used the passive in studies of sen-
tence processing because of its clear relation to the active form and its greater
surface complexity.4 Gordon & Chan studied pronouns and full NPs in passive
and active sentences presented in short constructed contexts. They consider sur-
face structure factors and thematic roles and conclude that the passive allows
for “optimal discourse organization” by maximizing continuity based on sur-
face form and syntactic relations. The semantic factor of thematic role was less
important (1995:229). Their conclusion supports the approach of this book, in
which presentation is separated from semantics.
The short passive, without an agent, is much more common than the full
passive in spoken and written discourse. Corpus studies from 1966, 1979, and
1987 found that 80–83% of the passives were agentless (Svarthvik 1966, Givón
1979, S. Thompson 1987). Birner & Ward (1998) also found that short passives
3. There are some passives which appear to be counter-examples to Birner & Ward’s generalization.
In the example below, the surface subject information may be less familiar than the by-phrase.
The passive appears in the third sentence.
There was only one important exception, one new product, in those first fifty years: the
steamboat, first made practical by Robert Fulton in 1807. It had little impact until thirty
or forty years later. In fact, until almost the end of the nineteenth century more freight
was carried on the world’s oceans by sailing vessels than by steamships.
“Freight” is perhaps evoked in the context by “impact” but this does not seem like a salient
poset. However, “sailing vessels” is a link to the context via a poset “ships” to which both
sailing vessels and steamboats belong.
4. Psycholinguistic experiments showed that reversible passive sentences in isolation took longer
for subjects to process than actives (Gough 1965). This result was taken to mean that passives
are more complex in processing. However, processing time was reduced when passives were
presented in the context of previous mention of the subject referent of the passive (Turner &
Rommetveit 1968, Davison & Lutz 1985). When passives and actives were presented in context,
few processing differences were found by Gordon & Chan (1995).
218 Non-canonical structures and presentation
are more frequent than full passives. In the texts in this study, short passives are
also more frequent than full passives.
Existential there. In this construction the underlying subject is displaced to
the predicate with there as the surface subject and the copula as main verb. The
displaced phrase receives the sentence accent. There-sentences are all-focus,
thetic rather than categorical, and therefore have no topic phrase. Given the
lack of a topic phrase, the displaced-subject entity is the locus for presentational
progression.
Sentences of this type present new entities. As Lambrecht puts it, “the
sentence expressing the thetic proposition introduces a new element into the
discourse without linking . . . to an established topic or to some presupposed
proposition” (1994:144). Example (2) illustrates:
(2) Products made in the new factories differed from traditional products only in
that they were uniform, with fewer defects than existed in products made by
any but the top craftsmen of earlier periods.
There was only one important exception, one new product, in those first fifty
years: the steamboat, first made practical by Robert Fulton in 1807. It had
little impact until thirty or forty years later.
In this example “there” introduces the “one exception,” which is not prepared
for in the preceding text. The entity introduced by the displaced NP is the point
of the message, not the starting point (Hannay 1991:138). In addition to the
verb to be, verbs of appearance or emergence such as appear, come, exist are
found in this construction; some researchers treat sentences with the latter class
of verbs as a distinct type of construction (Birner & Ward 1998).
There is a strong requirement on familiarity status in existential there-
sentences: the entity presented must be hearer-new or discourse-new. Typically
the displaced NP in a there-sentence is indefinite. However, it need not be.
Felicitous examples with definite NPs are often cited, e.g. “There strode into
town the ugliest gunslinger alive.” In an extensive discussion, Birner & Ward
show that definite NPs can appear in there-sentences when they refer to a hearer-
new discourse entity. They suggest that the frequency of indefinites results from
the strong requirement that the referent be new (1998:120ff).
Cleft and pseudo-cleft. These constructions syntactically highlight a phrase
by extraction. The extracted, “clefted phrase” is introduced with the main verb
to be, and followed by a “cleft clause” that has a missing element, similar to
a relative clause. It-clefts have expletive it in subject position; wh-clefts, also
known as “pseudo-clefts,” have a wh-phrase as subject.
9.2 Argument constructions 219
Cleft sentences semantically presuppose the material in the cleft clause; they
cannot be directly questioned with felicity and are unaffected by question or
negation of the main clause. These are the standard tests for presupposition.
Clefts suggest a set of alternatives, and in positive sentences introduce an entity
that satisfies the predicate of the cleft clause. Canonical sentences that corre-
spond to clefts are cognitively synonymous, but do not have these semantic
properties. Cleft sentences are derived states due to the main verb to be, and
have the discourse properties of states. Wh-clefts are essentially equative, ac-
cording to Heycock & Kroch (1999). In spite of their complex surface structure,
wh-clefts (also known as pseudo-clefts) behave like canonical sentences, even
in their potential for connection between sentences.
The topic and focus of it-clefts depend on sentence accent and context. If
unaccented, the clefted phrase is often the topic phrase, as in (3a). If the clefted
phrase receives the sentence accent, it is the focus, as in (3b–c):
(3) a. The newly hatched Formica workers . . . forage for nectar and dead arthro-
pods, regurgitate food to colony members, remove wastes and excavate new
chambers. When the population becomes too large for the existing nest, it
is the 3,000 or so Formica slaves that locate another site and physically
transport the 2,000 Polyergus workers, together with eggs, larvae, pupae
and even the queen, to the new nest.
b. we sometimes use the stated intentions of dictators against them while ral-
lying world opinion. But to what end? When Stalin engineered the world-
wide peace movement in the early 1950s, or Slobodan Milosevic promises
to allow “peace-loving” Albanian refugees to return, it is our own inten-
tions and our own public opinion that these dictators are reflecting and
manipulating.
c. The truly revolutionary impact of the Information Revolution is just be-
ginning to be felt. But it is not “information” that fuels this impact. It
is not “artificial intelligence.” It is not the effect of computers and data
processing on decision-making, policymaking, or strategy.
The topic phrases in (3b–c) are these dictators and this impact; the referents of
both phrases are familiar from the context.
Two main types of it-clefts are recognized, according to whether the clefted
phrase is topic or focus. I will call them “comment-clauses” and “topic-clauses,”
following Hedberg (1990). In comment-clause clefts such as (3a), the clefted
phrase is the topic and the clause the comment. The sentence accent falls within
the cleft clause. Comment-clause clefts are often used with a backgrounding
effect in discourse, Prince (1978) notes. In topic-clause clefts like (3b–c) the
clefted phrase is the focus and receives the sentence accent; the topic phrase
220 Non-canonical structures and presentation
appears in the cleft clause. Topic-cleft sentences are natural answers to ques-
tions; they may also indicate contrast. And because the information in the cleft
clause of a topic-cleft is familiar, the cleft clause may often be omitted. Fragment
(3c) exemplifies both contrast and the omission of the cleft clause.
Traditionally, clefting is felicitous when there is a prior basis for the presup-
posed information. Thus cleft sentences are natural answers to questions, with
the sentence accent on the extracted constituent. For instance, “Is it john who
writes poetry? No, it is b i l l who writes poetry” (Chomsky 1971, Jackendoff
1972). Neither point, however, holds generally. Clefts often appear with no
prior basis; and they allow more than one placement of the sentence accent.
In fact, new information often appears in the presupposed, clefted clause;
this is perhaps the most frequent use of clefts according to Prince (1978).
It may seem contradictory that a syntactic structure implying presupposition
is used to present new information. But there is no contradiction. Rather, the
clefted clause conveys pragmatically that the presupposed information is to be
accepted as shared knowledge. Receivers automatically assume the information
in the clefted clause, without engaging in a process of accommodation. Thus
the notion of presupposition that is relevant for clefts does not require mutual
knowledge (Delin 1995).
It-clefts also appear in a third use, where the clefted phrase gives information
that sets the stage for the situation in the cleft clause. In this case both topic and
focus phrase fall within the cleft clause. The example in (4) illustrates, repeated
from Chapter 2. The cleft phrase sets the scene:
(4) I feel reasonably certain of the final verdict on the current impeachment affair
because I think history will see it as the climax of a six-year period marred by
a troubling and deepening failure of the Republican party to play within the
established constitutional rules.
It was on Election Night 1992, not very far into the evening, that the Senate
minority leader, Bob Dole, hinted at the way his party planned to conduct
itself in the months ahead.
The clefted phrase is adverbial here; both topic and focus phrases of the sentence
are in the cleft clause. The cleft sentence suggests a story to experienced readers.
There are fairy tales, for instance, that open in a similar way: “It was a dark
and stormy night when the beautiful princess stole out of the castle.” The sense
of fairy tale is bolstered in this text when later one comes upon the sentence
“The Republicans were already on the road to further adventure” (the full text
is given in Appendix A). Other adverbial functions of it-clefts, especially of a
temporal nature, are discussed in Delin & Oberlander (1995).
9.2 Argument constructions 221
In discourse, wh- and it-clefts have different distributions and functions. The
wh-cleft clause represents “given information, assumed to be in the hearer’s
consciousness”; the it-cleft clause tends to “mark the information in the that-
clause . . . as known” (Prince 1981:904). In wh-clefts, the clefted information
is often familiar or inferrable, as in (5a). It may also, however, be new, as
in (5b):
(5) a. Underwater they [humpback whales] can blast out at 170 decibels – louder
than a jet’s roar. They also make all kinds of lower intensity social sounds.
I wish I knew what they were talking about. What I like about humpback
research is the way it lets your imagination roam free.
b. The difference between Giuliani’s and Dinkins’s anticrime policies is not
that Giuliani hired more cops: Dinkins hired 7,000 new police in his final
years in office. What Dinkins would not do, according to celebrated former
New York police chief William Bratton, was to reorient policing around a
universal standard of nonviolent deviancy.
It-cleft sentences are more frequent in the texts in this study than wh-clefts.
Extraposition. In Extraposition a sentential subject is postposed, with ex-
pletive it in subject position. Choice of this structure affects the possible topic
phrases of a sentence. Since the expletive subject is not a denoting expression, it
cannot be the topic phrase. However, the topic phrase may be the direct object,
if there is one; the situation or proposition of the extraposed clause; or a phrase
in the extraposed clause. In some cases Extraposition sentences may not have
a topic phrase (see Chapter 10, ex. 7).
The extraposed clause is pragmatically presupposed, as are subjects gener-
ally. The presupposition attached to the clause allows this construction to be
used to present information as uncontroversial, much as the it-cleft construction
is used.
Familiarity status is the main factor in extraposition. Sentential subjects that
are postposed invariably convey new information, as in (6).
(6) a. When people try to get a message from one individual to another in the
party game “Telephone,” they usually garble the words beyond recognition.
It might seem surprising, then, that mere molecules inside our cells con-
stantly enact their own version of telephone without distorting the relayed
information in the least.
Actually, no one could survive without such precise signalling in cells.
b. “The only intention we have is to weaken the forces that have occupied our
country and to regain our sovereignty. That is all.” A week after Ethiopia
started an offensive that it says is aimed at ending the two-year-old war, it
is now clear that the whole of Eritrea could become a battlefield.
222 Non-canonical structures and presentation
(7) The kilns clearly specialized in the production of the porcellanous ware. It
is characterized by the extreme whiteness and hardness of the body, which
may be translucent. That the kilns confined themselves very largely to the
production of bowls, basins, dishes and plates, is evident from the immense
waster heaps in the vicinity of the kilns and from the predominance of these
shapes in collections all over the world.
The sentential subject is relatively heavy. Examples like this show that famil-
iarity status rather than heaviness is the determining factor in extraposition.
9.2.2 Inversion
The subject is displaced to the right of the verb in inversion constructions, and
a phrase from the predicate appears in initial position. There are three main
types. In subject–auxiliary inversion the first auxiliary and subject are inverted;
other verbs follow. Quotation inversion preposes the entire quoted phrase, with
9.2 Argument constructions 223
the subject and verb following. In predicate inversion a phrase from the pred-
icate is preposed. The first two are illustrated in (8); I discuss the third type
below.
(8) a. It is true that the filibuster has a long and disreputable Senate history, and
that . . . it has been used more by Democrats than by Republicans. But only
after 1992 did it become the centerpiece of opposition conduct toward an
elected President.
b. The whale . . . was visible 40 feet below, suspended head down in pure
blueness with its 15-foot-long arms, or flippers, flared out to either side
like wings. “That’s the posture humpbacks most often assume when they
sing,” Darling said.
In (9a) the adjective phrase with “surprising” is more familiar in the discourse
context than “two other errors.” The sentence is presentational, with no topic
224 Non-canonical structures and presentation
The preposed phrase refers to Europe; mentioned in the prior sentence, it is more
familiar than the post-verbal phrase. The topic structures of such sentences vary
according to context. Here the inverted phrase functions as the topic; Coopmans
calls such phrases “topicalized adverbial PPs” (1989:735). Bolinger notes that
the initial phrase in locative inversions often has an almost visual “staging
effect” (1977:94). Locative inversion may also be presentational, with no topic
phrase. The verb of such sentences is the copula or one of a small set of motion
verbs.
Predicate inversion also applies to existential-there sentences.
(11) No other group of adults young or old is confined to an age-segregated envi-
ronment, much like a gang in which individuals of the same age group define
each other’s world.
In no workplace, not even in colleges or universities, is there such a narrow
segmentation by chronology.
The displaced subject is the focus phrase. The familiarity status requirement
for there-inversion is the same as for such sentences generally: the dislocated
phrase must be discourse-new.
The topics of inversion structures vary. In subject–auxiliary inversion and
quotation inversion, the topic is often the inverted surface subject. In predi-
cate inversion the sentence may be presentational, with no topic phrase; or the
inverted phrase may be the topic phrase.
tend to occur in speech rather than written texts. Examples are relatively rare
in the texts in this study; the only ones found were in narrative fiction, which
mimic the patterns of speech. The argument postposing constructions are Right-
dislocation, Dative Alternation, and Heavy NP Shift.
In Topicalization, an argument of the verb or the entire verb phrase is preposed
to initial position. The preposed phrase must be linked to the context in the strong
sense of linking developed above.
(12) “Why, what am I a-thinking of!” said Toby, suddenly recovering a position as
near the perpendicular as it was possible for him to assume. “I shall forget my
own name next. It’s tripe!” Tripe it was; and Meg, in high joy, protested he
should say, in half a minute more, that it was the best tripe ever stewed.
Both Topicalization and Focus Preposing structure the propositions they repre-
sent into a focus and focus frame (Partee 1991, Prince 1986). The open proposi-
tion conveys that an entity has a certain attribute; the focus represents the value
of that attribute.
Left-dislocation has an initial phrase followed by a full sentence. The phrase
is coreferential with a pronoun in the sentence and may function as the topic,
as in: “My grandmother, I remember when she used to work” (from Prince
1997). The familiarity status of the preposed phrase varies: it may express in-
formation that is familiar and linked to the context, or discourse-new. In the
latter case the coreferential pronoun tends to appear in a position that is not
favored for discourse-new entities, often an embedded subject as in the grand-
mother example. Prince (1997) suggests a processing account of the structure:
226 Non-canonical structures and presentation
This construction is used when the topic referent is relatively salient, but not
enough to be identified with a pronoun alone, according to Lambrecht. Right-
dislocation signals to the receiver that the topic referent will be named at the
end of the sentence (1994:203). The two dislocation structures are sometimes
used in speech to maintain reference to a topic and thus maximize discourse
continuity, according to Givón (1983).
Dative Alternation and Heavy NP Shift are rightward-movement construc-
tions that move phrases to the right in the predicate of a sentence. In Dative
Alternation, a direct object phrase is moved over an indirect object and the
preposition is deleted: for instance, “We gave a book to Mary” alternates with
“We gave Mary a book.”6 In Heavy NP Shift, a long and/or complex direct ob-
ject or complement is moved over another phrase in the predicate. The phrase
that is moved is the focus phrase, receiving the sentence accent. In English this
accent may hold for the smallest phrase or for successively larger phrases.
(15) a. Dative Alternation
First, he backed an end to forced busing. Then, he supported Republi-
can Governor George Voinovich’s radical school choice law, which offers
5. Prince discusses Left-dislocation cases in which the pronoun rescues what would otherwise be
an island violation. These constructions occasionally occur in writing; there were none in the
texts in this study – for instance: “There are always guests who I am curious about what t h e y
are going to say.” Prince notes that this marginally acceptable sentence would be impossible
with a gap in the position of the pronoun. Right- and Left-dislocation in French are discussed
in Lambrecht (1994).
6. There are several differences between canonical Dative sentences and the Dative Alternative
construction. The alternation is possible only for sentences with certain verbs; Gropen et al.
(1989) attempt to characterize them on semantic grounds. Green (1974) shows that the two
structures may have different entailments: “I taught Latin to the students” entails that they
learned Latin, whereas “I taught the students Latin” does not have such an entailment.
9.2 Argument constructions 227
Since the rightmost phrase in a sentence receives the accent, these constructions
result in a focus phrase that would canonically be in another position. Thus the
discourse function of postposing is to introduce a marked focus phrase (Hajicová
and Sgall 1987; see also Erteschik-Shir 1979).
Familiarity status is an important factor in non-canonical constructions, as the
foregoing discussion has established. Yet in rightward movement the heaviness
of the moved phrase also seems to be significant, cf. Hawkins (1994). Often,
but not necessarily, the moved phrases in the Dative Alternation are relatively
heavy; the rightmost phrase in (15a), for instance, is longer and more complex
than the one that precedes it. The Heavy NP Shift construction by definition
involves a heavy phrase.
The relative importance of heaviness and familiarity status in Dative Alter-
nation and Heavy NP Shift is studied by Arnold et al. (2000). The authors ex-
amined instances of these constructions in a corpus consisting of parliamentary
debate transcripts from Canada; they also elicited dative sentences experimen-
tally. Heaviness was measured by number of words; familiarity status was coded
as given, inferrable, or new. Arnold et al. asked which factor better accounted
for the sentences in which movement did and did not occur. Both factors were
relevant, they found: the phrases that appeared in rightmost position tended to
provide new information and to be relatively heavy.
Summarizing, non-canonical constructions that involve the verb and its
arguments highlight by position and syntax. Topic possibilities vary. No topic
phrase occurs in existential-there sentences or in some inversion constructions.
The topic phrase is the subject or leftmost phrase in passive, some clefts, some
inversions, some argument preposings. The topic phrase is in rightward position
in extraposition, some clefts, some inversions. To determine the actual patterns
of use would require a large-scale study.
What these constructions have in common is that they change phrases with
familiar information from canonical to non-canonical positions. All but two
constructions position relatively familiar information to the left and relatively
228 Non-canonical structures and presentation
(16) a. But how do circuits within cells achieve this high-fidelity transmission?
For a long time, biologists had only rudimentary explanations. In the past
15 years, they have made great progress in unlocking the code that cells
use for their internal communications.
7. Quirk et al. (1985) distinguish between adjuncts and disjuncts. Adjuncts pertain to the situation
in the main clause and allow syntactic processes of focusing with clefts, pseudo-clefts, negation,
question, and focusing operators. Disjuncts comment on the style, form, or content of what was
said; they are peripheral to the clause and do not allow syntactic focusing (1985:1070–71).
