Open navigation menu
Close suggestions
Search
Search
en
Change Language
Upload
Sign in
Sign in
Download free for days
0 ratings
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
3K views
Probability - An Introduction
Uploaded by
JANGJAE LEE
AI-enhanced title
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content,
claim it here
.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
Download now
Download
Save Probability_ an Introduction For Later
Download
Save
Save Probability_ an Introduction For Later
0%
0% found this document useful, undefined
0%
, undefined
Embed
Share
Print
Report
0 ratings
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
3K views
Probability - An Introduction
Uploaded by
JANGJAE LEE
AI-enhanced title
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content,
claim it here
.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
Download now
Download
Save Probability_ an Introduction For Later
Carousel Previous
Carousel Next
Save
Save Probability_ an Introduction For Later
0%
0% found this document useful, undefined
0%
, undefined
Embed
Share
Print
Report
Download now
Download
You are on page 1
/ 221
Search
Fullscreen
Probability an introduction Geoffrey Grimmett and | Dominic WelshProbability an introduction Geoffrey Grimmett School of Mathematics, University of Bristol Dominic Welsh Merton College, Oxford CLARENDON PRESS OXFORD 1986Oxford University Press, Walton Street, Oxford OX2 6DP_ Oxford New York Toronto Delhi Bombay Calcutta Madras Karachi Petaling Jaya Singapore Hong Kong Tokyo Nairobi Dar es Salaam Cape Town Melbourne Auckland and associated companies in Beirut Berlin Ibadan Nicosia Oxford is a trade mark of Oxford University Press Published in the United States by Oxford University Press, New York © Geoffrey Grimmett and Dominic Welsh, 1986 Alll rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Oxford University Press This book is sold subject to the condition that it shall not, by way of trade or otherwise, be lent, re-sold, hired out or otherwise circulated without the publisher's prior consent in any form of binding or cover other than that in which it is published and without a similar condition including this condition being imposed on the subsequent purchaser British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Grimmett, Geoffrey Probability: an introduction. 1. Probabilities 1. Title I. Welsh, Dominic 5192 QA273 ISBN 0-19-853272-5 ISBN 0-19-853264-4 (pbk.) Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Grimmett, Geoffrey. Probability: an introduction. Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Probabilities. I. Welsh, D.J.. A. __ IL. Title. QA273.G735 1986 519.2, 85-31035 ISBN 0-19-853272-5 ISBN 0-19-853264-4 (pbk.) Filmset and printed in Northern Ireland by The Universities Press (Belfast) Lid.Preface Probability and statistics are now taught widely in schools and are integral parts of many O-level and A-level syllabuses. Consequently the attitudes of universities towards these subjects have changed over the last few years and, at many universities, first-year mathematics students learn material which was previously taught in the third year only. This text is based upon first and second year courses in probability theory which are given at the Universities of Bristol and Oxford. Broadly speaking we cover the usual material, but we hope that our account will have certain special attractions for the reader and we shall say what these may be in a moment. The first eight chapters form a course in basic probability, being an account of events, random variables, and distributions—we treat discrete and continuous random variables separately—together with simple versions of the law of large numbers and the central limit theorem. There is an account of moment generating functions and their applications. The last three chapters are about branching processes, random walks, and continuous-time random pro- cesses such as the Poisson process; we hope that these chapters are adequate at this level and are suitable appetizers for courses in applied probability and random processes. We have deliberately omitted various topics which are crucial in more advanced treatments, such as the theory of Markov chains, and we hope that most critics will agree with such decisions. In the case of Markov chains, we could not justify to ourselves the space required to teach more than mere fragments of the theory. On the other hand we have included a brief treatment of characteristic functions in two optional sections for the more advanced reader. We have divided the text into three sections: (A) Probability, (B) Further Probability, and (C) Random Processes. In doing so we hope to indicate two things. First, the probability in Part A seems to us to be core material for first-year students, whereas the material in Part B is somewhat more difficult. Secondly, although random processes are collected together in the final three chapters, they may well be introduced much earlier in the course. The chapters on branching processes and random walks might well come after Chapter 5, and the chapter on continuous-time processes after Chapter 6. We have two major aims: to be concise and to be honest about mathematical rigour. Some will say that this book reads like a set ofvi Preface lecture notes. We would not regard this as entirely unfair; indeed a principal reason for writing it was that we believe that most students benefit more from possessing a compact account of the subject in 200 printed pages or so (at a suitable price) than a diffuse account of 400 pages. Most undergraduates learn probability theory by attending lec- tures, at which they normally take copious and occasionally incorrect notes; they may also attend tutorials and classes. Few are the under- graduates who learn probability in private by relying on a textbook as the sole, or even principal, source of inspiration and learning. Although some will say that this book is too difficult, it is the case that first-year students at many universities learn some quite difficult things, such as axiomatic systems in algebra and ¢/6 analysis, and we doubt if much of the material covered here is inherently more challenging than these. Also, lecturers and tutors have certain advantages over authors—they have the power to hear and speak to their audiences—and these advantages should help them to explain the harder things to