Aristotle On Meaning and Essence (Oxford University Press, 2001)
Aristotle On Meaning and Essence (Oxford University Press, 2001)
Aristotle On Meaning and Essence (Oxford University Press, 2001)
General Editors
Julia Annas and Lindsay Judson
Aristotle on Meaning and Essence
David Charles
of Aristotelian philosophical scholars, working on similar questions, beginning with Richard Kilvington in 1326, and
including (amongst others) Richard Whately, Edward Poste, and John Cook Wilson. They represent one part of the
outstanding Oxford tradition in the study of ancient philosophy, to which I am deeply indebted.
My own interest in these topics stems from a reading group I organized on Posterior Analytics Β.8–10 in 1983–5. We
read these chapters slowly, often spending two or three hours on one or two lines. Such discussions have great merits:
detailed attention to the text, the requirement for high standards of precision (both philosophical and philological), the
opportunity for a free exchange of views between faculty and graduate students, and the sheer fun of shared work and
enthusiasm. I owe a particular debt to the 1983–5Analytics group, which included (at various times) Kei Chiba, Paula
Gottlieb, Tomomasa Imai, Vassilis Karasmanis, Gavin Lawrence, Penelope Mackie, Christopher Megone, Michael
Morris, Dory Scaltsas, Pantazis Tselemanis, Jennifer Whiting, and Michael Woods. I am sure that they all influenced my
thinking on these topics.
Since then, I have given seminars on the Analytics with Jonathan Barnes and with Robert Bolton (at Rutgers
University), on the Metaphysics with Michael Frede and with Montgomery Furth (at UCLA), on Aristotle's biological
works with Allan Gotthelf and James Lennox, on the Physics with Lindsay Judson, and on De Anima with Shigeru
Kanzaki and Kei Chiba (at Tokyo Metropolitan University). I have gained greatly from all of these and also from a
long-lived discussion group on De Anima, which began in 1988 and continues to this day. Indeed, it was only through
the latter's work that I came to see points of connection between Aristotle's account of thought and of colour
perception and his analysis of definition and explanation in the Analytics. In this, I am indebted to (amongst others)
Stephen Everson and, particularly, Michael Frede.
I began to write this book as a Fellow at the idyllic Center for Hellenic Studies in Washington DC in 1985/6, under the
kindly and supportive Directorship of Zeph Stewart. I benefited then, as in 1994 and in 1998, from sabbatical leave
granted by the Provost and Fellows of Oriel. Earlier versions of the following Chapters have appeared elsewhere:
Chapter 4:‘Aristotle on names and their signification’, in Stephen Everson (ed), Companions to Ancient Thought 3: Language
(Cambridge, 1994). Chapter 11: ‘Matter and Form: Unity, Persistence, and Identity’ in T. Scaltsas, D. Charles and M. L.
Gill (eds), Unity, Identity, and Explanation in Aristotle's Metaphysics (Oxford 1994).
Chapter 12: ‘Natural Kinds and Natural History’, in D. Devereux and P. Pellegrin (eds), Biologie, Logique et Metaphysique
(Paris, 1990). ‘Aristotle and the Unity and Essence of Biological Kinds’, in W. Kullmann and S. Follinger (eds),
Aristotelische Biologie (Stuttgart, 1997).
PREFACE ix
These papers, together with ones representing the basis of Chapters 2, 3, 5, 8, and 9 and Appendix 2, have been
presented at conferences or seminars in a variety of places in Europe, the USA, and Japan. I am grateful to many
audiences for interesting criticisms and difficult questions. I have also gained from detailed comments on specific
topics from Justin Broackes, Victor Caston, Alan Code, Andrea Falcon, Mary Louise Gill, Terry Irwin, Yoshihiko
Kaneko, Vassilis Karasmanis, Atsushi Kawatanai, Frank Lewis, Geoffrey Lloyd, Christopher Megone, Mario Mignucci,
Pierre Pellegrin, Gerhard Seel, Richard Sorabji, Michael Wedin, and Audrius Zakarauskas.
I have learned from the discussion of related issues in contemporary philosophy. In this I am particularly indebted to
Bill Brewer, John Campbell, Bill Child, Dorothy Edgington, Lizzie Fricker, Jennifer Hornsby, Ian Rumfitt, Paul
Snowdon, Helen Steward, Tom Stoneham, Rowland Stout, and Timothy Williamson. Our weekly discussions, on a
wide variety of topics, have been a constant source of illumination and encouragement.
In completing the book, I have been greatly assisted by helpful and searching comments on the penultimate draft from
John Campbell, Lindsay Judson, and Timothy Williamson. Adam Beresford, Kei Chiba, and Greville Healey provided
constructive and stimulating philosophical and philological advice on several versions. Without their support, I would
not even now have finished the book.
This page intentionally left blank
Contents
Abbreviations xv
Introduction 1
1. Meaning, Essence, and Necessity 4
1.1 Introduction 4
1.2 One Form of Modern Essentialism 5
1.3 Problems and Alternatives 11
1.4 Aristotle's Essentialism Introduced 14
1.5 Existence: Further Differences between Aristotle and my Modern Essentialist 16
1.6 Necessity, and Essentiality 18
1.7 Outline of what Follows 19
PART I: ARISTOTLE ON SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
2. Posterior Analytics Β.8–10: the Three-Stage View 23
2.1 Introduction 23
2.2 Initial Evidence for the Three-Stage View: Sections [A] and [B] of Β.10 24
2.3 The First Sentence of Β.10 26
2.4 Section [B]: The Three-Stage View Developed? 34
2.5 Section [C]: 93b35–37: Varieties of Stage 1 40
2.6 Sections [D]–[G]: 93b38–94a10: Further Defence of the Liberal Reading of Β.10 43
2.7 Section [H]: 94a11–14: Aristotle's Summary of Β.10 47
2.8 Interim Conclusions and Sceptical Challenges* 48
2.9 Semantic Depth 53
2.10 Further Gaps in Aristotle's Account 56
3. Preparation for the Three-Stage View 57
3.1 Introduction 57
3.2 Β.792b4–25: Independence Problem 58
3.3. Β.792a34–b3, 19–25: The Formal Problem Introduced 60
3.4 The Final Argument of Β.7: 92b26–34: Accounts of what Names Signify 62
3.5 Independence Problem Resolved 64
3.6 The Formal Problems Resolved 67
xii CONTENTS
Works Of Aristotle
Cat. Categories
De An. De Anima
De Insom. De Insomniis
De Int. De Interpretatione
De Mem. De Memoria
De Resp. De Respiratione
De Sensu De Sensu et Sensibilibus
EE Eudemian Ethics
GA Generation of Animals
GC De Generatione et Corruptione
HA Historia Animalium
IA De Incessu Animalium
Meta. Metaphysics
NE Nicomachean Ethics
PA Parts of Animals
Phys. Physics
Post. An. Posterior Analytics
Pr. An. Prior Analytics
Rhet. Rhetoric
Soph. El. De Sophisticis Elenchis
Top. Topics
This page intentionally left blank
Introduction
This book is an essay on two themes in Aristotle's philosophy and their interconnection. The first is his account of the
meaning of terms such as ‘man’, ‘fish’, and ‘eclipse’, which pick out kinds of objects or processes. The second is his
theory of the essences of these kinds, the features we refer to in defining them, the ones that make them what they are.
The first is discussed in Part I, the second in the Part II.
These two themes can be connected in a variety of ways. In one contemporary account, ordinary thinkers who grasp
the meaning of natural-kind terms (such as ‘man’) must make (or be sensitive to) deep theoretical assumptions about
the internal structure of a kind they already know to exist. (I set out a version of this view in Chapter I.) On this basis,
some modern essentialists have sought to vindicate talk of the essential features of objects and kinds. Indeed, in their
view, if our practices are in good order, there is no need for any further metaphysical theory of essence.
Aristotle's account is fundamentally different. According to him, grasp of the meaning of a natural-kind term involves
knowledge neither of the existence nor of the essence of the kind signified. As a consequence, he needed to formulate
an independent metaphysical theory to vindicate claims about the essence and nature of kinds. He could not rely on
the (supposedly) profound theoretical intuitions of ordinary thinkers. Indeed, in his view, they need not (in general)
have intuitions of this type. While the modern essentialist's account involves a deep theory of meaning and little or no
metaphysics, for Aristotle the balance is reversed. Because his relevant account of signification is comparatively
shallow, it is the task of metaphysics and not of the philosophy of language to vindicate essentialist claims.
