Piaget and Cognitive Development
Piaget and Cognitive Development
_______
4- 2
Piaget: Some Biographical Facts
4- 3
Basic Piagetian Concepts
Piagetian Conservation Tasks
Before plunging headlong into Piaget’s sometimes abstract
theoretical ideas about the ways in which children learn at different
stages of development, it may be helpful – particularly to students
with no familiarity with Piaget – to begin with a few examples of
his well-known conservation tasks. These nicely illustrate Piaget’s
approach to observing children as they grapple with ordinary
objects.
Piaget noticed that students below a certain level of maturity
(prior to about age seven) had difficulty in comprehending certain
problems involving invariants in quantity. In his famous water
level task, for instance (see Fig. 4.1), a child is shown a large glass
or pitcher of water. The water is poured into a different size
container – one that is wider – so that the resulting water level is
lower than it was for the original container. Young children simply
did not see that the amount of water was unchanged. They might
report that the glass with the lower level has less water, because
the height is lower, or less commonly, that there is more water in
the glass with the lower level because it is more spread out.
Similarly, if a large lump of clay is broken into several smaller
lumps, the child may claim that there is now more clay, because
the number of lumps has increase, or perhaps that there is less clay,
because the lumps are smaller. Or, if the large lump of clay is
flattened, they likewise believe that the amount has changed
simply because of the change in shape of the mass. In these, and in
other tasks illustrated in Figure 3.1, the child fails to see that the
amounts are the same: that the quantities are preserved or
conserved under these transformations (i.e., they do not actually
change, even though their appearances change).
Piaget called the stage of development just before children
reach the level where they can correctly solve the conservation
tasks the preoperational stage (see Table 4.1). At this stage,
children seem to have difficulty focusing on more than one aspect
of a situation. He called this tendency to focus on just a single
aspect of a situation centration. For example, the child’s attention
4- 4
may be centered primarily on the height of the water level, yet the
child fails to see that the width also changes, and compensates for
the lowered height. A key feature of the preoperational stage is that
the child’s thinking process precludes the notion of reversibility in
these mental operations: he or she cannot seem to grasp the notion
that conservation requires (mentally) seeing that pouring the water
back into the original container should result in the same, original
quantity. Thus, preoperational thought is characterized by a certain
kind of fixedness of thought that Piaget called irreversibility.
4- 5
concept of conservation, including reversibility, as well as the loss
of centration.
4- 6
Hierarchical integration. Each period represents a hierarchical
integration of lower stages into higher ones. Earlier thinking
patterns are not lost; rather, they are incorporated into the higher
levels.
One may wonder, then, whether these periods and stages are
genetically determined or “programmed into” the child’s nervous
system, as a maturationist might claim. The answer is no: only in
the sense that a certain maturation of the nervous system is
required before a child can move to a higher stage. Cognition and
learning of particular tasks – say the conservation of volume in the
water level task – are not in any sense genetically programmed into
the child. Rather, children’s brains have, through the process of
evolution, the necessary flexibility to enable the solutions of
certain kinds of problems at certain levels of development. This
learning takes through natural interactions with the environment.
Thus, Piaget was a true developmentalist as this term was
described in the second chapter.
Another question often comes to mind with Piaget: exactly
how discrete are these periods and stages – do changes in the
child’s abilities occur suddenly and abruptly? It is more or less true
that a child who can solve one kind of conservation task – say the
conservation of number (as when a large chunk of clay is divided
into smaller lumps) – can also solve another – for instance, the
conservation of mass (such as when a large lump of clay is
flattened or reshaped). However, development of cognitive skills is
not always quite this clear cut. In the early concrete operational
stage, a child may be able to do some tasks but not others. Piaget
referred to this phenomenon as horizontal décalage, meaning that
developmental growth can be “spread out” (décalaged) within each
period. In this sense, Piaget came to recognize that learning is
actually somewhat continuous within a stage. Indeed, development
within a stage continues until a kind of equilibrium (as discussed
below) is achieved.
4- 7
The notion of development by relatively discrete stages has
always been controversial, and Piaget’s ideas have been questioned
and in some cases, modified, by other researchers. This research is
considered in the evaluation of Piaget’s theory, near the end of the
chapter.
