Tree of Philosophy
Tree of Philosophy
Note: The full text, excluding diagrams, of the (now outdated) third
edition is also still available on this site. The most important of the many
differences between the two editions is briefly summarized in the Preface
to this fourth edition.
List of Lectures
Preface - viii
List of Figures
The Tree of Philosophy (1992, 1993, 1995, 2000) is based on the lectures
delivered for the Introduction to Philosophy classes I have taught 31 times at
Hong Kong Baptist University from 1987 to 2000. It is the second in a series of
three texts on "philopsychy". (This term, meaning "soul-loving", refers to any
creative and disciplined application of scholarly learning-especially in philosophy
and psychology-that encourages self-awareness.) The second book in the series
consists of lectures for a class I teach on dream interpretation for personal growth,
entitled Dreams of Wholeness (1997). The projected third volume is tentatively
entitled Elements of Love. Each book stands alone, but taken together they will
constitute a three-part course in philopsychy.
This fourth edition has been revised much more thoroughly than either of
the previous new editions. Besides adding eight new diagrams and redrawing all
76 of the old ones, I have added eight new lectures and made substantial
improvements to the 28 old ones. The topics (and numbers) of the new lectures
are: insight papers(2), post-Kantian metaphysics (9), how geometrical maps can
stimulate insights (15), hermeneutic philosophy (18), the superiority of
perspectivism over relativism and deconstructionism (24), how ideas are
perverted into ideologies (27), and Kant's view of what it means to be religious
(32 and 33). I have also reorganized the format (see the List of Lectures),
conforming it to the more systematic arrangement used for Dreams. Previously
consisting of seven short lectures, each of the four main Parts is now divided into
three "Weeks", with three lectures each. Publishing this fourth edition at the outset
of a new century (and a new millennium) has also provided a much-needed
opportunity to update the time references throughout the text and to reassess the
current state of philosophy in general.
As with Dreams and the planned second sequel, The Tree is written
primarily as a textbook. With the self-motivated student in mind, I have included
an updated set of eight "Recommended Readings" per week, as well as a set of
eight "Questions for Further Thought/Dialogue". The readings normally include
texts quoted and/or discussed in the foregoing chapter, supplemented with other
useful works that can be consulted by students who have a special interest in that
week's lecture topics. The questions are grouped into four sets of "A" and "B"
pairs. This is to enable teachers, if deemed appropriate, to assign one set (e.g., all
the "A" questions) for individual reflection and the other set (e.g., all the "B"
questions) for small group discussion/debate (i.e., "dialogue").
As students in my philosophy classes find out by the end of our first week,
the most important challenge of this course is to learn to recall, express, and
criticize one's own "insights". Students must keep a record of their insights and
submit "insight papers" throughout the semester. Learning the insightful theories
of past philosophers, as described in the book, should provide plenty of examples
of how this can be done. In this fourth edition, I have incorporated into the main
text some advice regarding how to have and write about insights. Students are
advised to pay close attention to Lecture 2 in this regard, and to the list (on p.8)
indicating sections of other relevant lectures that discuss the nature of insight in
more depth. Sample insight papers will often be read during class sessions to
illustrate various points being considered that week. Ideally, these paper should
not be graded, except on a "pass-fail" basis, thus allowing maximum freedom of
expression to the students-though this may not be possible in some educational
settings.
All students, especially those using this book in a class not taught by the
author, should keep in mind that no textbook should be used as a substitute for
developing your own perspective on philosophical issues or your own critical
appraisals of past philosophers-two clues to being a good philosopher that work
best in combination. The "myth of the tree" that you will learn in this course is
intended to assist you in both these areas (especially the former), but only in the
early stages of your philosophical development. Your examination of past
philosophers in particular ought to be supplemented by reading a good anthology,
such as Wolff's Ten Great Works of Philosophy or any of a host of others, and by
consulting the recommended readings as frequently as possible.
Anyone reading The Tree without the guidance of a teacher should keep in
mind that the book is meant to be read slowly, to be "mulled over", roughly one
chapter (i.e., three lectures) per week. Those who imagine their reading to be part
of a real 12-week course, requiring concentrated periods of individual reflection
and critical writing each week, are much more likely to benefit from the emphasis
on insight than those who simply read the book through as quickly as possible.
The point is not that this book cannot be read quickly, but that it will not have its
maximum effect unless the ideas and theories it describes are gradually put into
practice in the reader's own philosophical thinking and writing.
In addition to reading roughly three lectures per week, those who opt for
this more challenging approach should also try to do some of the recommended
readings each week. A good way to compensate for not having a teacher is to read
the book concurrently with a friend or family member, or as part of a small group
of people who can share their progress with each other in an atmosphere of
trust.Spend an hour or two each week thinking about and/or discussing the
questions/topics provided for that purpose. These suggestions may seem silly; but
following them is the best way to infuse the reading of this book with the power
to promote significant philosophical development. Taking this slower, 12-week
approach will give the reader's insights a chance to mature and deepen in
interaction with the topics discussed in the text. Reading ahead or rushing through
the book too quickly is sure to limit the reader's ability to learn the skill of having
and criticizing insights.
A Note on References
Acknowledgments
3 July 2000
Student D.
1.What is Philosophy?
"That's silly", you're probably thinking, "we are taking this course because
we don't know what philosophy is, so how do you expect us to answer such a
fundamental question at the very beginning of the first day?"
Trust me. Taking just ten or fifteen minutes here at the outset to attempt to
answer this question will give us a very good start on understanding what
philosophy is. Now, if your mind is blank, try thinking about what we are doing
right now. What is it about what we are doing right now that is different from
what is done in other academic subjects?
Students. "Hmm."
Come on, who wants to be first? Don't be shy.... You know, the first time I
ever taught this course, the first person who tried to answer this question ended up
earning an "A"! Now, who would like to be first?
Yes. This is indeed a central part of the philosopher's task. By the way, the
second time I taught this course, the first person who tried to answer this question
ended up with a "D"-so don't expect an easy "A"! A problem with your answer is
that we often think in ways that could not really be called "philosophical". So,
how does philosophical thinking differ from other types of thinking?
Student B. "It is abstract. There are no definite answers. Everyone has their
own idea about philosophical issues, and nobody can claim to have the absolute
truth."
But let's continue observing what we are doing right now, and try to get
more clues as to the nature of philosophy. Some philosophers have said that in
philosophy, as in life itself, "we are building the boat in which we are floating."
So, what then are we -- yes?
The last two divisions are both practical. The third could be called "applied
philosophy". Now the application of meaningful words should lead to knowledge,
and the English word "science" comes from the Latin word sciens, which means
"knowing"; so we can call this third division science, provided we remember that
we are not using this word in the same way it is normally used in everyday
language. The question of this philosophical sort of science is "Where is the
proper boundary line between knowledge and ignorance?". The fourth division,
ontology, asks question such as "What does it mean to exist?" By asking and
answering ontological questions, philosophers hope to improve our understanding
of the essential characteristics of distinct types of things (e.g., animals, human
beings, or God), or of types of experiences (e.g., beauty, love, or death).
We will, of course, ask many other philosophical questions during this course, but
these four deserve to be regarded as fundamental.
The task of doing philosophy can be understood in three ways. The first
views philosophy as the process of using logical thinking to solve difficult
problems by clarifying our concepts. In twentieth century western philosophy, the
school of "analytic philosophy", which in one form or another dominated the
English speaking world for most of that century, typically adopted this notion as
its hallmark. Analytic philosophers tend to regard philosophy as a specialized kind
of scientific profession, sometimes explicitly rejecting the notion that it should be
closely related to our daily life.
The first hour is drawing to a close now, but we have time for one more
suggestion as to how we can answer our main question. I wonder if anyone has a
different sort of answer from the ones we have been considering so far. For
philosophy is many things, and we have really only scratched the surface of
possible answers.
What sort of wonder? Do you mean just looking up at the sky and
daydreaming? Or do you have in mind transporting yourself into a purely
imaginary world, as in the story, Alice in Wonderland?
Well, we have obviously not yet finished answering our question. Indeed,
the question "What is philosophy?" should be kept at the back of our minds
throughout the entirety of this course. If we were able to answer it completely
today, then we could all quit here and the remaining thirty-five lectures would be
redundant. But this is far from being the case. Instead, I want to suggest to you
that by the end of this course you will (hopefully) know less about philosophy
than you did before you came to class today!
I say that because, as we shall see, philosophy actually begins with the
recognition of ignorance. The reason for beginning an introductory course by
studying metaphysics is precisely that metaphysics can teach us the difference
between what we can and cannot know. Only when we have learned this will we
be prepared to learn from logic how we go about gaining an understanding of
words. In particular, logic should teach us the difference between what words
mean when they refer to something we can know about, and what they mean
when they refer to something of which we are necessarily ignorant. Once we have
this theoretical foundation to build on, we can apply our new understanding in
practical ways. We do this by reaching out for truth and knowledge that is
relevant to human life, and this search for a true "science" is properly called the
love of wisdom. By loving wisdom we can enter into the fourth stage of the
philosophical task without being "lost in wonderland", so to speak. For the final
task is to learn truly to appreciate the wonder of silence. In a sense, all philosophy
begins with silent wonder. Yet, as we shall see in Part Four of this course, it ends
in silent wonder as well.
This gives us plenty to think about for the first lesson. I'll conclude simply
by adding that the four tasks I've just described correspond exactly to the four
"branches" of philosophy listed in Figure I.1 , and can be mapped onto the same
cross, as follows:
At the end of each chapter or "week" (i.e., after each set of three lectures
recorded in this book), I provide four pairs of "Questions for Further
Thought/Dialogue", with some blank space in case you want to jot down a few
notes as you think about each question. You may wish to use these as topics for
some of your insight papers, though any topic is acceptable, provided you treat it
in a philosophical way. In either case you should not search through this book for
a "set" solution to the problem you choose to reflect and write about. Insight
papers are a record of your own insights, not mine-though of course, you might
find it helpful to use the contents of my lectures as a springboard for developing
your own unique way of thinking.
Insight papers are by far the most important aspect of this course, because
they complement the lectures and readings with a real, personal experience of
philosophizing. Where relevant, students' insight papers are therefore used as the
basis for class discussions. The task of discussing the implications of the issues
raised in various papers is often interesting enough to occupy most of any given
class hour. The remaining time is devoted to a discussion of questions arising out
of the textbook and other readings assigned for that day. This means that from the
second class session onwards every student is expected to read the relevant lecture
in this book before the class hour to which it corresponds. It would also be helpful
for you to read at least some of the texts listed in the "Recommended Readings"
sections each week. These are usually arranged in order, starting with shorter or
more specific texts that were mentioned in the lectures, and ending with more
lengthy and/or general texts that will assist you in exploring more deeply the
implications of the topics discussed in that week's lectures. These readings should
also serve to stimulate insights and can often provide good topics for insight
papers.
Keeping in mind the following guidelines should help you read more
insightfully:
1. Don't worry if you do not understand every word and every sentence.
3. Underline the main points, and try to catch the general flow of the argument.
4. Excessive underlining will defeat the purpose and make review too difficult.
5. For short definitions of key terms, refer to the Glossary at the end of this text.
6. Interact with the text. If you disagree, write your reasons in the margin; if you
agree, write something like "yes!" If it reminds you of something else, make a
note of this; if you're confused, write "?", then ask for clarification in class.
7. When you find an interesting passage in the textbook, spend more time on it,
then seek out Recommended Readings or ask the lecturer for further references.
8. If a passage is boring you, try to read faster or just skim until you reach a more
interesting part. You can form a quick idea of the content by reading the first few
and last few paragraphs and the first sentence of every paragraph in between. (Use
this for extra, Recommended Readings, not for the textbook!)
What? An insight paper is a short record of your own thoughts, ideas, and rea‐
soning on any topic, provided you can treat it in a philosophical way. Preparing
and writing such papers is one of the most important aspects of this class. You
should therefore write an insight paper after having one or more periods of at
least fifteen minutes of concentrated thinking or meditating (pondering) on some‐
thing philosophical. In addition to the questions given at the end of each week,
here are a few examples of the kinds of subject you might choose to ponder: any
question or issue raised in these lectures or discussed in class; a question about the
meaning or nature of something; a theory or argument put forward by some
philosopher you have read about; an object or idea which you think is beautiful or
unusual; an experience you regard as philosophically profound; etc.
How? Be concise! Don't think that longer papers will always get better results.
This is not true. Sometimes several sentences might be enough to demonstrate
that you have a significant philosophical insight. Anything that is not directly
related to the insight itself should be summarized or omitted. Your paper should
devote as little space as possible to describing background information, such as
other people's ideas. Most of the space should be devoted to your own reflections,
criticisms, analysis, ideas for possible answers, etc. As a general rule, you should
think in terms of one side of a standard sheet of paper as being long enough. If
you need to use two pages, please help to preserve trees by writing on both sides
(front and back) of one sheet of paper.
How many? Write as many insight papers as you can! If you are using this book
as a textbook for a class, consult the syllabus for details on the number of required
insight papers, their due dates, and other more specific guidelines.
Why? The purpose of the insight papers is for you to practice the skill of doing
philosophy, by allowing you to explore philosophical ideas in depth. So you
should write them with this in mind. Ask questions that drive your thinking below
the surface, such as "why?", "what does it mean?", "how do I know?", "what is
it?", etc. Do not simply repeat someone else's ideas. You can mention other
people's ideas (e.g. the theories of some philosopher you have studied), but try to
do this as briefly as possible. Most of the paper should be devoted to an
explanation and analysis of your own ideas. Both creativity and careful
argumentation will be highly valued, as well as clarity and orderliness. The mere
statement of your own opinion, with no reasons given for support, is not
satisfactory. Opinions can be mentioned as a starting point for further inquiry, but
genuine insights are more than just undefended opinions.
What next? The insight papers should be used as the basis for discussions, both
inside and outside of class. The former will require some papers to be read
(anonymously) in front of the whole class. (If you ever write something you
would not want to be read in class, you should write somewhere on your paper
"Please do not read this in class, because..." and explain the reason.) Normally, the
papers will be returned at the end of the next class session; the key points will be
underlined, and some relevant questions or comments will be written on your
paper. These do not necessarily reflect the lecturer's own point of view, but are
intended to help you think more deeply about the issues raised.
The question that is probably on the mind of most student readers at this
point is: how are insight papers going to be graded? (Non-student readers may
wish to skip this and the following paragraph.) Of course, different teachers will
inevitably have different criteria for judging the relative merits of such
assignments. My own practise is to look for a balance between creativity, clarity,
and critical rigor (i.e., examining the pros and cons of a variety of possible
viewpoints). A rough grading scale can be based directly on these three criteria, as
follows. An "A" paper will be one that is strong in all three areas. A "B" paper
should be either strong in two areas, but rather weak in the third area, or strong in
one area and mediocre in the other two. Likewise, a "C" paper could be either
strong in one area and weak in the other two, or mediocre in all three areas. A "D"
paper will not be strong in any of the three areas and will be significantly lacking
in one or two areas. And a paper will fail if it is weak in all three areas; this
usually means most or all of the paper has been merely copied from some other
source, or that the paper consists of nothing but the description of a story, event,
etc., with no attempt whatsoever to reflect on its implications.
Once you have had an insight and chosen a topic on that basis, you should
do more than just state what your insight is. That is, you should not be satisfied
merely to ask a question and then give the "right" answer. Instead, you should
analyze the validity of your insight by considering objections other people might
make and providing reasons to support your position. Such an approach will
prevent your insight from looking like nothing but an expression of your opinion.
For the same reason, you should consider a variety of possible positions-perhaps
even all possible positions, if you can. That is, you should consider the issue from
as many different perspectives as possible.
This term, "perspective", will turn out to be one of the most important
technical terms in this entire course. A perspective is a way of looking at
something, or a general context for interpreting an issue, and determines to a large
extent what kind of answer will be given. An important lesson to learn as early as
possible in your philosophical education is that the same question can have
different right answers, if a different perspective is being assumed. Much more
will be said about this as we proceed through the course.
The comments I write on student insight papers are usually intended to
assist in this process of seeing the issue from a variety of perspectives. As a result,
what I write does not necessarily represent my own view; more often I merely ask
a question that I think the paper has neglected and should therefore be taken into
consideration if/when any further reflection is done on that topic. If you are not
reading this book as part of a class, then I suggest you find a philosophically-
minded friend with whom you can exchange insight papers. Read and comment
on each other's papers regularly, with the aim of assisting each other in thinking
more deeply about the issues in question.
3.Philosophy as Myth
Once there was a tree, and her name was "Philosophy"....
Throughout this entire course I would like us all to treat this little one-line
story as if it holds the key to the nature of philosophy. We can express the same
idea in the more philosophical form of an analogy by saying "philosophy is like a
tree". In either case, we are assuming as a given-an unquestionable starting point
for all our inquiries-that the nature and constituent parts of trees give us clues as
to the nature and constituent parts of philosophy. Like any genuine
presupposition, there is no way of defending this starting point with
incontrovertible proofs; the best we can do is to believe in its truth and value, and
then explore its various implications. If the final result is less than satisfactory, we
can always discard the presupposition and start again with some new hypothesis.
But in the meantime, I shall return to this analogy on repeated occasions during
this course in hopes of gaining deeper and clearer insights into the discipline we
call "philosophy".
This means the assumption that there was once a tree called "Philosophy"
will serve as the myth that guides and holds together the various ideas we will be
discussing. The word "myth", when used in this way, does not mean "a false story
or belief", as it ordinarily does in its everyday English usage. Rather, I am using it
here in the special way some anthropologists use it in their descriptions of the
primitive origins of religion. Today I want to explore this new sense of the word
"myth", not only so that we can understand more clearly what it means to say the
"tree of philosophy" will serve as our myth, but also because, as we shall see, the
origins of philosophy itself are to a large extent rooted in this special type of
mythological thinking.
In the first chapter of Myth and Reality, Mircea Eliade, one of the past
century's most influential scholars in the scientific study of religion, provides a
good explanation of the way myths function in primitive societies. Since the
meaning he assigns to the word "myth" is quite similar to the one I want us to
assume, I would like to highlight several of the important points he makes. First,
he defines a myth as an old story about the origin of the world or the things in the
world, which in some way explains why human existence is the way it is, or why
one's own cultural norms have developed the way they have. The myth of
Prometheus, for example, tells us, among other things, about the origin of fire. A
society's customs relating to sexuality, family relationships, and death are among
the most common subjects of its myths.
The actors in these myths are usually gods, other supernatural beings, or
heroes with superhuman powers. Unfortunately, this tends to obscure for the
modern reader the fact that these stories functioned primarily as models for
human behavior. Nevertheless, during the twentieth century there were numerous
attempts to show that ancient myths tell the story, so to speak of Everyman. The
psychologist Sigmund Freud, for example, argued that the myth of Oedipus, the
man whose fate it was to kill his father and marry his mother, tells the story of the
childhood experience of every little boy, not just those who lived in ancient
Greece. (See Lecture 8 of Dreams for further details.) Likewise, whenever we
read an ancient myth, it is helpful to regard all the characters as, in one sense or
another, telling the story of who we are. If I read a myth as a story of myself, then
what once seemed aloof and irrelevant suddenly takes on a new meaning.
The histories of most cultures look back to an original "golden age" when
human life was significantly different from the way it is now. And the longing for
a return to this golden age (often closely related to the "dream time" or "mythical
time" mentioned earlier) is the impetus for much cultural change. For the early
Hebrews, the golden age was the Garden of Eden, where Adam and Eve "walked
with God in the cool of the evening". For the Chinese people in the age of
Confucius (551-479 B.C.), the golden age was the period of the "sage kings",
when China was ruled with wisdom and benevolence. Since western philosophy,
which will be the primary focus of this course, began in ancient Greece, it is most
significant for us to note that the Greeks also believed in a golden age. Let us
therefore look briefly at the history of ancient Greece in order to gain some
understanding of how philosophy was born from myth.
Some scholars believe the dream of the golden age in ancient Greece
referred back to the Minoan-Mycenaean culture, which had ended by the time of
the Trojan War (circa 1200 B.C.). This age was the inspiration for the making of
the Greek myths (see MM 87-89 and BM 213-215,278). The next major
development in Greek history was "the creation of the Homeric epics [c.900
B.C.], which derived their material from this complex of myths" (MM 88, BM
464). These epics converted the unorganized mass of myths into a poetic form,
rendering their meaning more apparent (BM 256f). But human consciousness had
not yet developed into the form we know it today. According to Jaynes, our
modern "subjective conscious mind" replaced a more primitive way of thinking
"in the sixth century B.C." (259-260,285-286)-that is, at about the same time as
the appearance of the first philosopher in ancient Greece, named Thales (c.624-
c.546 B.C.). There then followed three centuries of intense philosophical activity
in Greece, culminating in the work of a philosopher named Aristotle (384-322
B.C.). Aristotle's work was significant because, as we shall see in Lecture 6, he
was the first major Greek philosopher to develop something like a "scientific"
point of view, in the modern sense of that term. If we place these major
developments on a time line, this rough sketch of ancient Greek history looks like
this:
The three hundred year gaps between each of the major changes
represented in this diagram are, of course, only approximations of the dates when
these changes actually occurred. Nevertheless, it is significant that history itself
suggests to us such a regular pattern of development. The pattern is, in fact,
reminiscent of the face of a clock, consisting as it does of twelve parts
(hours/centuries) grouped into four quarters. (In Week V we will examine the
logical structure of this pattern, which also provides the basis for the systematic
organization of the chapters in this book.) Interestingly, this whole period of
ancient Greek civilization is itself regarded by some as a "golden age"-a fact
suggesting that this pattern is one that repeats itself indefinitely. If so, then a good
way to picture the relationships between these four developments would be to
map them onto a clock-face (i.e., a circle divided into four quadrants).
If we now recall the fact that our modern (A.D.) calendar starts at the point
where Figure I.5 leaves off (namely, at the birth of Jesus, albeit, not in Greece),
then we can see that the best way to map this time line onto a circle is to proceed
backwards (putting the 9:00 term in the 3:00 position and vice versa), just as our
reckoning of B.C. dates goes in the reverse order of our reckoning of A.D. dates.
This gives us the map of four interrelated human thought forms shown in Figure
I.6.
is like living inside a circle without knowing anything about the existence of the
circle itself. This is because mythological thinking is ignorant of all boundary
lines. Poets withdraw themselves from the circle of myth just enough to recognize
the existence of the boundary line. Poetry attempts to express the myth in such a
way as to enable its meaning to be understood by those who live completely
outside the boundary. Hence the poet lives on the boundary. Philosophers, by
contrast, step completely beyond the boundary line; yet they remain close enough
to the "circle" of myth to recognize the reality and significance of the "hidden
meaning" contained in the myth's poetic expression. The philosopher attempts to
explain that meaning in a more literal or objective way: whereas the poet
can write poetry without explicitly questioning the myth, the philosopher must
question the myth. That, indeed, is one of the main tasks of philosophy. Scientists
differ from philosophers by withdrawing themselves so far from the realm of
myth that they are no longer able to see the presence of any hidden meaning
whatsoever. Whereas the philosopher questions the truth value of the myth (i.e.,
remains open to the possibility of seeing truth revealed in it), the scientist rejects
the myth as nothing but a "false story" (see Figure I.4). Scientists live so far away
from the myth that, if they see the circle of myth at all, it appears to be only a
point way off in the distance, with no meaningful content.
Obviously, the everyday use of the term "myth" derives its meaning from
our modern culture's tendency to put absolute trust in science. Yet ironically, our
way of using this key term reveals that science itself shares some of the same
characteristics as myths, such as ignorance of the boundary lines. And this raises
the question as to whether or not the four basic thought forms might function as a
cycle, whereby science itself, when taken to an extreme, becomes another form of
myth. With this in mind, one of our main tasks in this course, if we are to become
good philosophers in the present climate, will be to call into question the
exclusive rights of the scientific world view over our minds. Next week we will
therefore begin by examining the cyclical nature of these four human thought
forms in more detail. We will then pay special attention to the developments in
ancient Greece, where two of the most influential systems of philosophy were
produced, systems that typify the two main ways of doing philosophy (cf. Figure
I.2) so effectively that they continue to bear the fruit of insight to this day.
1. A. What is philosophy?
RECOMMENDED READINGS
1. Shel Silverstein, The Giving Tree (New York: Harper & Row, 1964).
3. Richard Osborne, Philosophy for Beginners (New York: Writers and Readers
Publishing, Inc., 1992).
4. Robert Paul Wolff, About Philosophy5 (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall,
1992[1976]), Ch. 1, "What Is Philosophy?", and Appendix, "How to Write a
Philosophy Paper", pp.1-37, 452-472.
5. Roger L. Dominowski and Pamela Dallob, "Insight and Problem Solving", Ch.
2 in R.J. Sternberg and J.E. Davidson (ed.), The Nature of Insight (Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press, 1995), pp.33-62.
6. Mircea Eliade, Myth and Reality (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1964), Ch.
One, "The Structure of Myths", pp.1-20.
7. Richard A. Underwood, "Living by Myth: Joseph Campbell, C.G. Jung, and the
Religious Life-Journey", Ch. 2 in D.C. Noel (ed.), Paths to the Power of Myth
(New York: Crossroad, 1990), pp.13-28.
4. PhilosophyasMetaphysicalDemythologizing
Having seen in Week I that philosophy is born out of myth, we must now
acknowledge that myth as such is not philosophy. On the contrary, the path that
leads from myth to science, through poetry and philosophy, could be called the
path of "demythologizing". This term refers to the process of taking the "myth"
(in the modern sense of "false beliefs") out of myth-i.e., questioning our
unquestioned beliefs in hopes of transforming them into a more reliable
expression of the truth. Thus, for example, when I suggested in the previous
lecture that we all regard "the tree of philosophy" as the myth for this course, I
was not really doing philosophy. Rather, I was preparing the ground in which the
tree itself will be planted. After you finish this course, I hope you will take the
time to question seriously not only the myth, but also the (poetic) analogy that
"philosophy is like a tree". But if you question this presupposition here at the
beginning, you may find that the ground of your mind will be too hard to receive
the insights this myth can inspire.
One such insight is that, just as a tree is an organic whole consisting of four main
parts (the roots, the trunk, the branches, and the leaves), so also many, if not most,
sets of philosophical ideas are organized according to such a pattern. We have
already seen several such patterns in the first two sessions. But before we look at
some examples of how demythologization worked in ancient Greece, I would like
to point out several other interesting fourfold patterns.
If the "myth, poetry, philosophy, science" pattern is regarded as a description of
the way human thinking develops on a macrocosmic scale (i.e., in human
cultures), then we should not be surprised to find a similar pattern operating on a
microcosmic scale (i.e., in human individuals). One of the most common ways of
describing the stages of an individual's development is to refer to a person's birth,
youth, maturity, and old age. By correlating each of these with a progressively
higher level of consciousness, the pattern shown in Figure II.1 emerges. Just as
the progression from birth to youth coincides with the awakening of a child's
unconscious mind, so also the progression from youth to maturity requires the
gradual sharpening of consciousness, until a distinct awareness of one's own self
arises. And the self-conscious person whose natural development is not
interrupted eventually enters into a new stage which, for want of a better term, we
can call super-consciousness. The elderly
of the Individual
"golden age" that many cultures look back to (see Lecture 3). Yet the latter
corresponds not to old age but to the pre-natal experiences of the baby in its
mother's womb. Mapping these relations onto a circle appropriately suggests the
cyclical character of the development we are here considering: super-
consciousness may well involve a recapturing of something a person loses at
birth-an idea we will see Plato defending in
Lecture 5.
Each
of these four stages can also be
correlated with a particular
"faculty", or power, of the
human mind, as shown in Figure
II.2. Imagination is the power
governing the earliest years of
our life, just as myth governs the
thinking of those who live in
primitive cultures. As everyone
knows, the difference between
fantasy and reality is not distinct
in the mind of a true child. In
youth, how-
Figure II.2:
ever, this power is overcome by passion: as the physical body changes in puberty,
so also the mind changes the way it adapts to the world. The poet is driven by this
passion to express in words what for the child is only a dream. Philosophers, by
contrast, are not usually known for their passion. This is because the power
corresponding to mature self-consciousness is the power of understanding. This
power, when developed to its fullest extent, is transformed into the power of
judgment. The task of scientists is to transcend their own point of view in order to
judge how the world really is. Likewise, the people who truly deserve to be called
"old" are those whose minds are governed primarily by this power of judgment.
Determining what each of these powers aims to express will give us a more
complete understanding of the interrelationships between these ideas. Myth uses
imagination to express beliefs. Poetry uses passion to express beauty. Philosophy
uses understanding to express truth. And science uses judgment to express
knowledge. We can represent these ultimate goals by mapping them onto a square
that encompasses the circle presented in Figure II.2, as shown below:
I have taken the time to show you these patterns not only because I think they are
intrinsically interesting, but also because they should help you see philosophy in
its proper context. And the better your understanding of that context, the stronger
will be the roots of your own philosophical "tree". The diagrams in Figures II.1-3
depict logical patterns, so many of their implications will not become clear until
we study logic in the second part of this course (especially Week V).
Nevertheless, it might be helpful at this point to take a brief look at the origins of
logic itself, since the proper employment of logic is necessary in order for
demythologization to take place.
The English word "logic" comes from the Greek word logos, meaning "word"-
including the spoken word ("speech"), the written word ("book"), and the thought
word ("reason"). But in Ancient Greece logos was also sometimes used to refer to
what we can call the hidden meaning in a myth. In this sense, the logos of a thing
is its final purpose or ultimate nature. This is how the Bible uses the word when,
for example, St. John's Gospel begins by exclaiming: "In the beginning was the
logos, and the logos was with God, and the logos was God." The person who lives
in a myth experiences this logos firsthand, and so has no need to explain it. The
poet is the first to recognize the need to use words to express the passion with
which an experience of the logos fills a person. The philosopher tries to
understand the logos in such a way as to separate truth from fiction. And the
scientist forgets the logos altogether in search of concrete facts that can be
manipulated. This "forgetting" is the source of the modern problem of
meaninglessness or "alienation" and will occupy our attention at several points
later on (see e.g., Lecture 18).
The process of moving from an intimate experience of the logos to a state wherein
its presence is forgotten is the process of demythologization. Forgetting the logos
is in a sense a catastrophe for mankind, and yet in another sense, as we shall see
in Lecture 9, such forgetting (or at least, ignoring) is a necessary requirement in
order for knowledge to arise. Science requires us to forget the hidden logos
because factual knowledge admits only what is openly revealed. Indeed, the
difficulties we all have in thinking in terms of this logos arise as a direct result of
the fact that we live in an age dominated by the scientific world view, which finds
no proper place for the logos. Yet it is always possible for a person to recapture
the meaning of myth, even after forgetting it in the process of attaining
knowledge. Nurturing the tree of philosophy within ourselves is one of the best
ways to revive the memory of that forgotten reality.
The earliest demythologizers in ancient Greece were the philosophers who lived
during the period of time from Thales to Aristotle (see Figure I.5). With two
important exceptions (to be discussed in the next lecture), these philosophers are
referred to as "presocratic" philosophers, because they lived before a very
influential philosopher named Socrates. One of the main concerns of the
presocratics was to describe the nature of "ultimate reality". And this, as I
mentioned in Lecture 1, is the main task of the branch of philosophy we now call
"metaphysics". Several of these early demythologizers regarded one of the four
traditional "elements" (or something like it) as constituting ultimate reality. Thales
himself argued that everything can ultimately be reduced to water. Anaximenes
(c.585-c.528) disagreed, claiming the most basic element is actually air. Not long
afterwards, Heraclitus (fl.500-480), who had some interesting ideas about the
logic of opposites (see Lecture 12), suggested that fire is the best candidate for a
basic metaphysical building-block. Democritus (c.460-c.371) then defended the
earliest form of "atomism", viewing the fundamental element as "being", or
simply what is. By this he meant something similar to what we mean by "matter",
thus suggesting at least a rough correspondence to the earth element, since the
latter clearly refers not merely to soil, but to all solid matter. These four early
metaphysical positions can be mapped onto a cross, as follows:
As the diagram suggests, the best of the early answers to the question of ultimate
reality was given by Anaximander (c.610-c.546), who argued that none of the four
elements is properly regarded as basic, since they necessarily stand in opposition
to each other (like wet and dry, hot and cold). If one element were "boundless",
then it would destroy all the others. He stood, as it were, at the center of the cross,
recognizing the need for all four elements to be held together in a creative tension.
Empedocles (c.495-435) further developed this view, regarding all four elements
as basic realities, explaining the tensions as being held together by the opposing
forces of "love" (philia) and "strife" (neikos).
Regardless of which answer to this question you think is best, we must beware of
regarding any of them as attempting to explain the nature of the physical world.
For the word "metaphysics" means "after" or "beyond" physics (i.e., "nature"). So
we must be careful not to think these philosophers were arguing that everything
on the earth is quite literally made out of (for example) fire. That is obviously not
true, otherwise we would have all burned up long ago! Moreover, such
explanations are the task of science, not philosophy. Instead, we should regard
these philosophers' theories as the earliest attempts to discover a single,
irreducible truth that lies behind the diverse appearances of our everyday
experience. In other words, they were trying to grasp the hidden meaning of their
own mythical heritage from a position outside the myth itself. The result was what
we might today call "symbolic" explanations for how we can solve the problem of
metaphysics. (The nature of symbolism will be discussed in Lecture 31.)
However, as we shall see in our next session, all these solutions were bound to
fail.
Little is known of Socrates' life, and some scholars even question whether such a
person ever really lived; but for our purposes we can ignore such debates. For
even if his character was merely an invention of Plato and his contemporaries, the
fact is that it soon came to serve as a "myth" that has guided the development of
western philosophy for more than two millennia. Socrates was a highly original
thinker who practiced what he preached. Although he was a member in good
standing of the political elite in Athens, he willingly gave up his position
sometime in mid-life in order to live a life of "extreme poverty" as a philosopher
(PA 23b). During this time he spent his days going around engaging people in
conversations on various issues. He often clashed with the Sophists, the popular
professional philosophers who would dispense their "wisdom" (typically, hair-
splitting distinctions without any universal applications) for a fee. Although
Socrates insisted he was not a teacher (33a), a group of young men (one of whom
was Plato) soon gathered around him, interested in learning the art of doing
philosophy in this new way.
The most significant part of Socrates' career, as recorded by Plato in his Apology,
began when his lifelong friend, Chaerephon, asked the Delphic oracle whether
there was anyone wiser than Socrates. When Socrates heard that the priestess had
answered "no", he felt he had been presented with a riddle to solve, since he
believed he did not deserve to be called wise. So he went around interviewing all
those who had the reputation of being wise, such as politicians, poets, and
artisans, in hopes of learning from them what wisdom really is. But in each case,
their attempt to explain their own "wisdom" was frustrated by Socrates' persistent
questioning. Not only were they unable to explain in what their "wisdom"
consisted, but Socrates publicly attempted to "prove" to such men that they were
not, in fact, wise. Naturally, by questioning all of the traditional myths held by the
wealthy and powerful members of his society, he made plenty of enemies! But for
Socrates this was not important, since in so doing he was able to discover "that
the people with the greatest reputations [for wisdom] were almost entirely
deficient, while others who were supposed to be their inferiors were much better
qualified in practical intelligence" (PA 22a).
Socrates' final conclusion (PA 23a-b) was that the oracle did contain a riddle, but
its solution is a bitter pill to swallow for those whose role in society requires them
to defend the glories of human wisdom:
[Some people have described] me as a professor of wisdom.... But the truth of the
matter ... is pretty certainly this, that real wisdom is the property of God, and this
oracle is his way of telling us that human wisdom has little or no value. It seems
to me that he is not referring literally to Socrates, but has merely taken my name
as an example, as if he would say to us, The wisest of you men is he who has
realized, like Socrates, that in respect of wisdom he is really worthless.
The price Socrates paid for this insight was his life. For the powerful citizens of
Athens took him to court, accusing him "of corrupting the minds of the young,
and of believing in deities of his own invention instead of the gods recognized by
the state" (PA 24b). During his trial, he defended himself not by pleading for
mercy or promising to behave in a more civilized way, but by speaking openly
and harshly to his accusers. He explained how the philosophic life is a life that is
worth dying for. The philosopher is the person who obeys the imperative of the
inscription on the temple at Delphi, "Know thyself". The person who fails to
accept this challenge is in a sad situation, for "life without this sort of examination
is not worth living" (38a). Indeed, Socrates clearly regarded the life of self-
examination as one lived in service to God: although he intentionally cast doubt
on the proliferation of gods in the Greek tradition, Socrates himself regarded
philosophy as a divinely inspired vocation. Only by living such a life can a person
be virtuous, and so help to usher in a just society:
For I spend all my time going about trying to persuade you, young and old, to
make your first and chief concern not for your bodies nor for your possessions,
but for the highest welfare of your souls ... Wealth does not bring goodness [i.e.,
virtue], but goodness brings wealth and every other blessing, both to the
individual and to the state. (30a-b)
Such statements, of course, must have seemed like a slap in the face to those he
was speaking to, many of whom would have regarded Socrates as a friend, since
he had himself been a member of that very court at one time. So it is hardly
surprising that when the votes were counted, Socrates was condemned to death
(albeit, by the surprisingly narrow margin of 281 to 220). But instead of being
outraged by this decision, Socrates accepted it with calm integrity, predicting that
the number of those who are willing to question the status quo-i.e., the number of
philosophers-will increase, rather than decrease, as a result of his death (PA 39c)!
Rather than shrinking back in fear of death, he boldly described how his task as a
philosopher had been the task of learning how to die. Thus Plato's Apology ends
(42a) with Socrates exclaiming: "Now it is time that we were going, I to die and
you to live, but which of us has the happier prospect is unknown to anyone but
God."
Plato presented his philosophical ideas in the form of Dialogues. These books
transform Socrates' habit of persistent questioning into a specific philosophical
method. On one level, a is simply a book that records a conversation between a main speaker-
usually Socrates in Plato's Dialogues-and one or more secondary characters. In the course of
this conversation the main character acts as a
"midwife" for the potential insights waiting to be "born" in the minds of the secondary
characters. (Socrates' mother, incidentally, was a midwife by profession.) In other words, just
as a good midwife coaches the pregnant mother so that the mother can give birth to her baby
(rather than the midwife having to take the baby out by force), so also Socrates asks questions
and offers suggestions in order, as it were, to "coach" the secondary characters into discovering
the desired conclusion without having to be told what it is. But on a deeper level, the
significance of this new method lies in its appeal to a higher authority, reason, as the proper
arbitrator of all disputes. As depicted in Figure II.6,
the dialogue is carried out under the assumption that this higher authority, to which all
participants have equal access, is capable of imparting a deeper understanding of ultimate reali-
ty, or truth.Plato used the method of dialogue to construct, on the basis of his understanding of
Socrates' ideas (though undoubt-edly going beyond them in certain respects), the first
thoroughgoing system of metaphysics with a modern ring. His philosophy, which provides the
archetype of all "idealist" metaphysical systems, is far too complex to study in any depth in an
introductory course. However, looking briefly into his theories of knowledge and of human
nature should provide us with a good sampling of how his idealism works.
The branch of philosophy concerned with answering questions about the nature and origin of
human knowledge is called "Epistemology" (from the Greek words
epistemos, meaning "knowledge", and logos, here best taken to mean "the study of").
Metaphysics and epistemology are always intimately related to each other, because a
philosopher's understanding of what reality ultimately is will inevitably influence his or her
account of how we know what is real, and vice versa. So for
the remainder of our study of metaphysics, I shall include in my account of each major
philosopher a description of his epistemology.
Plato's epistemology is based on the metaphysical assumption that "universals"
(or what he sometimes calls "forms" or "ideas") are the only true reality, whereas
"particulars" (i.e., "matter" or "things") are only appearances of this reality. In
much of our everyday experience we therefore suffer from the illusion that the
things and objects around us in the physical world constitute the ultimate reality.
But the actual situation for human beings, according to Plato, is that our ideas
reveal to us not merely subjective inner states, but the true nature of reality itself.
The philosopher's ultimate task, therefore, is to look beyond the mere appearances
of things in order to come to know these ideas.
been prisoners inside a cave since their childhood. Their necks and legs are
chained in such a way that they are unable to look toward the opening of the cave.