In Part I, I set out an interpretation of Aristotle's account of the meaning of natural-kind terms and of our
understanding of them. My starting point is his discussion of accounts of what terms signify in the Posterior Analytics Β. 7–10
(Chapters 2 and 3). Here, Aristotle sets out three stages of scientific enquiry. At the first stage, one may possess an
account of what a term signifies, but yet not know of the existence of the kind signified. At the second and third stages,
one will (if all goes well) discover the existence and subsequently the essence of the relevant kind. I argue for this
interpretation against a number of alternatives.
2 INTRODUCTION
In Chapter 4 I consider Aristotle's discussion of the signification of such terms. In his view, this is determined (firstly)
by the thoughts with which they are correlated and (secondly) by the kinds with which those thoughts are (in a certain
way) causally connected. Indeed, it is this distinctive type of efficient causal connection which determines the object (or
content) of the relevant thoughts, and thereby the signification of the term in question. This, I argue, is an account of
the meaning of such terms, although it differs in certain respects from accounts of meaning with which we are familiar.
In Chapter 5 I set out Aristotle's account of the object (or content) of thought and perception, on which his account of
the meaning of kind terms is based.
At this point, there is a problem. How can the signification of a kind term be determined by the kind itself, if the
thinker (at the first stage of scientific enquiry) does not know, in understanding the term, that the kind in question
exists? For, if she does not know this, how can she know the signification of the term? Is there a major inconsistency in
his account of these issues?
Aristotle can, and does, overcome this problem (as I argue in Chapter 6), but only at the cost of separating signification
and understanding in ways which sharply distinguish his account from Fregean (and other modern) analyses of these
issues. His discussion of what is involved in understanding a natural-kind term is equally distinctive. He focuses (I
suggest) on the type of understanding possessed by master craftsmen, unaffected by scientific theory, who are able
skilfully to engage with the kinds they encounter. Their grasp of the signification of these terms does not involve
knowledge of either the essence or the existence of the kind in question. In Chapter 6 I examine a number of
objections to my interpretation of Aristotle's account of signification, as given in Part I. I also consider some
philosophical objections to the view itself.
The aim in Part II is to understand the metaphysical basis of Aristotle's essentialism. The distinctive nature of his
approach emerges first in the interdependency he detects between the practices of definition and of explanation (when
correctly understood). In Posterior Analytics Β, neither practice is complete without the assistance of the other (Chapters
7–9). This interdependency rests, at the metaphysical level, on the co-determination of essence and causation: all
essences are per se causes of a given type, and all such per se causes are essences. These two theses are developed and
examined in Chapter 10.
In Chapters 11 and 12 I argue that Aristotle's discussion of substances and of animal kinds in the Metaphysics and the
biological writings is based (in large measure) on the two theses outlined in Chapter 10. However, once again, there is a
problem. While Aristotle succeeds in sustaining his Analytics-based account in his metaphysical writings, he encounters
major problems in his study of biology. Not only does he fail to locate the type
INTRODUCTION 3
of unitary essence his theory requires, but, worse still, he appears to have come to believe that no such unitary essences
could be found. It seems that his favoured area for scientific research did not contain the types of essence required by
his scientific and metaphysical picture. There is, it appears, a crisis in Aristotle's essentialism, which can (given his
biological discoveries) only be overcome at the cost of modifying several of his central Analytics-style claims about
essence and the unity of kinds.
In Chapter 13 I review the basic components of Aristotle's picture (as it has emerged) and consider its distinctive
metaphysical and epistemological foundations. Aristotle's account of essentialism is, I argue, distinct from that offered
by its major competitors (whether conventionalist or Platonist, as these are characterized in Chapter 1), and is immune
to some of the criticisms developed by (for example) Descartes, Locke, and Quine. Aristotle is not, in my view, the
type of Aristotelian essentialist they attack. Indeed, the form of essentialism he defends is preferable (in certain major
respects) to the alternatives currently available.
The book is constructed like a house with three storeys. On the ground floor, you will find (in Chapters 2, 3, 7–9 and
10 Sections 1 and 6) an analysis of Aristotle's discussion of signification, definition, and explanation in the Posterior
Analytics. On the next floor, you will see (in Chapters 4, 5, 6) Sections 1 and 2, 10 Sections 4 and 5, 11 and 12) an
account of his attempts to develop the Analytics model. Thus, in Part I some foundational issues concerning
signification, left unresolved in the Analytics, are addressed elsewhere, while in Part II the more abstract Analytics view
of explanation and definition is supplemented and made more determinate in the Metaphysics and biological writings.
On the third floor (in Chapters 6 Sections 3–6, 10 Sections 2 and 3, and 13), there is an attempt to locate and assess
Aristotle's accounts of signification and of definition in a broader conceptual context. Here, what is sought is an
Aristotelian vantage point from which to see familiar non-Aristotelian discussions in a distinctive way. These more
speculative sections offer the view from the highest window of a house whose lower storeys have been constructed in
a more cautious style.
The scholarly basis of this book lies in the careful exegesis of complex and difficult texts. While this work is
fundamental to my project, I have asterisked sections which can be omitted by those less preoccupied with detail of
this type. A reader interested in Aristotle's philosophical picture and wishing to see only some part of its exegetical
underpinnings may wish to follow a route consisting of the following Chapters or Sections: Chapter 1, Chapter 4
Sections 5 and 6, Chapter 5 Section 9, Chapter 6, Chapter 10 Sections 1, 2, and 4, Chapter 11 Section 6, Chapter 12
Sections 4, 7, and 10, and Chapter 13.
1 Meaning, Essence, and Necessity
1.1 Introduction
The study of meaning, essence, and necessity is of ancient vintage. Its subject matter, in so far as it concerns natural
kinds, can be defined by a set of questions:
(A) How is the meaning of linguistic terms such as ‘man’, ‘thunder’, ‘water’, ‘fish’, or ‘soul’ determined? What is
the relation between the meaning of these terms and what the speaker understands by them? Is an account of
the former also an account of the latter?
(B) Man, it is said, is essentially rational and necessarily capable of acquiring a culture. What, if anything, makes
these claims true? Is their source to be found in us as thinkers or in the kinds themselves? Or are they, in some
way, the joint product of ourselves and the world? What is the relation between essence and necessity?
(C) How can we know that kinds possess some features essentially and some necessarily? How is it possible for us,
on the basis of our knowledge of the relevant term and of some truths about this world, to come to know that
man is essentially rational?
Question (A) concerns linguistic terms and their meaning, (B) the metaphysics of necessity and essentiality, and (C) the
epistemology of necessary and essential truths. Aristotle laid the foundations for subsequent work on each of these
topics. My first aim is to understand his answers to these questions.1
1
My concern in this book is primarily with the essences of kinds not of individuals. Thus, I shall focus on such claims as:Man is essentially rationalorWater is necessarily
composed of hydrogen and oxygenand not on:Socrates is essentially a manorThis is necessarily water.With regard to the individual Socrates, my concern is with the issue of
whether (e.g.) he, considered as a man, is essentially rational, rather than with that of whether he is essentially a man.
MEANING, ESSENCE, AND NECESSITY 5
Aristotle's views on these issues are different from the ones widely accepted today. Discernment of these differences
has scholarly value. But there will be further philosophical gains if his ideas constitute (as they sometimes do in this
area) a live, and challenging, alternative to those currently in fashion. For, the study of his views may assist us in our
continuing attempts to address these topics.
Philosophers who work on the history of their subject make such claims as these more often than they substantiate
them. However, in this particular area such hopes are well-founded. In the early days of ‘modern’ philosophy, Locke
and Hume doubted whether we could have knowledge of metaphysical necessities in nature. They argued that the
source of all intelligible discourse about necessity must lie in our ideas and concepts. Their rejection of Aristotle's
account was further developed by their successors, Kantian and positivist alike. For them, our understanding of
necessity is grounded either in the preconditions of rational thought or in our freely chosen conventions and practices.
Indeed, it is only in the past three decades, as a result of developments in the study of modal logic, that this
longstanding, anti-Aristotelian orthodoxy has been challenged. Some recent writers have even claimed to defend ‘good
old-fashioned Aristotelian essentialism’.2 So, it should not be surprising that we still have something to learn from
Aristotle on these topics. For, he dedicated much of his life to their study.3
2
For use of this (or related) terminology, see for instance R. B. Marcus, Modalities (Oxford 1993), 45–70, B. Brody, ‘Why Settle for Anything Less Than Good Old-
fashioned Aristotelian Essentialism?’, Nous 7 (1973), 351–65. The term ‘old-fashioned’ comes from Quine.