4- 8
Often a child can develop a scheme to work out the mechanics
of a problem (“plane of action”) but yet cannot verbalize the
solution (“plane of thought”) for a number of months following the
initial learning. Piaget called this lag between the two kinds of
understanding vertical décalage.
4- 10
Equilibrium and Equilibration. When a child reaches a point
at which he is not making such big steps, learning has leveled off,
and there is a balance between assimilation and accommodation,
the child has reached what Piaget called a state equilibrium. By the
end of the concrete operational stage, for instance, the child can
easily grasp all of Piaget’s conservation tasks, and has a clear idea
of the concept of reversibility; that is a state of equilibrium. But
when a child is ready for new learning, and cannot seem to meet
his environmental challenges, a state of disequilibrium ensues, in
which the child experiences cognitive discomfort. In other words,
the child has needs and is ready to take on more complex tasks,
and may in fact be progressing toward a new stage of cognitive
development, involving major new accommodations.
Equilibration simply refers to the process of moving from a state
of disequilibrium to equilibrium.
4- 11
engagement with her/his environment in which the child constructs
new schemes, which are built on top of older ones. This concept,
known as constructivism, contrasts very sharply with traditional
learning theory, in which the child is viewed in a much more
passive manner (see Chapter 10). But today, the concept of
constructivism is widely embraced by cognitive scientists
(Wadsworth, 1996).
Miller (2002) further notes that Piaget used equilibration to
refer to three separate processes, all of which represent different
states of equilibrium. These can be summarized briefly as:
4- 12
Organization. Organization is the second Piagetian process for
building schemes. It is more of a mental process than is adaptation.
Rather than learning through manipulation of objects in the
environment the child develops new mental concepts – not
necessarily verbal ones – that connect existing schemes.
Organization is therefore a process of integration. As an example, a
child begins to develop a mental concept of distance based on
many prior experiences of tossing or throwing and dropping. At a
later age the child develops a more sophisticated concept of
distance that he can put into words, representing yet a higher
degree of organization.
Just as assimilation and accommodation are two
complementary processes that define adaptation, Piaget
emphasized that organization and adaptation are also quite
complementary, and they are often difficult to separate in practice.
In this sense Piaget thought of organization as the internal
component of cognition and adaptation as the external portion.
Sensorimotor Period
Major periods are listed in Table 3.1. The first period, from
birth to about two years, is called the sensorimotor period (see
Table 4.2 for stages within this period). During this period most
schemes are organizations of physical action patterns. Piaget’s
(1936/1974) account refers frequently to observations of his infant
son, Laurent, and daughters, Lucienne and Jacqueline.
4- 13
until ultimately he accommodates, and does not have to have the
breast presented directly in order to nurse.
4- 15
Stage 6 (18 months – 2 years). It is in this final stage of the
sensorimotor period in which symbolic thought begins. Piaget did
not believe that thinking requires language; in fact, the child’s
earliest thought consists of the non-linguistic use of symbols. In an
interesting experiment, Piaget (1936/1974; Ginsburg & Opper,
1988) hid a watch chain from Lucienne in a match box. She sees
the box drawer open and close, but this action sequence is new to
her. Lucienne clearly wants to get the chain from the matchbox,
but using existing schemes (turning the box and trying to reach her
finger into the opening slit) fail. Piaget then notices his daughter
opening and closing her mouth, wider and wider! Then she “gets”
the idea of the matchbox drawer opening and closing – she is able
to open the slot with her finger, then she can pull out the watch
chain.
The interesting discovery about this observation is that
Lucienne seemed to form the concept of a box drawer opening and
closing not through verbal reasoning, but by “feeling out” the
solution in a physical way – by opening and closing her mouth in
order to “symbolize” the needed action scheme.
Increasingly throughout the sensorimotor period the child
becomes more adept at imitating models (adults or other children),
but at this final stage she becomes adept at deferred imitation
(imitating an act that was observed on a prior occasion). Piaget
(1952; Ginsburg & Opper, 1988) recounts that his daughter
Jacqueline, having observed a boy throwing a temper tantrum,
attempts one herself the following day.
4- 16
Table 4.1
Piaget’s Periods of Development
Preoperational Period
The young child at this stage is able to form symbols – mental
representations of ideas and events although they are not very
logical or well organized. Piaget believed that children form their
first mental symbols as extensions of physical imitative gestures.