9.3 Non-argument preposing: Adjuncts 229
b. At the turn of the century, city governments often took aim at monopo-
listic private corporations and utilities. Now, the focus is more often on
monopolistic government agencies.
c. Our French teacher, a crusty character named Bertram Bradstock, made it
clear that in studying French, speaking it was an unnecessary luxury.
The first preposed adverb in (16a) is unrelated to the context; the second is
linked to the first, since both express time intervals. The contrast from one
preposed adverb to the other contributes to (16b). These adverbs set the scene
for the situation expressed in the sentence.8 In (16c), the metaphorical location
of studying French is evoked by the prior phrase “our French teacher”; the
example is from Lambrecht (1994).
The fragment in (17) has three preposed adjunct phrases:
(17) 1 The low price has been a mixed blessing . . . 2a With little incentive for
drillers to find and tap new oil, supplies eventually dropped, b and in the past
year the Organization of Petroleum Exporting Countries deliberately dropped
its production as well. 3 In response to the law of supply and demand, prices
have now risen.
8. There have been suggestions from time to time that scene-setting adverbials are topic phrases.
Halliday’s notion of theme essentially takes this view (1967). In some cases it is not implausible
to claim that the adverbial is the topic referent, the locus for truth-conditional assessment and
for storage of the information in the sentence. For (16a) one can say, “Speaking of the past
fifteen years, biologists have made great progress,” though the other topic paraphrases proposed
in Chapter 7 are less felicitous. But in my judgment this analysis fails to account adequately for
the main clause. Lambrecht calls adverbials like this “secondary topics.” For him, scene-setting
pertains to aboutness but does not have topic status.
230 Non-canonical structures and presentation
(18) In the past 15 years, they [biologists] have made great progress in unlocking
the code that cells use for their internal communications.
a. That’s not true: they haven’t made great progress.
b. That’s not true: it wasn’t in the past 15 years.
Both denials are felicitous, which shows that the information of the locative is
asserted. In contrast, the information of non-locative PPs is presupposed rather
than asserted. Example (19) illustrates, using sentence 2 from the fragment
in (17):
(19) With little incentive for drillers to find and tap new oil, supplies eventually
dropped.
a. That’s not true – they didn’t [drop].
b. #That’s not true – there wasn’t [little incentive].
The denial of the main clause is felicitous but that of the adverbial is
not. The information in many adjunct clauses is also presupposed, as noted
below.
Semantically, preposed material is outside the scope of negation and other
operators in the main clause. For instance, the sentence “George doesn’t eat
chocolate because he wants to be thin” is ambiguous. On one reading, the
because clause is within the scope of negation, on the other it is not. In preposed
position, however, the clause is outside the scope of negation: “Because he wants
to be thin, George doesn’t eat chocolate.” This difference holds for adverbials
generally (Davison 1984). One function of preposing, then, is to remove the
adjunct from the scope of semantic operators in the main clause.
Condensed clauses are sentences with participial or infinitival clause ad-
juncts. They are tightly bound to the main clause, as discussed in Chapter 6.
Condensed clauses usually have null subjects and lack a tense morpheme; (20)
illustrates.9
(20) a. 1 it was the explosive growth of the steam-engine based textile industry
that revived slavery. 2 Considered to be practically dead by the Founders
of the American Republic, slavery roared back to life as the cotton gin –
soon steam-driven – created a huge demand for low-cost labor and made
breeding slaves America’s most profitable industry for some decades.
9. English allows condensed clauses with overt subjects, but they are relatively rare in the modern
language. I found one example only in the texts for this study:
The moulds were made of a slightly greyish, compact stoneware clay with a concave
recess on the underside, the upper surface being ornamented with a design of neatly
carved intaglio.
9.3 Non-argument preposing: Adjuncts 231
The subject of the condensed clause is coreferential with the main clause subject,
and reinforces its role as topic phrase. Condensed clauses are part of the assertion
of a sentence. The condensed clause in S2 of (20a) is related to the context by
the prior phrase “revived slavery.” The other condensed clauses in (20) express
information that is new to the discourse. The condensed clause is temporally
dependent on the main clause; the situation it expresses precedes or overlaps
that of the main clause.
Temporal clauses with after, as, before, when, while, unless, etc., temporally
locate the situation of the main clause.10 The clauses are complete but depend
temporally on the main clause, with a requirement of tense harmony.
(21) a. At his news conference here, even before he took questions, Schroeder
implicitly challenged the official US explanation for the bombing of the
Chinese embassy in Belgrade – that target analysts relied on a faulty street
map – by renewing his demand for a formal NATO inquiry into the bombing.
b. The 19-member alliance is at a critical crossroads: as time runs out to
prepare hundreds of thousands of ethnic Albanians to return to their homes
before winter, the allies are badly divided over the timing and conditions
for the use of ground troops.
c. Soon after SH2 domains were identified, investigators realized that these
modules are present in well over 100 separate proteins.
The condensed clauses in these examples introduce new information to the dis-
course. The position of a temporal adverbial affects the interpretation of a sen-
tence, as de Swart (1999) points out. In preposed position, temporal adverbials
provide Reference Time for the situation expressed in a sentence. Adverbials
in canonical right position may have other functions.
10. Temporal clauses are discussed in Partee (1984), Smith (1991), de Swart (1993), Kamp &
Reyle (1993), Sandstrom (1993), among others. There are certain idiosyncrasies. For instance,
the Event of a before-clause may not take place, due to the meaning of “before”:
Mary Jane brushed past the others and ran to the staircase, but before she reached it the
singing stopped and the piano was closed abruptly.
We infer that Mary Jane didn’t get to the staircase after all.
232 Non-canonical structures and presentation
(22) The driver [of the mailcoach] . . . in a temper, raised his arm, and gave a full
swing of his big whip, lashing her [Félicité] from the stomach to the nape of
her neck, so that she fell to the ground on her back.
The first thing she did, when she regained consciousness, was to open her
basket.
In this fragment Félicité, the main character of the story, tries to stop a mailcoach.
The when-clause informs us as an accepted event that Félicité came back to
consciousness (and indirectly that she had lost consciousness); the receiver adds
these Events to the ongoing discourse model. This is a compact way to convey
information and gives it a certain authority since no source or justification
is cited. Unless, until, and certain cases of before (see footnote 10) do not
presuppose the situations they express.
Temporal clauses usually involve a consequential relation between situations
as well as a temporal one. In some cases the temporal aspect is less important
than the consequential, as the examples in (23) illustrate:
(23) a. When inflation is taken into account, that 1999 price was the lowest in
modern history, while oil has gone above today’s seemingly high price
several times.
b. When puberty meets education and learning in modern America, the victory
of puberty masquerading as popular culture and the tyranny of peer groups
based on ludicrous values meets little resistance.
(24) a. Brunel’s tunnel shield, a giant iron frame, was forced through soft soil by
screw jacks while miners dug through shuttered openings in the shield’s
forward face.
b. While Darwin came in for severe criticism from other scientists and in
turn often expressed his disagreement with their views, he responded cour-
teously, used scientific arguments, and completely avoided personalizing
disputes.
c. In the United States, we have lost over 500,000 jobs in the oil industry
while we have grossly increased our dependency on foreign oil; we now
import 55 percent of what we use.
main clause. Relative clauses typically have the shared NP referent as topic:
they are about their topics, as Kuno (1976) argues. However, relatives of locative
phrases and locative inversion are exceptions to the generalization.11
The function of a restrictive relative clause is to modify the shared Noun-
Phrase. More precisely, the relative contributes to a referring expression by
narrowing down the set of possible referents. Example (25) illustrates restric-
tive relative clauses on subject and object NounPhrases:
11. For instance, the following sentence has three relative clauses on NPs after the colon, all
preposed with prepositions, and all underlined.
Between these rival ends ran parallel lines of side-dishes: two little minsters of jelly,
red and yellow; a shallow dish full of blocks of blancmange and red jam, a large green
leaf-shaped dish with a stalk-shaped handle, on which lay bunches of purple raisins
and peeled almonds, a companion dish on which lay a solid rectangle of Smyrna figs, a
dish of custard topped with grated nutmeg, a small bowl full of chocolates and sweets
wrapped in gold and silver papers and a glass vase in which stood some tall celery stalks.
All three are inverted locatives: presentational clauses in which the postverbal NP is the new
information.
9.4 Multi-clause sentences 235
b. All the humpbacks in a given region sing the same song, which is constantly
evolving.
(27) 1 As they [workers] moved on, they removed mud, blasted through rock, and
bolted together the iron rings that would form the lining of the tunnel. 2 On a
good day, they moved about 40 feet. 3 Near the New York shore, where they
ran into a thousand feet of solid rock, progress slowed to less than a foot a
day.
In the S1 relative the topic is “that,” coreferential with “the iron rings.” The S3
relative clause has “the New York shore” as topic; this is the noun of a locative
PP, and does not contribute to the topic structure of the main clause.
Adjuncts. Adverbials, PPs, and adjunct clauses of all types appear in rightmost
position after the verb. In this position the information expressed is not presup-
posed. This presentation emphasizes the relations between clauses or PPs. The
contribution of the different connectives is usually interpreted in terms of the
discourse relations, as Matthiessen & Thompson (1988) argue.
Conjunctions also emphasize the close relations between situations. Con-
junction is the only other context besides the condensed clause that allows null
subject pronouns in English, as in (28):
(28) The Littleton killers felt trapped in the artificiality of the high school world
and believed it to be real.
Discussion of the many types of conjunction is beyond the scope of this chapter.
Complex sentences. In written texts one sometimes encounters complex sen-
tences related by connectives, semicolons, colons, and/or dashes. The examples
in (29) illustrate:
(29) a. In the United States, we have lost over 500,000 jobs in the oil industry
while we have grossly increased our dependency on foreign oil; we now
import 55 percent of what we use.
b. Mr Browne, whose face was once more wrinkling with mirth, poured out
for himself a glass of whisky while Freddy Malins exploded, before he had
well reached the climax of his story, in a kink of high-pitched bronchitic
236 Non-canonical structures and presentation
laughter and, setting down his untasted and overflowing glass, began to
run the knuckles of his left fist backwards and forwards into his left eye,
repeating words of his last phrase as well as his fit of laughter would allow
him.
Such complex sentences are an artifact of the written mode and the subtle
possibilities of punctuation.
9.5 Paragraphs
Paragraphs are text units, integral parts of modern written texts. Paragraphs
organize the text into chunks, each set off with spaces and indentations. The
beginnings and endings of paragraphs are salient positions in the text, as are very
short paragraphs. Paragraphs vary in length and organization. They represent a
writer’s choices of chunking and highlighting information. The presentational
aspects of a text thus include its paragraphs. The authors’ paragraphs have been
retained in the examples in this book.
One question is whether paragraphs coincide significantly with Discourse
Modes; another is whether presentational patterns relate to paragraph units.
More generally, we ask whether paragraphing is significant for understanding
text structure.
Although some regularities can be found in paragraphs, they do not conform
to any single pattern or convention. Linguistic, rhetorical, and psychological
studies agree that paragraphs are flexible and can be used in more than one way.
Some paragraphs are about a particular theme or topic, others are not. Some
paragraphs are long; others are short, drawing attention to a particular point or
direction in a text. There is no one convention but rather a set of possibilities.12
Linguists have discussed the nature of the paragraph as a semantic unit.
According to Giora (1983), semantic unity revolves around a discourse topic,
which tends to hold for a paragraph. She suggests that discourse topics are
analogous to sentence topics and can be recognized with the intuitive notion of
aboutness. Another approach to paragraph unity is taken by Longacre (1979)
and Hinds (1979), who argue that cohesive and pragmatic relations between
sentences unify the sentences of a paragraph. The relations they invoke are those
currently known as discourse relations (see Chapter 11). Of course, discourse
relations are not peculiar to paragraphs. They are relevant at all levels of a text:
sentences, parts of paragraphs, paragraphs, and larger segments. This point is
12. Chafe (1994) suggests that paragraphs in written texts correspond to topic boundaries in speak-
ing. They can appear at different levels, according to the writer’s choice.
9.5 Paragraphs 237
made with particular force by Mann & Thompson (1987, 1992), who use the
same discourse relations to structure texts at successively higher levels. Fries
(1983) argues for the thematic unity of paragraphs as structural units, using
Halliday’s notion of theme as the starting point of a sentence.
Coreference patterns often provide linguistic cues to paragraphs. Shifts from
pronoun to full NPs tend to coincide with paragraph breaks in narrative and
expository prose, according to Fox (1987a,b). The impetus for such shifts is
usually a change of theme, or topic. Longacre (1979) suggests that corefer-
ential expressions indicate thematic unity. Other cues are change of direction
or discontinuity, “theme-marking” with non-canonical syntactic structures, and
repetition of terms within a paragraph (Crothers 1979, Bond & Hayes 1984,
Hoey 1991). In some languages there are linguistic forms that have the para-
graph as their domain.13
Paragraph boundaries can be significant indicators of the linear organization
of texts. In a study of discourse topic continuity and discontinuity, Goutsos
(1997) found that paragraph breaks are powerful signals of a shift from one
discourse topic to another.14 However, there is another important pattern for
the introduction of new discourse topics. In some texts, a new discourse topic
is introduced in the final position of a paragraph and then developed in the
paragraph immediately following (Giora 1983).
There is no single pattern for paragraphs and Discourse Modes. Discourse
Modes are often maintained within a paragraph; but a Discourse Mode may
shift in the middle of a paragraph. Examples given in Chapters 2 and 5 have a
shift of Discourse Mode that coincides with the paragraph break; and shifts that
do not so coincide. In other cases, passages of a Discourse Mode may continue
for more than one paragraph. I conclude that there is no clear relation between
Discourse Modes and paragraphs.
The history of texts shows that they were not always divided into para-
graphs. With the development of printing and industrialization in sixteenth- and
13. Longacre (1979) points to markers for paragraph boundaries in Huichol (Mexico), Shipibo
(Peru), Gurung (Nepal), Sanio-Hiowe (New Guinea). Paez and Ica (Colombia) have anaphoric
devices with the paragraph as their domain. In Ica there is a special verbal suffix for referring to
the most prominent participant in a paragraph (Tracy & Levinsohn 1977). This is reminiscent
of the discourse uses of pronouns in proximal–obviative systems of American Indian languages
discussed briefly in Chapter 6.
14. Goutsos found that paragraphs did not necessarily coincide with discourse topic continuity –
more than one discourse topic may occur in a single paragraph. However, topics rarely continue
across paragraphs. Goutsos worked with three corpora of English expository texts. The para-
graphing for newspaper articles was slightly different than other genres, probably reflecting
journalistic norms and requirements.
238 Non-canonical structures and presentation
powerful set of construction rules than those used here. For another view see
McNally (1988).
Whether other aspects of surface presentation should be included in a DRS is
debatable. Syntactic structures have the potential for a certain rhetorical force,
from general effects such as surprise, emphasis, and contrast, to specifics such
as proposition concession and affirmation.15 Such interpretations depend on
details of the context as well as on a given structure: there is no single rhetor-
ical function for syntactic structures. For instance, proposition affirmation is
conveyed by certain inversions, Ward (1985) argues. In the cases he considers,
an affirmed proposition is evoked but not entailed by the context, as in “It’s
odd that dogs eat cheese, but eat it they do.” Concession/affirmation is a spe-
cial rhetorical meaning of inversions, according to Horn (1991). The speaker
concedes one proposition and affirms another; the second may follow from the
first but contrasts with it rhetorically, as in “They barely made it, but make it
they did.”
Subtleties of presentation such as the difference between independent and
relative clauses, or between full and condensed clauses, belong to the surface of
the text. They contribute to rhetorical interpretation. Certain close connections
between clauses are indirectly preserved in the DRS. For instance, since a
condensed clause has no tense, no independent times for that clause appear in
the DRS.
The rhetorical effects of inversion and other non-canonical constructions are
part of text meaning, however. Levinson (2000) suggests that they are General
Conversational Implicatures. They occupy a level of pragmatics between the
general Gricean maxims and the particular implicatures conveyed by a given
sentence in context. These rhetorical interpretations depend on pragmatic rea-
soning, and require access to surface structure. Such pragmatic interpretation
may take place in parallel with the conceptual. The two are distinct in kind,
perhaps belonging to different modules, Levinson suggests. I shall assume that
rhetorical meanings are treated differently from the conceptual meanings ad-
duced in this book.
There is reason to think that the surface structure of a sentence is not included
in the discourse representations that people actually construct. Evidence from
psycholinguistics shows that people do not remember the surface structures of
sentences. For instance, Sachs (1967) found that people rapidly forget details of
15. The studies of construction grammar emphasize the pragmatic meanings of particular con-
structions (as in Lambrecht 1986, Goldberg 1995, etc.). They tend to focus on internal aspects
of a structure rather than its role in a context.
240 Non-canonical structures and presentation
16. It was seen that after less than a minute people were not able to recall the linguistic forms of
sentences they had seen. They remembered the meanings conveyed, however.
Example sources
(1a) and (9a) Jared Diamond, A tale of two reputations. Natural History, February
2001.
(1b), (24a), and (27) Jim Collins, How it works. US Airways Magazine, Attaché, May
2001.
(1c), (11), (23b), and (28) Leon Botstein, Let teenagers try adulthood. New York Times,
May 1999.
(2), (3c), and (20a) Peter Drucker, The information revolution, Atlantic Monthly,
October 1999.
(3a), (9b), and (25b) Howard Topoff, Slave-making queens. Scientific American,
November 1999.
(3b) Tony Judt, Tyrannized by weaklings. New York Times, April 5, 1999.
(4), (8a), and (15b) Alan Ehrenhalt, Hijacking the rulebook. New York Times, December
20, 1998.
(5a), (8b), and (26b) Douglas H. Chadwick, Listening to humpbacks. National
Geographic, July 1999.
(5b), (15a), (16b), and (25a) Peter Beinart, The pride of the cities. New Republic, June
1997.
(6a), (16a), and (21c) John D. Scott & Tony Pawson, Cell communication. Scientific
American, June 2000.
(6b) After a victory, Ethiopia looks toward other fronts. New York Times, May 20, 2000.
(7) and (26a) Margaret Medley, The Chinese Potter, London: Phaidon, 1989, pp. 106,
112.
(10) and (24b) Jared Diamond, Guns Germs and Steel. New York: W. W. Norton, 1997,
p. 40.
(12) and (13) Charles Dickens, The Chimes. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 89,
93.
(14) and (29b) James, Joyce, “The Dead.” In Dubliners, 1916: reprinted, London:
Penguin Books, 1982, pp. 175, 185.
(17), (23a), (24c), and (29a) Robert Mosbacher, Cheap oil’s tough bargains. New York
Times, March 13, 2000.
(20b) Arthur Levine, The Soul of a New University. New York Times, March 13, 2000.