3
Aristotle's writings on particular topics in areas as diverse as biology, psychology, and physics are motivated by his search for a general theory which answers these three
questions. In what follows I shall omit many of the details of his account of natural kinds in the hope of grasping its general outline.
6 MEANING, ESSENCE, AND NECESSITY
programme of modern essentialism.4 My first task is to set out the general outlines of this programme.5 Since I shall seek to
be explicit where its more cautious proponents remain uncommitted, I shall refer to the view presented here as that of
‘my modern essentialist’.6
According to my modern essentialist, certain terms in natural language, such as ‘water’ or ‘gold’, are correlated with
natural kinds with essences. This is because they were introduced in one of two ways. The first requires us to point to
particular samples of water. Here, in learning the term ‘water’, we acquire the intention to count a liquid as water
(roughly) as follows:
(1) For every possible world, w, and every individual, x, in w, x is water if and only if x in w is the same liquid as this
(or these) samples.7
In (1) the demonstrative ‘this’ refers to a particular sample of water, one situated within the speaker's visual field. We
intend to count something as water in any possible world (situation) only if it is the same liquid as this sample before us.
There is a second route to learn the term ‘water’, which may be characterized as the ‘stereotypical’ one. Here, we
acquire the intention to count a liquid as water (roughly) as follows:
(1′) For every possible world w, and every individual, x, in w, x is water if and only if x in w is a sample of the
colourless, tasteless liquid that fills these lakes and rivers (or most of them).8
There is no need for a sample of water to be before us when we learn the term, provided that we refer to the liquid in
our lakes and rivers, and intend to count something as water only if it is the same liquid as the one we find there. Of
these formulations, (1) is the more basic. For, our grasp on the relevant liquid is grounded in our ability to pick out
instances of it when confronted by it. We need to be able to distinguish water from other similar
4
In my presentation of modern essentialism I derive my main inspiration from the writings of Hilary Putnam. Saul Kripke's work on these issues is marked by great caution on
some of the questions which are central to our discussion.
5
My concern is with those aspects of modern essentialism that are sometimes labelled ‘non-trivial essentialism’. These are to be distinguished from trivial essentialist claims,
such as those concerning the necessity of true identity statements involving genuine names. The latter, it appears, follow from the theory of reference alone. For this
distinction, see N. Salmon, Reference and Essence (Oxford, 1982), 5.
6
On some issues modern essentialists disagree. On others they have changed their views. My ‘modern essentialist’ is one who has been prepared to adapt his earlier
formulations in the light of subsequent work. His position is, thus, something of an amalgam, although (I believe) a currently fashionable one. One version of this position is
characterized by Penelope Mackie in her review of A. Sidelle, Necessity, Essence and Individuation: A Defense of Conventionalism (Ithaca, 1989), in Mind 99 (1990), 635.
7
Putnam, Philosophical Papers ii. 232, ‘Meaning and Reference’, 128, in S. P. Schwartz (ed.), Naming, Necessity and Natural Kinds (Ithaca, 1977).
8
Putnam, Philosophical Papers, ii. 229–30.
MEANING, ESSENCE, AND NECESSITY 7
liquids in our lakes (or elsewhere). Thus, in what follows, I shall focus mainly on (1).
(1) and (1′) depend on the notion of ‘the same liquid’. For my modern essentialist, this is grounded in the intuition that
a liquid can look and taste like water (resemble water in its superficial properties) without being water.9 Thus, he
envisages our agreeing not to count something as water if it has a different fundamental physical property from that of
the water with which we are familiar in this world.10 He notes: ‘whether something is or is not the same liquid as this
may take an indeterminate amount of scientific investigation to determine’.11 Since we may discover by scientific
investigation whether two samples are indeed of the same liquid, we intend our usage of ‘water’ to be sensitive to
scientific discoveries about what being the same liquid consists in. The latter is a theoretical relation to be made more
precise by an empirical investigation conducted by the relevant experts.
One example of this approach is offered by Hilary Putnam. He characterizes being the same liquid as follows: two
samples of water are samples of the same liquid only if they possess the ‘same important physical properties’,12 ones
which constitute the underlying (non-superficial) ‘composition of water’.13 This account can (perhaps) be best
summarized as follows: two samples of water are samples of water only if both have the same basic determining and
underlying property, which is to be discovered by scientific means. Thus, we might characterize our grasp on the
notion of being the same liquid substance as follows:
(2) A sample s1 in some possible world w1 is a sample of the same liquid substance as sample s2 in possible world w2
if and only if sample s1 in w1 has the same determining and basic scientific physical feature as s2 in w2.
As things turned out, difference and similarity in micro-character constitute the relevant scientifically important
differences and similarities. This was an a posteriori discovery. It took much scientific investigation to discover the
fundamental scientific properties.14 Still more may be needed.
9
As Putnam notes in Schwartz (ed.), Naming, Necessity and Natural Kinds, 130.
10
As Putnum suggests in Schwartz (ed.), Naming, Necessity and Natural Kinds, 129 (final four lines) and 130 (top twelve lines).
11
As Putnum remarks in Schwartz (ed.), Naming, Necessity and Natural Kinds, 122–3.
12
Schwartz (ed.), Naming, Necessity and Natural Kinds, 129, l. 20. Putnam is not always clear as to the precise interpretation of being the same liquid. Sometimes he writes as if he
is assuming that possession of the same fundamental chemical properties (or ‘micro-structure’) is the important feature at issue. Nathan Salmon (Reference and Essence,
185–6) understands him in the latter way. I have preferred his more cautious formulation, which allows that it is (possibly) a discovery that micro-structural features are the
basic scientific ones.
13
Putnam, ‘Realism and Reason’, in Philosophical Papers (1983), iii. 63, ll. 1–5.
14
We are interested both in fundamental properties and in how such properties are structured. See Naming, Necessity and Natural Kinds, 122 (final three lines).
8 MEANING, ESSENCE, AND NECESSITY
Thus, while in (2) we grasp a priori what it is for s1 and s2 to be members of the same kind, empirical research is
required to specify what the determining physical features are.
(1) represents my modern essentialist's account of the way in which we fix the reference of the term ‘water’. We know a
priori that something is a sample of water if and only if it is a sample of the same liquid substance as these samples
(pointing to instances of water). (2) explicates the ordinary thinker's a priori grasp on the idea of being the same liquid
substance. It too is grounded in our positive reflections, conjectures, and thought experiments about what it is to be
the same liquid. (2) goes beyond (1) because it introduces the idea of a scientifically based, theoretical, sameness
relation. However, both are grounded a priori in the understanding of the ordinary speaker of the language.
(1) and (2) together explain certain features of our practice in using natural-kind terms. It should be no surprise that,
given (1) and (2), the ordinary thinker defers to the scientist about what things are (e.g.) water. For, the former accepts
that water has some determining physical feature of a type which it is up to the latter to discover. The pre-scientific
thinker's use of these terms will march in step with that of the scientist because the former has ceded to the latter
authority in determining what water is. Indeed, the term ‘water’ was introduced with the aim of correlating it with a
natural kind whose essence the scientist is best placed to discover.
My modern essentialist's account allows that different people may use the term ‘water’ in the same way even though
they disagree about many of the properties of water (including its fundamental one). Provided that they are all in
contact with the same liquid and believe (at least implicitly) that the liquid has an (as yet possibly unknown)
scientifically basic, determining feature, they can use the term with the same sense even if they hold differing beliefs.
The scientist who knows that water has certain scientific properties unknown to (or falsely diagnosed by) the pre-
scientific thinker can use the word with the same sense as his pre-scientific colleague. People with importantly different
beliefs about water can be using the term ‘water’ with the same meaning. 15
(1) and (2) have, it is claimed, ‘startling consequences for the theory of necessary truth’.16 If one adds the further
premiss:
(3) Water, in this world, has as its fundamental physical feature being composed of hydrogen and oxygen, it appears
to follow that water, in any possible world in which it exists, must
15
This applies at least to all who agree that (e.g.) water has a fundamental physical constitution and one which it must possess in all possible situations in which it exists. Both
these features cause difficulties which are discussed below.
16
As Putnam notes in Schwartz (ed.), Naming, Necessity and Natural Kinds, 128–9.
