03chapters4 5
03chapters4 5
03chapters4 5
border of philosophy and theology will find it necessary to get a clear conception
of the scientific relation of both‘. Tillich (ibid:39) continues: ‗By the appearance
begins to show the relationship between philosophy and theology by recalling his
intellectual development and career. Tillich (ibid:40) writes: ‗To these ideas, which
Halle and Berlin; Professor of the Science of Religion in Dresden and the same time
philosophy and theology helps us to better understand the Frankfurt years. Tillich
(ibid:83-84) writes:
ideal is the complete unity of both types, an ideal which is reached only by the
greatest theologians and ever by them only appropriately. The fact that every human
creativity has its typological limitations makes it desirable that theological faculties
philosophy, before attempting a description of the world in unity with all kinds of
scientific and nonscientific experience, tries to understand being itself and the
categories and structures which are common to all kinds of beings. This makes the
division between philosophy and theology impossible, for, whatever the relation of
God, world, and man may be, it lies in the frame of being; and any interpretation
for the interpretation of God, man, and the world in their interrelations‘. Paul
Tillich (ibid:87) concludes: ‗In which philosophy shows kerygmatic and therefore
a theological character, for this is the task of theology: to ask for being as far as it
ultimately, unconditionally‘. Tillich (ibid:87) adds: ‗Philosophy asks the questions theology
supplies the answers‘. Carey (2002:37) asked Protestant and Roman Catholic scholars at
exploration of Tillich‘s work. The answer is rather surprising but pertains to Tillich‘s
ontological theology: ‗An embarrassed silence followed, and then one theologian noted that
there was little interest in Germany in Tillich‘s ontological approach to theology, and
that in fact there was considerable sentiment in Germany that after Tillich came to
America and began to develop his systematic theology he removed himself from the
years carry with them the Tillichean understanding of ‗the relationship between
133
philosophy and theology‘. Tillich‘s theology was built on the ontological model.
Horton (1952:45) visited Frankfurt shortly after Tillich had left in 1933. Horton
(ibid:45) writes: ‗His teaching at Frankfurt was so much concerned with art,
science, economics, politics, and general culture that hostile critics frequently
charged him with deserting his job as a philosopher of religion‘. The bias of the
critics must be admitted and allowed for since they would be in all likelihood,
National Socialists loyal to Adolf Hitler. The Frankfurt years are understood even
better when Tillich‘s boundary and border line concept are understood. Tillich (1966:
13) writes:
Paul Tillich wrote two autobiographical sketches-the first one in his fiftieth
year, the second in the year 1952. In the first sketch from 1936, Tillich
describes his destiny as an existence ―on the boundary.‖ Of course, every
life can be understood as always lived on ―boundaries,‖ for life is transition.
But Tillich‘s sense of his existence as running on boundaries had a particular
intensity, directness, and totality. For him, moreover, these boundaries are
not only transitions but also battlegrounds, controversies, difficult tensions,
and ever new endurance tests.
and kerygmatic theology are both necessary aspects of theology. They should not
and in his interpretation of history as the History of Salvation. I must confess that
even today I find more ―theonomous philosophy‖ in Schelling than in any of the
salvation‘. The problem was that Schelling‘s metaphysical religious thought failed
to achieve ‗a unity of theology and philosophy‘ (ibid:35). The First World War
aimed at the union of philosophy and theology. It failed because it did not include
Tillich‘s concept of the abyss (ibid:35). The result of all of this was the birth of Tillich‘s
philosophy of religion. The union of theology and philosophy is the result of Tillich‘s
135
the concept of the abyss and ‗the idea of justification a limitation of philosophy‘ (ibid:36).
Tillich (ibid:36) claimed his philosophy of religion was determined by both the
and also phenomenology. Neo-Kantianism didn‘t include the experience of the abyss.
sphere of values. All this was assumed in the experience of the abyss. Tillich (1959:74)
defines the abyss: ‗That which is expressed is the ―dimension of depth‖ in the
encountered reality, the ground and abyss in which every thing is rooted‘.
Nietzsche expressed the concept of the abyss, more clearly than the thought of the
philosophy that made it possible for Tillich to be able to approach and interpret
Nietzsche. The philosophy of life became attractive to Tillich in the years after
the First World War. The philosophy of life was a reaction against the ‗years of
death and hunger‘. The German Revolution of 1918 gave new direction to Tillich‘s
oriented (ibid:37). However, the philosophy of history had originated not with
Tillich but with Ernst Troeltsch. Tillich adapted it making it his own. Tillich
There is just one thing which the original Protestantism so long as it held strictly
to its fundamental idea, did not and could not do-and the omissions is of the
highest significance for the whole understanding of its relation to the modern
world: it never elevated artistic feeling into the principle of a philosophy of life,
of metaphysics or ethics. It could not do that, because its asceticism and its
absolute metaphysical dualism made it impossible. It could not reconcile
itself to the admission of art as an end in itself, as a particular way of knowing
God and the world which is necessarily in some way or other bound up with his
principle, and the not less closely connected transfiguration of the sensuous,
and the sense of the world as harmony.
Troeltsch was speaking on the philosophy of history which had not been treated since
Hegel‘s death (Tillich 1936:37). Troeltsch failed due to his adherence to German
Tillich espoused a new philosophy of history the ‗the philosophy of history of religious
Tillich believes Troeltsch was never able to resolve the tensions in the way in
which he hoped to, for in the struggle over the contradiction between the
absolute and ―the preponderance lay on the side of the relative.‖ ―It was not
for external reasons alone that he abandoned theology.‖ Not that his passage
from theology to philosophy was simply a passage from the absolute to the
relative. ―The opposite would be more correct.‖ His actual intention was to
move from the false absolute to the genuine. But in his striving for standards
Troeltsch attached himself to that wing of Kantianism which moved in the
scientific methodology in accord with Windelband and Rickert.
In inspection, one of Tillich‘s goals at Frankfurt was to bring about the union
137
of philosophy and theology. Tillich developed his own Christian philosophy of religion.
Tillich sought to show another aspect of the union of theology and philosophy.
This was the dimension between theology and philosophy of religion and culture.
Tillich (1959:40) began by defining religion: ‗Being ultimately concerned about that
which is and should be our ultimate concern. This means that faith is the state of being
grasped by an ultimate concern, and the belief in the existence of a highest being God,
and the theoretical and practical consequences of such a belief‘. Religion defined by
Tillich was absolute and universal. His proof for this claim is the absolute and universal
nature of religion as evidenced in the idea of God. Religion is not a sub category of
culture. Neither is religion to be placed as being an entirely separate realm from culture
(Tillich 1936:50). Culture has a claim upon philosophy. Culture decides the forms and
context that expresses the ‗Absolute‘. Culture‘s substance is religion. Religion‘s form
is culture. Tillich (ibid:50) explains the one difference: ‗In religion the substance which
is the unconditioned source and abyss of meaning is designated, and the cultural forms
serve as symbols for it‘ whereas in culture the form, which is the conditioned meaning
138
becomes perceptible only indirectly, throughout the autonomous form‘. Culture seeks to
understand man‘s finiteness and search for the infinite. Religion by way of contrast must
include ‗the autonomous form‘ the ‗Logos‘ (ibid:50). Tillich concludes by saying that
these ideas were the foundation for both a philosophy of religion and a philosophy of
culture (ibid:50). Tillich was then able to treat cultural movements from the perspective
of religion (ibid:50-51).
Tillich wanted to show the relation of religion to culture. Culture that included
politics, art, depth psychology and also sociology (Tillich 1966:7). Tillich (1967:43)
writes: ‗Frankfurt was the most modern and liberal university in Germany, but it had
no theological faculty. So it was quite natural that my lectures moved on the boundary
line between philosophy and theology and tried to make philosophy existential for the
German culture had experienced culture shocks at all levels due to the
devastation of World War I. Germany was experiencing two digit inflation. The
German people were open to these new ideas. Tillich formed an apologetical
theology. This became part of his curriculum while he was teaching at Frankfurt.