There is a wall behind them, and on the other side of the wall other people carry
objects of different sorts that stick up over the wall. Behind them all is the light
from a great fire, later identified as the sun. The prisoners are able to see only the
shadows these objects cast on the back of the cave. Having never known anything
other than these shapes and images, they mistakenly treat the shadows as the real
objects.
The analogy, at least in this simplified form, is quite straightforward. The cave
represents the world we live in and the prisoners in chains represent those who
have not yet learned to philosophize. The shadows are the material objects
("appearances") we normally treat as real. And the objects casting the shadows are
the true "forms" of these appearances, whose nature can be revealed to us through
philosophical reflection. The philosopher's task, therefore, is to become aware of
these true forms by breaking the chains that bind us to the illusory reality of the
material world; this is done by reflecting upon our ideas, and learning to treat
them as the ultimate reality. This is Plato's version of the recognition of ignorance:
our ignorance remains only as long as we continue to make the mistake of treating
the material world as ultimately real. For this happens whenever we turn our
backs on the sun, which represents the highest of all ideas in Plato's system, the
idea of "the good". Goodness is the reality from which the light of reason and
truth shines forth, thus enabling us to see all the other eternal forms.
Plato constructed a hierarchical system of ideas, ranging from those that are more
closely connected to the material world (e.g., ideas relating to human desires) to
those that can take us virtually all the way out of the cave. Of the latter, truth and
beauty join goodness to constitute the three highest ideas. Although we sometimes
find approximations to them in the material world, these ideas can never in
themselves be perfectly manifested in the world of appearances. We can never
point to something in the world and say "there it is; that is the thing we call truth".
This is because truth is an eternally existing form that never changes or passes
away. Plato advised young philosophers to begin by coming to know the lower
forms, working their way up to a universal vision of ultimate reality, which (like
the "super-conscious" state discussed in Lecture 4) is likely to occur only rather
late in life. The form of knowledge that serves as the most reliable guide along the
way, he argued, is mathematics, and within mathematics, geometry. Perhaps this
is one good reason why the use of diagrams can be helpful in understanding
difficult philosophical ideas.
Those who succeed in attaining the goal of a universal vision, Plato believed, are
the best qualified to govern the ideal state (the "republic"). The policies Plato
thought such "philosopher-kings" should enforce have often been harshly
criticized for various reasons. We will look more closely at political philosophy in
Week IX. At this point it will suffice to point out that Plato's theory of the
philosopher-king deserves to be seriously considered: for who is more capable of
ruling in a just and benevolent way, a person who is hungry to possess power and
authority, or one who has seen and understood the ideas of power and authority as
they truly are?
In working out his theory of forms Plato, like most great philosophers, regarded
the question of the ultimate reality of mankind as one of the most significant
aspects of his metaphysical theory. So let's conclude our discussion of Plato's
idealism by looking briefly at its implications for human nature. If the material
world is an illusion, then the human body is obviously not the defining reality of
human nature. On the contrary, the body, according to Plato, is what chains us to
the cave, limiting our vision to the shadows of reality. Our true reality lies in the
idea, or form, of "humanness" and is best expressed in terms of the idea of a
"soul" (psyche). The soul is the eternal reality that is, as it
Today I have had time only to skim the surface of the ideas put forward by Plato
(and Socrates). We could spend the rest of this course examining the intricacies of
his idealism, and even then we would have just begun to understand the depths of
his thought. Plato himself believed his system of eternal forms was capable of
transforming philosophy into a science, a body of well-established knowledge-a
goal shared by many philosophers ever since. And yet, how this is to be
accomplished has been a matter of continuous controversy. Indeed, in the next
lecture we will examine the ideas of a pupil of Plato's who believed a scientific
philosophy can be established only by following a radically different path.
In the previous lecture we looked at the ideas of Socrates and his follower, Plato.
Socrates' appeal to universal reason and Plato's use of dialogue to construct a
system of idealism, based on Socrates' teachings, revolutionized the development
of philosophy in ancient Greece. I concluded by mentioning Plato's notion that
idealism can lead to the construction of a universal science. The fact that virtually
no scientists today would look back to Plato's ideas as the source of modern
science suggests that Plato failed in this task (at least, given modern notions of
what science is). However, as we shall see today, the very different system
proposed by Plato's most influential pupil was to succeed in this goal in a way his
teacher's ideas never would.
Having studied at the famous school Plato had founded, called the "Academy",
Aristotle taught there until after Plato's death. During those twenty years he
obviously must have become thoroughly familiar with Plato's ideas. He then left
the Academy, however, and served for about three years as the private tutor for
Alexander the Great. Upon his return to Athens, he set up his own school, where
he developed and taught a system of philosophy that many regard as being
diametrically opposed to Plato's. Unfortunately, all that survives of Aristotle's
writings are his lecture notes and textbooks intended for use by his students. As a
result much of his writing is dry and considerably less entertaining than Plato's
lively Dialogues. Whereas Plato's writing style sometimes obscures his meaning
by being too loose, Aristotle's meaning is often obscured by his rigidity.
Something in between would, no doubt, make for a more suitable style for
presenting philosophical insights.
Aristotle based his system on a metaphysics that virtually stands Plato's idealism
on its head by arguing that particulars, not universals, are ultimately real. He
connected particulars with a special term, "ousia", which itself means "reality",
though it is usually translated as "substance". The basic question in his "first
philosophy" (as he referred to metaphysics) is therefore "What is substance?" He
answered this question by defining a substance as an individual, existing thing
(see AC 1b-4b). Such a "thing" is not merely a form, nor is it a hunk of matter.
Instead, it must always combine matter and form within itself. Substance
combines form and matter in such a way that the matter fulfills a necessary
function, rather than being just an accident or an illusion. For the material of a
substance gives it its "distinctive mark", which is that, "while remaining
numerically one and the same, it is capable of admitting contrary qualities"
through a material change. For example, the chalk I am now holding in my hand
would still be an example of the substance "chalk" even if it changed from having
the quality of white chalk into having the quality of red chalk. This way of
looking at the nature of reality is typically called "realism".
Modern science is, of course, one of the fruits of the empiricist tradition. So it
should come as no surprise to find that many of the names we now give to the
different branches of the sciences, as well as other academic disciples, were first
established as such by Aristotle's teleological classifications. Many of his books
were devoted to naming and providing a basic grounding for disciplines such as
"psychology", "zoology", and even "metaphysics" itself. Thus, for instance, he
distinguished between mathematics, physics, and theology by saying they deal
with formal, material, and divine causes, respectively (AM 1026a). Moreover, he
established many distinctions we now take for granted, not only in philosophy
(such as essence-existence and cause-effect), but also in empirical science (such
as genus-species and plant-animal-human). This certainly justifies the view that
Aristotle was a "grandfather" of modern science, even though his own teleological
methodology is now discredited by most scientists. (Most, but not all. The
Anthropic Cosmological Principle is a significant example of a recent book
written by scientists who do recognize the value of the teleological method.)
For both Plato and Aristotle, then, a thing's form is a necessary factor in
determining its reality. But for Plato the form alone is sufficient, while for
Aristotle a definite link with matter is also required. Their views can be
summarized quite simply in the following way:
This summary only scratches the surface of Aristotle's account of the nature of
substance, but it will suffice for our introductory purposes.
What about Aristotle's view of human nature? How did his new metaphysical
standpoint, his realism, influence the way he understood the reality of being
human? He agreed with Plato that the soul (psyche) is the form of the body. As
such, its main functions are described in terms of "the nutritive, the appetitive, the
sensory, the locomotive [powers], and the power of thinking" (DA 414a). The
body itself is now regarded not just as an accident or an illusion to be overcome,
but as a necessary constituent of the human substance, through which these
powers are realized. This view probably feels far more natural to most of you than
Plato's idealist view; yet some of its consequences may be less than desirable. For
if the body is a necessary element in being human, then when the body dies, so
does the reality of the individual existing person. A soul alone would have no
more reality than the mere idea of chalkness and would be of no more use than the
pile of chalk dust here on the floor is for writing on the chalkboard. And this
negative implication of Aristotle's realism, for anyone who believes in life after
death, begins to make Plato's idealism look not so bad after all! (Another way
around this problem would be to believe the body itself is somehow brought back
to life, albeit in some transformed state, after we die. We will discuss this
possibility further in Lecture 35.)
Aristotle himself may have been trying to make up for this potentially undesirable
consequence of his realism when he argued that the human soul has a distinctive
purpose that makes us different from all other earthly substances. Plant souls are
characterized by nutritive and appetitive powers. Animal souls share these
characteristics, but add sensation and locomotion (i.e., the power to move).
Human souls share all the ends, or purposes, that define plant and animal souls,
but rise above these through the power of rationality (nous). Viewing God as a
purely rational being, Aristotle thought this aspect of human nature reveals a
"spark of the divine" in each of us. Accordingly, he described the human soul as
being that of a "rational animal"-a notion that has become one of the most widely
accepted ways of defining human nature. By treating rationality as itself a
characteristic of the divine soul, we can map Aristotle's distinction onto a cross, as
shown in Figure II.9.
This view of the soul provided Aristotle with a way of allowing for a type of
survival after death. In DA 430a he stated that, when the soul "is set free from its
present conditions" (i.e., when a person's body dies), the remaining core of
rationality "is immortal and eternal". This implies that the "spark" of rationality in
an individual's soul will eventually return to the "fire" of God from which it came.
Although this still does not allow for survival of the individual, it does at least
provide a universal goal to keep us going and to make life worth living. If the
purpose of life is to expand and develop rationality to its maximum extent, then
obviously philosophy is the most meaningful vocation a person can pursue. For in
Aristotle's view, the universal and philosophical
Figure II.9: Aristotle's Four Life (Soul) Forms
part of you, and that part alone, will survive your death.
1. A. Which of the four elements do you think is most basic, and why?
3. A. Is matter an illusion?
B. Why is it so difficult for philosophy to establish itself as a science?
4. A. What is purpose?
RECOMMENDED READINGS
3. Reginald E. Allen (ed.), Greek Philosophy: Thales to Aristotle (New York: The
Free Press, 1966), "Presocratic Philosophy", pp.25-54.
4. Plato, Apology (PA) and Book VII of Republic (PR) (CDP 3-26, 747-772).
6. Allan Bloom, The Closing of the American Mind (New York: Simon and
Schuster, 1987), "From Socrates' Apology to Heidegger's Rektoratsrede", pp.243-
312.
7. John D. Barrow and Frank J. Tipler, The Anthropic Cosmological Principle
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), Ch. Two, "Design Arguments", pp.27-122.
Imagine a tree. Perhaps the drawing I've made here (see Figure III.1) will
help you to do so (although it will also demonstrate that you don't have to be an
artist in order to be a philosopher!). Just how is it that philosophy is like a tree?
There are, in fact, many different possible ways of applying this analogy. One
interesting way is suggested by the philosopher whose ideas we shall be
discussing today. He worked out his own version of the myth that guides this
course, by claiming philosophy is like a tree that has metaphysics as its roots,
physics as its trunk, and the other sciences as its branches. In such a case, which
may well have been an accurate reflection of how philosophy functioned in the
seventeenth century, the leaves of the tree would probably best be correlated to
knowledge, though the philosopher in question did not carry his analogy this far.
For our purposes here in Part One of this course, we can at least agree that
metaphysics certainly does have a function similar to the roots of a tree. By the
time we have completed the first nine lectures, I hope the reasons for this will be
clear enough. Later on, however, I shall suggest revisions of some of the other
aspects of this version of the myth, in order to bring it up to date (see Figure
VII.1).
What then can we doubt? How about our senses? Can you trust your
senses? One day, not long after moving to Hong Kong, I went shopping with my
family in a local mall. It was getting quite late, so we started looking for a place to
eat. As we walked into a supermarket that had food stalls all along the front, I
noticed at a distance a very nice display of Japanese food on sale. I was quite
hungry, so my mouth began watering immediately. We agreed to try eating at this
place, though it was rather crowded. As we came closer I was really impressed by
the apparently high quality of the meals they had on display. Only when we
reached the counter itself did I realize that the food on display was not food at all,
but plastic! My senses had been utterly fooled by the ingenuity of some marketing
agent. And by your laughter I can tell that many of you have made similar
mistakes.
What about our ideas? Perhaps Plato was right after all, and our ideas are
the proper foundation for all knowledge. But Descartes found it just as easy to
cast doubt in this realm as well. Even ideas that seem to us to be certain, ideas
most people would never think of doubting, can be doubted if we try. For
example, there would be many ways of casting doubt on the spatial and temporal
character of our everyday experience. Most of us have had dreams that violate
spatial laws such as gravity (e.g., when we fly in our dreams) or dreams in which
time seems to go slower or faster than when we are awake. How do we know our
everyday experience is not just a dream, from which we will wake up any minute
now? Perhaps there is an evil demon who is deceiving us all into mistaking this
long dream for our real world. Even if there is no such demon, we have all had the
experience of suddenly realizing that some idea we have held to be true for a long
time is actually false. Any single idea might turn out to be an illusion of this kind,
so there is nothing to prevent all our ideas from being illusory. Hence, Plato's
idealism is of no more use than Aristotle's realism in our search for something
absolutely certain.
Figure III.2:
Descartes' dualism has several important consequences. For one thing, it replaces
Aristotle's definition of the human person as a "rational animal" with the notion of
a mind imbedded in a fleshly machine. In the field of natural science this had the
significant effect of providing scientists with a world view that enabled them to
attain (or at least, to believe they could attain) a totally objective perspective on
the external world, totally eliminating any influence the observer's own mind
might have on what we come to know. In this sense, Descartes' dualism can be
regarded as paving the way for Newtonian science. The view that the human ego
controls the material world, though now called into question by many modern
thinkers (see e.g., Lecture 18), is what enabled technology to develop so rapidly
over the past three hundred years.
Materialism: Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) argued that only matter truly exists.
The mind is just a special configuration of brain matter. Therefore there is no
problem of interaction, because the whole system is physical. This view is similar,
though by no means identical, to Aristotle's realism.
(2) Immaterialism: George Berkeley (1685-1753) argued that only
perceptions truly exist. There is no reason to believe matter has any independent
existence outside of the perceiving mind. Therefore there is no problem of
interaction, because the whole system is spiritual. This view is similar, though by
no means identical, to Plato's idealism.
One of the chief dangers for beginning students of philosophy is that they
may be overwhelmed by the great diversity of viewpoints and arguments that
have been expressed on a given subject, such as metaphysics. Although maps like
the one above inevitably over-simplify the complex relationships between such
philosophers, they nevertheless can help us to get a handle on their basic
similarities and differences, as well as suggesting further insights of various sorts.
For example, this diagram suggests that the development of western philosophy
can be regarded as a process of slowly working backwards from, as it were, the
highest and most aloof insights, to the deepest groundings of human reasoning.
We shall see in the next two lectures the extent to which this suggestion gives us
an accurate description of the contribution Kant made to the roots of our
philosophical tree.
8. Philosophy as Transcendental Critique
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) was born into a working class family in the
Prussian port city of Königsberg (now Kaliningrad). He lived a quiet, regulated
life, never marrying and never traveling more than about thirty miles from his
birthplace during his entire life. Kant is often the subject of some rather unfair
caricatures, such as that his daily routine was so rigid that his neighbors found
they could set their clocks by his daily comings and goings! However, I prefer to
regard such stories as reflecting the integrity of a life lived in accordance with
one's own ideas. For as we shall see, Kant's idea of philosophy was that it ought to
be a systematic whole, governed by regular patterns of interrelated ideas. When
he died, the epitaph on his tomb simply said "The Philosopher"-an appropriate
title, considering that the philosophical cycle that began with Socrates reached its
fulfillment, to a large extent, with Kant.
Kant was motivated to conceive a new philosophical method for much the
same reason as Descartes: he asked himself why other sciences have progressed,
but metaphysics has not. Yet his answer to this question not only ignored the
whole mind-body problem, but also called into question another of Descartes' key
contributions: namely, his belief in the absolute objectivity of the external world.
Kant asked a new question: was Descartes (and most other philosophers) right to
assume that the objects we experience and come to know are things in
themselves? The term "thing in itself" is a technical term he used to talk about the
nature of ultimate reality; it means "the things in the world, considered apart from
the conditions that make it possible to know anything about them." Given this
definition, Kant claimed, things in themselves must be unknowable. In stark
contrast to Descartes, who required his starting point to be an absolutely certain
item of knowledge, Kant posited a philosophical faith in the reality of unknowable
things in themselves as the starting point of his system. This is just one of many
ways Descartes and Kant are diametrically opposed to each other in their
philosophical methods.
Kant called his own way of philosophizing the "Critical" method. The titles
of the three main books wherein he developed his System each begin with the
word "Critique". Each book adopts a different "standpoint"; that is, it addresses all
its questions with a particular end in view. The first Critique (of Pure Reason), the
focus of our attention today, assumes a theoretical standpoint. This means the
answers to all the questions it asks are concerned with our knowledge. The other
Critiques, as we shall see later on, sometimes answer the same questions in differ‐
ent ways, because they assume different standpoints. Recognizing the differences
between these standpoints is therefore crucial for a proper understanding of Kant's
philosophy. We can picture the interrelationships between the three parts of Kant's
System in the following way:
Figure III.4: Kant's Critiques and Their Standpoints
Comparing Figure III.4 with Figure II.6 suggests that the Critical method is
a new form of the Socratic method. Whereas Socrates' main concern was to
scrutinize himself and others in the search for wisdom, Kant's Critical method
requires the self-examination of reason. In other words, a true "critique", for Kant,
is a process whereby reason asks itself about the extent and limits of its own
powers. The purpose of such self-examination is to discover once and for all the
boundary between what
Figure III.6:
Kant's new method requires us to see the truth in both extremes in any
debate, to recognize how each limits the other, and as a result, to adopt a
standpoint that affirms the legitimate points from both sides. As I hope you recall
from the last lecture, this stands in stark contrast to Descartes' method: whereas
the latter assumes both Plato and Aristotle to be wrong, Kant's method assumes
both are right, as shown below:
According to Kant, Plato and Aristotle both made the mistake, like that of most
other western philosophers, of ignoring their opponent's point of view and
adopting an extreme position that ends up expressing only half the truth. If Kant's
view of things in themselves is correct, then Plato was right to say objects of
experience are mere appearances of a thing in itself; for in saying this, he was
adopting Kant's "transcendental" perspective. Likewise, Aristotle was right to say
appearances are the true objects of science (i.e., of knowledge); for in saying this,
he was adopting Kant's "empirical" perspective. In both cases their mistakes were
caused by the fact that they had not yet recognized their ignorance of the thing in
itself. This neglect is what led Plato mistakenly to believe we could attain
absolute knowledge of mere ideas and it is what led Aristotle mistakenly to
believe substances are the ultimate reality. So the Critical method encourages us
not only to synthesize Plato's idealism and Aristotle's realism, but also to explain
both the truth in each, which has kept them alive for so long, and the errors that
make them inherently unsatisfactory. Let us now investigate how Kant
accomplished this task.
In the second edition Preface to the first Critique, Kant turned to the
established sciences in hopes of finding clues to their success. Logic, he found,
could become an exact science only when its field of inquiry was clearly limited
(CPR 18). Mathematics made progress only when people began to search for the
necessary and universal characteristics we read into mathematical objects, instead
of paying attention only to their accidental characteristics (19). And natural
sciences succeed only when they proceed according to some predetermined plan
(20). Armed with these hints, Kant gained one final clue by turning to a particular
scientist, whose daring insight profoundly changed the way we view the universe.
vice versa. Why not experiment with the opposite assumption? Perhaps in
metaphysics, just as in astronomy, the correct description of what appears to be
true is different from the correct description of what is true in reality. In other
words, Kant proposed that for metaphysics it may be more accurate to say objects
conform themselves to the knowledge of the subject (i.e., to the human mind)!
Kant attempted to prove that space and time are the transcendental "forms
of intuition" and a special set of twelve categories are the transcendental "forms of
conception". The categories are arranged in four groups of three, under the
headings "quantity", "quality", "relation", and "modality", as shown in Figure
III.9. Today we can safely ignore the
Figure III.9: Kant's Twelvefold Division of Categories
details of this part of Kant theory, because Lecture 21 will include a closer look at
the most important category, causality. Moreover, as we will discover in Week V,
understanding the logical form of this set of categories is more important than
understanding Kant's reasons for selecting these specific twelve. The key at this
point is to understand the function of the categories, along with space and time,
their counterpart forms of intuition.
this. For now it will suffice to say that Kant himself believed that recognizing the
limitations of knowledge is very good for metaphysics. As he confessed in CPR
29: "I have ... found it necessary to deny knowledge, in order to make room for
faith." An honest and courageous recognition of reason's limits may make
philosophy a more difficult and dangerous task, but as we shall see in Lectures 32
and 33, it is the best (if not the only) way to preserve the meaningfulness of
human life.
4. Knowledge inevitably gives rise to ideas about what ultimate reality might be
like if we could know it; but attempting to prove these ideas leads reason into self-
contradiction, so they can never become items of scientific knowledge.
The implications of the philosophical System that arises out of these tenets are
manifold. At this point, let's just look at four of the most significant implications
for metaphysics.
With Kant, therefore, metaphysics finally came of age. After two thousand
years of philosophers attempting to combat necessary ignorance with
metaphysical knowledge, Kant completed a cycle in the history of western
philosophy, and in so doing, opened up a whole new set of problems. For the next
implication of Kant's System is that we must now find a way to cope with our
necessary ignorance. How can we do philosophy without having any knowledge
of ultimate reality? The last two hundred years of philosophy has been a series of
different suggestions as to how this can best be accomplished. Kant's own
solutions, such as his "Copernican" theory that the subject reads the
transcendental conditions of knowledge onto the object, have been rejected by
most subsequent philosophers. However, I don't think we should be too quick to
reject this rather strange sounding theory. For just as Descartes' "cogito" paved the
way for Newtonian physics, I believe Kant's Copernican revolution paved the way
for relativity physics and quantum mechanics, based as they are on a very similar
notions of the observer participating in the formation of knowledge.
Because Kant defined such a clear-cut set of limits for human knowledge,
we can say philosophy becomes more complete with Kant than ever before. Kant
himself was well aware of this aspect of his System (CPR 10):
I have made completeness my chief aim, and I venture to assert that there is not a
single metaphysical problem which has not been solved, or for the solution of
which the key at least has not been supplied.
Interestingly, if you think back to our discussion of myths in Lecture 3, you might
recall that a myth is also something that is enclosed in limits. So I think it would
be right to say that with Kant western philosophy experienced such a major
"paradigm shift" that we can say Kant gave philosophy a new "myth"-the myth of
the thing in itself. Of course, as long as we treat this as an "enlightened" myth-i.e.,
as long as we always remember it is a myth, and so treat it not as an absolute
truth, but as a basic assumption, freely adopted on faith-we can avoid many of the
pitfalls that "living in a myth" otherwise tends to have.
One final implication of Kant's philosophy is that its insistence on an area
of necessary human ignorance keeps the philosopher humble. This might seem
surprising, especially for those of you who have read some of Kant's own writing,
since Kant was certainly not ignorant about the greatness of his own achievement!
For on several occasions he proudly claimed that his System is superior to those
of all past philosophers. My point here is that, whereas most philosophers appeal
to certain speculative ideas, requiring access to some kind of special, transcendent
knowledge that is inaccessible to ordinary people, Kant's philosophy replaces
these with hypotheses, thus putting philosophers in general on an even par with
non-philosophers when it comes to their ability to gain knowledge about the most
basic metaphysical issues. Because Kant used such complicated terminology to
express his ideas, this implication of his philosophy is often overlooked, even by
those who spend years studying his writings. Yet Kant stated this "humiliating"
aspect of his Critical System clearly enough on several occasions. One of the best
examples, near the end of the first Critique (651-652), is worth quoting in full:
But, it will be said, is this all that pure reason achieves in opening up
prospects beyond the limits of experience? .... Surely the common understanding
could have achieved as much, without appealing to philosophers for counsel in
the matter.
I shall not dwell here upon the service which philosophy has done to human
reason through the laborious efforts of its criticism, granting even that in the end it
should turn out to be merely negative ... But I may at once reply: Do you really
require that a mode of knowledge which concerns all men should transcend the
common understanding, and should only be revealed to you by philosophers?
Precisely what you find fault with is the best confirmation of the correctness of
the [Critical philosophy]. For we have thereby revealed to us, what could not at
the start have been foreseen, namely, that in matters which concern all men
without distinction nature is not guilty of any partial distribution of her gifts, and
that in regard to the essential ends of human nature the highest philosophy cannot
advance further than is possible under the guidance which nature has bestowed
even upon the most ordinary understanding.
In other words, philosophy is special not because it allows us proudly to claim a
higher level of knowledge than ordinary people, but because it humbles us by
showing us the limitations of all our knowledge.
The German idealists (most notably, Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, and Marx)
were the first and most notorious examples of post-Kantian attempts to regain for
human beings the capacity to know ultimate reality. Johann Fichte (1762-1814)
was initially thought by many to be earmarked as Kant's chosen successor;
however, he soon made an obvious break with Kant, by arguing that the
"transcendental ego" actually produces the whole natural world out of itself. The
problematic "thing in itself" could then be discarded, since there is no longer a
need for anything to exist apart from our minds. Friedrich Schelling (1775-1854)
belonged as much to the concurrent Romantic Movement as to the idealists; this
was evident in his emphasis on art, feeling, and individual diversity. His book,
System of Transcendental Idealism (1800), outlines a position much like Fichte's,
whereby the ego "posits itself" (i.e., makes itself into an object), thus creating the
external world and setting itself the task of coming to know it. Both views reject
the empirical realism Kant valued so highly.
German idealism reached its height with Georg Friedrich Hegel (1770-
1831), whose major contribution was to bring history into the center stage of
metaphysics. He argued that the three-step process used by Fichte and Schelling
(itself having strong roots in Kant [see e.g., Figure III.1]) constitutes a fixed,
logical pattern that tells us just how history develops. This makes it possible for
us to gain a priori access to ultimate reality in the form of what Hegel called
"Absolute Spirit". (We shall look more closely at Hegelian logic in Lecture 12.)
Karl Marx (1818-1883) can be regarded as the concluding figure in this tradition,
not because he was an idealist, but because he constructed his entire philosophy as
a reaction against the Hegelian system. Ironically, this required him to accept
many of Hegel's underlying assumptions, including the basic myth that ultimate
reality can be made known through historical development. But because his focus
was not so much on metaphysics as on political philosophy, we shall postpone
any further discussion of Marx's ideas until Week IX.
RECOMMENDED READINGS
1. Ren?Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy2, tr. Laurence J. Lafleur (New
York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1960[1951]).
2. Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind (New York: Barnes & Noble, 1949), Ch. I,
"Descartes' Myth", pp.13-25.
6. Will Durant, The Story of Philosophy: The lives and opinions of the greater
philosophers3 (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1982[1928]).
What is Logic?
Today we begin the second of the four main parts of this course. In Part
One the roots of the tree of philosophy provided us with an important insight
about metaphysics, initially discovered by Socrates, but expressed in a far more
complete form by Kant. Just as the roots of a tree are almost entirely buried in the
soil so that we cannot see them as they are (at least, not without uprooting the
tree), so also the metaphysical underpinnings of our knowledge consist of
something essentially unknowable to the human mind. Armed with this insight,
we can now extract ourselves from the murky depths of metaphysics and ascend
to a part of the philosophical tree that allows itself to be seen more readily.
Student H. "I think logic is like science: it's supposed to teach us about the
facts in the world, so we don't have to rely only on our own opinion."
Logic certainly does have something to do with helping us see beyond our
own opinion. But I'm afraid I can't agree with you when you relate logic so
closely to scientific facts. Nevertheless, I'm glad you spoke up, because this is a
mistaken idea about logic that many beginning philosophy students have. Logic
actually has nothing to do with teaching us new facts! In fact, it's more like
metaphysics than physics when it comes to the issue of teaching us new facts.
Metaphysics, at least for Kant, does not extend knowledge at all, but prevents
errors, just as the roots of a tree do not bear fruit, yet need to be cared for in order
to insure the fruit will be healthy. And the same is true for the trunk, logic. The
reason for studying metaphysics and logic is not so we can know more, but rather
so we can learn to express more clearly and accurately the knowledge we gain
from other sources. Otherwise we might find ourselves cultivating insights that
look good on the outside, but are rotten when we "bite into" them. So what is
logic?
Student I. "Logic is step by step thinking, like the kind scientists always
use."
I think you're right to suggest that scientific thinking must be logical. And
"step by step" thinking, assuming the steps follow according to some definite
order, is certainly one of the main characteristics of anything logical. The word
"order" implies a definite relationship exists between the different steps we follow
in our thinking. I assume that's what you mean by saying "step by step". But your
answer shows that you have misunderstood my question. Can anyone see how? If
a beginning history student asks me "What is history?", would it be adequate for
me to answer him by saying "History is something important about the past"? Can
any of you who are studying history right now tell me whether or not this
accurately describes what you are learning about?
Student J. "We do learn a lot about significant events that happened in the
past."
But is that all you learn about? Surely students in all subjects learn
important things about the past without actually studying history. For example, in
the last few lectures we've been learning about metaphysics by studying the ideas
of past philosophers; but taking an historical approach does not mean we were
studying history as such. What else have you been learning about in your history
classes?
Very good! Now, just as all academic disciplines teach something about the
past without necessarily teaching history, so also all academic disciplines are-or at
least, should be-logical, yet do not teach logic. Not just science subjects, but
history, economics, politics, religion, even music and art, are also normally taught
in an orderly, logical way (though there are, of course, different types of order).
So what I am asking you now is to tell me what makes logic itself different as an
academic discipline? As we turn our attention to logic, what is it that we will be
studying?
Yes! This could even be used as the basis for a general definition of logic.
Logic as an academic discipline is distinguished from other disciplines by the fact
that logicians do not simply use orderly thinking; they think in an orderly way
about orderly thinking. Probably the most common definition for logic is to
regard it as "the science of the laws of thinking".
This definition reminds me of a special term Kant had for describing the
patterns built in to human reason. He compared good philosophers to architects
who construct systems (conceptual "buildings") according to a predetermined
plan. Reason's own "architectonic" structure provides a set of ready-made patterns
that Kant believed philosophers should use as tools for presenting their
philosophical ideas in a more orderly way. Kant himself never spent much time
explaining just what these patterns are; but here in Part Two, quite a lot of our
attention will be devoted to this task. As we shall see, it is through logic that we
can best recognize an idea and an ordering of its parts, which Kant regarded as a
prerequisite for understanding a philosophical system.
Student L. "I remember in one of the first lectures you talked about the
Greek word logos. Does that have anything to do with what we're supposed to be
learning for the next few weeks?"
You probably also remember that, when I mentioned logos in the third
lecture, I was trying to shed some light on the significance of myths for
philosophy. The term logos can sometimes refer to the myth itself, or to some
unknown, hidden meaning. However, I think it is best to interpret it as referring to
the first attempt to express this meaning in words. Since "logos" means "word",
we could say that in this sense the term "logical" refers to a use of words whereby
the words carry some meaning. As we shall see in this week's lectures, there are
two types of logic: one type virtually ignores any hidden (i.e., mythical)
meanings, while the other type focuses almost entirely on bringing just such
meanings out into the light.
Why is it important to learn how words get their meaning? If we know what
a word means, why do we need to go further and learn the laws that determine
how that meaning arises? This should be an easy question to answer, since I've
already mentioned the reason at the beginning of today's session.
Student M. "If we don't know the rules, we might make errors without
knowing it. Learning the rules will help us think and speak truthfully. A logical
person can avoid saying anything that is false."
Avoiding errors is indeed the answer I was thinking of. But once again, we
have to be careful not to think something we say is always true just because it is
logical. It might surprise you to find out that logic is not really concerned about
the truth of the words we use, but only about their truth value. As we shall see, it
is possible to say something that is utterly false, yet to express it in a logically
correct (or "valid") way, or to say something that is very true, but to state that
truth in a logically incorrect way. The kind of errors logic helps us to avoid are
not called "falsehoods", but "fallacies".
This fallacy can be corrected in two ways. First, we can recognize that the
proposition in question is an exception to the rule. In this case, we are essentially
admitting the presence of a myth. That is, a person can say: "The only definite
answer to this question is that there are no definite answers (other than this one)."
To do so is to affirm a myth; but the problem of self-reference illustrates that we
can never do away completely with all myths. Sometimes it is better simply to
become aware of our myths (our indefensible presuppositions), rather than to
pretend that we have none at all. A second option would be to express the
conclusion in a more accurate and meaningful way, such as: "there are too many
definite answers". This fits the kind of evidence typically provided in such insight
papers, where the preceding argument has compared several competing definite
answers to whatever question is being considered. Indeed, most (if not all)
philosophical questions have this important characteristic. They are not questions
that have no answer, otherwise it would be pointless to discuss them. Rather, they
are questions whose multitude of potentially good answers leaves us unable to say
for certain which answer is best. Of course, this second option is not independent
of the first, because we are actually saying: "The best answer is that there are
many good answers, but no best answer (other than this one)."
Learning to identify this and the many other types of fallacies can be a very
useful skill, though you needn't bother to learn the fancy Latin names they are
often given. Some common fallacies to watch out for when writing your insight
papers are: arguing ad hoc (from a single example), ad antiquitatem (from
tradition), ad novitatem (from newness), ad baculum (by appealing to force), or
ad hominem (appealing to a personal weakness of the opponent or of others who
accept the same conclusion); shifting the "burden of proof" (i.e., claiming your
view is justified as long as nobody proves it is wrong); equivocation (i.e., using a
word in two different ways without pointing out the difference); arguing against a
"straw man" (i.e., a weak, easily refuted version of the opponent's view); "begging
the question" by assuming what you want to prove-and the list goes on almost
without an end. However, some philosophers are so fond of labeling any and
every type of logical error as a fallacy that their search for fallacies becomes a
fallacy of its own. This happens whenever a person assumes that locating a fallacy
in an argument is a sufficient reason to treat the argument's conclusion as either
false or meaningless, and therefore refuses to consider it any further. To treat
fallacies in this way is to commit what I call (intentionally playing around with a
bit of self-reference) the "fallacy fallacy"! That is, it is a fallacy to infer from the
fact that an argument contains a fallacy that its conclusion must be untrue.
Let me illustrate this point with a simple example. If I say "History and
philosophy have nothing in common with each other; you are an historian and I
am a philosopher; therefore we have no common interests", then my argument is
fallacious. Even if the first two statements (called "premises") are both true, they
do not necessarily imply the third statement, because you and I might have
something in common that has nothing to do with history or philosophy. On the
other hand, even if one or both premises were false, the conclusion might be true:
history and philosophy might be closely related in certain respects, or you might
be studying chemistry, not history; but we might have no common interests. Logic
on its own is incapable of telling us whether or not either of these two scenarios is
factually true; all it can do is tell us under what conditions the truth of a specific
claim can be demonstrated to be true. It would therefore be a fallacy to assume
that because my argument contains a fallacy, it's conclusion is necessarily untrue.
A proposition's formal truth does not depend at all on the specific meanings
of the words used within the proposition. All that matters is that we know the
truth value of each of its parts. For that reason, logicians often find it is helpful to
substitute the words in a proposition with symbols. Because the symbols represent
only the general or formal properties of each word, they make it easier to look
beyond the particular content and see the proposition's underlying logical
structure. Thus, the ideal goal of some logicians is to develop a complete
symbolic logic that can function, rather ironically, as a language without words
(i.e., logic without logoi). For example, the above "If ... then ..." proposition can
be expressed by replacing "this chalk" with "a", "all white" with "w", "not" with
"-", and "blue" with "-w" (i.e., "not white"), so that the formal structure of the
proposition becomes clear: "If a is w, then a is -(-w)" is always a true proposition,
no matter what words we use to replace these symbols.
The proliferation of symbols in logic texts is, perhaps more than anything
else, what scares beginning philosophy students away from logic. But like any
new language, once we learn how to use these symbols, the initial awkwardness
and confusion goes away. In this course I shall introduce only a very small
number of logical symbols to you. But judging from your insightful suggestions
regarding the nature of logic, I am hopeful that some of you will be interested
enough to do further reading on your own in the area of symbolic logic. My main
interest in the next eight lectures will be to help you deepen your insight into what
logic itself actually is.
I shall begin this lecture by looking at a typical example of how logic can
help us see the formal relations between words and the truth value of the
proposition they compose. A proposition's truth value, as I explained in the last
session, is quite distinct from its actual, material truth. It refers to the truth or
falsity a proposition would have under any given set of conditions. Thus, we can
find the truth value of a proposition without knowing anything at all about its
actual content, provided we know what kind of proposition it is. One way of
doing this is to construct what is called a "truth table" for the proposition. Let's
take as an example the proposition: "If you read the textbook, then you will do
well on the final exam." (Actually, I would prefer not to give written exams-or
any grades, for that matter-since it is nearly impossible to judge how much real
philosophy you have learned just by administering a conventional test. The
purpose of this course is not to teach you about philosophy-that can be tested
quite easily-but to teach you to philosophize. Nevertheless, universities require
teachers to "grade" their students, so let's use logic to remind ourselves of one
good way to make that grade a high one, if you are reading this as part of a graded
course.)
Being aware of the truth value of various types of proposition can help us
avoid being fooled by arguments that attempt to prove something by presupposing
a false p. Since the whole proposition is formally true regardless of the truth or
falsity of q, we can use such an argument to "prove" the truth of something that is
actually false. For example, if I want to make myself appear to be your favorite
teacher, I could argue: "If you are the Chief Executive of Hong Kong SAR, then I
am your favorite teacher!" Since the premise is false (because none of you is the
Chief Executive), this proposition is true whether or not I am actually your
favorite teacher! For it is the same as saying "Either you are not the Chief
Executive of Hong Kong SAR, or I am your favorite teacher." So when faced with
a proposition that has a false p, always be sure to remember that it is a fallacy to
conclude from the truth value of the whole proposition that the q is actually true.
Now let's imagine that you do the recommended readings for this class, but
you end up failing the exam anyway. If the proposition whose form is analyzed in
Figure IV.1a were actually true, then you could come and argue from logic alone
that you should pass the class. For example, you could remind me that the
proposition I stated at the beginning of today's class is equivalent to another
proposition: "Either you did not do the readings, or you passed the exam." The
truth value of this proposition, as shown in Figure IV.1b, requires that in order for
it to be true, at least one of its two parts must be true. So if p ("you did not do the
readings") is false, and if my original proposition is true, then as the truth table
shows, q ("you passed the exam") must be true. So don't ever say logic is too
abstract to have any practical value!
In this case the first proposition (or "major premise") puts forward a universal
assumption; the second proposition (or "minor premise") puts forward a particular
test case; and the third proposition, of course, draws a necessary ("categorical")
conclusion, also called the "inference". The only way the conclusion could prove
to be false would be if one of the two premises is false, unless of course the
formal relations between the terms in these propositions are in some way
fallacious.
A good way to test whether or not the terms in a deduction contain a fallacy
is to convert the propositions into a set of corresponding logical symbols. In the
example given above, commonly known as "universal implication" (because of
the use of the word "all"), the words are typically converted into symbols such as
the following:
S is an h.
\ S is m.
As far as formal logic is concerned, the validity of this syllogism remains exactly
the same, whether "h" refers to humans or horses, whether "m" refers to being
mortal or to being moral, and whether "S" refers to Socrates or Santa Claus! But
remember: proving an argument to be valid still leaves open the question of
whether the premises are actually true. (The other words, "all", "are", etc., can
also be converted into symbols-but I don't want to scare you away from logic at
this early stage!)
Another important aid for anyone who wishes to explore the formal
structure of any deductive argument was provided more than two thousand years
ago, by Aristotle, the founder of formal logic. He developed a virtually complete
system of all the possible forms of deductive argument. Until the beginning of the
twentieth century, virtually all philosophers regarded this system as giving an
unsurpassable account of all the basic propositions of formal logic. This, without
a doubt, gives Aristotle the honor of introducing the single most universally
recognized and longest-lasting contribution ever made to philosophy. However,
for our purposes it is not necessary to learn all the details of Aristotle's system,
especially since his ideas were superseded in numerous respects during the past
one hundred years.