MEANING, ESSENCE, AND NECESSITY 9
have that fundamental physical feature. Thus, we may conclude from (1), (2), and (3) that:
(4) If water is composed of hydrogen and oxygen in this world, it is necessarily composed of hydrogen and
oxygen.17
My modern essentialist locates the source of necessity in (4) in our semantically deep pre-scientific referential
intentions (especially as in (2)). At the outset, we agreed to attach the term ‘water’ to the liquid with the same scientific
determining feature as this liquid in the actual world. We would count nothing as water if it lacked that determining
feature. Thus, we assumed that water possesses a scientifically discoverable, determining physical feature, and that
possession of that feature determines whether something is water in any possible world in which that liquid exists.
There is no possibility of something being water and lacking this property because (in our view, as reflected by the
referential intentions noted above) nothing could be correctly referred to as ‘water’ if it differed in this way from the
water we encounter. Thus, the source of the necessity of such claims as:
is to be found in the practices we follow in introducing the term ‘water’. For these convert empirical truths about the
actual structure of water (3) into necessary truths about how water has to be.18
According to my modern essentialist, no distinctive modal facts in reality are required to make (4) true. The injection
of a modal element comes from us and our conventions and not from reality itself. As Putnam himself notes, the
modern essentialist's proposal should not seem ‘so very metaphysical’:
17
I interpret this claim as the following one:□∀x [x is water x→□ x is composed of hydrogen and oxygen].and not the far stronger:∀x [x is water x→□ x is composed of
hydrogen and oxygen].The former concerns the essences of kinds, the latter the essences of individuals. One can only derive the latter claim from the former by adding as a
further premiss:∀x [x is water →□ x is water].This premiss requires further support from an account of the essence of individuals. My present concern is with the essences
of kinds.
18
While this claim locates the source of the necessity of such statements as:Water is H2O.in our linguistic conventions, it does not follow that such statements are about our
linguistic conventions. They are about the world which we understand as we do in virtue of our possessing the conventions we do.
10 MEANING, ESSENCE, AND NECESSITY
Rather [such a theory] seems to me to be what Carnap would have called an explication, a convention which has
some intuitive appeal and which enables us to systematize our pre-analytic use of modal notions.19
Sentences such as (4) will be true solely in virtue of non-modal facts about this world and our acceptance of certain
linguistic conventions.
My modern essentialist holds (1) and (2) as a priori truths grasped by ordinary thinkers, and adopts an explicitly
conventionalist approach to (2). He has a near relative who agrees that both (1) and (2) are grasped a priori by pre-
scientific thinkers, but denies that (2) is to be understood in a purely conventionalist fashion. The latter will interpret
(2) as expressing our grasp on (e.g.) certain principles of possibility, understood as essential ingredients in any
understanding of the world. In such an account, the a priori status of (2) rests on the preconditions of any thought
about an intelligible world.20 It is not appropriate to ask whether the source of such world-defining conditions lies
solely in us or in the world. Indeed, there will be no priority as between our contribution and that of the world. Both
are governed by one set of principles, which simultaneously determine our thought and the world about which we
think.
Despite the important differences between this approach and that of my modern essentialist, both share the
assumption (definitive, in my view, of modern essentialism) that the basis for (4) lies in the pre-scientific, implicit, a
priori knowledge of ordinary thinkers (such as is involved in their grasp of the kind terms). They differ in that the latter
group (whom I shall call ‘democratic Kantians’)21 do not accord the ordinary thinker's assumptions a purely
conventional status.
These accounts are taken to explain how we come to have knowledge of necessary properties of water. At the outset,
we know, in grasping the relevant term, that water has some (as yet unspecified) scientifically fundamental
19
Putnam, Philosophical Papers, iii. 65. In this context Putnam is speaking of Saul Kripke's account of individual essences. But the point applies equally to their account of the
essences of natural kinds. Indeed, Putnam represents himself in contrast to Kripke as adopting this conventionalist account of the matter in his own later writings: ‘If I am
right, then, given these referential intentions, it was always impossible for a liquid other than H2 O to be water . . . But the “essence” of water in this sense is a product of our use
of the word, the kinds of referential intentions we have: this sort of essence is not “built into this world’ ”. (Philosophical Papers iii. 221, top 10 lines.)
20
This second type of account goes further towards legitimizing our modal discourse than the first, purely conventionalist, one. It would be compatible with the first that we
are in error in making the semantically deep assumptions noted in Putnam's account of these issues. Locke and Hume both argued that while people believe that there are
objective modal connections in reality, they are mistaken to do so. In this they suggested what John Mackie has called in another context ‘an error theory’ of necessary
connections and real essences. (See his Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (New York, 1977), Ch. 1.)
21
Democratic Kantians are to be distinguished from élitist Kantians, who take the grounding for (4) to lie in the a priori knowledge of the élite thinker, whether scientist or
metaphysician. In the first part of this book my concern is with the question of whether Aristotle is a conventionalist or a democratic Kantian. It is only in Chapter 13 that I
consider whether he is an élitist Kantian.
MEANING, ESSENCE, AND NECESSITY 11
property. When we discover by ordinary scientific means that in the actual world this is the property of being H2O, we
know that this is the relevant necessary property of water. We upgrade the results of respectably empirical science into
necessary truths because of the commitments we accepted in grasping the relevant terms. There is no need for any
special form of metaphysical speculation to explain how we come to have knowledge of necessities in nature. We can
be essentialists without countenancing natural kinds, as classically conceived, possessed of their own essential
properties quite independently of how we describe them.22 Nor do we need a special faculty of intuition, or any
distinctive epistemological capacity, to grasp them.
22
The point is made by Putnam in Philosophical Papers, iii. 220. In this passage, Putnam (tentatively) represents himself as preferring the ‘conventionalist’ approach, and
contrasts his account with Kripke's (Philosophical Papers, iii. 221).
23
Ordinary thinkers need not assume that the particular feature in question can be discovered by scientists. It is enough that they believe that there is a kind-unifying feature of
a type some of whose instances can be discovered by scientists.
12 MEANING, ESSENCE, AND NECESSITY
(assumption(2)). But they may still remain agnostic as to whether the identity of the kind in all possible worlds rests on
its possession of that fundamental scientific feature (assumption(3)). Perhaps they have never given the matter a
moment's thought and would not know whether to accept assumption (3), if asked. They might think even that other
necessary features of the kind are as important for its identity, or prefer to remain agnostic on this controversial topic.
But, nonetheless, they use the term ‘water’ to refer to the relevant natural kind.24
Story 2: The Unsophisticated. Others may have no view as to whether water has a fundamental scientific physical feature
(as required by assumption (1)), even though they think that water does have some properties in all worlds in which it
exists which determine its identity (as is required by assumption (2)). They may be confident that there are some
properties which water must have to be water, but not believe that these are the scientifically fundamental ones. They
may think of water as having the same important properties as these samples, but regard as important only those
intrinsic properties which are relevant to their skills, not those which feature in a master physical science.25 They may
have no view as to whether the remaining properties of water flow from one fundamental scientific feature. Indeed,
they may not have grasped the idea of a determining physical feature of the type a physical scientist might uncover.
But, nonetheless, they may accept that water is a kind, and that as such it must possess certain properties whenever it
exists. In this way, more primitive people may succeed in grasping genuine kinds, and using terms to refer to them.
Such kinds may indeed have fundamental scientific features, but they are of no interest to the people who introduce
the term.
Both stories attribute to ordinary thinkers, using natural-kind terms, assumptions semantically shallower than those
required by my modern essentialist. Of course, confident and sophisticated thinkers may often make the latter
assumptions in using natural-kind terms. But this cannot by itself show that all ordinary thinkers who master natural-
kind terms always make assumptions of this type. Indeed, as the two stories suggest, we can (it appears) grasp these
terms without them.26
Many, favouring modern essentialism, will wish to reject the conventionalist interpretation of (2). But what alternative
basis can be provided
24
For consideration of related issues, see Graeme Forbes's The Metaphysics of Modality (Oxford, 1985), 193 ff.
25
For a view of this type, see David Wiggins's ‘Putnam's Doctrine of Natural Kind Words’ in P. Clark and B. Hale (eds.), Reading Putnam (Oxford, 1994), 203.
26
Nor is the issue altered if one invokes the idea of a pre-scientific thinker's reliance (via some deference mechanism) on his experts. For, there is no reason to assume (1) that
his experts are scientists rather than craftsmen, or (2) that he has ceded authority to them over matters in remote possible worlds. He need never have considered the latter
question at all.