their students. Here are a few words about our approach to rigour. It is clearly impossible to prove everything with complete rigour at this level; on the other hand it is important that students should understand why rigour is necessary. We try to be rigorous where possible, and elsewhere we go to some lengths to point out how and where we skate over thin ice. This can occasionally be tedious. Most sections finish with a few exercises; these are usually completely routine, and students should do them as a matter of course. Each chapter finishes with a collection of problems; these are often much harder than the exercises, and include many parts of questions taken from examina- tion papers set in Bristol and Oxford; we acknowledge permission from Bristol University and from Oxford University Press in this regard. There is a final chapter containing some hints for solving the problems. Problems marked with an asterisk may be rather difficult. We hope that the remaining mistakes and misprints are not held against us too much, and that they do not pose overmuch of a hazard to the reader. Only with the kind help of our students have we reduced them to the present level. Finally we thank Rhoda Rees for typing the manuscript with such skill, speed and good cheer. Bristol and Oxford .G. July 1985 D.W.Contents A. BASIC PROBABILITY Events and probabilities 11 Experiments with chance Outcomes and events Probabilities Probability spaces Discrete sample spaces Conditional probabilities Independent events The partition theorem Probability measures are continuous 7 10 Worked problems 1.11 Problems Discrete random variables 21 Probability mass functions Examples Functions of discrete random variables Expectation Conditional expectation and the partition theorem Problems Multivariate discrete distributions and independence Bivariate discrete distributions Expectation in the multivariate case Independence of discrete random variables Sums of random variables Problems Probability generating functions 4.1 4.2 Generating functions Integef-valued random variables 22 24 28 29 32 34 36 38 42 43 45viii Contents 4.3, Moments 4.4 Sums of independent random variables ~ 4.5 Problems Distribution functions and density functions 5.1 Distribution functions 5.2 Examples of distribution functions 5.3 Continuous random variables 5.4 Some common density functions 5.5 Functions of random variables 5.6 Expectations of continuous random variables 5.7 Problems B. FURTHER PROBABILITY Multivariate distributions and independence 6.1 Random vectors and independence 6.2 Joint density functions 6.3 Marginal density functions and independence 6.4 Sums of continuous random variables 6.5 Changes of variables 6.6 Conditional density functions 6.7 Expectations of continuous random variables 6.8 Conditional expectation and the bivariate normal distribution 6.9 Problems Moments, and moment generating functions 7.1 A general note 7.2 Moments 7.3 Variance and covariance 7.4 Moment generating functions 7.5 Characteristic functions 7.6 Problems The two main limit theorems 8.1. The law of averages 8.2 Chebyshev’s inequality and the weak law 8.3. The central limit theorem 49 51 53 56 59 63 65 67 70 SRRssra gs 124 126 12910 11 Contents ix 8.4 Convergence in distribution, and characteristic functions 8.5 Problems C. RANDOM PROCESSES Branching processes 9.1 Random processes 9.2 A model for population growth 9.3 The generating-function method 9.4 An example 9.5 The probability of extinction 9.6 Problems Random walks 10.1 One-dimensional random walks 10.2 Transition probabilities 10.3. Recurrence and transience in random walks 10.4 The Gambler’s Ruin problem 10.5 Problems Random processes in continuous time 11.1. Life at a telephone exchange 11.2 Poisson processes 11.3 Inter-arrival times and the exponential distribution 11.4 Population growth and the simple birth process 11.5. Birth and death processes 11.6 A simple queueing model 11.7 Problems Appendix Difference equations Answers to exercises Remarks on the problems Reading list Index 132 136 143 143 145 147 149 152 153 154 156 159 164 168 171 174 177 182 185 190 195 198 201 207 208A. Basic Probability1 Events and probab' 1.1 les Experiments with chance Many actions have outcomes which are largely unpredictable in advance—tossing a coin and throwing a dart are simple examples. Probability theory is about such actions and their consequences. The mathematical theory starts with the idea of an experiment (or trial), being a course of action whose consequence is not predetermined; this experiment is reformulated as a mathematical object called a probability space. In broad terms the probability space corresponding to a given experiment comprises three items: (i) the set of all possible outcomes of the experiment, (ii) a list of all the events which may possibly occur as consequences of the experiment, (iii) an assessment of the likelihoods of these events. For example, if the experiment is the throwing of a fair six-sided die, then the probability space contains (i) the set {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6} of possible outcomes, (ii) a list of events such as ‘the result is 3’, ‘the result is at least 4’, ‘the result is a prime number’, (iii) the assessment that each number 1, 2,3, 4,5, 6 is equally likely to be the result of the throw. Given any experiment involving chance, there is a corresponding probability space, and the study of such spaces is called probability theory. Next, we shall see how to construct such spaces more explicitly. 