Dresden had been a center of the visual arts including painting, architecture, dance,
and opera. Tillich (1966-9-10) writes: ‗The cultural situation was not much different
Tillich brought the culture of Berlin, Dresden and Frankfurt to bear in his lectures in
Frankfurt. This element became an important part of Tillich‘s efforts to show the
139
In 1929 Tillich was called to the chair that Scheler had held in Frankfurt as
ordinarius for philosophy and sociology; he remained there until 1933. The
lectures from this time indicate no specifically theological themes, with the
exception of a course Dogmatics I, in Marburg. The themes are all on religion
and culture, on the social situation, or on ―religious experience,‖ the ―religious
interpretation of being,‖ and the ―essence of religion.‖ In the themes of these
lectures and in the way that Tillich moved from university to university is
reflected the tendency of Tillich‘s working. At the peak of this tendency is
the theme of his life: the theology of culture..
(ibid:24) writes: ‗In this problem his historical elan, his religio-philosophical
system, his poltical theory, and his religious passion were brought together‘.
between philosophy and theology. This was the union of religion and culture. Culture‘s
substance is religion. Religion‘s form is culture. Tillich related religion to politics, art,
The German people were open to new ideas as a result of the culture shocks from
World War I and two digit inflation. Tillich formed an apologetical theology. This became
Tillich accepted the position in Frankfurt with the title Professor of Philosophy
140
and Sociology (Pauck and Pauck 1976:112-113). Fritz Medicus wrote a public
‗Tillich‘s former teacher and friend Fritz Medicus, who had observed Tillich‘s popularity
piece for the Neue Zurcher Zeitung, the leading Swiss newspaper, proclaiming
that the appointment of Tillich to Scheler‘s chair was the beginning of a new
philosophical era. His experience in Davos convinced him that his former pupil,
whom he described as a genius, had rescued the Schellingian philosophy from the
dusty theory in which it was held captive and transformed it into meaning for a
responsible way of life‘. The Paucks (ibid:113) add: ‗Tillich‘s formal task at the
University of Frankfort [Frankfurt] was in fact to teach social education, and in his
lectures and seminars between the years 1929 and 1933 he thus emphasized the
aspects of social ethics, historical action, and political direction rather than the
classroom. More than ever he felt obliged to make philosophical questions existential
for the numerous students for whom philosophical courses were mandatory‘. The
Paucks (ibid:113) continue: ‗He gave courses on Kant, Hegel, and Schelling, on
Locke and Thomas Aquinas‘. Tillich lectured: ‗on ―Being and Action,‖ ―The Masses and
course on questions of systematic theology only during the last semester in Frankfort and
for Tillich‘s ‗systematic science of culture‘ during the German university years.
Ratschow (ibid:24) continues: ‗Its dialectic is rooted in the fact that every science
must use universal concepts to set forth a concrete normative science of its own does
does not wish to remain without fruit in a merely general validity‘. Ratschow
(ibid:24) argues: ‗This is also true for theology. As a normative science—that is,
as part of the concretizing that is turned toward life—it is a part of the science of
science of religion, the problem of cultural theology can be discussed only in the
large horizon of religion and culture. At this time, moreover, religion for Tillich
(ibid:25) concludes:
‗The period at Frankfort [Frankfurt] turned out to be the richest and most successful
German university life, Tillich deepened and refined his teaching skills.
He sought the truth, as of old, in his non authoritarian way. That was
unusual for a theologian. His colleagues soon learned that he had
somehow freed himself from the stuffy moralism of his Protestant
background. Moreover, he did not merely teach his students; he lived
with them and mobilized their intellectual forces. The largeness of his
nature, the broadmindedness that gave others confidence to speak their
own words, became more and more evident.
Tillich made his students feel worthwhile and intelligent by his responses to
their questions and input (ibid:114). Moreover, Tillich had the great ability
to be a very good listener. Tillich was a very open person. He was able to
Frankfurt. The first was Harald Polechau ‗whom Tillich brought from Berlin‘.
Polechau was writing his dissertation at this time. Tillich had a second
or Adorno (ibid:114-115).
‗The menace of National Socialist power, at first mere parody and a shadow,
wide circle of friends that met to discuss academic questions (ibid:119). Tillich
Donnelly (2003:2) writes: ‗This bringing together and fusing of religious and
Marxist thought in the early Tillich has been the subject of special study for
Quinney, Ronald Stone, and John Stumme‘. Donnelly (ibid:2) argues that
Tillich was ‗widely perceived as a Marxist, and not without good reason‘.
in Donnelly 2003:27) admits his debt to Marx: ‗ I owe to Marx, first of all,
the insight into the ideological character not only idealism but of all systems
even though unconsciously, the more righteous form of social reality‘. Further,
Thomas (1963:14) argues that Tillich‘s public speaking brought him into
conflict with the growing Nazi movement in Germany. His argument is built on
Tillich biographical details (1963:14). Tillich was convinced of the need for religious
socialism for Germany (Thomas 2000:43). Thomas (ibid:43) argues based on Tillich‘s
book The Socialist Decision. It contained Tillich‘s ‗developed political theology‘ (ibid:43).
This book showed Tillich‘s commitment to ‗socialist politics‘, and it was ‗a deliberate
The critical analysis of this section shows that Tillich was Professor of Philosophy
at Frankfurt. Tillich was replacing Scheler. Scheler was to replace Cornelius. Scheler died
before his appointment was to begin. Tillich emphasized the social, historical action, and
political direction. Tillich made his philosophical questions existential while he was at
Frankfurt. Tillich attracted a large number of students at Frankfurt. This was his most
successful teaching period. Tillich became involved with the Institute for Social Research
at Frankfurt. The early Tillich had fused together religious and Marxist thought into
religious socialism.
145
Paul Tillich‘s years at Frankfurt were lived out against the background
of political turmoil and turbulence in Germany. Thomas (ibid:19) writes: ‗As the 1920s
wore on, the National Socialist Movement grew in strength and influence. Thomas (ibid:43)
continues : ‗By the end of the decade, the threat it posed was sufficient‘. The Great Depression
which had its origin in the Wall Street Crash that occurred on October 29, 1929 in the United
States sent financial shockwaves around the globe. By mid 1930‘s the economic
pressures of the Great Depression were causing the German democratic government to come
apart (Duiker and Spielvogel 2007:646-649). January 30, 1933, saw Hitler named as
‗The political events of recent years have been decisive in providing the impulse to
begin and complete the book: the decline of the political influence of the Social
Democrats, the apparently final split in the proletarian working class, the triumphal
In 1919, the Treaty of Versailles had laid heavy war ‗reparations for all the
damage to which the Allied governments and their people were subject as a result
writes:
In 1919, however, most Germans longed not for democracy but for stability and
order. The Weimar Republic, its birth accompanied by right-wing soldiers‘
uprisings and Communist attempts at revolution, was an uncertain government
in a volatile environment. It was burdened by the social and economic costs of
the war and the additional obligations of paying war reparations, which the
victorious European powers had set at 132 billion gold marks.
Germany a loan of two hundred million. Reparations were reduced and made
The Americans made heavy investments in Europe which created European prosperity
during the years 1924 to 1929. In 1928, American investors called in these loans
made to Germany. This was so as to be able to invest in the New York stock market.
The October 1929 stock market crash led American investors to have to withdraw
even more loaned money to Germany (ibid:647). Duiker and Spielvogel (ibid:649)
write:
In inquiry, Tillich‘s Frankfurt years were lived out against the background of
political turmoil and economic instability. The treaty of Versailles had laid heavy
war reparation payments on Germany. The booming New York stock market of 1928
caused American investors to withdraw loans made to Germany. This was in order that
147
they could invest in the New York stock market. The crash of the New York stock
market in 1929 sent financial shockwaves around the globe. American investors called
in more loans made to Germany. The Hindenberg democratic government was coming
apart. Hindenberg made a concession to Adolf Hitler on January 30, 1933. Hitler was
named Chancellor of Germany. Later, in March, 1933, Hitler became dictator of all of
Germany.
Tillich produced his book The Socialist Decision during his German years.
Stumme (1977:xxiii) writes: ‗Tillich wrote the bulk of The Socialist Decision during
the summer of 1932 in the mountains of Sils Maria, Switzerland‘,….But it was too
late. Historical events foreclosed any genuine decision; on 30 January 1933, Adolf Hitler
took power, and the barbaric future began‘. Stumme (ibid:xxiii-xxiv) continues: ‗The
Socialist Decision was suppressed and all the socialist literature of Alfred Protte,
Tillich‘s publisher, was confiscated. Later, the remaining copies of the work were
destroyed when the Protte warehouse in Potsdam was leveled by Allied bombs‘.