(21a) and (21b) Kosovo strategy splitting NATO. New York Times, May 20, 1999.
I V Discourse Modes and their
context
10 Information in text passages
This chapter brings together the main points of Discourse Mode, subjectivity,
and presentational progression; and analyzes passages of text with the tools de-
veloped above. Section 10.1 gives the basic points of each area of analysis, with
a reprise of the criteria for determining Primary Referents and sentence topics.
Section 10.2 analyzes text passages of the five Discourse Modes, according to
temporality and types of entities, I discuss temporal, spatial, and metaphorical
progression. For each passage, I also consider subjectivity and presentational
factors. Section 10.3 presents a temporal and an atemporal DRS, with informa-
tion about Discourse Mode and subjectivity.
243
244 Information in text passages
10.1.1 Subjectivity
In texts of all modes there are forms that convey subjectivity, access to a
mind. The major categories are communication, contents of mind, eviden-
tiality/evaluation, and perception and perspective. To interpret the forms of
subjectivity we identify the mind responsible – the Responsible Source – and
its scope.
Verbs of communication introduce quoted speech, represented speech, and
indirect speech. Indirect speech is systematically ambiguous: responsibility for
the content may rest with the reporter or with the original speaker. In reports of
belief and other contents of mind such as “Mary believed that John was sick”
we ascribe the belief expressed in the complement clause to Mary. Perception
and perspective follow the same principles as contents of mind. The speaker is
responsible for modals, evidentials, and evaluative forms unless they are clearly
associated with a text participant.
The scope of a subjective form may extend over several sentences, so long
as subjective continuity is maintained. Subjective continuity is broken with a
change of time or place, or introduction of a new candidate for Responsible
Source.
is organized; and how sentences are connected to each other in a text. Sentences
may be linked by poset linking, in the technical sense presented in Chapter 9,
or connected by weaker relations of familiarity.
Presentational progression depends on sentence topics: texts progress from
one topic phrase to another. The subject phrase is canonically the topic of a
sentence, since the subject is salient grammatically and positionally. In non-
canonical structures other phrases may be topic. If there is no topic the entity
introduced is the locus for progression.
The topic phrase refers to what a sentence is about. The main criteria for
identifying the topic phrase are salience, familiarity, and continuity. The criteria
are listed below, repeated from Chapter 8.
NPs with sentence accent or other focus cues are not candidates for topic.
This approach allows for some variation in the position of topic phrases.
However, there is a striking consistency in the text passages that I have exam-
ined. Topics almost always appear in the subject position of a sentence, whether
the syntactic structure is canonical or not.
“Sir Alexander Flemming” is the focused referent of S1 and the topic referent
(“he”) of S2. “A certain species of germ” is focus of S2, and topic of the
relative clause at the end of S2. The chaining relation is allowed by the syntactic
structures of the sentences. The passive S1 ends with a proper name, which is
coreferential with the subject and topic phrase of S2.
The second type has a “continuous theme”: the same topic referent recurs
in a succession of sentences. I call this type Topic Chaining, following Givón
(1983).
All sentences in (4) have the same topic, the Rousseauist. Note the shift from
pronoun subject back to full nominal in the last sentence. The shift suggests
a change of direction, perhaps the end of a paragraph, as noted in Chapters 6
and 9.
In the third type, Unchained, each sentence has a different topic and a different
focus referent, as in (5). The sentences of the passage are not unrelated, however:
they all predicate something about New Jersey, as Daneš recognized:
(5) Unchained
New Jersey is flat along the coast and southern portion; the northwestern region
is mountainous. The coastal climate is mild, but there is considerable cold in
the mountain areas during the winter months. Summers are fairly hot. The
leading industrial production includes chemicals, . . . food, coal, petroleum,
metals, and electric equipment.
The topic pattern approach does not give a way to establish the connections we
intuitively make between these sentences.
The connections can be established nicely by the poset linking of Chapter 9.
Recall that poset linking relates a referent to a salient poset that can be inferred
in the context. In (5) each subject phrase after the first sentence refers to a
characteristic of New Jersey. The poset of such characteristics is evoked by the
“New Jersey” in the first sentence. Thus the topic phrases of (5) are in effect
chained at the level of poset linking.
The topic phrases in the examples are all surface structure subjects, although
the syntactic position is not the concern of the topic pattern analysis. This is the
position that recurs strikingly across the text passages examined for this study.
10.2 Multiple analyses of text passages 247
The clauses with event verb constellations all have the perfective viewpoint,
presenting bounded events. They are taken as sequential, advancing the narra-
tive, on the continuity tense pattern. States are expressed in clauses 2b, 3a–b,
4a–c, and 7b; they are located at the preceding Reference Time on the limited
anaphora tense pattern. Since states overlap or surround Reference Time the
states are not limited to that time but are understood as continuing indefinitely
before and after it. The state sentences constitute a small descriptive passage in
themselves.
I now add information about subjectivity and topic phrases; forms of sub-
jectivity appear in bold, and the topic phrases are italicized. Several clauses
1. This pattern was demonstrated for the essay The Elements of Ethics by Bertrand Russell in
Smith (1971).
248 Information in text passages
are presentational and do not have topics; for them, the phrases introducing
referents are noted with single quotes.
The topic phrases are subjects in all but one clause. Most have several topic
properties. In 1, and 5–7 the topic phrases are agents. After S1 the dynamic topic
phrases are coreferential with earlier phrases; the clauses in 5–6 have parallel
syntactic structures.
The topic pattern follows the shift in mode from Narrative to Description
and back. The first narrative chunk has two clauses, 1 and 2a; the sentences are
related by Topic Chaining.2 The second chunk, a description, consists of clause
2b, and 3 and 4. 2b is linked to 2a by Focus–Topic Chaining. The other clauses
have no topic phrase. Sentences 4a–b are existential there-sentences; S3b is
a predicate inversion structure. The inverted pronoun is linked to the context,
since it is coreferential with the topic of the preceding clause. The inversion
maximizes continuity. The third chunk, also narrative, has Topic Chaining.
At S6 the focus phrase of 5c is picked up, and the topic shifts from “Dr. P” to
“we”; then to “I.”
The one subjective expression is the verb “recall” which implies an experi-
encer. Since the narration is in the first person, the Responsible Source is both
author and participant.
The next example is a passage in the Descriptive mode. The mode is temporal
and static: time does not change. Text progression is spatial through the scene.
The phrases that indicate spatial location are underlined; phrases that introduce
referents in presentational clauses are in single quotes.
2. The topic phrase of clause 2a is the direct object of a canonical S-V-O sentence. The subject
and object phrases are both possible topics: they meet slightly different criteria. The subject
“Mrs P” is coreferential with “his wife” in S1, and has the agent role. The object is coreferential
with the topic of S1 and a pronoun. I identify the object pronoun as the topic phrase, by the
criteria of local topic continuity.
10.2 Multiple analyses of text passages 249
The verb constellations are all states, though of different types. The first clauses
are locational; 6b and 7 indicate personal experience. The passage begins with
a tour of the front of the shop, then moves to the back with its workshop and
drying room, and to Mara. The spatial progression is due to lexical information
and world knowledge.
This passage occurs in a novel, just after a dialogue between Mara and a
friend; context and the subjective forms indicate the perspectival standpoint of
Mara. The subjective elements are given in bold in (9).
The third version of the passage adds topic information. The topic phrases are
italicized; in sentences without topics, phrases in presentational constructions
appear in single quotes.
When spatial location and topic phrase coincide, a phrase has both underlining
and italics.
The subject and topic phrases in all but the last sentence are related by poset
linking. The passive in S3 puts the locational phrase in subject position; the
preposed phrase in S4 also highlights location. Both S2 and 5a–b are presenta-
tional there-sentences which do not have a topic phrase. The quotation inversion
of S7b puts presentational “there” in subject position. Thus the paragraph has
relatively few topic phrases. The effect is to highlight the spatial progression.
Now consider a passage in the Report mode, from Chapter 2; as usual only
the tensed clauses are analyzed.
The situation entities in this passage are all events and states. The passage is
intricate in syntax and temporal relations. There are two events in S1, related
to each other. The temporal clause has strong focus due to the operator “even.”
10.2 Multiple analyses of text passages 251
The event of the appositive clause is not related to the others except by world
knowledge. S2 returns to the present with a report about the past. The subjective
elements have different sources. For the deictic “here” the author is Responsible
Source. For the complement of the “say” the Responsible Source is the subject
referent, “diplomats.” Presentational progression proceeds by Topic Chaining
until S2c, where a new topic appears.
An Informative passage is presented in (12). The entities are marked as
subscripts on clauses – “Ge” for Generalizing sentence; the Primary Referent
phrases are underlined.
(12) Informative a: Situation entities, Primary Referents
1aGe The Information Revolution is now at the point bGe at which the
Industrial Revolution was in the early 1820s, about forty years cE after
James Watt’s improved steam engine (first installed in 1776) was first ap-
plied, in 1785, to an industrial operation – the spinning of cotton. 2aGe And
the steam engine was to the first Industrial Revolution what bGe the computer
has been to the Information Revolution – its trigger, but above all its
symbol. 3aGe Almost everybody today believes bGe that S [nothing in eco-
nomic history has ever moved as fast as, or had a greater impact than, the
Information Revolution]. 4aGe But the Industrial Revolution moved at least as
fast in the same time span, bGe and φ had probably an equal impact if not a
greater one.
The choices of Primary Referent are justified below. The letters following
each phrase refer to the relevant criterion for Primary Referent in (1).
(13) Justification for Primary Referents of (12)
1. a. “The Information Revolution”: e metaphorical location
b. “Industrial Revolution”: e metaphorical location
c. “an industrial operation”: b causally affected
2. a. “the steam engine”: e metaphorical location
b. “the computer”: e metaphorical location
3. a. S: e metaphorical location, object of belief
b. “the Information Revolution”: d entity that moves (metaphorically)
4. a. “Industrial Revolution”: d entity that moves (metaphorically)
b. “an equal impact”: f dependent on the situation
The Primary Referents are in parallel throughout the passage. The text pro-
gresses from the “Information Revolution” and “Industrial Revolution” to more
detail with “steam engine” and “computer”; in the last two sentences the first
parallel is resumed. There is little metaphorical motion in the passage.
Next consider the presentational aspects of the passage. The topic phrases
are in italics, the Primary Referents are underlined, and the subjective forms
are in bold. The syntax is relatively complex in the predicates of the clauses,
252 Information in text passages
but this does not affect the topic phrases: they are the subject NPs in every
clause.
(14) Informational b: Topic, Primary Referent, subjectivity
1aGe The Information Revolution is now at the point bGe at which the
Industrial Revolution was in the early 1820s, about forty years cE after
James Watt’s improved steam engine (first installed in 1776) was first ap-
plied, in 1785, to an industrial operation – the spinning of cotton. 2aGe And
the steam engine was to the first Industrial Revolution bGe what the computer
has been to the Information Revolution – its trigger, but above all its symbol.
3aGeS Almost everybody today believes bGe that nothing in economic history
has ever moved as fast as, or had a greater impact than, the Information Rev-
olution. 4aGe But the Industrial Revolution moved at least as fast in the same
time span, bGe and φ had probably an equal impact if not a greater one.
Topic and Primary Referent are the same in S1a–b, S2a–b, and S4a. They differ
in clauses expressing events with effects or changes: S3b and S4b. The topic
referent tends to be the cause of a change or an effect in canonical sentences;
the Primary Referent is usually the entity that changes.
Finally I present a short passage in the Argument mode. The first version
indicates the situation entities and the Primary Referents:
(15) Argument a: Situations, Primary Referents
1aS A pretty good argument can be made that bProp the defining moment of
American democracy didn’t occur in 1776 or 1787, as commonly supposed,
but in 1801 – on the day cE that John Adams, having been beaten at the polls,
quietly packed his things and went home. 2aE Only then did we know for sure
b thatFact the system worked as advertised.
3aGe The routine transfer of power may not be the most dramatic feature of
American democracy, b but it is the most important.
(16) Justification for Primary Referents of (15)
1. a. “that S,” clausal complement: f dependent on the situation
b. “defining moment”: e temporally located
c. “John Adams”: d moves
2. a. “that S,” clausal complement: e metaphorically located (possessed
mental State)
b. “the system”: h property ascribed
3. a. “The routine transfer of power”: h property ascribed
b. “it”: h property ascribed
The first two sentences introduce abstract entities. The complement that-clause
in S1b refers to a proposition. The corresponding wh-question form would be
ungrammatical, so it meets the substitution criteria for a proposition, discussed
in Chapter 4. The complement clause of 2b refers to a fact: it is a that-clause,
and would allow substitution of the wh-question form. The entity introduced
by S1a is technically a state because of the modal; S2a introduces an event
10.2 Multiple analyses of text passages 253
The main clause of S1 is passive, putting the phrase “a pretty good argument”
in subject position. S2 has a preposed adverbial phrase with subject–auxiliary
inversion. The syntax highlights the temporal adverbial by putting it in initial
position; demotes the subject phrase from its canonical position of prominence;
and highlights the complement clause, now in final position. Thus non-canonical
syntax enables the topic phrase pattern.
The topic phrases are not related by chaining, poset linking, or familiarity.
Both presentational and text progression pick out the same phrases in four
clauses, giving the text a strong forward sense. When topic and Primary Referent
phrase are different, as in the other three clauses, the organization is more
complex.
This explication sorts out some of the information conveyed and automati-
cally processed by the reader in the text passage above.
254 Information in text passages
(19) 1 A few days later I called on Dr P and his wife at home. 2a Mrs. P showed
me into a lofty apartment, 2b which recalled fin-de-siècle Berlin.
The subjective form is the state verb “recall.” The implicit Experiencer argu-
ment is included with the state condition, and its content given in a sub-DRS,
indicated by dots. The Author is a discourse entity (A) at the top of the DRS, and
is interpreted as Responsible Source, RS. Identifying the RS with the narrator
is automatic for a first-person narrator since the passage has no other candidate
for this role. The referents of the “recall” relation appear in the sub-DRS and
also in the main DRS because their existence is not contingent on the sub-DRS.
(20) 1 A few days later I called on Dr P and his wife at home. 2a Mrs. P showed
me into a lofty apartment, 2b which recalled fin-de-siècle Berlin.
26. q = r
27. p = o
256 Information in text passages
The next DRS interprets an atemporal text passage. I use a simplified fragment
from a passage presented earlier. The DRS encodes information about Discourse
Mode – situation entities and Primary Referents – and subjectivity.
(21) Within the next fifty years fish farming may change us from hunters and
gatherers into marine pastoralists. It is likely that other new technologies will
appear.
1. e: appear (r)
2. t2d > t1d; t3d = t2d
3. r = other new technologies
4. r = Primary Referent
The situation entities of the fragment consist of states, a proposition, and events
in the sub-DRSs. The complement clause of “likely” refers to a proposition, as
10.3 Formalization in DRSs 257
we know from the class of predicate and the substitution possibilities (“that S”
may appear but not a wh-complement).
Entities of situations, times, and individuals appear at the top of the DRS
if they exist independently. In the first clause, for instance, “fish farming” and
“us” are listed independently; but “marine pastoralists” depends for existence
on the sub-DRS. In the second clause “other new technologies” depends on the
sub-DRS.
The Primary Referents are identified by a condition on the entity. In each case
the complement is Primary Referent for the clause. Within the first complement,
“us” is Primary Referent, the entity that changes; within the second complement,
“other new technologies” is primary, dependent on the situation for existence.
There are forms of subjectivity in both clauses; the Author is the Responsible
Source.
This inquiry into local text structure has stayed close to the linguistic ground,
concentrating on linguistic forms and categories. In this final chapter I widen the
range of discussion to consider some of the organizing principles of discourse. I
begin with hierarchical structure and functional units, and then discuss discourse
relations. Finally, I comment on how the Discourse Modes pertain to discourse
relations and to lexical patterns, which distinguish units at different levels of
text structure.
(1) HAMMER
Lifting Striking
Repeated hammering consists of many such steps, each with the same hier-
archically organized sub-goals. More complex activities have many sub-goals.
Even a relatively simple activity such as going to work has a number of
258
11.1 Organizing principles of texts 259
sub-goals: getting ready, leaving the house, deciding how to get there, choosing
a route, etc.
If we assume that intentions are hierarchical, and that discourse is organized
into functional units of goals and sub-goals, we both predict and explain its
hierarchical nature. The recognition of hierarchical structure has led to studies
of how plans are made, executed, and recognized, as in Allen & Perrault (1980),
Litman (1985). Much of this work applies to written discourse as planned, in-
tentional action. Intentional structure is proposed as a distinct level of discourse
structure by Grosz & Sidner (1986).
The intuition that texts have hierarchical structure is shared by all who work
with them. Hierarchical structure is often modeled in abstract tree structures.1
The units posited may function as part of the global structure of the discourse;
their parts may be topically related;2 or they may realize discourse relations
such as Causation, Evidence, etc., discussed below.
1. Linguists come to this conclusion from many traditions; they include Halliday (1967), Linde
(1979), Grimes (1975), Longacre (1983/1996), Polanyi (1988), Martin (1992), and many others.
The tree structures of linguistics are generated with phrase structure rules, which encode
hierarchical relations. Thus the first rule of a simple sentence grammar might be: S → NP + VP
which would be realized in a tree structure with a topmost node S, dominating the two nodes
NP and VP:
S
NP VP
2. Topically related means, roughly, “about the same thing.” The parts of a topically related segment
may or may not have an explicit shared topic; see Chapter 8 for discussion.
260 Discourse structure and Discourse Modes
3. In a study of spoken personal narratives, Labov & Waletsky (1966) posit similar functional
units: Orientation, Action, and Evaluation, with an optional Preface. These studies owe much
to the work of Propp (1958), which identified the basic units of stories and the ways in which
they combine and vary.
11.2 Discourse relations 261
(2) (a) He was in a foul humor. (b) He hadn’t slept well that night. (c) His electric
blanket hadn’t worked.
The event of (2b) is the cause of the state expressed in (2a), and (2c) gives the
cause of the situation in (2b); the example is cited by Hobbs (1985:13). The
urge to find relations is so powerful that we can make sense of almost anything
even if many inferences are needed. Inventing texts which are incoherent is
actually quite difficult; Knott gives this example (1996:3):
(3) Sally decided to take the history course. The ducks on the lake were not eating
the bread.
Bible study was the first attempt to identify and work with discourse relations.
Fuller recognized “increasingly large sections of text according to a small num-
ber of explicit organizing relations” (Grimes 1975:208). The approach is further
developed in Beekman (1970). Along similar lines, Halliday & Hasan noted
four types of “underlying semantic relations” which they saw as conjunctions
that are optionally signaled on the surface: Additive, Adversative, Causal, and
Temporal (1976). Again, Longacre (1983) discusses deep structure relations,
“combinations of predications” into larger units; his list includes such notions
as Conjunction, Contrast, Alternation, Comparison.
and, but, etc. Nevertheless there has been some useful study of such words.
