0% found this document useful (0 votes)
77 views14 pages

Bayesian Methods in Applied Econometrics, Or, Why Econometrics Should Always and Everywhere Be Bayesian

- Bayesian inference provides probability statements conditioned on observations, allowing characterization of uncertainty about parameters given observed data. This is useful for decision-making. - Objections to Bayesian methods, such as subjectivity, are untrue or overstated. Bayesian inference is no more assumption-laden than frequentist asymptotics. While computationally challenging, Bayesian thinking provides a clearer starting point for data analysis and interpretation. - Frequentist methods can often be interpreted through an approximate Bayesian lens. Asymptotic distributions of estimators imply approximate Bayesian probability statements about parameters given estimators.

Uploaded by

Ngoc Chi Minh
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
77 views14 pages

Bayesian Methods in Applied Econometrics, Or, Why Econometrics Should Always and Everywhere Be Bayesian

- Bayesian inference provides probability statements conditioned on observations, allowing characterization of uncertainty about parameters given observed data. This is useful for decision-making. - Objections to Bayesian methods, such as subjectivity, are untrue or overstated. Bayesian inference is no more assumption-laden than frequentist asymptotics. While computationally challenging, Bayesian thinking provides a clearer starting point for data analysis and interpretation. - Frequentist methods can often be interpreted through an approximate Bayesian lens. Asymptotic distributions of estimators imply approximate Bayesian probability statements about parameters given estimators.

Uploaded by

Ngoc Chi Minh
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 14

Bayesian Methods in Applied Econometrics, or,

Why Econometrics Should Always and


Everywhere Be Bayesian

Christopher A. Sims
Princeton University
[email protected]
August 6, 2007

Introduction

• The first part of the talk makes some unoriginal claims about the role of Bayesian
thinking.

• Despite being unoriginal, and obvious to me and to a minority of econome-


tricians, they are unfamiliar, thought-provoking, or outrageous to quite a few
econometricians.

• A summer seminar talk seems a good place to restate claims that are both ob-
vious and outrageous and that therefore (for one of these reasons or the other)
are usually excluded from journal articles.

• The latter part of the talk discusses some areas of econometric application
where frequentist asymptotics seems particularly persistent and suggests how
Bayesian approaches might become more practical and prevalent.

1 Bayesian Inference is a Way of Thinking, Not a Bas-


ket of “Methods”
1.1 What it is
Probability statements conditioned on observations

• Frequentist inference makes only pre-sample probability assertions.

2007
c by Christopher A. Sims. This document may be reproduced for educational and research
purposes, so long as the copies contain this notice and are retained for personal use or distributed
free.
– A 95% confidence interval contains the true parameter value with proba-
bility .95 only before one has seen the data. After the data has been seen,
the probability is zero or one.
– Yet confidence intervals are universally interpreted in practice as guides
to post-sample uncertainty.
– They often are reasonable guides, but only because they often are close to
posterior probability intervals that would emerge from a Bayesian analy-
sis.

• People want guides to uncertainty as an aid to decision-making. They want


to characterize uncertainty about parameter values, given the sample that has
actually been observed. That it aims to help with this is the distinguishing
characteristic of Bayesian inference.

Bayesian inference should be the starting point

• For discussing implications of data analysis with decision makers.

• They often are quite familiar with the language of probability and may ask,
for example, for what the data say about the odds of a parameter being in one
region vs. being in another.

• A carefully trained frequentist econometrician who knows only how to con-


struct confidence regions and hypothesis tests must be tongue-tied in the face
of such a request.

• The Bayesian approach to inference should be the starting point also of our
education of econometricians. For the time being, they need also to learn what
a confidence region is (what it really is, as opposed to what most of them think
it is after a one-year statistics or econometrics course). But I think that full
understanding of what confidence regions and hypothesis tests actually are
will lead to declining interest in constructing them.

1.2 Objections
It’s subjective, whereas frequentist approaches are objective

• This is simply untrue.

• The objective aspect of Bayesian inference is the set of rules for transforming an
initial distribution into an updated distribution conditional on observations.

2
• Bayesian thinking makes it clear that for decision-making, pre-sample beliefs
are therefore in general important.

• But most of what econometricians do is not decision-making. It is reporting of


data-analysis for an audience that is likely to have diverse initial beliefs.

• In such a situation, as was pointed out long ago by Hildreth (1963) and Savage
(1977, p.14-15), the task is to present useful information about the shape of the
likelihood.

(Subjective/objective, continued: How to characterize the likelihood

• Present its maximum.

• Present a local approximation to it based on a second-order Taylor expansion


of its log. (Standard MLE asymptotics.)

• Plot it, if the dimension is low.

• If the dimension is high, present slices of it, marginalizations of it, and implied
expected values of functions of the parameter. The functions you choose might
be chosen in the light of possible decision applications.