In the last stage of the sensorimotor period the example of Piaget’s
daughter Jacqueline imitating the mechanics of a matchbox with
her mouth (see above) was an example of deferred imitation; it was
for Jacqueline a primitive kind of mental representation of a
particular behavior. Note that there is nothing conscious about such
4- 17
a representation; the child does not have to be aware of a concept
that she has formed in order to make use of it (in Jacqueline’s case
by mimicking). In time such physical action sequences become
less pronounced and more subtle – the muscle movement may
become faint – until the concept itself becomes completely
nonphysical: the child merely imagines the physical motions.
4- 18
Table 4.2
Stages Within the Sensorimotor Period
Approximate
Stage Age Cognitive Characteristics
Realism
Realism is the failure to recognize the existence of a self that is
separate from this external world; hence “regarding one’s own
perspective as immediate and absolute” (p. 34). Realism in the
child represents a kind of ultra-naïve conception of reality in which
there is not only no self-awareness but also no distinction between
the subjective and the objective. There is no awareness that the
perception of others differ from one’s own. This is thus another
example of the kind of egocentricity that characterizes pre-
operational children. Young children have only a very rudimentary
grasp of the very notion of thought, and probably none of the ideas
of mind or brain (i.e., they lack a theory of mind.)
When asked about thought, the child at this stage is likely to
identify thinking with the mouth, or with speech. Thus language is
implicated in the child’s conception of thought. In fact, Piaget
claims that for the child, “. . . to think is to speak – either with the
mouth or with a little voice in the head …” (p. 60).
The young child also fails to distinguish the name of an
object (sun, moon, tree, etc.) from the object itself, hence the child
is unable to appreciate the arbitrariness of language, perhaps even
until the ages of 9 to 11 or so. It is also as though the name of a
thing belongs exclusively to that object. The child sometimes fails
to understand that names can arbitrarily be changed (e.g., if people
began to refer to the Earth as Mars it could not possibly still really
be the Earth). Piaget referred to this phenomenon as nominal
realism. Piaget concluded that “The child is a realist, since he
supposes thought to be inseparable from its object, name from the
4- 21
things named, and dreams to be eternal” (p. 124).
Piaget states that preoperational children seem to believe in the
reality of their dreams: they are “real” at one moment (while
asleep), but gone the next (after awakening). The boogeyman in
the room was really there, but now he’s gone. And they seem to
think that adults as well should have privy to their dreams (“didn’t
you see it too, Mom”)?
Actually, Piaget believed that there were three stages in
children’s conceptions of dreaming. In the first, dreams seem to
come from outside the child and remain external. In the second
stage the dream seems external, yet the child realizes that it arises
within him/herself. In the third stage the child realizes that the
dream arises within and is entirely an internal phenomenon.
Animism
Animism refers to the attribution of human characteristics such
as feelings, thoughts, actions, and intentions, to non-living objects.
Objects that move, such as clouds, the sun and moon, or toy trains
and trucks, all may be given such attributes by young children.
Here is an example of a dialog between one of Piaget’s
assistants and a young child (p. 197):
Artificialism
For Piaget, “[Artificialism] consists in regarding things as the
product of human creation, rather than in attributing creative
activity to the things themselves” (p. 153). That is why when
children ask such questions as “Who made the sun?” or “Who is it
makes the stars twinkle?” (p. 256), it becomes clear that children
simply assume that “someone” is responsible for such things.
Children also often ask such questions about the origins of trees
and mountains or the weather, such as it is on a given day. A child
is likely to assume that a lake or sea has been carved out or created
by an act of some being.
Relationship to Egocentricity
All three concepts – realism, animism, and artificialism –
clearly reflect the young child’s egocentric perceptions of the
world. Perhaps this is most evident in the case of realism, in which
the child is simply unable to separate her/his own self from the rest
of what constitutes his or her reality. In the case of animism, the
child believes that other objects, people, or animals, all function
mentally in the same way as he or she does. With artificialism, the
belief is that things have been made not by the child, but by “us,”
or other people, who by implication from the child’s egocentric
perspective, are in fact like him or her.