Schiffrin looked at the distribution and interpretation of certain “discourse
markers” in conversation. She found that the scope of these words varies: for
instance, in some contexts because has scope over multiple clauses (Schiffrin
1987:197).4 Knott (1996) collected over 200 such “cue words” and used them
in a substitution task to test for basic discourse relations that are psychologically
real.
Relational words and concepts are not always one-to-one. For instance, the re-
lation “cause” is signaled by several cue words, e.g. so, therefore, consequently,
thus, as a result. Conversely, one word may indicate different relations, e.g.
but can indicate “thesis–antithesis” and/or “concession” (Mann & Thompson
1987:71). Relational words do not necessarily translate directly from one lan-
guage to another: the semantic space covered may differ (Fabricius-Hansen
& Behrens 2000). In computational generation of texts, Hovy uses a large
set of coherence relations. He distinguishes three classes, Semantic, Interper-
sonal, and Presentational (1993). Grosz & Sidner (1986) offer a computationally
based theory of text structure that emphasizes attentional and intentional phe-
nomena. They argue that it is futile to seek a fixed list of discourse purposes,
instead recognizing two general “intentional structural relations,” dominance
and satisfaction–precedence.
Taking a semantic–pragmatic approach, Asher & Lascarides have developed
formal accounts of certain discourse relations (Lascarides & Asher 1993). They
propose a defeasible logic and theory of commonsense entailment to account
for the patterns of inference that people use. Their aim is to “place knowledge
in a logic where its implications can be precisely calculated” (1993:439). For
simple narrative texts they offer a procedure for determining the relations of
Elaboration, Explanation, Narration, and Background in short text segments
(Asher & Lascarides 2000).
The abstract relational structures of discourse are represented in an exten-
sion of DR Theory, Segmented Discourse Representation Theory (SDRT). The
theory, due to Asher (1993), constructs hierarchical structures of text segments
that realize the relational segments of discourse relations. The output of the
SDRT construction rules is not a single DRS but a complex propositional struc-
ture of DRSs. The complex representation is a recursive structure of clausal
4. Schiffrin (1987) posits the following components: exchange, action, and idea structures; infor-
mation State; participation framework. She investigated the expressions oh, well, and, but, or,
so, because, now, then, I mean, y’know. Some of these expressions signal relations in the sense
under discussion here, others do not.
264 Discourse structure and Discourse Modes
DRSs, linked together by relations such as Narration and Parallel. The construc-
tion procedure requires that new units be attached only to tree nodes which are
“structurally accessible.” The rightmost nodes of each sub-tree or constituent
are taken to be accessible, following Polanyi (1988).
In the extended version of the theory, DRSs or SDRSs are organized to form
discourse segments. The stated goal is to model as precisely as possible the
insights of Hobbs, Mann & Thompson, and others about discourse relations.
The theory infers discourse relations with a formal theory of pragmatics which
draws on multiple information sources. The sources of information are primarily
semantic content, including lexical semantics; domain and world knowledge;
and Gricean principles of orderliness. The type of discourse relation that a
segment realizes is notated in the SDRT representation.
11.4 Conclusion
The classification of text passages into Discourse Modes is a fairly radical
extension of aspectual and temporal notions, and it has been quite successful in
bringing out important features of texts. The essential point is that the modes
are notional units with linguistic correlates.
This book is devoted to English, but it is likely that Discourse Modes are a
general phenomenon in language. There are bound to be differences in the lin-
guistic correlates to the Discourse Modes. Some language-particular correlates
are already known: for instance, in French the Descriptive mode is convention-
ally realized by the imparfait, a past tense with the imperfective viewpoint. The
linguistic features of abstract entities may vary, since not all languages have
the formal variety in their clausal complements of English. The expression of
temporal progression in tenseless languages must rely on linguistic features
other than tense. The features of the discourse modes provide a useful research
tool for studying similarities and differences between languages.
Appendix A: The texts
Appendix A presents a selection of texts that are found frequently in the chapters.
Short texts are given in their entirety; fragments are excerpted from the longer texts.
Unless otherwise noted, the fragment begins at the beginning of the text. The original
paragraphing is preserved. The texts are given in the order presented in this book.
The texts: (a) from A Necessary End, by Peter Robinson, New York: Avon Books,
1989, p. 182; (b) Barak fights on many fronts, New York Times, May 20, 2000; (c) Cheap
oil’s tough bargains by Robert Mosbacher, New York Times, March 13, 2000; (d) After a
victory. Ethiopia looks toward other fronts, New York Times, May 20, 2000; (e) from Cell
communication, by John Scott & Tony Pawson, Scientific American, June, 2000; (f) from
Listening to humpbacks, by Douglas H. Chadwick, National Geographic, July 1999;
(g) from Slave-making queens, by Howard Topoff, Scientific American, November 1999;
(h) Hijacking the rulebook, by Alan Ehrenhalt, New York Times, December 20, 1998;
(i) The Information Revolution, Peter Drucker, Atlantic Monthly, October 1999; (j) The
Chinese Potter, by Margaret Medley, London: Phaidon, 1989; (k) from The pride of
the cities, by Peter Beinart, New Republic, June 1997; (l) from How it works, by Jim
Collins, US Airways Magazine, Attaché, May 2001; (m) from “The Dead” by James
Joyce. In Dubliners, 1916; reprinted London: Penguin Books, 1982, pp. 177–79; (n) Let
teenagers try adulthood, by Leon Botstein, New York Times, May 1999.
THE TEXTS
(a) Fragment from A Necessary End, by Peter Robinson; pages 81ff.
Mara walked along the street, head down, thinking about her talk with Banks. Like
all policemen, he asked nothing but bloody awkward questions. And Mara was sick of
awkward questions. Why couldn’t things just get back to normal so she could get on
with her life?
“Hello, love,” Elspeth greeted her as she walked into the shop.
“Hello. How’s Dottie?”
“She won’t eat. How she can expect to get better when she refuses to eat, I just don’t
know.
They both knew that Dottie wasn’t going to get better, but nobody said so.
“What’s wrong with you?” Elspeth asked “You’ve got a face as long as next week.”
Mara told her about Paul.
“I don’t want to say I told you so,” Elspeth said, smoothing her dark tweed skirt, “but
I thought that lad was trouble from the start. You’re best rid of him, all of you.”
267
268 Appendix A
“I suppose you’re right.” Mara didn’t agree, but there was no point arguing Paul’s
case against Elspeth. She hadn’t expected any sympathy.
“Go in the back and get the wheel spinning, love,” Elspeth said. “It’ll do you a power
of good.”
The front part of the shop was cluttered with goods for tourists. There were locally
knit sweaters on shelves on the walls, tables of pottery – some of which Mara had made –
and trays of trinkets, such as key-rings bearing the Dales National Park emblem – the
black face of a Swaledale sheep. As if that weren’t enough, the rest of the space was
taken up by fancy notepaper, glass paperweights, fluffy animals and fridge-door magnets
shaped like strawberries or Humpty Dumpty.
In the back, though, the setup was very different. First, there was a small pottery
workshop, complete with wheel and dishes of brown and black metallic oxide glaze,
and beyond that a drying room and a small electric kiln. The workshop was dusty and
messy, crusted with bits of old clay, and it suited a part of Mara’s personality. Mostly
she preferred cleanliness and tidiness, but there was something special, she found, about
creating beautiful objects in a chaotic environment.
She put on her apron, took a lump of clay from the bin and weighed off enough for
a small vase. The clay was too wet, so she wedged it with a flat concrete tray, which
absorbed the excess moisture. As she wedged – pushing hard with the heels of her hands,
then pulling the clay forward with her fingers to get all the air out – she couldn’t seem
to lose herself in the task as usual, but kept thinking about her conversation with Banks.
Frowning, she cut the lump in half with a cheese wire to check for air bubbles, then
slammed the pieces together much harder than usual. A fleck of clay spun off and hit her
forehead, just above her right eye. She put the clay down and took a few deep breaths,
trying to bring her mind to bear only on what she was doing.
No good. It was Banks’s fault, of course. He had introduced her to speculation that
caused nothing but distress. True, she didn’t want Paul to be guilty, but if, as Banks had
said, that meant someone else she knew had killed the policeman, that only made things
worse.
Sighing, she started the wheel with the foot pedal and slammed the clay as close to
the centre as she could. Then she drenched both it and her hands with water from a bowl
by her side. As the wheel spun, clayey water flew off and splashed her apron.
She couldn’t believe that any of her friends had stabbed Gill. Much better if Osmond
or one of the students had done it for political reasons. Tim and Abha seemed nice
enough, if a bit naive and gushing, but Mara had never trusted Osmond; he had always
seemed somehow too oily and opinionated for her taste.
(b) A year after victory, Barak fights on many fronts. New York Times,
May 20, 2000
A week that began in violence ended violently here, with bloody clashes in the West Bank
and Gaza and intensified fighting in Southern Lebanon. On the one-year anniversary of
his election by a sweeping majority, Prime Minister Ehud Barak was trying to put out
fires on many fronts at once. Because of trouble in the north, the south, and within
his political coalition, he was weighing a cancellation of his scheduled departure this
weekend to the United States to confer with President Clinton and meet with Jewish
American leaders.
The texts 269
(c) Cheap oil’s tough bargains, by Robert Mosbacher, New York Times,
March 13, 2000
The press has trumpeted the news that crude oil prices are three times higher than they
were a year ago. But it was the $10 or $11 price of February 1999, not the one today,
that really deserved the headlines.
When inflation is taken into account, that 1999 price was the lowest in modern history,
while oil has gone above today’s seemingly high price several times. And for the past
14 years, at $17.50, oil has been one of the real bargains of the modern age.
The low price has been a mixed blessing. In the United States, we have lost over
500,000 jobs in the oil industry while we have grossly increased our dependency on
foreign oil; we now import 55 percent of what we use. With little incentive for drillers to
find and tap new oil, supplies eventually dropped, and in the past year the Organization of
Petroleum Exporting Countries deliberately dropped its production as well. In response
to the law of supply and demand, prices have now risen.
A high oil price is not the inflationary threat it once was because with the shift toward
the information and service economy, and away from manufacturing, the United States
270 Appendix A
is less dependent on oil. But try to tell a consumer paying to heat his home, a trucker
moving goods across the country or a commuter who goes by car that oil and gasoline
are not major factors in the economy, and the answer is likely to be, “It feels like I’m
being ripped off.”
American consumers have been lulled into thinking cheap oil is their entitlement.
Syndicated columnist Carl T. Rowan wrote recently: “We are truly a spoiled society!
We insist on driving gas guzzlers and using a grossly disproportionate amount of the
world’s energy, and we believe we should forever be able to do so at bargain rates.”
Sooner or later, oil prices are likely to drop. But prices at today’s level have their
advantages. With the incentive for more production back in place, there will be more
drilling in new places, like the deep water off the coasts of many countries of the world,
including the United States. Off our Gulf Coast, deep-water drilling, developing and
producing are already going on.
Remarkable new technology now allows pipelines to bring oil from miles out to sea,
where the water is as much as 8,000 feet deep. The ubiquitous deep waters of the world
have great potential for additional oil and gas reserves, but drilling in 5,000 to 10,000 feet
of water and then through many thousands of feet of sand, shale and other formations
makes for huge costs. In many cases, this kind of oil production can only be justified by
prices of at least $25 to $35 a barrel.
A high price also encourages development of other new technologies already on the
horizon, including three-dimensional seismology for mapping and horizontal drilling.
And $30 oil also brings attention back to development of synthetic fuel, solar energy,
wind power, gasification of coal and other methods of producing energy.
Some members of Congress have been lobbying for taking oil from the Strategic
Petroleum Reserve to help bring prices down, and President Clinton recently announced
he is not ruling this out. But these reserves are set aside for use in an emergency, and
tapping them is only justified if there is a genuine threat of a supply interruption, as there
might be in a war or political crisis. The reserve holds about 570 million barrels, not
much when we use about 19.4 million barrels of oil products daily. Even releasing all of
it could be only a temporary solution to the price problem. Tapping it would also signal
the main oil-producing countries that we were trying to control world energy prices,
which is inconsistent with our normal free and fair trade policies.
Even if the control of oil prices were in American hands, which it is not (since we
have no means of influencing it other than using our reserves or jawboning OPEC), we
would still face a daunting decision. Would we be better off getting prices back under
$20 a barrel to prevent any oil-influenced inflation today, or should we take the longer
view and let today’s price work to bring about more drilling and new interest in other
sources of energy?
Simple realities argue for the latter course: In the long term, even if bent by cartels,
the law of supply and demand will rule. And in the long term, we will need the new
sources of energy that high prices can bring.
(d) After a victory, Ethiopia looks toward other fronts. New York Times,
May 20, 2000
It took three days for Ethiopian troops to battle their way into this town, and now that
they have it, they are pressing deeper into Eritrea, denying with every step that they plan
The texts 271
any long-term invasion of their neighbor and once-tight ally. “We have no intentions, no
plans, no need to occupy Eritrea,” an Ethiopian commander, Colonel Gabre Kidane, said
tonight as he stood on the old Italian fortress in this hilly town 45 miles inside Eritrea.
“The only intention we have is to weaken the forces that have occupied our country and
to regain our sovereignty. That is all.”
A week after Ethiopia started an offensive that it says is aimed at ending the two-
year-old war, it is now clear that the whole of Eritrea could become a battlefield. With
hundreds of civilians fleeing the region, Colonel Kidane said Ethiopian soldiers continue
to skirmish with Eritrean soldiers on the run here in western Eritrea.
Tonight, Ethiopian officials said planes bombed the main Eritrean military training
center at Sawa, an American-built base 100 miles west of Asmara, the capital. The
officials also said they had taken a village, Maidema, 30 miles from Asmara, on the way
from the western front to the central front along the disputed border. That is where the
next round of fighting, already heavy, is generally expected.
For Eritrea, Ethiopia’s rapid advance out of the border trenches into the countryside
is not merely a military setback. For 30 years, when Eritrea was the northernmost
province of Ethiopia, rebels fought two successive governments in Addis Ababa for
their independence. Those rebels, the Eritrean People’s Liberation Front, are now in
power in Eritrea, and they say this advance is a frightening continuation of Ethiopia’s
attempts at domination.
An Eritrean government statement said today that a bombing on Thursday south of the
port of Massawa killed a civilian. That death, the statement said, was “further evidence
of Ethiopia’s resurgent aim to annex this country and, in so doing, to make targets of
Eritrea’s civilian populations.” Ethiopia said the target was a military installation.
The paradox is that the leaders of Ethiopia fought side by side with the Eritreans to
oust the military government of Mengistu Haile Mariam in 1991. For the first two years,
the two governments were close friends, so close that they never demarcated the border
when Eritrea became independent in 1993. But tensions grew over personality clashes
and economic rivalry, exploding in May 1998 when Eritrea claimed the Badme border
region based on old colonial maps. Eritrea moved troops into the area. Ethiopia said
it was invaded, and a war ignited that has defied long peace talks and claimed tens of
thousands of lives on both sides.
Until Ethiopia began its offensive last Friday, the fighting had been confined to three
fronts along the 620-mile border. But since then, Ethiopia has pressed 65 miles into
Eritrea, displacing 340,000 people, the World Food Program said today.
Officials in neighboring Sudan said today that an additional 50,000 Eritreans had fled
across their border. In both places, relief officials said, people lack food and shelter.
Even without the war, the United Nations says 800,000 Eritreans face food shortages
because of drought. Most civilians fled from around this town, the regional capital and
a strategically important point because the area was a main supply route for Eritrea’s
westernmost front.
The battle has been intense. Starting on Monday, Colonel Kidane said, Ethiopian
troops had pounded areas around the town with bombs, tanks and artillery and then
engaged Eritrean troops along a mountain pass eight miles from town. Along the
heavily mined road from the south, the route of Ethiopia’s advance, huge numbers
of empty mortar shells, captured Eritrean ammunition and destroyed trucks from both
272 Appendix A
sides remain. At spots, the smell of rotting corpses was strong. Colonel Kidane would
not give the number of casualties.
On Thursday morning, Ethiopian troops took the town, the biggest one that they have
captured, and called it a major victory. The Eritreans said they had staged a tactical
withdrawal.
This evening, Ethiopian troops milled around and ate their rations at the hilltop build-
ing that was once a fortress for Italian troops in the colonial period and that, until
Thursday, according to the Ethiopians, was the command center for Eritrean troops in
the region. The Ethiopians joked about marching to Asmara. “It’s nice to take the place
of the invading army,” said an Ethiopian soldier, Seife Yechenju, 21, who has fought in
the army since the war began. “There is no question that I am very happy.”
(e) Fragment from cell communication, by John D. Scott & Tony Pawson,
Scientific American, June 2000
As anyone familiar with the party game “telephone” knows, when people try to get a
message from one individual to another in a line, they usually garble the words beyond
recognition. It might seem surprising, then, that mere molecules inside our cells con-
stantly enact their own version of telephone without distorting the relayed information
in the least.
Actually, no one could survive without such precise signalling in cells. The body func-
tions properly only because cells communicate with one another constantly. Pancreatic
cells, for instance, release insulin to tell muscle cells to take up sugar from the blood for
energy. Cells of the immune system instruct their cousins to attack invaders, and cells of
the nervous system rapidly fire messages to and from the brain. Those messages elicit
the right responses only because they are transmitted accurately far into a recipient cell
and to the exact molecules able to carry out the directives.
But how do circuits within cells achieve this high-fidelity transmission? For a long
time, biologists had only rudimentary explanations. In the past 15 years, though, they
have made great progress in unlocking the code that cells use for their internal commu-
nications. The ongoing advances are suggesting radically new strategies for attacking
diseases that are caused or exacerbated by faulty signaling in cells – among them cancer,
diabetes and disorders of the immune system.
The earliest insights into information transfer in cells emerged in the late 1950s,
when Edwin G. Krebs and Edmond H. Fischer of the University of Washington and the
late Earl W. Sutherland, Jr., of Vanderbilt University identified the first known signal-
relaying molecules in the cytoplasm (the material between the nucleus and a cell’s outer
membrane). All three received Nobel Prizes for their discoveries.
By the early 1980s researchers had gathered many details of how signal transmis-
sion occurs. For instance, it usually begins after a messenger responsible for carrying
information between cells (often with a hormone) docks temporarily, in lock-and-key
fashion, with a specific receptor on a recipient cell. Such receptors, the functional equiv-
alent of antennae, are able to relay a messenger’s command into a cell because they
are physically connected to the cytoplasm. The typical receptor is a protein, a folded
chain of amino acids. It includes at least three domains: an external docking region
for a hormone or other messenger, a component that spans the cell’s outer membrane,
and a “tail” that extends a distance into the cytoplasm. When a messenger binds to the
The texts 273
external site, this linkage induces a change in the shape of the cytoplasmic tail, thereby
facilitating the tail’s interaction with one or more information-relaying molecules in the
cytoplasm. These interactions in turn initiate cascades of further intracellular signalling.