MEANING, ESSENCE, AND NECESSITY 13
for this claim? Nathan Salmon once characterized (2) as ‘irreducibly metaphysical’, and ‘if knowable at all, knowable a
priori’, ‘the product of a sui generis branch of philosophy’.27 But these formulations, despite their salutary caution, offer
little insight into the metaphysical basis or knowability of (2). If (2) is to be understood in ways other than those
proposed by my modern conventionalist, its basis and knowability need to be explained.
At this point, some have emphasized the primitive and irreducible nature of necessity.28 But this move by itself is
unsatisfactory, because it is itself compatible with a wide variety of distinct metaphysical theories. Thus, my modern
essentialist could agree that necessity is irreducible. So too could Plato, opting for a rich metaphysical theory in which
necessities and essences are real independent features of the natural world. The same is true for the Kantian, whether
democratic or elitist.29 Irreducible necessary truths could be based on the a priori convictions of the ordinary thinker
(as in my modern essentialist's account), or on some yet to be specified metaphysical picture. As theorists, we need to
know which of these options is to be preferred.30
Some modal realists seem to think that we (or some of us) have a special sort of intuition which allows us to detect
what must be the case, a form of privileged access to the metaphysical grid which binds this world and all other
possible worlds.31 In their view, there are natural kinds with their own essential features existing independently of us,
and we are aware of them by intuition or some other special epistemological faculty. However, this form of Platonism
can only be successful if it can resist the objections brought by Locke and other empiricist writers. For, they challenged
the very coherence of this position on epistemological grounds.
Some modern writers have been attracted to the view that (2) is knowable a posteriori, ‘the product of scientific
discovery, of scientific theories’.32 Thus, Saul Kripke once wrote:
27
Salmon, Reference and Essence, 263 f.
28
As Kripke does in Naming and Necessity, 18–19, esp. n. 18.
29
An élitist Kantian is one who, like his democratic cousin (introduced in the previous section), believes that the source of necessity does not lie either in us or in the world, but
in a set of principles which simultaneously define both together. The élitist Kantian holds that this insight is the result of philosophical investigation, not one immediately
accessible to all concept users.
30
This issue is acute if one follows Salmon in separating trivial and non-trivial essentialism (Reference and Essence, 5). (See n. 5 above.) For, one needs to know the basis for
nontrivial essentialist claims.
31
This type of view is criticized by Saul Kripke in Naming and Necessity, 43–5. It is sometimes (perhaps implausibly) associated with the writings of David Lewis (e.g.
‘Counterpart Theory and Quantified Modal Logic’ JP 65 (1968), 113–26).
32
Keith Donnellan, ‘Rigid Designators, Natural Kinds, and Individuals’ (unpublished, 1974). This paper, originally read at a UCLA Philosophy Colloquium, is cited by Salmon,
Reference and Essence, 165.
14 MEANING, ESSENCE, AND NECESSITY
Science attempts, by investigating basic structural traits, to find the nature and thus the essence (in the philosophical
sense) of a kind.33
suggest that a good deal of what contemporary philosophy regards as mere physical necessity is actually necessity
tout court.34
However, he did not endorse this proposal, cautiously concluding that he was uncertain as to ‘how far this line can be
pushed’. His caution was fully justified. For, to sustain his suggestion, he would need to show how scientific theory
could give us knowledge of what is the case not merely in this world, but in all possible worlds. One would need to
know how (if at all) physical necessity is converted into metaphysical necessity. These fundamental questions would
need to be resolved before Kripke's suggestion could be vindicated.35
Contemporary debate on these issues has two poles. At one, the foundations for talk of necessity lie in our
conventions, in the deep a priori assumptions chosen by ordinary thinkers. At the other, they are the product of a
substantive metaphysical theory. The first option makes great, apparently implausible, demands on the ordinary
thinker. The second presupposes an (as yet to be developed) metaphysical theory of how the world has to be, and an
epistemological account of how we can grasp that this is so. But little has been done to make good these latter
presuppositions.
(*) F is an essential feature of kind K if and only if F is the feature selected when we define K.36
But this bi-conditional claim can be interpreted in several ways. For my modern essentialist, essential features are made
such because we have a set of definitional procedures. These definitional procedures are conventional, and embedded
in our grasp of natural-kind terms. Metaphysical priority is given to the right-hand side of (*). For the Platonist, by
contrast, essential features are there to be seen, graspable by anyone capable of
33
Kripke, Naming and Necessity, 138.
34
Kripke, Naming and Necessity, 164.
35
As Salmon notes, Reference and Essence, 264.
36
For some parallel distinctions, see my ‘Aristotle and Modern Moral Realism’ in R. Heinaman (ed.), Aristotle and Modern Realism (London, 1995).
MEANING, ESSENCE, AND NECESSITY 15
reason-based intuition. For him, priority is given to the left-hand side of (*). The Kantian denies that priority should be
given to either side of (*). In his view, our definitional practices cannot be understood without reference to essential
features of objects, but the latter cannot be understood without reference to our definitional practices. It is already a
mistake to ask which side of (*) is prior.
Are these the only alternatives? Is there a form of metaphysical account, distinct from those just sketched above, which
is immune to traditional empiricist criticisms?
Aristotle, I shall argue, sought to devise just such an account. His writings, far from adopting (ahead of his time) any
form of the modern essentialist programme, constitute a well-defended attempt to vindicate the claims of traditional
metaphysics without attributing to the ordinary thinker the deep a priori assumptions invoked by my modern
essentialist. Further, his metaphysical account differs in fundamental ways from the Platonist and Kantian options
introduced above.37 Thus, his views cannot be assimilated to any of the three options just outlined.38
Aristotle (as I shall argue in Part I) developed an account of the meaning and understanding of natural-kind terms
which does not require us, as users, to have intentions with the degree of semantic depth presupposed by my modern
essentialist. According to his account, one can understand the term ‘water’ as a natural-kind term without having any
views as to whether water possesses a fundamental scientific feature. Nor need one intend to defer to scientific
specialists who have such knowledge. For Aristotle, it is the craftsman not the scientist who is the key to understanding
terms for natural kinds. The craftsman can grasp terms for natural kinds without making the semantically deep
assumptions implicit in my modern essentialist's account.
If this is correct, Aristotle cannot have sought to explain the source and nature of necessity of claims such as (4) on the
basis of our pre-scientific linguistic intentions.39 Their status has to be explained independently of
37
Platonism, so characterized, does not necessarily involve either of the two following theses:(a)The world is composed fundamentally of universals, conceived as necessary
entities.(b)The fundamental components of reality can be known a priori.Thesis (b) is labelled ‘epistemological Platonism’ in Chapter 10 Section 6. If Plato held some version
of (a) and (b), his views would represent one species within the broader genus of Platonism (as I have defined it).
38
Of the options previously considered, Aristotle's views approximate most closely to Kripke's (cautious and unendorsed) suggestion that science uncovers metaphysical
necessities. But Aristotle's view of science, as it will emerge, is one permeated by essentialist thinking.
39
It is not merely that appeal to pre-scientific intuitions is insufficient to account for the source and nature of the necessity of claims such as (4). Aristotle, as I understand him,
also rejects the necessity of any appeal to such intuitions.
16 MEANING, ESSENCE, AND NECESSITY
resources drawn from the philosophy of language or an account of prescientific thought. If so, Aristotle needed to
develop the type of metaphysical and epistemological theory required by any who are drawn to essentialism but wish to
reject my modern essentialist's programme. I shall argue (in Part II) that in doing so he proposed an account distinct
from and preferable to the three traditional metaphysical options set out above.
Existence Assumption: If one understands the term ‘water’, one must therein know that the kind has instances.
For, it is a constitutive condition of understanding ‘water’ (on this account) that one knows of certain instances that
they are (in fact) instances of water (or is in contact with someone who does). In one version, one who understands the
term must be able to discriminate instances of water from instances of other kinds (or is prepared to defer to someone
who can). More cautiously, at the centre of the relevant practice, there must be someone who knows that the relevant
kind is instantiated and which kind it is (viz. the one instantiated by (some of) those examples). In another version, to
master the term one must stand in some less demanding form of epistemically reliable connection with actual instances
of water (one which does not require anyone to be able to distinguish them from samples of certain other kinds).
40
It should be noted, however, that Kripke's own writings suggest a marked degree of caution about the use of reference-fixing devices of this type. (See Naming and Necessity,
121 ff, 136.)