1.2 Outcomes and events We use the letter to denote a particular experiment whose outcome is not completely predetermined. The first thing which we do is to make a list of all the possible outcomes of @; the set of all such possible outcomes is called the sample space of € and we usually denote it by 2. The Greek letter w denotes a typical member of 22, and we call each member @ of 2 an elementary event. If, for example, @ is the experiment of throwing a fair die once,4 Events and probabilities 12 a then Q= (1, 2,3, 4,5, 6}. There are many questions which we may wish to ask about the actual outcome of this experiment (questions such as ‘is the outcome a prime number?”’), and all such questions may be rewritten in terms of subsets of Q (the previous question becomes ‘does the outcome lie in the subset {2,3, 5} of Q”). The second thing which we do is to make a list of all the events which are interesting to us; this list takes the form of a collection of subsets of Q, each such subset A representing the event ‘the outcome of @ lies in A’. Thus we ask ‘which possible events are interesting to us’ and then we make a list of the corresponding subsets of 9. This relationship between events and subsets is very natural, especially because two or more events combine with each other in just the same way as the corresponding subsets combine; for example, if A and B are subsets of 2 then the set A U B corresponds to the event ‘either A or B occurs’, the set AM B corresponds to the event ‘both A and B occur’, the set 2\A corresponds} to the event ‘A does not occur’, where we say that a subset C of 22 ‘occurs’ whenever the outcome of € lies in C. Thus all set-theoretic statements and combinations may be interpreted in terms of events; for example, the formula Q\(ANB)=(Q\A)U(Q\B) may be read as ‘if A and B do not both occur, then either A does not occur or B does not occur’. In a similar way, if A,, Ao, ... are events then the sets 7, A; and (2, A; represent the events ‘A, occurs, for some i’ and ‘A, occurs, for every i’, respectively. Thus we write down a collection ¥ = {A;:i€I} of subsets of Q which are interesting to us; each A € F is called an event. In simple cases, such as the die-throwing example above, we usually take ¥ to be the set of all subsets of Q (called the power set of Q), but for reasons which may be appreciated later there are many circumstances in which we take ¥ to be a very much smaller collection than the entire power set. In all cases we demand a certain consistency of ¥, in the following sense. If A, B, C, . . . € ¥ then we may reasonably be interested also in the events ‘A does not occur’ and ‘at least one of A, B, C,... occurs’. With this in mind we require that F satisfy the following definition. The collection ¥ of subsets of the sample space 9 is called an event space if F is non-empty, + For any subset A of @, the complement of A is the set of all members of @ which are not members of A. We denote the complement of A by either 2\A or A°, depending on the context.@) 3) Example 4 Example 5 Example 6 Exercises Probabilities 5 if Ae F then Q\AcF, if A,, Ao,...€# then UA, F P= We speak of an event space ¥ as being ‘closed under the operations of taking complements and countable unions’. An ele- mentary consequence of axioms (1)—(3) is that an event space ¥ must contain the empty set @ and the whole set Q. This holds since ¥ contains some set A (from (1)), and hence ¥ contains Q\A (from (2), giving also that ¥ contains the union Q = A U(Q\A) together with the complement 2\2 = © of this last set. Here are some examples of pairs (@, ¥) of sample spaces and event spaces. Qis any set and is the power set of Q. oO Qis any set and ¥ = {Z, A, Q\A, Q} where A is a given subset of Q. a Qz={1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6} and F is the collection ©, {1, 2}, {3,4}, {5, 6}, {1, 2,3, 4}, (3,4, 5, 6}, {1, 2,5, 6}, 2 of subsets of @. This event space is unlikely to arise naturally in practice. a In these exercises, Q is a set and ¥ is an event space of subsets of Q. If A, Be F, show that AN Be F. The difference A\B of two subsets A and B of @is the set AM (Q\B) of all points of @ which are in A but not in B. Show that if A, B ¢ ¥, then A\B ee F. 3. The symmetric difference AA B of two subsets A and B of Qis defined to be the set of points of @ which are in either A or B but not in both. If A, Be &, show that AABe F. 4. If Aj, Az,.-., Am € ¥ and k is a positive integer, show that the set of points in 2 which belong to exactly k of the A’s belongs to ¥ (the previous exercise is the case when m = 2 and k = 1). 5. Show that if Qis a finite set then ¥ contains an even number of subsets of Q. 1.3. Probabilities From our experiment €, we have so far constructed a sample space Q and an event space ¥ associated with @, but there has been no mention yet of probabilities. The third thing which we do is to6 Events and probabilities 13 ”) (8) (9) Example 10 allocate probabilities to each event in ¥, writing P(A) for the probability of the event A. We shall assume that this can be done in such a way that the probability function P satisfies certain intuitively attractive conditions: (i) each event A in the event space should have a probability P(A) which lies between 0 and 1; (ii) the event Q, that ‘something happens’, should have probability 1, and the event @, that ‘nothing happens’, should have probability 0; (iii) if A and B are disjoint events (so that AN B=@) then P(A U B) = P(A) + P(B). We collect these conditions into a formal definition as follows. A mapping P : ¥—>R is called a probability measure on (Q, F) if P(A)=0 forall Ae, P(Q)=1 and P(@)=0, if A,, Az, ... are disjoint events in F (so that A, A, =@ whenever i#j) then e(U A.) = z P(A,). We emphasize that a probability measure P on (Q, ¥) is defined only on those subsets of @ which lie in ¥. The second part of condition (8) is superfluous in the above definition; to see this, note that @ and Q are disjoint events with union QU@= @ and so P(Q) = P(2 UD) = P(Q) + P(D) by (9). Condition (9) requires that the probability of the union of a countable+ collection of non-overlapping sets is the sum of the individual probabilities. Let @ be a set and A be a proper subset of Q (so that A #@, Q). If F is the event space {B, A, Q\A, Q} then all probability measures on (, #) have the form for some p satisfying 0=p <1. o +A set S is called countable if it may be put in one-one correspondence with a subset of the natural numbers {1,2,3,...}14 Example 11 Exercises Probability spaces 7 Let Q= {@,, @2,..., Oy} be a finite set of exactly N points, and let F be the power set of Q. It is easy to check that the function P defined byt P(A)= BIA for AeF is a probability measure on (Q, ¥). a 6. Let ps, P2,-..,py be non-negative numbers such that p; +p2+ +++ + Pw =1, and let Q={c, @2,..., @y}, with ¥ the power set of Q, as in Example 11 above. Show that the function Q given by Q(A)= Dp, for Ac#, cA is a probability measure on (@, #). Is Q a probability measure if F is not the power set of @ but merely some event space of subsets of 2? 