Yet no one had a good explanation for how communiqués reached their destination
without being diverted along the way. At that time, cells were viewed as balloonlike bags
filled with a soupy cytoplasm containing floating proteins and organelles (membrane-
bound compartments, such as the nucleus and mitochondria). It was hard to see how, in
such an unstructured milieu, any given internal messenger molecule could consistently
and quickly find exactly the right tag team needed to convey a directive to the laborers
deep within the cell that could execute the order.
Today’s fuller understanding grew in part from efforts to identify the first cytoplas-
mic proteins that are contacted by activated (messenger-bound) receptors in a large and
important family: the receptor tyrosine kinases. These vital receptors transmit the com-
mands of many hormones that regulate cellular replication, specialization or metabolism.
They are so named because they are kinases – enzymes that add phosphate groups to
(“phosphorylate”) selected amino acids in a protein chain. And, as Tony R. Hunter of the
Salk Institute for Biological Sciences in La Jolla, Calif., demonstrated, they specifically
put phosphates onto the amino acid tyrosense.
In the 1980s work by Joseph Schlessinger of New York University and others indicated
that the binding of hormones to receptor tyrosine kinases at the cell surface causes
the individual receptor molecules to cluster into pairs and to attach phosphates to the
tyrosines on each other’s cytoplasmic tails. In trying to figure out what happens next,
one of us (Pawson) and his colleagues found that the altered receptors interact directly
with proteins that contain a molecule they called an SH2 domain. The term “domain”
or “module” refers to a relatively short sequence of about 100 amino acids that adopts
a defined three-dimensional structure within a protein.
At the time, prevailing wisdom held that messages were transmitted within cells pri-
marily through enzymatic reactions, in which one molecule alters a second without
tightly binding to it and without itself being altered. Surprisingly, though, the phospho-
rylated receptors did not necessarily alter the chemistry of the SH2-containing proteins.
Instead many simply induced the SH2 domains to latch onto the phosphate-decorated
tyrosines, as if the SH2 domains and tyrosenes were Lego blocks being snapped together.
issued from the lowest octave of a cathedral pipe organ gave way to plaintive moans and
then to glissandos like air squealing out of a balloon when you stretch the neck taut.
With the notes building into phrases and the phrases into repeated themes, the song
may be the longest – up to 30 minutes – and the most complex in the animal kingdom.
All the humpbacks in a given region sing the same song, which is constantly evolving.
Experts have analyzed the frequencies, rhythms, and harmonics and the way themes
change from year to year and vary from one population to the next. Yet no one really
understands what these intricate arias are about.
We do know that humpbacks are found in every ocean. Together with blue, fin, sei,
Bryde’s, and mink whales, they belong to the rorqual family of baleen whales. Fully
grown females, which are bulkier than the males, can weigh 40 tons and reach lengths
of 50 feet.
Humpbacks tend to favor shallow areas, often quite close to shore, and they are among
the most sociable of the great whales and the most active at the surface, all of which
makes them among the easiest to observe. As a result, we know more about them than
about any other large whale. But we still don’t know a lot.
One thing the experts are certain of is that this species, depleted by whaling and
not protected throughout its range until 1966, is showing signs of a comeback. Early
population estimates are unreliable, and recent ones are hard to get, but numbers in the
North Atlantic seem to have rebounded from a few thousand to between 10,000 and
12,000. The North Pacific population was thought to have tumbled from 15,000 to fewer
than 2,000. That group stands at 5,000 to 8,000 today.
Knowing I was eager to absorb what biologists have been discovering about hump-
backs and their ongoing recovery, Darling, director of the West Coast Whale Research
Foundation in Vancouver, British Columbia, brought me along to Hawaii.
Since the singer beneath the boat didn’t seem bothered by our company, Darling asked
his longtime research partner, photographer Flip Nicklin, who often serves as Darling’s
eyes underwater, to slip overboard. I followed.
found throughout the world, these ants have completely lost the ability to care for them-
selves. The workers do not forage for food, feed the young or the queen, or even clean up
their own nest. To survive, Polyergus ants must get workers from the related ant genus
Formica to do their chores for them. Thus, Polyergus workers periodically undertake
a slave raid in which about 1,500 of them travel up to 150 meters (492 feet), enter a
Formica nest, expel the Formica queen and workers, and capture the pupae.
Back at the Polyergus nest, slaves rear the raided brood until the young emerge.
The newly hatched Formica workers then assume all responsibility for maintaining the
mixed-species nest. They forage for nectar and dead arthropods, regurgitate food to
colony members, remove wastes and excavate new chambers. When the population be-
comes too large for the existing nest, it is the 3,000 or so Formica slaves that locate
another site and physically transport the approximately 2,000 Polyergus workers,
together with eggs, larvae, pupae and even the queen, to the new nest.
The Railroad
The Information Revolution is now at the point at which the Industrial Revolution was
in the early 1820s, about forty years after James Watt’s improved steam engine (first
installed in 1776) was first applied, in 1785, to an industrial operation – the spinning of
278 Appendix A
cotton. And the steam engine was to the first Industrial Revolution what the computer
has been to the Information Revolution – its trigger, but above all its symbol. Almost
everybody today believes that nothing in economic history has ever moved as fast as,
or had a greater impact than, the Information Revolution. But the Industrial Revolution
moved at least as fast in the same time span, and had probably an equal impact if
not a greater one. In short order it mechanized the great majority of manufacturing
processes, beginning with the production of the most important industrial commodity of
the eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries: textiles. Moore’s Law asserts that the price
of the Information Revolution’s basic element, the microchip, drops by 50 percent every
eighteen months. The same was true of the products whose manufacture was mechanized
by the first Industrial Revolution. The price of cotton textiles fell by 90 percent in the
fifty years spanning the start of the eighteenth century. The production of cotton textiles
increased at least 150-fold in Britain alone in the same period. And although textiles
were the most visible product of its early years, the Industrial Revolution mechanized
the production of practically all other major goods, such as paper, glass, leather, and
bricks. Its impact was by no means confined to consumer goods. The production of
iron and ironware – for example, wire – became mechanized and steam-driven as fast
as did that of textiles, with the same effects on cost, price, and output. By the end of
the Napoleonic Wars the making of guns was steam-driven throughout Europe; cannons
were made ten to twenty times as fast as before, and their cost dropped by more than two
thirds. By that time Eli Whitney had similarly mechanized the manufacture of muskets
in America and had created the first mass-production industry.
among reeds, dragons, and of fish. The carving and incising was a highly developed
skill and must have been carried out by craftsmen specially trained in this work. Were
this not the case it would be almost impossible to account for the consistency in design,
the fluency of line and the almost unequalled high quality.
(k) Fragment from The pride of the cities, by Peter Beinart, New Republic,
June 1997
Michael White, the mayor of Cleveland, is a Democrat, an African American and the son
of a union activist. And he is at war with his party. First, he backed an end to forced busing.
Then, he supported Republican Governor George Voinovich’s radical school choice law,
which offers students vouchers at parochial as well as private schools. Then, he made
city workers compete against private firms for garbage collection, road maintenance
and other contracts, prompting union officials to walk out of a speech he gave at the
Democratic National Convention. Now, he’s allied with the governor again, backing a
bill by two Republican State legislators to grant him control over Cleveland’s desti-
tute school system and the authority to get “rid of any people who aren’t directly tied to
the direct education of children.” Arrayed against him: the teachers’ union, the NAACP
and just about every elected Democrat in the city of Cleveland.
For a big-city mayor to be so at odds with his party would seem peculiar. Except
that it’s happening everywhere. Mike White got the idea to take over the schools from
Richard Daley, the Democratic mayor of Chicago, who battled the municipal unions
and his own party’s nominee for governor, and two years ago won the right to introduce
radical reforms to the management of Chicago’s public schools. And White learned
about the introduction of competition into city services in part from a study trip he
and his staff took to Indianapolis, where Republican Mayor Steven Goldsmith has
reduced city bureaucracy so radically that he’s angered both patronage-minded GOP
officials and the traditional pro-Republican police unions. Goldsmith is also viewed as
a “kindred spirit” by Mayor John Norquist of Milwaukee, a Democrat who, for the sin
of supporting Republican Governor Tommy Thompson’s welfare and school choice re-
forms, has made himself persona non grata with his city’s public employee unions, the
NAACP and the Democratic speaker of the House of Representatives.
It goes on. Los Angeles Mayor Richard Riordan, whose support for affirmative
action, gay rights and Senator Dianne Feinstein has led GOP Californians to dub him
a RNO (Republican in Name Only), journeyed to Indianapolis during his first week in
office and cited Goldsmith in his inaugural address. And Rudolph Giuliani, the Mario
Cuomo-endorsing, illegal-immigrant defending, New York Republican who recently
admitted that ideologically he is a “moderate Democrat,” has met with Goldsmith on
four separate occasions. Giuliani and Riordan also received pre-inauguration seminars
from Philadelphia Mayor Ed Rendell, a Democrat, who, like Mike White, forced city
employees to compete for contracts with outside firms, outraging municipal unions and
most of his party.
Something interesting is happening here. Over the past five years or so, a half dozen
Democratic and Republican mayors have come together in what an aide to one calls
“an informal network.” They speak to each other regularly, they cite each other without
prompting, they copy each other’s initiatives. In almost every case, they represent a
radical break with their predecessors in office, and that break is largely about managing
280 Appendix A
city government efficiently in the public interest rather than using it as a mechanism for
arbitrating competing group interests. The new mayors are hugely popular: Mike White,
Richard Daley, Steven Goldsmith, John Norquist, Richard Riordan and Ed Rendell have
all been re-elected by wide margins, and Rudy Giuliani will almost certainly follow
suit this fall. But they are outsiders in their own parties, viewed with suspicion and
even contempt by the parties’ most powerful constituencies. To explain their success
and their iconoclasm, the press often dubs them pragmatists. But that misses the point.
They have an ideology: that cities can dramatically alleviate seemingly endemic urban
afflictions without a massive redistribution of wealth, that the way to achieve this is by
using competition to make city services radically more efficient, and that cities must
tolerate diverse identities without celebrating them to the detriment of a shared sense
of public interest. These ideas have a coherence and a history. They just don’t have a
party, yet.
The history is progressivism. At the turn of the last century, America’s cities were a
scandal. The squalor, pathology and cultural transformation to which mass immigration
had given rise shocked and terrified the native-born middle class. And, as outraged as
they were by the immigrants themselves, respectable people were even more hostile
to the municipal regimes the immigrants spawned. As Andrew White, the president of
Cornell, wrote in the journal Forum in 1890, “the city governments of the United States
are the worse in Christendom.”
The political machines that men like White despised had been created to bridge the
material and cultural distance separating the immigrants from native society. In cities that
offered newcomers few formal services, and in which the private sector often remained
closed, the immigrant-driven city machines supplied housing, fuel, charity and – most
importantly – jobs. Under machine leadership, America’s cities built roads, sewers,
streetlights and railcars at a furious pace, usually with little attention to the projects’
cost-effectiveness, creating as many jobs as possible and distributing them to appease
different constituencies. As Kenneth Fox notes in Better City Government, his history of
that era, America’s big cities in 1880 spent more than twice as much per capita as did the
federal government. And the machines appealed to the immigrants symbolically as well
as materially, installing ward leaders and aldermen who looked and talked like them,
and defending their traditions against a disapproving native middle class that wanted
to close down the immigrants’ saloons and their dance halls – and bust their corrupt,
powerful machines.
Threading 35 lane-miles of tunnel through Boston’s 3-D maze of subway lines and
building foundations, all without drastically disturbing the normal routines of surface
life, is an engineering plan that borders on the fantastic. In some places the tunnels are
120 feet deep. In some particularly delicate places the road-work passes within just a few
feet of skyscraper foundations or beneath construction projects. The first two frequently
asked questions on the project’s official Web site are “What are you building?” and “Are
you nuts?”
Surprisingly, tunnels are among the most ancient engineering feats. The earliest were
very likely extensions of prehistoric cave dwellings. The Babylonians, in the twenty-
second century BC, built a masonry tunnel beneath the Euphrates River that connected
the royal palace with a major temple. The Egyptians, using copper-bladed saws, exca-
vated long passageways and intricate rooms inside soft-rock cliffs. The Romans built
an elaborate network of above- and below-ground acqueducts to carry water. And
they tunneled through solid rock by repeatedly heating it with fire and then cooling
it with water, causing the rock face to fracture. The greatest of those acqueduct tunnels,
which eventually drained Lake Fucino in central Italy, stretched more than three miles
underground.
By the 1700s, tunnels were increasingly being constructed for use with canal systems.
In the history of freight transportation, prior to the invention of the railroad, canals proved
the most logical way to ship material over great distances. Sections of the canals often
need to be buried beneath ground, and this was accomplished with long open trenches
that were dug down from the surface, faced with masonry, then covered over. Canals
of extraordinary length were built in this manner, including the longest in the United
States, the 729-feet Union Canal Tunnel in Pennsylvania.
About the same time, an important hard-rock blasting technique was developed using
explosives. Dynamite was something new, and it gave engineers their most powerful
tool for tunneling through hillsides that couldn’t be opened by digging from above.
One of the most famous – and costly – early examples of a corridor blasted with
dynamite is the Hoosac Tunnel, in the Berkshire Mountains of Western Massachusetts.
Started in 1851, the Hoosac was a desperate attempt to compete with the convenient
Hudson River transportation corridor. It was hoped that direct east–west rail service
would connect and help exploit the burgeoning centers that were springing up in the
Midwest and around the Great Lakes. The planned route had just one major problem:
a small mountain directly in its path, an obstacle that would require an unprecedented
tunnel almost five miles long. The Hoosac was the first commercial project to make
use of the powerful and extremely unstable explosive nitroglycerine. Its human toll
would be immense, as science-and-technology writer Fred Hapgood vividly describes:
“In those days hard-rock tunnels were dig by chiseling a hole, filling it with explosive,
lighting a fuse, running back behind a shield, waiting for the blast, then returning to
the heading to wedge reinforcing timers into place, shatter the “muck” with sledges,
and shovel it into muckcars for excavation. This cycle could be interrupted at any point
by falling rocks or machinery, collapsing timbers, unintended explosions, or a dozen
other species of industrial accident, including fire and floods. In 1867 a wooden house
built over a shaft caught fire and collapsed downward, killing all 13 in the shift working
below. The explosives killed constantly, year after year . . . Nearly 200 were killed on
the job.
282 Appendix A
The Hoosac Tunnel took 22 years and $21 million to complete. As with the Big
Dig, critics railed against the project for overruns, poor planning, and delays in the
construction schedule. But at 4.82 miles it was an engineering marvel and it remained
the longest tunnel in America until 1916. It never came close, though, to approaching
the economic expectations of its promoters.
The blasting technique used in the Hoosac’s construction remains basically the same
to this day. But during the final years of the Hoosac Tunnel’s construction, blasting
was enhanced by the safer technique of drilling, which British inventor George Law
developed in 1865. A hammer tool operated by an air-driven piston was quickly being
used to break up rock, which could then be excavated through horizontal shafts called
drifts, or lifted through vertical shafts that also provided ventilation and exhaust.
By the time of the rock drill and the great railroad tunnels, a Frenchman named Marc
Isambard Brunel had already solved another of tunneling’s great challenges: how to
excavate below water without mud and water seeping in and causing the opening to
collapse. Borrowing an idea from nature, Brunel recreated the action of a tiny marine
borer known as the shipworm, whose shell plates allow it to bore through timber and
push sawdust out behind as it goes along. Brunel’s tunnel shield, a giant iron frame, was
forced through soft soil by screw jacks while miners dug through shuttered openings in
the shield’s forward face. Excavated earth was transported back through the frame as it
slowly advanced. Brunel used his rectangular shield to complete the world’s first true
tunnel in 1843 in London, below the Thames River.
Within a few years such cutting shields would be made smaller, circular, and more
powerful. Many of them even made use of compressed air to keep water out while the
steel linings were being installed.
And it was these developments, taken together, that set the stage for one of the truly
remarkable achievements of the twentieth century, the construction of New York and
New Jersey’s Holland Tunnel.
He was a stout, tallish young man. The high colour of his cheeks pushed upwards even
to his forehead, where it scattered itself in a few formless patches of pale red; and on
his hairless face there scintillated restlessly the polished lenses and the bright gilt rims
of the glasses which screened his delicate and restless eyes. His glossy black hair was
parted in the middle and brushed in a long curve behind his ears where it curled slightly
beneath the groove left by his hat. When he had flicked lustre into his shoes he stood
up and pulled his waistcoat down more tightly on his plump body. Then he took a coin
rapidly from his pocket.
“O Lily,” he said, thrusting it into her hands, “it’s Christmastime, isn’t it? Just . . .
here’s a little . . .” He walked rapidly towards the door.
“O no, sir!” cried the girl, following him. “Really, sir, I wouldn’t take it.”
“Christmas-time! Christmas-time!” said Gabriel, almost trotting to the stairs and
waving his hand to her in deprecation. The girl, seeing that he had gained the stairs,
called out after him: “Well, thank you, sir.”
He waited outside the drawing-room door until the waltz should finish, listening to
the skirts that swept against it and to the shuffling of feet. He was still discomposed by
the girl’s bitter and sudden retort. It had cast a gloom over him which he tried to dispel
by arranging his cuffs and the bows of his tie. He then took from his waistcoat pocket a
little paper and glanced at the headings he had made for his speech. He was undecided
about the lines from Robert Browning, for he feared they would be above the heads of
his hearers. Some quotation that they would recognize from Shakespeare or from the
Melodies would be better. The indelicate clacking of the men’s heels and the shuffling
of their soles reminded him that their grade of culture differed from his. He would only
make himself ridiculous by quoting poetry to them which they could not understand.
They would think that he was airing his superior education. He would fail with them
just as he had failed with the girl in the pantry. He had taken up a wrong tone. His whole
speech was a mistake from first to last, an utter failure.
(n) Let teenagers try adulthood, by Leon Botstein, New York Times, May 1999
The national outpouring after the Littleton shootings has forced us to confront something
we have suspected for a long time: the American high school is obsolete and should be
abolished. In the last month, high school students present and past have come forward
with stories about cliques and the artificial intensity of a world defined by insiders and
outsiders, in which the insiders hold sway because of superficial definitions of good
looks and attractiveness, popularity and sports prowess.
The team sports of high school dominate more than student culture. A community’s
loyalty to the high school system is often based on the extent to which varsity teams
succeed. High school administrators and faculty members are often former coaches, and
the coaches themselves are placed in a separate, untouchable category. The result is that
the culture of the inside elite is not contested by the adults in the school. Individuality
and dissent are discouraged.
But the rules of high school turn out not to be the rules of life. Often the high school
outsider becomes the more successful and admired adult. The definitions of masculinity
and femininity go through sufficient transformations to make the game of popularity in
high school an embarrassment. No other group of adults young or old is confined to
284 Appendix A
an age-segregated environment, much like a gang in which individuals of the same age
group define each other’s world. In no workplace, not even in colleges or universities,
is there such a narrow segmentation by chronology.