MEANING, ESSENCE, AND NECESSITY 17
Both versions of modern essentialism require one who understands the term ‘water’ to have knowledge of certain
instances of water (or be dependent on someone who does), although they disagree about the precise conditions
required for such knowledge. Both would reject the view that one can understand ‘water’ without having any
knowledge (either directly or derivatively via one's experts) of any of its instances.41 Thus, my modern essentialist
accepts (first) that one element of the meaning of a natural-kind term is determined by its referent and (second) that
one understands its meaning by having knowledge (either directly or indirectly) of its instances as instances of that
kind.42 He must reject the possibility of our distinguishing (e.g.) in the earlier stages of scientific investigation between:
(i) knowing the meaning of a natural kind term;
and
(ii) knowing that there is a kind referred to by this term.
In his account, there can be no determinate grasp on the meaning of such a term without knowing (derivatively or
directly) that the kind in question is instantiated (by certain cases). For, one cannot understand the term ‘water’ without
knowing that water is in fact instantiated by certain specific examples.
While some find this aspect of modern essentialism problematic,43 my modern essentialist aims to show that our grasp
of kind terms essentially involves knowledge of the existence of relevant instances.44 For
41
One could perhaps use the term ‘water’ without being able even derivatively to identify its instances. But, for my modern essentialist, in such a case one would not
understand the term, but merely ‘parrot’ it.
42
See, e.g. Putnam's remarks in Clark and Hale (eds.), Reading Putnam, 282–3. Here, he insists that the mind is to be conceived in terms of ‘a system of object-and-quality
involving abilities’, such that to possess the relevant concept of (e.g.) gold is to have ‘the beginnings of an identificatory ability’. The required ability is one which cannot be
fully explained without reference to the objects (or kinds) one is able to identify (perhaps with the aid of one's experts). Thus, to master the relevant term requires one to
have an identificatory ability which essentially involves actual cases of the kind. While Putnam's views on these topics may have altered over the years, my modern essentialist
is one for whom (as Evans and McDowell have insisted) mastery of a natural-kind term involves the ability (at least with assistance) to identify actual instances of that kind.
Thus, my modern essentialist is not a proponent of the ‘dual component account’ in which one can master a term without the relevant ability. (In earlier days, Putnam was
sometimes taken to be just such a dual-component theorist. See McDowell's ‘Putnam on Mind and Meaning’, Philosophical Topics 20 (1992), 35–48, and C. McGinn's ‘The
Structure of Content’, in A. Woodfield (ed.), Thought and Object (Oxford, 1982).)
43
See, e.g. Paul Boghossian's ‘What the Externalist Can Know A Priori’, PAS. 97 (1997), 161–75.
44
See, e.g. Bill Brewer's Perception and Reason (Oxford, 1999), 262 ff.
18 MEANING, ESSENCE, AND NECESSITY
Aristotle, by contrast, knowledge of the meaning of a kind-term need not involve anyone's having knowledge of the
existence of instances of the kind. I shall argue that he separates these two stages of enquiry, and thus rejects my
modern essentialist's Existence Assumption. The challenge he faces is that of showing that one can determinately
grasp natural-kind terms without knowing (even derivatively) of some cases that they are instances of that kind.45 My
modern essentialist thinks that it cannot be done. In Part I I shall examine Aristotle's (complicated) attempt to show
that it can.
are only necessary truths. For my modern essentialist, by contrast, ‘essentialism’ consists solely in the belief that objects
or kinds have certain properties necessarily, or (as he would say) in all possible worlds.46 This is quite different from
Aristotle's view, since it fails to respect his central distinction between necessary and essential features,47 both of which
are possessed by a kind in all possible worlds in which it exists.
At this point Aristotle faces two challenges. He must show how the distinction between necessary and essential
features can be maintained. It cannot be enough to point to the fact that we have intuitions about essences distinct
from (and more demanding than) those concerning merely necessary properties.48 He needs to establish that these
intuitions
45
If examples are involved in Aristotle's account of the acquisition of natural-kind terms, they must play a role different from that envisaged by my modern essentialist.
46
This understanding is captured in both (1) and (2).
47
This point was emphasized by Joan Kung in ‘Aristotle on Essence and Explanation’, PS 31 (1977), 361–83.
48
These points have been made recently by Kit Fine in a series of important papers. See, e.g. ‘Essence and Modality’, Philosophical Perspectives: Logic and Language 8 (1994),
1–16. Fine appears to base his claims on shared intuition. He has not (so far) been concerned to support them on the basis of a more general metaphysical or
epistemological theory.
MEANING, ESSENCE, AND NECESSITY 19
are metaphysically well grounded. Further, he must indicate how we are to make sense of the logical grammar of
claims involving necessary and essential features without referring to possible worlds.
[A] Since a definition is said to be an account given in reply to the ‘What is —?’ question, it is clear that one kind of
definition will be an account given in reply to the question ‘What is it that a name or other name-like expression
signifies? An example of such a question is ‘What does “triangle” signify?’50 [B] When we grasp that what is signified
exists, we seek the answer to the ‘Why?’ question. But it is difficult to understand in this way [viz. via an answer to
the ‘Why?’ question] things which we do not know to exist. We have stated the source of this difficulty above: that
we do not know whether or not the thing exists, except in an accidental way. [C] An account may be one in two
ways: either by being stitched together, like the Iliad, or because it shows that one thing belongs to one thing non-
accidentally.
[D] The above is one definition of definition, but another definition is an account which shows the answer to the
‘Why?’ question. In this way the first type of definition signifies [something] but does not prove anything, whereas
the latter type will clearly be like a demonstration of what F is, differing from a demonstration in the arrangement of
terms. [E] For, there is a difference between saying why there is thunder and what thunder is. For, one will say in the
first case ‘because fire is quenched in the clouds’. But what is thunder? It is the noise of fire being quenched in the
clouds. Thus, the same account is given in more than one way, first as a continuous demonstration and second as a
definition. [F] Another definition of thunder is ‘noise in the clouds’. This is the conclusion of a demonstration of
what it is. [G] The definition of immediates is an undemonstrable positing of what they are.
[H] One definition, therefore, is an undemonstrable account of what a thing is. One is a deduction of what it is,
differing in aspect from the demonstration. A third is a conclusion of the demonstration of what it is. (93b29–94a14)
49 b a
This is offered as a revisable first attempt at a translation of this chapter. I have separated eight sections between 93 29 and 94 14, [A]–[H], solely for ease of reference.
50 b
In this translation, I follow Ross, Aristotle's Prior and Posterior Analytics (Oxford, 1949), in deleting ti esti in 93 31. (But see below.)
24 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
Aristotle ends with a summary of what has been achieved in the last three chapters (Β 8–10). He writes:
So it is clear from what has been said [i] in what way there is a demonstration of the what it is and in what way not,
[ii] of what things there is a demonstration of the what it is, and of what things not, [iii] in how many different ways
‘definition’ is predicated, [iv] in what way definition proves the what it is and in what way not, [v] of what things
there is a definition and of what things not, [vi] what the relation is between definition and demonstration, and [vii]
in what way it is possible for them to be of the same thing, and in what way not.
Of the issues mentioned, (ii) and (iii) are addressed primarily in Β.8 and 9, while (iii), (iv), and (v) are the concern of
Β.10. The discussion of (vi) and (vii) spans Β.8, Β.9, and Β.10.
In this Chapter and the next I shall focus on Aristotle's discussion of issues (iii), (iv), and (v). My main aim is to argue
that Β.10 sets out Aristotle's three-stage view of scientific enquiry, and to support my interpretation by considering the
relevant sections of Β.8. I shall also investigate his account of the form and role of accounts of what names signify. In
Chapters 4, 5, and 6 I shall discuss Aristotle's account of names and their signification. In Part II (Chapters 7 and 8)
the issues raised by (i), (ii), (vi), and (vii) concerning the relation between definition and demonstration will be
discussed.
2.2 Initial Evidence for the Three-Stage View: Sections [A] and [B] of
Β.10
In sections [A] and [B] of Β.10, Aristotle appears to separate three distinct stages of enquiry as follows:
Stage 1:This stage is achieved when one knows an account of what a name or another name-like expression
signifies (section [A]: 93b30–2).
Stage 2: This stage is achieved when one knows that what is signified by a name or name-like expression exists
(section [B]: 93b32).