Stumme (ibid:xxiv) concludes: ‗The book‘s public existence was extremely short-lived,
and no reviews of it were printed. Like other anti-Nazi material, The Socialist Decision
was consumed by the fires of repression‘. Carey (2002:4) writes: ‗Tillich was dismissed
148
by the Nazis from his position at the University of Frankfurt on April 13, 1933, and in
In examination, Tillich‘s book The Socialist Decision did not come out soon enough.
It was published in 1933 by Alfred Protte. Hitler took power on January 30, 1933. All
socialist literature was confiscated. Allied bombs leveled the Protte warehouse. Tillich
was dismissed from his teaching position at Frankfurt by the Nazis on April 13, 1933.
It was in December of 1933 that Tillich and his family came to America.
4:7 Summary
theology. This helps us in our understanding of the Frankfurt years. Tillich distinguished
second kind of theology is kerygmatic theology. Kerygmatic is derived from the New
Testament word for message. It tries to reproduce the Christian message in a systematic
way without referring to philosophy. Philosophical theology is also based on the kerygma.
It tries to explain the contents of the kerygma in close interrelation with philosophy.
Kerygmatic theology has always used philosophical terms and methods. Philosophical
theology has always tried to explain the content of the message. The theological ideal is
the unity of both types of theology. Philosophical theology is also called apologetics,
Philosophy attempts a description of the world in unity with all kinds of scientific
and nonscientific experience. However, it must first try to understand being itself, the
categories, and the structures common to all kinds of beings. This makes the division
between philosophy and theology impossible because of the relation of God, world, and
man. Whatever the relation is it lies within the frame of being. Philosophy asks the questions.
Theology supplies the answers. The Frankfurt years (1929-1933) show the Tillichean
The Frankfurt years help us in our understanding of Tillich‘s boundary and border
the boundary. The boundaries had particular intensity, directness, and totality for Tillich.
endurance tests.
Tillich tried to show the union between philosophy and theology at Frankfurt.
This became possible because of the explanation that Schelling‘s Christian philosophy
of the abyss. The result was the birth of Tillich‘s Christian philosophy of religion. The
union of theology and philosophy was achieved because of Tillich‘s Christian philosophy
of religion. His Christian philosophy of religion abides on the border between theology
and philosophy. The abyss is that which is expressed in dimension of depth. The ground
150
because of Schelling. The German revolution of 1918 gave new direction to Tillich‘s
philosophy of history. Tillich‘s new Christian philosophy of history became the Christian
A second dimension of the union between philosophy and theology was that of
religion and culture. Tillich defined religion as ultimate concern concerning that which
should be our ultimate concern. Faith is the state of being grasped by an ultimate concern.
Faith is also the belief in the highest being‘s existence God, the theoretical, and the
practical consequences of such belief. Culture decides the forms and the context that
Tillich showed the relationship of religion to culture. Culture included politics, art,
Frankfurt didn‘t have a theological faculty. It was natural for Tillich‘s lectures
to move on the boundary between philosophy and theology. Tillich tried to make
The German people were open to new ideas due to the culture shocks of World
War I and two digit inflation. Tillich formed an apologetical theology. This became
part of his curriculum when he was teaching at Frankfurt. Tillich lectured on the themes
151
of religion and culture, the social situation, religious experience, the religious interpretation
of being, and the essence of religion. Tillich‘s theology of culture was the theological
problem that joined together his historical elan, his religio-philosophical system, his
Fritz Medicus, a former teacher wrote an article about Tillich in a leading Swiss newspaper.
The article pointed out that Tillich‘s appointment as a successor of Scheler was the
beginning of a new philosophical era. Tillich became well known throughout Germany
as a result of his position at the University of Frankfurt. Tillich had a wide circle of
friends at Frankfurt. They met to discuss academic questions in the Frankfurt School
(Institute for Social Research). The early Tillich fused together religious and Marxist
and economic instability. The Wall Street Crash on October 29, 1929 in the United
States sent financial shockwaves around the globe. The German democratic government
collapsed. On January 30, 1933, Hitler was named Chancellor of Gernany by the concession
Tillich‘s closing days at Frankfurt saw the completion of his book The Socialist
Decision. This book was published in 1933. Hitler‘s barbaric reign began on January
30, 1933. The Socialist Decision and all socialist literature was suppressed and
confiscated. The remaining copies of The Socialist Decision were destroyed when the
152
Alfred Protte warehouse was levelled by Allied bombs. Tillich was dismissed by the
Nazis on April 13, 1933. He and his family came to America in December of 1933.
The procession of our thesis is to consider the influences on Tillich during the
INFLUENCES
5:1 Academic
Paul Tillich‘s life had many influences on it during the German years.
Bernard Martin (1963:2) argues that Tillich‘s biographical data ‗sets forth the major
facts of Tillich‘s life‘. Martin (ibid:7) seeks to explain what ‗incidents‘ and ‗experiences
of his personal historical destiny have been of basic importance in molding his thought‘.
In addition, Martin (ibid:7) argues for the ‗crucial intellectual influences upon‘ Tillich‘s
life. Tillich had studied philosophy on his own. He had a working knowledge of the history
of philosophy and familiarity with Fichte and Kant. At the University, he had studied
Christian philosophy of religion (ibid:17). Tillich had studied theology at the University
of Berlin, Tubingen, and also Halle. He took his first theological exam in 1909. His
second theological exam was written in 1911. He received the Doctor of Philosophy degree
from the University of Breslau in 1911. In 1912, Tillich received the Licentiate of Theology
154
from the University of Halle (ibid:17). Paul Tillich was interested in the ideological character
not only of ‗idealism‘ but as well ‗all systems of thought both religious and profane‘. He
had learned earlier from Kierkegaard that truth is always to be found in the context of the
knower (ibid:21). It was during the German years that Tillich became interested in the
social movements of his day. He had a profound interest in Marx who had a new and a
that every human being exists in a situation of despair (ibid:21). The German masses were
involved in a class struggle during and after World War I. Marx thought every system of
harmony was untrue (ibid:21). Tillich was now able to connect truth to a particular
argues that Marx was one of the definite influences on Tillich. Martin (ibid:21) writes of
Martin follows the biographical details of Paul Tillich‘s life to establish his
argument. In 1900, the Tillich family moved to Berlin, Germany. Tillich‘s father,
Johannes had accepted a church position as pastor. Martin (Tillich 1936:6 in Martin
1963:16) quotes Tillich: ‗I was saved from romantic enmity against technical
civilizations and was taught to appreciate the importance of the big city for the critical
side of intellectual and artistic life. Later there was added to this a vital and thoughtful
understanding of the world of Bohemianism, possible only in the large cities; and also an
aesthetic appreciation of the internal and external immensity of the metropolis‘. Tillich
155
(ibid:6 in ibid:16) gained ‗personal experience‘ of both the political and the social movements
in Berlin. Tillich (1952:9) graduated from the Gymnasium in 1904. He developed a love for
both the Greek language, culture, and as well Greek philosophy (ibid:9). Tillich (ibid:10)
confirms that he (ibid:10) had studied philosophy on his own prior to beginning his theological
studies at the university. Tillich (ibid:10) had a knowledge of both Fichte and Kant when he
entered the university. Tillich (ibid:10) studied Schleiermacher, Hegel, and Schelling
during his university days. Tillich studied theology at the Universities of Berlin,
Tubingen, and Halle (Martin 1963:17). In 1909, he took his first theological exam. In
1911, his second theological exam (ibid:17). In 1911, Tillich received the Doctor of
Philosophy degree from the University of Breslau. In 1912, he received the Licentiate of
Theology at Halle (ibid:17). His doctoral dissertation and his Licentiate of Theology were
both written on the work of Friedrich Schelling (Tillich 1952:10 in ibid:17). Schelling‘s
work made an impact on Tillich‘s life. Martin doesn‘t draw this conclusion from Tillich‘s
biographical data. His purpose comes out in that his argument is to support only the theme
of his book The Existential Theology of Paul Tillich (ibid:26). Martin (ibid:26) argues:
‗Kierkegaard and Heidegger remain his philosophic heroes and the existentialist doctrine
of man continues to be for him the most valuable and enlightening account that has been
During the writing of these works, [his two dissertations on Schelling] I was a
student of Protestant theology, and at the conclusion of my studies became
assistant pastor at various parishes of the Old Prussian United Church. At that time,
Martin Kahler and Wilhelm Lutgert from Halle were my most important teachers.