What is more significant here is that deduction is not the only respectable
form of philosophical argument. For this analytic method is complemented by an
equally significant synthetic method. This method, called induction, requires us to
begin by appealing to various material facts which, taken together, point to the
desired conclusion. That is, in contrast to the necessity governing a valid
deduction, induction always involves some guesswork. Or, to borrow from Kant's
terminology (see Lecture 7), we could say deduction remains entirely within the
realm of concepts, while induction requires an appeal to intuitions as well.
Perhaps an example will help to illuminate this difference.
Let's say we want to prove that the proposition "The sun always rises in the
east" is true. In order to deduce the truth of this statement, we would need to find
at least two true assumptions which, taken together, necessitate such a conclusion.
For example, we might choose the following:
All planets revolve around a star in such a way that the star always appears
to rise on the planet's eastern horizon.
My father says the first day he saw the sun rise, it rose in the east.
My mother says the sun rose in the east on the day I was born.
The first day I remember seeing the sun rise, it rose in the east.
Last week I woke up early and saw the sun rising in the east.
Yesterday I did the same thing.
I have never heard anyone say they have seen the sun rise in the north, south,
or west.
In Lecture 21 we shall raise the question whether we are ever capable of reaching
a necessary truth by induction. But for now I am only trying to illustrate the
difference between it and deduction.
Whereas the actual process of constructing a deduction (as opposed to its written
form) starts by formulating a conclusion, then proves it by searching for two or
more true assumptions that can serve as its basis, the process of induction starts
by collecting innumerable bits of evidence, then using them as the basis to draw a
conclusion.
As I mentioned earlier, the terms "analytic" and "synthetic" have been used
in several quite different ways by philosophers. For a long time Euclid's way of
using the terms, to refer to two methods of argumentation, was the commonly
accepted usage. But Kant developed a new way of using the same terms, whereby
they refer to two distinct types of proposition. According to Kant, a proposition is
analytic if the subject is "contained in" the predicate, whereas it is synthetic if the
subject goes "outside" the predicate. Thus, for example, "Red is a color" is
analytic, because the concept "red" is already included as one of the constituents
of the concept "color". Likewise, "This chalk is white" is synthetic, because you
would not know that this thing I'm holding in my hand is chalk if I merely told
you it is white. Using these two examples, we can picture Kant's initial
description of this distinction in terms of the two maps shown in Figure IV.3.
Kant also gave several other, more rigorous, guidelines for determining
whether a proposition is analytic or synthetic. The truth of an
(a) "Yellow is a color." (b) "This chalk is white."
analytic proposition can always be known through logic alone; so, if the meanings
of the words are already known, the proposition is not informative. An analytic
proposition is self-explanatory. All I have to do is say "white" and any of you who
understand the meaning of this word will already know I'm talking about a color.
So, like the conclusion of a good deduction, the truth of an analytic proposition is
purely conceptual, and therefore, necessary. The truth of a synthetic proposition,
by contrast, requires an appeal to something more than mere concepts. Like an
inductive argument, an appeal will be made to some intuition-i.e., to some factual
state of affairs. As a result, synthetic propositions are always informative, and the
truth of their conclusions is contingent on a given state of affairs continuing to
exist. When I tell you this piece of chalk hidden in the palm of my hand is white,
the truth of my statement depends on whether or not I have somehow fooled you
by slipping it into my pocket, or by replacing it with a blue piece of chalk, etc.
I hope you will try out a few of your own sample propositions to test your
grasp of this distinction between analytic and synthetic propositions. Some
philosophers nowadays think so many propositions are difficult to pin down as
either analytic or synthetic that the whole distinction is worthless. However, I
believe such "gray areas" cause problems only when we forget to look at the
context of a proposition, or when we forget to apply each of Kant's guidelines
with sufficient care. In any case, this is not an issue we can resolve in an
introductory course such as this.
Instead, I'll just mention here that Kant combined this distinction between
analytic and synthetic propositions (or "judgments", as he also referred to them)
with another distinction, between "a priori" and "a posteriori" kinds of knowledge.
"A priori" refers to something that can be known to be true without appealing to
experience; by contrast, something is "a posteriori" if a demonstration of its truth
requires an appeal to experience. This gives rise to four possible kinds of
knowledge, two of which are non-controversial: analytic a priori knowledge is
simply logical knowledge, and synthetic a posteriori knowledge is simply
empirical knowledge. Kant believed there is no analytic a posteriori knowledge; I
contend, however, that this term actually defines a very important, though often
neglected, epistemological category. I've defended this contention at length
elsewhere (see APK and KSP 129-140), so here I'll simply assert that classifying
our hypothetical beliefs about the world in this way can do the crucial work of
saving the appearances, both from being proudly mistaken for ultimate reality
and from being discarded as mere appearances. The synthetic a priori class of
knowledge occupied most of Kant's attention; for he argued that all
transcendental knowledge is of this type. This is why he said the question "How
are synthetic judgments a priori possible?" is the central question of all Critical
philosophy. Although we won't have time to discuss the intricacies of these
different logical classifications, you should make an effort to learn their
interrelationships, as shown in the following map:
It would be difficult to overstate the profound influence this law has had on the
past two thousand three hundred years of philosophy. For upon it is based nearly
all of the arguments western philosophers have put forward. Moreover, we would
not be able to communicate with each other without assuming that when we use a
word, we want those who hear us to think of the thing that word refers to, and not
its opposite!
At the end of the previous lecture I asked you to go away and think about
two questions: What should we call the opposite of traditional, "analytic" logic?
and On what law would such logic be based? Any of you who have read the
lecture outline for this course (see above, p.vii) will have easily guessed that the
term I think best describes the kind of logic governing functions like induction
and synthetic propositions is "synthetic logic". But you may have had a bit more
trouble thinking of a law to set alongside Aristotle's "law of noncontradiction". So
let's begin today by determining what such a law would be.
Finding the basic law of synthetic logic need not be a difficult task.
Analytic and synthetic logic always function in opposite ways, so all we have to
do is determine the opposite of Aristotle's famous "A≠-A". There are two ways of
doing this. We can either change the "≠" to "=" or change the "-A" to "A". In this
way, we derive the following two laws:
I suggest we call the first new law the "law of contradiction", since it shows us
the inherently contradictory form followed by anything that functions in a
"synthetic" way. The second is actually the opposite of a rather boring law of
analytic logic, usually called the "law of identity" (A=A); so we can refer to
"A≠A" as the "law of nonidentity". This gives us a complete set of four basic laws
of logic:
Figure IV.5: The Four Fundamental Laws of Logic
Obviously, the laws of synthetic logic require some explanation. For how
could contradiction or even nonidentity be the basis for constructing any
meaningful proposition? A computer, for example, could never work if it were
programmed using synthetic logic rather than analytic logic. To attempt this
would be like trying to operate the computer while it is submerged in water: the
whole thing would short-circuit! What then is the point of talking about synthetic
logic at all? What sense could it ever make to say, for instance, "Black is not
black"? Fortunately, in spite of the tremendous advances we saw in computer
technology during the 1990s, human thinking still surpasses that of the best
computer. For, although even a small computer can out-think the most highly
developed human brain in analytic operations, computers are incapable of
performing genuinely synthetic operations. In order to see how synthetic logic can
have meaningful applications, let's look at some examples.
Everything has its "that", everything has its "this". From the point of view of
"that" you cannot see it, but through understanding you can know it. So I say,
"that" comes out of "this" and "this" depends on "that"-which is to say that "this"
and "that" give birth to each other. But where there is birth there must be death;
where there is death there must be birth. Where there is acceptability there must
be unacceptability. Where there is recognition of right there must be recognition
of wrong; where there is recognition of wrong there must be recognition of right.
(CTBW 34-35)
So far, Chuang Tzu has merely pointed out the universal need of human
beings to think analytically. He notes, quite rightly, that in such cases, the
opposites actually depend on each other for their existence. But he then
continues:
Therefore the sage does not proceed in such a way, but illuminates all in the light
of heaven. He too recognizes a "this", but a "this" which is also a "that", a "that"
which is also a "this". His "that" has both a right and a wrong in it; his "this" too
has both a right and a wrong in it. So, in fact, does he still have a "this" and a
"that"? Or does he in fact no longer have a "this" and a "that"? A state in which
"this" and "that" no longer find their opposites is called the hinge of the Way [i.e.,
of the Tao]. When the hinge is fitted into the socket, it can respond endlessly. Its
right then is a single endlessness and its wrong too is a single endlessness. So I
say, the best thing to use is clarity. (CTBW 35)
Here Chuang Tzu explains that the way of the sage is to follow the Tao (the
"Way" of heaven), and that this Way can be expressed in words only by using the
contradictory language of synthesized opposites: "this" and "that" (Chuang Tzu's
equivalent of "A" and "-A") must be identified with each other; moreover, each
must be regarded as itself containing what we would normally regard as a
contradiction: e.g., both right and wrong; both birth and death, etc.
Do you think Chuang Tzu was being serious when he wrote this, or did he
intend it all to be a joke? Why did he end this rather confusing paragraph by
stressing the need for clarity? Later (CTBW 37-38) he says: "The torch of chaos
and doubt ... is what the sage steers by.... This is what it means to use clarity." He
then announces he will "make a statement" that "fits into some category", though
he's not sure which. What follows is a series of blatant contradictions, such as:
"There is nothing in the world bigger than the tip of an autumn hair, and Mount
T'ai is little. No one has lived longer than a dead child, and P'eng-tsu [the Chinese
Methuselah] died young." Could he really have been aiming at clarity when he
made such odd statements?
I don't think Chuang Tzu was joking at all-though the truth can often be
funny. He reveals his intentions more fully when he says:
The Great Way is not named; Great Discriminations are not spoken; Great
Benevolence is not benevolent; Great Modesty is not humble; Great Daring does
not attack. If the Way is made clear, it is not the Way. If discriminations are put
into words, they do not suffice.... (CTBW 39-40)
Right is not right; so is not so. If right were really right, it would differ so clearly
from not right that there would be no need for argument. If so were really so, it
would differ so clearly from not so that there would be no need for argument.
Forget the years; forget distinctions. Leap into the boundless and make it your
home! (CTBW 44)
Trying to force Chuang Tzu into the straight-jacket of analytic logic would
leave us little choice but to declare him insane. However, once we recognize that
his goal was to give us a glimpse of something beyond the boundaries of analytic
logic, his words begin to take on a new kind of meaning. The "clarity" he
recommended is not the clarity of thought (i.e., thinking about what we know),
but the clarity of vision (i.e., seeing what remains mysterious). The irony is that he
used words to point us to this vision. In so doing, he recognized that he was, in a
sense, falsifying the true Way-at least, for anyone who focuses on his words as a
literal description of his meaning, instead of focusing on what his words point to.
And what we discover when we examine his words is that the tool he used most
frequently to do the pointing is intentional contradiction. "Right is not right."
What better example could there be of the law of nonidentity (A≠A) at work?
"'This' is 'that'." What better example could there be of the law of contradiction
(A=-A) at work?
The western tradition has relatively few good examples of how synthetic
logic can be employed to help us cope with our ignorance of ultimate reality. One
ancient Greek philosopher, Heraclitus, touched upon synthetic logic with his
insightful principle that "Opposites are the same" (i.e., "A=-A"). However, the
little that remains of his writing does not provide much help as to how to apply
this principle. Others have developed forms of synthetic logic into much more
elaborate systems. The best example, undoubtedly, is Hegel (1770-1831), who
constructed his entire "dialectical" philosophy on the principle that historical
development
Dialectical Method
the pseudonym "Dionysius the Areopagite". Showing the futility of any attempt to
describe ultimate reality (referred to as "It") he concludes:
Once more, ascending yet higher, we maintain that It is not soul or mind, or
endowed with the faculty of imagination, conjecture, reason, or understanding;
nor is It any act of reason or understanding; nor can It be described by the reason
or perceived by the understanding, since It is not number or order or greatness or
littleness or equality or inequality, and since It is not immovable nor in motion or
at rest and has no power and is not power or light and does not live and is not life;
nor is It personal essence or eternity or time; nor can It be grasped by the
understanding, since It is not knowledge or truth; nor is It kingship or wisdom;
nor is It one, nor is It unity, nor is It Godhead or Goodness...; nor is It any other
thing such as we or any other being can have knowledge of; nor does It belong to
the category of nonexistence or to that of existence; nor do existent beings know
It as it actually is, nor does It know them as they actually are; nor can the reason
attain to It to name It or to know It; nor is It darkness, nor is It light or error or
truth; nor can any affirmation or negation apply to It ..., inasmuch as It transcends
all affirmation by being the perfect and unique Cause of all things, and transcends
all negation by the preeminence of Its simple and absolute nature-free from every
limitation and beyond them all. (MT V)
This quotation reveals a profound awareness, long before Kant, of the fact that we
can know virtually nothing about ultimate reality. Yet if we insist on interpreting
these words according to the laws of analytic logic, then much of it appears to be
nonsense! How, for example, can something be "not immovable nor in motion or
at rest"? Such claims must be rejected as blatant contradictions, until we realize
they are to be interpreted in terms of synthetic logic; for in so doing the same
contradictions can point us toward deeper insights about the Being whom we
normally call "God".
Although it is rare to find even a hint of the existence of synthetic logic in
most logic textbooks, there have been a few scholars in this century who have
recognized its significance and attempted to describe the way it works. No one to
my knowledge has thoroughly explored to what extent it constitutes an entirely
distinct kind of logic; yet some have openly acknowledged the possibility of using
alternative laws as the basis for the way we use words. For instance, some
anthropologists, in their study of how people in primitive societies think, have
concluded that their minds operate according to what they sometimes call the
"law of participation" (which means they see concepts as participating in their
opposites). Other scholars have suggested still other names for what I have called
the "law of contradiction", such as the "law of paradox". This name has the
advantage of making it clear that the true purpose of synthetic logic is not to utter
meaningless contradictions, but to drive our imagination to the point where it
discovers new perspectives, from which the apparent contradictions can be
resolved.
What we call this alternative kind of logic and its basic laws is not nearly as
important as knowing how to use it. With this in mind, I'll discuss in Week V
some very practical ways of using synthetic logic to gain insights. For today, let's
conclude by reviewing what we have learned so far about logic, using the table
given in Figure IV.8.
There are fundamentally two different types of logic: analytic logic arises
out of the laws of identity and noncontradiction; synthetic
FigureIV.8:ThreeTypesofAnalytic-SyntheticDistinction
logic arises out of the opposite laws of nonidentity and contradiction. The former
is properly used to describe anything that is possible for us to know; the latter is
properly used to describe what, by its very nature, we can never know. Analytic
propositions are an expression of analytic logic, because they identify two
concepts that are already known to be, in some sense, identical; synthetic
propositions are an expression of synthetic logic, because they identify two
essentially nonidentical things-namely, a concept and an intuition. Finally,
analytic logic is most appropriately manifested in the form of a deductive
argument, where the conclusion follows from the premises as a matter of
mathematical (i.e., noncontradictory) certainty; synthetic logic is most
appropriately manifested in the form of an inductive argument, where the
conclusion always depends on some degree of guesswork (i.e., on the paradoxical
affirmation of what we do not know).
Having now introduced to you three of the most basic distinctions in logic, I
shall devote next week's lectures to the task of explaining the logical basis of the
various diagrams I have been using throughout this course. We will then conclude
Part Two by looking at two examples from the twentieth century of philosophical
schools that tended to over-emphasize analytic and synthetic logic, respectively,
following by a third school that can be regarded as attempting to synthesize key
aspects of the first two.
3. A. What could it mean to say that an existing thing "does not exist"?
B. What kind of logic does God use to think? (Assume God exists.)
RECOMMENDED READINGS
6. Chuang Tzu, Basic Writings, Ch.2, "Discussion on Making All Things Equal"
(CTBW 31-44).
8. G.W.F. Hegel, The Phenomenology of Spirit, tr. A.V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1977), Preface, "On Scientific Cognition", pp.1-45.
border=0 height=62 width=88>
D1
In the first lecture on logic we learned that logic-analytic logic, that is-
abstracts from the concrete truth of a proposition, and focuses attention first and
foremost on its bare (essentially mathematical) form, its truth value. This week I
want to explore some ways of converting this bare form into a richer, pictorial
form.
Philosophers since Aristotle, and even before that, have almost universally
recognized that logic and mathematics are closely related disciplines. Until the
middle of the nineteenth century, most philosophers would have said this
relationship is confined primarily to arithmetic, where functions such as addition,
subtraction, multiplication and division have clear analogies to logical operators
such as "and", "not", etc. But then a scholar named George Boole (1815-1864)
wrote a book defending what he called the "Algebra of Logic". He demonstrated
that algebraic relations are also closely related in many ways to logical relations.
Note that I have labeled these figures with a mere "+" and "-". These symbols are
derived directly from the law of noncontradiction, simply by dropping the "A"
from both sides of the "+A≠-A" equation. The "A" is a formal representation for
"some content", so dropping this symbol implies, quite rightly, that in the
Geometry of Logic we are concerned with nothing but the bare logical form of the
sets of concepts we use. Since this simple distinction arises out of the laws of
analytic logic, I refer to it as a "first-level analytic relation" (or "1LAR"). As we
shall see, representing this law with the simpler equation, "+ ≠ -" (i.e., positivity is
not negativity), makes it much easier to work with more complex, higher levels of
logical opposition.
The circle and line segment can be used as maps of virtually any distinction
between two opposite terms. Such distinctions, as we learned from Chuang Tzu
last week, are a commonplace in our ordinary ways of thinking about the world.
We naturally divide things into pairs of opposites: male and female, day and night,
hot and cold, etc. In most cases I believe the line segment offers the most
appropriate way of representing such distinctions. Since the circle marks out a
boundary between "outside" and "inside", we should employ this figure only
when there is an imbalance between the two terms in question-as, for example,
when one acts as a limitation on the other, but not vice versa.
Now if we were to stop here, the Geometry of Logic would not be a very
interesting subject. No one has any trouble seeing the logical relationship between
a pair of opposite terms, to say nothing of a single term in its relation to itself.
Using points, line segments, or circles in such a way is helpful only when the
terms in question do not define an obvious opposition. This is especially true of
the circle. For example, using a circle to represent Kant's distinction between our
necessary ignorance and our possible knowledge, as we did in Lecture 7 (see
Figures III.5 and III.10), helped us fix in our minds the proper relationship
between these two, with the former limiting the extent of the latter.
In any case, one of the most interesting and useful tools in the Geometry of
Logic arises out of the simple application of the law of noncontradiction to itself.
By this I am referring to cases involving each side of a pair of opposed concepts
being itself broken down into a further pair of two opposing concepts. As an
example, let's consider the familiar concept "one day". We all know how to
perform the simple analytic process whereby we divide "one day" into two more
or less equal and opposite halves, called "daytime" and "nighttime" (i.e., "not
daytime"). This is a good example of a typical 1LAR. However, as with most
1LARs, if we try to apply this strict division to every moment in a day, we find
there are certain times during the day when we hesitate to say whether it is
"daytime" or "nighttime"; and as a result, we make a further analytic division,
between "dusk" and "dawn".
In order to translate this into the form of our logical apparatus, using "+"
and "-" combinations to replace the actual content of our distinctions, all we need
to do is add another "+" and "-" term, in turn, to each of the original terms from
the simple 1LAR. This gives rise to the following four "components" (i.e.,
combinations of one or more +/- terms) of a "second-level analytic relation" (or
"2LAR"):
-- +- -+ ++
I call the first and last components (i.e., "--" and "++") pure, because both terms
are the same, whereas I call the middle two components (i.e., "+-" and "-+")
mixed, because they both combine one "+" and one "-".
The components are mapped onto the cross in Figure V.3a according to
their complementary opposites. That means the two components located at
opposite ends of each line segment will share one common term. For example, the
first term in both components might be a "+", while the second term will be a "+"
on one side and a "-" on the other. By contrast, the components mapped onto the
square in Figure V.3b are organized according to contradictory opposites. That
means the component at any given corner of the square does not overlap at all
with the component at the opposite corner. For example, if the component at one
corner has a "+" in the first position, the component at the opposite corner must
have a "-" in that position; and likewise for the second position.
The square is, in fact, the one geometrical figure that can be found fairly
consistently in most logic textbooks. For it is the formal basis of what is
commonly referred to as "the square of opposition". This square has proved to be
very helpful in clarifying for logicians the formal relations between propositions
that are opposed to each other in different ways (namely, as "contradictions" or as
"contraries"). However, I do not wish to dwell on that well-known application
here. Instead, since I've already used the cross as a map on numerous occasions in
these lectures, let's look more closely at how it can represent the relationships
between complementary opposites.
The third and fourth types of first-level relationships visible on the cross
can be called "subordinate" types, because they are not as evident as the two
"primary" types. Hence, when we want to call attention to them, it is helpful to
draw a diagonal line through the center of the cross, either from the top right to
the bottom left, or from the top left to the bottom right. The former diagonal line,
as shown in Figures I.1, III.3, and IV.5, calls our attention to the secondary
complementary relationship existing between the components with different first
terms, but the same second term (i.e., between "--" and "+-", and between "-+"
and "++"). The latter diagonal line highlights the fourth type of first-level
relationship, between pairs of contradictory opposites (i.e., between the two pure
components, "++" and "--", and between the two mixed components, "+-" and "-
+"). I have not included this type of diagonal line in the maps used so far, but it
would be appropriate to add it to the cross any time we want to call special
attention to the two pairs of concepts that are diametrically opposed in a given
2LAR.
Having given this warning, I can now add that there is actually quite a
simple method of testing any set of four concepts that we think might be related
according to the form of a 2LAR. All we need to do is find two yes-or-no
questions whose answers, when put together, give rise to simple descriptions of
the four concepts we have before us. Thus, for example, in order to prove that the
four concepts mentioned above, "daytime", "nighttime", "dusk", and "dawn",
compose a 2LAR, all we need to do is posit the two questions: (1) Is it obviously
either daytime or nighttime (as opposed to being a transition period)? and (2) Is it
lighter now than at the opposite time of day? This gives rise to four possible
situations, corresponding to the four components of a 2LAR as follows:
This demonstrates that the four terms in question can be mapped properly onto the
2LAR cross, as shown in Figure V.4a.
Of course, there are actually more than four physical "elements" in the
universe; likewise, a day can be divided into more than just four parts, and the
weather has far more than just four variations! In the same way, the process of
analytic division can and does go on and on, forming increasingly complex
patterns of relations between groups of concepts. In this course we have no time
to examine the complex relations created by these "higher levels" of analytic
division. However, I would like to mention one final example. But first I should
point out that, no matter how far we go in making analytic divisions, the patterns
will always follow this very simple formula:
C = 2t
where "C" refers to the total number of different components possible and "t"
refers to the number of +/- terms in each component. The latter, incidentally, is
always identical to the number of the level. Thus, as we have seen, the number of
divisions required to construct a 2LAR is two, the number of terms in each
resulting component is also two, and the total number of components is four (22 =
4). Likewise, the number of divisions required to construct a 3LAR is three, the
number of terms in each resulting component is three, and the total number of
components is eight (23 = 8).
The higher the level of analytic relation, the more complex is the map that
has to be constructed to give an accurate picture of all the logical relations
involved. One good example of such a complex system can be found in the
ancient Chinese book of wisdom, the I Ching. This book describes a set of 64
"hexagrams" (i.e., six-part pictures), each representing some kind of life situation.
The book was originally used primarily for predicting future events: in some
arbitrary way, such as throwing dice, a person selects two of the 64 hexagrams,
and the transformation from one to the other is then used as the basis for
answering a question, usually about how some present situation will change in the
future. (Thus it is also called The Book of Changes.) For our purposes, of course,
the predictive power of the I Ching is not its main attraction; rather, its logical
form is what interests us. For the 64 hexagrams actually function as six-term
components of a 6LAR. The traditional way of representing this system of logical
possibilities is to use sets of six solid or broken lines to define each hexagram. By
simply replacing the solid lines with a "+" and the broken lines with a "-", we can
translate this system directly into the one developed above. If we arrange the
components according to their contradictory opposites (as is normally done in
using the I Ching), then the intricate relationships between these hexagrams can
be mapped onto a sphere, which, when projected onto a plane surface so that the
opposite poles of the sphere are represented as the center and the circumference of
a circle, looks like this:
Figure V.5: A Map of the 6LAR in the I Ching
Don't worry if this map confuses you. It is intended to present the logical
form of a highly complex system of concepts at a glance. If you are not familiar
with the system, the map is not likely to be very meaningful. Nevertheless, I
would like to end this lecture simply by pointing out that this map bears a striking
resemblance to the symmetrical pictures used in some eastern religions (called
"mandalas"). Such mandalas are constructed not in order to clarify the logical
structure of a set of concepts, but rather, in order to stimulate new insights (and
eventually, "enlightenment") in those who use them as tools for meditation (see
DW 157-159). As we shall see in the next lecture, the Geometry of Logic itself is
also not limited to such analytic applications, but can actually touch upon the way
we live our life.
14. Mapping Synthetic Relations
In the last lecture, we saw the orderly way logical patterns are constructed
when we use analytic logic in our thinking. This kind of pattern, we found, can be
directly related to the patterns exhibited by some simple geometrical figures. This
fact should not surprise us. For in both cases such patterns originate in the mind.
Recognizing these orderly patterns, Kant suggested that reason itself contains a
fixed, architectonic structure. And his promotion of what he called reason's
"architectonic unity" is an inseparable aspect of his a priori approach. For his
assertion that there are certain necessary conditions for the possibility of any
human experience (see Lecture 8) assumes human reason operates according to a
fixed order. Because reason fixes this order-this architectonic -for us,
philosophers ought to do their best to understand and follow it whenever they
adopt an a priori perspective in their philosophizing (i.e., whenever they ask what
the mind imposes upon experience, rather than what it draws out of experience).
Kant believed philosophers ought to allow these patterns to serve as an a priori
"plan" for the construction of a philosophical system, much as a building
contractor uses the architect's blueprints as the plan for constructing a building. It
is no wonder, then, that Kant regarded Pythagoras (c.569-c.475 B.C.), not Thales,
as the first genuine philosopher (see OST 392); for Pythagoras focused not on
metaphysical issues, but on mathematics and number mysticism.
Logic is one kind of a priori perspective (see Figure IV.4), so we should not
be surprised to find such numerical patterns playing an important role in this
branch of philosophy. However, logical patterns do not relate only to our a priori
ways of thinking. As Pythagoras recognized, they also relate very closely to the
way we live our lives. That is one reason I ended the previous lecture with an
example from Chinese philosophy. In ancient China, the I Ching was never
regarded merely as a logical table of a priori thought-forms. Most-perhaps even
all-who used it were not even aware of its neat, logical structure, as a perfect
6LAR. Rather, they used it intuitively, as a reflection of the ever-present changes
in their daily life situations. In the real world, things do not remain eternally
opposed to each other, as our concepts might lead us to believe. Instead, opposites
gradually fade into each other by passing through an infinite series of degrees.
Once we recognize this fact, we might wish to view the line in Figure V.2b no
longer as representing an absolute separation, requiring a choice between two
discrete kinds, but as representing a continuum, containing infinitely many
degrees.
There is, in fact, another symbol from the Chinese tradition that performs
this same, synthetic function, even though it can also serve as a map of an analytic
relation. I am thinking here of the famous "Tai Chi" symbol, depicting the
opposition between the forces of yin (dark) and yang (light). As shown in Figure
V.6, this symbol can be regarded as simply another way of mapping a 2LAR.
However, in the Chinese tradition its primary symbolic value was quite different,
for it was regarded
Another way of mapping a 1LSR is to use the circle given in Figure V.2a,
labeling the circumference with an "x". This is appropriate because the boundary
participates in both the outside and the inside of the circle, just as "x" participates
in both "+" and "-". Whenever we use a circle as a logical map, the concept
labeling the circumference ought therefore to fulfill a synthetic function in relation
to the two opposite concepts it separates. However, synthetic logic, like analytic
logic, also has higher levels of relations; and the triangle has a more natural
application to these higher relations than the circle, so I'll treat the former as the
standard 1LSR map.
++ -+ x+
+- -- x-
+x -x xx
where "C" refers once again to the total number of different components possible
and "t" refers both to the number of different terms and to the number of the level.
I hope you will experiment with some of these higher levels on your own.
of David as a 6CR
This map can be used to explore the logical relationships between any two
sets of three concepts we believe might be related in this way. For example, one of
my students once came up with the idea of comparing the famous philosophical
triad, "truth, goodness, and beauty" with the famous religious triad, "faith, hope,
and love". The way to test whether or not these six concepts make up a legitimate
6CR is to find a way of mapping them onto the diagram in Figure V.8, such that
the concepts placed in opposition to each other really do have characteristics that
make them complementary opposites. We could begin this task by associating the
"-" triangle with the philosophical concepts and the "+" triangle with the
religious concepts, thus defining the basic 1LAR. But once again, I prefer to let
you experiment for yourself with the other details, or with other examples of your
own making.
This is where synthetic logic and the Geometry of Logic share a common
function. For both are instrumental in providing us with the means to develop our
capacity to see old issues in new ways, and in so doing, to deepen our insight into
whatever is perplexing us. Indeed, taken together, these two logical tools probably
constitute philosophy's most useful practical application. For as we shall see, a
clear understanding of these tools can assist you in thinking and writing more
clearly and more insightfully in virtually any area, not just when dealing with
philosophical issues. Let us therefore look first at synthetic logic on its own, and
then move from there into a discussion of how geometrical maps can be used in a
similar way to promote clarity and insight.
Let me illustrate lateral thinking with a personal story. When I was a boy I
used to have a great deal of trouble eating chicken with a fork and knife. I always
preferred to use my fingers. When I noticed one day how easily my grandfather
ate chicken with a fork and knife, I asked him how he performed this difficult task
with such ease. His answer was simple: "You are trying to remove the chicken
from the bone; what you need to do is to remove the bone from the chicken." This
is lateral thinking! And it worked: all along the bones had been disturbing my
enjoyment of one of my favorite foods; but when I changed the way I thought
about my task, the disturbance virtually vanished! It is also an example of using
synthetic logic, because my grandfather's suggestion enabled me to pass beyond
what seemed before like an absolute opposition between "It is easy to get the
chicken off the bone when I use my fingers" and "It is difficult to get the chicken
off the bone when I use a fork and knife". The new perspective, "remove the bone
from the chicken" enabled me to synthesize the "It is easy" of the first proposition
with the "use a fork and knife" of the second proposition. Lateral thinking always
cuts across our former way of thinking in just this way, much as the vertical axis
of a cross cuts across the horizontal axis.
In another book, called Po: Beyond Yes and No, de Bono suggests another
tool for making new discoveries. As the very title reveals, this new tool is rooted
in synthetic logic even more obviously than lateral thinking. In this book de Bono
coins a new word, "po", as a way of responding to questions whose proper answer
is neither "yes" nor "no" (or both "yes" and "no"). The letters "P-O", he POints
out, are found together in many words that play an imPOrtant role in creative
thinking, such as "hyPOthesis", "POetry", "POssibility", "POtential", "POsitive
thinking", and "supPOse". "PO" can also be regarded as an acronym, an
abbreviation of the phrase "Presuppose the Opposite". In order to show how this
new word can actually help us develop our ability to gain new insights-i.e., to see
new POssibilities, new opPOrtunities, just over the horizon of our present
perspective-de Bono suggests we experiment with various "po situations". To
perform such an experiment, we must use "po" as an adjective, modifying a word
we wish to think about creatively; but our description of the characteristics of that
word must then presuppose the opposite of whatever we normally think about the
objects, activities, or situations related to the word. If we think about how things
would be different if this po situation were really the case, de Bono assures us that
gaining new insights will become much easier.
If I now step back from this po situation, and re-enter the "real world", I
find I have stumbled upon several new ideas about how I can improve my
teaching: I should be humble enough to learn from my students, respect them as
equals in the adventure of learning, not be upset if they show some disrespect
toward me, encourage them to ask and answer questions, and give them
opportunities to discuss issues among themselves. The first time I gave this
lecture, I had not prepared these insights beforehand: they just came to me as I
was experimenting with de Bono's method in front of the class. Yet I think these
are really very good insights, don't you? If so, it is important to remember that
they did not come to me because I am especially clever; they came because I used
po to think laterally, thus leading me to adopt a surprising new perspective on a
familiar subject. You can prove this for yourself simply by using the same method
to reflect on any area you wish to improve or any topic you need to view with
fresh insight. Just remember: po thinking stimulates insights because it causes us
intentionally to adopt a perspective we know is contradictory to the real situation-
a practical application of synthetic logic if ever there was one!
I hope the foregoing examples have helped you see the great value -indeed,
the necessity-of using synthetic logic. I'm confident that they have, because over
the years I've noticed that beginning philosophy students often find it easier to
grasp synthetic logic than do professional philosophers! This, no doubt, is partly
because western philosophers are often taught to have a prejudice in favor of the
exclusive validity of analytic logic. In some traditions logic is defined as
"analysis"; so of course, anyone who tries to propose a nonanalytic logic is
regarded as speaking nonsense! Nevertheless, as we have seen, synthetic logic
exhibits patterns just as much as analytic logic; so if we define logic as "patterns
of words", then synthetic and analytic logic clearly ought to have an equal right
to be called "logic". (Philosophers trained in eastern ways of thinking,
incidentally, sometimes develop a prejudice in favor of synthetic logic; in the end
this is no better than the western prejudice. A "good" philosopher will be able to
appreciate the value of using both.) Perhaps another reason beginners can accept
synthetic logic so easily is that it actually requires less formal training to use
synthetic logic than analytic logic: whereas analytic logic is the logic of
knowledge (especially thinking), synthetic logic is the logic of experience
(especially intuiting). In this sense, we can call synthetic logic the logic of life.
If you are reading this as a student, your life is likely to be focused largely
on studying, writing papers, and taking tests. With this in mind, I shall devote the
rest of this lecture to suggesting how an awareness of perspectives can be an aid
to improving your writing skills-a topic that should interest all readers, especially
those writing insight papers. We have already seen that insights tend to arise
when we learn to shift our perspective (as in lateral and po thinking) and that
synthetic logic is the logic that governs such changes; we shall now proceed to
examine how an ability to map our perspectives according to the principles of the
Geometry of Logic can improve our receptivity to insight still further.
First, let me warn you that before you actually use a logical map in a paper
or essay, you should carefully assess whether the reader(s) will be receptive to
thinking in pictures. Some people have a natural preference for this type of
thinking, while others seem to be virtually incapable of understanding it. My own
doctoral dissertation at Oxford was initially rejected because one of my
examiners had an allergic reaction to my use of diagrams. He claimed my thesis
contained "publishable material", but not as long as it was filled with diagrams
based on the Geometry of Logic. Ironically, the chapter where I defended my use
of diagrams (Chapter III of KSP) had at that time already been accepted for
publication in a very reputable professional journal! Nevertheless, I had to
rewrite my dissertation, removing the diagrams, before it was deemed acceptable
by that examiner. This illustrates that a person's response to a diagram may have
more to do with his or her bias (e.g., an unquestioned myth about what an
academic thesis should look like) than with any rationally justifiable objection to
pictorial thinking. If you think your reader(s) might have such a bias, you can still
use diagrams to help organize your thinking and stimulate insights; but it would
be wise not to include your diagrams in the final version of your essay. But if your
teacher likes using diagrams or at least has an open mind about such things,
including the actual diagram can be an impressive way of making a good essay
even better.
The most basic use for a logical map is in outlining the overall flow of your
essay, just as I did for this book in Figure I.1. What you may not have noticed is
that the 2LAR map provides a pattern that can serve as a universal guide for
constructing a clear and complete argument. In its simplest application, as shown
in Figure V.10, the pure components (-- and ++) stand for the Introductory and
Concluding parts
of your essay. In a well-organized essay these will not be mere "before and after"
summaries of what is contained in the other parts. Rather, a good introduction
sketches out the basic limiting conditions on the topic, just as "recognition of
ignorance" did for this course. Likewise, a good conclusion leaves the reader with
clear and interesting practical applications and/or ideas for future research. As
we shall see in Part Four, the "wonder of silence" will do just that for our study of
philosophy. The impure components (+- and -+), by contrast, will present two
opposite perspectives on the topic at hand. In our case, thinking (logic) and doing
(wisdom) are the two opposites that occupy our attention in Parts Two and Three.
Viewing these opposites as two perspectives can lead to an especially insightful
essay in cases where the views examined in these two parts tend to be regarded as
competing theories or approaches. If you can effectively demonstrate how the two
are actually compatible and/or give a clear account of why certain
incompatibilities are unavoidable, you will be well on your way to writing an
impressive piece.
Having a predetermined plan for the format of what you intend to write may
seem at first like an illegitimate procedure: since the real world is not so neatly
divided, how can we know in advance whether the topic will actually fit into such
a neat, logical pattern? Kant would reply that such a question ignores the fact
that reason itself has an essentially architectonic nature. That is, our thinking is
(or ought to be!) orderly and patterned, so in any essay that involves rational
thinking, that order ought not to be left to chance. Of course, the content of any
essay cannot be predetermined in this way. But if the essay is one that can benefit
by being written in a clear and orderly way, then selecting a pattern as common
as the 2LAR will virtually guarantee an increase in its level of clarity and
persuasiveness. Some essays may be so detailed that they will require a more
complex pattern, such as the 12CR used in organizing this course (and its sequel,
DW, as well as KSP and KCR). The alternative approach, adopted by most
writers even of highly abstract philosophical essays, is simply to divide the essay
into a haphazard number of sections without following any rule. Yet this leaves
the reader totally clueless as to why the essay is divided up in just this way, and
not some other.
By far the greatest benefit that comes from using the Geometry of Logic to
pre-plan a piece of writing is that doing so calls attention to gaps and previously
undetected connections between the various themes being considered. In the first
two lectures this week, I gave several examples of how geometrical maps can be
used to help promote insights. (Remember the rainbow?) The potential for giving
other such examples is so great that I could easily fill a whole book with them!
But for our purposes it will be enough to provide one more example to illustrate
how a map can assist us in deepening our insight by discovering a new
perspective on an old, familiar topic.
When I was preparing the present edition of this book, I had taught
Introduction to Philosophy more than thirty times, always using something like
Figures I.1 and I.3 on the first day as a preview of what students could expect.
Then one day after a Philosophy Cafe meeting here in Hong Kong, I was
discussing the nature of silence with one of the participants. Suddenly as I spoke I
realized that Parts Two and Four of this course can be described as the two ways
human beings experience meaning. The word "meaning" can therefore label the
vertical pole on Figure I.3. As I went home that night, this image of the labeled
vertical pole caused me to wonder: How, then, should the horizontal pole be
labeled? Had I not organized this course using the Geometry of Logic, this
question would surely never have arisen. But it now became so obvious that I was
amazed I had never in 13 years thought of this issue! For several weeks I reflected
on this matter without coming up with an answer. Then, in a conversation with a
former student, I finally sat down and drew the diagram. Seeing the horizontal
pole with "ignorance" on one end and "knowledge" on the other stimulated me all
in a flash to think of two good answers: Parts One and Three both deal with
reality, but from two different perspectives (ultimate and non-ultimate); but a
more natural way of contrasting this with "meaning" is to refer to it as
"existence". My new insight was now complete: the overall aim of this course is to
share a vision of what it means to exist.
RECOMMENDED READINGS
If Frege can be viewed as the "father" of linguistic analysis, then its greatest
"son" was, undoubtedly, Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951). Not long after coming
to Cambridge, Wittgenstein launched out on his own, to become one of this
century's two or three most influential philosophers. The bulk of his influence
came through his lectures and tutorials, and through the students and other
philosophers who shared in these discussions with him. For Wittgenstein himself
published only one book during his lifetime, written while he was still a young
man. When he died, however, he left the manuscript for a second book, eventually
published two years after his death. Each of these books laid the foundation for a
major new version of linguistic analysis. For the remainder of today's lecture, let's
take a look at these two trends in turn.
1.12 For the totality of facts determines what is the case, and also whatever
is not the case.
1.21 Each item can be the case or not the case while everything else
remains the same.
Throughout the book Wittgenstein follows the same rigorous, mathematical form
used in this introductory passage, numbering each successive paragraph in
hierarchical order. This logical form reflects the overall aim of the book: to
construct a set of analytic propositions that can be used as a framework for
understanding all "facts" (i.e., meaningful propositions) about the world. The
analytic focus of Wittgenstein's concern is evident when, for example, he states
that each of these facts "can be the case" (+) "or not the case" (-).