4- 23
one aspect of the problem (lack of centration), and clearly
understands that the process is reversible: when the water is poured
back into the original container the quantity is preserved. This
understanding also involves the complementary process of
compensation, or being able to see that the water amount in the
second container is the same because the container is wider rather
than taller, thus compensating for the fact that the level is lower
than in the first container. Another related concept the child attains
in this period is that of identity. The notion is that, since nothing
has been added or removed, the quantities in the two containers
must remain identical. In summary, reversibility, compensation,
identity, and lack of centration all characterize the child’s mental
schemes during this period. Once again it is worth noting that
Piaget believed that children were able to grasp these concepts
intuitively and on their own, through experimentation.
Formal Operations
Most teachers would hesitate to attempt to teach algebra or
geometry to children who are in the concrete operational stage.
They have some necessary arithmetic skills, but they lack the
ability to handle abstraction (“Let X be an unknown quantity”) or
hypothetical thinking (“Suppose cats glowed at night. How would
this affect mouse ecology?”). Hypothetical (or propositional)
thinking involves the ability to see possibilities, including abstract
ones. Logical reasoning before this period is also rudimentary. A
preoperational child might have difficulty understanding formal
logic, as in this syllogism:
(Note that one is not asked to evaluate the actual truth of the
premises; the task in deductive reasoning is to determine the
validity of the conclusion given the truth of the premises.)
At a further level of abstraction, a student of logic at the formal
operational stage might see that the following argument is valid:
4- 26
Educational Implications
Quite obviously, Piaget thought (as did Rousseau and Maria
Montessori, founder of the Montessori schools) that young
children learned best by experimenting for themselves. Recall that,
in his early experiences with intelligence testing, Piaget was more
concerned with the way that children solve problems than with
whether or not they arrived at a correct solution. To take this a step
further, struggling with a problem can is in itself be seen as
learning something, even if it is not the answer to the problem one
began with. Teachers who are influenced by Piaget thus tend to
believe that quality learning comes from being challenged
naturally by problems, motivated intrinsically by curiosity, and
attempting different solutions through experimentation. The
Piagetian classroom is thus child centered, rather than being
knowledge centered: solutions to problems should come from the
child, not from the teacher. Learning is, for the child, an active
process of discovery.
Also, the tasks presented to the child should be appropriate for
that child’s level of development. Readiness is an important factor
in that one should not try to teach concepts that are beyond the
child’s period or stage of development (the child himself will learn
such concepts when he is ready).
Needless to say, this approach is in very sharp contrast with
educational practices in many (or perhaps most) schools. Many
schools use a more Lockian model, in which learning is gradual,
based on small increments in knowledge, with much of this based
on rote memorization. Contingencies (external rewards and
punishments) are also employed in the Lockian model; in other
words, motivation is largely extrinsic rather than intrinsic. Such a
model is also compatible with the behavioristic tradition in
psychology (as will be seen in Chapter 10).
Evaluating Piaget
The Concept of Developmental Stages
Models of development (as was seen in Chapter 1) vary with
4- 27
respect to the notion of stages. Piaget began with a very structured
model in which discrete periods or stages characterize different
levels of development. As his work progressed, he recognized that
horizontal décalage not only occurred, but was also very
commonplace, so that stages themselves were not entirely discreet.
Other psychologists – notably those in the behaviorist (or
Lockian) tradition (Chapter 10) – believe that learning is a more or
less continuous, incremental process. It may be characterized by
sudden leaps of learning – times in which new learning seems
rapid and accelerated – but this does not (for them) necessarily
imply that discrete stages are anything more than points at which
the child’s nervous system matures enough to handle such bursts of
learning.
A little thought suggests that both positions can be true in their
own way. If one thinks in terms of the gradual and incremental
increase in knowledge that takes place in factual learning (e.g.,
spelling; ordinary arithmetic), then the traditional position is
reasonable. But if one considers instead the kind of learning
espoused by Piaget, in which a reorganization of mental processes
permits the learning of tasks that were previously unattainable,
then the Piagetian position seems tenable. One must, of course,
grant that the phenomenon of horizontal décalage makes this stage
approach seem less like an abrupt shift in mentality than a
somewhat more gradual one. But this still does not discount the
notion that thinking becomes reorganized; and when equilibration
occurs at the end of each period, the process of reorganization can
be said to be consolidated, per Piaget’s theory.