1.4 Probability spaces (12) Proof (13) Proof a4) We now combine the previous ideas and define a probability space to be a triple (Q, ¥, P) of objects such that () Qisa set, (ii) F is an event space of subsets of 2, (iii) P is a probability measure on (Q, ¥). There are many elementary consequences of the axioms which underlie this definition, and we describe some of these. Let (Q, ¥, P) be a probability space. If A, Be F thent A\Be F. The complement of A\B equals (@\A)UB, which is the union of events and is therefore an event. Hence A\B is an event, by (2). 0 If Ay, Az)... € F then () A, € F. is The complement of (7.1 A, equals U7, (@\A,) which is the union of the complements of events and is therefore an event. Hence the intersection of the A’s is an event also, as before. o If Ae F then P(A) + P(Q\A)= 1. + The cardinality |A| of a set A is the number of points in A. $A\B = AN (Q\B) is the set of points in A which are not in B.8 Events and probabilities 14 Proof A and Q\A are disjoint events with union Q, and so 1=P(Q)=P(A) + P(Q\A). Q (15) If A, Be ¥ then P(A UB) + P(AN B) =P(A) + P(B). Proof _—The set A is the union of the disjoint sets A\B and AN B, and hence P(A) = P(A\B) + P(A NB) by (9). A similar remark holds for the set B, giving that P(A) + P(B) = P(A\B) + 2P(A NB) + P(B\A) =P((A\B) U(AN B)U(B\A)) + P(ANB) by (9) =P(AUB)+P(ANB). oO (16) If A, Be ¥ and ACB then P(A) =P(B). Proof P(B) = P(A) + P(B\A) = P(A). a It is often useful to draw a Venn diagram when working with probabilities, For example, to show the formula in (15) above we might draw the diagram in Fig. 1.1, and note that the probability of AU Bis the sum of P(A) and P(B) minus P(A B), since this latter probability is counted twice in the simple sum P(A) + P(B). Exercises In these exercises (@, F, P) is a probability space. 7. If A, Be &, show that P(A\B) = P(A) — P(ANB). 8. If A, B, Ce &, show that P(A UBUC)=P(A) + P(B) + P(C)— P(A NB) —P(ANC)-P(BNC)+P(ANBNC). Fig. 1.1. A Venn diagram which illustrates the fact that P(A U B) = P(A) + P(B)— P(ANB)Discrete sample spaces 9 ( Let A, B, C be three events such that P(A)=i0, = P(B)=%, = P(C)=%, P(ANB)=%, P(BNC)=%, P(ANC)=%, P(ANBNC)=%. By drawing a Venn diagram or otherwise, find the probability that exactly two of the events A, B, C occur. 10. A fair coin is tossed 10 times (so that heads appears with probability } at each toss). Describe the appropriate probability space in detail for the two cases when (i) the outcome of every toss is of interest, i) only the total number of tails is of interest. In the first case your event space should have 2” events, but in the second case it should have only 2" events. 1.5 Discrete sample spaces Example 7 Example 18 Let € be an experiment with probability space (Q, ¥,P). The structure of this space depends greatly upon whether @ is a countable set (that is, a finite or countably infinite set) or an uncountable set. If Q is a countable set then we normally take F to be the set of all subsets of , for the following reason. Suppose that Q= {@;, @2,-..} and, for each w € Q, we are interested in whether or not this given w is the actual outcome of @; then we require that each singleton set {w} belongs to ¥. Let AcQ. Then A is countable (since Q is countable) and so A may be expressed as the union of the countably many @’s which belong to A, giving that A =U,.4 {@} € F by (3). The probability P(A) of the event A is determined by the collection {P({«@}) : € Q} of probabilities since, by (9), P(A) = =, P({o}). We usually write P(w) for the probability P({w}) of an event containing only one point in Q. Equiprobable outcomes. If Q= {o,, @2,..., Oy} and P(@,) = P(o,) for all i and j, then P(w)=N~ for all @ € Q, and P(A) =[A|/N for all AcQ. a Random integers. There are “intuitively-clear” statements which are without meaning in probability theory, and here is an example: if we pick a positive integer at random, then it is an even integer with probability }. Interpreting “at random” to mean that each positive integer is equally likely to be picked, then this experiment would10 Events and probabilities 15 Exercises have probability space (Q, ¥, P) where @aeta - (ii) F is the set of all subsets of Q, (iii) if A c Q then P(A) = Dies P() = |A| where z is the probabil- ity that any given integer, i say, is picked. However, if 2 =0 then P(Q) = if >0 then P(Q)= >) r=”, a neither of which is in agreement with the rule that P(Q)=1. One possible way of interpreting the italicized statement above is as follows. Fix N, a large positive integer, and let &y be the experiment of picking an integer from Qy={1,2,...,N} at random. The probability that the outcome of y is even is 1 los N, so that, as N->«, the required probability tends to 4. Despite this sensible interpretation of the italicized statement, we emphasize that this statement is without meaning in its present form and should be shunned by serious probabilists. a Pants ow 2 Lif Nis even, and 5 ( )ifvis odd, The most elementary problems in probability theory are those which involve experiments such as the shuffling of cards or the throwing of dice, and these usually give rise to situations in which every possible outcome is equally likely to occur. This is the case of Example 17 above. Such problems usually reduce to the problem of counting the number of ways in which some event may occur, and the following exercises are of this type. 11. Show that if a coin is tossed n times, then there are exactly (“ena sequences of possible outcomes in which exactly k heads are obtained. If the coin is fair (so that heads and tails are equally likely on each toss), show that the probability of getting at least k heads is #3 (1): 12. We distribute r distinguishable balls into n cells at random, multiple occupancy being permitted. Show that (i there are n” possible arrangements, (ii) there are (Je — 1)~* arrangements in which the first cell contains exactly k balls,Conditional probabilities 11 (iii) the probability that the first cell contains exactly k balls is Ast re (OG) 0-2) 13. Show that the probability that each of the four players in a game of bridge receives one ace is 24-481 13° =0.105. . oe 14. Show that the probability that two given hands in bridge contain k aces between them is 4\/ 48 52) ()loe=)/ Ce): 15. Show that the probability that a hand in bridge contains 6 spades, 3 hearts, 2 diamonds, and 2 clubs is (8)(5)(2) /(a) 6/A3/\2 13/* Which of the following is more probable: (i) getting at least one six with 4 throws of a die, (ii) getting at least one double six with 24 throws of two dice? This is sometimes called ‘de Méré’s paradox’, after the professional gambler Chevalier de Méré who believed these two events to have equal probability. 