156
The former was a personality of overwhelming ethical and religious power and
intellectual concentration; as teacher and writer difficult to understand;
profoundest and in many respects the most modern representative of the theology
of mediation of the nineteenth century; an opponent of Albert Ritschl, herald of the
theological doctrine of justification, and critic of idealism and humanism, out of
which he himself evolved. I am indebted to him primarily for the insight he gave
me into the all-controlling character of the Pauline-Lutheran idea of justification….
At this point, I parted soon from the teachings of the theologians in Halle and
became less and less in accord with the new supranaturalism, which has grown up
within Barth‘s theology, and wishes to repeat the dogmatic doctrines of the
Reformation, by discarding the scientific work of two hundred years. At first it
was the interpretation of the Old Testament by Wellhausen and Gunkel, the
so-called religions-geschichtliche Methode, which fascinated me and revealed to me
the Old Testament in its fundamental meaning for Christianity and humanity. My
preference for the Old Testament and the spirit of prophetic criticism and expectation
has stayed with me and through the bearing of this upon my political attitude, it has
become decisive for the shaping of my life and thought….My historical insights into
the New Testament I owe principally to Albert Schweitzer‘s ―The Quest of the
Historical Jesus‖ and Bultmans Synoptische Tradition. Ernst Troeltsch caused my
transfer of interest from all mediating-theological and apologetic remains in Church
History and in the problem of historical criticism.
and the Old Testament prophetic criticism for his political attitude.
interpretation of history as a class struggle gave Tillich insight into the situation of the
German masses during and after World War I. Schelling‘s views became Tillich‘s
views. Tillich wrote both his doctoral dissertation and his dissertation for Licentiate of
Theology on Schelling. Tillich had insight from Martin Kahler into the Pauline-Lutheran
idea of justification. Wellhausen and Gunkel gave Tillich insight into the Old Testament.
157
Tillich‘s political attitude was influenced by the spirit of prophetic criticism from
Martin does draw a conclusion from the biographical data of Tillich‘s church
service and duty as a chaplain in World War I. Tillich served as a chaplain in the
German army from September 1914 to September 1918. Martin (1963:20) points out
Tillich saw World War I as a disaster for Europe. The unity of the German nation was
a myth. Germany was divided into conflicting classes. Further, the proletariat viewed
the church as the ally of the ruling classes. The conflict between the masses and the ruling
class led to the revolution of 1918. The result was Imperial Germany collapsed. Martin
(1963:20) argues: ‗Tillich in deep sympathy with social aspects of the short-lived
revolution. He became one of the founders of German religious socialism; and as one
of the major theoreticians of the movement, developed some of its key concepts‘. Niebuhr
(1956:10) interprets Tillich‘s The Religious Situation as a revolt ‗against the spirit of
Tillich became involved in the social movements (Martin 1963:20). Tillich incorporated
158
Marx‘s thought into his life and teaching. Tillich (1956:122-125) writes:
Among the ideas which betray the true character of capitalist society is its conception
of the state. In the pre-capitalist period of the state as the law giving and law-enforcing
community possessed the unction and sanctity which naturally belongs to it when the
whole community regards it as the fundamental structure of the social life, determining
all aspects of the social culture….[T]he capitalist conception of the state may be
characterized as its complete secularization….[T]he vital force which supported the
capitalistic state was nationalism….[I]n…socialism….[I]ts…contradiction.
He developed the concept of the kairos which was espoused during the regular meetings
Ludwig Feuerbach who lived from 1804-1872 thought the ‗true sense of
was an appeal to the German people to accept Socialism rather than Nazism. Tillich
sought justice in the realms of economics and politics. Tillich wanted a meaningful
society that would make the question of Marxism to Christianity an open question
(Stumme 1977:xxvi).
1914 to 1918 deeply affected Tillich‘s views. He saw the unity of the German nation
as a myth. Germany was experiencing class warfare. The proletariat distrusted the
church and the ruling classes. It was conflict between the masses and the ruling classes
that led to the revolution of 1918. Tillich became a religious socialist. He was one of
the founders and theoreticians of the religious socialist movement. His books The
religious socialism. The Religious Situation was written against the spirit of the
capitalist society. His book The Socialist Decision was an appeal to the German people to
5:3 Marx
writes:
That Paul Tillich was interested in the thought of Karl Marx is widely known among
Tillich scholars. Tillich‘s early German writings on socialism, his sympathy for
the social critiques of religion, and his efforts to promulgate a religious-socialist
movement in Germany are all evidences of his debt to Karl Marx. Tillich was
deeply influenced by Marx‘s critique of capitalism, and he used that critique
in his numerous early assessments of capitalism as the basic source of economic
injustice in the modern world.
Tillich consistently refused to join the ranks of those who dismiss Marx as a
diabolical thinker who unleased the wave of communist terror upon the earth.
Quite the contrary, he saw many key insights in Marx‘s thought as having
relevance for the twentieth century because Marx interpreted history ―in a
way which makes even his erroneous prophecies significant.
For Marx, too, being must move in the direction of that which is demanded,
so that the demand does not remain abstract and impotent. In his analysis of
capitalist society these basic presuppositions receive concrete application and
are elaborated by means of scientific methods. The structure of capitalism
itself drives towards its transmutation into socialism, towards the classless society.
Tillich (1977:160) took seriously Marx‘s words on ‗another possibility: chaos‘. Tillich
(ibid:160-161) writes:
160
If, in the encounter between the bourgeoisie and political romanticism, the bourgeois
principle should once again gain a complete victory, the increasingly severe crises
would make chaos virtually invevitable. If on the other hand political romanticism
and, with it, militant nationalism proves victorious, a self-annihilating struggle of
the European peoples is inevitable. The salvation of European society from a
return to barbarism lies in the hands of socialism.
Tillich (1936:66 in ibid:29) argues for the need to appropriate, criticize, and
Tillich felt that there are far-reaching analogies between Marx‘s interpretation
of history and the perspective of the Old Testament prophets. Both saw history
in dynamic terms, as a struggle between good and evil powers. Humanity is
called to identify itself with the historical group that carries on the fight for good.
Redemption is the conquest and extermination of evil in history. In this sense
Marx, like the prophets, set himself against the ―nonhistorical‖ interpretations
of history which attempt to understand history through categories of nature or
space.
Carey (ibid:30) concludes: ‗Tillich recognized, of course, that Marx had shifted the
insisted nevertheless that Marx shows a greater affinity to the prophets than do most
Carey (2002:30) points out: ‗Tillich gives priority to Marx‘s view of justice‘.
Carey argues that economics as the basis for historical change is an oversimplification
(ibid:30). Yet Carey (ibid:30-31) admits the ‗significance of the economic factor in life,
and in being aware of the physical needs of persons‘. Tillich saw in Marx the prophetic
that allows for ‗decision and involvement‘ (ibid:31). Carey (2002:32) argues:
developed by all societies to justify the status quo. Marx developed this point as a
part of his attack on Idealism; as opposed to appeals to a transcendent order, he
wanted to stress the primacy of humanity‘s actual situation. Ideologies that are
presented as eternal truths, independent of humanity‘s concrete situation, distort the
actual human situation, and keep us from taking the necessary steps to improve our
conditions. This, too, Tillich saw as a valid insight, and he appropriated this into
his own understanding of history.
Carey (Tillich 1936:63 in ibid:32) quotes Tillich: ‗I owe to Marx, first of all, the insight
into the ideological character, not only of idealism but of all systems of thought, religious
as well as profane, which as the servants of power hinder, even though unconsciously,
the more righteous form of social reality‘. Tillich (1938:116-117 in ibid:32) admitted
the accuracy of Marx‘s thought that religion was a ideology of the privileged classes.
Carey (Tillich 1936:192-194 in ibid:34) makes an interesting point on the need for a
Further, Carey makes another interesting point on Tillich which is beyond the scope of this
thesis on the German years. Carey (ibid:23) writes: ‗What is less well known, even
among Tillich scholars, is that Tillich had a lifelong interest in Marx and Marxism‘.