Given the poor quality of recruitment and training for high school teachers, it is no
wonder that the curriculum and the enterprise of learning hold so little sway over young
people. When puberty meets education and learning in modern America, the victory
of puberty masquerading as popular culture and the tyranny of peer groups based on
ludicrous values meets little resistance.
By the time those who graduate from high school go on to college and realize what
is really at stake in becoming an adult, too many opportunities have been lost and
too much time has been wasted. Most thoughtful young people suffer the high school
environment in silence and in their junior and senior years mark time waiting for col-
lege to begin. The Littleton killers, above and beyond the psychological demons that
drove them to violence, felt trapped in the artificiality of the high school world and
believed it to be real. They engineered their moment of undivided attention and impor-
tance in the absence of any confidence that life after high school could have a different
meaning.
Adults should face the fact that they don’t like adolescents and that they have used
high school to isolate the pubescent and hormonally active adolescent away from both
the picture-book idealized innocence of childhood and the more accountable world of
adulthood. But the primary reason high school doesn’t work anymore, if it ever did, is
that young people mature substantially earlier in the late 20th century than they did when
the high school was invented. For example, the age of menstruation has dropped at least
two years since the beginning of this century and not surprisingly, the onset of sexual
activity has dropped in proportion. An institution intended for children in transition now
holds young adults back well beyond the developmental point for which high school
was originally designed.
Furthermore, whatever constraints to the presumption of adulthood among young
people may have existed decades ago have now fallen away. Information and images, as
well as the real and virtual freedom of movement we associate with adulthood, are now
accessible to every 15- and 16-year-old.
Secondary education must be re-thought. Elementary school should begin at age 4 or
5 and end with the sixth grade. We should entirely abandon the concept of the middle
school and junior high school. Beginning with the seventh grade, there should be four
years of secondary education that we may call high school. Young people should graduate
at 16 rather than 18.
They could then enter the real world, the world of work or national service, in which
they would take a place of responsibility along with older adults in mixed company. They
could stay at home and attend junior college, or they could go away to college. For all the
faults of college, at least the adults who dominate the world of colleges, the faculty, were
selected precisely because they were exceptional and different, not because they were
popular. Despite the often cavalier attitude toward teaching in college, at least physicists
know their physics, mathematicians know and love their mathematics, and music is
taught by musicians, not by graduates of education schools, where the disciplines are
subordinated to the study of classroom management.
The texts 285
For those 16-year-olds who do not want to do any of the above, we might construct
new kinds of institutions, each dedicated to one activity, from science to dance, to which
adolescents could devote their energies while working together with professionals in
those fields.
At 16, young Americans are prepared to be taken seriously and to develop the moti-
vations and interests that will serve them well in adult life. They need to enter a world
where they are not in a lunchroom only with their peers, estranged from other age groups
and cut off from the game of life as it is really played. There is nothing utopian about this
idea; it is immensely practical and efficient, and its implementation is long overdue. We
need to face biological and cultural facts and not prolong the life of a flawed institution
that is out of date.
Appendix B: Glossary
Abstract entity: The class of situations, and discourse entities, that consists
of Facts and Propositions. They are licensed by clausal
complements of certain predicates. For instance, the clausal
complement of “I know that Mary refused the offer” refers
to a Fact; the clausal complement of “Mary’s refusing the
offer was unlikely” refers to a Proposition.
Accommodation: A type of inference in which the receiver infers the existence
of an entity if it is necessary to do so for coherence. For
instance on encountering the cat if no cat has been
introduced, one infers the existence of a cat.
Accomplishment: An event that is telic, durative, and dynamic, resulting in a
change of state, e.g. “John ate an apple,” “Mary walked to
school.”
Achievement: An event that is telic, instantaneous, and dynamic, resulting
in a change of state, e.g. “Mary won the race,” “John reached
the top.” Instantaneous events consist only of a single stage.
Activity: An event that is atelic, durative, and dynamic, e.g. “John
strolled in the park,” “Mary slept.”
Anaphora: The interpretation of a pronoun or tense that depends on an
antecedent for interpretation. For instance, in “John washed
himself,” “Mary said that she was ready,” the anaphor
himself and the pronoun she depend on the antecedent
proper names for interpretation.
Anaphoric Tense: The pattern of tense interpretation in which a time is
identified with an earlier time in the discourse. It is typical of
passages in the Description mode.
Aspectual viewpoint: Viewpoint makes visible for semantic interpretation all or
part of a situation. It is indicated by the simple and
progressive verb forms. The simple form conveys the
perfective viewpoint, making visible a bounded event or
state, as in “Mary talked to Bill.” “Kim was here.” The
progressive makes visible part of an ongoing event, as in
“Mary was talking to Bill.”
Background: Sentences can be partitioned into background and focus. The
background may consist of a topic phrase and other material,
286
Glossary 287
Abusch, Dorit, 1997. Sequence of tense & temporal de re. Linguistics & Philosophy 20:
1–50.
Acker, Liane, & Bruce Porter, 1994. Extracting viewpoints from knowledge bases.
Proceedings of the 12th National Conference on Artificial Intelligence. Menlo Park,
Calif.: 547–52.
Allen, James, 1983. Maintaining knowledge about temporal intervals. Communications
of the Association for Computing Machinery 26 (11): 832–43.
Allen, James, & C. Raymond Perrault, 1980. Analyzing intentions in utterances. Com-
putational Linguistics, 15: 143–78.
Ariel, Mira, 1989. Referring and accessibility. Journal of Linguistics 24: 65–87.
1990. Accessing Noun Phrase Antecedents. London: Routledge.
Arnold, Jennifer, Thomas Wasow, Anthony Losonoco, & Ryan Ginstrom, 2000.
Heaviness vs newness: The effects of structural complexity and discourse status on
constituent ordering. Language 76: 28–55.
Asher, Nicholas, 1993. Reference to Abstract Objects in Discourse. Dordrecht: Kluwer
Academic Publishers.
Asher, Nicholas, & Alex Lascarides, 1993. Temporal interpretation, discourse relations
and commonsense entailment. Linguistics & Philosophy 16: 437–94.
1998a. Bridging. Journal of Semantics 15: 83–113.
1998b. The semantics and pragmatics of Presupposition. Journal of Semantics 15:
239–99.
Bach, Emmon, 1981. On time, tense, and aspect: An essay in English metaphysics. In
P. Cole (ed.), Radical Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press.
Bach, Kent, 1999. The semantics–pragmatics distinction: What it is and why it matters.
In K. Turner (ed.), The Semantics–Pragmatics Interface from Different Points of
View. Oxford: Elsevier, pp. 65–84.
Bain, Alexander, 1877. English Composition and Rhetoric. London: Longmans.
Baker, Carl Lee, 1995. Contrast, discourse prominence, and identification, with special
reference to locally free reflexives in British English. Language 71: 63–101.
Baker, Mark, 1988. Incorporation. Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press.
Bal, Mieke, 1991. On Story-telling. Sonoma, Calif.: Polebridge Press.
Banfield, Ann, 1982. Unspeakable Sentences. Boston: Routledge & Kegan
Paul.
Barker, Chris, 2000. Definite possessives and discourse novelty. Theoretical Linguistics
26: 211–27.
294
References 295
Bartsch, R., 1976. Topik-Fokus-Struktur und Kategoriale Syntax. In V. Ehrich & P. Find
(eds.), Grammatik und Pragmatik. Kronberg: Scriptor Verlag.
Bechtel, William, & Arthur Abrahamsen, 1991. Connectionism and the Mind: An Intro-
duction to Parallel Processing in Networks. Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell.
Beekman, John, 1970. Propositions and theory relations within a discourse. Notes on
Translation 37: 6–23.
Benson, James, & William Greaves, 1992. Collocation and field of discourse. In
W. Mann & S. Thompson (eds.), Discourse Description: Diverse Linguistic
Analyses of a Fund-raising Text. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Bever, Thomas, 1970. The cognitive basis for linguistic structures. In J. R. Hayes (ed.),
Cognition and the Development of Language. New York: John Wiley.
Biber, Douglas, 1988. Variation across Speech and Writing. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
1989. A typology of English texts. Linguistics 27: 3–43.
Biber, Douglas, & Edward Finegan, 1989. Drift and the evolution of English style: A
history of three genres. Language 65: 487–517.
Birner, Betty, 1994. Information status and word order: An analysis of English inversion.
Language 70: 233–59.
1996. Form and Function in English By-phrase Passives. Proceedings of the Chicago
23rd Annual Meeting, Chicago Linguistic Society. Chicago, Ill.: Chicago Linguistic
Society.
Birner, Betty, & Gregory Ward, 1998. Information Status and Non-Canonical Word
Order in English. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Black, J. B., & Gordon Bower, 1980. Story understanding as problem solving. Poetics
9: 224–350.
Blakemore, Diane, 1988. The organization of discourse. In F. Newmeyer (ed.),
Linguistics: The Cambridge Survey, Vol. IV. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
1989. Denial and contrast: A relevance theoretic account of BUT. Linguistics &
Philosophy 12: 15–38.
Blass, Regina, 1990. Relevance Relations in Discourse. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Bolinger, Dwight, 1961. Contrastive accent and contrastive stress. Language 37: 83–96.
1972. Accent is predictable (if you’re a mind-reader). Language 48: 639–44.
1977. Meaning and Form. London: Longman.
Bond, S. J., & John Hayes, 1984. Cues people use to paragraph text. Research in the
Teaching of English 18: 147–67.
Bosch, P., & R. van der Sandt (eds.), Focus: Linguistic, Cognitive, and Computational
Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bower, G. H., J. B. Black, & T. J. Turner, 1979. Scripts in memory for text. Cognitive
Psychology, 2: 177–220.
Braddock, Richard, 1974. The frequency and placement of topic sentences in expository
prose. Research in the Teaching of English 8: 287–302.
Bransford, John, J. Richard Barclay, & Jeffery Franks, 1972. Sentence memory: A
constructive vs interpretive approach. Cognitive Psychology 3: 193–209.
296 References
Brennan, Susan E., 1995. Centering attention in discourse. Language & Cognitive
Processes, 10: 137–67.
Britton, James, Tony Burgess, Nancy Martin, Alex McLeod, & Harold Rosen, 1975.
The Development of Writing Abilities (11–18). London: Macmillan.
Brooks, Cleanth, & Robert Penn Warren, 1958. Modern Rhetoric. New York: Harcourt,
Brace & Company.
Brown, Gillian, & George Yule, 1983. Discourse Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Brown, Penelope, & Colin Fraser, 1982. Social markers in speech. In K. Scherer &
H. Giles (eds.), Advances in the Social Psychology of Language. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Bruder, Gail, & Janyce Wiebe, 1995. Recognizing subjectivity and identifying sub-
jective characters in third-person fictional narrative. In J. Duchan, G. Bruder, &
L. Hewitt (eds.), Deixis in Narrative: A Cognitive Science Approach. Hillsdale,
N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Büring, Daniel, 1999. Topic. In P. Bosch & R. van der Sandt (eds.), Focus: Linguistic,
Cognitive, and Computational Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Caenepeel, Mimo, 1989. Aspect, temporal ordering and perspective in narrative fiction.
Ph.D. thesis, University of Edinburgh.
1995. Aspect and text structure. Linguistics 33: 213–53.
1997. Putting while in context. Human Communication Research Centre, #RP-85.
Edinburgh: University of Edinburgh.
Caenepeel, Mimo, & Mark Moens, 1994. Temporal structure and discourse structure.
In C. Vet & C. Vetters (eds.), Tense and Aspect in Discourse. Berlin: Mouton de
Gruyter.
Caenepeel, Mimo & Görel Sandström, 1992. A discourse-level approach to the past
perfect in narrative. In M. Aurnague, A. Borillo, M. Borillo, and M. Bras (eds.),
Semantics of Time, Space, Movement and Spatio-temporal Reasoning. Toulouse:
Université Paul Sabatier.
Cairns, William B., 1902. The Forms of Discourse. Boston: Ginn & Co.
Cantrall, William, 1969. On the nature of the reflexive in English. Ph.D. dissertation,
University of Illinois.
Carlson, Greg, 1977. Reference to kinds in English. Ph.D. dissertation, University of
Massachusetts.
Carlson, Greg, & Geoffrey Pelletier, 1995. The Generic Book. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Chafe, Wallace, 1976. Given, contrastiveness, definiteness, subject, topics and point of
view. In Charles Li (ed.), Subject and Topic. New York: Academic Press.
1982. Integration and involvement in speaking, writing, and oral literature. In
D. Tannen (ed.), Spoken and Written Language: Exploring Orality and Literacy.
Norwood, N.J.: Ablex Publishing Company.
1987. Cognitive constraints on information flow. In R. Tomlin (ed.), Coherence and
Grounding in Discourse. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
1994. Discourse, Consciousness, and Time. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
References 297
Chafe, Wallace, & Joanna Nichols (eds.), 1986. Evidentiality: The Linguistic Coding of
Epistemology. Norwood, N.J.: Ablex Publishing Corporation.
Chierchia, Gennaro, 1992. Anaphora and dynamic binding. Linguistics & Philosophy
15: 111–83.
Chomsky, Noam, 1970. Remarks on nominalization. In R. Jacobs & P. Rosenbaum
(eds.), Readings in English Transformational Grammar. Waltham, Mass.: Ginn &
Co.
1971. Deep structure, surface structure and semantic interpretation. In D. Steinberg &
L. Jakobovits (eds.), Semantics: An Inter-Disciplinary Reader. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
1981. Lectures on Government and Binding. Dordrecht: Foris.
Christiansen, Francis. 1965. A generative rhetoric of the paragraph. College Composition
and Communication 15: 144–57.
Chu, Chauncy, 1983. A Reference Grammar of Mandarin for English Speakers. New
York: Peter Lang.
Cinque, G. 1999. Adverbs and Functional Heads: A Cross-linguistic Perspective.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Clancy, Patricia, 1980. Referential choice in English and Japanese narrative discourse.
In W. Chafe (ed.), The Pear Stories. Norwood, N.J.: Ablex.
Clark, Andy, 1989. Microcognition. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Clark, Herbert, 1973. Space, time, semantics, and the child. In T. Moore (ed.), Cognitive
Development and the Acquisition of Language. New York: Academic Press.
1996. Using Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cohan, Jocelyn, 2001. Reconsidering identificational focus. In M. Kim & U. Strauss
(eds.), Proceedings of the New England Linguistic Society 31. Amherst, Mass.:
GLSA, University of Massachusetts.
Cohn, Dorritt, 1978. Transparent Minds. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
Comrie, Bernard, 1976. Aspect. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
1983. Switch reference in Huichol: A typological study. In J. Haiman & P. Munro
(eds.), Switch Reference and Universal Grammar. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
1985. Tense. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Connors, Robert J., 1997. Composition–Rhetoric. Pittsburgh, Pa.: University of
Pittsburgh Press.
Corbett, Edward P., 1965. Classical Rhetoric for the Modern Student. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Couper-Kuhlen, Elizabeth, 1989. Foregrounding and temporal relations in narrative
discourse. In A. Schopf (ed.), Essays on Tensing in English, Vol. II. Tübingen:
Niemeyer.
Creider, Chet, 1979. On the explanation of transformations. In T. Givón (ed.), Discourse
and Syntax, Syntax & Semantics, 12. New York: Academic Press.
Croft, William, 1991. Syntactic Categories and Grammatical Relations: The Cognitive
Organization of Information. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Crothers, Edward, 1979. Paragraph Structure Inference. Norwood, N.J.: Ablex.
Culicover, Peter, 1997. Principles and Parameters: An Introduction to Syntactic Theory.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
298 References
Dahl, Oesten, 1974. Topic and comment structure revisited. In O. Dahl (ed.), Topic &
Comment, Contextual Boundedness and Focus, Papers in Text Linguistics, 6.
Hamburg: Buske.
Danasio, Antonio, 2002. Remembering when. Scientific American 287: 66–73.
Daneš, Frederik, 1974. Functional sentence perspective and the organization of the text.
In F. Daneš (ed.), Papers on Functional Sentence Perspective. Prague: Academia.
Davison, Alice, 1984. Syntactic markedness and the notion of sentence topic. Language
60: 797–846.
Davison, Alice, & Richard Lutz, 1985. Measuring syntactic complexity relative to
discourse. In D. Dowty (ed.), Natural Language Processing: Psycholinguistic,
Computational and Theoretical Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
de Beaugrande, Robert-Alain, & Wolfgang Dressler, 1981. Introduction to Text Linguis-
tics. London: Longman.
Delin, Judy, 1995. Presupposition and shared knowledge in It-clefts. Language and
Cognitive Processes 10: 97–120.
Delin, Judy, & Jon Oberlander, 1995. Syntactic constraints on discourse structure: the
case of It-clefts. Linguistics 33: 465–500.
Dendale, Patrick, & Liliane Tasmowski (eds.), 2001. Evidentiality and related notions:
Special issue. Journal of Pragmatics 33: 339–48.
de Swart, Henriette, 1993. Adverbs of Quantification: A Generalized Quantifier
Approach. New York: Garland Publications.
1998. Introduction to Natural Language Semantics. Stanford, Calif.: Center for the
Study of Language and Information Publications.
1999. Position and meaning: Time adverbials in context. In P. Bosch & R. van der Sandt
(eds.), Focus: Linguistics, Cognitive, and Computational Perspectives. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
van Dijk, Teun, 1972. Some Aspects of Text Grammars. The Hague: Mouton.
1977. Text and Context. London: Longman.
1982. Episodes as units of discourse analysis. In D. Tannen (ed.), Georgetown Uni-
versity Roundtable on Languages & Linguistics. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown
University Press.
van Dijk, Teun, & Walter Kintsch, 1983. Strategies of Discourse Comprehension. New
York: Academic Press.
Dowty, David, 1979. Word Meaning and Montague Grammar. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
1986. The effects of aspectual class on the temporal structure of discourse: Semantics
or pragmatics? Linguistics & Philosophy 9: 37–62.
1991. Thematic proto-roles and argument selection. Language 67: 547–619.
Dowty, David, Robert Wall, & Stanley Peters, 1981. Introduction to Montague Seman-
tics. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Duchan, Judith, Gail Bruder, & Lynne Hewitt (eds.), 1995. Deixis in Narrative: A
Cognitive Science Perspective. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum.
Dundes, Alan, 1975. Analytic Essays in Folklare. The Hague: Mouton.
Eggins, Suzanne, 1994. Introduction to Systemic Functional Linguistics. London: Pinter
Publishers.
References 299
Enç, Murvet, 1986. Towards a referential analysis of temporal expressions. Linguistics &
Philosophy 9: 405–26.
1987. Anchoring conditions for tense. Linguistic Inquiry 18: 633–57.
1991. Tense and modality. In S. Lappin (ed.), The Handbook of Contemporary
Semantic Theory. Oxford: Blackwell.