After setting up a fixed boundary line between what counts as "the world"
and what does not-i.e., between "facts" and "things"-Wittgenstein weaves an
intricate web of logical propositions in sections 2-6 of his book. These
propositions are supposed to establish a philosophical framework for
understanding any legitimate fact that the "world" (i.e., the set of all meaningful
propositions) presents to us. He then concludes with a passage that is worth
quoting at length:
6.522 There are, indeed, things that cannot be put into words. They make
themselves manifest. They are what is mystical.
Analytic philosophers have debated long and hard over the proper
interpretation of the enigmas in this surprise ending to Wittgenstein's Tractatus.
But if we keep in mind the distinction between analytic and synthetic logic, then
the meaning of these claims can be seen quite clearly. Relating the distinction
between "facts" and "things" to the distinction between analytic and synthetic
logic, especially as depicted in Figure IV.6, suggests the following way of
picturing the main structure of Wittgenstein's argument in the above passage:
The knife Ayer used to cut away all such illusions came in the form of what
he called the "verification" principle. He described this principle in the form of a
question we are supposed to ask about any proposition put forward as a possible
"fact" about the world: "Would any observations be relevant to the determination
of its truth or falsehood?" (LTL 38). If the answer is "no", reasoned Ayer, then
there is no way to verify the truth or falsity of the proposition in question; and in
any such situation, the proposition must be literally meaningless. So, if I were
trying to defend the truth of a proposition such as "God exists", Ayer would
require me to describe some potential empirical situation that would cause me to
give up my belief in God. For example, if I said I would give up my belief in God
if my mother were to die a tragic death, then he would admit that my belief has
some meaningful content; but it is now primarily a belief about my mother, not a
belief about God. A person who claimed to have an unshakable faith would
simply be regarded as believing utter nonsense. Ayer argues along these lines in
the remainder of his book, employing the knife of verification to carve away most
of what have traditionally been regarded as the most important areas of
philosophical inquiry. Not only metaphysical propositions as such, but also most
of the nearest and dearest propositions of moral, religious, and aesthetic value are
also explained away as, at best, a mere expression of a person's emotional state
(and hence, as irrational).
However, there is a serious problem with Ayer's program, as with any such
attempt to establish on logical grounds a set of so-called "positive" limits to
philosophical inquiry. The problem is that the very principle this whole school of
thought is based on cannot pass the test of verification. In other words, if Ayer
were here today and we asked him to point to some observation-any observation-
that would count as evidence against the principle of verification, he would be
unable to do so! Why? Because this principle is not merely a "logical tool", as
Ayer thought; it is itself a metaphysical belief every bit as much as those he tried
to discard as nonsense. This means either the principle is true, in which case the
principle itself is meaningless, or else the principle is false, in which case the very
foundation of logical positivism falls to pieces. We can express the self-
contradictory character of the verification principle in a more rigorous form as
follows (assuming "VP" stands for "verification principle" and "-v" stands for "a
proposition not verifiable by some observation"):
VP is a -v.
The form of this argument should look familiar to you; it is the infamous problem
of "self-reference", exposed as a fallacy in Lecture 10.
... there could be no beings without the Being that lets them be; but Being is
present and manifest in the beings, and apart from the beings, Being would
become indistinguishable from nothing. Hence Being and the beings, though
neither can be assimilated to the other, cannot be separated from each other either.
This distinction between Being and beings serves as the primary starting-point for
many existentialists, though philosophers who are not so theologically-minded
often prefer to start from the even more basic distinction between Being (and/or
beings) and nothing.
gious language; and there have traditionally been two ways of solving it.
The first kind of solution can be called the "way of negation". Those who
take this approach insist that any words used to describe Being must be literally
true-i.e., true in the same way they would be if we applied the same words to
beings. The result is that this way of approaching language about God gives rise
either to extremely austere descriptions of ultimate reality, or to no description at
all. We have already come across several typical representatives of this approach.
The long passage quoted in Lecture 12 from Pseudo-Dionysius is one of the
earliest and best examples. As we saw, his propositions are limiting to the point of
being virtually empty if we interpret them solely in terms of analytic logic, though
they can point to deeper meanings if we interpret them in terms of synthetic logic.
Kant's theory of knowledge, outlined in Lecture 8, is also frequently interpreted as
implying a strict limitation of language to the realm of beings. And, of course,
Wittgenstein's Tractatus ends with an explicit recommendation that we remain
silent when it comes to the "mystical things" that "manifest themselves" to us,
beyond the "world of facts".
The second approach to explaining how words can be used to construct
meaningful expressions concerning some ultimate "Being" has been called the
"way of affirmation". Interestingly, each of the above-mentioned philosophers
proposed, at some point, not only a negative "way", but also a complementary
affirmative "way"-evidence suggesting they all deserve to be called "good"
philosophers. Wittgenstein's Investigations can be regarded as his attempt to forge
an affirmative way. Kant's moral philosophy, to be examined in Lecture 22, was
purposefully constructed as an affirmative complement to the negative restrictions
established by his epistemology. And Pseudo-Dionysius himself was actually the
philosopher who first named these two "ways"; his elaboration of an affirmative
way is, in fact, surprisingly rich, given the extreme austerity of his negative
theology.
This analogy does not imply that every relationship between two beings is
somehow similar to the relationship between Being and all beings, but only that in
certain instances such a similarity comes to our minds as an appropriate way of
using words to explain our experience of Being. For example, Jesus experienced
the relation of Being to beings in a way that reminded him of the relation between
a father and a son, so he taught his followers to pray to their "heavenly father".
The analogy here is:
where "father" refers, of course, to the ideal of perfect fatherhood.
We will look more closely at some of Tillich's ideas in Part Four of this
course; but for now it will suffice merely to point out that, when Tillich insists we
should not, strictly speaking, say "God exists", since God simply is the Being
from which existing beings stand out, he is adopting the "negative way". If we
look at the same problem from the more "affirmative" point of view of the
analogy of being, then we can say that God's mode of existence (or perhaps we
can say God's reality) is to our human mode of existence (or reality) as the
mountain-tops are to the valleys below, or as the sun is to the moon, or as any
other higher or primary power we know about is to its corresponding lower or
derivative power. Such comparisons do not give us knowledge of God, but they do
give us a way of using words to express our belief about how our experience of
God can best be described. In other words, the distinction between Being and
beings does not imply that God is not real, but that God's reality is of a
fundamentally different kind than that of any other beings we know about.
Whereas Tillich would say that, strictly speaking, it is not correct to say either
"God exists" or "God does not exist", I would add that, from the more flexible
point of view of synthetic logic, we are better off saying both of these
propositions are true and meaningful, each in its own way. For God is not merely
the greatest of all existing beings: we beings have existence; God is existence -or,
as Macquarrie puts it, God "lets-be" (PCT 141). This is surely the main point of
Tillich's claim that God does not literally "exist".
Macquarrie also notes that God talk has its historical roots in the language
of myths (PCT 130-134). He describes the view of some existentialists, that myth
is a form of narrative attempting to answer a basically subjective question, "Who
am I?", in an objectified form. But he warns that myths also have a properly
objective aspect (134): "The myth talks indeed of our human existence, but it
talks of this existence in relation to Being, in so far as Being has disclosed itself."
In other words, the experience is an experience of something objective, even
though the knowledge it reveals is primarily about the situation of the person
having the experience. Although today we "live in a post-mythical age" (132),
understanding the nature of mythological language is important because of its
close relationship to religious language: both types of language depend heavily on
the use of symbols.
In Part Four of this course, we will consider in some detail how certain
symbols function in such a way as to enable us to cope with our ignorance of
ultimate reality. So it will be helpful here to give a brief, preliminary account of
how symbols function in religious language. A symbol, according to Macquarrie,
is anything in the realm of beings that discloses and thereby points our attention
toward the realm of Being. He calls attention to the synthetic character of symbols
when he notes that they inevitably involve "paradox" (PCT 145): "Just because
symbols are symbols, that is to say, they both stand for what they symbolize and
yet fall short of it, they must be at once affirmed and denied." Macquarrie also
alludes on several occasions (e.g., 135-136) to the definition of symbols suggested
by Tillich. As we shall see in Lecture 31, Tillich defines a symbol as a sign that
participates in the reality to which it points. In other words, the symbol in once
sense is the reality itself (A), even though in another sense, as a merely empirical
object, it is not the reality (-A). Accordingly, some writers refer to the law of
contradiction as the law of "participation", governing situations where "A
participates in -A."
Unlike most Greek gods, who were regarded as governing only one or two
aspects of life, Hermes was associated with a wide variety of attributes. Because
of his initial act, he became the god of thieves and the trickster god, with cunning
being one of his chief characteristics. But he was also honored as the god of
musicians, shepherds, traders, and craftsmen, as well as the god of love-making
and magic (especially spells to be used in attracting one's beloved). Of all his
traits, the ones that defined his role among the gods more than any other was his
job as the messenger. (Interestingly, the Greek term for "angel" also literally
means "messenger of God".) As one of the few gods who was allowed to travel
freely between the human and divine realms, Hermes can be regarded as the god
of boundaries-a title whose suitability is evident in Figure VI.3.
The third major school of philosophy in the twentieth century draws its
name, with good reason, from this mythical character. Just as
One of Gadamer's central arguments in Truth and Method was that the
scientist's "naive faith in scientific method" (268) "leads one to deny one's own
historicality." Actually, any attempt to gain truth must be based on some method;
and whatever method we choose is paradoxically bound to limit our view of what
is true. This is because, as I have stressed at various points throughout this course,
we can recognize something as true only when we view it from some perspective.
(I shall examine this theme in more detail in Lecture 24.) But the scientific
method is particularly dangerous in this regard, because its most vocal proponents
tend to treat it as the one and only method of attaining truth; yet by remaining
ignorant of their own prejudices (or "myths", as we called them in Part One), such
claims end up hiding as much truth as they reveal-if not more. By contrast, a
philosophical appreciation for the principle of effective history gives us a
"consciousness of the hermeneutical situation" (268).
One way of emphasizing the importance of making room for our own
prejudices is to distinguish between "exegesis" (reading the meaning out of a text)
and "eisegesis" (reading your own meaning into a text). Most scholars nowadays
still regard the former as the only valid approach to interpretation. But Gadamer's
philosophy demonstrates that analytically picking apart the meaning of a text
(exegesis) and synthetically adding our own insight to the text's possible
meanings (eisegesis) are both necessary aspects of the hermeneutic process. A
rare example of a scholar who did not share the bias against eisegesis is Kant,
who argued that all biblical interpretation that takes place in the context of a
religion ought to be given a moral interpretation, even if that is not part of the
text's literal meaning-provided it does not contradict that meaning. We shall talk
more about Kant's view of religion in Week XI. The point here is that, without
some measure of eisegesis, our understanding will be void of insight and so also,
void of any deep meaning. Before concluding today's lecture, let us therefore
explore in more detail the nature of insight in relation to the distinction between
analytic and synthetic logic.
2. Alfred Jules Ayer, Language, Truth and Logic2, Ch. One, "The Elimination of
Metaphysics" (LTL 33-45).
7. "Hermes" (http://web.uvic.ca/grs/bowman/myth/gods/hermes_t.html),
maintained by Laurel Bowman.
8. Hans Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method2, Second Part, §II.1, "The Elevation
of the Historicality of Understanding to the Status of Hermeneutical Principle"
(TM 235-274).
D1
19. What is Wisdom?
For the benefit of those of you who have not yet had the opportunity to read
the book I mentioned at the end of the last lecture, Jonathan Livingston Seagull, I
will begin today by giving you a brief summary of its contents. After that, I'd like
to hear how those of you who have read the story would answer the following
three questions:
(2) What does the story tell us about the pursuit of wisdom?
Finally, I will end today's lecture by explaining how some of the lessons contained
in this story are related to the various issues we will be examining during this
third part of the course.
Now, let's begin with the first question. Who has an idea as to what flying
might represent in this story? By the way, don't say "the search for wisdom",
because that's too obvious. I've already told you I want us to view the whole story
as giving us insight into the search for wisdom, so now I'd like you to be more
specific. Then, in our discussion of the second question, we can try to apply what
we learn from the symbolism of flying to the issue of the nature of loving
wisdom. So who would like to be first?
Student N. "Freedom."
Yes, I suppose that's a good place to start. Without even reading the story
we could be fairly confident that this is part of the intended symbolism, since it's
quite common to associate a bird in flight with freedom. This is probably part of
the reason the author chose to write a story about a bird, rather than, say, a fish or
a dog. The story itself confirms this by telling how Jonathan saw himself as free
from the things that trapped the other gulls into an unhappy and meaningless life,
such as the desires for food, acceptance by others, and political power. As he
learned to fly, he also learned to free himself, more and more, from such
entrapments; and in so doing he learned how to live a truly meaningful life. In
Part Two he even learned to free himself from his life-long tendency to view
literal flying (i.e., flying with his physical body) as the ultimate purpose of his
life.
Very good. I agree that the element of the unknown plays an important role
throughout the whole story. Jonathan was willing to pursue his goal even though
he never seemed to know what was around the next corner-at least, not until he
returned to the flock in Part Three. As you suggest, his quest for "perfect speed"
was really a quest for the unattainable. As a result he was, paradoxically, able to
reach his goal only when he was willing to give up all his conventional ideas
about how it could be reached, especially his assumption that it would be reached
by means of the "flight of wing and feather". Likewise, I think you've chosen
exactly the right words when you say he was always "breaking through the limits
...". In fact, one of the reasons why the flight of a bird symbolizes freedom is that
birds seem to have found the secret of breaking through the chains of the law of
gravity, which binds us human beings so firmly to the earth. Moreover, the story
itself suggests that breaking through old boundaries is one of the fundamental
keys to self-discovery. Did you notice that in Part One Jonathan actually referred
to one of his major discoveries about flying as "the breakthrough"? Then, in Part
Two, his discovery of the "flight" of the imagination was a breakthrough not only
in his level of skill, but also in his understanding. And his return to the flock in
Part Three represented yet another kind of breakthrough, which also has to do
with the symbolism of flying as it is presented in the story.
What other lessons can we learn from the symbol of flying? In a philosophy
class, an obvious answer, suggested by some of my past students, is that flying for
a bird corresponds to thinking, or perhaps self-understanding, for a philosopher.
Or another possibility is that the whole story is about the learning process in
general, the passage from ignorance to knowledge, which, of course, is also one
of the main themes we have been developing in this course. Do any of you have
anything to add to these ideas, before we go on to the second question?
Student Q. "I think flying represents perfection, since the story mentions
'perfect speed' several times. Even though we cannot fly, we can strive to be
perfect in the things we are able to do."
Maybe so, but I think we have to be careful not to misunderstand what this
kind of "perfection" is all about. I don't think it merely refers to being right or
good all of the time, otherwise Jonathan would have had to follow the "Law of the
Flock", even though it sometimes went against the "true law", of "freedom" (JLS
114). In any case, perfection is a very high ideal to set for oneself. Do you think
Jonathan's quest for perfection did him any good? What can we learn from his
experiences?
Student Q. "Well, without that goal, I don't think Jonathan's life would
have been very meaningful. I think flying is what gave Jonathan's life its
meaning."
So flying represents not just the quest for perfection, but the quest for a
kind of perfection that can bestow real meaning on our otherwise mundane life.
Yes, I think this is one of the key points of the whole book. Not everything can
function in this way, and this means we must be very careful in choosing what we
make the object of our life's quest. Jonathan himself, as I've already said, changed
the way he viewed flying several times during the story, coming closer and closer
with each change to achieving the ultimate goal of participation in a meaningful
reality.
Student R. "Those who are really serious about pursuing wisdom are likely
to live a hard and lonely life."
Yes indeed. But what is it that gives us the power to stick to such an endless
task? What keeps us from losing hope and simply giving up in despair? Does the
story give us any clues?
Student S. "I believe Jonathan was able to continue pursuing his goal only
because he was able to see a dimension that goes beyond time and space."
This is a very important point. But actually, it takes us directly to the third
question; so before I comment on your answer, does anyone have any ideas about
where this strange place was that Jonathan was transported to in Part Two?
Student T. "Doesn't the story say he went to heaven? I got the impression
that Jonathan was supposed to have died at the end of Part One, and the two gulls
were like angels taking him up to heaven."
I'm not surprised the story gave you this impression. Indeed, it would
certainly be one possible interpretation, especially since Jonathan himself actually
interpreted the new place in this way at the very beginning of Part Two, when he
thought to himself "So this is heaven ..." (JLS 57). Nevertheless, a little bit later
(64), after realizing he had not yet reached his final goal, Jonathan asked Chiang
"this world isn't heaven at all, is it?" and Chiang answered "there is no such place.
Heaven is not a place and it is not a time. Heaven is being perfect." Unfortunately,
when Chiang was just about to explain in more detail what heaven really is,
Jonathan interrupted him (79)-but not before Chiang had the chance to tell
Jonathan that perfection is intimately interconnected with love.
If the place Jonathan went in Part Two was not heaven, since the story
portrays heaven more as a state of being, then where was that place? Or, in other
words, what could that place symbolize for us?
This is one good way of looking at it, though I would prefer to say he went
into his imagination. For he was able to do things in that place that we can do
only in our imaginations. One of the main points of Part Two, in fact, seems to be
that the imagination is just as real as the parts of our mind that give us knowledge
of the external world. In any case, however we wish to interpret that place, it was
certainly a place where the dimension beyond space and time was more readily at
hand than it is for us most of the time. Thus, if we say that in Part One Jonathan
found a treasure chest within himself, but it remained locked, then Part Two
would be the place where he found the key, in the imagination, or if you prefer, in
the ideas found in his own mind. And in Part Three he unlocked the treasure, for
the benefit of those who had once cast him out.
Using a bit of eisegesis, we can also compare the place Jonathan went in
Part Two to a philosophy class. Part One is like the life each of you have lived up
until now in the real world, where you have learned a great deal about how to
live. But in Part Two Jonathan learned about learning; this "second order"
activity is one way of describing the task of philosophy. This interpretation
implies that the purpose of studying philosophy is not to become a professional
philosopher who writes boring, technical papers no one can understand, in order
to publish them in scholarly journals that no one reads; rather, the purpose is to
prepare you to return to the place you were before (or at least to its horizon), but
with a newfound sense of your connection with a higher reality, a reality capable
of empowering you to pursue the study of wisdom to the very end of your life,
regardless of your profession. Along similar lines, if we think of the three parts of
the story as corresponding to three types of skill, arising out of the physical,
mental, and spiritual aspects of human nature (cf. Figure II.8), then we can use
Figure VII.1 as a map of the developmental process illustrated in the story of
Jonathan's life.
Let's look briefly at two other stories that powerfully illustrate the
importance of returning to the boundary of our former world to share the insights
we gained by breaking through the boundary. The first is a part of Plato's story of
the cave (see Figure II.7) that I did not mention in Lecture 5. Those who manage
to find their way all the way out into the sunlight and are able to see the world as
it is, having learned the philosophical skill of seeing things according to their
form, are so impressed by the sun's power that they are impelled to return to the
cave in hopes of freeing those who are still prisoners in the world of shadows. So
Plato's story actually follows the same form shown in Figure VII.2. The second
one, adapted from a story by G.K. Chesterton (see CO), is quite different from
both Plato's and Jonathan's, but has a similar moral.
Once there was a boy who grew up in a small village, secluded in the hills
of a far-away land. Throughout his childhood, he frequently heard the older
villagers telling stories about a Great Mountain that was shaped in the image of a
person's face. He was so filled with wonder at the tales he heard that he left home
at an unusually early age to search for the famed mountain. Yet, after many years
of tiresome wandering throughout his entire country, he never caught so much as
a glimpse of the image he sought. Disappointed at what he now regarded as the
deceptions of his youth, he finally decided to return home. As he approached his
village, however, he was shocked to discover that the mountain rising up behind it
was shaped in the distinct form of a person's face! Throughout his entire youth he
had never traveled far enough from home to see "the whole picture", and once he
left, he had never turned back to look. Now, of course, his travels had changed
him so much that he would never be able to fit into the life of the village the way
he used to: he would always remain, we might say, "on the boundary".
With this new insight in mind, let us now recall that Parts One and Two of
this course have dealt primarily with the two most important areas of theoretical
philosophy. In Parts Three and Four we will be turning our attention to the two
most important areas of practical philosophy. The first can be called "applied
philosophy", since it requires us to apply what we have learned about logic to
various kinds of human endeavor. But it can also be called science, since the aim
in each case is to establish some kind of knowledge. For the remainder of Part
Three we will be examining three of the major branches of the tree of philosophy:
the philosophies of natural science, moral science, and political science. In each
case our goal will be to discover the boundary conditions that can be transcended
(e.g., by means of synthetic logic), yet constitute the proper home of any
philosopher who wishes to reflect upon these disciplines. In so doing, we will
actually say very little about wisdom as such. However, the underlying
assumption throughout our examination of each of these topics will be that in
locating the proper position for the boundary lines, we will in fact be carrying out
one of the most important tasks in the quest for wisdom.
20. Science and the Anatomy of Wisdom
One of the most important lessons we learned from our discussion in the
previous session was that philosophy, like learning to fly, is primarily a skill. I
want to begin this lecture by emphasizing the same point, especially since the first
eighteen lectures dealt mainly with the theoretical aspects of the tree of
philosophy. If your study of philosophy so far has given you the impression that
philosophy is more a set of theories or doctrines than an activity, then please
forget that impression right now! Philosophy is first and foremost something
people do. And learning to do philosophy is in many ways similar to learning to
play football or speak a language. There are always certain theories and methods
that have to be learned along the way; but in the end you'll never become a good
football player without repeating hours of drills out on the field, and you'll never
become fluent in a language without finding someone who speaks that language
and conversing with them.
The examples of games and languages suggest that two indispensable steps
to learning a skill are practice and imitation; and the same applies to the skill of
doing philosophy. This is why I have encouraged everyone who takes this course
to set aside a regular time for reflecting on philosophical issues raised in the
lectures or listed in the "Questions" section at the end of each week, and then to
write insight papers in response. The insight papers are your chance to practice
doing philosophy. But, unless you have a natural talent for philosophizing, mere
practice is not enough to bring success. You also need someone to imitate. With
this in mind, I hope that as you are attending (or reading) these lectures, you are
paying more attention to the way I do philosophy than to memorizing "facts"
about various philosophers. But, just as there are many different strategies for
playing good football and many different ideas about how best to learn a
language, so also, as we have already seen, there are many different conceptions
of the best way of doing philosophy. This is why it is important for you to read the
original writings of other philosophers as well (such as those suggested in the
"Recommended Readings" sections at the end of each week). When reading these
texts, you should not think of yourself as merely learning the content of
philosophical ideas, but also as learning to imitate how that philosopher does
philosophy. Eventually, you should be able to do philosophy as you read, by
actively employing appropriate methods in dialogue with the text you are reading.
Philosophy is a skill, but it is not just any skill. Indeed, it would be easy to
take the comparison between philosophy and other skills too far. For philosophy
can actually be regarded as the ultimate skill, or the skill of skills. In other words,
philosophy at its best, as the skill of having ideas and discovering the truth in
them, provides the foundation for all other skills. This is the reason virtually every
academic discipline has a "philosophy of ..." attached to it. In addition to the
branches of the tree of philosophy to be considered here in Part Three-philosophy
of science, philosophy of morals, and philosophy of politics-we could study the
philosophy of religion, the philosophy of physics (and of other specific sciences),
the philosophy of art (and of specific forms of art), the philosophy of education-
the list goes on and on. That the skill of philosophizing is the foundation of all
these skills is reflected in our educational establishment by the fact that a person
who masters a certain academic discipline is usually given a degree entitled
"doctor of philosophy". Although most doctoral degrees do not actually require
students to study any philosophy as such, the name of the degree does suggest that
graduates have mastered the foundation of the discipline-and so ought, in
principle at least, to be able to philosophize about it. However, even skills not
normally associated with university education can have a "philosophy of ...", such
as the philosophy of playing chess, the philosophy of cooking, the philosophy of
hunting, etc. And then, of course there is the philosophy of life, not to mention the
philosophy of death. Both of these topics, to be examined in Week XII, refer
primarily to skills: namely, learning how to live, or learning how to die.
How does this view of philosophy as the ideal skill relate to the
fundamental myth of this course? In other words, if philosophy is like a tree, then
what should we call the skill of doing philosophy? And how should we picture the
philosopher? Philosophers work with philosophy in much the same way
gardeners work with the plants in a garden: just as gardeners do not create or
even construct plants, but nurture something that is already given (e.g., in the
form of a seed), so also philosophers do not (or at least should not) see their task
as inventing arguments out of nothing or as building systems up in some
mechanical fashion, but as nurturing a reality that is already given (e.g., in the
form of an idea). With this in mind, let's take a closer look at this course's basic
myth.
The trunk and branches, as we have seen, are for us not physics and the
other sciences, but logic and science (where "science" is taken in its original
meaning to refer to any justifiable "knowledge", not just to those types of
knowledge patterned on the methods of the physical sciences). Just as all the
branches of a tree grow out of the trunk, all our knowledge (i.e., sciens) is
expressible in words (i.e., logoi). We could add that the bark of the tree is like
analytic logic, showing us the protective surface of our ways of thinking, whereas
the core of the tree is like
Figure VII.3: The Tree of Philosophy
synthetic logic, taking us to the very heart and life of thought itself.
Although Descartes did not carry his analogy of the tree beyond the
branches, we will see in Part Four that the leaves of a tree can be compared to the
area of philosophical inquiry usually known as ontology (the "study of being").
Just as the leaves of most types of trees fall off each year and grow anew in the
spring in a continuous cycle of birth, growth, death, and rebirth, so also the
phenomena we will study in Part Four are often fleeting and temporary. Yet, even
as a tree's leaves give it its distinctive character, so also the distinctive character of
human beings is determined by such experiences as beauty, love, religious
experience, and death. Moreover, just as dead leaves fall to the ground and then
decompose, in order to constitute the soil that nourishes the roots of the tree, so
also the accumulation of generations of human experiences has constituted a
tradition that cannot be neglected without peril, since it forms the very ground in
which the tree of philosophy grows.
Now let's take this myth of the tree of philosophy one step further, by
assuming we are nurturing a tree that bears fruit. If so, what is the nature of this
fruit? I suggest we view it as the starting point of the various sciences. History
tells us that most of the disciplines we now regard as sciences were at one time
regarded as branches of philosophy. Mathematics, for example, can be traced back
to the ancient Greek philosopher named Pythagoras (whose "Pythagorean
theorem" you probably learned in school). Sciences as diverse as physics, biology,
psychology, and politics all have their origin in Aristotle's philosophical
empiricism. Even chemistry developed out of a quasi-philosophical discipline,
named Alchemy, in which people who called themselves "philosophers" tried to
find ways of converting various common materials into gold. (Alchemists
regarded the "arbor philosophicus" as a symbol of this transformation process,
though this version of the tree of philosophy, as described by Carl Jung (in PSA
420; see also Figures 122,131,135,188,221,231), was very different from the one
employed in this course.) Sociology and Economics also began as aspects of
philosophical systems. And again, the list goes on. Why is it that sciences so often
arise in this way? The tree of philosophy provides a plausible answer: the
branches of this tree represent science in the special sense of the love of wisdom;
on them grow various types of fruit; when one such fruit drops to the ground, rots,
and then takes root, a specific science is born. This explains, incidentally, why
trying to make philosophy itself into just another science is so hopeless: the tree
of philosophy can never become a science, because she is the mother of all
sciences! The tragedy is that these younger trees, though protected as tender
young shoots under the shade of the tree of philosophy, often threaten to choke
out their mother when they reach maturity.
If the new trees that grow out of the fruit of the tree of philosophy are the
specific sciences, then what are the seeds we find at the center of each fruit? The
seeds can represent our ideas, or insights. I believe most, if not all, of us have
many valuable insights throughout our lifetime. The problem is that we usually
fail to recognize their value when they come to us, so we eat the sweet fruit of
opinion, to satisfy our appetite, but throw away the bitter seeds, even though they
could eventually give birth to knowledge. An insight must be planted, watered,
and nurtured by our constant attention if it is to grow into an idea worth
considering by other people, not just held by ourselves as a personal opinion.
Kant's distinction is actually based on two questions that form a 2LAR: (1)
Is the truth of p subjectively certain? and (2) Is the truth of p objectively certain?
Kant explained three of the possible situations that arise out of these two
questions, but he did not address the fourth possibility. He probably assumed it is
meaningless to think of a proposition as being objectively certain, yet subjectively
uncertain. Yet I do not think we should be too quick to regard this as an imperfect
2LAR. For what about ignorance? Is not ignorance the state of being subjectively
uncertain about something that has in itself some kind of objective certainty? If
so, then we can map these four cognitive states onto the 2LAR cross, as in Figure
VII.4.
An insight is never a mere opinion; it is more like a sudden revelation of
something new, an awareness of potential knowledge about something we were
completely ignorant of prior to having the insight. Accordingly, once we have
recognized our ignorance, philosophy calls
us to focus our attention away from opinions and toward knowledge and belief.
Science, by contrast, always aims for knowledge alone, in the sense of objectively
provable certainty. The scientist studies the relations between particular natural
phenomena by observing their general structure, and attempts to discover patterns
that will eventually lead to the understanding of some natural law followed by the
phenomena in question. If a phenomenon always operates in a certain way, then
its activity will be predictable; and of course, one of the great attractions of
science is that, whenever it truly reaches its ultimate goal of establishing
objectively justifiable knowledge, it enables us to know the future! The philosophy
of science, by contrast, is not interested in establishing particular items of
empirical knowledge, but in studying the nature of the overall assumptions and
methods of science. Thus, philosophers of science, instead of asking questions
about particular phenomena, ask questions such as: What is science? What is the
proper scientific method? What gives science its reliability? and Does science
give us knowledge of a reality that is entirely independent of our minds?
The main point I want to make about views like scientism and naturalism is
that, contrary to the assumption of many who hold such views, they are not part of
science, nor are they in any way necessitated by the nature of science; rather, they
are philosophies of science. Scientism is, or ought to be regarded as, an
epistemological theory, and naturalism, a metaphysical theory. Yet in many cases
they are more a result of a one-sided prejudice, an inability to see anything from
more than one point of view, than a well-reasoned philosophical foundation for
science. The fact is that other philosophies of science recognize that our world
consists of more than just mechanically determined material, that science is only
one of many legitimate ways of discovering truth, and that these views of science
provide just as good a foundation for scientific research as do their more narrow-
minded alternatives. Once we realize that an absolute trust in science has nothing
to do with science itself, much of the force is taken away from philosophies such
as scientism and naturalism.
Today we will look more closely at one of the fundamental issues in the
philosophy of science: the reliability of induction as a tool for gaining knowledge.
But first, let me direct your attention to a question I want you to think about
during the next few weeks, though it is not directly related to the philosophy of
science, . The question, paraphrased from Kierkegaard's quote (in CUP 97) from
Lessing (1729-1781), is:
In a later lecture, about the time I think you will have forgotten my request that
you reflect on this difficult question, I shall make some suggestions as to how I
believe we should respond.
Do you recall our discussion in Lecture 11 of the analytic and synthetic
methods of argument? At that point we contrasted deduction, the method that
begins with two or more premises and draws a necessary conclusion from them,
with induction, the method that begins by gathering evidence from observations
and generalizes from these to form a probable conclusion. Many scientists, from
the beginnings of science down to the present day, have assumed their task
requires careful observation more than rigorous argumentation, so that the proper
way of doing science is to proceed by the path of induction. The problem this
raises is that scientists nearly always view their task as a search for facts, and they
normally assume that once a "fact" is demonstrated, it is known for certain to be
true; yet, as we saw in Lecture 11, induction on its own cannot provide us with
such certain knowledge, since it always depends to some extent on guesswork.
Solving this problem is of the utmost importance for the philosophy of science,
because it appears to call into question one of our most basic beliefs about
scientific knowledge: that scientific facts are reliable and trustworthy, because
scientists have proved that they must be true.
For most scientists who have thought philosophically about what they are
doing, the solution to the "problem of induction" has been to assume the
phenomena they observe are somehow bound together by a necessary connection.
This would mean the necessity of scientific facts comes not from the logical
structure of the scientific method, but from some law within the phenomena
themselves. And the most basic natural law, governing all other more specific
laws about how phenomena interact, is that any effect we observe in the world is
necessarily determined by some preceding cause. The important thing to
understand about this solution is that this use of the law of necessary causation is
a philosophical assumption, not one based on any scientific proof. Indeed, we
could call it the "myth" that most of modern science is based on. In this century
there have been some scientists, mostly physicists, who claim to reject this myth,
on the grounds that on the subatomic level events "just happen": the path of an
electron, for example, is believed to be entirely random, and thus unpredictable at
any given point of time, so that only the "probability" of any given path can be
known beforehand. Other scientists, however, believe that such an explanation,
even as a way of accounting for the mysterious movements of subatomic
particles, is merely a confession that the physicists have come to the end of their
science. Indeed, it is as if they had "bumped their heads" on the outer boundary of
science itself.
If physicists really have reached the boundary of the physical world, then
the assumption that subatomic events are uncaused is just as mythical as the more
traditional assumption that all events have a cause. In either case scientists ought
to recognize that the debate over which assumption serves as a better myth to
build a science on is primarily a philosophical debate, not one that can be
answered merely through scientific observation. Accordingly, I shall now
introduce to you two ways philosophers have dealt with the issue of the necessary
connection that is so often believed to give inductive knowledge its reliability.
One comes from the doubts raised by David Hume (1711-1776), and the other
comes from Kant's influential attempt to refute Hume's position.
When we run over libraries, persuaded of these principles, what havoc must we
make? If we take in our hand any volume-of divinity or school metaphysics, for
instance-let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or
number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of
fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames, for it can contain nothing
but sophistry and illusion. (EHU §XII, Part III)
When it comes to scientific knowledge, Hume used this "fork" not to deny
the validity of all science whatsoever, but to argue that it is wrong to think of such
knowledge as giving us access to any necessary truth. For he believed it is
impossible to use induction to reach necessity. The reason is that he could find no
grounds for believing in a hidden law of necessary connection. We cannot observe
such a law, and we cannot prove it by deductive reasoning; so it must not be true!
He expressed this argument in a variety of ways. For example, when discussing
the possibility that the human will might give us access to such a law, he
reasoned:
Why has the will an influence over the tongue and fingers, not over the heart and
liver? This question would never embarrass us, were we conscious of a power in
the former case, not in the latter. We should then perceive, independent of
experience, why the authority of will over the organs of the body is circumscribed
within such particular limits. Being in that case fully acquainted with the power or
force ... we should also know, why its influence reaches precisely to such
boundaries, and no farther. (EHU §VII, Part I, my italics)
Here Hume recognized that the search for necessary connection is a search for a
boundary, outside of ordinary experience, that would give us consciousness of
why things are connected the way they are. But he went on to reject such a
possibility, on the following grounds:
... consciousness never deceives. Consequently, neither in the one case nor in the
other are we ever conscious of any power. We learn the influence of our will from
experience alone. And experience only teaches us, how one event constantly
follows another; without instructing us in the secret connection, which binds them
together, and renders them inseparable.
Hume's argument here is that, in order to understand the reasons the human
will works the way it does, we would have to be conscious of some power
underlying and determining our experience. But we are in fact conscious of
nothing but our own experiences; we never have even a glimpse of such a hidden
power. We come to believe in such abstract ideas by copying impressions from
our senses and "associating" the resulting ideas with each other. A simple
example is that we may form the illusory idea of "a golden mountain" by copying
legitimate impressions we have had of gold and mountains (EHU §II). The
problem is that some of our most trusted beliefs seem to be just as poorly
grounded (§VII, Part II):
... upon the whole, there appears not, throughout all nature, any one instance of
[necessary] connection which is conceivable by us. All events seem entirely loose
and separate. One event follows another; but we never can observe any tie
between them. They seem conjoined; but never connected. And as we can have no
idea of anything which never appeared to our outward sense or inward sentiment,
the necessary conclusion seems to be that we have no idea of connection or power
at all, and that these words are absolutely without any meaning, when employed
either in philosophical reasonings or common life.
If the idea of necessary connection is indeed "without any meaning", then this
poses seemingly insurmountable problems for the view that the inductive method
is sufficient for establishing scientific facts. This way of undermining the
foundation of what was previously assumed to constitute knowledge is typical of
the skeptical method in philosophy.
But there is nothing in a number of instances, different from every single instance,
which is supposed to be exactly similar; except only, that after a repetition of
similar instances, the mind is carried by habit, upon the appearance of one event,
to expect its usual attendant, and to believe that it will exist. This connection,
therefore, which we feel in the mind, this customary transition of the imagination
from one object to its usual attendant, is the sentiment or impression from which
we form the idea of power or necessary connection. Nothing farther is the case.
Contemplate the subject on all sides; you will never find any other origin of that
idea. (EHU §VII, Part II)
Kant and Hume both agreed that we have experience, but they disagreed
over what our subjective experience implies about the objective world. Whereas
Hume argued that our subjective experience is merely a "bundle of perceptions",
implying little or nothing about objective reality, Kant argued that "we must
derive the subjective succession of apprehension from the objective succession of
appearances", otherwise it would be impossible to explain why we perceive, or
"apprehend", a series of events in a given order, or a group of objects as distinct
from each other (CPR 221). In other words, our subjective experience is only
possible on the assumption that it is "bound down" to some objective reality. With
this in mind, Kant constructed the following argument:
Hume would not deny the second premise; so his only rebuttal would be to
question the first premise. Is there really anything that must be true in order for
our experience to be possible at all? If so, then those truths, taken together, would
define the boundary line between what we can and cannot know. Would it be
possible, for example, to imagine a kind of experience that does not require us to
presuppose that we have in some way been determined by something that
happened at some time in the past? Kant believed that in such a case we would
not be justified in claiming to have any experience. "Experience" here refers to an
awareness of "subjective succession" in our perceptions; and if there were not
also some "objective succession", then there would simply be no basis for our
subjective succession to be apprehended. In other words, an appeal to "habit" is
irrelevant, since without an objective succession as the basis for our so-called
habits, we could not even be conscious of those habits.
Some of you are probably rather confused at this point. This is not
surprising, for the arguments we have been considering are among the most
difficult ever proposed by philosophers. Professional philosophers who study
Hume and Kant all their life still debate over how to interpret their views and
which one gives a better description of the way the world really is. So we cannot
hope to settle the question once and for all in an introductory course!
Nevertheless, in hopes of clarifying what each of these positions involves, and
perhaps at the same time, helping you make up your mind about which one is
closer to the truth, I would like to perform a little "thought-experiment".
Imagine you've just finished with all your classes for the day. Let's assume
you live in Shatin, as I do; so you walk up the road to the nearest bus stop and
wait there for the next bus. After only a few minutes, the bus you normally ride
drives up. It is full of people; but the driver, a friendly man who you remember
seeing before, stops to let you on. Even though the only place for you to stand is
an awkward space right next to the driver, you love philosophy so much that you
immediately pull out the book you are currently reading from the lists of Recom‐
mended Readings, and begin to read. The traffic is not too bad, so after only a
minute or two the bus enters Lion Rock Tunnel, on its way to Shatin. You hardly
notice this, though, since you are so engrossed in your philosophizing. Then, all
of a sudden, you feel the bus stopping. At first, you just continue reading,
assuming there must be heavy traffic in the tunnel. But after a few minutes, you
begin to wonder why the bus still isn't moving. So you pull your eyes away from
your book to see if you can tell what is causing the delay. To your surprise, there
are no vehicles in front of the bus; and the bus driver is still sitting in the same
position he was in before, with his hands on the steering wheel and his feet on the
pedals, just as if he were still driving!