Tillich‘s statement of Marxian thought has always been contingent on the dialectical
which combines a yes and a no. The positive element on Marx‘s thought in Tillich‘s life
162
was ‗on prophetic, humanistic, and realistic elements‘ (Martin 1963:22). The no or the
negative element of Marxian thought in Tillich‘s life was ‗in Marx‘s analysis, polemics,
and propaganda‘ (ibid:22). Carey‘s conclusion on Marx‘s influence is important for our
thesis. Carey (ibid:35) writes: ‗There is no doubt that Karl Marx exerted a greater influence
on Tillich than anyone else concerning political consciousness and the interpretation
from the American years 1933-1965 which is beyond the scope of this thesis. Carey
(ibid:34) argues that Tillich felt Marx was mistaken in his thinking on the proletariat.
Marx made the rise of the proletariat ‗the focal point of history‘. Carey (2002:29-35)
agrees that Tillich‘s thinking on Karl Marx was always dialectical. This was a combination
of both positive and negative elements. The positive would be that Tillich saw in Marx the
voice of the Old Testament prophets (ibid:29). Tillich admired Marx‘s view of justice
with the call for the need for a just society (ibid:30). Tillich admired Marx‘s historical
approach with the need for decision and involvement (ibid:31). Tillich agreed with Marx
on Marx‘s criticism of ideologies that were oppressive to the human situation (ibid:32).
The negative for Tillich would be Marx‘s failure to distinguish the divine from human
ecclesiastical expressions. Marx‘s interpretation of history did not allow for the kairos, his
interpretation of history was too utopian, a wrong emphasis on the proletariat, and some of
Marx‘s thought was not relevant for the twentieth century (ibid:33-34). Carey (ibid:34)
lists Marx‘s irrelevant thought as follows: ‗Marx‘s theories of work and value, accumulation
Marx‘s critique of capitalism that Tillich used in his early writings. Tillich pointed
out that capitalism was the cause of economic injustice in the world. Tillich saw in
Marx the spirit of the Old Testament prophets. Tillich argued for the need to continue
the dialogue with Marx. Tillich admitted his debt to Marx. Karl Marx had a greater
influence on Tillich than anyone else in both Tillich‘s political view and his interpretation
of history.
5:4 Art
Tillich became interested in painting during his time as a chaplain in World War I.
Palmer (Pauck and Pauck 1976:51 in Palmer 1984:3) writes:: ‗For Tillich‘s
appreciation of painting began in the trenches, during the First World War and thus
belongs to the most shattering and formative period of his life. During his four years
Amiens and Aisne-Marne, received the Iron Cross, sustained two nervous breakdowns,
and emerged with a consciousness of suffering and death from which, so his
this time painting provided him with his principal means of relaxation and escape, an
inevitable reaction‘. Tillich (1966:27-28 in ibid:3) tells that this was due ‗to the horror,
ugliness and destructiveness of war. My delight even in the poor reproductions obtainable
at the military bookstores developed into a systematic study of the history of art. And out
164
of this study came the experience of art‘. Palmer (ibid:3) relates another experience
that made a great impact on Tillich during Tillich‘s last furlough of World War I.
During his last furlough of the war, Tillich visited the Kaiser Friedrich Museum
in Berlin. There he saw Botticelli‘s ‗Madonna with Singing Angels‘, the
picture hanging alone on a wall opposite the entrance. The setting itself
was dramatic and the painting‘s impact on him enormous: ever afterwards
Tillich was to speak of it as a moment of ‗revelation‘, as an experience in
which he had been grasped not only by the beauty and power of visual art
but by the reality of the absolute.
Berlin from 1919 to 1924. He tried to relate religion to other subjects of which art
was one. Tillich (ibid:13) continues: ‗Revolutionary art came into the foreground,
theology of culture was also a theology of art. Art had a great influence on Tillich
interest in art. Tillich longed for beauty amidst the horrors of World War I. He sought
relief and escape in the paintings of the military bookshops. Tillich‘s interest in art and
5:5 Freud
During the German years, Tillich thought the ‗new depth psychology of Freud‘
165
‗a little short of revelatory‘ (Martin 1963:23). Freud was another intellectual influence
upon Tillich. Tillich had been introduced to Freud‘s work by Eckart Von Sydow
(Pauck & Pauck 1976:75). The Paucks (ibid:223) tell us that Tillich‘s interest in
Freud grew ‗which he had nourished since 1919‘. Tillich lectured ‗on subjects which
included the relation of religion to politics, art, philosophy, depth psychology, and
sociology‘ (Tillich 1967:41). This was when Tillich was at the University of Berlin as
‗I presented in my lectures on the philosophy of religion, its history and its structure.
The situation during those years in Berlin was very favorable for such an enterprise….
Psychoanalytic ideas spread and produced a consciousness of realities which had been
psychological terminology and Luther used theological concepts, both pointed toward
the fundamental human dilemma—the darker regions of the psyche have a multitude of
maneuvers for keeping themselves unknown‘. Cooper (ibid:21) continues: ‗It is Tillich‘s
understanding of the demonic which draws deeply from both Freud and Marx. Freud reinstated
the psychological bondage of the will, which seems to reflect a kind of demonic activity‘.
Cooper (ibid:21) concludes: ‗Marx, on the other hand, describes the undercurrents of class
conflict and economic injustice which represent social demons‘. Tillich (1966:69 in Cooper
The only sufficient term I found was in the New Testament use of the ―demonic,‖
166
which is in stories about Jesus: similar to being possessed. That means a force,
under a force, which is stronger than the individual good will. And so I used that
term. Of course I emphasized very much I don‘t mean in a mythological sense-as
little demons or a personal Satan running around the world-but I mean it as structures
which are ambiguous, both to a certain extent creative, but ultimately destructive.
I had to find a term which covers the transpersonal power which takes hold of men
and society.
revolt‘ (Cooper 2006:66). This was against the philosophy of consciousness which reached its
(ibid:66). Tillich (1964:116) adds: ‗now through Freud‘ came ‗ methodological scientific
words‘. Cooper (2006:66) expands and clarifies Tillich‘s words: ‗Freud is especially
power of the irrational unconsciousness. While previous thinkers had offered insightful
In brief, Tillich found in Freud confirmation for his existentialism. Freud‘s thought
167
was taken up with the human psyche. Tillich tried to relate religion to depth psychology when
he was a Privatdozent at the University of Berlin from 1919 to 1924. Freud‘s psychoanalysis
the same revolt against Hegel. Both existentialism and psychoanalysis were concerned with
man‘s estrangement. Tillich‘s understanding of the demonic was drawn from Freud.
5:6 Heidegger
intellectual influence of Heidegger ‗upon his thinking: ‗of a prime order of magnitude‘.
Achtemeier (1969:27) writes: ‗the fundamental question with which Heidegger sets
out to deal with is the question of ―Being‖ ‘. Godbieba (1995:1) adds: ‗Any attempt on a
discussion about the religious status of God in postmodern philosophy of religion must
reckon with Martin Heidegger‘s critique of ontotheology and its effect of questioning
of the identification of God with Being, an identification ―goes without saying‖ for
centuries is the crucial step in the attempt to overcome metaphysics, and also influences
understanding of the relation between philosophy and theology. The lectures of Martin
Heidegger given at Marburg, the impression of which on my Marburg students and upon
some of my colleagues I experienced; then his writing Sein Und Zeit (Being and Time)‘.
existentialism. This intellectual influence reaches to both the nineteenth and the
and Sartre in the twentieth, as one of the great formative influences in the evolution
of his own thinking‘. Baron (2003:1) admits these intellectual influences: ‗Tillich‘s
thought was guided by ontological/existential categories‘. The proof of this came out
presented God as the ‗Ground of Our Being‘. His argument is that Robinson borrowed
this concept from Tillich and others. Le Mahieu (ibid:7) continues: ‗Robinson adopted
5:7 Husserl
Martin (1963:19) acknowledges this intellectual source: ‗Aside from Heidegger, the
most significance for the philosophy of religion‘. Martin (ibid:19) continues: ‗For Tillich,
Husserl‘s doctrine was the most satisfying confirmation of what he claims to have learned
from Kant and Fichte, and to Husserl‘s phenomenology he owes, as we shall observe, much
Tillich had a romantic relation to nature. Tillich (1952:3-4) admits his early
what has been challenged as the romantic trend in my feeling and thinking‘. Tillich
relation. It is the reason for the tremendous emotional impact that Schelling‘s philosophy
of nature made upon me- although I was well aware that this philosophy was
of the participation of nature in the process of fall and salvation‘. Tillich (ibid:4)
points to three possible causes that account for his romanticism to nature. Tillich (ibid:4)
writes: ‗First, I find the actual communication with nature daily in my early years, in my
later years for several months of every year‘. Tillich (ibid:5) adds: ‗A second cause of the
romantic relation to nature is the impact of poetry. The German poetic literature, even aside
from the romantic school, is full of expressions of nature mysticism. There are verses of
Goethe, Holderlin, Novalis, Eichendorff, Nietzsche, George, and Rilke which never have
ceased to move me as deeply as they did when I first heard them‘. Tillich (ibid:5)
continues:
A third cause of this attitude toward nature came out of my Lutheran background.
