Lesson 5. Twelve Stages of The Human Act
Lesson 5. Twelve Stages of The Human Act
Lesson Objectives:
After studying this lesson on the twelve stages of the human act,
you shall be able to:
1. understand through two illustrations of the logical sequencing of
St. Thomas Aquinas' twelve stages of human act.
2. give your own example of how these stages work in your life or
someone else's life.
The Nature of Each of the Twelve Stages of the Human Act according
to St. Thomas Aquinas:
1
5. deliberation on the means - presentation of choices
6. consent to means - judges each of the means
7. practical judgment of choice - arriving at the choice of the best
means
8. choice - a free act
9. command - will commands to obtain the desired object using the
choice arrived at
10. use - he uses the object
11. intellectual attainment of the end - the person apprehends the
suitability of his acts
12. fruition - he enjoys the acquisition
Objection 3.
Knowledge is necessary to voluntariness. But concupiscence impair
knowledge; delight or the lust of pleasure destroys the judgment of
prudence. Therefore concupiscence cause involuntariness.
Reply to Obj. 3
If concupiscence were to destroy knowledge altogether, as
happens with those whom concupiscence has rendered mad, it
would follow that concupiscence would take away
voluntariness. And yet, properly speaking, it would not result
in the act being involuntary, because in things bereft of reason,
there is neither voluntary or involuntary. But sometimes in
those actions which are done from concupiscence, knowledge
is not completely destroyed, because the power of knowledge is
not taken away entirely, but only the actual consideration in
some possible act. Nevertheless, this itself is voluntary,
according as by voluntary we mean that which is in the
power of the will, for
example, not to act or not to will, and in like manner not to consider; for
the will can resist the passion.
As regards the commanded acts of the will, then, the will can
suffer violence, in so far as violence can prevent the exterior
members from executing the will's command. But as to the
will's own proper act, violence cannot be done to the will.
The reason is that the act of the will is nothing else than as
inclination proceeding from the interior principle of knowledge:
just as the natural appetite is an inclination proceeding from an
interior principle without knowledge. Now what is compelled
or violent is from an exterior principle. Consequently, it is
contrary to the nature of the will's own act, that it should be
subject to compulsion and violence: just as it is also contrary to
the nature of a natural inclination or movement. For a stone may
have an upward movement from violence, but that this violent
movement be from its natural inclination is impossible. In like
manner, a man may be dragged by force: but it is contrary to the
very notion of violence that he be thus dragged of his own
will.
Reply Obj. 1:
God who is more powerful than the human will, can move the
will of man. But if this were compulsion, it would no longer be
by an act of the will, nor would the will itself be moved, but
something else against the will.
From An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation Excerpts from "
Of the Principle of Utility," by Jeremy Bentham.
1. Nature has placed mankind under the governance of two sovereign
masters, pain and pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we
ought to do, as well as to determine what we shall do. On the one
hand, the standard of right and wrong, on the other chain of causes
and effects, are fastened to their throne. They govern us in all we
do, in all we say, in all we think: every effort we can make to throw
off our subjection, will serve but to demonstrate and confirm it. In
words a man may pretend to abjure their empire: but in reality he
will remain subject to it all the while. The principle of utility
recognizes this subjection, and assumes it for the foundation of that
system, the subject of which is to rear the fabric of felicity by the
hands of reason and of law.
2. The principle of utility is the foundation of the present work: it
will be proper therefore at the outset to give an explicit and
determinate account of what is meant by it. By the principle of utility
is meant that principle which approves or disapproves of every
action whatsoever, according to the tendency which it appears to
have to augment or diminish that happiness of the party whose
interest is in question: or, what is the same thing in other words, to
promote or to oppose that happiness. I say of every action
whatsoever; and therefore not only of every action of a private
individual, but of every measure of government.
3. By utility is meant that property in any object, whereby it tends to
produce benefit, advantage, pleasure, good or happiness or to
prevent the happening of mischief, pain, evil, or unhappiness to the
party whose interest is considered: if that party be the community in
general, then the happiness of the community; if a particular
individual, then the happiness of that individual.
4. The interest of the community is one of the most general expressions
that can occur in the phraseology of morals: no wonder that
meaning of it is often lost. When it has a meaning, it is this. The
community is a fictitious body, composed of the individual persons
who are considered as it were its members. The interest of the
community then is, what? - the sum of the interests of several
members who compose it.
5. It is in vain to talk of the interest of the community, without
understanding what the interest of the individual is. A thing is
said to promote the interest, or to be for the interest, of an individual
when it tends to add to the sum total of his pleasure: or, what comes to
the same thing, to diminish the sum total of his pains.