• The marginalization is often more useful if a simple, transparent prior is used


to downweight regions of the parameter space that are widely agreed to be
uninteresting.

It requires stronger assumptions than frequentist asymptotics

• Bayesian small-sample inference based on specific parametric assumptions is


of course approximately correct also when the parametric assumptions are ap-
proximately correct.

• Likelihoods often become approximately Gaussian in large samples, and dis-


tributions of estimators β̂ then tend to become symmetric functions of β̂ − β,
so that the likelihood and the pdf of the parameter have the same shape.

• The conditions that allow these claims about asymptotic likelihood shapes are
almost the same as the “weak” conditions allowing asymptotic distribution
claims for estimators.

• So in standard cases Bayesian inference is approximately correct in large sam-


ples under assumptions roughly as “weak” as those that make frequentist in-
ference approximately correct in large samples.

3
Assumptions, continued: Asymptotic results under weak assumptions do not jus-
tify small-sample assertions under weak assumptions

• Consider kernel estimation of a regression function: yi = f ( xi ) + ε i

• It will be consistent and allow accurate confidence statements for a large class
of functions f — in large samples under weak assumptions.

• But in a particular sample, we have to pick a bandwidth. If f shows rapid


changes over intervals shorter than the kernel bandwidth, our kernel estimator
will be badly biased.

• The needed restriction on variability of f is not a “weak” assumption, and in


frequentist inference it is not explicit.

Bayesian inference is hard

• I think it’s Don Berry who said, “Bayesian inference is hard in the sense that
thinking is hard.”

• But it is true that Bayesian inference is usually described and often imple-
mented in a bottom-up way: define your model, define your prior, apply Bayes
rule, emerge with unique, optimal, correct inference.

• This is indeed often hard. Not just computationally, in the third step, but intel-
lectually, in the first two.

• Frequentist inference could be approached in the same way: Define your model,
derive fully efficient estimators, pay no attention to anything else.

• This is actually even harder, and furthermore is not guaranteed to give you any
answer, or a unique answer as to how to proceed.

Hard, continued: Frequentists take shortcuts because doing it right is harder for
them.

• It is standard practice for frequentists to write papers about methods that are
convenient, or intuitively appealing, and describe their properties, often only
approximately, based on asymptotics.

• People use such procedures, often in preference to more elaborate fully efficient
procedures.

• Bayesians can also analyze the properties of estimators or statistics that are not
optimal given the model and prior.

4
• They also can use asymptotic approximation as a shortcut when exact deriva-
tions are hard or as a way of avoiding the need to commit fully to all the details
of a probability model.

• They should probably do more of this, and also stop claiming that it is an ad-
vantage of Bayesian procedures that they give “exact small sample results”.

Frequentists can test hypotheses without specifying the alternative

• Neymann would not have agreed.

• There is always at least an implicit alternative, and there are always alterna-
tives under which a given test would be senseless.

• Nonetheless hypothesis testing is often taught without attention to dependence


of the test’s usefulness on the alternative.

• The view that formal econometrics leads to “testing” and “rejecting” models
without presenting an alternative is part of what has given econometrics a bad
name in some quarters (e.g. among macro calibraters).

One-handed tests, continued

• So it is an advantage of Bayesian approaches that they make it clear that one


can only emerge from data analysis with odds ratios of models against one
another, not with a “test” of a model in isolation.

• (Some Bayesians, in the area of “Bayesian model validation”, come perilously


close to trying to produce alternative-free “tests” with Bayesian machinery.)

1.3 Frequentist methods from a Bayesian perspective


Frequentist asymptotics usually imply Bayesian asymptotics
√ D
• If → N (0, Σ), with Σ not dependent on β, this usually implies
T ( β̂ − β) | β −
√ D
→ N (0, Σ).
that T ( β − β̂) | β̂ −

• That is, frequentist approximate confidence statements based on asymptotics


are usually interpretable as Bayesian probability statements about parameter
location conditional on the estimator — rather than conditional on the full sample.

• Such asymptotic results, in other words, can be interpreted as delivering lim-


ited information approximate Bayesian inference. (See Kwan (1998) and Kim
(2002).)

5
But much of frequentist econometric theory looks like wasted effort

• For example, “testing” of compound hypotheses where probabilities of rejec-


tion vary across the null set.

• Or most of the unit root literature.

• Or most of the “testing for breaks” literature. (In the simple case of a single
break for a regression model, one can easily compute integrated posteriors for
each possible break date, and the plot of these gives the posterior for the break
date under a uniform prior. No analysis of the asymptotic behavior of the
likelihood as a stochastic process on the break dates conditional on the break
date is needed.)

• These are instances where tracing out the implications of the likelihood is quite
straightforward in a given sample, but frequentist results are much harder —
and less useful.