Theologians, know that one of the points of disagreement between the two wings of
the Continental Reformation, the Lutheran and the Reformed, was the so called
―Extra Calvinisticum,‖ the doctrine that the finite is not capable of the infinite. (non
capax infiniti), and that consequently in Christ the two natures, the divine and the
human, remain outside each other. Against this doctrine the Lutherans asserted the
―Infra Lutheranum‖; namely, the view that the finite is capable of the infinite, and
consequently that in Christ there is a mutual indwelling of the two natures. The
difference means that on Lutheran ground the vision of the presence of the infinite
in everything finite was theologically affirmed, that nature mysticism was possible
and real, whereas on Calvinistic ground such an attitude is suspect of pantheism and
the divine transcendence is understood in a way which for a Lutheran is suspect of
deism.
171
Tillich (ibid:5) concludes: ‗Romanticism means not only a special relation to nature; it
means also a special relation to history. To grow up in towns in which every stone is witness
of a period many centuries past produces a feeling of history, not as a matter of knowledge,
Tillich (ibid:4) admits the tremendous emotional impact that Schelling‘s Christian
philosophy of nature made upon him. Tillich‘s (1936:7) own autobiography bears out the
truth of this point: ‗Schelling‘s Philosophy of Nature, which I read in a state of intoxication,
as it were, surrounded by the beauties of nature became for me the direct expression of this
feeling for nature‘. Schelling was the subject of Tillich‘s doctoral dissertation and his
Licentiate in Theology. Tillich (1966:47) writes: ‗I read through his collected works several
times, and eventually made his work the subject of my dissertations for the degree of Doctor
of Philosophy and Licentiate of Theology‘. Walter Leibrecht (1972:25) writes: ‗But follows
…Schelling where he visualizes both otherness and being dynamically united in ultimate
reality. It is the awareness of this problem which has led Tillich to vernture a new synthesis,
witnessed to the final identity in the ultimate ground‘. Hutchinson (1953:138) draws our
the ‗Existentialist protest‘ long before Kierkegaard. Tillich denotes the importance of
Schelling‘s work in his work, On The Boundary. Tillich (1966:56) highlights Schelling‘s
Christian philosophy of existence as one of the factors that caused him to accept the
existential position. Schelling‘s philosophy of existence was derived from Jacob Bohme.
172
Mysticism had an influence on Schelling and German Idealism, and through Schelling,
again on Irrationalism and the philosophy of life of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries‘.
The Paucks (1976:175) add that Tillich was a Christian thinker who held the religious views
of Schelling. Tillich (1936:31) admitted that Schelling had become the basis for this thought
and development. Falk (1961:1-28) argues that Tillich relied heavily on Schelling‘s The Ages
of the World. Falk (ibid:26-27) is referring to Tillich‘s second dissertation for the degree of
metaphysical theology to be Tillich‘s position. Tillich (1936:35) admits that Schelling had
become the basis for his theonomous philosophy. Tillich (ibid:37) was able to interpret
Nietzsche‘s philosophy of life because of Schelling. Tillich (ibid:37) writes: ‗The historical
dependence of the philosophy of life on Schelling made it easy for me to approach it‘.
collected works through several times as a student and wrote two dissertations (1911 and 1912)
dealing with Schelling‘s thought‘. Wheat (ibid:214) argues that Tillich outlined Schelling‘s
thought ‗in mysticism and theism‘. God is man who was mediated to Tillich by Schelling
Tillich (ibid:225) was ‗centrally occupied with the principle of identity‘ based on
The concept of God was likewise a rich area for Tillich (see, for example, his
Systematic Theology, volume 1) and is obviously an area in which he made a
major contribution to twentieth-century theology. Tillich, however, drew on
a wide variety of sources as he tried to understand the problem of God. He was
indebted to the German idealistic philosopher Friedrich Schelling.
Carey misses the essence of Schelling‘s Christian thought. He does argue for Tillich‘s
debt to Schelling which is important for our chapter on the influences on Tillich during
the German years (1886 to 1933). Carey (ibid:21) adds: ‗Scholars have tended
Tillich‘s daily communication with nature, German poetry, and his Lutheran background
account for his romanticism to nature. Romanticism meant as well a interest in history.
Tillich attributes this to the medieval towns in which he grew up. Schelling‘s Christian
subject of both Tillich‘s doctoral dissertation, and his Licentitate of Theology. Schelling‘s
views made it possible for Tillich to accept the existential position. Tillich‘s own
admission is that Schelling had become the basis for his thought and development.
Paucks, Falk, Re Manning, Wheat, Scharlemann, and Carey argue for Tillich‘s reliance
on Schelling‘s thought.
174
5:9 Bohme
Another intellectual influence on Paul Tillich was Jacob Bohme. Tillich (1966:75)
calls him the ‗philosophical spokesman for German mysticism‘. Bohme‘s thought was an
elaboration of mystical Lutheranism (ibid:75). It was through Bohme that Lutheran mysticism
influenced both Schelling, German Idealism, and in turn Tillich. Schelling‘s work was
derived from Bohme. Tillich‘s work was derived from Schelling‘s Christian philosophy
(ibid:75). Adams (1965:32) writes: ‗The concepts ―ground‖ and ―abyss‖ stem from Jacob
Boehme.. As we shall observe again and again, Boehme is a major source for certain
crucial elements in Tillich‘s outlook‘. Carey (2002:14) writes: ‗He was indebted…,
Christian mysticism influenced the thinking of Schelling, German Idealism, and Tillich.
Tillich derived his concepts of ground and abyss from Bohme. Bohme was another
5:10 Barth
Tillich stood with Barth in the dialectical movement (Horton 1952:26). Horton
(ibid:26-27) writes:
Horton (ibid:27) states: ‗His article in Kant-Studien, XXVII (1922), where he speaks (p.447)
of his ―spiritual comradeship‖ with Barth and Gogarten in a theology of ―paradox‖ to which
they and he had independently been led. Barth, Tillich, and Otto Piper belonged to the group
of theologians called progressives after World War I‘. Horton (ibid:28) clarifies for us:
Tillich rejected any intellectual influence that would have been derived from either Karl
Barth or Emmanuel Hirsch. It was both Hirsch and Barth who opposed socialism (Tillich
1966:76). Adams (1965:19) argues that Tillich ‗radically criticized Barthianism‘. Tillich
thought Barth deficient because of his reliance on the thinking of Immanuel Kant. Kant‘s
‗categorical imperative‘ for Tillich was too abstract. It gave no importance to facing ‗the
176
present concretely‘ (ibid:20). Cremer points to an article that Tillich wrote in 1923, in
which he uses both Marx and Nietzsche to refute Barth. Cremer (1995:295) writes:
In examination, any religious sentimentalism with Karl Barth was short lived.
Tillich rejected Barth‘s supernaturalism. Further, Barth opposed the religious socialism
which Tillich advocated. Tillich became a radical opponent of Karl Barth and his
neo-orthodox theology.
5:11 Hegel
Tillich uses both Feuerbach and Marx to refute Hegelianism‘s lack of social
concern (Adams 1965:22). Tillich‘s (1966:56) ontology is not derived from the Hegelian
categories. Leibrecht (1972:25) argues that Tillich did follow Hegel‘s thinking. This was
‗in terms of eternal separation of spirit from itself and its eternal return to itself within the
divine ‗ (ibid:25). Leibrecht (ibid:25) develops his argument by saying: ‗His thought comes
to Hegel again in his deeper insights penetrating to an essential metaphysics in describing the
essential structures of being‘. Tillich‘s use of such terminology such as ‗synthesis‘ demonstrates
177
the intellectual influence of Hegel upon his life and thought (ibid:25). Wheat (1970:102)
argues for many of Tillich‘s concepts to be derived from Hegel. The concept of
self-transcendence that Tillich uses is also used by Hegel (ibid:102). Tillich‘s thought
emphasizes the concept of the dialectic. Tillich spoke of Hegel‘s concept of the ‗great
synthesis‘. It was Hegel who put forward the idea of thesis, anti-thesis, and synthesis (ibid:105).