What would you do in such a case? My guess is that, given a long enough
delay, you would eventually ask the bus driver to explain why he had stopped the
bus. Now let's imagine he answers you by saying "I didn't stop the bus" (or the
equivalent expression in Cantonese). You would probably respond by saying
"Well, then, you better call for help, because the bus must be having some engine
trouble." But the driver replies: "No, the engine is working just fine. Listen." And
sure enough, you then notice that the rumble of the bus engine sounds the same as
it normally does when it is driving through the tunnel at a normal speed. I think
you would be a bit perplexed; but after a while, especially if you were going to be
late for dinner, you would again raise some kind of question, such as: "Well, if
you didn't stop the bus, who did? God? Or a ghost?" If the driver then answered
"No, of course not. How many times do I have to tell you, nobody stopped the
bus", then most of us, I think would say, or at least think, something like: "Look,
either someone stopped the bus intentionally, or there is some engine trouble,
because buses just don't stop for no reason at all!"
I wonder how would you respond if the bus driver replied to this claim by
retorting: "Ha! You just feel that way because of the habit you have developed
over your years of living in Hong Kong, of thinking that buses don't stop in
polluted tunnels for no reason. In fact, they can and do sometimes stop for no
reason; it's just that this is the first time you have experienced an exception to
your habitual expectations." If the driver then turned away and resumed his
driving position, as if nothing at all were unusual, I suspect that most of us would
try to get out of that bus as fast as we could! Why? Because we would all assume
this driver is either playing a very inappropriate (possibly dangerous) joke on his
passengers, or else he is crazy!
If, on the other hand, we accept Kant's argument and regard everything that
happens as determined by something that happened prior to it, a new problem
arises: How can we explain the feeling we human beings have that we are free? If
everything in the world is determined, does this mean we must discard our belief
in human freedom? This would cause a major problem, given the close
relationship between freedom and wisdom (see Lecture 19). Here the philosophy
of science impinges directly upon one of the central questions of the branch of
applied philosophy we will climb in the next lecture, the branch of moral
philosophy. There we will find to what extent our search for wisdom can lead us
to accept both the determinism of science and the freedom of moral action.
2. A. Is heaven a place?
RECOMMENDED READINGS
3. Jostein Gaarder, Sophie's World, tr. P. Møller (New York: Farrar, Strauss &
Giroux, Inc., 1994[1991]).
Near the end of the previous lecture I left you in a rather uncomfortable
position. Do you remember? You were stuck in Lion Rock Tunnel, inside a bus
being driven by a man who claimed that things just "happen", without being
caused by anything. What should you do in such a situation? Instead of answering
this question directly, I want to change the story a little bit. Let's imagine that
when you ask the bus driver why he stopped the bus, instead of saying "I didn't
...", he pulls out a gun and asks you to give him all your money and leave the bus,
or he will shoot. You would probably obey his demands. But after the bus drove
away, as you walk through the tunnel, you would probably become quite upset at
what that man had done to you. In fact, most of us would probably report his
action to the police as soon as possible, accusing him of doing something wrong.
What would be the rational basis of our claim in such a case? Why would
we judge that man's action to be morally wrong? In philosophy these kinds of
questions are called "ethical". Ethical questions are about how we should and
should not act. There are many, many ethical questions-so many that we cannot
even begin in this class to explore the different kinds of ethical questions, to say
nothing of specific questions about the rightness or wrongness of particular acts.
Ethical questions are like the many small twigs on the end of a tree branch: they
are very important, for on them grow the leaves and the fruit of the tree; yet there
are so many that any one of them could be removed without significantly
changing the appearance or the health of the tree.
The first necessary condition for the possibility of moral action is freedom.
Freedom, Kant argued, is the one and only "given fact" of practical reason. By
adopting the practical standpoint, we can actually break through the boundaries of
space and time (the limitations of our "sensibility") and replace them with
freedom. But this freedom does not leave us lost in a boundless world of
unlimited confusion; rather, freedom itself functions as a new kind of limitation.
Whereas space and time are necessary limits that anything we can know must
appear within, freedom is the necessary limit that any moral action must conform
to. The former is the world-limitation imposed on our heads so we can know the
truth; the latter is the self-limitation imposed on our bellies so we can do the good.
Though these two standpoints lead us in opposite directions, we need not view
them as irreconcilably contradictory, provided we recognize that they refer to
fundamentally different aspects of human life.
Kant never claimed he could prove human beings are free; on the contrary,
the first Critique demonstrates why such a proof is impossible. Instead, his
argument is that we must presuppose freedom in order to enter the realm of
morality, just as we must presuppose space and time in order to enter the realm of
knowledge. In both cases we are faced with a brute fact that cannot even be
questioned without radically changing (or perhaps even undermining) our human
experience. Although Kant would not have put it in this way, we could therefore
say these "facts" function like complementary myths for anyone in the modern
world who wants to interpret their experience in terms of knowledge or moral
action.
If freedom in the second Critique corresponds to space and time in the first,
what corresponds to the categories? The logical aspect of the boundary of morals
Kant called the "moral law", or "categorical imperative". All maxims (i.e.,
subjective rules of action) must conform to this law to qualify as moral. By
"categorical" Kant meant that this imperative makes an unconditional demand.
"Hypothetical" imperatives, by contrast, are ones with an "if" attached. If I say to
you "Please be quiet when I am in the room", then my command is hypothetical,
because you are not required to be quiet if I am not in the room. A command such
as "Do not tell lies", by contrast, is normally regarded as unconditional. I doubt if
your mother ever said to you "Do not tell lies, unless it makes you feel good"!
That is because commands such as telling the truth are usually regarded as duties.
A "duty", according to Kant, is an action performed out of respect for the moral
law-i.e., in obedience to one's conscience, rather than just following the desires or
"inclinations" of one's belly.
Kant believed he could determine a formula that would apply to all moral
action. In the end he actually proposed three distinct criteria for (or formulations
of) the categorical imperative. The first states that an action is moral only if its
maxim is universalizable: "Act only according to that maxim by which you can at
the same time will that it should become a universal law" (FMM 421). This does
not mean everyone will actually agree with your maxim, but only that everyone
ought to agree. The second requires us to respect human persons: "Act so that you
treat humanity, whether in your own person or in that of another, always as an end
and never as a means only" (429). The third requires that our maxim must be
autonomous (i.e., self-legislated): since "every rational creature [makes] universal
law", a moral maxim must be "consistent with the universal lawgiving of will"
(431). Let's test these necessary criteria, especially the first, by applying them to
an example.
If I cheat on an exam and someone asks me "Did you cheat on that exam?",
then I am faced with a moral choice. I can either lie, and hope nobody discovers
the truth, or I can tell the truth and suffer the consequences. Although lying in
such a case might make me happier, Kant thought this choice would be morally
wrong, because it would be based on a maxim on that could never become a
universal law. In the former case my maxim might be "It is acceptable to tell a lie,
if it will get me out of a difficult situation", whereas in the latter case my maxim
would be "Never tell a lie". Kant freely admitted it is possible to will (i.e., want to
tell)a particular lie, but he argued it would be irrational to will "a universal law to
lie": in such a case "my maxim would necessarily destroy itself as soon as it was
made a universal law" (FMM 403). In other words, if we imagine a world where it
would be acceptable for everyone to lie whenever it would make them happy, the
primary function of language (i.e., its ability to convey truth) would be
undermined. Moreover, a lie also breaks the second and third criteria: it uses
another human being, neglecting their rational capacity, solely in order to make
oneself happy. Because lying requires us to break a universalizable law (and
therefore also to disrespect human rationality), telling a lie is always morally
wrong, no matter how happy a lie might make us feel.
Kant gave other examples, relating to suicide, laziness, and apathy (see
FMM 421-424); but for our purposes it will suffice to point out the function
Kant's criteria for judging moral actions are supposed to fulfill. According to
Kant, we do not have to think consciously about the categorical imperative's three
formulations each time we face a moral dilemma; rather, their function is to
enable philosophers to locate truly moral issues and then define an objectively
valid boundary line between morally good and evil actions. The boundary line is
objective because it is true for everyone (i.e., universal) and because it uses an
objectively existing reality (i.e., humanity) as a basis for judgment.
When the moral law tells us to do something, performing that action makes
us worthy of praise only if our choice is not also meant to satisfy one of our
inclinations-i.e., only if our reason for doing it is unrelated to satisfying our
desires. Thus, Kant's moral philosophy can be restated as follows: an action can
be morally good or bad only if it is done freely and out respect for the moral law
rather than out of our inclination to fulfill our own desire for happiness. Kant
devoted much attention to the contrast between following inclinations and duty.
Of course, sometimes a single action can both satisfy the moral law and fulfill our
inclination to be happy. But whenever this is not possible, we must choose to say
"No!" to our own happiness. Accordingly, we can express the basic command of
the categorical imperative as: "Respect the moral law!" or "Follow your
conscience as an objective principle!" or simply, "Do your duty!"
In order for morality to be truly rational, Kant thought moral action must be
capable of fulfilling its purpose: to bring into being the highest possible good. Just
how this "summum bonum" ought to be defined is, however, a question that has
been debated among philosophers since ancient times. The Stoics believed the
highest good is virtue, and that a virtuous life ought to be pursued without any
regard for happiness. The Epicureans, by contrast, thought the highest good is to
fulfill one's pleasures, and therefore pursue happiness. This difference can be
traced back to the difference between Plato, with his focus on the ideal of
goodness, and Aristotle, with his concern for the experience of real happiness. It
may also appear at first to correspond to the distinction between Kant's
deontology and Mill's utilitarianism. However, Kant rejected this interpretation of
the implications of his own moral philosophy.
Kant argued that the best conception of the highest good must include both
virtue and happiness. Happiness without virtue would be unjust; virtue without
happiness would not be worth the effort. Therefore Kant explained the highest
good as the picture of an ideal world where each person is rewarded for their
virtue with a proportional level of happiness. In other words, if your level of
virtue reaches eight on a scale of one to ten and mine only reaches seven, then
you should be rewarded with 80% happiness, whereas I should be rewarded with
70% happiness. Any other conception of the ultimate purpose of moral action
would make morality irrational, inasmuch as morality would then aim at
something less than perfect goodness and justice.
Kant has often been criticized for introducing happiness into his theory at
this late stage: how could he include happiness in the highest good when he had
already defined virtue in terms of obeying duty rather than happiness? But this
criticism is based on a misunderstanding. By including happiness in the highest
good Kant was not suddenly changing his mind and saying that happiness can be
the motivation for our action after all. Rather, we must distinguish between
happiness as an original motive and happiness as a rational hope. The reality of
human life, according to Kant, is that right action often requires us to do
something we know will make us less happy (such as resisting the temptation to
steal someone else's money, to lie in order protect our reputation, etc.); yet at the
same time our reason tells us that in the end the person who chooses to obey the
moral law is more worthy to be happy than the person who chooses to pursue
happiness as an end in itself.
This presents a problem that must be solved if morality is to be rational: in
the world as we know it, virtuous people often are not rewarded with happiness.
How then can we conceive of the highest good as possible? Kant argued that
practical reason requires us to "postulate" (i.e., put forward as a necessary
assumption) the reality of life after death and the existence of God. Unlike
freedom, these postulates play no role in making an action moral; instead, they
help us understand the rational purpose of morality itself. Without believing in
another life and in a holy God governing that life, we may well be able to act
morally, but we will not be able to explain how the highest good could ever be
realized. This is Kant's famous "moral argument" for the existence of God. He
never claimed it could give us real knowledge of God's existence; but he did argue
that it provides the best practical reason for believing in God. Essentially, his
argument is that anyone who acts morally and believes such action is rational is
acting as if God exists, whether or not they actually believe in God. In other
words, Kant claimed we must either believe in God or else reject one of the
following propositions: (1) moral action is good; (2) morality is rational; (3) the
highest good combines virtue with proportional happiness.
Aside from providing this "practical proof" of God's existence, Kant's moral
philosophy made several other important contributions. For instance, as we have
seen, it established a clearly defined boundary between moral and non-moral
actions. An action is moral only if it is done freely (i.e., without depending on our
own happiness) and in accordance with the moral law (i.e., based on a
universalizable maxim). These are necessary conditions that must be true for
anyone who wishes to act morally, so they define an absolute set of guidelines for
our inner motivation, just as space, time, and the categories define an absolute set
of guidelines for understanding the outer world. We can picture the opposition
between Kant's two fundamental standpoints as follows:
(a) The bounds of knowledge (b) The bounds of action
FigureVIII.2:TheTheoreticalandPracticalStandpoints
Two things fill the mind with ever new and increasing admiration and awe, the
oftener and more steadily we reflect upon them: the starry heavens above me [i.e.,
nature] and the moral law within me [i.e., freedom]. I do not merely conjecture
them and seek them as though obscured in darkness or in the transcendent region
beyond my horizon: I see them before me, and I associate them directly with the
consciousness of my own existence. (CPrR 161-162)
We saw last time how Kant tried to intensify the rational significance of
acting morally by arguing that morality is based on an internal
FigureVIII.3:
sense of freedom and moral duty. His belief in a universally valid "voice" inside
us, telling each person the difference between right and wrong, may seem odd to
anyone who has been thoroughly immersed in the relativism that tends to
dominate modern western culture, where no clear distinction is drawn between
right and wrong. As a quick review of Kant's moral philosophy, and in order to
point up some of the differences between his view that moral ends (or aims) are
"objective" and the common view that they are all "subjective", I have
summarized some of the main differences in Figure VIII.3. Ever since Kant
proposed his radical distinction between the standpoints of moral action and
empirical knowledge, philosophers have been attempting various ways of
overcoming the limitations he proposed. (More often than not, the ways Kant
himself tried to reconcile these two realms have, unfortunately, been completely
ignored.) In this lecture we shall examine the main ideas of one such philosopher,
a man who foresaw many of the changes in ways of thinking and acting that have
occurred in the twentieth century and who, in some respects at least, was
responsible for them; for he started, as it were, a new cycle in the history of
western philosophy (cf. Figure III.3).
Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900) was a German philosopher who believed
the traditional values of the society of his day had cut religion and philosophy-and
indeed, humanity itself-from their proper roots. As a response to the impending
disaster he saw looming on the horizon, he called for a thoroughgoing
"transvaluation of values"-that is, a complete rethinking of the whole
philosophical and religious tradition that produced those traditional values. The
theories he developed in carrying out this task set up something like a new myth,
replacing the myth of dispassionate rationality, established by Socrates and
popularized by Plato, with a myth of passionate irrationality, whose implications
are only now beginning to be understood. (Nietzsche claimed, incidentally, that
his philosophy would not be fully understood until two hundred years after it was
written.) The problem with understanding his ideas is that he intentionally wrote
in an unsystematic way; constructing systems he saw as part of the old set of
values. Not only do some of his ideas contradict his other ideas, but many of his
books do not even pretend to develop a single, well-argued set of ideas. Rather,
they contain collections of diverse ideas, often expressed in the fragmented form
of "aphorisms". It is as if Nietzsche simply wrote a bunch of insight papers, then
published them whenever he had enough to make a book! He viewed himself
more as a poet, a psychologist, or even a prophet than as a philosopher in any
conventional sense. Nevertheless, many of his insights are directly addressed to
philosophical issues; so a summary of his main ideas should enable us to
appreciate his significance for the philosophical tradition.
Nietzsche's transvaluation of values, a focal point uniting all his other ideas,
was primarily an attempt to break through the traditional understanding of the
boundaries that limit our moral and intellectual life, establishing in its place a new
set of higher values. The old values, as represented especially by Christianity and
the philosophical tradition culminating in Kant, are "life-denying", he argued;
they must therefore be replaced by "life-affirming" values, the best examples
being found in the pagan religions and philosophies of ancient Greece. Science,
with its narrow field of vision, interpreting the world as basically dead, is not
solely responsible for this faulty world view. For the traditional Christian morals
accepted by the vast majority of the western world, and defended in Kant's
philosophy, also support notions such as love, humility, and self-sacrifice; and
such values, according to Nietzsche, have killed the human spirit itself, and
caused us to forget how to dance.
Looking back to ancient Greek mythology, Nietzsche chose names for these
two types of outlook on life: the traditional, life-denying outlook he called
"Apollonian" (after the God of the sun, named "Apollo"), while the life-affirming
outlook Nietzsche hoped to put in its place he called "Dionysian" (after the God
of wine, named "Dionysius"). Whereas the Apollonian outlook is conscious,
rational, and calm, the Dionysian is unconscious, irrational, and passionate. The
former gives rise to a "slave morality" that causes people to adopt a "herd
mentality" and view themselves as determined by a fixed boundary line defining
good and evil; in politics this attitude gives rise to democracy (rule by the
masses), thus encouraging everyone to be alike in mediocrity. By contrast, the
latter gives rise to a "master morality" that causes people to adopt a "hero
mentality" and view themselves as free to break out of the conventional ways of
interpreting right and wrong; in politics this attitude gives rise to aristocracy (rule
by a few people), thus encouraging the greatness of the human spirit to be
expressed.
sage inevitably came across as madness. This is at least one of the points of
Nietzsche's famous story of the madman in the market place:
Have you not heard as yet of that mad-man who on one bright forenoon lit a
lantern, ran out into the market-place and cried out again and again, "I seek God! I
seek God! -Because there were standing about just at that time many who did not
believe in God, the mad-man was the occasion of great merriment. Has God been
lost? said one of them. Or is He hiding himself? Is He afraid of us? Has He
boarded a ship? Has He emigrated? Thus they cried and laughed.
But the mad-man pierced them with his glance: "Whither has God gone?" he
cried; "I am going to tell you. We have killed Him-you and I! We all are His
murderers. But how have we accomplished this? How have we been able to empty
the sea? Who gave us the sponge to wipe off the entire horizon? What were we
doing when we unchained this earth from its sun? Whither does the earth now
move? Whither do we ourselves move?
"Are we not groping our way in an infinite nothingness? Do we not feel the
breath of the empty spaces. Has it not become colder? Is there not night and ever
more night? How do we manage to console ourselves, we master-assassins? Who
is going to wipe the blood off our hands? Must not we ourselves become gods to
make ourselves worthy of such a deed? (JW 125)
This famous passage not only states the problem, that our lifeless, Apollonian
personalities have killed God, it also gives a clue as to Nietzsche's solution. The
only beings capable of killing God are those who can themselves become gods.
Out of this arose Nietzsche's theory of Superman.
What is the ape to man? A laughing-stock, a thing of shame. And just the
same shall man be to the Superman: a laughing-stock, a thing of shame.
Ye have made your way from the worm to man, and much within you is still
worm....
The Superman is the meaning of the earth. Let your will say: The Superman
shall be the meaning of the earth!
I conjure you, my brethren, remain true to the earth, and believe not those who
speak unto you of superearthly hopes! Poisoners are they, whether they know it or
not.
Despisers of life are they, decaying ones and poisoned ones themselves, of
whom the earth is weary: so away with them!
Once blasphemy against God was the greatest blasphemy; but God died, and
therewith also those blasphemers. To blaspheme the earth is now the dreadfulest
sin, and to rate the heart of the unknowable higher than the meaning of the earth!
...
Lo, I teach you the Superman: he is that sea; in him can your greatest
contempt be submerged. (TSZ Prologue ?)
Someone in the crowd, getting impatient with Zarathustra's strange words, then
asks to be shown this "rope-dancer" (meaning the Superman). Zarathustra
responds by saying: "Man is a rope stretched between the animal and the
Superman-a rope over an abyss." After suggesting with this metaphor the picture
of humanity shown in Figure VIII.5, Nietzsche told how, after another speech by
Zarathustra, the tight-rope walker then
started his act, but was disturbed by someone else on the rope, who, "like a
buffoon", caused the tight-rope walker to fall to the ground. The story ends by
telling how Zarathustra helps the injured and dying man. Although we do not
have time to discuss the interpretation of this story in detail, I should at least add
that in the first section of the book itself, Nietzsche told a story about "three
metamorphoses": a spirit is transformed into a camel, the camel into a lion, and
the lion into a child. If we treat this as symbolizing three stages in the
development of humanity, it could be used to argue that for Nietzsche the
Dionysian ("lion") outlook was not to be part of the ideal man, but was merely a
necessary compensation for the over-rational bias of the contemporary Apollonian
("camel") outlook. The ultimate ideal of Nietzsche may well have been the person
who transcends the distinction between the Apollonian and the Dionysian, by
adopting neither the servant-based outlook of a camel nor the power-based
outlook of a lion, but the instinct-based outlook of a child.
In any case, the final aspect of Nietzsche's philosophy I shall present to you
today is his theory of perspectivism. Nietzsche was the first philosopher to use the
word "perspective" as a technical term in his philosophizing. And this, as you
may have noticed, is a practice I believe can be of utmost value to the
philosopher. However, for Nietzsche, the implication of saying that everything we
"know" is limited to some perspective is that there are actually no facts, only
interpretations. Indeed, he went so far as to suggest that everything is false; in
other words, language falsifies reality. This view is similar in some respects to
both Kant and Wittgenstein, as well as to the ideas of many other philosophers
who wished to distinguish between what is and what we can say about what is.
Unlike Kant, but like Wittgenstein, he was highly critical of all metaphysical
theories (especially dualism). For the very idea of a "true world" beyond this one
is, he believed, the root of all life-denying outlooks. This radical rejection of all
truth, metaphysical and otherwise, is an aspect of what is often called "nihilism".
For the true nihilist there are no real moral limitations whatsoever: all values can
be rejected as meaningless. Understood in this way, there is some debate as to
whether or not Nietzsche, whose ultimate goal was to reach a Higher Value
(namely, Superman), ought to be called a "nihilist" in the strict sense.
Finally, I should mention that, for the last eleven years of his life, Nietzsche
was insane. Trying to explain what caused his insanity can only be a matter of
conjecture. Some believe it was the result of a physical illness. Others interpret
his suffering as that of a true prophet, as if he were symbolically accepting such a
punishment on behalf of those who could not see mankind's tendency toward self-
destruction so clearly. Still others regard his final fate as a natural outcome of his
philosophical outlook. In the latter case his example could certainly serve as a
warning to anyone who wishes to experiment with a philosophy cut off from its
natural roots in metaphysics. In any case, because of her brother's insanity,
Nietzsche's sister ended up taking charge over the publication of his writings and
the promotion of his ideas. Unfortunately, she perverted his ideas in such a way
that Hitler was able to use what looked like Nietzsche's ideas as a philosophical
support for his own fascist political regime. Political philosophy will, in fact, be
the focus of next week's lectures. But we can end today by noting that the use
Hitler (and others) made of Nietzsche is now generally recognized to be a gross
misrepresentation. For Nietzsche was no anti-Semitic fascist, but truly a
philosopher unto himself-a new Socrates (or anti-Socrates) if ever there was one.
24.Perspectivism:ReconstructingtheBoundaries
Strict relativism, the view that no opinion is ultimately any better than any
others, must be clearly distinguished from "perspectivism". For Nietzsche, as we
have seen, the latter means that everything is false. Yet, if we really take this
seriously, we are left with a tree without roots-and perhaps even without a trunk!
Throughout this course I am defending a radically different version of
perspectivism. Instead of arguing from the perspectival nature of all knowledge
(as demonstrated by Kant) to the falseness of all language, we can regard each
well-defined perspective as an opportunity to gain truth within boundaries. Thus,
for example, I have defended a philosophy of perspective wherein truth does
exist, but can be known as such only within the boundary of a distinct
perspective. In this way we can say truth is relative, without saying it all boils
down to personal opinions: once we realize that the love of wisdom requires first
and foremost a search for the proper perspective for interpreting ideas such as
truth and goodness, then and only then will we be able to affirm that opinions
(sometimes even the majority opinion) can be wrong! Rather than saying, with
Nietzsche, that all interpretations of the world are false, we can then affirm that
many of them can be true. Indeed, even when two views appear to conflict with
each other, they may both be right, if they are assuming different perspectives.
As a literary critic, Derrida values the act of writing as the primary category
of all philosophy and the most basic form of verbal communication. The essence
of writing is a "free play" of language, not the communication of some deeper
"meaning". As he puts it: "There is nothing outside the text." Rather than
searching for some elusive "true meaning", interpreters should view their task as
playing with the text until some new insight arises as a result. Some of the "tricks"
Derrida uses to deconstruct classical texts in this way are to find a dominant
metaphor that guides the way the key terms are used and understood, to trace all
such terms back to their original or literal meanings, to focus on differences
between what might seem to be the "obvious" meaning of a text and other, hidden
meanings, and to explore the way different types of differences interact (including
differences in sound, spelling, etc.). He coined the term "différance" to refer to the
latter, the interplay between different differences, emphasizing that we are able to
examine only one type of difference at a time: the other types must "defer" to the
one that grabs our attention at any given time. To locate such alternative or under‐
lying metaphors, meanings, differences-such différance-Derrida often utilizes
concepts from depth psychology, arguing that unconscious connections are
imbedded in the text. In so doing, his aim is not to deny a text's "traditional"
interpretation(s), so much as to play around with the wide variety of other
interpretations that might be just as plausible.
So convinced is Derrida that the proper interpretation of a text must always
remain an "open", unstructured question, that he claims that the margins of a book
are as important as the printed words. The margins, together with all the spaces
between the words, constitute the différance that makes reading possible in the
first place. On the one hand, the margins represent what is not written, and this
tells us as much about a text's meaning as what is written. On the other hand,
when a reader writes his or her own comments in the margins, these become as
much a part of the text's meaning as what the original writer had in mind.
Kant did recognize a level of reality that goes beyond the relatively absolute
principles of his perspectivism. But as we saw in Lecture 8, he regarded this
absolute or "ultimate" reality, the realm of the "thing in itself", as unknowable.
Rather than merely defending the "old" morality, as Nietzsche claimed, Kant's
perspectivism thus provided us with a third alternative. Traditional morality lives
in the myth that a specific set of moral maxims (e.g., those found in the Bible) are
absolutely true for all people and at all times. Relativism breaks through this myth
by arguing that, because nothing is absolute, anything can be true or right.
"Cultural relativism" is the more specific view that each culture sets its own
boundaries, and that right and wrong are in fact nothing but cultural norms. But if
this were the case, then no culture could ever be wrong and it would be difficult to
imagine how or why a culture would ever change its moral standards. Nietzsche's
relativism is not cultural, for he clearly accuses some cultures (namely, the
Apollonian ones) of being morally corrupt. His view might rather be called
absolute relativism, inasmuch as he argued that the only healthy moral theory is
one that breaks through all boundaries, cultural or otherwise. Kant's position goes
beyond relativism by encouraging us to return to the boundary of morality even
though we are ignorant of exactly how fully we are following the moral law at
any given time. For Kant, we are to believe there is something absolute, even
though we cannot know exactly what it is; only when we humbly accept this
unknowable absolute as a boundary-defining reality will we be able to make
moral decisions that are genuinely our decisions (i.e., free) and yet genuinely
moral as well.
The presence of a moral absolute, even if it is in a sense outside the world
of our actions, has important implications for how we treat those who disagree
with our opinions. Relativists usually encourage us always to be tolerant of the
views of others. Tolerance in general is, of course, a very good thing. It is a
reaction against an older way of looking at the world, as full of absolute, black
and white distinctions that ought to be strictly forced onto all other people. In the
name of absolute truth and goodness many people down through history have
been attacked, ostracized, beheaded, and burned at the stake, merely for holding
opinions differing from those of the people with more political power.
Nevertheless, the danger in relativism is that it ultimately leads to the destruction
of both knowledge and morality. By blurring the distinction between true and
false or between right and wrong, it convinces people nowadays to ignore the
inner guidelines that reason provides for us to determine truth and goodness. Must
we, so to speak, "throw out the baby with the bath water"? Kant would say "No!"
Be tolerant up to a point, but not at the expense of denying two of the highest
values in human life. Kantian perspectivism provides an alternative to relativism
by maintaining that there are rational absolutes, and that, although these absolutes
are objectively unknowable, practical reason itself communicates them to each
person, if only we will listen to its voice. Because goodness and truth have their
absolute basis not in the actions and objects found in the world, but in the rational
voice within each individual, intolerance can still be opposed, but not so
systematically as to destroy the possibility of knowledge and morality.
Kant's own keyword for the basic principle of morality, respect is actually
related in a significant etymological way (at least in English) to the whole notion
of a perspective. To "re-spect" a person is "to look again" at them and their
situation-to think twice before judging or acting according to one's own
inclinations. To "per-spect" a situation is "to look through (or by means of)" a
given presupposition at the various details under consideration. Interestingly, at
least one translator has used "to perspect" for Kant's term "einsehen", literally
meaning "to see in" and as a noun, "understanding" or "insight". This accurately
reflects the close relationship we have seen operating throughout this course
between perspectives and insights. Thus we could say that, as respecting is to
morality, perspecting is to insight, and so also to philosophy in general.
Before concluding this lecture, I would like to mention that some of you are
still falling into the self-reference trap (see Lecture 10) in your insight papers.
Now that we have a deeper understanding of perspectives and how they function
in relation to myths, I hope you will be more adept at stating your arguments more
carefully. With this in mind, let me now give another example of how to deal with
philosophical questions without falling into this fallacy. Once I read a paper that
claimed "Truth always hurts", and another that similarly argued "The only time
we can be certain of what is true is when it inflicts pain on us." Such claims may
be true and even wise in a variety of human situations. But if we present such an
insight as a universal principle, then it obviously fails the self-reference test. For
merely believing the statement "Truth always hurts" does not, in itself, inflict any
pain on the believer. If the principle is true, then there is at least one truth that
does not hurt!
1. A. Can a single action be both free and determined at the same time?
RECOMMENDED READINGS
1. Immanuel Kant, Foundation of the Metaphysics of Morals, Second Section,
"Transition From the Popular Moral Philosophy to the Metaphysics of Morals"
(FMM 405-445).
Here in Part Three we have been learning that philosophy deals not only
with abstract theoretical issues relating to metaphysics, epistemology, logic, and
language usage, but also with more concrete practical issues, such as those
relating to science and morality. The philosophy of science and moral philosophy
are both major branches of philosophy: they provide the basis for applying
philosophy to more practical issues relating to specific sciences or specific ethical
situations. In this and the following lecture I want us to consider one further
branch of the tree of philosophy, political philosophy. There are actually a number
of other fields of philosophical inquiry that might be included in Part Three, if we
had time. But for our purposes a discussion of political philosophy can serve as an
adequate way of completing our study of how to apply philosophical thinking in
our search for wisdom.
Many of the philosophers we have already studied had much to say about
political philosophy. For example, the main point of Plato's longest and most
systematic book, called Republic, is to set out a rational plan for the ideal political
system. However, many aspects of his proposal appear to modern readers to be
too unrealistic and/or outdated to be considered very seriously. The suggestion
that philosophers ought to be trained to serve as kings, for instance, is an idea that
has rarely, if ever, been put into practice. One of the reasons Plato's political
philosophy seems so distant from our own ways of thinking about politics is that
modern political thought is rooted to a large extent in the quite different ideas put
forward by his star student. Aristotle's book, Politics, also contains some
examples whose relevance is limited to the ancient Greek city-states, where the
political systems were early forerunners of modern democracies; yet the main
issues it raises are of timeless interest, transcending their original historical
context in their applicability. Hence, we shall use today's lecture to take a close
look at this classic text in political philosophy.
Aristotle began his study of politics by claiming that "every city is some
form of partnership ... for the sake of some good", and that the political
philosopher's task is that of "investigating what the city is composed of" (AP
1252a(35)). He then pointed out that families and business relations are also
examples of partnerships exhibiting something like politics on a lower level. A
partnership between several families gives rise to a village, and a partnership
between several villages gives rise to a city. The partnership that makes up a city
therefore requires certain agreements between "similar persons, for the sake of a
life that is the best possible" (1328a(209)). Aristotle never suggested that such
partners must be similar in every respect, but that both unity and diversity must
exist between the partners in different respects: "a city tends to come into being at
the point when the partnership formed by a multitude is self-sufficient" (1261a-
b(55-57)). The purpose of a city, therefore, is
not [to be] a partnership in a location and for the sake of not committing injustice
against each other and of transacting business. These things must necessarily be
present if there is to be a city, but not even when all of them are present is it yet a
city, but [the city is] the partnership in living well both of households and families
for the sake of a complete and self-sufficient life. (1280b(99))
Anyone who can participate actively in the political partnership that makes
up a city is qualified to be a "citizen". Thus Aristotle defined a citizen as anyone
who can hold a government office: "Whoever is entitled to participate in an office
involving deliberation or decision is ... a citizen in this city; and the city is the
multitude of such persons that is adequate with a view to a self-sufficient life" (AP
1275a-b(87)). Sharing in the political partnership of the city requires the citizen
not only to be a capable decision-maker, but also to be a person who is willing to
abide by decisions made by others. For Aristotle stressed (1277b(92)) that "the
good citizen should know and have the capacity both to be ruled and to rule, and
this very thing is the virtue of a citizen-knowledge of rule over free persons from
both [points of view]."
In this sense monarchies, where only one person rules, have no citizens; in
fact, they technically have no city and no politics either, inasmuch as there is no
partnership between equals for the purpose of ruling and being ruled. This is why
Aristotle sometimes contrasted monarchies with what we would call "republican"
(i.e., non-monarchical) political systems: only the latter are politeiai in the strict
sense of the word (though he sometimes used this term loosely to refer to
monarchies as well), so republican systems occupied his primary attention in
Politics.
The names Aristotle assigned each of these six systems are as follows. The
correct form of monarchy is called a "kingship". (In ancient Greek monos means
"alone" or "single"; archos means "ruler". The suffix "-cracy" comes from kratos,
meaning "power".) The correct form of "rule by the few" is "aristocracy", meaning
the power is held by the best (aristos) people. And "polity" is the correct form of
majority rule, though Aristotle also used this term to refer in a general way to all
political systems. Since he sometimes contrasted politeiai with monarchy,
Aristotle in this context probably intended politeiai to be interpreted in this
narrow sense; as such, his claim was that all non-monarchical systems (i.e., all
republics) can be called polities. In Nicomachean Ethics (NE 1160a), he avoided
the equivocal use of "polity" by referring to this third correct political system as
"timocracy", meaning power held by those who own property (timema).
Moreover, he explicitly stated that this term is to be preferred to the term "polity",
even though the latter is the more common of the two terms. However, this brief
account of timocracy is difficult to distinguish from oligarchy (see below); so I
shall adopt the usage given in Politics in spite of its possible ambiguity.
Aristotle also described deviations from each of the three basically positive
forms of political system:
Deviations from those mentioned are tyranny from kingship, oligarchy from
aristocracy, democracy from polity. Tyranny is monarchy with a view to the
advantage of the monarch, oligarchy [rule] with a view to the advantage of the
well off, democracy [rule] with a view to the advantage of those who are poor;
none of them is with a view to the common gain. (AP 1279b(96))
Let's now examine each of these six political systems in a bit more detail.
In his discussion of kingship, Aristotle was careful to point out that there
are several different kinds of kings. The main distinction is between those whose
authority transcends the law and those who must themselves obey the law. A
political system where the "so-called king" rules "according to law" is not a true
kingship; such a king is more like a "permanent general" (AP 1287a(113)). A
kingship in the true sense of the word is an "absolute kingship", where "one
person has authority over all matters ..., with an arrangement that resembles
household management" (1285b(110-111)). In a kingship, "the best political
system is not one based on written (rules) and laws", because a good king will be
able to judge fairly according to the circumstances of each specific situation,
being guided by the general principles of the law, even though his judgment need
not be determined by them (1286a(111)). As Aristotle put it in AP 1284a(106-
107): "If there is one person so outstanding by his excess of virtue-or a number of
persons ...-... such persons can no longer be regarded as a part of the city.... [For]
they themselves are law." He then pointed out that "ostracism" is the inevitable
fate for such persons "in the deviant political systems" (1284b(108)), even though
in "the best political systems ... persons of this sort will be permanent kings in
their cities."
oligarchy is when those with property have authority in the political system; and
democracy is the opposite, when those have authority who do not possess a
[significant] amount of property but are poor ... What makes democracy and
oligarchy differ is poverty and wealth: wherever some rule on account of wealth,
whether a minority or a majority, this is necessarily an oligarchy, and wherever
those who are poor, a democracy. But it turns out ... that the former are few and
the latter many ...
Aristotle warned that the best political system for a given city cannot be
determined in advance: any of the systems (except tyranny) may end up being the
most appropriate, once the specific situation is taken into consideration. Thus, for
example, he admitted that sometimes a kingship will be the best system for a city,
even though in general "to have law rule is to be chosen in preference to having
one of the citizens do so" (AP 1288a(115-116)). Polity, the political system
Aristotle thought is most often to be preferred, is midway between aristocracy and
democracy. Yet even in the case of polity, he granted that "there is nothing to
prevent another political system being more advantageous for certain [cities]"
(1296b(136)).
Polity is a political system based on the "golden mean" (see e.g., NE 1106a-
1109b(65-75)), Aristotle's famous principle telling us always to avoid extremes; in
this case it tells us that "the middling sort of life is best" for both the city and the
individual (AP 1295a(133)). In other words, polity is a political system where the
"middle class", as we would now call it, forms a majority of people who have the
power and authority to rule in a way that mixes elements of the other three
republican systems. The mixture Aristotle had in mind involves a combination of
democracy and oligarchy (the two extremes) in such a way that their extreme
elements will cancel each other out: a polity requires "a mixture of ... the well off
and the poor" (1293b-1294b(129-132)). But it might also mix elements of
aristocracy and oligarchy, as when a polity requires "a law distributing offices on
the basis of merit [as in aristocracy] to those who are well off [as in oligarchy]"
(1288a(116)). When we read Aristotle saying that the best sort of oligarchy "is
very close to so-called polity" (1320b(190)), we must assume this good oligarchy
is actually an aristocracy. For aristocracy and polity are the good "means"
between the bad "extremes" of oligarchy and democracy.
With this in mind, we can now map the relations between the four
republican (non-monarchical) political systems, by using either a simple flow
chart (as in Figure IX.1a), or a 2LAR cross (as in Figure IX.1b) based on the
following two underlying questions: (1) Are there only a few rulers? and (2) Is the
system good (i.e., "correct")?
(a) As a Flow Chart (b) Mapped onto the Cross
These maps help us see why Aristotle sometimes virtually equated polity with
aristocracy (e.g., AP 1286b(112)): these systems, as the "means", are good for
most cities, while democracy and oligarchy, as the "extremes", are bad.
Kingship accords with aristocracy, while tyranny is composed of the ultimate sort
of oligarchy and of democracy-hence it is composed of the two bad political
systems and involves the deviations and errors of both of them....
.... Having wealth as its end comes from oligarchy ..., as does its distrust of the
multitude.... From democracy comes their war on the notables ... (1310b-
1311a(168-169))
If we now add the two forms of monarchy to the four forms of republican
political system, we can put all six systems together in the form of a circular flow
chart, enabling us to see the entire framework at a single glance.
ests of his subjects in mind. Since he has absolute power and authority over all the
people, no one will be able to prevent the king from putting his good will into
practice. Even though an aristocracy consists of the "best" men, it is not as good
as kingship, because it is more likely that a few bad men will infiltrate the
aristocracy and corrupt the intentions of the otherwise good rulers. And when all
property owners are allowed to influence the way laws are formed and rights are
distributed among the citizens, such corruption becomes even more likely.
Aristotle compared the relationship between the citizen and the city in these
three good political systems to three types of family relationships. In kingship the
king is like a father and the citizen is like a son. In aristocracy the ruling class is
like a husband and the other citizens are like a wife. And in timocracy (or polity)
the relationship between property owners is like that between siblings. But just as
family relationships are not always harmonious, each of these political systems
can be perverted, thus giving rise to tyranny, oligarchy, and democracy,
respectively.
As we have seen, kingship is the most risky option, because "the worst is
that which is the opposite to the best." When choosing a political system, we must
therefore keep in mind that when we aim at a particular system, we might end up
with its opposite instead. This is why, as we have seen, Aristotle elsewhere
defended polity (i.e., timocracy) as the safest option: even if it slips into
democracy, the negative effect on the average citizen is kept to a minimum, since
democracy is "the least bad" of the three bad political systems. In a "majority
rules" system the will of the majority is likely to be adversely influenced by the
selfish motives of the many bad people who live in any society, though in some
cases this will be balanced by the good motives of the virtuous people. In the next
lecture I shall suggest a rather surprising way of breaking through the boundary of
politics as defined by Aristotle's system. We shall then conclude Part Three by
considering what type of political system is wisest for modern western societies as
we enter the third millennium.