Good frequentist practice has a Bayesian interpretation

• This is a definition, not a theorem.

• Working out the priors and modeling assumptions that would justify a fre-
quentist procedure as Bayesian, or approximately Bayesian, can be helpful.

• It can reassure us (at least us Bayesians) that the procedure makes sense.

• It can turn up situations in which an implied prior has strange characteristics,


and thereby lead us to better estimates or procedures.

• It can help us identify rare conditions or samples in which the frequentist pro-
cedure deviates sharply from its Bayesian approximant, and thereby again lead
us to better estimates or procedures.

2 Recent Successes
Macro policy modeling

• The ECB and the New York Fed have research groups working on models using
a Bayesian approach and meant to integrate into the regular policy cycle. Other
central banks and academic researchers are also working on models using these
methods.

• Bayesian methods have gained increasing attention in this area because:

6
– the modeling is directly tied to repeated decision-making use;
– it involves large models with many parameters, so that attempting to pro-
ceed without any use of prior distributions is a dead end;
– computational power and MCMC methods now make Bayesian analysis
of large models feasible.

What is MCMC?

• This is not the place for a detailed explanation.

• It is a method of posterior simulation.

• Its appeal is that whenever the posterior density function can be computed for
arbitrary points in the parameter space, it is possible with MCMC to generate
simulated samples from that posterior density, even though the density corre-
sponds to no known distribution.

Mixed models
In statistics, mixed models, estimated by MCMC, have received a lot of attention.
They should receive more attention from economists.

yit = Xit β i + uit


β i ∼ N ( β̄, Ω)
uit ∼ N (0, σ2 )

This type of model is easy to handle by MCMC, harder to make sense of from a
frequentist perspective because it has “parameters” that are “random”. It should
probably be preferred in most applications to trying to control for conditional het-
eroscedasticity via “cluster” corrections on standard errors.

3 Frontiers: “Weak Assumptions”


Areas of econometrics where Baysian approaches are rare

• In cross-section and panel data econometrics frequentist theory and practice


remain dominant.

• Instrumental variables, GMM, and non-parametric modeling are widely used,


and there is a general impression that Bayesians have no substitute for them.

7
3.1 IV,GMM
IV

• IV estimates and confidence bands generally satisfy the regularity conditions


allowing their interpretation as approximate Bayes estimators and probability
intervals.

• The sample moments from which IV estimators are constructed are sufficient
statistics under the model that leads to the LIML likelihood.

• A natural Bayesian approach, then, which improves on the usual IV proce-


dures, is to characterize the shape of the LIML likelihood, perhaps using a
prior that captures consensus views on what are interesting parameter values.

• This approach handles “weak instruments” transparently. Samples with a weak


instruments problem are samples where the posterior density contours are far
from the usual Gaussian eggs in regions of the parameter space that are a priori
interesting.

• When there are large numbers of instruments, a prior will help in making sense
of results, and in avoiding the trivial result from 2SLS when the first stage has
negative or small degrees of freedom.

• See my paper “Thinking about Instrumental Variables”, available on my web-


site.

But doesn’t this involve making strong distributional assumptions?

• The trivial answer just points to the fact that IV, LIML, and Bayesian posterior
means all will agree asymptotically.

• So the Bayesian posterior probability intervals calculated with “strong assump-


tions” have the same asymptotic validity, under the same “weak” assumptions,
as the asymptotic-theory based intervals for IV.

• The Bayesian analysis makes clear exactly what assumptions are needed to
make “asymptotically justified” probability statements actually justified.

Conservative models

• But we can go farther. We can ask, if given the moment assumptions on which
IV is based, what is the most “conservative” small-sample probability model
satisfying those assumptions?

8
• A natural formulation: minimize the mutual information, in Shannon’s sense,
between the model parameters and the data.

• The LIML Gaussian setup emerges from this kind of reasoning.

GMM

• Here a model and prior that would lead to the usual procedures is less appar-
ent.

• Suppose our moment conditions are E[ g(y; β) | β)] = 0.

• Usually we start with E[ g0 (γ) | γ, Σ)] = 0, and add

g1 (y; γ, Σ) = g0 (y; γ, Σ) g0 (y; γ, Σ)0 − Σ

• Our g includes both g0 and g1 and our β includes both γ and Σ.

Mutual information minimization


With p(y | β) the pdf of i.i.d. y’s and π the prior pdf on β, minimize w.r.t. p(y | β)
Z Z 
0 0 0
− log p(y | β )π ( β )dβ p(y | β)π ( β)dβ dy
Z
+ log( p(y | β)) p(y | β)dy π ( β)dβ (1)

subject to, for each β,


Z Z
p(y | β)dy = 1 g(y | β) p(y | β)dy = 0 .