Erbaugh, Mary, 1986. Taking stock: The development of Chinese noun classifiers. In
C. Craig (ed.), Noun Classes and Categorization. Philadelphia: Benjamins.
Erteschik-Shir, Nomi, 1979. Discourse constraints on dative movement. In T. Givón
(ed.), Discourse and Syntax, Syntax and Semantics, 12. New York: Academic
Press.
1997. The Dynamics of Focus Structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Erteschik-Shir, Nomi, & Sheldon Lappin, 1979. Dominance and the functional expla-
nation of island phenomena. Theoretical Linguistics 6: 41–85.
Erteschik-Shir, Nomi, & Tova Rapoport, in press. Bare aspect: A theory of syntactic
projection. In J. Guéron and J. Lacarme (eds.), The Syntax of Time. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
Fabricius-Hansen, Cathrine, & Bergljot Behrens, 2000. Elaboration and related discourse
relations viewed from an interlingual perspective. In Proceedings of the Third
Workshop on Text Structure. Austin, Tex.: Department of Linguistics, University
of Texas.
Faigley, Lester, & Paul Meyer, 1983. Rhetorical theory and readers’ classification of
text types. Text 3: 305–25.
Fauconnier, Gilles, 1985. Mental Spaces: Aspects of Meaning Construction in Natural
Language. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Reprinted 1994, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Fauconnier, Gilles, & Eve Sweetser (eds.), 1996. Spaces, World, and Grammar. Chicago,
Ill.: University of Chicago Press.
Ferro, Lisa, 1993. On “self ” as a focus marker. In Michael Bernstein (ed.), Proceedings of
the Ninth Eastern States Conference on Linguistics. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University
Department of Modern Languages and Linguistics.
Fillmore, Charles, 1975. Santa Cruz Lectures on Deixis. Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana
University Linguistics Club.
von Fintel, Kai, 1994. Restrictions on quantifier domains. Ph.D. dissertation, Mas-
sachusetts Institute of Technology.
Firbas, Jan, 1964. On defining the theme in functional sentence analysis. Travaux de
Circle Linguistique de Prague 1: 267–80.
1974. Some aspects of the Czechoslovak approach to functional sentence perspective.
In F. Daneš (ed.), Papers on Functional Sentence Perspective. Prague: Academia.
1992. Functional Sentence Perspective in Written and Spoken Communication.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Flashner, Vanessa, 1987. The grammatical marking of theme in oral Polish narra-
tive. In R. Tomlin (ed.), Coherence and Grounding in Discourse. Amsterdam:
Benjamins.
Fleischman, Suzanne, 1991. Verb tense and point of view in narrative. In S. Fleischman &
L. Waugh (eds.), Discourse-Pragmatics and the Verb. London: Routledge.
300 References
Forster, Kenneth, 1979. Levels of processing and the structure of the language processor.
In W. E. Cooper & E. C. T. Walker (eds.), Sentence Processing: Psycholinguistic
Studies Presented to Merrill Garrett. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Fox, Barbara, 1987a. Anaphora in popular English written narratives. In R. Tomlin (ed.),
Coherence and Grounding in Discourse. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
1987b. Discourse Structure and Anaphora in Written and Conversational English.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Frank, Anette, & Hans Kamp, 1997. On context dependence in modal constructions. In
A. Lawson (ed.), SALT VII. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University.
Frantz, Donald, 1966. Person indexing in Blackfoot. International Journal of American
Linguistics, 32: 50–58.
Freksa, C., 1992. Using orientation information for qualitative spatial reasoning. In
M. Aurnague et al. (eds.), Semantics of Time, Space, Movement and Spatio-temporal
Reasoning. Toulouse: Université Paul Sabatier.
Friedman, William, 1993. About Time. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Fries, Peter, 1983. On the status of theme in English: Arguments from discourse. In
J. Petöfi & E. Sözer (eds.), Micro and Macro Connexity in Texts. Hamburg: Helmut
Buske.
Fuller, Daniel, 1959. The Inductive Method of Bible Study, 3rd edition. Pasadena: Fuller
Theological Seminary.
Galbraith, Mary, 1995. Deictic shift theory and the poetics of involvement in narrative. In
J. Duchan, G. Bruder, & L. Hewitt (eds.), Deixis in Narrative: A Cognitive Science
Approach. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Garnham, Alan, 1983. What’s wrong with story grammars? Cognition 15: 145–54.
1985. Psycholinguistics. London: Methuen.
1987. Mental Models as Representation of Discourse and Text. Chichester: Ellis
Horwood.
Garnham, Alan, & Jane Oakhill, 1989. The everyday use of anaphoric expressions:
Implications for the “mental models” theory of text comprehension. In N. E.
Sharkey (ed.), Modelling Cognition: An Annual Review of Cognitive Science, Vol. I.
Norwood, N.J.: Ablex.
Garrod, Simon, & Anthony Sanford, 1985. On the real-time character of interpretation
during reading. Language & Cognitive Processes 1: 43–61.
1994. Resolving sentences in a discourse context. In M. A. Gernsbacher (ed.), Hand-
book of Psycholinguistics. New York: Academic Press.
Gazdar, Gerald, Ewan Klein, Geoffrey Pullum, & Ivan Sag, 1985. Generalized Phrase
Structure Grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.
Gelman, Rachel, 1990. First principles organize attention to and learning about rele-
vant data: Number and the animate/inanimate distinction. Cognitive Science 14:
79–106.
Genette, Gérard, 1980. Narrative Discourse: An Essay in Method. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell
University Press.
Genung, John F., 1900. The Working Principles of Rhetoric. Boston: Ginn & Co.
Giora, Rachel, 1983. Functional sentence perspective. In J. Petöfi & E. Sözer (eds.),
Micro and Macro Connexity in Texts. Hamburg: Helmut Buske.
References 301
Giorgi, Alessandra, & Fabio Pianesi, 1991. Towards a syntax of temporal representations.
Probus 2: 187–213.
1997. Tense and Aspect. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Givón, Talmy, 1979. From discourse to syntax: Grammar as a processing strategy. In
T. Givón (ed.), Discourse and Syntax, Syntax and Semantics, 12. New York:
Academic Press.
1983. Topic continuity in discourse: An introduction. In T. Givón (ed.), Topic Conti-
nuity in Discourse: A Quantitative Cross-Language Study. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
1993. The pragmatics of de-transitive voice: Functional and typological aspects of
inversion. In T. Givón (ed.), Voice and Inversion. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Glenberg, A. M., M. Mayer, & K. Linden, 1987. Mental models contribute to fore-
grounding during text interpretation. Journal of Memory & Language 26: 69–83.
Goddard, Ives, 1990. Aspects of the topic structure of Fox narratives: Proximate shifts
and the use of overt and inflectional NPs. International Journal of American Lin-
guistics 56: 317–40.
Goldberg, Adele, 1995. Constructions. Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press.
Gordon, Peter, & Davina Chan, 1995. Pronouns, passives, and discourse coherence.
Journal of Memory & Language 34: 216–31.
Gough, Philip, 1965. Grammatical transformations and speed of understanding. Journal
of Verbal Learning & Verbal Behavior 5: 107–11.
Goutsos, Dionysis, 1997. Modeling Discourse Topic: Sequential Relations and Strate-
gies in Expository Texts. Norwood, N.J.: Ablex.
Graesser, Arthur, 1981. Prose Comprehension Beyond the Word. New York: Springer.
Green, Georgia, 1974. Semantics and Syntactic Regularity. Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana
University Press.
Grice, H. P., 1975. Logic and conversation. In P. Cole & J. Morgan (eds.), Speech Acts,
Syntax and Semantics, 3. New York: Academic Press.
1989. Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Grimes, Joseph, 1975. The Thread of Discourse. The Hague: Mouton.
Grimshaw, Jane, 1990. Argument Structure. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Groenendijk, Jeroen, & Martin Stokhof, 1991. Dynamic predicate logic. Linguistics &
Philosophy 14: 39–100.
Gropen, J., S. Pinker, S. Hollander, R. Goldberg, & R. Wilson, 1989. The learnability
and acquisition of the dative alternation in English. Language 65: 203–55.
Grosz, Barbara, 1977. The representation and use of focus in dialogue understanding.
Tech Note, 15. Menlo Park, Calif.: Artificial Intelligence Center, SRI International.
Grosz, Barbara, & Candace Sidner, 1986. Attention, intensions, and the structure of
discourse. Computational Linguistics 12: 175–204.
Gruber, Jeffrey, 1965. Studies in Lexical Relations. Ph.D. dissertation, MIT. Reprinted
Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana University Linguistics Club.
Gundel, Jeannette, 1974. The role of topic and comment in linguistic theory. Ph.D. disser-
tation, University of Texas. Reprinted 1977, Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana University
Linguistics Club.
1998. Centering theory and a givenness hierarchy. In M. Walker, A. Joshi, & E. Prince
(eds.), Centering Theory in Discourse. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
302 References
1999. On different kinds of focus. In P. Bosch & R. van der Sandt (eds.), Focus:
Linguistic, Cognitive, and Computational Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Gundel, Jeannette, Nancy Hedberg, & Ron Zacharski, 1993. Cognitive status and the
form of referring expressions in discourse. Language 69: 274–307.
Gussenhoven, Carlos, 1983. Focus, mode and the nucleus. Journal of Linguistics 19:
377–417.
Gutwinski, Waldemar, 1976. Cohesion in Literary Texts. The Hague: Mouton.
Hagège, Claude, 1974. Les pronoms logophoriques. Bulletin de la Société de Linguis-
tique de Paris 69: 297–310.
Haiman, John, & Pamela Munro (eds.), Switch Reference and Universal Grammar.
Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Hajičová, Eva, 1971. Some remarks on presupposition. Prague Bulletin of Mathematical
Linguistics 17: 11–23.
Hajičová, Eva, & Petr Sgall, 1987. The ordering principle. Journal of Pragmatics 11:
435–54.
Hajičová, Eva, M. Cervenka, O. Leška, & Petr Sgall (eds.), 1995. Travaux du Cercle
Linguistique de Prague, nouvelle série, Vol. I. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Hajičová, Eva, Barbara Partee, & Petr Sgall, 1998. Topic-Focus Articulation, Tripartite
Structures, and Semantic Content. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Hale, Kenneth, & Samuel Jay Keyser, 1993. On argument stucture and the lexical expres-
sion of syntactic relations. In K. Hale & S. J. Kayser (eds.), The View from Building
20: Essays in Honor of Sylvan Bromberger. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Halliday, Michael A. K., 1967. Notes on transitivity and theme in English, Part II. Journal
of Linguistics 3: 199–244.
1992. Some lexicogrammatical features of the Aero Population Growth Text. In
W. Mann & S. Thompson (eds.), Discourse Description: Diverse Linguistic
Analyses of a Fund-raising Text. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Halliday, Michael A. K., & Ruqaiya Hasan, 1976. Cohesion in English. London:
Longman.
Hamburger, Käte, 1973. The Logic of Literature. Trans. Marilynn Rose. Bloomington,
Ind.: Indiana University Press.
Hannay, Mike, 1991. Pragmatic function assignment and word order variation in a
functional grammar of English. Journal of Pragmatics 16: 131–55.
Harris, Zellig, 1982. A Grammar of English on Mathematical Principles. New York:
Methuen.
Haviland, Susan, & Herbert Clark, 1974. What’s new? Acquiring new information as
a process in comprehension. Journal of Verbal Learning & Verbal Behavior 13:
512–21.
Hawkins, John, 1994. A Performance Theory of Order and Constituency. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Hearst, Marti, 1997. TextTiling: Segmenting text into multi-paragraph subtopic passages.
Computational Linguistics 23: 33–64.
Hedberg, Nancy, 1990. Discourse pragmatics and cleft sentences in English. Ph.D.
dissertation, University of Minnesota.
References 303
Heim, Irene, 1982. The semantics of definite and indefinite Nounphrases. Ph.D. disser-
tation, University of Massachusetts.
Herbst, Peter, 1956. The nature of facts. In A. Flew (ed.), Essays in Conceptual Analysis.
New York: MacMillan.
Heycock, Caroline, & Anthony Kroch. 1999. Pseudo-cleft connectedness: Implications
for the LF interface level. Linguistic Inquiry 30: 365–98.
Heyrich, Wolfgang, Fritz Neubauer, Janos Petöfi, & Erich Sözer (eds.), 1989. Connexity
and Coherence. Berlin: De Gruyter.
Hinds, John, 1977. Paragraph structure and pronominalization. Papers in Linguistics 10:
77–99.
1979. Organizational patterns in discourse. In T. Givón (ed.), Discourse and Syntax,
Syntax & Semantics, 12. New York: Academic Press.
Hinrichs, Erhard, 1986. Temporal anaphora in discourses of English. Linguistics &
Philosophy 9: 63–82.
Hirose, Yukio, 2000. Public and private self as two aspects of the speaker: A contrastive
study of Japanese and English. Journal of Pragmatics 32: 1623–56.
Hirschberg, Julia, 1991. A Theory of Scalar Implicature. New York: Garland Press.
Hobbs, Jerry, 1985. On the Coherence and Structure of Discourse. Report No. CSLI-
85–37. Stanford, Calif.: Center for the Study of Language and Information.
Hockett, Charles, 1958. A Course in Modern Linguistics. New York: Macmillan.
Hoey, Michael, 1991. Patterns of Lexis in Text. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hopper, Paul, 1979. Aspect and foregrounding in discourse. In T. Givón (ed.), Discourse
and Syntax, Syntax & Semantics, 12. New York: Academic Press.
Horn, Laurence, 1988. Pragmatic theory. In F. Newmeyer (ed.), Linguistic Theory:
Foundations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
1991. Given as new: When redundant information isn’t. Journal of Pragmatics 15:
305–28.
Hornstein, Norbert, 1990. As Time Goes By. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Hovy, Eduard, 1993. Automated discourse generation using discourse structure relations.
Artificial Intelligence 63: 341–85.
Hunston, S., & G. Thompson (eds.), 2000. Evaluation in Text. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Jackendoff, Ray, 1972. Semantic Interpretation in Generative Grammar. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
1987. The status of thematic relations in linguistic theory. Linguistic Inquiry 18:
369–411.
1990. Semantic Structures. Cambridge, Mass. MIT Press.
Jacobsen, William, 1967. Switch-reference in Hokan-Coahuiltecan. In D. Hymes &
W. Biddle (eds.), Studies in Southwestern Ethnolinguistics. The Hague: Mouton.
Jakobson, Roman, 1957. Shifters, verbal categories, and the Russian verb. In L. Waugh &
M. Halle (eds.), Russian and Slavic Grammar: Studies 1931–1981. Berlin: Mouton,
1984.
Jesperson, Otto, 1940. A Modern English Grammar on Historical Principles. London:
George Allen & Unwin.
1924/1965. The Philosophy of Grammar. New York: W. W. Norton.
304 References
Kratzer, Angelika, 1981. The notional category of modality. In H. Eikmeyer & H. Rieser
(eds.), Words, Worlds, and Contexts. Berlin: De Gruyter.
Kratzer, Angelika, 1995. Stage-level and individual-level predicates. In G. Carlson &
F. J. Pelletier (eds.), The Generic Book. Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago
Press.
Krifka, Manfred, 1989. Nominal reference, temporal constitution and quantification in
event semantics. In R. Bartsch et al. (eds.), Semantics and Contextual Expressions.
Dordrecht: Foris.
1991. A compositional semantics for multiple Focus constructions. In Proceedings
from Semantics and Linguistic Theory 1, Working Papers in Linguistics, 10. Ithaca,
N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
Krifka, Manfred, Francis J. Pelletier, Gregory Carlson, Alice ter Meulen, Gennaro
Chierchia, & Godehard Link, 1995. Genericity: An introduction. In G. Carlson &
F. J. Pelletier (eds.), The Generic Book. Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago
Press.
Kuno, Susumo, 1972. Functional sentence perspective. Linguistic Inquiry 3: 161–95.
1976. Subject, theme, and speaker’s empathy: A re-examination of relativization
phenomena. In C. Li (ed.), Subject and Topic. New York: Academic Press.
Kuno, Susumo, 1987. Functional Syntax: Anaphora, Discourse, and Empathy. Chicago,
Ill.: University of Chicago Press.
van Kuppevelt, Jan, 1995. Disourse structure, topicality, and questioning. Journal of
Linguistics 31: 109–47.
1996. Directionality in discourse: Prominence difference in subordination relations.
Journal of Semantics 13: 363–95.
Kuroda, Yuki, 1973. Where epistemology, grammar and style meet: A case study from
Japanese. In S. Anderson & P. Kiparsky (eds.), A Festschrift for Morris Halle. New
York: Holt, Rinehart Winston.
Labov, William, & Joshua Waletzky, 1966. Narrative analysis: Oral versions of personal
experience. In Essays on the Verbal and Visual Arts: Proceedings of the 1996
Annual Meeting, American Ethnological Society. Seattle: University of Washington
Press.
Lambrecht, Knud, 1986. Pragmatically motivated syntax: Presentational cleft construc-
tions in spoken French. In Proceedings of the 13th Annual Meeting, Chicago
Linguistic Society. Chicago, Ill.: Chicago Linguistic Society.
1994. Information Structure and Sentence Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Larson, Richard, 1984. Classifying discourse. In R. J. Connors, L. S. Ede, & A. Lunsford
(eds.), Essays on Classical Rhetoric and Modern Discourse. Carbondale: Southern
Illinois Press.
Lascarides, Alex, & Nicholas Asher, 1993. Temporal interpretation, discourse relations,
and commonsense entailment. Linguistics & Philosophy 16: 437–93.
Lee, Gregory, 1971. Subjects and Agents II. Working Papers in Linguistics, 7. Columbus,
Ohio: Department of Linguistics, Ohio State University.
Leška, Oldrich, 1995. Prague school teaching of the classical period and beyond. In
E. Hajičová, M. Cervenka, O. Leška, & P. Sgall (eds.), Travaux du Cercle
Linguistique de Prague, nouvelle série, Vol. I. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
306 References
Leslie, A. M., 1994. ToMM, ToBy, and Agency: Core architecture and domain speci-
ficity. In L. Hirschfield & S. Gelman (eds.), Mapping the Mind: Domain Specificity
in Cognition and Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Levin, Beth, 1993. English Verb Classes and Alternations. Chicago, Ill.: University of
Chicago Press.
Levinson, Stephen, 1979/1992: Activity types in language. Linguistics 17: 356–99.
2000. Presumptive Meanings. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Lewis, David, 1979. Scorekeeping in a language game. In R. Bauerle, U. Egli, & A. von
Stchow (eds.), Semantics from Different Points of View. Berlin: De Gruyter.
Li, Charles, & Sandra Thompson, 1976. Subject and topic: A new typology of language.
In C. Li (ed.), Subject and Topic. New York: Academic Press.
Linde, Charlotte, 1979. Focus of attention and choice of pronouns in discourse. In
T. Givón (ed.), Discourse and Syntax, Syntax & Semantics, 12. New York:
Academic Press.