Gelman and Baillargeon (1983) have raised doubts about the
notion that stages always unfold in the invariant sequence that
Piaget postulated. Such criticisms raise serious concerns, though
they are not necessarily fatal, for Piaget’s theory. Still,
psychologists today view cognitive development as somewhat
more continuous than did Piaget.
Piaget’s Methodology
Potential weaknesses in Piaget’s methodology have already
been discussed: his research was based on clinical observations of
a few case studies with small samples, and lack of statistical
4- 28
analysis. Piaget did do experiments (especially on his own
children), but these were in no sense tightly controlled
experiments.
The value of clinical research using case studies is never clear
until the findings can be shown to hold using more traditional,
experimental techniques with tight controls, and a sufficient
number of cases to allow generality. Greater sophistication is also
needed in providing improved measurement techniques
(standardized psychometric tests; e.g., of conservation tasks).
Many examples of theories based on case studies will be seen later
in the text, including the chapters on Freud and the ethologists. In
the case of Freud, results seem mixed to say the least. The
ethologists, however, have made some valuable contributions that
are experimentally verifiable. Piaget, too, was a shrewd observer
whose observations have largely been verified. That Piaget has
generated so much research is a great testament to him. This is true
even when his theories required modification (as Piaget did
himself); indeed, that is the way that scientific progress is made.
Some experimental research places certain Piagetian notions in
question (see next section), but experimental research has largely
favored at least some form of his stage sequences. Fleming and
DeAvila (1980, p. 73) state: “It is inevitable, perhaps, in the
evolution of scientific theory that insight [per Piaget’s clinical
observations] is gradually supplanted by refinement, as
measurement assumes a greater and greater role.” They suggest
some precise psychometric and statistical methods to use for
testing Piagetian stage sequences, including décalages within
periods.
****
4- 32
For Thought or Discussion
****
4- 34
Chapter Notes
1. Piaget (1929/1951), p. 370.
2. When he first visited America in 1921, it was said that
Einstein’s work could only be understood by 12 living people
(Paterniti, 2000). Piaget, like Einstein, was unquestionably
brilliant, and though he wrote succinctly he, too, can be
difficult reading (Inhelder, 1988). Piaget was so busy revising
and extending his theory that he seldom stopped to try to pull it
all together for the reader. I try to give a proper introduction to
Piaget, and one that is lengthier than that of the average
beginning textbook – but one could write an entire chapter on
the stages of sensorimotor period alone. For an advanced
treatment the reader is referred to Piaget’s original works
(especially Piaget, 1936/1974, 1936/1954); to Ginsburg and
Opper (1988); or to Flavell, Miller, and Miller (2001).
3. Here as elsewhere, Piaget seems ahead of his time: note the
importance of modeling in Bandura’s social learning theory
which comes much later in the history of American psychology
(per Chapter 11).
4. The term “circular reaction” was coined by the American
developmentalist James Mark Baldwin, whose work influenced
Piaget, who frequently cited Baldwin in his writings.
4- 35
References
Baillargeon, R., & DeVos, J. (1991). Object permanence in young
infants: Further evidence. Child Development, 62, 1227-
1246.
Binet, A., & Simon, T. (1905). Methodes nouvelles pour le
diagnostic du niveau intellectuel des anormaux. Anee
Psychologique, 11, 191-244.
Borke, H. (1975). Piaget’s mountains revisited: Changes in the
egocentric landscape. Developmental Psychology, 11, 240-
243.
Case, R. (1998). The development of conceptual structures. In W.
Damon (Editor-in Chief), & D. Kuhn, and R. S. Siegler (Vol.
Eds.), Handbook of child psychology: Vol. 2, Cognition,
perception, and language (5th Ed., pp. 745-800). New York:
Wiley.
Elkind, D. (1994). A sympathetic understanding of the child: Birth
to sixteen (3rd Ed.). Boston: Allyn & Bacon.
Elkind, D., & Bowen, R. (1979). Imaginary audience behavior in
children and adolescents. Developmental Psychology, 15, 33-
44.
Fischer, K. W. (1980). A theory of cognitive development: The
control and construction of hierarchies and skills.
Psychological Review, 87, 477-531.