With this in mind, let's examine more closely how Aristotle's three pairs of
political systems differ in the level of freedom they offer to their citizens. It is
often said that there is no such thing as unlimited freedom: indeed, freedom is
normally defined by reference to some limitations, such as the self-imposed
limitations of loyalty to an authority, or obedience to laws. So the question here is,
how does each type of political system set up a boundary defining the citizen's
freedom? A king requires a high level of loyalty from his subjects, to the extent
that they cannot properly be called "citizens" at all; but in return a good king gives
his subjects a high level of freedom. Their daily lives need not be encumbered by
excessive laws as long as they remain loyal to the king. The ruling class in an
aristocracy requires a more moderate level of respect and loyalty, but offers in
return only a moderate level of freedom. More laws are needed to keep the lower
classes under control, and these laws restrict the freedom of all citizens. Finally, in
a polity (or timocracy), and even more so in a democracy, the level of freedom for
the citizens is actually at a comparatively low level-despite the common belief to
the contrary. Why? Because in these systems there is little or no need for the
citizen to be loyal or respectful to fellow citizens; so instead, a complex network
of laws must be instituted in hopes of preventing the stronger citizens from
mistreating the weaker ones.
In a polity or a democracy the laws take away freedoms and replace them
with rights. Aristotle's framework of political systems clearly reveals that such a
sacrifice of freedom is the price that must be paid by those who wish to minimize
the risk of tyranny. For a system boasting a higher level of freedom can quickly
change into its opposite, offering little or no freedom to the citizens, but
promoting injustice and oppression of a type that is unlikely to occur in a
democracy. (This inverse relationship between freedom and risk is a key
component of the table given in Figure IX.6, summarizing the Aristotle's six basic
types of political system, plus the two new extremes we will examine today.) As
we shall see in Lecture 27, Aristotle's terminology is now somewhat outdated.
Nevertheless, by providing a clear framework for understanding how political
systems operate (whatever we call them!), he has demonstrated how loyalty to
those in power forms the boundary that enables political systems to make freedom
possible for their citizens.
There are numerous other models for utopian societies; but today I shall
focus special attention on one alternative to communism that is rarely
acknowledged as a viable political system, even by those who are supposed to
believe in it. This is the vision of a utopia quite different from Marx's communist
state or Nietzsche's Superman; for it is a vision of the purpose of the earth as
determined and controlled not by people breaking through the alienating limits of
a life-denying outlook, but by God breaking through the hardened shell of human
hearts. Most religious people believe not only that God exists and that we can
somehow communicate with God, but also that God has a plan for this world-a
plan whose ultimate fulfillment cannot be thwarted by any counter-efforts on the
part of humanity. Some religious people believe this plan is confined to a
"spiritual" realm, and that in the "material" realm of (for example) economics and
politics, human systems can function quite apart from this divine plan. However,
the deepest (and most philosophically-minded) religious thinkers have always
affirmed that such an artificial distinction is illegitimate. If there is a God with a
plan, then this plan relates just as closely to the political activities of entire
societies as it does to the personal activities of any individual within a given
society.
The best name for the idea that God's rule applies not only to the operation
of divine power in human hearts, but also to its operation in the courtroom and the
market-place, is "theocracy" (with theos meaning "God" and kratos meaning
"power"). Unfortunately, this term has often been used in the past to refer to a
deceptively similar idea that is actually quite opposed to theocracy in its pure
form. Traditionally a political system has been called a "theocracy" if a religious
group (such as a church) regards itself as God's mouthpiece on earth, so that
whatever policies the leaders formulate must be accepted by the people as direct
commands from God. In order to distinguish this traditional usage from what I
believe to be the proper meaning of "theocracy", I have coined the term
"ecclesiocracy" to refer to any political system where the power is wielded by the
leader(s) of an "assembly" (ekklesia) of religious people. Typical examples of
ecclesiocracy would be the nation of Israel during the period following Ezra and
Nehemiah (i.e., after returning from Babylonian exile), most of southern Europe
during the time of the Holy Roman Empire, and the city of Geneva during the
latter part of John Calvin's life.
Figure IX.4:
God's Transvalua-
tion of Values
The fact that theocracy is described most often in the Bible in terms of a
kingdom suggests it is most properly viewed as a type of monarchical political
system, rather than a republican one. Indeed, if we consider theocracy and its
perversion, ecclesiocracy, together with Aristotle's two forms of monarchical
political system, kingship and tyranny, we can depict their relationship as a
perfect 2LAR, arising out of the two questions: (1) Is the system a religious one?
and (2) Is the system good (or "correct")? Just as theocracy is a religious form of
kingship (regarding God as the king), ecclesiocracy is a religious form of tyranny.
The same two maps used in Figure IX.1 to describe the relations between the four
republican political systems can therefore be used to map the relations between
the four monarchical political systems:
By putting the 2LAR cross here in Figure IX.5b together with its republican
correlate in Figure IX.1b, we can now construct a perfect 3LAR. The three
questions that give rise to the complete set of eight possible political systems are:
(1) Is the system monarchical? (2) Is the system either religious or ruled by a few
people? (3) Is the system good (or "correct")? These eight systems could be
mapped onto a double cross (i.e., a pair of concentric crosses, with one rotated at
a 45˚ angle from the other). But instead of drawing such a complex figure here, I
have provided a more detailed summary of the relationships between the eight
systems in the table given in Figure IX.6. This table lists the eight types of
political system from the best to the worst, together with the 3LAR component
corresponding to each. The second column provides a simple description of how
the name for each system is derived from some key Greek word referring to its
source of political power. The third and fourth columns compare the levels of
risk, freedom, and rights provided by each system. And the fifth column
summarizes and expands
Figure IX.6: Eight Basic Types of Political System
If we now take a step back and look at the variety of solutions we have
considered to the problem of finding the best political system, we might easily
become discouraged. Indeed, the same could be said for most of the other topics
we have discussed, especially here in Part Three. Without a doubt, the theme I
have come across most frequently in reading students' insight papers has been the
idea that philosophical questions have "no definite answers"; and this is
sometimes used as evidence for the view that the realities such questions refer to
are either nonexistent or irrelevant to real life. However, I hope I have
demonstrated by now that both of these views are incorrect. Far from finding no
definite answers to the questions we have been considering, we have usually
found many definite answers! For good philosophers seek definite answers, just as
much as natural scientists do; the problem, of course, is that philosophers are
unable to attain the level of agreement reached by natural scientists, because
philosophical questions are concerned with ideas, rather than empirical objects. In
other words, the problem raised by the experience of coming face to face with a
reality we are necessarily ignorant of is usually not the problem of having nothing
to say about it; on the contrary, the problem is that we have many, apparently
conflicting things to say about it. The task of the philosopher, therefore, is to seek
to fit each part of the puzzle together in such a way that the true aspects of each
answer can be recognized for what they are. Philosophers who regard the love of
wisdom as an essential part of their task will never be satisfied with a single,
supposedly all-encompassing answer; yet this is not because they doubt such an
answer exists, but because they have seen a glimpse of its awesome reality!
The alternative to loving wisdom "on the boundary" between our
knowledge and our recognized ignorance is to single out a single idea or set of
ideas and raise it to the level of absolute truth. When this happens, those who
claim to possess this "truth" typically regard it as their duty to share this gospel
(the "good news" that absolute truth can be knowable!) with others who remain in
the dark. Unfortunately, this goal is all too often taken to the extreme of forcing
others to "agree" with the single definite answer that is being taken as absolutely
true. As a result, a set of philosophical ideas that may have a wealth of insight to
offer us is transformed into a political ideology, the very antithesis of good
philosophy. An ideology, as I am using the term, is any set of ideas-often very
insightful ones when viewed objectively, outside their political (mis)application-
that is presented in such a way that the "believers" regard themselves as having a
monopoly on the truth. That is, when a person denies at the outset the very
possibility of other legitimate perspectives, an ideology is sure to be at work. An
ideology is a well-developed system of thought that is not only treated as a myth
by those who "live in" it, but is forced on those who do not wish to accept the
myth as it stands.
Every action is right which in itself, or in the maxim on which it proceeds, is such
that it can coexist along with the freedom of the will of each and all in action,
according to a universal law. (SR 45)
That is, an external act (as governed by the domain of politics) can be right only if
it can coexist with the free (right) acts of all other individuals. This principle is
not only the basis for a Kantian theory of rights, but also lies at the foundation of
theocracy! Unfortunately, Kant's understanding of human rights is often taken out
of its proper context and used to make rights-based democracy into a political
ideology.
First: each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive basic liberty
compatible with a similar liberty for others.
Second: social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are
both (a) reasonably expected to be to everyone's advantage, and (b) attached to
positions and offices open to all. (TJ 60)
These principles guarantee equal rights and equal opportunity, respectively, to all
citizens. Governments should use the first principle as a guide for assigning a
basic set of rights, such as "life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness" (as in the
U.S. Bill of Rights), to all persons, regardless of their race, religion, sex, etc.
Rawls' own examples of such rights include the right to vote, to own property, to
speak freely, etc. The second principle likewise requires governments to insure
that positions such as political offices and high paying jobs (or any paid employ‐
ment, for that matter) are open to all persons without discrimination that is
unrelated to their suitability for the position. The second principle is an attempt to
preserve a sense of justice in spite of economic and social inequalities by defining
"injustice" as inequalities that are not to everyone's mutual benefit.
The way forward from democracy, if we take into consideration this wider
context of Kant's political vision, is to begin doing away with the common
assumption that morality can be legislated. The more democracies can move
toward anarchy (i.e., fewer laws, and eventually no laws), the better off we will
be. For one thing, this will give people the opportunity to be genuinely moral,
rather than just "politically correct". In the current situation in most western
countries, the majority of people don't care much about being moral because they
have come to believe that the government legislates morality; this leads to the
mythical belief that, as long as I am a "law abiding citizen", I am morally good.
But as Kant's arguments demonstrate, legal (external) goodness does not
necessarily coincide with moral (internal) goodness. Ironically, legal systems that
try to enforce so-called "moral" laws end up taking away the potential
praiseworthiness of the citizens' good actions.
Has the human race developed to the stage where all outward political
forms can simply vanish in the near future? Obviously not! That this ought to be
our ultimate goal is the grain of truth in Marxist ideology. But to attempt to
implement such policies in the short term would not be a step forward, but a grave
setback to humanity's political development-as the twentieth century's experiment
with Marxism so poignantly illustrated. Instead of trying to force the goal ("peace
on earth") through ideological coercion, our aim should be to seek to implement
political structures that have an in-built self-negating form-i.e., structures that
discourage by their very nature anyone who would seek to raise them to the status
of ideology. The more this happens, the more human beings will learn to trust
their own inner principles above the feeble attempts of politics to determine right
and wrong by external means. Perhaps the single most important lesson we can
learn from our study of wisdom here in Part Three is that, as we live in waiting for
the day when human beings can live in peace without outward political structures,
we must welcome differences of opinion rather than resisting them. The more we
can incorporate the idea that "opposition is true friendship" into our understanding
of political reality, the closer we will come to bringing the entire human race to a
deep awareness of wisdom on the boundary.
QUESTIONS FOR FURTHER THOUGHT/DIALOGUE
1. A. What is power?
RECOMMENDED READINGS
1. Aristotle, The Politics, Book 4, Ch. 2 (AP 1289a-b).
4. Antoine de Saint-Exupéry, The Little Prince, tr. Katherine Woods (New York:
Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1943).
6. Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Manifesto of the Communist Party, tr. Samuel
Moore (Moscow: Progress Press, 1952[1888]).
7. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, ?1, "Two Principles of Justice" (TJ 60-65).
8. Stephen Palmquist, "'The Kingdom of God is at Hand!' (Did Kant really say
that?)", History of Philosophy Quarterly 11 (1994), pp.421-437.
During the first three parts of this course we have encountered a variety of
different philosophical theories, proposed by philosophers attempting to solve a
diversity of problems. This very diversity, compounded by the variety of
approaches we have at our disposal, is one of the most serious threats to the health
of the tree of philosophy. For if nothing can unify the diversity that naturally
arises out of our human experience and out of our reflection upon it, then we are
in danger of meeting the same fate as Nietzsche. As we saw in Lecture 23,
Nietzsche uprooted the tree of philosophy in an attempt to awaken modern man
from our self-satisfied slumber under the shade of Socrates' philosophical tree.
But just as the first sign of impending death in an uprooted plant is that its leaves
go limp, so also Nietzsche's attempt to philosophize without grounding his
reasoning in an ultimate reality ended when his own experience went limp in the
unceasing noise of insanity.
The person whose quest for wisdom ends in insanity has completely lost touch
with the reality that makes the quest worthwhile. Fortunately, this tragic fate is not
inevitable, provided we learn to respond to the diversity of thought and life by
replacing the noise generated by the virtually endless choices at our disposal with
a silence that can lend unity and purpose to our fragmented existence. For this
reason, I shall begin this final part of our course by asking you to suggest some
answers to the question, "What is silence?"
As you think about this question, let me remind you that the part of the tree of
philosophy that best represents our need for a unifying principle in our thinking
and a unifying power in our lives is the leaves. For when we look at a tree with no
leaves, the distinction between its branches stands out clearly; yet when the same
tree has a full set of leaves, the branches actually appear to be connected, as if the
leaves have resolved the tension between the branches by holding them together
in a higher unity. The leaves of a tree, more than any other part, give us the
impression that the tree is a unit: especially when viewing a tree from a distance,
the leaves lose their distinctness and blur into each other. Moreover, a tree is often
more difficult to distinguish from other types of tree if it has no leaves. For
botanists normally use a tree's leaf to identify and classify it in relation to other
types of tree.
This analogy suggests one of the most important principles we will come across
here in Part Four: just as a tree's leaves give the tree both its distinctiveness and its
unity, so also the part of the tree of philosophy we shall now begin examining
operates according to the principle of "unity in diversity". Since
"unity" and "diversity" are opposites, this principle clearly requires us to think in
terms of synthetic logic if we are to make any sense out of it. But before we begin
looking at some examples of how this principle works, does anyone have any
ideas about how we can define silence?
I was hoping someone would give this kind of answer, because it gives me the
opportunity to clarify the question I am really asking. Your answer is correct as
far as it goes; but it defines silence in a merely superficial way. On the surface,
silence is indeed just the absence of sound. Thus, for example, if several of you
start talking while I am trying to give today's lecture, I might say "Silence
please!"; this would mean something like "Please stop making those sounds!"
However, the word "silence" normally suggests much more than this. For aren't
there some kinds of sound that do not disturb our silence? And what about the
popular song that talks about the "Sound of Silence"? If silence is the absence of
sound, then how could silence itself have a sound? In any case, does anyone have
a suggestion as to how we could go a little deeper into the meaning of silence?
What is silence?
Student X. "It's quite subjective. What is silence for me might be noise for you."
That depends on what you mean by "subjective". So let's press your idea a bit
deeper. When you say silence is "subjective", does this mean merely that different
people experience silence in different ways (a rather obvious point), or does it also
tell us something about where silence is actually located? In other words, what
makes the difference between a person who can experience silence in a certain
situation and another person who cannot?
Student X. "It must be something inside the person. Yes, I think that's what I
meant by 'subjective'! Real silence is inner silence."
Good! This is precisely the point of my original question: What is inner silence?
What can we do to cultivate within ourselves a disposition that enables us to
experience silence when other people are being disturbed by the sounds all around
us? How can what is noise to other people become like music to our ears?Is this
just a basic difference between different people's personalities, or is there anything
we can do to improve our capacity for hearing the sound of silence?
Student Y. "I find that getting away from everyone and being alone for
awhile often gives me an inner peace that helps me cope with the disturbances
that come from my relationships with other people."
The kind of experience you are referring to is sometimes called "solitude". I too
enjoy being by myself sometimes; and I agree that it can foster the development
of a sense of inner silence. But the strange thing about solitude is that some
people don't like it; they are too afraid of becoming lonely. What's the difference,
then, between "being alone" and "being lonely"?
Student Z. "Some people can be alone for long periods of time without
feeling lonely at all; others will feel lonely even when they are with a group of
friends."
People who spend much of their time in solitude and silence are sometimes
called "contemplatives". Contemplatives in virtually every major religious
tradition have worked hard to explain what silence and solitude are and how we
can go about nurturing the potential for such experiences. In ancient China, Lao
Tzu is a good example of such a contemplative. His poetic account of how to
follow the "Tao" that "cannot be expressed" is full of practical advice-though
often couched in terms of synthetic logic-as to how we can live a life of humility,
solitude, and silence, even amidst the apparent busyness of everyday life. The
Buddha would, of course, be another good example. And numerous others could
be cited from Hinduism, Islam, and various other religions.
The Jewish and Christian religious traditions also have a long line of such
contemplatives. One of the most influential Christian contemplatives in the
twentieth century was Thomas Merton, whose writings inspired many to deepen
their own inner experiences. An extended quote from his little book, Thoughts in
Solitude, can help us understand how solitude and silence work together in our
experience of the reality religious people call "God":
Some people live for God, some people live with God, some live in God.
Those who live for God, live with other people and live in the activities of
Those who live in God do not live with other men or in themselves still less in
what they do, for He does all things in them.
Sitting under this tree I can live for God, or with Him, or in Him....
Yet it is not hard to commune with other men and with Him, as long as we find
them in Him.
Solitary life-essentially the most simple. Common life prepares for it in so far as
we find God in the simplicity of common life-then seek Him more and find Him
better in the greater simplicity of solitude.
But if our community life is intensely complicated-(through our own fault)-we are
likely to become even more complicated in solitude.
Do not flee to solitude from the community. Find God first in the community,
then He will lead you to solitude.
A man cannot understand the true value of silence unless he has a real respect for
the validity of language: for the reality which is expressible in language is found,
face to face and without any medium, in silence. Nor would we find this reality in
itself, that is to say in its own silence, unless we were first brought there by
language.
Those who emphasize such contemplative control over our inner disposition are
sometimes called "mystics". Mystics are those who experience a power that
unifies the diversity of their everyday experiences, and in response, change their
way of life accordingly. For the mystic, silence is not just a convenient tool used
to reduce the level of stress in a busy life, or even to develop the skill of having
insights; rather, in its deepest sense it is a way of life. Thus, the mystic "vision"
(SF 9) sees all of life as a "a supreme gift for which the most appropriate posture
is the giving of thanks.... To acknowledge life as a supreme gift is to sense that the
underlying mystery ... is nevertheless benevolent. To receive it as a mystery is to
respect the beauty of its pathos." We have no right to possess a gift, but must
patiently wait for it to be given, and then accept or reject it when and as it comes.
The disciplines of a mystical way of life are intended to prepare us to receive the
mysterious gifts of silence and solitude when they do come.
This mystical vision can also help us understand the nature of insights. We can
prepare ourselves to receive insights; but cannot control exactly when or how
they will come to us. All we can do is sit, as it were, under the tree, waiting for
the fruit to drop into our open hands, just like the sage pictured on the cover of
this book. The control that comes from spiritual discipline is not control over the
mysterious reality that gives insights; rather, it is control over our own hands (and
minds), which are usually too busy (filled with "noise") to receive what is being
offered. The same point is made in The Giving Tree: because the boy's hands are
always too full of his own selfish interests, he is unable to receive the love and
happiness the tree offers him. This is why I have asked you to spend some time
quietly meditating before you begin the process of actually writing your insight
papers. During these times of silence we prepare our minds (as well as our hearts)
for receiving insights. The most important insight might not come during the time
of silence; but without that time of preparation, our attention would be too
cluttered with other concerns to receive any real insights.
Once an insight "comes" to us, we should not, of course, merely let it sit there
collecting dust. Rather, the proper response, as suggested in Lecture 18, is to
criticize it. Such criticism does not require us to deny the validity of the original
insight (though such a denial might be appropriate sometimes), but should always
help us separate what can be known to be true from what is false or unknowable.
A good philosopher always tries to balance the tasks of insight and criticism, so
that the two work together: when new insights break through into old ways of
thinking, we should not merely reject the old ways, but make an effort to
synthesize the old and the new to form a consistent whole. The best insight papers
are always those utilizing both of these complementary activities, as suggested by
the map introduced in Figure VI.5.
Comparing that map with those given in Figures VIII.4 and IX.4, we find
there are, in fact, two quite distinct types of philosophical "breakthrough". The
first is the one I have described above: a mystery manifests itself through some
insight (see Figure X.1a). But the mysterious origin of the insight is only fully
apparent when we try to comprehend it with
Words like "mystery" and "paradox" can give the impression that the insights
arising out of such breakthroughs are unclear. This is a complaint I have heard
on a number of occasions from beginning philosophy students. Although it is, of
course, entirely possible that my explanation of an idea is unclear, or that a given
student's understanding of a clear explanation might be clouded in various ways,
we should beware of thinking philosophical ideas themselves are necessarily
unclear. On the contrary, once we recognize the difference between two kinds of
clarity, we shall see that philosophical ideas are the clearest of all ideas!
Consider the difference between a cloudy day and a sunny day. On a cloudy day
the sunlight is blocked, so the things we look at outside are not as distinct as they
are on a sunny day. Even if you've never noticed that things look "duller" on a
cloudy day, I'm sure you've noticed that the shadows of things (if any) are not
very clearly visible, whereas they become crisp and sharp when the sun comes
out. This is one type of clarity. But what about our ability to look at the sun itself?
On a clear day the sun is difficult to look at-indeed, if we look at it for very long
we could go blind! However, on a cloudy day we can look in the direction of the
sun for a long time without difficulty. This second type of clarity is different from
the first, because the clearer it is, the harder it is for us to see it! In other words,
on a clear day, the source of light cannot be looked at, because it is too clear; yet
the things it illuminates can be seen more clearly.
Philosophical clarity is often not like the things the sun enables us to see, but like
the sun itself. For our deepest and most profound insights are the ones that appear
to be the most clear, and whose certainty we are therefore the least likely to doubt.
Yet if asked to express such insights in words, we are often unable to do so
without great difficulty. For it is actually easier to describe a deep insight when it
is not very clear in our mind. The true test of the clarity of a deep insight,
therefore, is not how well we can express the insight itself, but how well we can
use that insight to illuminate other aspects of our thought and experience. Take as
an example the idea that the "recognition of ignorance" is the starting-point of all
philosophy. My hope is that at some point during the first part of this course you
were suddenly struck with the truth of this idea: whereas you probably did not
understand it before taking this course, now (assuming it has become an insight
for you) you are certain it can illuminate your understanding of what philosophy
is. Yet if someone asks you at this point to explain just how it is possible for you
to recognize your ignorance, you will probably remain speechless. On the one
hand, you can see clearly the results of the insight; yet on the other hand, you are
unable to state exactly what it is that enables you to have this gift of vision. My
point here is that this is typical of philosophical ideas in general: they are so clear
that their brightness often makes them unbearable to look at directly.
29. Finality and the Paradox of Beauty
Let me begin today by sharing a memorable experience I had when I was living in
England. Shortly before dawn one crisp winter morning my young daughter woke
up crying. It was my turn to do "night duty", so I dragged myself out of bed and
did my best to comfort her. Before too long she was quiet again, and a bit later
she was fast asleep. Usually on such occasions I was so tired that I had no trouble
falling asleep again once my task was finished. This time, however, I left the
room feeling wide awake. Even though it was still quite dark, I decided to sit in
the living room instead of going back to bed. As I looked out the window of our
cozy flat, I could see that the dark sky was beginning to lighten ever so slightly in
the east. Everything was quiet, inside and out. Three stories below, just on the
other side of the tree whose branches nearly touched the window of our flat, the
main road into the city center had not yet begun to fill up with its daily traffic of
noisy commuters. The beauty of the scene which then unfolded before my eyes
was truly unforgettable. Beyond the leafless branches and over the housetops
across the street emerged a deep purple glow gradually pushing the blackness to
its home in the west. Before long the purples faded into
deep red, and then brightened to a pastel orange. When the whole sky was ablaze
in a strange mixture of reds, oranges, and yellows, a band of bright blue began to
rise up as if from the depths of the sea. It was breathtaking. I could hardly move,
much less think or speak.
As I sat there in silence, on the boundary line between nighttime and daytime,
time itself seemed to stand still amidst the changeless changes unfolding before
me. Looking back, I would guess the transformation I beheld took an hour or
more, though it might have been less than fifteen minutes for all I know. When I
finally came to my senses, I decided I should try to capture this "moment" on film
before it was too late. That way perhaps those who were now sleeping might later
be able to share in the awesome scene I was witnessing. A camera can be an
effective tool for artists, if it is used to distort a natural scene in such a way as to
reveal an underlying beauty that would remain hidden to the naked eye. However,
when we use the same machine in hopes of copying the beauty of a natural scene
that is already manifested before our eyes, the result is often the very antithesis of
artistic beauty. Unfortunately, the photo I took that morning probably illustrates
the latter principle better than the former. (A mere copy of nature is bad enough,
but a copy of the copy is even worse. Nevertheless, I have reproduced my
photograph in black and white on the previous page, in hopes of sparking the
reader's imagination to fill in the missing colors.)
Let's just imagine this photo is good enough to put you in touch with the beauty of
the boundary-experience I had that morning. Why is it that we judge such a scene
to be beautiful? What does the word "beauty" mean when we use it in a
proposition such as "That sunrise is beautiful"? How are judgments of beauty
related to other kinds of judgment? Answering such questions is the task of the
area of philosophy called "aesthetics" (from the Greek word, aisthetikos, meaning
"sense perception"). The leaves of experience that grow on this branch of the
philosophical tree are so healthy, and so familiar to us all, that such questions are
better dealt with in terms of ontology (the study of "being") than in terms of
science. In other words, although we will never know enough to construct a
science of beauty, we can experience enough to construct an ontology of beauty.
And that is, in fact, what many philosophers have done when dealing with
questions of aesthetics.
The aesthetic question asked most frequently in students' insight papers goes
something like this: Is there an objective standard of beauty? or Is there a fixed
set of guidelines we can use to test whether such a judgment is right or wrong?
Students nearly always answer these questions in the negative. But philosophers-
especially good philosophers-are not so quick to assume that aesthetic judgments
are based on nothing more than mere personal opinions. Any attempt to construct
an ontology of beauty would assume that beauty is something, and would seek
first and foremost to discover the nature of that hidden essence. So let's look today
at one example of how philosophers answer such questions.
Because the first two powers adopt the opposite standpoints of theory and
practice, Kant claimed a third standpoint is needed to form a bridge between these
two. This third standpoint must be both free (as in our moral judgments) and yet
based on a sensible object (as in our cognitive judgments). In its most general
sense, this "third thing" in Kant's System always consists of experience itself; but
in the third Critique his particular focus is on specific types of judgments, so I call
this third, mediating standpoint the "judicial". The judicial standpoint focuses on
the judgments we make about the kinds of experience we cannot interpret
straightforwardly in terms of scientific knowledge or moral practice-in particular,
the judgments that arise out of our power to feel "pleasure and pain". Thus, if we
think of Kant's first two Critiques as viewing experience from the perspectives of
the head and belly, respectively, then we can think of the third Critique as viewing
experience from the perspective of the heart, the physical organ ordinary
associated with our feelings. Like the moral judgments that correspond to the
belly (see Lecture 22), so also aesthetic judgments, according to Kant, are always
noncognitive-i.e., they do not produce knowledge, the way logical (i.e.,
theoretical) judgments do (see e.g., CJ 228). In a logical judgment our thinking
controls our imagination to expose truth, whereas in an aesthetic judgment our
imagination controls our thinking to reveal beauty. This account of the
relationship between Kant's three systems can now be used to construct a more
detailed synthesis of Figures II.8 and III.4:
Figure X.2:
In his attempt to explain what is unique about our judgments of beauty, what
makes them different from all other types of judgments we make, Kant
distinguished between four "moments" (or essential elements) of any such
judgment of taste. These correspond, as usual, to the pattern determined by his
special set of four categories. But because beauty itself is most like the category
of quality, he began his ontology of beauty with a description of the "moment of
quality" (CJ 203); it stipulates that the delight experienced in an object judged to
be beautiful must be disinterested. An "interest" is any "delight which we connect
with the representation of the real existence of an object" (204). The judgments
that determine "the agreeable and the good" are both "invariably coupled with an
interest in the object" (209): the former depends on the existence of something
"the senses find pleasing in sensation" (205), and the latter on the existence of
something "reason recommends ... by its mere concept" (207). By contrast, a
judgment of beauty, being a pure judgment of taste, "relies on no interest" (205n):
a person making such a judgment ought to have "complete indifference"
concerning "the real existence of the thing" (205). Otherwise, Kant warned, our
judgments of taste will be "biased" in favor of our own interest, instead of
assessing whether or not our feeling truly merits the ascription of "beauty" to the
object.
An illustration should help clarify this first, and perhaps most important, of Kant's
points. Let's imagine three possible situations when a person might refer to the
sun's "beauty". First, imagine the weather was so fine this morning that you
decided to skip your classes and go to the beach for the day. In that case, you
might be laying on the sand right now with your closest friend, soaking up the
warm sun. If you turned to your friend and said "The sun feels beautiful right
now", then, according to Kant, you would be misusing the word "beautiful". Your
feeling of pleasure would be a direct result of your interest in the existence of the
sun's existence, aroused by your sensation of its warmth on your body. So it
would be better to say the sun feels "agreeable" (or "nice") in such a situation. For
the second scenario, imagine you are now walking along the road with your
geography teacher, talking about the various forms of life on earth. Suddenly you
become aware of the sun shining brightly all around you, so you exclaim, "Isn't
the sun beautiful, the way it sustains life on earth?" This too would be a misuse of
"beautiful". For once again, your feeling of pleasure would be a direct result of
your interest in the sun's existence, though this time your interest would be
aroused by your intellectual grasp of the sun's goodness. The third scenario could
be the one I described at the beginning of today's lecture. Only if, as I sat there
gazing at the sunrise, the pleasure welling up in me had nothing to do with the
sun's objective existence, only if my judgment was based not on my agreeable
sensations (I was actually quite cold at the time!) nor on my appreciation of the
sun's usefulness (I was too tired to think so clearly!), was I justified in exclaiming:
"This sunrise is beautiful!" But if my judgment was not based on my own interest
in the object, what was it based on? Kant answered this question in his discussion
of the other three essential characteristics of any judgment of beauty.
Although a judgment of beauty is always subjective, and thus has "no bearing
upon the Object" (CJ 215), Kant argued that the "quantity" of such a judgment
requires that some object "pleases universally" (219). The second characteristic is
therefore a special kind of subjective universality. By contrast, judgments of the
agreeable express a delight that is subjective but not universal, and judgments of
the good express a delight that is universal but objective. The criterion of
subjective universality means that a person must regard delight in the object
as resting on what he may also presuppose in every other person; and therefore he
must believe that he has reason for demanding a similar delight from everyone.
Accordingly, he will speak of the beautiful as if beauty were a quality of the
object and the judgment logical [even though it is not] ... (211).
Unlike a truly logical judgment, a judgment of taste "does not postulate the
agreement of every one ...; it only imputes this agreement to everyone" (216). We
assume everyone will agree that the sun is good because it sustains life, but we do
not assume everyone will agree that sunbathing is an agreeable experience. These
two kinds of judgment are quite straightforward. But when we judge something to
be beautiful, we feel everyone ought to make the same judgment if placed in the
same position: for we adopt the "idea" that our judgment extends "to all subjects,
as unreservedly as it would if it were an objective judgement" (285), even though
we may know very well that, as a matter of fact, everyone does not agree.
The third characteristic of all judgments of beauty deals with the relation of
"ends" (CJ 219): the object of such judgments must exhibit "the form of finality
[i.e., purposiveness] ... apart from the representation of an end [i.e., purpose]"
(236). This paradox requires that, in judging an object to be beautiful, we regard it
as existing for a reason, because we perceive an inner purposiveness; yet no
external purpose can be found. This is no illusion, according to Kant, but part of
what it means for something to be called beautiful: judging something to be
beautiful means judging that it points to itself rather than to some agreeable sensa‐
tion or good state of affairs outside of the object. Since the "determining ground"
of such a judgment "is simply finality of form" (223), our delight in something
beautiful is based solely on the conviction that "the state of the representation
itself" is intrinsically worth preserving (222). By contrast, our delight in
experiencing something agreeable or good is determined by the external goal it
points to, such as the pleasant sensation of tasting well prepared food, or the
ability of food to satisfy our hunger. In other words, delight in the beautiful means
delight in something we do not wish to consume but to preserve, just as in the
case of the "timeless moment" I described at the beginning of this lecture.
The fourth and final characteristic, the "moment" of modality in any judgment of
beauty, is that the experience must produce "a necessary delight" (CJ 240). Kant
carefully distinguished between the "theoretical objective necessity" of empirical
knowledge, the "practical necessity" of moral action, and the
"exemplary" necessity of aesthetic judgment (236-237). An experience of delight
in a beautiful object can be regarded as a necessary example only when we
presuppose "the existence of a common sense" (i.e., a common way of sensing the
world), corresponding to the "common understanding" that enables us to agree on
cognitive judgments (238). (The latter, by the way, is closer to the traditional
notion of "common sense" than is the former.) All but the most extreme skeptics
assume this common sense to be "the necessary condition of the universal
communicability of our knowledge", so it can also serve as an "ideal norm" that
forms the basis for the necessity of our aesthetic judgments (239). Kant also
referred in a similar way to an internal "archetype of taste" that serves as "the
highest model" for aesthetic judgments, but cautioned that people vary widely in
their ability to access it; "each person must beget [this archetype] in his own
consciousness" (232), for it is a skill that must be acquired. What we do all have
access to, Kant believed, is "a universal voice" telling us "only the possibility of
an aesthetic judgment capable of being ... deemed valid for every one" (216).
Having now examined Kant's often paradoxical account of the four principles
essential to the ontological nature of our judgments of beauty, we can
summarize his theory with this map:
Note that the two characteristics mapped onto the horizontal line are both
expressed in terms of synthetic logic, while those on the vertical line both
conform to analytic logic.
Taken together, these four characteristics of all judgments of beauty suggest that
such judgments point not to some obvious purpose, but to a mystery hidden deep
within certain objects we experience: our aesthetic ideas "strain after something
lying out beyond the confines of experience" (CJ 314). In addition to
using the term "finality" (or purposiveness) to describe this mystery, Kant also
claimed that, ultimately, "the beautiful is the symbol of the morally good" (353).
By this he did not mean that the experience of beauty is in any way dependent
upon the experience of goodness, but only that, just as respect for the moral law
gives moral goodness a foothold in the will, so also the "analogy" between beauty
and morality can give morality a foothold in nature. In so doing, such experiences
serve to resolve the tension between our theoretical and practical standpoints (cf.
Figures VIII.2 and X.2).
Let's now take a step back from Kant's theory and ask: Do such basic
characteristics establish an objective standard of beauty? Yes and no! On the one
hand, they do demonstrate that we use the word "beauty" at precisely those times
when we are acting as if everyone else ought to agree. And this means judgments
of beauty require us to adopt the universal standpoint of "common sense"-or, as
we could also call it, the unifying standpoint, through which the diversity of our
ordinary experience is held together by a common, gut-level feeling. But on the
other hand, Kant fully recognized that this feeling is subjective, and that people
are therefore bound to disagree about what ought to be regarded as beautiful
(239). In such a case, he argued, if both parties are truly judging aesthetically,
then "both would ... be judging correctly" (231). This is possible, of course, only
if we interpret such experiences in terms of synthetic logic. So, although his
account of the four essential elements in any judgment of beauty cannot be said to
give us an objective standard, in the sense of a set of universal criteria that can be
externally forced upon all possible objects, it does give us a universal standard, in
the sense of a set of criteria that is internally applicable to all possible subjects
who hope to experience beauty. And this is no small achievement!
This means our ability to experience beauty depends not so much on the objective
characteristics of the objects we meet every day, as on whether we are able to
adopt this standpoint when the appropriate situations present themselves. In other
words, like all the unifying experiences we shall examine here in Part Four, an
experience of beauty is likely to "hit" us only when we are prepared internally to
receive the mystery of such a gift. It is therefore entirely possible that people
living near me on that bleak winter's morning in England might have woken up at
the same time as me, looked out the window, and noticed nothing beautiful. Had I
met them, I would have felt quite strongly that they ought to have
noticed the beauty of the sunrise, and would have noticed it, had they adequately
nurtured the "common sense" that gives us our taste for beauty; nevertheless, I
could have done nothing to force them to agree with my judgment.
Kant's ontology of beauty therefore suggests that the old saying "beauty is in the
eye of the beholder" has some measure of truth. However, this saying is grossly
misinterpreted if we associate it with a relativistic saying such as
"different strokes for different folks", and thereby take it to mean that "it doesn't
really matter what different people think about what is and isn't beautiful, because
beauty is different for everyone". By assuming that because beauty is not
scientific it must be a mere illusion, this all-too-common view strips beauty of the
paradox that makes it what it is. For, as Kant has shown us, the subjective
character of such judgments (i.e., the fact that they depend primarily on our own
eyes) does not imply that our experiences of beauty are all merely relative; on the
contrary, such experiences put us into contact with an absolute reality, a mystery
that our imagination glimpses but our thoughts cannot fully comprehend. Just
because beauty is not in my eye at one particular moment does not mean it is not
there, waiting to be seen and tasted, if only I am willing to feel its presence.
What is love?
Answering this question is, or at least ought to be, of interest to everyone, even
people who know nothing about philosophy. For each of us has experienced love
on numerous occasions in the past, though admittedly our awareness of love
varies greatly. Some people feel they have rarely experienced more than glimpses
of love here and there, while others feel they have to hold love back, lest it rush
forth like a raging flood and wash away the objects it is directed toward. Nearly
everyone agrees that love is an indispensable aspect of human life, and that
without love it would be difficult if not impossible to live a meaningful life.
Therefore, it is not surprising to find that love is usually one of the most
frequently discussed topics (along with truth, beauty, death, and the meaning of
life) in students' insight papers.
Where does this leave the philosopher? Is it hopeless to try to give a truly
philosophical account of love-that is, one that describes an underlying similarity
between all types of love, and a common factor in all acceptable definitions? In
one sense it is. For as we have seen on numerous occasions, some experiences can
never be adequately described, especially in terms of analytic logic alone; and in
such cases we actually discover that we can sometimes understand our experience
better in silence than we can in words. However, in another sense, the philosopher
is never satisfied with complete silence, but always holds out a hope that words
can somehow be used to express the inexpressible. This is the purpose of
symbolic language, as we shall see more fully in Lecture 31, and is made possible
by synthetic logic. Provided we do not expect to grasp love completely, as if we
could reduce it to a mere formula, but attempt only to learn what it means to be
grasped by love, I see no reason why we should not search for a philosophy of
love that enables us to see the diversity of human experiences as part of a unified
whole.
Many philosophers, from Plato and Aristotle right down to the present day, have,
in fact, developed theories of love. Since we have no time to examine the whole
history of the philosophy of love, let's take a closer look at the ideas of one fairly
recent philosopher, whose quest for love's meaning led him to some very
interesting conclusions. The person I am thinking of is Paul Tillich, whose idea of
faith as expressed in terms of symbols of ultimate concern will be examined in
Lecture 31. His insightful little book, called Love, Power, and Justice (1954),
devotes most of one chapter to the explanation of "The Ontology of Love". The
term "ontology" can be defined rather simply as "the study of being". However,
let us look briefly at the more in depth account of the meaning of this term that
comes at the beginning of Tillich's chapter on love.
Tillich's account begins by suggesting that the Greek words for "ontology" are
best translated as referring to "the 'rational word' [logos] which grasps 'being as
such' [on]" (LPJ 18). In order to grasp this "word", he paradoxically claims,
"ontology asks the simple and infinitely difficult question: What does it mean to
be? What are the structures [or "characteristics"] common to everything that ...
participates in being?" (19). Ontology recognizes the "manifoldness" of being, but
attempts to unify this diversity by describing "the texture of being itself" (20).