1 a 1.6 Conditional probabil (as) ies Let & be an experiment with probability space (Q, ¥, P). We may sometimes possess incomplete information about the actual outcome of @ without knowing this outcome exactly. For example, if we throw a fair die and a friend tells us that an even number is showing, then this information affects all our calculations of probabilities. In general, if A and B are events (that is A, B € #) and we are given that B occurs, then, in the light of this information, the new probability of A may no longer be P(A). Clearly, in this new circumstance, A occurs if and only if AM B occurs, suggesting that the new probability of A is proportional to P(A MB). We make this chat more formal in a definition. If A, B € ¥ and P(B)>0, then the (conditional) probability of A given B is denoted by P(A | B) and defined by P(A|B)=—S Note that the constant of proportionality in (19) hs been chosen so12 Events and probabilities W7 that the probability P(B |B), that B occurs given that B occurs, satisfies P(B | B)=1. We must first check that this definition gives rise to a probability space. Theorem If Be ¥ and P(B)>0 then (Q, F, Q) is a probability space where 1A Q: FR is defined by Q(A) = P(A |B). Proof We need only check that Q is a probability measure on (Q, ¥). Certainly Q(A)=0 for all A e F and P(QNB) P(B) and it remains to check that Q satisfies (9). Suppose that Aj, Ap,... are disjoint events in ¥. Then (4) Fw (Ya) na) Ut4.nB)) Q(@) =P(@| B)= -1 7; e(L =a FHV PANB) since P satisfies (9) =D OA). a Exercises 17. If (@, %, P) is a probability space and A, B, C are events, show that P(ANBNC)=P(A|BNC)P(B | C)P(C) so long as P(BNC)>0. 18. Show that P(B) PBI A)=PCAIB) sy if P(A) >0 and P(B) >0. 19. Consider the experiment of tossing a fair coin 7 times. Find the probability of getting a prime number of heads given that heads occurs on at least 6 of the tosses. 1.7 Independent events We call two events A and B ‘independent’ if the occurrence of one of them does not affect the probability that the other occurs; more formally this requires that, if P(A), P(B)>0, then (20) P(A|B)=P(A) and P(B|A)=P(B).@y) (22) Example . 23 Exercises Independent events 13 Writing P(A | B)= P(A B)/P(B), we see that the following defini- tion is appropriate. Events A and B of a probability space (@, ¥,P) are called independent if P(A NB) =P(A)P(B) and dependent otherwise. This definition is slightly more general than (20) since it allows A and B to have zero probability. It is easily generalized to more than two events. A family of = (A; :i€ 1) of events is called independent if, for all finite subsets J of I, P(Q4)) = TPC). The family sf is called pairwise independent if (22) holds whenever yl=2. Thus, three events A, B, C are independent if and only if the following equalities hold: P(ANBNC)=P(A)P(B)P(C), — P(AN B)=P(A)P(B), P(ANC)=P(A)P(C), — P(BNC)=P(B)P(C). There are families of events which are pairwise independent but not independent. Suppose that we throw a fair four-sided die (you may think of this as a square die thrown in a two-dimensional universe). Then we may take Q = {1, 2, 3, 4} where each w € Q is equally likely to occur. The events A= {1,2}, B= {1,3}, C={1, 4} are pairwise independent but not independent. a 20. Let A and B be events satisfying P(A), P(B)>0, and such that P(A | B) = P(A). Show that P(B | A) = P(B). 21. If A and B are events which are disjoint and independent, what can be said about the probabilities of A and B? 22. Show that events A and B are independent if and only if A and Q\B are independent. 23. Show that events A,, Az, ..., Am are independent if and only if Q\A,, Q\A;,..., Q\A,, are independent. 24. If Aj, Az,...,Am are independent and P(A,)=p for i=1,2,...,m, find the probability that (i) none of the A’s occur, (ii) an even number of the A’s occur 25. On your desk there is a very special die which has a prime number p of faces, and you throw this die once. Show that no two events A and B can be independent unless either A or B is the whole sample space.14 Events and probabilities 18 1.8 The partition theorem Theorem 1B Proof Example 24 Solution Exercises Let (@, F, P) be a probability space. A partition of Q is a collection {B; :i € 1} of disjoint events (so that B; € ¥ for each i and B, NB, =@ if i+) with union U, B;=2. The following partition theorem is extremely useful. If {B,, By, .. .} is a partition of Q such that P(B;)>0 for each i, then P(A) => P(A|B)P(B,) forall Ae F. This theorem has several other fancy names, such as ‘the theorem of total probability’; it is closely related to the so-called ‘Bayes formula’. ruy=r(an(ya) =P(Utna)) => P(ANB) by (9) => P(A | B)P(B,) by (19). a Here is an example of this theorem in action. Tomorrow there will be either rain or snow but not both; the probability of rain is 3 and the probability of snow is 3. If it rains then the probability that I will be late for my lecture is $, while the corresponding probability in the event of snow is 3. What is the probability that I will be late? Let A be the event that I am late and B be the event that it rains. Then the pair B, B° is a partition of the sample space (since one or other of them must occur). We apply Theorem 1B to find that P(A) =P(A | B)P(B) + P(A | B°)P(B°) =b-34+3-3=8. a 26. Here is a routine problem about balls in urns. You are presented with two urns. Urn I contains 3 white and 4 black balls and Urn II contains 2 white and 6 black balls. You pick a ball randomly from Urn I and place it in Urn II. Next you pick a ball randomly from Urn Il. What is the probability that this ball is black? 21. A biased coin shows heads with probability p= 1—q whenever it isProbability measures are continuous 15 tossed. Let u, be the probability that, in tosses, no pair of heads occur successively. Show that for n= 1 Uns2 = Uns + Pens and find u, by the usual method (described in the appendix) if p (Hint: use Theorem 1B with B, the event that the first i — 1 tosses yield heads and the ith yields tails. 