Form of the joint pdf


We emerge with the joint pdf

q(y, β) = e A( β)+ B(y)+C( β) g(y| β) .

• This implies that the posterior depends on the data only through ∑ g(yi | β).

• The linear IV setup, leading to normality, is a special case.

9
• The result generally depends, through A, B, and C, on the prior.

• It does not, when ∂g/∂y is non-constant, generally lead to a model in which g0


is N (0, Σ).

• One shortcut is to ignore A and B, at least if holding them constant gives us


an integrable posterior. Probably A and B do not matter asymptotically in this
case.

• It seems worthwhile to explore in more detail what emerges from this setup.

3.2 Nonparametrics
What applied modelers do in practice

1. Specify a reasonable-looking model.

2. Estimate its parameters.

3. Apply “specification tests”, by comparing the model to more complicated ones

4. If the specification tests so indicate, expand the model and go to (2).

Bayesian sieve

• Put a prior on an ∞-dimensional parameter space by putting probability one


on a countable union of finite-dimensional parameter spaces.

• E.g., B( L)yt = ε t , B( L) is of order n with probability 2−n .

• This leads to doing essentially what was described on the previous slide —
estimating finite-dimensional models, expanding or shrinking the number of
parameters based on evidence of the extent to which larger models fit better.

• If the finite-dimensional spaces are dense in the full space, then under some
regularity conditions we can get consistency in the full space.

A countable union of finite-d subspaces is a small piece of an ∞-d topological


vector space

• ∞-d TVS’s are not locally compact.

• Finite-d TVS’s are locally compact.

• Finite-d subspaces are nowhere dense.

10
• Countable unions of them are “meagre”. One topological definition of “small”.

• So this looks restrictive. We’ve put probability one on a small subset of the
parameter space.

Every prior on an ∞-d space does this

• Probability measures on complete, separable metric spaces are “tight”, mean-


ing they put probability one on countable unions of compact sets.

• But this means they put probability one on subsets that are topologically small
in the same sense that a countable union of finite-d subspaces is small.

• In an AR, where the natural topology of fit on the coefficients is equivalent to


`2 , another way to get a dense countable union of compact sets of B( L)’s is to
require that for |bi | < A( B)i−q for some fixed q ≥ 1, for example.

But this is not a problem peculiar to Bayesian inference

• Asymptotically valid confidence statements require exactly the same kinds of


restrictive assumptions.

• Kernel estimates impose bounds on tail behavior and/or derivatives.

• Conclusion 1: If you want to estimate an infinite-dimensional parameter from


a countable sequence of finite-dimensional observations, you have to take a
strong prior position, so you might be wrong forever in your probability asser-
tions.

• Conclusion 2: Don’t be embarrassed to proceed as usual with finite parameter-


izations, tests for specification error. Fancy non-parametric methods are not in
fact any more general.

Bayesian “kernel” regression

yt = f ( xt ) + ε t
ε t i.i.d., zero mean conditional on { xs }. The parameter is f . Assume f is a stochastic
process on x as index set, e.g. Gaussian with Cov( f ( x ), f (z)) = R f ( x − z). Then we
have a covariance matrix for a sample of y’s, a cross-covariance of the y’s with the
f ( x )’s, and thus a projection formula for E[ f ( x ∗ ) | y1 , . . . , y T ].
For x’s in the midst of observed xi ’s, the weights in the projection look very much
like kernel weights. For x’s at the boundary of the sample, or in areas where xi ’s are

11
very sparse, the kernel spreads out, becomes asymmetric. This corresponds to what
applied workers actually do.
The plots on the next slide show the weights from an example in which the
R f ( x ) = 1 − | x | k on [−k, k], with k = .12. More detail is in Sims (2000), from which
these graphs were extracted. One of the plots shows a case where the x ∗ value has
many observed xi near-neighbors. The other shows a case of an x ∗ at the boundary
of the x range and without many near neighbors.

12
13
Conclusion
Lose your inhibitions: Put probabilities on parameters without embarrassment.

References
H ILDRETH , C. (1963): “Bayesian Statisticians and Remote Clients,” Econometrica,
31(3), 422–438.

K IM , J.- Y. (2002): “Limited information likelihood and Bayesian analysis,” Journal of


Econometrics, 107, 175–193.

K WAN , Y. K. (1998): “Asymptotic Bayesian analysis based on a limited information


estimator,” Journal of Econometrics, 88, 99–121.

S AVAGE , L. J. (1977): “The Shifting Foundations of Statistics,” in Logic, Laws and Life,
ed. by R. Colodny, pp. 3–18. University of Pittsburgh Press.

S IMS , C. A. (2000): “Using a Likelihood Perspective to Sharpen Econometric Dis-


course: Three Examples,” Journal of Econometrics, 95(2), 443–462, http://www.
princeton.edu/˜sims/.

14

You might also like