Flavell, J. H. (2000). Development of children’s knowledge about
the mental world. International Journal of Behavioral
Development, 24, 15-23.
Flavell, J. H., Miller, P. H., & Miller, S. A. (2001). Cognitive
development. (4rth Ed.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ.: Prentice-
Hall.
Fleming, J. S., & DeAvila, E. A. (1980). Scalogram and factor
analysis of two tests of cognitive development. Multivariate
Behavioral Research, 15, 73-93.
Gelman, R. (1969). Conservation acquisition: A problem of
learning to attend to relevant attributes. Journal of
Experimental Child Psychology, 7, 167-187.
4- 36
Gelman, R., & Baillargeon, R. (1983). A review of some Piagetian
concepts. In P. H. Mussen (Series Ed.), J. H. Flavell & E. M.
Markman (Vol. Eds.), Handbook of child psychology, Vol. 3:
Cognitive development (4rth Ed., pp. 167-230). New York:
Wiley
Gesell, A. (1954). The ontogenesis of infant behavior. In L.
Carmichael (Ed.), Manual of child psychology (2nd. Ed.).
New York: Wiley. (Originally published in 1946)
Ginsberg, H. P., & Opper, S. (1988). Piaget’s theory of
intellectual development. (3rd. Ed.). Englewood Cliffs, NJ.:
Prentice-Hall.
Haggbloom, S. J., Warnick, R., Warnick, J., Jones, V. K.,
Yarbrough, G. L., Russell, T. M., Borecky, C. M.,
McGahhey, R., Powell III, J. L., Beavers, J., & Monte, E.
(2002). The 100 most eminent psychologists of the 20th
Century. Review of General Psychology, 6, 139-152.
Inhelder, B. (1988). Foreword. In H. P. Ginsburg & S. Opper,
Piaget’s theory of intellectual development. (3rd. Ed., p. iv).
Englewood Cliffs, NJ.: Prentice-Hall.
Keil, F. (2006). Cognitive science and cognitive development.. In
W. Damon (Editor-in-chief), & D. Kuhn & R. S. Siegler
(Vol. Eds.), Handbook of child psychology, Vol. 2:
Cognition, perception, and language (6th Ed., pp. 609-635).
New York: Wiley.
Kohlberg, L. (1968). Early education: A cognitive-developmental
approach. Child Development, 39, 1013-1062.
Miller, P. H. (2002). Theories of developmental psychology. (4rth
Ed.). New York: Worth.
Murakata, Y. (2006). Information processing approaches to
development. In W. Damon (Editor-in-chief), & D. Kuhn &
R. S. Siegler (Vol. Eds.), Handbook of child psychology, Vol.
2: Cognition, perception, and language (6th Ed., pp. 426-
463). New York: Wiley.
Myers, D. G. (2004). Psychology in modules. (7th Ed.). New York:
Worth.
Paterniti, M. (2000). Driving Mr. Albert: A trip across America
with Einstein’s brain. New York: Dell.
4- 37
Pascual-Leone, J. A. (1970). A mathematical model for the
transition rule in Piaget’s developmental stages. Acta
Psychologica, 32, 301-345.
Piaget, J. (1951). The child’s conception of the world. Savage,
MD: Littlefield-Adams. (Originally published in 1929.)
Piaget, J. (1952). Autobiography. In E. G. Boring and others,
History of psychology in autobiography. Worcester, MA:
Clark University Press.
Piaget, J. (1954). The construction of reality in children (M. Cook,
Trans.). New York: Ballantine Books. (Originally published
in 1936.)
Piaget, J. (1972). Judgment and reasoning in the child. (M.
Warden, trans.). Savage, MD: Littlefield-Adams. (Originally
published in 1924.)
Piaget, J. (1974). The origins of intelligence for children (M. Cook,
Trans.). New York: International Universities Press.
(Originally published in 1936.)
Piaget, J., & Szeminska, A. (1952). The child’s conception of
number (C. Gattegno & F. M. Hodgson, Trans.) London:
Routeledge & Kegan Paul. (Originally published in 1941.)
Wadsworth, B. J. (1996). Piaget’s theory of cognitive and affective
development: Foundations of constructionism (5th Ed.).
Boston: Allyn & Bacon.
4- 38