Stage 3: This stage is achieved when one knows the essence of the object/kind signified by a name or name-like
expression (section [B]: 93b32–3).51
51 a a
For the answer to the ‘Why?’ question is (in this context) to be identified with the essence of the phenomenon (see Post. An. Β.2, 90 15, Β.8, 93 4). Some might refer to
the essence (so understood) as the basic essence and allow other derived features also to be part of the essence. Aristotle sometimes refers to the latter type of feature as ‘in
the essence’ (see Β.6, 92a 7 ff.). Both types of feature need to be distinguished from any non-accidental features which are not (for any reason) part of the essence. (Idia may
be of this type.)
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS B.810: THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 25
Stage 1 is, apparently, distinguished from Stage 2, since it is the answer (in the case of a name) to the question:
52
For a contrasting view, see Robert Bolton's ‘Essentialism and Semantic Theory in Aristotle: Posterior Analytics II.7–10’, PR 85 (1976), 523 ff.
53
(1) encapsulates the enquirer's knowledge of the existence of the kind, (2) his knowledge that the kind has an essence yet to be discovered. (See Ch. 1 Sect. 1.2.)
26 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
54
In what follows I shall focus on the case of names and leave on one side the category of other name-like expressions. Ross identified these with terms such as ‘straight line’
or ‘complex angle’ which are name-like, but not (simple) names. An alternative is to regard as name-like expressions ‘accounts which signify the same as names’ (Β.7,
b
92 27–8). This latter suggestion might be strengthened by construing the subsequent line as follows:(e.g.) that which is signified by the answer to the question ‘What is
“triangle”?’In this interpretation, one would retain the to from the MSS and take it as a place-holder for the subject phrase ti esti trigonon (as W. Detel suggests, Aristoteles:
Analytica Posteriora (Berlin, 1993), 675–6). ‘Trigonon’ (or perhaps better ‘trigonou’) might be taken to refer to the term ‘triangle’. If so, the answer to the question ‘What is
“triangle”?’ would be a phrase like ‘figure with internal angle sum of two right angles’. So, the whole phrase would mean:(e.g.) that which is signified by a phrase like ‘figure
with internal angle sum of two right angles’.One might ask what this phrase signifies if one does not know what (e.g.) ‘right angle’ signifies. So understood, Aristotle is
envisaging two questions:What does ‘triangle’ signify?andWhat is signified by the phrase used to answer the question ‘What does “triangle” signify?’Both answers could be
useful in teaching.While this interpretation is attractive, I shall not rely on it in what follows. The text is too short and too uncertain to allow one to place confidence in any of
these readings.
55
I take the logical form of these claims to be:(1)∀x [x is a definition ↔ x is an account of what something is]. (Premiss)(2)∀x [x is an account of what a name signifies ↔ x is
an account of what something is]. (Premiss)(C)∀x [x is an account of what a name signifies ↔ x is a definition] (from (1) and (2)).From (2), it follows that some accounts of
what something is are accounts of what a name signifies. From (C), it follows that some definitions are accounts of what names signify. I take horismos as the subject of the
conclusion because this seems to be the topic of the chapter and the next passage begins with the term ‘horos’ which seems to refer back to ‘horismos’ in 93b29 and to contrast
this type of definition with another.
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS B.810: THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 27
Presumably, if the claim in (C) is obvious, this can only be because P(2) is also obvious.
How is the argument to be understood? In one traditional account (2) is interpreted as follows.56 The question:
What is triangle?
is to be understood as:
What is ‘triangle’?
and
interchangeably (71a13–15).57 These questions can both be answered by a claim of the form:
‘Triangle’ signifies . . .
where the dots are filled by an account which says what the term signifies. Alternatively, they can be answered by saying
‘Triangles' are . . . ’
where the dots are filled by a phrase which tells us what the term ‘triangle’ signifies. This is one way in which one might
explain the meaning of the term ‘triangle’ to someone who does not understand the English term. To him, one might
say:
where this is replaced by an account which signifies the same as the name (92b5–7). There can, as the immediate context
makes clear, be accounts of this type whether or not there is an object or kind in the world signified by the name. For,
there can be an account of what ‘goatstag’ signifies
56
This was the line taken by the Greek commentators, Themistius (Paraphrasis p. 51, 14 ff.), Eustratius (Commentarium p. 128, 20–35) and Philoponus (Commentarium p. 372,
8–19).
57
In this passage, ‘to legomenon ’ is in apposition to ‘to trigonon ’, which must itself be a term and not an object since it is the signifier and not the signified.
28 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
(92b5–7). Thus, if this interpretation of Aristotle's argument is accepted, there can also be a type of definition of what
‘goatstag’ signifies.
I shall argue that this traditional interpretation is correct. However, there is a problem. In Β.7 Aristotle limits the term
definition to accounts of things that exist (92b26–8). This being so, how can he accept in Β.10 that there is a type of
definition (horismos) associated with the name ‘goatstag’, since there are no goatstags? Nor is his restricted use of the
term ‘definition’ confined to one passage in Β.7. In Β.3 (90b16–17) ‘definitions’ are said to be accounts which give
knowledge of essence. But, since non-existents lack essences (92b28), there can be no definitions of non-existents.
Further, in Β.3, at 90a36, Aristotle introduces the phrase ‘what something is’ in the context of proof and
demonstration. But, since there can be no demonstrative proofs about goatstags, there should not be a ‘what
something is’ (of this type) in their case. Indeed, throughout book Β of the Posterior Analytics Aristotle restricts the use
of the phrase ‘what something is’ to accounts of existing objects or kinds.
There are two ways to respond to this problem. One, implicit in the traditional account, is to suggest that in Β.10,
93b29–32 Aristotle is expanding the range of definition to allow for a type of definition which gives an account of what
names signify, and not restricting definitions to accounts of some object or kind. If so, there can be a type of definition
which states what names for either existents or non-existents signify. On this understanding, Aristotle will accept in
premiss (2) that an account of what ‘F’ signifies is an account that, in the way explained above, gives a reply to the
‘What is F?’ question (even if there is no kind or object signified by the name). I shall call this ‘the liberal
interpretation’.58
The alternative, restrictive, interpretation accepts that Aristotle's full constraints on definition are in force in the first
sentence of Β.10 and exclude the very possibility of there being a definitional account of what ‘goatstag’ signifies. On a
restrictive reading, one would interpret premiss
(2) above as:
(2*) Some accounts of what F is will be identical with some accounts of what names signify,
from which one can derive:
58
Aristotle sometimes uses the phrase ‘F tis ’ to indicate not a type of F but rather something like an F in the alienans use of ‘tis ’ in which self-control is described as a virtue
b b
of a sort (See NE 1128 34). Can ‘tis ’ in 93 30 be taken in this alienans way (with horismos understood)? While it is difficult to find an exact parallel for the alienans use
with the relevant noun suppressed, such a use may not be impossible. However, the liberal interpretation does not require this reading. For, as argued above, Aristotle can
relax his constraints on definition, in the case of accounts of what terms signify, without describing them as only ‘definitions of a kind’. Indeed, the liberal interpreter may
prefer to take such accounts as definitions (of what terms signify and not of things).
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS B.810: THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 29
(C*) It is obvious that some definitions of F will be identical with some accounts of what ‘F’ signifies.59
The restrictive interpretation has two distinctive features. First, the claims in (2*) and (C*) concern a certain subset of
accounts of what names signify (those which signify existents with essences). Second, these accounts of what ‘F’
signifies will be identical in content with some genuinely definitional accounts of what F is. As a consequence, only a
subset of accounts of what names signify will be counted as definitions.60
There are two possible versions of the restrictive interpretation. In both, definitional accounts of what names signify
are confined to cases of terms which signify existents and reveal something of their essence. As a consequence, in
both, these accounts of what the terms signify will be the same in content as (some) genuine definitions of the kind.
But in the first version it is not required that one knows, in grasping this type of account, that the kind in question
exists. For, one may not know that the account of what the term signifies in fact defines the kind. This might be
discovered later, when one comes to know that the kind in question exists and has a certain essence. One will not
know what is definitional solely on the basis of one's grasp of the account of what the term signifies. Something further
is required.
According to the second version, by contrast, grasping a definitional account of what a name signifies involves
knowledge of the existence and essence of the kind signified. For, if the account of what the name signifies is indeed
definitional of the kind, one will (according to this view) know that this is so in grasping it. So understood, Aristotle's
view would be similar to that of my modern essentialist, as set out in Chapter 1. Indeed, one might justifiably regard
Aristotle as the founding father of this version of modern essentialism.61
Of these two versions of the restrictive interpretation, the first is fully
59
Thus understood, the logical form of these sentences would run as follows.(1)∀x [x is a definition of F ↔ x is an account of what F is]. Premiss.(2)∀x [x is a subset of
accounts of what a name signifies ↔ is an account of what F is]. (Premiss.)(C)∀x [x is a subset of accounts of what a name signifies ↔ is a definition of F]. (From 1 and 2.