John Powell Clayton (1980:132-133) recognized Tillich‘s use of Hegel‘s thought. Clayton
(ibid:135) adds: ‗Even though Tillich‘s theory of culture is not simply Hegelian, he was
nonetheless much influenced by the tradition in which culture was principally Geistesleben‘.
criticized the idealist tradition, Tillich remained tangled to some extent in its web‘.
Hegelian ideas remained popular in Germany after 1860 (Bentley 1999:86). Rowse
primal ‗Idea‘. Hegel analyzed art, and aesthetics. He taught earlier at the University of
Frankfurt where Tillich was a professor from 1929 to 1933 (Harris 1996:34). Stumme
(1977:xviii) argues that it was Tillich‘s ‗intention to return to the Hegelian sources of the
Marxist dialectic and to reconstruct socialist theory on this basis‘. Tillich rejected Hegel‘s
political views. Tillich viewed Hegel as an agent of the German state. He (ibid:80) writes:
his ambiguous Christology, was the most important alliance of bourgeosie and feudalism‘.
Another prelude to the things to come occurred in the period between my student
178
years and the beginning of the First World War. It was the encounter with Schelling‘s
second period, especially with his so-called ―positive philosophy.‖ Here lies the
philosophically decisive break with Hegel, and the beginning of that movement
which is today Existentialism. I was ready for it when it appeared in full strength after
the First World War, and I saw it in the light of the general revolt against Hegel‘s system
of reconciliation which occurred in the decades after Hegel‘s death, and which through
Kierkegaard, Marx, and Nietzsche has become decisive for the destiny of the twentieth
century.
Niebuhr (1952:217) argues for the difference between Tillich and Hegel based on Tillich‘s
Paul Tillich‘s magnum opus, his Systematic Theology, of which unfortunately only the
first volume is available at the time this analysis of his work is attempted, will become a
landmark in history of modern theology for two reasons. First, his ontological speculations
are more rigorous and include all of the disciplines of culture more imaginatively than
anything which has been done in the realm of philosophy of religion or natural theology
in our day or in many decades. Secondly, it distinguishes itself from the natural theology
inspired by Hegel and Kant in the past two centuries by a fuller appreciation of the limits
of reason in penetrating to the ultimate mystery or in comprehending the mystery of human
existence.
Tillich (1964:84) writes: ‗Schelling calls the claim of Hegel‘s rational system to embrace not
only the real, the What, but also its reality, the That, a ―deception.‖ No ‗merely logical
process is also a process of real becoming‘. John Carey (2002:14) claims Tillich ‗was indebted
…to Georg Hegel as he combined the categories of biblical faith with issues raised by Western
philosophy. Tillich felt that one could grasp the mystery of the Divine through the Judeo-
In evaluation, Tillich and Hegel may have used similar terminology. Tillich had
studied Hegel‘s thought. Tillich viewed Hegel as an agent of the German state. He
perceived Hegel as a promoter of the alliance between the bourgeoisie and feudalism.
179
Tillich maintained that Schelling‘s thought made it possible to relinquish Hegel between
his student years and the beginning of World War I. Those who promote Hegel‘s
5:12 Nietzsche
Tillich‘s words:
It was in the name of life that Nietzsche fought against the ―nihilism‖ of the
technical culture. Many followed him in all spheres of spiritual creativity.
He and the movement of which he is the most conspicuous symbol saw more
clearly than Kierkegaard and Marx the deepest roots of the dehumanizing and
depersonalizing implications of modern society.
life‘. This is the ability of one to affirm one‘s own existence in life (ibid:142). Nuovo
The ecstatic influence of existence so prevalent after the war as a reaction against the
wartime years of death and hunger made Nietzsche‘s affirmation of life very attractive.
Because it is, at least partly, historically rooted in Schelling‘s thought, I could readily
accept it. I might well have developed my philosophy along these lines, incorporating
pagan elements instead of Jewish and Catholic motifs; but the experience of the German
revolution of 1918 decisively redirected my concerns toward a sociologically based and
politically oriented philosophy of history.
180
Nietzsche‘s thought was acceptable to Tillich because it was ‗partly, historically rooted
in Schelling‘s thought‘ (ibid:54). Carey (2002:55) adds: ‗In this typology Tillich clearly
life, and the creative were acceptable to Tillich because of its historical roots in Schelling.
Nietzsche‘s thought was evaluated based on Schelling. Tillich sided with the philosophers
of life.
5:13 Buber
Diamond (1967:244) argues Buber and Tillich had ‗much in common in the way
of background and perspective‘. Novak (1992:159) emphasises: ‗As a model for Jewish-
Christian dialogue, this role that Buber played for Tillich‘s own thought is not to be
underestimated‘. Novak refers to an incident that took place back in the 1920‘s in Germany
at ‗a conference of religious socialists‘. Tillich had wanted to change the name God and find
a word to replace it. Buber replied: ‗Aber Gott ist ein Urwort! (God is a primordial word!)‘
Wherever the question of the language of the Christian gospel is taken seriously,
for example in the Neuwerk-Kreis, and in the magazine of the same name, edited by
my old friend and fellow-combatant, Herman Schafft, great difficulties arise. It
181
is certain that the original religious terminology, as it is used in the Bible and in the
liturgies of the Ancient church, cannot be supplanted. There are religious original
or archetypal words (Urworte) of mankind, as Martin Buber remarked to me some
time ago. But these original or archetypal words have been robbed of their original
power by our objective thinking, and the scientific conception of the world, and thus,
have become subject to dissolution. In face of what the archetypal word ―God‖ means,
rational criticism is powerless. In face of an objectively existing God, atheism is right.
A situation is hopeless and meaningless in which the speaker means the original word,
and the listener hears the objective word. Thus, we may understand the proposal which
is meant symbolically rather than literally, that the church impose a thirty-year silence
upon all of its archetypal words. But if it should do this, as it did in a few instances,
it would be necessary to develop a new terminology.
and the question of the language of the Christian gospel. Buber stimulated Tillich‘s thinking
5:14 Troeltsch
thought as the basis for the furtherance and development of his own thinking. Tillich
(1966:54-55) writes:
My study of Troeltsch had paved the way for this change of direction. I clearly remember
the statement he made during his first Berlin lecture on the philosophy of history,
claiming that his was the first philosophical treatment of this subject at the University of
Berlin since Hegel‘s death. Although we were to a great extent agreed about the problems
involved, I repudiated his idealistic point of departure. Troeltsch;s idealism made it
impossible for him to overcome what he called historicism, against which he fought.
Historicism could be overcome only by a generation that had been forced to make
fundamental historical decisions. In light of the necessity of facing history squarely
-a demand that is both grounded in and limited by the Christian paradox-I sought to
develop a philosophy of history that could become also a philosophy of religious
182
socialism.
Tillich rejected Troeltsch‘s idealism. Tillich developed a philosophy of history which lent
draws a further clarification between Troeltsch and Tillich. Siegfried (ibid:68-69) writes:
The spiritual shock produced by the catastrophes of the First World War drove members of
the older as well as the younger generation in Germany to look for a radical reorientation in
all realms of life. This is true of the liberal theologians who much earlier had created the
Evangelical Social Congress, and who, at this critical moment, tried to transform it into a
tool for a democratic and social renewal. Men like Rade, the editor of Die Christliche
Welt (the German counterpart of The Christian Century), Adolph Harnack, Ernst Troeltsch,
and Rudolf Otto belonged to their group. But the younger generation, of whom Tillich
was one of the leaders, reached beyond the limited goal of a political and social reform. The
reality and power of the socialist movement grasped their imagination. They joined
the attacks on the bourgeois world and did so just at the moment in which the socialist
movement, after having been excluded in imperial Germany from any participation in
political responsibility, was obliged to take over the full responsibility in the most tragic
183
Tillich represented something more magnificent the splendor of religious socialism explained
5:15 Luther
Horton (1952:27) argues that Tillich ‗owes much to Luther‘. The similarities
between Luther and Tillich are those that fit within Tillich‘s religious socialism. Tillich and
Luther thought human nature to be ‗finite freedom‘ (Siegfried 1952:81). A further comparision
between Tillich and Luther would be ‗Luther‘s intuition of the relativity of all social orders‘
(ibid:81). Tillich and Luther spoke on the subject of ethics. Tillich‘s comments compared
to Luther are ‗in broad and general terms‘ (Thomas 1952:92). Luther‘s ‗justification by faith‘
and the authority of the Bible‘ though relative, for Tillich was ‗the ‗New Being‘ in Jesus as the
Christ‘ (ibid:94). Carey (2002:9) points out four areas of ‗affinities between Luther and
Tillich‘. Carey (ibid:9-20) lists the theological method, concept of God, the human condition,
The issue of theological method needs to be discussed primarily because of the study by
Wayne G. Johnson, Theological Method in Luther and Tillich. This book was Johnson‘s
doctoral dissertation at the University of Iowa and argues the thesis that there is a general
184
similarity between Luther‘s theological method and that of Tillich. It is an open question
in Luther scholarship whether Luther in fact had a clearly defined theological method.