1993. Life Stories: The Creation of Coherence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Litman, David, 1985. Plan recognition and discourse analysis: An integrated approach
for understanding dialogues. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Rochester.
Longacre, Robert, 1968. Discourse, Paragraph, and Sentence Structure in Selected
Philippine Languages. Santa Ana, Calif.: Summer Institute of Linguistics.
1979. The paragraph as a grammatical unit. In. T. Givón (ed.), Discourse and Syntax,
Syntax and Semantics, 12. New York: Academic Press.
1983/1996. The Grammar of Discourse. New York: Plenum Press.
1992. The discourse strategy of an appeals letter. In W. Mann & S. Thompson
(eds.), Discourse Description: Diverse Linguistic Analyses of a Fund-raising Text.
Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Loriot, James, & B. Hollenbach, 1970. Shipibo paragraph structure. Foundations of
Language 6: 43–66.
Lunsford, Andrea, & Lisa Ede, 1984. On distinctions between classical and modern
rhetoric. In R. J. Connors, L. Ede, & A. Lunsford (eds.), Essays on Classical
Rhetoric and Modern Discourse. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University
Press.
Lyons, John, 1977. Semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
1982. Deixis and subjectivity: Loquor, ergo sum? In R. J. Jarvella & W. Klein (eds.),
Speech, Place, and Action. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Mann, William, & Sandra Thompson, 1987. Rhetorical Structure Theory: A Theory
of Text Organization. ISI Reprint Series, ISI /RS-87–90. Marina Del Rey, Calif.:
Information Sciences Institute.
1992. Rhetorical Structure theory and text analysis. In W. Mann & S. Thompson
(eds.), Discourse Description: Diverse Linguistic Analyses of a Fund-raising Text.
Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
2000. Two Views of Rhetorical Structure Theory. Lyon, France: Society for Text and
Discourse.
Markels, Robin Bell, 1984. A New Perspective on Cohesion in Expository Paragraphs.
Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
Marr, David, 1982. Vision. San Francisco, Calif.: Freeman.
References 307
Oakhill, Jane, Alan Garnham, & Willem Vonk, 1989. The online construction of
discourse models. Language & Cognitive Processes 4: SI 263–86.
Ogihara, Toshiyuki, 1996. Tense, Attitude, and Scope. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Olman, Lynda, 1998. Evidence for iconicity: The instance relation in informational
exposition. MA thesis, University of Texas at Austin.
Palacas, Arthur, 1993. Attribution semantics: Linguistic worlds and point of view.
Discourse Processes 16: 239–77.
Palmer, Frank, 1983. Semantic explanations for the syntax of English modals. In
F. Heny & B. Richards (eds.), Linguistic Categories: Auxiliaries and Related
Puzzles, Vol. II. Dordrecht: Reidel.
1986. Mood and Modality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Parkes, M. B., 1993. Pause and Effect. Berkeley, Calif.: University of California
Press.
Parsons, Terence, 1990. Events in the Semantics of English. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.
Partee, Barbara, 1973. The syntax and semantics of quotation. In S. Anderson &
P. Kiparsky (eds.), A Festchrift for Morris Halle. New York: Holt, Rinehart &
Winston.
1984. Nominal and temporal anaphora. Linguistics & Philosophy 7: 243–86.
1987. Nounphrase interpretation and type-shifting principles. In J. Groenenjik, D. de
Jongh, & M. Stockhof (eds.), Studies in Discourse Representation theory and the
Theory of Generalized Quantifiers. Dordrecht: Foris.
1991. Topic, focus, and quantification. In S. Moore & A. Wyner (eds.), Proceedings
of SALT I. Ithaca, N.Y.: Department of Linguistics, Cornell University.
Penhallurick, John, 1984. Full-verb inversion in English. Australian Journal of
Linguistics 4: 33–56.
Peterson, Philip, 1997. Fact, Proposition, Event. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Pub-
lishers.
Petöfi, J. S., 1978. A few comments on the methodology of text theoretical research.
Journal of Pragmatics 2: 365–72.
Pierrehumbert, Janet, 1980. The phonology and phonetics of English intonation. Ph.D.
dissertation, MIT.
Polanyi, Livia, 1988. A formal model of the structure of discourse structure and
discourse. Journal of Pragmatics 12: 601–38.
Polinsky, Maria, 1996. Situation perspective: on the relations of thematic roles, discourse
categories, and grammatical relations to figure and ground. In A. Goldberg (ed.),
Conceptual Structure, Discourse, and Language. Stanford, Calif.: Center for the
Study of Language and Information Publications.
Porter, Bruce, et al., 1988. AI Research in the Context of a Multifunctional Knowledge
Base. AI Laboratory Report, 88–88. Austin, Tex.: University of Texas.
Portner, Paul, & Katsuhiko Yabushita, 1998. The semantics and pragmatics of topic
phrases. Linguistics & Philosophy 21: 117–57.
Prideaux, Gary, 1993. Subordination and information distribution in oral and written
narratives. Pragmatics & Cognition 1: 51–69.
Prince, Ellen, 1978a. Comparison of Wh-clefts and It-clefts in discourse. Language 54:
883–906.
References 309
Sperber, Dan, & Deirdre Wilson, 1986. Relevance: Communication and Cognition.
Oxford: Blackwell.
Stalnaker, Richard, 1978. Assertion. In P. Cole (ed.), Pragmatics, Syntax and Semantics,
9. New York: Academic Press.
Stark, Heather, 1988. What do paragraph markings do? Discourse Processes 11:
275–303.
Steedman, Mark, 2000. The Syntactic Process. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Stern, Arthur, 1976. When is a paragraph? College Composition and Communication
36: 253–57.
Stirling, Leslie, 1993. Switch-Reference and Discourse Representation. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Stoddard, Sally, 1991. Text and Texture: Patterns of Cohesion. Norwood, N.J.:
Ablex.
Stowell, Tim, 1996. The phrase structure of tense. In J. Rooryck & L. Zaring (eds.),
Phrase Structure and the Lexicon. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Strawson, Peter, 1964. Identifying reference and truth value. Theoreia 30: 96–118.
Reprinted in D. Steinberg & L. Jakobovits (eds.), 1971. Semantics. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Svarthvik, Jan, 1966. On Voice in the English Verb. The Hague: Mouton.
Swales, John, 1990. Genre Analysis: English in Academic and Research Settings.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Talmy, Leonard, 1978. Figure and ground in complex sentences. In J. Greenberg,
C. Ferguson, & E. Moravcsik (eds.), Universals of Human Language: Syntax.
Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
1985. Lexicalization patterns: Semantic structure in lexical forms. In T. Shopen (ed.),
Language Typology and Syntactic Description, Vol. III: Grammatical Categories
and the Lexicon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
2000. Towards a Cognitive Semantics. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Tannen, Deborah, 1989. Talking Voices. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tardieu, Hubert, Marie-France Ehrlich & Valérie Gyselinkck, 1992. Levels of repre-
sentation and domain-specific knowledge in comprehension of scientific texts.
Language & Cognitive Processes 7: 335–51.
Taylor, Barry, 1977. Tense and continuity. Linguistics & Philosophy 1: 199–220.
Thomason, Lucy, 1994. The assignment of proximate and obviative in informal Fox
narrative. Ms., The University of Texas at Austin.
Thompson, Ellen, 1999. The temporal structure of discourse: The syntax and semantics
of temporal then. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 17: 123–60.
Thompson, Geoff, & Susan Hunston, 2000. Evaluation: An introduction. In
S. Hunston & G. Thompson (eds.), Evaluation in Text: Authorial Stance and the
Construction of Discourse. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Thompson, Sandra, 1987. The passive in English: A discourse perspective. In
R. Chaman & L. Shockey (eds.), In Honor of I1se Lehiste. Dordrecht: Foris.
2001. “Object complements” and conversation: Towards a realistic account. To appear
in Studies in Language.
Thorndyke, P. W., 1977. Cognitive structures in comprehension and memory of narrative
discourse. Cognitive Psychology 9: 77–110.
312 References
Tomlin, Russell (ed.), 1987. Coherence and Grounding in Discourse. Amsterdam: John
Benjamins.
Tracy, H. P., & S. H. Levinsohn, 1977. Participant reference in Ica expository discourse.
In R. Longacre (ed.), Discourse Grammar, Part III. Dallas, Tex.: Summer Institute
of Linguistics.
Turner, Elizabeth, & Ragnar Rommetveit, 1968. Focus of attention in recall of active
and passive sentences. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 7: 543–48.
Vallduvı́, Enric, 1992. The Informational Component. New York: Garland Press.
Vallduvı́, Enric, & Elisabet Engdahl, 1996. The linguistic realization of information
packaging. Linguistics 34: 459–519.
Vallduvı́, Enric, & Maria Vilkuna, 1998. On rheme and kontrast. In P. Culicover &
L. McNally (eds.), The Limits of Syntax, Syntax and Semantics, 26. New York:
Academic Press.
Vendler, Zeno, 1957. Verbs and times. Philosophical Review 66: 143–60. Reprinted
in Vendler, 1967. Linguistics in Philosophy. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University
Press.
1967. Linguistics in Philosophy. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
1972. Res Cogitans: An Essay in Rational Psychology. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University
Press.
Venneman, Theodor, 1975. Topic, sentence accent, ellipsis: A proposal for their formal
treatment. In E. Keenan (ed.), Formal Semantics of Natural Language. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Verkuyl, Henk, 1972. On the Compositional Nature of the Aspects. Foundations of
Language Supplementary Series, Vol. XV. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Verstraete, Jean-Christophe, 2001. Subjective and objective modality: Interpersonal and
ideational functions in the English modal auxiliary system. Journal of Pragmatics
33: 1505–28.
Vlach, Frank, 1981. The semantics of the progressive. In P. Tedeschi & A. Zaenen (eds.),
Tense and Aspect, Syntax and Semantics, 14. Academic Press, New York.
Voegelin, C. F., & F. M. Voegelin, 1975. Hopi (-qa). International Journal of American
Linguistics 41: 381–98.
Vonk, Wietske, Lettica Hustinx, & Wim Simons, 1992. The use of referential expressions
in structuring discourse. Language & Cognitive Processes 7: 302–33.
Walker, Marilyn, Aravind Joshi, & Ellen Prince (eds.), 1998. Centering Theory in
Discourse. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Ward, Gregory, & Ellen Prince, 1991. On the topicalization of indefinite NPs. Journal
of Pragmatics 16: 167–77.
Whately, Richard, 1828/1963. Elements of Rhetoric. Carbondale, Ill.: Southern Illinois
Press.
Whorf, Benjamin L., 1956. Language, Thought and Reality: Selected Writings of
Benjamin Lee Whorf . New York: Wiley and Son.
Whitaker, Jeanne, & Carlota S. Smith, 1985. Some significant omissions: Ellipsis in
Flaubert’s “Un Coeur Simple.” Language, and Style 14: 251–92.
Wiebe, Janyce, 1991. Tracking point of view in narrative. Computational Linguistics
20: 233–87.
References 313
Abstract Entities 24, 78, 88 common ground, context set 49, 56, 191,
Facts 24, 74, 89 237
Propositions 24, 74, 89, 163 communication, expressions of 159
accent, accentuation 188, 193–95, 204, direct address 149, 162, 178
219 direct speech 149, 159, 178
accommodation, see inference indirect speech 160, 169–77, 211
adjunct preposing 228, 232, 233 quoted speech 159, 178
locative PPs 228 represented speech 161
temporal clauses 231 verbs of 161
advancement, temporal 14, 26–28, 30, 57, communicative dynamism 185, 187
93 complement clauses and abstract entities 78,
adverbials 104
durative adverbial, tacit 80, 96, 112, 212 communication verbs 104
locating 120 temporal interpretation 27, 69, 119, 120
anaphora 62, 150 composite 10, 57, 175
argument mode 20, 33–34, 37, 98, 252 compositional rules in DR Theory 82, 83, 84,
argument preposing 224 88, 123
aspectual systems 67, 70 condensed clauses 140, 230
attention 13, 25, 202 construction rules, see Discourse
Representation Theory
Background, see Foreground and Background Context 11, 105, 108
Bounded Event Constraint 76, 88, 102–3 continuity 112, 145, 149, 178
exceptions to 103 global continuity 13, 20, 198
Boundedness, bounded events 14, 26, 71, local continuity 13, 198
102–3 subjective 168
continuity tense interpretation, see tense
canonical sentences 13, 148, 187, 213 contrast and emphasis 205, 208
categorical sentences 195–96 alternatives 205
Centering Theory 13, 146, 193 oppositional contrast 198–208
Cleft constructions 24, 220
it-cleft 34, 219, 221 dative alternation 226
wh-cleft 219, 221 Deictic tense, see tense
closed system 13, 69, 100, 118, 132 deixis, deictic 17, 30, 128, 155
coercion 71, 86, 96, 118, 123 adverbs 101, 108, 160
coherence 45, 47 derived situation types, see situation type
cohesion 46 Description mode 20, 28, 36, 95, 248
lexical 46, 47, 265 discourse continuity 149, 178
commentary 33 discourse grammar 44–45
314
General index 315
Discourse Modes 39, 265 focus phrase 187, 201, 202, 203, 207, 212, 227
atemporal 25, 31, 58, 243 all-focus 202, 218
temporal 25, 30 argument focus 202
discourse relations 132, 253, 260 focus–background partition 185, 203,
formalization 263 209–10
inference 260 identificational 207
relational segment 261 informational 201, 207
SDRT 263 predicate focus 202
Discourse Representation Structure (DRS) 25, Focus Preposing 225
60–64, 86, 107, 112, 151 Foreground and Background 34
description fragment 112, 113 in narrative 35
narrative fragment 110 shifts 33, 35
subjectivity 169–77, 211 forms of discourse 38–39, 218
temporal 107 functional units 259
Discourse Representation Theory narrative 259
(DR Theory) 11, 55–57, 149
construction rules 57–58, 60, 107, 254 General Stative 24
discourse topic 197, 236–37 Generalizing 24, 72–73, 77, 87
dislocation 225, 226 Generic 24, 72, 77
duality 19, 80, 96, 186, 212 genre 9, 10, 41, 42
dynamism, dynamic/static 26, 27, 69, 75, 76, global continuity 13, 20, 198
120 grammatical terms 11
metaphorical motion, location 17, 18, 26, 31, Prague School 185, 188, 196, 209
32, 58, 123, 254 predominant entity
multi-clause sentences 233 presentation 13, 37, 212, 233
complex sentences 235 and grammar 5ßß
conjunction 235 in DRS 238
relative clauses 233 progression 13, 213, 244
patterns 245
Narrative mode 14, 19, 27, 33, 108, presupposition 24, 209, 213, 219, 231
247 pragmatic 53, 136, 221
advancement 26–28, 93, 235 semantic 53, 54
as background 36 Primary Referent 17, 19, 31, 123, 129
tense in narrative 26, 108 construction rules 130
non-canonical sentences 213, 215, 239 criteria 125–29
heaviness 216, 222, 227 states 125–27
normalization, complements 80–81, 96, 98, progression, see Presentation, progression; text
212 progression
noun classifiers 133 progressive 14, 27, 68, 69, 71, 72, 91, 120,
171
obviation, see pronoun prominent argument 129
order 187, 188 pronouns 11, 52, 132, 136
in a DRS 61
paragraphs 45, 56, 236–37 Locally Free Reflexives 137–40, 150
and discourse relations 236 empathy 138
partitioning 209 emphasis 139
dual 209, 211 intensive 139
focus–background 210 logophoric 135, 138
Link 210 null 140
passage 22, 105 parallel structure 146
passive 215, 217, 234 proximal–obviative 133, 134, 197
perception and subjectivity 27, 169, 170, reflexive 150, 161, 173
182 stressed 136–37
inferred perception 171, 182 switch reference 134, 141
perfect 24, 72, 100, 101 Propositions, see Abstract entities
perfective viewpoint 27, 68, 71, 91
Activity sentences 70, 96, 113 quantification test, for Abstract Entities 81
and narrative 93
perspectival subjectivity 172, 175, 182 Reference Time 93, 94, 95, 100, 104, 106,
deictic adverbials and 175 114
empathy 174 referring expressions 141, 147, 148, 149,
reflexives 173, 174 169–77, 187, 211
point of view 155, 171 accessibility 143, 150
poset, see linking cognitive status 144
position 192, 204, 214, 223, 227, 235 in DRT 149
pragmatics 50, 51, 58, 64, 94, 97, 123, 132, reflexives, see pronouns
136, 145, 158–80 Report mode 16, 20, 30, 36, 42, 97, 108,
and semantic meaning 50, 56, 127 250
and sentence topic 200 representations
constraint 103 in DR Theory 12
in DRS 56, 151 mental 55
General index 317
Responsible Source 13, 156, 158 modeled with subordination 156, 176
rhetoric objective sentences 157, 158
classical 38 scope 162, 168
modern 39, 238 syntax, syntactic 11, 53–59, 96, 239
rhetorical modes 40–42
Rhetorical Structure Theory 262 telic/atelic 76, 118
role 121 temporality 12
tense 26, 30, 92, 95, 99, 102, 105, 160
salience 146, 198–208 anaphora 97, 112
sentence Topic 13, 15, 19, 58, 187, 192, 197, continuity 28, 94–95, 108–10
207, 212, 216, 221, 225, 229, 234, 246, deictic pattern 95, 106, 113, 114
252, 253, 260 present 76
aboutness 189, 190 text
and grammatical voice 193 linguistics 45
identifying cues 198 units 9, 45
paraphrase tests 190 well- and ill-formed 44
sentences without topic 195 text progression 12
terminology 195–96 atemporal 132
topic–comment partition 185, 188, 209 presentational 19
unclear cases 200 temporal, see advancement
shifts, discourse mode 22, 34, 35, 38 text type 43–44
situation entities 12, 24, 67, 82 thematic role 31, 128
Situation Time 100, 102, 106 Experiencer 15
situation type 68, 69, 82, 83, 86 Theme/Patient 17, 58, 128, 130
derived 71, 85 Theme 189, 196
shifts, see coercion thetic sentences 195, 202
situations – classified 23–25, 69 time, temporality 12, 99
space, spatial 26, 58, 115 Topic, see sentence topic, discourse topic
spatial progression 26–28, 29 topicalization 225
specific situations 22, 32, 37
Speech Time 30, 99, 106, 121 unbounded situations 27, 71, 102–3, 125–29
State 71
static, see dynamism, dynamic/static variety in texts 8, 40
sub-interval property 71 verb constellation 23, 68, 72–73, 83
subjectivity 13, 58, 156, 162, 167, 244 viewpoint
construction, compositional rules 176, aspectual 68–69, 70, 82
178 in DRS 90
in fiction 157, 158–80 visible information 68, 71, 82, 124
lexical choice 156
linguistic forms 175 will auxiliary 30, 100, 121
Index of names
318
Index of names 319