Everyone who has knowledge engages in ontology, because "knowing means
recognizing something as being." He distinguished ontology from metaphysics in
the following way:
... ontology is the foundation of metaphysics, but not metaphysics itself. Ontology
asks the question of being, i.e. of something that is present to everybody at every
moment.... Ontology is descriptive, not speculative. It tries to find out which the
basic structures of being are. And being is given to everybody who is and who
therefore participates in being-itself. Ontology, in this sense, is analytical. It
analyses the encountered reality, trying to find the structural elements which
enable a being to participate in being. (23)
Although Tillich never explicitly said so, this passage clearly implies that
ontology is both analytic and a posteriori (see Figure IV.4): like logic, ontology is
"analytic", yet unlike logic, it is "descriptive" (i.e., it focuses a posteriori on what
is rather than on what we think). Metaphysics, by contrast, is synthetic and a
priori (at least according to Kant): it asks questions about what is necessary
before we experience "what is", but it requires us to step outside of our analytical
concepts. Rather than saying ontology is the "foundation" of metaphysics, it
would therefore be more accurate to say metaphysics and ontology are two
diametrically opposed tasks that nevertheless depend on each other, just as the
opposites -- and ++ depend on each other, and just as do the roots and leaves of a
tree.
The passage where Tillich set out his ontological description of love is actually
quite brief. It begins with a description of the relationship between love and life
itself (LPJ 25): "Life is being in actuality and love is the moving power of life." In
other words, when a being ceases to be merely possible, and becomes actual, we
can say it is "alive"; and the very power that moves beings into life and through
life is called "love". This means being requires love in order to become "actual",
and through love we learn what life really is. Of course, this description is so
broad that it seems to include nearly everything! So Tillich narrowed his
description with an idea borrowed directly from Plato's Symposium:
Love is the drive towards the unity of the separated. Reunion presupposes sepa‐
ration of that which belongs essentially together.... [But] separation presupposes
an original unity.... It is impossible to unite that which is essentially separated....
Therefore love cannot be described as the union of the strange but as the reunion
of the estranged. Estrangement presupposes original oneness.
The basic meaning of this passage can be understood quite effectively by mapping
the key ideas onto the pair of 1LSR triangles shown in Figure V.7 (cf. Figure
III.7). The resulting map, given in Figure X.5, depicts how estrangement is a
necessary step in the process of love, the process whereby two "estranged"
opposites (+ and -) that were once held together in a mysterious, original unity
(0), are brought back together in a "reunion" (1). Almost any pair of opposites
could be used to exemplify
this process. But an obvious example occurs whenever a man (+) and a woman (-)
are in love. The two lovers, as they gaze into each other's eyes, want to be closer
and closer, until, if possible, they merge into one being (1). Whenever they are
together they feel as if they have returned to a long lost home (0); yet there
always seem to be obstacles keeping them ultimately estranged. An indispensable
point in Tillich's discussion, therefore, is that the reunion itself is not love, but is
the goal love drives toward. Love itself, the being of love, is the power of driving
toward reunion. This means it is a mistake to think of love as the goal; love is the
unifying power of a relationship, enabling two beings to drive toward a higher
goal.
Tillich warned his readers not to make the mistake of confusing this rather
abstract, ontological description of love's essential nature with the emotion we
often associate with love. Love as such can occur without being accompanied by
any emotion whatsoever. However, when emotion does accompany love, Tillich
argued, the ontology of love helps us explain why it is present. Since love is the
drive toward reunion, it is certainly possible to love someone without thinking
much about what the final state of reunion will be like. If this happens, then there
will be little or no emotion associated with love, for "love as an emotion is the
anticipation of the reunion" (LPJ 26). This means a person who, by contrast,
frequently imagines a future state of increased unity with another person will find
that a great deal of emotion accompanies the experience of driving toward that
reunion (i.e., of love).
Once this point is recognized, an interesting paradox arises when we consider
what happens when we experience the fulfillment of love: "Fulfilled love is, at the
same time, extreme happiness and the end of happiness. The separation is
overcome. But without the separation there is no love and no life" (LPJ 27).
Tillich's point here is that the very nature of our anticipation of a goal is such that
the moment of reaching that goal, the very moment of most intense satisfaction, is
at the same time the beginning of a feeling of emptiness at the prospects of no
longer having that goal to strive after. This enables us to understand why the
romantic emphasis on love as a feeling can be so misleading. Feeling is important,
of course, for it is aroused by our anticipation of reunion; and if we never
anticipate this goal, our love is less likely to develop toward its proper end. But if
love is not based more fundamentally on a commitment of the will, then when the
"end of happiness" arrives-as it inevitably does-we will be caught off guard, and
might even think our love has died, just because the old feelings are gone.
This point reveals a very practical insight as to how we ought to view marriage.
Lovers who view marriage as the final goal of their relationship are likely to be
quite shocked once they realize, usually soon after their wedding day, that
marriage is not all pleasant feelings: the person who was once viewed as the ideal
lover inevitably "changes" into an ordinary, imperfect human being. This is why
the typical Hollywood love story is so misleading: I'm sure you've all seen plenty
of films and/or read lots of novels where the man and woman fall in love with
each other, struggle to overcome numerous obstacles to the fulfillment of their
love, finally get married, and then ride off into the sunset at the end of the film, to
live "happily ever after". By the end of such stories most of us are wishing "if only
that could be me ...". But beware: the whole thing is an impossible dream, because
the point where the film ends is where life's real struggles are likely to begin!
The lesson this should teach us is to set high goals in love relationships
(indeed, perhaps even absolute goals), so that each small step along the way (each
"mini-reunion", so to speak) can bring its extreme happiness and at the same time
complete the happiness experienced in the process of driving toward that step,
without undermining the basis of the love relationship. In other words, there is
always room for any relationship to grow into a deeper level of love: we must
never expect to reach "true love", since true love is the process of reaching toward
an ultimate goal. The fulfillment of this goal is the end of love, and hence can
come only at (or after) the end of life. This is why, as we shall see in Week XII,
death is such an important topic in ontology. But in the meantime we must
recognize that our problems are not solved merely by understanding the essential
ontological nature of love; on the contrary, the process of understanding the being
of love is, like ontology itself, "a never-ending task" (LPJ 20).
This map shows how epithymia and philia are similar in that they both require the
loving subject and the loved object to be mutual participants in the love
relationship, while eros and agape both require the two parties to have unequal
roles; likewise, it shows how eros and epithymia are similar in being primarily
impersonal, while agape and philia are similar in being personal. The sense in
which "transpersonal" is a special type of impersonal love and "super-personal" is
a special type of personal love should become clear as we look more closely at
Tillich's account of how each of these types of love illustrates his definition of
love's essence.
The Greek word "epithymia" (meaning desire) is roughly equivalent, according to
Tillich (LPJ 28-30), to the Latin term "libido", as popularized by Freud (see DW
56-61). These terms refer to the basic instinctual desires that characterize all
animals, especially the sex drive. In itself (viewed apart from the other types of
love that often accompany it in human beings), epithymia is radically impersonal.
One's sexual urges, for example, could in principle be satisfied by virtually
anyone, regardless of their personality, just as hunger can be satisfied by any type
of food, regardless of how bad it might taste. Normally, the parties in such an
encounter desire mutually to fulfill each other's urges. In this way, epithymia gives
rise to sensual pleasure in the process of driving two separated beings into
physical reunion. But, Tillich argued, in a proper expression of epithymia love, "it
is not the pleasure as such which is desired, but the union with that which fulfils
the desire." That is, the two lovers desire reunion, and this reunion produces
pleasure. Hence this basic animal desire has a legitimate right to be called "love",
even though it represents only the "lowest" of the basic types of love.
When epithymia transcends the mere expression of sexual union and is sublimated
in the form of a drive "towards union with the forms of nature and culture" (LPJ
30), it is more properly called "eros". This Greek word (related rather
misleadingly to the English word "erotic") was used by Plato and other ancient
Greek philosophers to describe the philosophical search for union with the ideas-
especially with truth, goodness, and beauty. As such, it refers to a transpersonal
form of love that "strives for union with that which is the bearer of values". Unlike
epithymia, this higher form of impersonal love is fundamentally one-sided or
unequal, in the sense that the "lover" strives toward something that does not
necessarily respond with a mutual drive toward unity of its own. Truth, goodness,
and beauty often fail to cooperate when we try to apprehend them. Have you ever
suddenly realized that what you formerly thought was true is actually false? Have
you ever tried to do something right, but ended up doing something you know is
wrong instead? Or have you ever had people laugh at your choice in clothing, or in
anything else that required a judgment of taste? If so, then you have experienced
the struggle that inevitably accompanies the drive of eros toward reunion with a
recalcitrant object of value.
Tillich referred to the mutual interdependence between eros and "philia" (the
Greek word for friendship) as a "polar" relationship (LPJ 31). This is reflected in
Figure X.6 by the fact that these two terms both appear on the "impure" (+- and -
+) positions of the cross (though I would refer to this as a "contradictory" form of
interdependence). As the truly "personal" love, philia is a prerequisite of eros,
since one cannot pass from the impersonal to what transcends the personal until
one has achieved personhood. As such, philia refers not only to conventional
friendships, but also to the mutual drive toward unity that characterizes family
relationships and all other relationships between individuals in a common group.
As Tillich put it (32): "Love as philia presupposes some amount of familiarity
with the object of love. For this reason Aristotle asserted that philia is possible
only between equals."
Whereas the first three types of love are closely interrelated in human
experience, Tillich claimed that the fourth type, known as "agape" (the Greek
word for love used primarily in the New Testament), is radically different:
One could call agape the depth of love or love in relation to the ground of life
[i.e., God]. One could say that in agape ultimate reality manifests itself and
transforms life and love. Agape is love cutting into love, just as revelation is
reason cutting into reason ... (LPJ 33)
Unlike eros, which transcends philia by driving toward a higher unity beyond
personhood, agape transcends philia by driving toward a higher unity within
personhood. Agape achieves this super-personal kind of love by reversing the
goal set by eros. Agape is like eros, however, insofar as they both presuppose a
fundamentally unequal relationship between the lover and the object of love:
whereas eros is the drive of a person lacking value toward unity with an
intrinsically valuable object, agape is the drive of a person having value toward
unity with an object that has in itself no value to the lover. This is the kind of love
Christians believe God has for human beings and we ought to have toward people
we would not naturally love. From an ontological point of view, this is the most
profound type of love, especially since it has the same, analytic a posteriori status
as does ontology itself (cf. Figures I.1, IV.4, and X.7). This status is expressed in
terms of synthetic logic in Jesus' command that we should love our enemies.
To conclude this week's study of ways of feeling united, let's use Tillich's
ontology of love, and especially his way of distinguishing between agape and
eros, to rephrase the question I quoted from Lessing (via Kierkegaard) at the
beginning of Lecture 22. Do you still remember the question? If not, I hope you
will go back and reread it; then, before forgetting it again, you should spend some
time thinking about how you would respond. Lessing, along with Plato and
anyone else who emphasizes the search for "heavenly" ideals, chose the lifelong
search. Which one do you think Tillich would have chosen? Once we recognize
that the "lifelong search" corresponds closely to eros, while the attainment of "all
truth" corresponds to agape, it becomes evident that Tillich would have regarded
the two as complementary. If so, the very idea that we must choose one or the
other is a mistake; for each has its proper place in life.
Relating agape and eros to beauty and sublimity can aptly illustrate the two forms
of breakthrough (see Figure X.1). We experience agape whenever Truth suddenly
breaks into our ordinary ways of thinking and puts us into communication with
the Mystery of life. Agape begins when synthetic logic breaks into our ordinary,
analytic ways of thinking with a concrete example of the law of non-identity: it
teaches us to accept as beautiful what we thought was ugly in ourselves and
others, and/or to reject as ugly what we thought was beautiful
(A=-A). We experience eros, by contrast, by actively pursuing the eternal quest
for a means of breaking through the boundaries that traditionally hold us in place.
Eros begins by assuming analytic logic; but once we achieve a breakthrough, we
realize we can speak of this breakthrough only in the paradoxical terms of the law
of contradiction: it teaches us that the quest for Truth requires the sublime
recognition that truth is not Truth (A≠A); we will be unable to proceed unless we
see our quest for literal truth as part of a sublime quest for the symbolic Truth. We
can thus picture the complementary relationship between eros, agape, beauty, and
the sublime as follows:
(a) Agape and Beauty (b) Eros and Sublimity
Figure X.7: The Mystery and Paradox of Love and Beauty
Our examination of beauty and love this week has exemplified how we all
experience the paradox and mystery of feeling united. Next week we shall look at
examples of how being religious leads to paradox and mystery as well. For now,
let me reiterate one of the most important lessons we have learned from Tillich:
that both unity and diversity, both the belief in a mysterious, "heavenly" Truth,
and a lifelong search for it, must coexist in order for love in its fullest
manifestation to continue to grow and prosper. Hence it should be clear that there
is no straightforward answer to Lessing's question, for it suggests that,
paradoxically, it is more important to keep asking the question than it is to settle
upon one side or the other as the exclusively correct answer.
B. Could a person who possesses "all truth" still search for truth?
3.?A. Does beauty relate only to objects of sense perception?
RECOMMENDED READINGS
3. Max Picard, The World of Silence (South Bend: Gateway Editions, 1952).
6. Paul Tillich, Love, Power, and Justice, Ch. II, "Being and Love" (LPJ 18-34).
7. Erich Fromm, The Art of Loving (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1957),
especially Chapters I-II, "Is Love an Art?" and "The Theory of Love", pp.9-61.
Philosophy begins in wonder. This was the view Plato expressed in his
Theaetetus ( 155d) and echoed by many other philosophers down through the
ages. Wonder in this sense is not merely idle curiosity, but a passion for the
unknown that drives us to seek an underlying meaning behind the diversity of our
life, impelling us to ever new depths of insight and heights of understanding. I
have chosen to introduce philosophy to you in this course by starting not with
wonder, but with its opposite, ignorance. This is because the logical progression
of the parts of the tree of philosophy is opposite to the normal chronological
progression in our experience of doing philosophy. In these lectures I am
attempting to explain philosophy in such a way that, having completed the course,
you will be able to set out on a philosophical journey of your own. That means
that, although the best way to learn philosophy may be to move from metaphysics
through logic and science to ontology, the best way to do philosophy will be to
move from wonder through wisdom and understanding to a fuller recognition of
your own ignorance.
... Know then, proud man, what a paradox you are to yourself. Humble
yourself, weak reason; be silent, foolish nature; learn that man infinitely
transcends man, and learn from your Master your true condition, of which you are
ignorant. Hear God....
Whence it seems that God, willing to render the difficulty of our existence
unintelligible to ourselves, has concealed the knot so high, or better speaking, so
low, that we are quite incapable of reaching it; so that it is not by the proud
exertions of our reason, but by the simple submissions of reason, that we can truly
know ourselves. (PP 434)
Pascal's paradoxes point us beyond our ordinary way of looking at the world, and
confront us with a transcendent reality whose mystery stirs up silent wonder in the
depths of our heart.
Today I shall introduce one of the most common and yet profound ways of
experiencing the wonder of silence: namely, the discipline that has as its object
the ultimate reality most people call "God". As we saw last week, one of the
names traditionally given to the philosophical task of understanding this and other
ways of experiencing the "unity in diversity" of existing things is "ontology"-i.e.,
the "study of being". Ontology, the study of what is, is one of the methods
philosophers have used to resolve the various tensions created by our
philosophical reasoning. For example, Kant not only recognized the tension
between freedom and fate, as we saw in Lecture 22, but also argued that man has
a "practical need" to resolve it in order to appreciate the "totality" of human
knowledge and experience. We saw in Lecture 29 how he initially attempted to
resolve this tension by adopting something like an ontological point of view in his
account of the role of beauty and purpose in nature. In Lectures 32 and 33 this
week we shall examine Kant's most significant example of how the tension
between theory and practice is resolved in experience.
Because the word "God" is not used in all religious traditions, and because
traditions that do refer to God inevitably employ different names and/or
descriptions of God, Otto decided to avoid using the word "God" as much as
possible. Moreover, in examining the bare phenomena of our experiences (i.e.,
when we focus only on what we can observe), we do not actually find God as
such. What we find is various types of experience. Therefore, Otto coined the
words "numen" and "numinous" to refer to whatever object gives rise to the deep,
religious experiences sometimes referred to as the "presence" of God.
(Remember, Kant had distinguished between the "phenomenal" and "noumenal"
in a similar way (see Figure III.5).) Of course, most people would call this object
"God". But Otto's goal was not to propose a theory about the object causing such
experiences (i.e., whether it is really God, or nature, or just something we ate for
lunch); instead, he only wanted to give a phenomenological description of what
happens. This is, by the way, the typical method employed in doing ontology. For
that reason ontology and "phenomenology"-i.e., describing the essential character
of the phenomena we experience-always tend to be closely related disciplines.
Otto devoted a great deal of effort to the task of explaining the nature of our
experience of the numinous. The "holy" object, he argued, will be both
"nonrational" and "nonmoral". This does not mean it will be irrational and
immoral, but only that questions of rationality and morality will be irrelevant
when it comes to the feeling aroused by such a deep experience. Otto further
named this feeling "mysterium tremendum" and argued that it involves five
distinct "elements": awe, majesty, urgency, mystery (or "otherness"), and
fascination. The feeling of awe refers to a special kind of fear or dread (a tremor)
in the presence of something mysterious. (We shall look more closely at this
feeling in Lecture 34.) The recognition of the majesty of the numinous object then
gives rise to a sense of humble self-abasement (or "creaturehood") in us. The fact
that this is a real experience of a living object, and not just an abstract philo‐
sophical theory, is expressed in the "energy" or urgency we feel whenever we
have such an experience. This urgency can sometimes intensify our
Breakthroughandthe
Idea of theHoly
Kant himself had a profound awareness of this kind of numinous experience. For
example, the passage concluding the second Critique (quoted above, at the very
end of Lecture 22) refers to the "starry heavens above me" and the "moral law
within me" as basic experiences ("I see them before me"), giving rise to the
feelings of "admiration and awe", as well as to a sense of mysterious urgency and
dependence ("I associate them directly with the consciousness of my own
existence"): one could hardly cite a better example of Otto's ontological
description of religious experience! Moreover, Kant elsewhere described these
same experiences in terms of the "hand of God" in nature and the "voice of God"
in our hearts. These two ways reason has of manifesting itself to human beings
were, for Kant, self-validating, for they represent the very source of our scientific
knowledge and moral goodness, respectively. As such, they unify the endless
diversity that always characterizes our actual experiences of truth and goodness.
This, in fact, is why the source of logical reasoning cannot itself be logical; nor
can the source of the moral law itself be moral. Kant recognized (though he
unfortunately did not emphasize the fact) that the "starry heavens" (nature) and
the "moral law" (freedom) are like boundaries that we bump our heads against if
we try to pass beyond them. For, just as Otto claimed, the source of these
boundaries must itself be nonrational and nonmoral in order to be capable of
unifying the diversity of our rational and moral experiences.
Anyone who has had such experiences of the numinous will have an
immediate response to Nietzsche, or to anyone else who wishes to argue that God
is dead. The death of God as Nietzsche proclaimed it was real enough; but it was
the death of a false God, a God invented by human rationality more than by divine
revelation. Those who have experienced God will know we cannot force God to
live within the boundaries of any human system. Just as Nietzsche rightly
claimed, to attempt to do so is to kill God; and the only proper response is to
break out of that mold in order to regain the possibility of experiencing the life-
giving reality itself. But this raises a crucial question: Once we have experienced
the numinous, how can we describe it or understand it without forcing it into an
unnatural mold?
For symbolic language is based on synthetic logic, while our ordinary, literal use
of words (as signs) is based on analytic logic. Thus, just as the former, according
to Tillich, relates to the language of faith, so also the latter relates to the language
of knowledge. As we saw in Part Two, our literal use of words requires any "A" to
remain "A" and hence always to be opposed to "-A". As a result, any "B" that is
not identical to "A" must be included as part of "-A". (This, by the way, is often
regarded as the third law of analytic logic, called the "law of the excluded
middle": "B = either A or -A".) Signs always direct us in this way around the
world of the known and the knowable. But whenever we use words in a symbolic
way, the original symbol ("A") itself presents to us a hidden reality ("-A") that
we can actually experience, because this A participates in the -A, and vice versa.
(Obviously, synthetic logic therefore rejects the law of the excluded middle.)
Symbols enable objects, paradoxically, to be for us something they are not, so we
should not be surprised to find some philosophers basing symbolic language on
the "law of paradox" or "law of participation" (see Lecture 12).
Let's take my wedding ring as a simple example. If I were to regard this
object merely as a sign of my status as a married person, then the ring itself, as an
object, would not be very important to me. I would be more concerned with how
it looks on me than with what it means to me. If I were to lose it, I would be sad
mainly because of its monetary value, being made out of gold. But the loss would
not have any effect on my marriage, since I could buy a new one that would point
to my married status just as effectively. However, because I regard my ring as a
symbol of my commitment to love my wife as long as we are alive, the ring itself
actually participates in my marriage. To lose it or even to decide not to wear it
would be a tragedy, since part of my marriage would thereby be lost. I could, of
course, buy another ring to replace it; but it would take a long time for that new
object to become as profound a symbol of the mystery of love as my original ring
is. For love, as we saw last week, is one of the most common types of experiences
that require us to interpret objects as symbols.
Since this week's lectures deal mainly with "religious experience", let's use
the Christian ritual of the Eucharist as another example to help clarify just how
symbols operate. When Christians partake of the Lord's Supper, each participant
usually eats a small piece of bread and drinks a small amount of wine or grape
juice. The significance of this ritual varies greatly, depending on whether the
person regards these common, "knowable" objects as signs or as symbols.
Regarded as signs, the bread and wine point the person to some other knowable
reality, such as the actual body and blood of the historical man named Jesus Christ
(in the case of the Catholic who believes in the doctrine of "transubstantiation"),
or to the memory of this same person and what he did (as in the typical Protestant
interpretation). In both cases the original objects lose their importance as bread
and wine once we apprehend the object to which they point. Regarded as symbols,
however, these same objects no longer have anything to do with magic or
memory; instead, they are recognized for what they are (namely, bread and wine),
but they are believed to participate in the mystery of the Incarnation of God in
human flesh. Eating them is therefore a profound expression of one's own
willingness to participate in this mystery. By experiencing this ritual symbolically,
the person is transported by these ordinary objects into a deep communion with a
mysterious reality that can never be comprehended, except perhaps in the
incomprehensible wonder of silence.
To conclude our brief look at Tillich's position, let's use his definition of
faith to distinguish between metaphysics and ontology-two disciplines that are
easily confused, even by philosophers. Whereas metaphysics is the search for
knowledge of an ultimate reality, ontology is a search for experience of an
ultimate concern. So as we study various forms of ontology here in Part Four, we
must keep in mind that the "ultimate", toward which our attention is pointed by
the various symbols we meet in our experience, is an ultimate attitude or way of
life much more than an ultimate object or set of dogmas. Such symbols should all
be regarded not as giving us metaphysical knowledge of ultimate reality, but only
as kindling within us the silent fire of concern for the ultimate direction and
meaning of our life. In the remaining two lectures this week, we will go back to
Kant, in the hope that his Critical philosophy may be able to provide us with some
even deeper insights into what it means to be religious in this way.
Ever since Lecture 8 I have been putting more emphasis on the ideas of
Immanuel Kant than on any other philosopher-indeed, far more than would
normally be thought appropriate for an introductory-level course such as this.
Kant's terminology is so complex, his theories so deep, and his arguments so
controversial, that most teachers of beginning students dare not mention anything
more than the essential features of Kant's moral theory, with perhaps some
passing references to his epistemology. But in this course, we have covered not
only these areas (in Lectures 22 and 8), but also his view of metaphysics proper
(Lecture 9), his basic logical distinctions (Lecture 11), his defense of the principle
of causality for science (Lecture 21), his political theory (Lecture 27), and his
theory of beauty (Lecture 29). I have two reasons for focusing so much attention
on this one philosopher. First, I am far more familiar with his theories than with
those of any other philosopher, so I am more confident in offering interpretations
that are both accurate and meaningful. Indeed, much of my research and nearly all
of my publications have focused on this one figure. The second reason, however,
is far more significant: I believe Kant comes closer to a balanced and systematic
treatment of the whole range of philosophical issues than any other philosopher.
Moreover, his treatment is nearly always insightful and usually right as well!
olent God must be presupposed. Books Three and Four then deal with the new
problems that arise when good-hearted people come together in social groups.
Book Three argues that the final "victory" over evil can take place only when
human beings join together in a religious community (i.e., a "church"). And Book
Four distinguishes between true and false ways of serving God in a church.
According to Kant evil is the basic limiting condition that gives rise to the
need for religion. That there is evil in the world is not an issue he believes is open
to doubt. The philosophical tasks are to identify what evil is, why it is here, and
where it comes from (i.e., how it arises). In the process of discussing these issues,
he totally ignored the so-called "problem of evil" that is now regarded as one of
the major areas of concern for philosophers of religion-i.e., the problem of
explaining how a good and all-powerful God could permit undeserved suffering
and evil to exist. Such an attempt to justify God in the face of evil is called a
"theodicy". Kant's total neglect of this issue in Religion may be due in part to the
fact that he had written a separate essay on this subject shortly before starting to
write this book. That essay, entitled "On the failure of all the philosophical essays
in the theodicy" (1791), had argued that the attempt to defend God in this way is
bound to fail. Appealing directly to the biblical story of Job (the Old Testament
character whom God allowed to suffer horrendously, merely as a test of his faith),
Kant had examined nine different types of theodicy, demonstrating why each one
must fail. Any attempt to concoct rational excuses for God's decision to allow evil
to exist is misdirected, because knowledge of such mysteries is beyond the limits
of human understanding. Instead, the very insolubility of the problem serves to
heighten the existential significance of evil by forcing each individual to accept or
reject God on the basis of faith.
Book One of Religion begins by asking whether human beings are good or
evil by nature. First, Kant rejected the possibility that we might be both good and
evil; this can be true of our empirical character (because actions can be partly
good and partly bad in their outcome), but the motive behind an action must be
either good or evil. Kant then distinguished between a "predisposition" (the
universal tendency all human beings have at birth, before any moral actions have
been performed), a "disposition" (the fundamental subjective basis, in the depths
of our character, that determines how we choose to act at any given point in time),
and a "propensity" (the likely tendency of a person, or indeed, of the whole
human race). Kant proceeded to argue that our predisposition is good, because our
animality, our humanity, and our personality all contain features that are clearly
intended for good; our disposition may be good or bad at any given time, because
it cannot be both; and our propensity is always towards evil, because our
predisposition has somehow been corrupted. Just how this corruption occurred is
a question Kant claimed human reason is powerless to answer. But as a reminder
that it has occurred, he adopted the term "radical evil", thus indicating that the
human will (or disposition) has been corrupted at the very outset ("radical" means
"at the root") by an unexplainable evil force that does not belong to our original
nature (our predisposition).
What exactly is this evil? Kant defined evil as a reversal in "the moral order
of the incentives" that determine our maxims (RBBR 31). You may recall from
Lecture 22 that for Kant a choice is morally good whenever we obey the voice of
the moral law in our hearts, and that a person who makes such a choice deserves
praise if he or she has had to sacrifice some personal happiness (or "self-love") in
order to do the right thing. Evil is therefore a person's decision to let matters of
self-love be more important than the commands of conscience. Kant argued that
empirical evidence alone is enough to demonstrate that human beings everywhere
begin their moral lives with choices based on self-love rather than on the moral
law. He also tried to develop a transcendental argument, though its details remain
obscure in the text. I have reconstructed this argument as follows: a person cannot
make a truly moral choice until he or she knows what evil involves as well as
good; since our predisposition is good, we instinctively know what is good by
listening to our conscience; but until we actually make an evil choice, we cannot
be said to have attained genuine freedom, inasmuch as we will not have a true
understanding of what is at stake; the first genuinely free (i.e., moral) act of every
person must therefore be a choice to do evil.
Why begin a book about "rational religion" with the claim that we all start
out by ruining our chances of living a morally spotless life? Doesn't this call into
question the rationality of our effort to obey the moral law-an effort whose
importance Kant had emphasized so firmly in the second Critique? Indeed it does!
And this point baffled most of Kant's philosophical peers, who accepted the
Enlightenment's absolute faith in the powers of human reason, and thought Kant
did too. Goethe, for example, exclaimed that Kant had "slobbered on his
philosopher's cloak" with the doctrine of radical evil (see KCR 129n). But Kant
himself was not put off; for he knew what he was doing. Our experience of evil
and our inability to explain its rational origin except by merely confirming its
mystery ("it's radical!") serve to fill us with an existential wonder that impels us to
be religious. Indeed, Kant's intention in Book One was to present us with the
transcendental conditions for the possibility of religion: religion is possible only
in a world where rational beings are meant to be good, but are unable to fulfill
that existential goal. And this is the world we find ourselves living in.
Book Two takes a somewhat surprising turn. Having argued that human
beings inevitably start out with an evil disposition as a result of the negative
influences of radical evil, Kant went on to claim that the presence of our good
predisposition gives us a grain of hope that there may be a way of transforming
our evil disposition into a good one. But how can this happen? First, Kant
suggested, the only hope for anyone who believes morality is a worthwhile goal to
pursue is to believe in a God who in some way provides us with the assistance we
need to overcome our evil disposition. In traditional Christian theology, such
assistance is referred to as "grace". The main question for Book Two is: on what
basis does a person have rational grounds for hoping that God will provide such
assistance? In particular, is there something we must do to merit divine grace, or
is it a free and unmerited gift from above? Kant's solution to this problem is often
criticized for being paradoxical and, as a result, unclear. But I believe the paradox
is intentional: for in the context of Kant's Critical philosophy, any attempt to
explain how God (the transcendent reality) could assist human beings (living as
we do in the phenomenal world) is bound to be paradoxical. Kant would defend
his explanation as merely an accurate reflection of a paradoxical situation.
Because the archetype has the same function in Kant's system of rational
religion that Jesus has in Christianity, Book Two deals with a number of
theological issues relating to Jesus' nature and status. The issues include Jesus'
divine nature, his human nature, his virgin birth, his resurrection from the dead,
his status as a moral example, and various broader doctrines such as
sanctification, eternal security, and justification by grace. Many interpreters have
claimed that Kant's intention was to deny any real value to most if not all of these
traditional doctrines. However, such interpretations are based on a careless
reading of the text. For what Kant's actual strategy in each case was to argue that
such doctrines can have a legitimate rational meaning provided they serve the
practical goal of helping the religious believer to follow the moral law more
consistently. In each case he warned against any interpretation that is likely to
produce a morally lazy individual. What many interpreters overlook is that he also
warned against the opposite danger: dogmatically asserting that certain doctrines
cannot be true, simply because they cannot be proved theoretically. Even a
doctrine such as the virgin birth, Kant warned, cannot be absolutely denied,
inasmuch as the possibility of miracles is an issue that lies beyond the bounds of
human reason. As explained in great detail in my recent book, Kant's Critical
Religion (2000), the true intention of Kant's arguments is to show us how those
who wish to believe that, for example, Jesus was God in human form, must
interpret this doctrine in order for it to support rather than hinder the genuinely
religious core of a person's beliefs. Kant himself certainly did not recommend that
we adopt such doctrines as philosophers; he did not claim that we must believe
them in order to be accepted by God. But he did demonstrate that we can believe
them without sacrificing our rationality, and that doing so can sometimes greatly
strengthen our religious faith.
In Book One we learned that reason can tell us what evil is, and that we are
all inevitably ensnared by evil desires; but it cannot tell us the source of this
mysterious phenomenon, except to say that it is not rooted in the very definition
of what it means to be human. In Book Two we learned that reason can tell us
how conversion works and what we must do in order to have rational grounds for
hoping God will save us; but it cannot tell us who really is good, nor can it give us
definite knowledge of who will receive God's grace. In the next lecture we shall
see how important it is to keep in mind that Kant was not promoting a one-sided
view of religion as nothing but moral reason in disguise, but was describing the
two sides of all genuine religion: the rational (and therefore universal) core along
with the historical (and therefore inevitably non-universal) shell. As we shall see,
both aspects of religion must work together in order our religious experience to be
genuine.
Taken together, evil and grace represent a twofold basis for wonder as we
ponder the human situation. Grace in particular is not something we can ever hope
to understand through reason alone-unless we have actually experienced it. Good
philosophy is superior to traditional theology precisely to the extent that it does
not claim to understand what is by its very nature incomprehensible. It merely
hopes and provides rational grounds for hope. But in so doing, its function is not
to undermine religion, but rather to prepare us to experience the fruit of such
hopes. Lecture 33 will examine how Kant himself regarded the first two stages of
his theory as giving rise to the experience of religion through the forming of
communities devoted to serving God.
You probably noticed in the previous lecture that Kant's account of what it
means to be religious bears a striking resemblance to the biblical stories of the fall
of Adam in Genesis 1-3 and the saving work of Jesus in the Gospels. So close are
the parallels that some commentators have actually accused Kant of simply
translating Christian ideas into a rational terminology. Before continuing with our
study of Religion, we must therefore consider how best to interpret these parallels.
They are, in fact, a crucial part of Kant's strategy. For in the Preface to the second
edition, he explained that the book carries out two experiments: the first is to see
how far philosophy can go in disclosing the rational elements of all genuine
religion; the second is to see how well the beliefs and practices of one specific
"historical faith" correspond to this rational ideal. For the latter, Kant chose
Christianity, the tradition "already at hand" (RBBR 11, 123). With this in mind, we
should not interpret the presence of parallels as a weakness in Kant's theory;
rather, the closer the parallels, the more successfully Kant has demonstrated that
Christianity has a high degree of compatibility with rational religion. For he
always justified the elements of the latter with arguments that do not depend on
Christian tradition.
In Books One and Two Kant has established the rational elements that make
religion a necessary concern for all human beings. Every person starts out with a
potential to be good (based on their predisposition), yet inevitably allows this
original innocence to be corrupted with evil choices. Each individual is thereby
presented with the challenge of how to transform their evil heart into a good
heart-a change that is possible only for those who have faith in the assistance of a
divine power present within them, in the form of the "archetype" of perfection.
Books Three and Four shift from a focus on individual salvation to an
examination of how individuals who have experienced such an inner
transformation can form communities of good-hearted people in order to please
God through their actions. This conception of the whole human race pleasing God
is the ultimate goal of all genuine religion. The problem, as Kant noted at the
outset of Book Three, is that individuals-even good-hearted ones-inevitably
corrupt each other whenever they relate together in groups:
Envy, the lust for power, greed, and the malignant inclinations bound up with
these, besiege his nature, contented within itself, as soon as he is among men.
And it is not even necessary to assume that these are men sunk in evil and
examples to lead him astray; it suffices that they are at hand, that they surround
him, and that they are men, for them mutually to corrupt each other's predispo‐
sitions and make one another evil. (RBBR 85)
The argument Kant used to support this crucial step is brief and has been
overlooked by virtually all past interpreters. So let us take a closer look. The
argument presented in the simple paragraph at RBBR 89 can be expressed in a
more logically precise form as follows:
1. The highest good: The true end of human life on earth is to realize the highest
good, by seeking to be worthy of happiness through obedience to the moral law.
Working towards this goal is a human duty.
2. Radical evil: Human beings on their own seem to be incapable of achieving the
highest good, because of the radical corruption in the heart of each individual. At
best, all we can say is that "we do not know whether ... it lies in our power or
not."
4. "Ought" implies "can": Anything reason calls us to do (i.e., any human duty)
must be possible; if it seems impossible, we are justified in making assumptions
that will enable us to conceive of its possibility.
6. God exists. In order to work towards the fulfilment of the highest good, we
must therefore presuppose that God exists as a gracious moral lawgiver, and that
to obey the moral law is to please God. That is, the ethical commonwealth can
succeed only if it takes a religious form. (KCR 167-168)
I call this Kant's "religious argument" for the existence of God. In a nutshell, it
states that trusting in a moral God provides the only rational basis for believing
that our human duties can be fulfilled.
The technical term used in Book Three for this "People of God" is church.
What is crucial in Kant's view is to regard the church not as a purely physical,
humanly-organized entity, but to see it as an invisible spiritual reality, based on
rationally-justifiable principles. Indeed, following the pattern of the four main
categories (see Figure III.9), Kant suggested four basic principles for the
organization of any "true church" (RBBR 92-93): (1) its quantity is "Universality,
and hence its numerical oneness ... with respect to its fundamental intention"; (2)
its "quality" is "purity, union under no motivating forces other than moral ones";
(3) its "relation", both "of its members to one another, and ... of the church to
political power", is determined by "the principle of freedom"; and (4) its
"modality" is "the unchangeableness of its constitution", i.e., of certain "settled
principles" that are "laid down, as it were, out of a book of laws, for guidance".
The form of the true (universal) church, then, can be mapped onto the cross as
follows:
Figure XI.4:
The two 1LARs that give rise to this 2LAR can be identified as distinguishing
between characteristics concerned with laws (+) or freedom (-) on the one hand,
and between their external (+) or internal (-) manifestations on the other.
The key question here is: "How does God wish to be honored?" (RBBR 95).
Religious believers tend to answer in one of two ways: either God wants us to be
good and regards worship as an optional extra, or God wants us to worship and
regards moral goodness as unimportant or even impossible. Kant argued that a
true religion will adopt the former standpoint, while a false religion adopts the
latter. The latter is false because it requires as a duty belief in dogmas that cannot
be known to be true by bare reason, claiming that those who blindly believe will
be given the gift of moral goodness without actually needing to do good deeds at
all. True religion, by contrast, correctly recognizes that doing good is the
universal duty of all human beings (the only way to please God), adding that our
inevitable moral shortcomings can be overcome through faith that God's grace
will provide a supplementary gift to make up for the duties we are unable to
fulfill. Book Four develops this theme in considerable detail, in terms of the
distinction between "true service" and "pseudo-service" of God.
To illustrate the difference between true and false service, we can imagine
ourselves ordering a meal at our favorite restaurant. Waiter A fills the order with
the food that was requested, but never smiles or engages in friendly conversation.
Waiter B is all smiles and chats at length about everything under the sun, but ends
up letting the food go cold and bringing someone else's order to the table. A
friendly attitude would obviously be a welcomed supplement to good service, but
on its own it is insufficient. In this example waiter A performs 'true service',
despite being unfriendly, whereas waiter B performs 'pseudo-service' by allowing
the supplement (friendliness) to stand in the way of performing good service
(delivering hot food to the correct table). Kant seemed to have such situations in
mind when he defined pseudo-service as
the persuasion that some one can be served by deeds which in fact frustrate the
very ends of him who is being served. This occurs ... when that which is of value
only indirectly, as a means of complying with the will of a superior, is proclaimed
to be, and is substituted for, what would make us directly well-pleasing to him.
(RBBR 141)
Does Kant's conception of the service of God in a true religion leave any
legitimate role for worship, prayer, and other attempts to experience God in our
daily life? The traditional interpretation claims that he totally rejected all such
practices as illusions that lead to pseudo-service. But this ignores one of the most
important distinctions in Book Four, between "direct" and "indirect" ways of
serving God. We serve God directly and immediately whenever we do our moral
duty; we serve God indirectly whenever we do something that heightens our
awareness of what this duty is, or encourage us to obey it. Along these lines, Kant
explicitly allowed that religious practices such as prayer, church-going, baptism,
and communion can play a significant role in a genuinely religious life: they stir
up our moral sense and make us more keenly aware of what we ought to do.
Kant's negative words about such practices apply only to false interpretations of
their significance, as when someone interprets praying for a neighbor's financial
problems as fulfilling a religious duty without ever considering helping the
neighbor, or thinks attending church pleases God even if we learn nothing about
how to live a better life, or regards baptism as a way of forcing God to accept
people into the heavenly kingdom, or treats the communion ritual as a magical
way of making a bad person good. The correct interpretation in each case must be
symbolic: such practices belong to genuine religion only when they point beyond
themselves to a moral meaning.
Some of you may be inclined to conclude up to this point that the traditional
interpretation is right, that Kant did attempt to reduce religion to morality. We can
settle this issue once and for all by examining Kant's definition of religion. The
first main section of Book Four begins by defining religion as "the recognition of
all duties as divine commands" (RBBR 142). The reductionist interpretation reads
this as meaning "to be religious is to act morally". But this is not what Kant
wrote! Rather, his whole point is that religion goes a step beyond self-sufficient
morality by calling on God for assistance in what is recognized as an otherwise
impossible task. The text goes on to distinguish between "natural religion"
(religion that can be universally known through bare reason) and "revealed
religion" (religion that requires access to some specific historical faith). For the
philosopher, natural religion must have priority, because it is grounded in what we
can know (namely, our human duties); but in order to realize the final goal of
religion and actually please God, natural religion must be supplemented with
revealed religion. The test of whether a faith's alleged revelation is genuine is
whether or not it encourages the believers to do their duties. But this is not
reductionism; rather, it is a reasoned attempt to ensure that religious faith is rooted
in a rational core than can be shared by all human beings.