Johnson argues, however, that the key for Luther as a theologian was his understanding of
law and gospel….[W]hat evidence…Tillich‘s method of correlation is in fact similar to
(or derives from) Luther‘s working hypothesis of law and gospel?...I do not think Johnson
establishes this case in his book, and in his…Systematic Theology Tillich never refers
to law-and-gospel scheme.
Carey (ibid:10) argues that the Law was God‘s commands in the Decalogue and at other
places in the Pentateuch. Luther felt as well it was ‗that natural law of God…broadly written
on the minds of all persons everywhere‘. The Law had two uses one was civil and the other
useage was theological (ibid:10). Carey (ibid:11) elaborates on Tillich‘s theological method:
Tillich took the problem of theological method more seriously than did Luther because
he struggled with some ambiguities Luther did not feel. Tillich was also more interested
than Luther ever was in the philosophical issues related to the nature of theological language
and religious knowledge. In a formal sense, I would argue that Tillich is actually closer to
Thomas Aquinas than to Luther in theological method.
Tillich and Luther are similar in their theological method because: ‗Both thinkers, for example,
are persuaded that theology is tied to the human experience and that in our experience we can
know the saving reality of God‘ (ibid:12). Further, both Tillich and Luther believed that
theology is existential dealing with the ‗profound issues of life‘ (ibid:12). Carey (ibid:12)
points to the concept of God. Luther argued against the rationalistic concept of God that
God was ‗sheer will‘(ibid:13). Luther believed the theme of the sovereignty of God, God‘s
presence through creation, God‘s absolute power, God‘s attributes both hidden and revealed.
Luther spoke against idols. Luther‘s problems dealt with the Medieval church and Rome‘s
authority (ibid:13-14). The concept of God was ‗a rich area for Tillich‘ (ibid:14). Carey
(ibid:14) adds: ‗In his approach to ―God language,‖ Tillich was clearly concerned to move
185
beyond the inadequate theistic understandings of God (that is, God as a person or as a being)
and to press for a larger and more comprehensive understandings of God. Tillich
understood that the biblical concept of transcendence needed to be replaced with more adequate
metaphors that can do justice to a scientific understanding of the universe‘. The concept of
the demonic was involved in Tillich‘s concept of God. Carey (ibid:14) writes: ‗Tillich insisted
that the Divine contained within itself the element of nonbeing as well as being‘. Carey
nonbeing, but is an insight through which Tillich thought one could understand the elements
of mystery and depth in the Deity. There is an irrational dimension in the Divine‘. Carey
(ibid:15) concludes: ‗Tillich felt a clear affinity with Luther concerning the irrational, hidden,
mysterious dimension of God‘. Luther‘s theme ‗God alone is God‘ is seen in Tillich‘s concept
the ‗Protestant Principle‘ (ibid:15). A third similarity between Tillich and Luther is ‗in their
understanding of the human situation‘ (ibid:16). Luther believed in the total ‗fallenness‘
of man (ibid:16). Luther thought man was ‗enslaved by demonic forces‘ (ibid:16). Man‘s
will was not able ‗to cooperate with God‘ (ibid:16). Tillich described the human situation
by the terms ‗estrangement‘ and ‗alienation‘ (ibid:17). The fourth area of similarity between
Luther and Tillich is in the area of justification (ibid:18). Carey (ibid18) writes: ‗Briefly put,
Luther—drawing heavily on the apostle Paul—felt that our deliverance from sin is a free act
of God‘. Carey (ibid:19) writes of Tillich‘s thought on justification: ‗Tillich stands very close
In evaluating, similarities of thought do exist between Luther and Tillich. These fit
186
Tillich‘s religious socialism. These similarities are human nature as finite freedom, Luther‘s
intuition of relativity of social orders, Luther‘s justification by faith is Tillich‘s New Being
in Jesus and the Protestant principle, theological method, the concept of God, and the human
condition. Tillich and Luther thought theology tied to human experience. Theology is
existential. Luther argued against the rationalistic concept of God. Luther and Tillich‘s
affinity can be seen as well in their concept of the irrational, the hidden, and the mysterious.
man‘s fallenness. Tillich used the terms estrangement and alienation to describe the same.
Ratschow argues that ‗Tillich was able to transcend the problems of his time‘ (Carey
2002:135). It was Tillich‘s ability to assess and make value judgments which were based on his
historical context of Germany in the 1920‘s and 1930‘s (ibid:39). Carey‘s (ibid:39) point is
well taken: ‗It is important, however, to note how Tillich appraised the strengths and
weaknesses of the theological left and right, and how he assessed both in the light of the
Christian claim‘. Carr (1961:76) adds that moral judgments occur within ‗a conceptual
framework which is itself the creation of history‘. Tillich (1952:13-14) argues in terms
of environment and social forces rather than personality or his ability to make value judgments.
Ratschow (ibid:8) continues: ‗Tillich identified himself with everything he met….It was
these identifications which led to the consequence that everyone who met him believed
himself to be quite specifically and quite exclusively the one about whom Tillich was
concerned and that never had he been so well understood by another human being as here
by Tillich‘. Ratschow (ibid:8) elaborates further: ‗In such identifications one thing was
quite decisive. Personal meetings with Tillich always ran their course completely without
any aggression on Tillich‘s side‘. Ratschow (ibid:8) adds: ‗That is also a striking feature in his
On this point, one must indeed say that Tillich wrote his apologetic theology strictly
for his time. But in doing this, he transcended the questions of the time toward their
solution. In them, he arrived at concepts of so great human depth that they can be
intelligible to every time, even though what is involved is a humanity and a human
spirituality which as such can prove to be time bound
In analyzing the material, the problems of Tillich‘s time influenced him. Tillich
was able to analyze the problems of his generation. He provided a working solution for
these problems. This became for Tillich his destiny. Tillich was very personable in his
identifications with others. Tillich was focused and devoted to those he met. Tillich wrote
188
an apologetic theology which Ratschow thought good only for Tillich‘s German generations.
5:17 Summary
The views of Kierkegaard and Marx influenced Tillich‘s existential and political
theology. Tillich‘s political theology was formed as well from the Old Testament prophets.
It was their spirit of prophetic criticism that Tillich saw in Marx. Schelling‘s Christian
philosophy became the basis for Tillich‘s Christian theology. Tillich‘s books The Religious
religious socialism.
Tillich to accept the views of Karl Marx. His army experience was the beginning of
his theology of art. He longed for beauty and an escape amidst the horrors and suffering
of Fichte and Kant. Husserl aided Tillich‘s understanding of the nature of philosophical
reflection. Tillich‘s greatest influence was his romanticism to nature, and the Christian
of Karl Barth. Hegel and Tillich may have used similar terminology. Hegel was viewed
by Tillich as a promoter of the alliance between the bourgeoisie and feudalism. Tillich
was able to discard Hegel because of Schelling‘s thought. Nietzsche‘s thought was
accepted by Tillich because it had historical roots in Schelling. Tillich sided with the
philosophers of life. Buber was a stimulus to Tillich‘s thinking on the language of the
Christian gospel. Troeltsch helped Tillich define what his philosophy of history should
Tillich can only be seen in terms of similarities. These similarities are those which fit
Schelling and Bohme had the greatest influence on Tillich in determining his Christian
theological views. Tillich maintained that Schelling had discovered existentialism long before
Kierkegaard. Marx had the greatest influence on Tillich in terms of determining Tillich‘s
political theology. The sequence of our thesis moves now to consider the Tillich legacy from