1.9 Probability measures are continuous Theorem 1c Example 25 There is a certain property of probability measures which will be crucially important later, and we describe this next. Too great an emphasis should not be laid on this property at this stage, and therefore we strongly recommend to the reader that he omit this section at the first reading. A sequence A, Az, ... of events in a probability space (@, ¥, P) is called increasing if A, CA, +++ CAQ-1 SAn SAnai S01 The union of such a sequence is called the limit of the sequence, and it is an elementary consequence of the axioms for an event space that A is an event. It is perhaps not surprising that the probability P(A) of A may be expressed as the limit lim,_... P(A,,) of the probabilities of the A’s. Let (2, ¥, P) be a probability space. If A, Az, .-. is an increasing sequence of events in ¥ with limit A, then P(A) = lim P(A,,). We precede the proof of the theorem with an application. It is intuitively clear that the chance of obtaining no heads in an infinite set of tosses of a fair coin is 0. A rigorous proof goes as follows. Let A,, be the event that the first n tosses of the coin yield at least one head. Then A, CAns for n=1,2,..., so that the A’s form an increasing sequence; the limit set A is the event that heads occurs sooner or later. From Theorem 1C, P(A) = lim P(A,,);16 Events and probabilities 1.10 Proof of Theorem however, P(A,,) = 1 — (3)" and so P(A,) > 1 as n>. Thus P(A) = 1, giving that the probability P(Q\A), that heads never appears, equals 0. Oo Let B;=A;\A;-, for i=2, 3,.... Then A=A,UB,UBU>>+ is the union of disjoint events in ¥ (draw a Venn diagram to make this clear). By (9), P(A) = P(A,) + P(B,) + P(Bs) + +++ =P(A,) + lim S) P(B). However, P(B,) =P(A,)— P(A;-1) for i=2,3,..., and so a P(A) = PCAL) + fim > [P(Ag) — Pc DI = lim P(A,) as required, since the last sum collapses. Qo The conclusion of Theorem 1C is expressed in terms of increasing sequences of events, but the corresponding result about decreasing sequences is valid too: if By, By, . . . is a sequence of events in ¥ such that B)> B;4, for i=1,2,..., then P(B,)—>P(B) as n>, where B=(2:B, is the limit of the B,’s as i>. The easiest way to deduce this is to set A, = Q\B; in the theorem. 1.10 Worked problems Example 26 Solution A fair six-sided die is thrown twice (when applied to such objects as dice or coins, the adjectives ‘fair’ and ‘unbiased’ imply that each possible outcome has equal probability of occurring). (a) Write down the probability space of this experiment. (b) Let B be the event that the first number thrown is no larger than 3, and let C be the event that the sum of the two numbers thrown equals 6. Find the probabilities of B and C, and the conditional probabilities of C given B, and of B given C. The probability space of this experiment is the triple (2, ¥, P) where (i) Q={@f):4j=1,2,..., 6} is the set of all ordered pairs of integers between 1 and 6,1.10 Example 27 Worked problems 17 ii) F is the set of all subsets of Q, (iii) each point in Q has equal probability, so that P(i,/))=36 for i, j=1,2, and, more generally, P(A)=%|A| for each AcQ. The events B and C are subsets of 2 given by B=({(i,j):i=1,2,3 and j=1,2,..., 6}, C={(i, j):itj=6 and i, j=1,2,..., 6}. B contains 3 X 6 = 18 ordered pairs, and C contains 5 ordered pairs, giving that P(B)=%=2, P(C)=%. Finally, B C is given by BNC={(1,5), (2,4), G, 3)} containing just 3 ordered pairs, so that P(COB (c| 8) == a= a, and P(IBNC PB | 0) =P ORO Baad 5 You are travelling in a train with your sister. Neither of you has a valid ticket and the inspector has caught you both. He is authorized to administer a special punishment for this offence. He holds a box containing nine apparently identical chocolates, but three of these are contaminated with a deadly poison. He makes each of you, in turn, choose and immediately eat a single chocolate. (a) If you choose before your sister, what is the probability that you survive? (b) If you choose first and survive, what is the probability that your sister survives? (c) If you choose first and die, what is the probability that your sister survives? (d) Is it in your best interests to persuade your sister to choose first? (e) If you choose first, what is the probability that you survive, given that your sister survives?18 Events and probabilities 111 Solution Let A be the event that the first chocolate picked is not poisoned, (28) 1.11 and let B be the event that the second chocolate picked is not poisoned. Elementary calculations, if you are allowed the time to perform them, would show that P(A4)=8, P(B|A)=3, — P(B| A‘) =8, giving by the partition theorem 1B that P(B) = P(B | A)P(A) + P(B | A®)P(A‘) =a$+§-(1-§)= Hence P(A) = P(B), so that the only reward of choosing second is to increase your life expectancy by a few seconds. ‘The final question (e) seems to be the wrong way round in time, since your sister chooses her chocolate after you. The way to answer such a question is to reverse the conditioning as follows: P(ANB) P(A) AUD EE Cys PCB)’ =P(B|A) 5) and hence a P(4| B)=3-8/3=3. We note that P(A|B)=P(B|A), in agreement with our earlier observation that the order in which you and your sister pick from the box is irrelevant to your chances of survival. o Problems 1. A fair die is thrown 7 times. Show that the probability that there are an even number of sixes is 11+ @' For the purpose of this question, 0 is an even number. . Does there exist an event space which contains just six events? Prove Boole’s inequality: P(t) A) =3 P(A,). ‘Two fair dice are thrown. Let A be the event that the first shows an odd number, B be the event that the second shows an even number, and C be the event that either both are odd or both are even. Show that A, B, C are pairwise independent but not independent. . Urn I contains 4 white and 3 black balls, and Urn II contains 3 white and 7 black balls. An urn is selected at random and a ball is picked from it. What is the probability that this ball is black? If this ball is white, what is the probability that Urn I was selected? 