I hope I have made clear in this and the previous lecture that Kant's theory
of religion is not so much a "philosophy of religion" that covers the topics we
now tend to expect from books on that subject, as a philosophical theology that
aims first and foremost to clarify what it means to be religious, and secondly
argues that the Christian faith has the highest potential of all such faiths to
promote the universal religion that has a pure moral core. That Kant (despite
commentators' tendency to believe otherwise) was writing a book about religious
experience can perhaps best be seen by examining the evidence that his entire
philosophy was an attempt to develop what I call a "Critical mysticism"-i.e., a
way of understanding how we can experience transcendent reality (e.g., God)
without interpreting that experience in a way that will transgress the boundaries of
Critical philosophy.
The last book Kant published before starting to develop his Critical
philosophy was called Dreams of a Spirit-Seer, Illustrated by Dreams of
Metaphysics (1766). In this work he examined and interpreted the mystical
experiences of the Swedish visionary, Emanuel Swedenborg (1688-1772). After
giving both positive and negative assessments of the nature of such experiences,
Kant settled on a moderate position: metaphysical speculations about ultimate
reality are to thought what mystical visions are to sensation; in both cases, we
must first determine the limits of what we can know, and beyond that, we should
affirm only those mysteries that promote moral goodness. That Kant himself had
a deep experience of transcendent reality is evident from numerous hints he gave
throughout his writings. But we have no time to consider such claims here;
instead, we shall begin next week with a lecture on an openly Christian
philosopher who was deeply affected by Kant's philosophy in general and his
philosophy of religion in particular.
1. Rudolf Otto, The Idea of the Holy: An inquiry into the non-rational factor in
the idea of the divine and its relation to the rational2, tr. J.W. Harvey (New York:
Oxford University Press, 1977[1923]), Chs. III-VI, pp.8-40.
4. Immanuel Kant, Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone, Book One and
"General Observation" to Book Four (RBBR 15-39,179-190).
The most fundamental question of all ontology is: Why is there something
(or being) rather than nothing (or non-being)? This question is the ultimate basis
of all existential wonder. For the question, Why is the world here? leads directly
to the question, Why am I here? and from there to a host of questions about the
meaning of life. The latter has been among the most frequent topics addressed in
my students' insight papers. This is particularly true once we recognize that most
questions about death are also, at least indirectly, questions about the meaning of
life. For the awareness of non-being first raises the question of being; and in the
same way the awareness of death first raises the question of the meaning of life.
In Lecture 35 we will examine how the inevitability of death affects the mystery
that arises when we search for life's meaning. But first let's focus on a closely
related paradox that arises within us any time we choose life in the face of death.
According to most existentialists, any time we come face to face with the
possibility of our own non-being (e.g., as when we reflect upon our eventual
death), we have a natural "existential response" involving a very special kind of
fear. Martin Heidegger (1889-1976), the German existentialist philosopher who,
with Wittgenstein, is generally regarded as one of the two most influential
twentieth-century philosophers (see Week VI), distinguished between this special
existential fear and ordinary kinds of fear in the following way. Ordinary fear is a
person's empirical response to a threatening object within the world: it usually
requires us either to fight the object in hopes of overpowering its threat, or to flee
from the object in hopes of escaping from its threat. In both cases we can say the
person who is afraid of something in the world responds by trying to push
something out of the world-either the feared object or one's own self (see Figure
XII.1a). By contrast, existential fear is a response in the depths of a person's being
to the general human situation, especially when that situation reveals within us the
presence of non-being or "nothingness" in some way. The natural human response
is to flee from the threat, since it seems impossible to fight against "nothing"! But
in this case we flee not by seeking to escape the world, but by immersing
ourselves more fully into the empirical objects of our ordinary experience (see
Figure XII.1b). This may be done in many ways, such as by pursuing hobbies,
watching television, becoming an avid sports fan, or even becoming a scholar and
immersing oneself in books. Heidegger's point is that the usual (unhealthy) way of
escaping from the threat of non-being is merely to pretend it is not there, by
immersing oneself in being.
Figure XII.1:
Kierkegaard's analysis of
angst and sin suggests that the
lack of angst is the worst possible
psychological state, since without
Figure XII.3: The Ontological Origins of Angst
angst we could
and Sin
never progress to the stage of spirit. In the original state of innocence angst arises
as a response to the "nothing" (i.e., the person's ignorance) of the future: "anxiety
is freedom's actuality as the possibility of possibility" (CA 313). To ignore this
freedom is actually idolatry when it causes the person in the aesthetic stage of life
to grasp innocence, peace, happiness, beauty, etc., as if they were good in and of
themselves. For to do so is to separate oneself from the spiritual depths of one's
own human nature: "The most effective means of escaping spiritual trial is to
become spiritless" (385). Yet once this freedom is utilized, an awareness of sin
arises, causing a new kind of angst, in the form of "anxiety about evil" (381-386).
This comes in three forms: (1) the desire to return to a state of innocence; (2) the
threat of falling deeper into sin; and (3) the wish that mere repentance were
enough to atone for sin. Unfortunately, the attempt of many religious people to
overcome such anxiety by means of outward goodness only gives rise to more
angst, in the form of "anxiety about the good" (386-420).
The truly religious person turns away from both aesthetic and ethical aims
in order to become inward. "Inwardness" refers to immediate self-understanding
in action (CA 408), requiring a person to be open to the eternal in one's own self.
To turn toward oneself in this way is therefore identical to turning toward God. As
a result, it always begins by heightening a person's awareness of guilt:
In turning toward himself, [the religious "genius"] eo ipso turns toward God, and
... when the finite spirit would see God, it must begin as guilty. As he turns toward
himself, he discovers guilt. The greater the genius, the more profoundly he
discovers guilt....
To the degree he discovers freedom, to that same degree the anxiety of sin is
upon him in the state of possibility.... (376-377)
Such a person will then recognize that anxiety really points beyond itself to faith:
The only thing that is truly able to disarm the sophistry of sin is faith, courage to
believe that the state [of sin] itself is a new sin, courage to renounce anxiety
without anxiety, which only faith can do; faith does not thereby annihilate anxiety,
but ... extricates itself from anxiety's moment of death. (385)
In other words, the proper response to anxiety is to stop being anxious about
anxiety, accepting it in the belief that it exists for a higher purpose. Whereas
pagan anxiety expresses itself most profoundly as fate, and Jewish anxiety as
guilt, the anxiety of the true Christian (whom Kierkegaard regarded as practicing
the most advanced form of religion) is therefore expressed in the form of suffering
(see Figure XII.2)
Kierkegaard argued that the key to solving the problem of angst is to learn
to face it courageously, with the paradoxical feelings of "sympathetic antipathy"
and "antipathetic sympathy" (CA 313). Anyone who "has learned to be anxious in
the right way has learned the ultimate" (421). For "anxiety is through faith
absolutely educative, because it consumes all finite ends" (422). Despite its
apparently negative character, the suffering caused by angst is therefore essential
to our spiritual growth: "the more profoundly he is in anxiety, the greater is the
man" (421). Kierkegaard had numerous other philosophical insights, not only
concerning the human experience of angst, but also about numerous other topics,
such as the paradoxical relationship between history (the finite) and subjectivity
(the infinite), and the true nature of Christian faith as requiring a subjective
willingness to die. However, we will be unable to pursue these or other interesting
topics here.
Instead, I want to point out that, given Kierkegaard's analysis of angst, the
relationship between dread and death is analogous to the relationship between
love and life: just as love is the moving power of life, so also dread is the moving
power of death. Whereas the former is the power of being, driving us toward the
unity of opposites, the latter is the power of non-being, driving us toward the
diversity of opposites. In other words, dread is the driving power behind the
"estrangement" Tillich regarded as the necessary prerequisite for love (see Figure
X.5). The struggle between these two powers is, in fact, what keeps us alive,
while at the same time giving us a glimpse of our eternality in the midst of our
finitude. In other words, dread, in spite of being a primarily negative experience,
reminds us of our capacity for self-transcendence. Together, the powers of love
and dread remind us that, on the one hand, we are not at home in this world, and
yet on the other hand, we are not entirely strangers either. Recognizing this
paradox can help us respond to real experiences of angst in a way that is
appropriate to the eternal dimension of our lives.
Tillich argued that we are all guilty of losing our eternality to some extent.
The best explanation for the angst we feel when we think honestly about our own
death, he claimed, is that we all know deep down inside that we deserve to die,
because of the inauthentic way we have lived. Too often, people's response to this
guilt is merely to flee from it into the safety of philosophical arguments for
immortality or a religious hope for eternal life. Yet the latter only increases the
philosopher's over-dependence on logical reasoning, while the former only
increases the believer's over-dependence on religious imagination. In other words,
these common "solutions", though not in themselves wrong, can sometimes
backfire by intensifying the loss of eternality that comes from denying one side of
the paradox.
the acceptance of despair is in itself faith on the boundary line of the courage to
be. In this situation the meaning of life is reduced to despair about the meaning of
life. But as long as this despair is an act of life it is positive in its negativity.
By living our life in the paradoxical power of the courage to be, we will
eventually be ready to welcome death itself not as a tragic confirmation of angst,
but as the final step in this life-long process. Along these lines, Tillich claimed
that Plato's arguments for the immortality of the soul were "attempts to interpret
the courage of Socrates", who had clearly recognized that "the courage to die is
the test of the courage to be" (164). We will look more fully at the experience of
death itself in the following lecture. For now, however, it will suffice merely to
summarize Tillich's theory of courage in terms of the following map:
In the previous lecture we learned about the paradox of courage in the face
of the dread of non-being. This leads us directly to the ultimate philosophical
question, for the inevitability of our own non-being-that is, of our own death-
raises the question of the meaning of life; and this question itself directs our
attention toward the ultimate silence beyond life. As far as we can judge by what
we observe when a person dies, death marks the end of our capacity to use words,
and thereby ushers in a silence unlike anything we have experienced during life.
The mystery of what, if anything, happens after we die is one of the primary
sources of the "angst" we all feel from time to time-this being, as we have seen,
one of the primary concerns of existentialist philosophers. This angst has
therefore driven ordinary people-even those who know nothing about philosophy-
to propose various ideas about what happens after death.
Is there a life after death? If so, what is it like? There are four basic ways of
answering such questions, though each type of answer, of course, has many
variations. We can analyze these four ways of envisioning the "after death"
experience as arising out of two questions: (1) Does our consciousness of our own
identity continue after we die? and (2) Will we acquire a new body after our
present body dies? With these questions in mind, we can map the four traditional
answers to the question of life after death onto the 2LAR cross, as shown in
Figure XII.5. This is probably not a "perfect" 2LAR, since it is highly unlikely
that all four possible answers describe what actually happens after death.
Although two or three of these views might be simultaneously true in different
ways, most people feel constrained to choose only one as the best hypothesis. So
let's compare these four possibilities in a bit more detail.
The theories of extinction and reincarnation both agree that the part of me
that enables me to remember who I am (often called the "mind" or "soul") will not
survive my death; but they disagree as to whether or not
Figure XII.5:
Those who, like Plato, believe in the immortality of the soul are actually
closer to those who believe in extinction than to those who believe in
reincarnation. For, although the immortality theory disagrees with both of these
two theories by claiming that we have a soul (i.e., a capacity for continuous,
conscious memory) that survives our body's death (+-), it actually agrees with the
extinction theory's claim that our dead body will not be replaced with a new one,
as the reincarnation theory believes it will. This might seem rather surprising,
especially to those who view Plato's belief in the immortality of the soul as the
ancient Greek equivalent of the Christian belief in life after death. The latter,
however, is not based on any logical arguments for the necessity of the soul's
immortality, but on a religious hope that people will be saved from extinction
through divine intervention in the form of resurrection.
Although we do not actually experience our own death from within our
present life, we do experience other people's death as the ultimate end of their life
as we know it. As a result, none of us can know for certain until after we die
which of these four views best describes what lies on the "other side". Perhaps
this is why philosophers are often less interested in the questions death raises
about a possible afterlife than in the questions it raises about life itself. Plato, for
example, insisted that the fear of death is appropriate only for those who are still
bound to the "cave" (cf. Figure II.7). Transcending this fear by "learning how to
die" is one of the basic tasks any good philosopher must perform. Plato was
referring here, I believe, to the lifelong task of learning how to live with the
darkness of the unknown, even before we die; for when we do so, we discover
that this absolutely real mystery paradoxically sheds light on how we should live.
In other words, by raising the question of the meaning of life, death points us
directly toward the need to live what existentialists call an authentic life.
Whichever view of death is correct, the issue raised by Lao Tzu highlights
the central paradox of life itself: an essential part of the human task is to seek
after the infinite, yet this search is bound to fail because death makes life itself
finite. But the search "fails" only if success is judged in terms of analytic logic. If
we affirm the paradox, if we affirm (with Lao Tzu) the presence of non-being
within all being, if we affirm (with the existentialists) our finitude in the very
process of seeking the infinite, then we have grounds for hope that meaning will
break through in the midst of our struggle. Even if this breakthrough occurs only
after our death, it legitimates the search within this life. Indeed, Lao Tzu's real
point is not that the search itself is wrong, but that we should not expect to
discover the infinite in a form we can grasp within this life.
The lesson we learn by facing the paradox of death, in other words, is that
the search for the infinite must be pursued in the context of a recognition of the
finitude of life as we know it. The need for a recognition of both human finitude
and an eternal context beyond human life is an insight recognized by most
religions. For example, one of the many ways the Bible expresses this paradox
comes in Isaiah 40:6-8:
... All flesh is grass, and all its loveliness is like the flower of the field.
The latter quotation suggests that life is to death as words are to silence.
Similarly, just as life ends in death yet draws its meaning from the mystery that
death veils, so also, as I mentioned at the beginning of this lecture, the questions
of philosophy end in a silence that no longer has use for questions. Life is, in fact,
full of such mysteries and paradoxes. The few we have touched upon here in the
fourth part of this course only represent the tip of the iceberg. Our dreams, for
example, put us in touch with a huge area full of mystery and paradox. If we had
more time we could look in greater detail into some of these other dark and inter‐
esting aspects of our lives. Indeed, I devote an entirely separate course to the
subject of dream interpretation and the unconscious aspects of self-knowledge
(see DW). So instead of developing that topic any further here, we shall return in
the final lecture to the question this course began with, in order to examine how it
too reveals the paradoxical mystery at the heart of human experience.
In Lecture 1 I said I hoped by the end of this course you would know less
about philosophy that you did at the beginning. Some of you laughed at this
suggestion. Others seemed to be confused. Still others thought I was confused.
Most of you probably thought it was just a joke. But in fact, I was quite serious.
At several points during this course I have argued against naive versions of
relativism, on the grounds that certain boundary lines are absolute. More adequate
versions of relativism always recognize that the very possibility of "relativity"
depends on something that is, by comparison, "absolute". In physics, for example,
the theory of relativity was able to acknowledge the relative character of events in
our time-space world only after physicists agreed to treat the speed of light as a
"constant" (i.e., as an absolute). I now want to add that the ultimate purpose of all
philosophical inquiry is to become more and more aware of such absolutes; for
the more we do so, the more fully we can appreciate the beauty of the "mystery"
we have been talking so much about here in Part Four. Indeed, the final
ontological paradox is that this mystery makes itself known first as my
philosophy, but gradually reveals itself to be the source of philosophy itself. In
other words, it is both absolute and yet the source of all relativity.
You may have noticed that this entire course has, to a large extent, been an
attempt to answer this basic question. With that in mind, let me suggest one last
answer. When we consider how philosophy is different from other academic
disciplines, its virtually unending concern with self-definition stands out,
suggesting that philosophy may be defined as "the discipline whose purpose is to
define itself"-or more simply, "philosophy is the self-defining discipline." For
when any other discipline asks the question of its own nature, it strays into the
realm of philosophy. A history teacher is doing philosophy, not history, when he
or she asks students to reflect on the very nature of history. But throughout this
course we have discovered that the focal point of most (if not all) good
philosophers is precisely this question: what am I doing when I practice
philosophy? Of course, defining philosophy as the self-defining discipline relates
only to its form; the content (i.e., the details of how philosophy actually goes
about defining itself) has been the topic of this entire course.
With this in mind, I would like us to consider a passage from a book that
encourages us to hear the wonder of silence throughout the busyness of our
everyday life. Anne Morrow Lindbergh's little book, Gift from the Sea, is a series
of meditations on her holidays at an island beach, focusing especially on the
symbolism of the activity of collecting sea shells. In considering the following
summary of her reflections on the prospects of returning home (GS 113-116,119-
120), let's interpret the "island" as a metaphor for studying philosophy, and the
"shells" as a metaphor for having insights.
As she packed her bags to leave the island, Lindbergh asked herself what
she had gained from all her meditative efforts: "What answers or solutions have I
found for my life? I have a few shells in my pocket, a few clues, only a few." She
thought back to her first days on the island, and realized how greedily she had
collected the shells at first: "My pockets bulged with wet shells ... The beach was
covered with beautiful shells and I could not let one go by unnoticed. I couldn't
even walk head up looking out to sea, for fear of missing something precious at
my feet." The problem with this way of collecting shells (or having insights) is
that "the acquisitive instinct is incompatible with true appreciation of beauty." But
after all her pockets were stretched to the limit with damp shells, she found it
necessary to become less acquisitive: "I began to discard my possessions, to
select." She then realized it would be impossible to collect all the beautiful shells
she saw: "One can collect only a few, and they are more beautiful if they are few."
Can we say the same for philosophical insights? Perhaps so. For Lindbergh
herself generalized the lesson she learned by saying "it is only framed in space
that beauty blooms. Only in space are events and objects and people unique and
significant-and therefore beautiful."
This insight, that beauty requires space and selectivity, prompted Lindbergh
to reconsider the reasons why her life at home tended to lack the qualities of
significance and beauty, so characteristic of her time on the island. Perhaps life
seems insignificant not because it is empty, but because it is too full: "there is so
little empty space.... Too many worthy activities, valuable things, and interesting
people.... We can have ... an excess of shells, where one or two would be
significant." Being on the island, by contrast, had given her the space and time to
look at life in a new way-as I hope this philosophy class has done for you.
"Paradoxically, ... space has been forced upon me.... Here there is time; time to be
quiet; time to work without pressure; time to think ... Time to look at the stars ...
Time, even, not to talk." The problem in going home is that in many ways the
island had selected what was significant for her (as this course of lectures may
have done for you) "better than I do myself at home." She therefore asked herself:
"When I go back will I be submerged again ...? ... Values weighed in quantity, not
quality; in speed, not stillness; in noise, not silence; in words, not thoughts; in
acquisitiveness, not beauty. How shall I resist the onslaught?" She answered by
suggesting that, in place of the island's natural selectivity, she will need to adopt
"a conscious selectivity based on another set of values-a sense of values I have
become more aware of here.... Simplicity of living ... Space for significance and
beauty. Time for solitude and sharing.... A few shells."
In the end Lindbergh discarded most of the shells she had collected on her
island holiday, and took with her only a few of the most special ones. Her
experiences on the island, she explained, now serve as "a lens" that she can take
home with her in order to examine her own life more effectively: "I must
remember to see with island eyes. The shells will remind me; they must be my
island eyes." In the same way, I hope this course has provided you with a new
way of seeing yourself and the world. For the real reason the university requires
you to take a philosophy course is not to train you to participate in academic
debates on technical issues, but to enlarge your capacity to experience the
unifying beauty of life-that is, to enable you to "see with island eyes", even when
the examination is over and you have returned home, to the ordinary world of
your infinitely diverse personal concerns.
In Shel Silverstein's story of The Giving Tree, the little boy does not learn
this lesson until the very end of his life. During his life he forgets all about the
carefree days of his childhood, when the tree was almost like part of his own self.
Instead he goes off on his own, in search of happiness and fortune. The boy
simply ignores the silent screams of the tree as she allowed herself to be torn to
pieces by the boy's selfish desires. Only as an old man is the little boy once again
able to sit and rest with the tree, enjoying with her the wonder of silence. To some
extent this process of leaving the tree, venturing out on our own, and finally
returning to it in the end, describes the paradoxical steps each of us must
inevitably pass through in our search for a suitable philosophy of life. The tragedy
of that story is that, unlike the story of Jonathan Livingston Seagull, the main
character virtually destroys the source of his wisdom in the process of looking for
a meaningful life, leaving only a stump in the end. My hope is that this course will
have supplied each of you with "a few shells" to help you avoid such a fate. With
these in hand, I hope each of you, even those who will never study any more
philosophy in a formal way, will be able to live with a continuous, silent
awareness of the mysterious tree of philosophy and will always respectfully wait
to receive from the endless supply of gifts she has to offer.
B. What is philosophy?
RECOMMENDED READINGS
6. John Hick, The Fifth Dimension: An exploration of the spiritual realm (Oxford:
Oneworld Publications, 1999), Ch. 26, "Death and Beyond", pp.241-252.
7. Shel Silverstein, The Giving Tree (New York: Harper & Row, 1964).
The following books are cited in the main text of the foregoing lectures,
using the abbreviations shown to the left of each entry. Citations in the main text
refer to that book's page numbers, unless otherwise specified in the corresponding
entry, below. Some works cited only once in the text or Recommended Readings
did not require abbreviations, and are not included here.
BWA The Basic Works of Aristotle. Tr. and ed. R. McKeon. New York:
Random House, 1941. Marginal (Greek) pagination used.
LTL Alfred Jules Ayer. Language, Truth and Logic2. New York: Dover
Publications, 1952(1938).
JLS Richard Bach. Jonathan Livingston Seagull. New York: Avon Books,
1970.
CTBW Chuang Tzu. Basic Writings. Tr. Burton Watson. New York: Columbia
University Press, 1964.
TM Hans Georg Gadamer. Truth and Method2. Tr. G. Barden and J. Cumming.
London: Sheed & Ward, 1975(1965).
PSA Carl G. Jung. Psychology and Alchemy2. Tr. R.F.C. Hull. London:
Routledge, 1968(1953).
CPR Immanuel Kant. Critique of Pure Reason. Tr. Norman Kemp Smith.
London: Macmillan, 1929.
CPrR Immanuel Kant. Critique of Practical Reason. Tr. Lewis White Beck.
Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1956. Marginal (German) pagination used.
RBBR Immanuel Kant. Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone2. Tr. T.M
Green and H.H. Hudson. New York: Harper & Row, 1960(1934).
GS Anne Morrow Lindbergh. Gift from the Sea2. New York: Pantheon
Books, 1975(1955).
HMD N. Scott Momaday. House Made of Dawn. New York: Harper & Row,
1966.
JW Friedrich Nietzsche. The Joyful Wisdom. Tr. Thomas Common. London:
George Allen and Unwin, 1910. References are to section numbers.
LPJ Paul Tillich. Love, Power, and Justice: Ontological analyses and ethical
applications. New York: Oxford University Press, 1954.
DF Paul Tillich. Dynamics of Faith. New York: Harper & Row, 1957.
This Glossary briefly defines the most important technical terms used in
The Tree of Philosophy. Where relevant, opposite terms are given in parentheses
at the end of the definition. Words defined herein (including slight variations)
appear in italics the first time they are used in the definition of some other word in
either section of this Glossary. An asterisk (*) is appended to any italicized word
that is defined in the other section. The first section defines terms used mainly by
Kant. The second section defines other technical terms as they are used in this
text, usually naming the philosopher(s) who used them in the specified way(s).
anarchy: a politicalsystem having "no ruling power" ("an" and "arche" in Greek)
and serving as the basis for many versions of utopian visions.
architectonic: the logical structure given by reason (especially through the use of
twofold and threefold divisions), which the philosopher should use as a plan to
organize the contents of any system.
autonomy: the principle of self-legislation, whereby the subject freely chooses his
or her own ends by imposing the moral law onto the will. An action must be
autonomous in order to be moral. (Cf. heteronomy.)
categories: the most general concepts, in terms of which every object must be
viewed in order for it to become an object of empirical knowledge. The four main
categories (quantity, quality, relation, and modality) each have three sub-
categories, forming a typical example of a twelvefold, architectonic pattern. (Cf.
space and time.)
conscience: the faculty of the human subject that enforces the moral law in a
particular way for each individual by providing an awareness of what is right and
wrong in each situation.
Copernican revolution: in astronomy, the theory that the earth revolves around
the sun; in philosophy*, the (analogous) theory that the subject of knowledge does
not remain at rest, but revolves around (i.e., actively determines certain aspects
of) the object. Thus, the formal characteristics of the empirical world (i.e., space
and time and the categories) are there only because the subject's mind puts them
there, transcendentally.
Critical: Kant's philosophical* method, distinguishing between different
perspectives and then using such distinctions to settle otherwise irresolvable
disputes. The Critical approach is not primarily negative, but is an attempt to
adjudicate quarrels by showing how both sides have a measure of validity, once
their perspective is properly understood. Kant's system of Critical philosophy
examines the structure and limitations of reason itself, in order to prepare a secure
foundation for metaphysics. .
Critique: to use the Critical approach to doing philosophy*. This term appears in
the titles of the three main books in Kant's Critical philosophy, which adopt the
theoretical, practical and judicial standpoints, respectively.
disposition: the tendency a person has in any given situation to act either good* or
bad (i.e., to obey the moral law or to disobey it). (Cf. predisposition.)
duty: an action that we are obligated to perform out of respect for the moral law.
formal: the active or subjective aspect of something-that is, the aspect that is
based on the rational activity of the subject. (Cf. material.)
heteronomy: the principle of letting something other than the moral law
determine what ought to be done. This replaces freedom with something outside
of practical reason, such as a person's inclinations. Such actions on their own are
nonmoral-i.e., neither moral nor immoral-but can be immoral if they prevent a
person from doing their duty. (Cf. autonomy.)
ideas: the species of representation that gives rise to metaphysical beliefs. Ideas
are special concepts that arise out of our knowledge of the empirical world, yet
seem to point beyond nature to some transcendent realm. The three most
important metaphysical ideas are God, freedom and immortality.
ideology: an idea or system* of ideas that is treated as a myth to live by and often
forced onto others who may not otherwise accept it as true.
imagination: the faculty which, when controlled by the understanding, makes
concepts out of intuitions and synthesizes intuitions with concepts to produce
objects that are ready to be judged. In aesthetic judgment, by contrast,
imagination takes control over the power of thinking. See also imagination*.
judgment: in the first Critique, the use of the understanding by which an object is
determined to be empirically real, through a synthesis of intuitions and concepts.
The third Critique (adopting the judicial standpoint) examines the form of our
feelings of pleasure and displeasure in order to construct a system based on the
faculty of judgment in its aesthetic and teleological manifestations.
material: the passive or objective aspect of something-that is, the aspect that is
based on the experience a subject has, or on the objects given in such an
experience. (Cf. formal.)
moral law: the one "fact" of practical reason that is present in every rational
person, though some people are more aware of it than others. The moral law, in
essence, is our knowledge of the difference between good* and evil, and our inner
conviction that we ought to do what is good. See also categorical imperative.
opinion: holding something to be true even though both objective and subjective
certainty are lacking. (Cf. ignorance*.)
perspective: Kant himself did not use this word, but he used a number of other,
equivalent expressions, such as standpoint, way of thinking, employment of
understanding, etc. The main Critical perspectives are the transcendental,
empirical, logical, and hypothetical. See also perspective*.
predisposition: the natural tendency a person has, apart from (or before having)
any experience, to be morally good* or evil. (Cf. disposition.)
pure: not mixed with anything sensible. Although its proper opposite is "impure",
Kant normally opposes "pure" to "empirical".
reality/real: if regarded from the empirical perspective, this refers to the ordinary
world of nature, or to an object in it; if regarded from the transcendental
perspective, it refers to the transcendent realm consisting of noumena.
reason: in the first Critique, the highest faculty of the human subject, to which all
other faculties are subordinated. It abstracts completely from the conditions of
sensibility and has a predetermined architectonic form. The second Critique
(adopting the practical standpoint) examines the form of our desires in order to
construct a system based on the faculty of reason. Reason's primary function is
practical; though interpreters have often regarded its theoretical function as
primary, Kant viewed the latter as being subordinate.
religion: the way of acting, or perspective, whereby we interpret all our duties as
divine commands.
representation: the most general word for an object at any stage in its de‐
termination by the subject, or for the subjective act of determining the object at
that level. The main types of representations are intuitions, concepts, and ideas.
space and time: considered from the empirical perspective, they constitute the
context in which objects interact outside of us; considered from the
transcendental perspective, they are pure, so they exist inside of us as conditions
of knowledge. (Cf. categories.)
standpoint: the special type of perspective that determines the point from which a
whole system of perspectives is viewed. The main Critical standpoints are the
theoretical, practical, and judicial.
subject: a general term for any rational person who is capable of having
knowledge. See also representation. (Cf. object.)
subjective: related more to the subject than to the object or representation out of
which knowledge is constructed. Considered transcendentally, subjective
knowledge is more certain than objective knowledge; considered empirically,
subjective knowledge is less certain. (Cf. objective.)
summum bonum: Latin for highest good*. This is the ultimate goal of the moral
system presented in the second Critique; it involves the ideal distribution of
happiness in exact proportion to each person's virtue. To conceive of its
possibility, we must postulate the existence* of God and human immortality, thus
giving practical reality to these ideas.
supersensible: see transcendent.
teleological: having to do with purposes or ends. The second half of the third
Critique examines the objective purposiveness in our perception of natural
organisms in order to construct a system of teleological judgment. (Cf. aesthetic.)
thing in itself: an object considered transcendentally apart from all the conditions
under which a subject can gain knowledge of it. Hence the thing in itself is, by
definition, unknowable. Sometimes used loosely as a synonym of noumenon. (Cf.
appearance.)
transcendent: the realm of thought that lies beyond the boundary of possible
knowledge, because it consists of objects that cannot be presented to us in
intuition-i.e., objects we can never experience with our senses (sometimes called
noumena). The closest we can come to gaining knowledge of the transcendent
realm is to think about it by means of ideas. The opposite of "transcendent" is
"immanent".
analytic logic: the type of logic based on the laws of identity (A=A) and
noncontradiction (A≠-A). (Cf. synthetic logic.)
angst: the Danish word for anxiety or dread. Kierkegaard used this term to refer
to a special kind of existential fear, involving a person's fear of non-being. It
therefore includes not only a fear of death, but a fear of the meaninglessness of
life.
appearance: Plato's term for an object* or event in the material world, indicating
it is an illusory reflection of an ultimate reality* in the world of forms. See also
appearance*.
Apollonian: Nietzsche's term for the type of person who is willing to sacrifice
personal greatness in order to follow traditional (life-denying) moral and political
norms. Following a "slave" morality and a "herd" mentality, they tend to be
conscious, rational, and calm in their actions, and democratic in their politics. (Cf.
Dionysian.)
aristocracy: Aristotle's term for a political system* wherein a few of the "best"
("aristos" in Greek) people have the power and authority to rule. (Cf. oligarchy.)
beauty: one of the three aims of the philosophical quest, as conceived by Plato
and many subsequent philosophers. It corresponds to the heart and is powered by
the spirit. See also aesthetic*.
being-itself: the term used by Tillich and other existentialists to refer to the
ultimate reality* from which existing things stand out; also referred to as "the
Ground of Being" or "God".
Dionysian: Nietzsche's term for the type of person who is more concerned about
personal greatness and other life-affirming values than about following traditional
moral and political norms. Following a "master" morality and a "hero" mentality,
they tend to be unconscious, irrational, and passionate in their actions, and
aristocratic in their politics. (Cf. Apollonian.)
ecclesiocracy: Palmquist's term for the worst kind of political system*, wherein
leaders believe God directs the people solely through their mediation and/or
church structures are imposed onto the secular political realm. Following this
system requires people to give up their God-given freedom in exchange for the
presumed right to claim salvation. (Cf. theocracy.)
existence: Tillich's term for the quality of "standing out" ("ex-sistere" in Latin)
from being-itself. Also Palmquist's term for the common factor uniting
metaphysics and science through the application of ignorance and knowledge*,
respectively. (Cf. meaning.)
goodness: according to Plato and many subsequent philosophers, one of the three
aims of the philosophical quest. It corresponds to the belly and is powered by
appetite.
hermeneutics: the major school of twentieth century western philosophy inspired
largely by Gadamer and based on the conviction that grasping the art of
meaningful interpretation is philosophy's main role. This is typically
accomplished by reflecting on the nature of texts-e.g., by focusing on the
fundamental interplay between the author's intentions and the reader's prejudices.
(Cf. existentialism and linguistic analysis.)
idealism: the metaphysical position inspired largely by Plato and based on the
conviction that the objects* we perceive in the external world are not ultimately
real, but are "shadows" or appearances of a higher or deeper reality*.
ignorance: the goal of metaphysics, serving as the door to all good philosophical
thinking. Kant distinguished between necessary (i.e., unavoidable) ignorance and
empirical* ignorance that can be transformed into knowledge* once we recognize
that it exists. (Cf. opinion*.)
imagination: the power of the mind that is typically most active in a person's
childhood and reaches its highest expression in myth. See also imagination*.
insight: the "fruit" of the tree of philosophy; a creative new thought that comes to
a person suddenly and often unexpectedly, providing a deeper understanding* of
some issue or a way of answering a previously unanswered question. Insights
often provide a new perspective that enables us to break through old, traditional
ways of thinking. To be sure they are more than mere opinions*. we should
subject our insights to thorough analysis*.
kingship: Aristotle's term for a political system* wherein one good person holds
all the power and authority. (Cf. tyranny.)
lateral thinking: de Bono's term for a way of thinking that runs counter to the
ordinary or accepted ("horizontal") way of thinking about a given problem or
situation . By looking at a familiar situation from a new perspective, we can gain
interesting new insights about how best to proceed.
logic: the systematic* study of the structures that enable words to be understood.
The main question of logic is: "What gives words and propositions their
meaning?" See also logical*.
meaning: Palmquist's term for the common factor uniting logic and ontology
through the processes of understanding* words and silent wonder, respectively.
Frege argued that a proposition has meaning only if it has both a "sense" and a
"reference". (Cf. existence.)
metaphysics: Aristotle's term for the area of philosophy that is "after" or "beyond"
physics. Its main question is "What is ultimate reality*?" Socrates and Kant both
thought the proper outcome of studying metaphysics is negative: to enable us to
recognize our ignorance. See also metaphysics*.
myth: Eliade's term for a belief* that is held to be absolutely true. Palmquist's
term for any unquestioned belief that a person holds with deep conviction. (Cf.
science.)
numen/numinous: Otto's terms for the mysterious object* that causes a religious*
experience* to happen. He argued that a numinous experience typically involves
the same set of five elements, regardless of one's religious tradition: awe, majesty,
urgency, mystery (or "otherness"), and fascination.
oligarchy: Aristotle's term for a political system* wherein only "a few" ("oligos"
in Greek) wealthy people hold all the power and authority. (Cf. aristocracy.)
ontology: the study of being, aiming to promote silent wonder of the mystery of
human existence. One of the four main aspects of philosophy, investigating the
essential nature of various kinds of human experience*.
perspective: Palmquist's term for a way of thinking about or dealing with an issue
or problem, or a set of assumptions adopted when viewing an object*. Knowing
which perspective is assumed is important because the same question can have
different answers if different perspectives are assumed. See also perspective*.
philosophy: the Greek term for love of wisdom. It is a product of human
understanding* whose four main aspects are metaphysics, logic, science, and
ontology. One distinctive feature of philosophy is that it is self-defining: it is the
only discipline wherein asking the question "What is this discipline?" is part of
the discipline itself.
polity: Aristotle's term for a political system* wherein the middle class holds the
power and authority to govern. In the version called "timocracy", only landowners
are eligible to vote. (Cf. democracy.)
rationalism: the approach to philosophy that regards logic and rational* argument
as the fundamental means of finding philosophical truth. Rationalists usually tend
to mistrust evidence based solely on the senses*. Descartes is a typical example of
a rationalist. (Cf. empiricism.)
realism: the metaphysical position inspired largely by Aristotle and based on the
conviction that the objects* we perceive in the external world are ultimately real.
republic: Plato's term for a political system* wherein a philosopher serves as king,
who wisely distributes the power and authority to a trusted body of advisers and
representatives.
science: a product of human judgment; derived from "sciens", Latin for
"knowing". Viewed in this broad sense, it is one of the four main aspects of
philosophy, aiming to determine the transcendental* boundary between
knowledge* and ignorance in various fields. Viewed more narrowly, as
empirical* or natural science, it is the discipline that attempts to transcend
philosophy by ignoring all myth, yet paradoxically ends up creating one of the
greatest modern myths.
second-level analytic relation (2LAR): the most widely used term in Palmquist's
geometry of logic, referring to any set of four concepts* that can be derived by
relating two sets of opposites to each other. A 2LAR is most often mapped onto
the four poles (or the four quadrants) of a cross, though the corners of a square
can also be used.
self-reference, the problem of: a paradox that arises by applying a certain type of
proposition to itself. For example, "This sentence is false" makes sense if it refers
to some other proposition; but if it refers to itself, it produces a logically
impossible situation.
skepticism: a metaphysical position that calls into question the human capacity to
obtain knowledge*, expressed in its most influential form by Hume.
spirit: together with mind and body, one of the three traditional aspects of human
nature. Kierkegaard regarded the human spirit as the paradoxical key to both
human sinfulness and genuine religious faith*.
symbol: Tillich's term for an empirical* object* that points beyond itself to a
transcendent* object and somehow participates in the reality* of that more real
object.
synthetic logic: the type of logic based on the laws of nonidentity (A≠A) and
contradiction (A=-A). (Cf. analytic logic.)
truth: according to Plato and many subsequent philosophers, one of the three aims
of the philosophical quest. It corresponds to the head and is powered by reason*.
truth table: any of numerous ways of displaying the truth value of a specific type
of logical* proposition. One of the functions of truth tables is to help avoid
committing fallacies.
tyranny: Aristotle's term for a political system* wherein one bad person holds all
the power and authority. (Cf. kingship.)
verification: the principle used by Ayer and other logical* positivists in the hope
of constructing a philosophy that would be genuinely scientific. It states that a
proposition should be admitted as true only if it can be shown to be true by
reference to some empirical* state or situation.
Dallob, Pamela 20
Davidovich, Adina 262
Davidson, J.E. 20, 109
De Bono, Edward (1933-) 103-105, 109
Democritus (c.460-c.371 B.C.) 25
Descartes, Ren? (1596-1650) 40-49, 51, 57, 62, 143, 145
Derrida, Jacques (1930-) 61, 179-181, 185
Dewey, John (1850-1952) 59
Dilthey, William (1833-1911) 127
Dionysius/Dionysian 172-173, 175-177
DionysiustheAreopogite(“Pseudo-Dionysius”) (c.485-c.513) 83-84, 86, 102, 120
Dominowski, Roger L. 20
Dudley, Underwood 109
Duerr, Hans Peter 39
Durant, Will 62
Eliade, Mircea (1907-) 14-16, 20
Empedocles (c.495-435 B.C.) 25
Engels, Frederick 210
Euclid (fl. c.330-300 B.C.) 75
Ezra (fl.457-430 B.C.) 198
Kant, Immanuel (1724-1804) vii, 47-63, 64, 66, 74-77, 82, 84, 86, 88, 96, 101, 107, 110, 119-120, 128-130,
146-147, 152, 155-157, 159-160, 162-172, 175-176, 179, 181-185, 205-210, 222-229, 231, 238, 241-244,
247-262, 271, 280
Kessler, Gary E. 20
Kierkegaard, Søren (1813-1855) 59-60, 150, 236, 264-267, 269, 271, 284
Kohák, Erazim 238
Lafleur, Laurence J. 62
Langer, Susan K. (1895-) 86
Lao Tzu (fl. c.600 B.C.) 215, 275-277, 284
Lawler, Robert 109
Lessing, Gottlob Ephraim (1729-1781) 150, 236-237
Lindbergh, Anne Morrow (1906-) 281-282
Losee, John 160
Oedipus 14
Osborne, Richard 20
Otto, Rudolf (1869-1937) 241-245, 271, 262
Underwood, Richard A. 20