6. A single card is removed at random from a deck of 52 cards. From the en s111 2 x e og i. Problems 19 MN Bn LO Fig. 1.2 Two electrical circuits incorporating switches remainder we draw two cards at random and find that they are both spades. What is the probability that the first card removed was also a spade? Two people toss a fair coin n times each. Show that the probability they throw equal numbers of heads is (Ca) oes In the circuits in Fig. 1.2 each switch is closed with probability p, independently of all other switches. For each circuit, find the probabil- ity that a flow of current is possible between A and B. Show that if u, is the probability that n tosses of a fair coin contain no tun of 4 heads, then for n =4 Uy, = Mya + Aina + Bln a + Hellas Use this difference equation to show that, in 8 throws, the probability of no such run is 28. Any number @ €[0, 1] has a decimal expansion @=0- xx... and we write f,(@,) for the proportion of times that the integer k appears in the first n digits in this expansion. We call a normal number if filo, n)>h as ne for k=0, 1,2,...,9. On intuitive grounds we may expect that most numbers w €[0, 1] are normal numbers, and Borel proved that this is indeed true. It is quite another matter to exhibit specific normal numbers. It is known that the number 0.1234567891011121314. . . is normal; prove this. It is an unsolved problem of mathematics to show that e — 2 and m3 are normal numbers also. A square board is divided into 16 equal squares by lines drawn parallel to its sides. A counter is placed at random on one of these squares and is then moved n times. At each of these moves it can be transferred to any neighbouring square, horizontally, vertically, or diagonally, all such moves being equally likely. Let c, be the probability that a particular corner site is occupied after 7 such independent moves, and let the corresponding probabilities for an intermediate site at the side of the board and for a site in the middle of the board be s, and m, respectively. Show that 2 4, +85,4+4m,=1, 2 =0,1,2,...20. Events and probabilities oe a gE 14. 15. and that Com Bettie, 21,2, Find two other relations for s, and m, in terms of ¢,_;, 5,1, and m,_; and hence find c,, $,, and m,. (Oxford 1974M) (a) Let P(A) denote the probability of the occurrence of an event A. Prove carefully, for events A,, A,...,A,, that P(,U4)= & Pad- DPM) + + cyrP(9,4,). (b) One evening a bemused lodge-porter tried to hang n keys on their n hooks, but only managed to hang them independently and at random. There was no limit to the number of keys which could be hung on any hook. Otherwise, or by using (a), find an expression for the probability that at least’ one key was hung on its own hook. The following morning the porter was rebuked by the Bursar, so that in the evening he was careful to hang only one key on each hook. But he still only managed to hang them independently and at random. Find an expression for the probability that no key was then hung on its own hook. Find the limits of both expressions as n tends to infinity. (You may assume that for all real x.) (Oxford 1978M) Two identical decks of cards, each containing N cards, are shuffled randomly. We say that a k-matching occurs if the two decks agree in exactly k places. Show that the probability that there is a k-matching is ( 1,11 y) mata at tL for k=0,1,2,...,N-1,N. We note that 2, ~(k!e)7' for large N and fixed k. Such matching probabilities are used in testing departures from randomness in circumstances such as psychological tests and wine-tasting competitions. (The convention is that 0! = 1.) The buses which stop at the end of my road do not keep to the timetable. They should run every quarter hour, at 08.30, 08.45, 09.00,..., but in fact each bus is either five minutes early or five minutes late, the two possibilities being equally probable and different buses being independent. Other people arrive at the stop in such a way that, ¢ minutes after the departure of one bus, the probability that no one is waiting for the next one is e~“*. What is the probability that no one is waiting at 09.00? One day I come to the stop at 09.00 and find no one there; show that the chances are more than four to one that I have missed the nine o’clock bus. (You may use the good approximation e? ~ 20.) (Oxford 1977M) A coin is tossed repeatedly; on each toss a head is shown with probability p, a tail with probability 1—p. All tosses are mutuallyoat “17. Problems 21 independent. Let E denote the event that the first run of r successive heads occurs earlier than the first run of s successive tails. Let A denote the outcome of the first toss. Show that P(E | A =head) =p™"' + (1—p”"")P(E| A = tail). Find a similar expression for P(E | A = tail) and hence find P(E). (Oxford 1981M) . Try Eddington’s Controversy: If A, B, C, D each speak the truth once in three times (independently) and A claims that B denies that C declares that D is a liar, what is the probability that D was speaking the truth? Show that the axiom that P is countably additive is equivalent to the axiom that P is finitely additive and continuous. That is to say, let 2 be a set and ¥ an event space of subsets of @. If P is a mapping from ¥ into [0 , 1] satisfying (i) P(Q)=1, P()=0, (ii) if A, Be ¥ and ANB =@ then P(AUB) = if Ay, Az,...€ Fand A,cA,,, for i=1, 2, P(A) = lim P(A,) where A=, A, then P satisfies P(UZ, A,) =, P(A,) for all sequences Ay, Az, .-. disjoint events. . In a piece of electronic equipment, a gate, which may be open or closed, has a random method of operation. Every millisecond it may change its state; the changes occur in the following manner: (i) if it is open it remains open with probability 1— a and becomes closed with probability «, (ii) if it is closed it remains so with probabi with probability B. If 0
You might also like
Joel Kilty, Alex McAllister - Mathematical Modeling and Applied Calculus-Oxford University Press (2018)
PDF
100% (1)
Joel Kilty, Alex McAllister - Mathematical Modeling and Applied Calculus-Oxford University Press (2018)
812 pages
Lukacs E. Characteristic Functions
PDF
67% (3)
Lukacs E. Characteristic Functions
215 pages
(Peter J. Olver, Chehrzad Shakiban) Instructor's S
PDF
No ratings yet
(Peter J. Olver, Chehrzad Shakiban) Instructor's S
357 pages
Probability Theory II Stochastic Calculus
PDF
No ratings yet
Probability Theory II Stochastic Calculus
428 pages
Probability - Leo Breiman
PDF
100% (1)
Probability - Leo Breiman
438 pages
T. W. Körner - Fourier Analysis (1988)
PDF
No ratings yet
T. W. Körner - Fourier Analysis (1988)
601 pages
Lecture Notes On Probability Theory Dmitry Panchenko
PDF
No ratings yet
Lecture Notes On Probability Theory Dmitry Panchenko
316 pages
An Introduction To Bayesian Inference, Methods and Computation
PDF
100% (1)
An Introduction To Bayesian Inference, Methods and Computation
177 pages
One Thousand Exercises in Probability (Solution Manual of Probability and Random Processes) by Geoffrey Grimmett, David Stirzaker
PDF
100% (1)
One Thousand Exercises in Probability (Solution Manual of Probability and Random Processes) by Geoffrey Grimmett, David Stirzaker
448 pages
A Mathematical Introduction To Wavelets PDF
PDF
No ratings yet
A Mathematical Introduction To Wavelets PDF
273 pages
Stochastic Processes - Ross
PDF
88% (8)
Stochastic Processes - Ross
520 pages
Prob ALecture Notes
PDF
No ratings yet
Prob ALecture Notes
202 pages
Casella Berger Statistical Inference
PDF
50% (4)
Casella Berger Statistical Inference
686 pages
(Rice J.a.) Mathematical Statistics and Data Analy
PDF
100% (3)
(Rice J.a.) Mathematical Statistics and Data Analy
685 pages
Applied+Mathematics J+David+Logan
PDF
100% (3)
Applied+Mathematics J+David+Logan
546 pages
Shu-Cherng Fang, Sarat Puthenpura - Linear Optimization and Extensions - Theory and Algorithms-Prentice Hall College Div (1993) PDF
PDF
No ratings yet
Shu-Cherng Fang, Sarat Puthenpura - Linear Optimization and Extensions - Theory and Algorithms-Prentice Hall College Div (1993) PDF
320 pages
H. Cartan - Differential Calculus-Houghton Mifflin (1971)
PDF
100% (1)
H. Cartan - Differential Calculus-Houghton Mifflin (1971)
161 pages
Asymptotical Statistics
PDF
100% (2)
Asymptotical Statistics
460 pages
Durrett 5e Solutions
PDF
No ratings yet
Durrett 5e Solutions
96 pages
Marek Capinski, Tomasz Jerzy Zastawniak - Probability Through Problems (2000, Springer) PDF
PDF
No ratings yet
Marek Capinski, Tomasz Jerzy Zastawniak - Probability Through Problems (2000, Springer) PDF
133 pages
(Advances in Applied Mathematics) Chow, Pao Liu-Stochastic Partial Differential Equations-CRC Press (2014)
PDF
100% (1)
(Advances in Applied Mathematics) Chow, Pao Liu-Stochastic Partial Differential Equations-CRC Press (2014)
333 pages
ProbabilitProbability With Martingalesy With Martingales
PDF
No ratings yet
ProbabilitProbability With Martingalesy With Martingales
265 pages
Ivan Niven, Herbert S. Zuckerman Hugh L. Montgomery An Introduction To The Theory of Numbers 1991
PDF
50% (2)
Ivan Niven, Herbert S. Zuckerman Hugh L. Montgomery An Introduction To The Theory of Numbers 1991
541 pages
Stirzaker D.-Probability and Random Variables. A Beginner's Guide-CUP (2003)
PDF
100% (1)
Stirzaker D.-Probability and Random Variables. A Beginner's Guide-CUP (2003)
382 pages
(T. Cacoullos) Exercises in Probability
PDF
100% (2)
(T. Cacoullos) Exercises in Probability
264 pages
Exercises in Probability (Problem Books in Mathematics) by T. Cacoullos
PDF
No ratings yet
Exercises in Probability (Problem Books in Mathematics) by T. Cacoullos
264 pages
Theory of Probability (1978) - Gnedenko PDF
PDF
100% (1)
Theory of Probability (1978) - Gnedenko PDF
390 pages
Grimmett G.R., Stirzaker D.R. Probability and Random Processes (3ed., Oxford, 2001)
PDF
100% (33)
Grimmett G.R., Stirzaker D.R. Probability and Random Processes (3ed., Oxford, 2001)
608 pages
(Yves Meyer, Ronald Coifman) Wavelets Calderón-Z
PDF
No ratings yet
(Yves Meyer, Ronald Coifman) Wavelets Calderón-Z
335 pages
Solutions Degroot
PDF
No ratings yet
Solutions Degroot
405 pages
105 Algebra Problems Look Inside PDF
PDF
No ratings yet
105 Algebra Problems Look Inside PDF
15 pages
Instant Access to Introduction To Stochastic Calculus With Applications 3Rd Edition Fima C Klebaner ebook Full Chapters
PDF
No ratings yet
Instant Access to Introduction To Stochastic Calculus With Applications 3Rd Edition Fima C Klebaner ebook Full Chapters
50 pages
Probability Theory - Varadhan
PDF
No ratings yet
Probability Theory - Varadhan
225 pages
Manual Bowers Completo
PDF
No ratings yet
Manual Bowers Completo
94 pages
Math Analysis
PDF
No ratings yet
Math Analysis
1,320 pages
(Eugene Isaacson, Herbert Bishop Keller) Analysis PDF
PDF
100% (1)
(Eugene Isaacson, Herbert Bishop Keller) Analysis PDF
558 pages
Lecture NotesLecture Notes For Introductory Probability
PDF
No ratings yet
Lecture NotesLecture Notes For Introductory Probability
218 pages
An Introduction To Probability Theory and Its Applications. Vol. 1. 3rd. Ed. W. Feller
PDF
100% (3)
An Introduction To Probability Theory and Its Applications. Vol. 1. 3rd. Ed. W. Feller
525 pages
Donald R. Woods Notes On Introductory Combinatorics
PDF
No ratings yet
Donald R. Woods Notes On Introductory Combinatorics
200 pages
Bollobás - Linear Analysis (1999)
PDF
100% (1)
Bollobás - Linear Analysis (1999)
251 pages
2002 - Stochastic Calculus PDF
PDF
100% (4)
2002 - Stochastic Calculus PDF
784 pages
Demidovich Mathematical Analysis
PDF
100% (1)
Demidovich Mathematical Analysis
100 pages
Robust Nonparametric Statistical Methods Second Edition
PDF
100% (2)
Robust Nonparametric Statistical Methods Second Edition
532 pages
Untitled
PDF
100% (1)
Untitled
201 pages
Stochastic Differential Equations. Introduction To Stochastic Models For Pollutants Dispersion, Epidemic and Finance
PDF
100% (1)
Stochastic Differential Equations. Introduction To Stochastic Models For Pollutants Dispersion, Epidemic and Finance
156 pages
(Arnold L.) Stochastic Differential Equations The (BookFi)
PDF
No ratings yet
(Arnold L.) Stochastic Differential Equations The (BookFi)
244 pages
Combinatorial Methods and Models PDF
PDF
No ratings yet
Combinatorial Methods and Models PDF
395 pages
Combinatorial Algorithms - Edward M Reingold
PDF
0% (1)
Combinatorial Algorithms - Edward M Reingold
12 pages
An Introduction To Probability Theory and Its Applications. Vol. 2. 2nd. Ed. W. Feller
PDF
90% (10)
An Introduction To Probability Theory and Its Applications. Vol. 2. 2nd. Ed. W. Feller
683 pages
Nonlinear and Dynamic Optimization
PDF
No ratings yet
Nonlinear and Dynamic Optimization
214 pages
An Introduction To Probability Theory and Its Applications, Vol. 2 by William Feller
PDF
100% (1)
An Introduction To Probability Theory and Its Applications, Vol. 2 by William Feller
683 pages
Calculus of Variations Project
PDF
No ratings yet
Calculus of Variations Project
10 pages
Poisson Point Processes Imaging, Tracking, and Sensing
PDF
No ratings yet
Poisson Point Processes Imaging, Tracking, and Sensing
280 pages
PrelimsProb MT23 26sep2023
PDF
No ratings yet
PrelimsProb MT23 26sep2023
71 pages
Probability
PDF
No ratings yet
Probability
78 pages
Probability and Random Processes
PDF
No ratings yet
Probability and Random Processes
608 pages
Math662TB 09S
PDF
100% (2)
Math662TB 09S
712 pages
Math 254
PDF
No ratings yet
Math 254
306 pages
Probability and Random Variables
PDF
100% (3)
Probability and Random Variables
380 pages
Probability Basics
PDF
100% (1)
Probability Basics
380 pages