)(2) and (C) could alternatively be understood as identity claims between some subsets of what a name signifies and some accounts/definitions of what F is.
60
This view was taken by Ross, apparently following Averroes and Zabarella. In more recent discussions, it has become generally accepted. It is held in some version by Robert
Bolton, Richard Sorabji in Necessity, Cause and Blame: Perspectives on Aristotle's Theory (London and Ithaca, 1980), 196 f., and by D. DeMoss and D. Devereux in ‘Essence,
Existence, and Nominal Definition in Aristotle's Posterior Analytics II.8–10’, Phronesis 33 (1988), 133–54.
61
As was suggested by Bolton in ‘Essentialism’, 515 ff.
30 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
consistent with the three-stage view, since knowledge of what a term signifies need not involve knowledge of the
existence of the kind signified. But the second is not, since it cannot allow there to be a distinction between Stages 1
and 2 (in cases of successful enquiry). Further, the first does not require that if we grasp a definitional account, we
know that we are doing so. In the second, by contrast, the definitional nature of such an account will be transparent
once we grasp it.
These three interpretations (i.e. the liberal and the two restrictive ones) offer differing answers to four questions:
(A) Does Aristotle accept the three-stage view? Does he think that every case of scientific enquiry involves a first
stage where one need not know of the existence of the kind, but must know an account of what the name
signifies?
(B) Are any Stage 1 accounts identical in content (in Aristotle's view) with any definition of a kind?
(C) Does Aristotle think that if one grasps an account which is in fact definitional one knows that it is so? Is the
definitional nature of that account transparent to the person who grasps it?
(D) Are all accounts of what names signify regarded by Aristotle as definitional in some way?
The differences can be represented as follows:
(A) (B) (C) (D)
Liberal: Yes No Yes Yes
Restrictive 1: Yes Yes No No
Restrictive 2: No Yes Yes No
I shall argue in favour of the liberal interpretation by defending affirmative answers to questions (A) and (D), and a
negative answer to question (B). That is, I shall defend the three-stage interpretation of scientific enquiry, in a form in
which all correct Stage 1 accounts of what names signify are definitional but different in content from any other
definition.
In the context of the book as a whole, an affirmative answer to (A) and a negative answer to (B) are more important
than an affirmative answer to (D). However, since an affirmative answer to (C) appears plausible,62
62
The argument runs as follows: definitions are accounts which reveal what something is (Β.3, 91a1) and, thus, make its nature known to us (Β.3, 90b16). Thus, if we grasp an
account which makes known to us the nature of something, we grasp its definition. There is no more to grasping a definition than grasping a knowledge-giving/revealing
account of this type. If so, there can be no case in which we grasp an account which makes a kind's nature known to us but do not grasp its definition.This argument could
be blocked in two ways:(A)Perhaps we do not label such an account a ‘definition’. But is mere labelling what is at stake (in Aristotle's account)? For, one could equally well
say (if this is all that is at stake) that we have a definition, and merely do not label it as such.(B)Perhaps (in Aristotle's view) we can know the nature of the thing but not know
that we know it. Perhaps he also thinks that we cannot have a definition unless we do not merely know the nature of the thing but also know that we do. If so, we will be able
(in his view) to know the nature of a thing but not have a definition of it.(B)would (if successful) give Aristotle reason for thinking that one could have an account which
makes a nature known to us without having a definition of it. But there is no evidence of any of these moves in Aristotle's discussion in Posterior Analytics Β. Further, they are
clearly controversial, and would need to be defended in some detail. Worse still, Aristotle defines definitions in terms of making things known to us (90b16), and not in terms
of making us know that we know things.
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS B.810: THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 31
the liberal interpreter needs to secure an affirmative answer to (D) to defend his affirmative answer to (A) and negative
answer to (B). For, if (C) were answered in the affirmative and (D) in the negative, one would be forced to answer (A)
in the negative and (B) in the affirmative (in line with the second restrictive interpretation).
The first section of Β.10 offers some evidence in favour of affirmative answers (A) and (D), the two central aspects of
the liberal view. Its support for the three-stage view has been indicated above (in Section 2). It also supports the claim
that for Aristotle all accounts of what names signify are definitional. Or so I shall now argue.
(1) This section contains no explicit restriction to some accounts of what names signify. If a restriction to some accounts
of what names signify had been intended, one would have expected a clear indication of this in the text.63 However,
there are no indications in the text that Aristotle is marking a restriction to a subset of definitions and to a subset of
accounts of what names signify. Further, if the context at the beginning of Β.10 is the one set by the earlier discussion
of all accounts of what names signify (Β.7, 92b5–7, 26–33), Aristotle's remarks in this sentence should apply to all such
accounts and not just to some.
But is this the context? Or has he shifted focus in the intervening chapters so that he is now concerned only with cases
of successful enquiry into existing kinds? For, if that were so, the relevant accounts of what names signify might, in
Β.10, be restricted to those which signify kinds with essences.
The immediate context at the beginning of Β.10 is, it appears, set by the aporetic discussion in Β.7. That was the last
time that the phrase ‘accounts of what names signify’ was used. It would be an extremely abrupt (not to say misleading)
transition if Aristotle were now to use the very same phrase in a far more restricted fashion. For, since his goal in Β.10
is to
63
The first ‘tis ’ must modify ‘horismos ’, and the phrase mean one type of definition. If ‘tis ’ had been intended to qualify ‘logos ’, it would have had to be placed after ‘logos ’ (cf.
de An. A.4, 407b 32) or (possibly) ‘estai ’ (cf. de An. frag. 4, 68).
32 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
resolve the problems raised in Β.7 and the preceding chapters, one would have expected him either to use the phrase
with precisely the same sense as previously or to signal clearly his more restricted use.64
(2) On the liberal interpretation, it is indeed obvious that accounts of what names signify are a type of definition, since
(as set out above) ‘What does “F” signify?’ can easily be taken as an example of the ‘What is F?’ question. By contrast,
it is not immediately obvious that all (or indeed any) accounts of what terms signify will be definitional accounts of what
the kind is. For, the latter will be of the form:
Fs are essentially . . .
where F specifies the kind and not its name, and the gap is filled by a description which refers to the essence of the
kind. But it is not obvious that such accounts are needed to teach a child the signification of terms such as ‘gold’? Why
cannot that be done by telling her that gold is a metal which looks yellow in certain light (assuming that this is not part
of its essence)? Answers to these questions cannot be assumed as obvious at the outset. Further, there is no
preparation for such a step in the immediate context. Indeed, in Β.7 Aristotle had made precisely the opposite
assumption: that accounts of what names signify are distinct from accounts of what something is (92b26–8). Given this
background, the transitions at the beginning of Β.10 are easier to understand on the liberal, rather than the restrictive,
style of interpretation.
(3) The first sentences of Β.10 contain some indication that Aristotle is making the liberalizing moves required if he is
to take answers to the ‘What does “F”signify?’ question as definitions and as proper answers to the ‘What is . . . ?’
question. To do so, he needs to introduce some relevant wider use of the term ‘definition’ and the what is . . . ?
question. But this is precisely what is suggested in the first sentence of Β.10, where Aristotle notes that definitions and
answers to the ‘What is . . . ?’ question are said to be coterminous. For, in this context, the use of ‘is said’ may be taken to
64 b
It may be objected that in Β.7, 92 26 ff. Aristotle dismisses as absurd the possibility of taking as definitions accounts of what names signify, which do not ‘take hold’ of the
‘what it is’. Thus, it might be said, he dismisses the possibility that there might be accounts of what names signify which do not take hold of the essence. If so, in Β.10 his
focus will be restricted to accounts of what names signify for the special case of names which signify existents with essences. However, this reply is unconvincing for several
reasons. First, in 92b 26 ff. Aristotle seeks to show only that accounts of what names signify which do not take hold of the ‘what it is’ are not definitions. He does not attempt
to show that they are not accounts of what the relevant name signifies. Indeed, he in no way challenges their status as accounts in these sentences (92b 30–1), only their status
as definitions. Further, it would be a big step (requiring argument) to disqualify as accounts statements which say what (e.g.) ‘goatstag’ signifies. For, answers to question like
‘What does “goatstag” signify?’ would most naturally be taken as accounts (unless further argument is provided), since they tell us something: what the name signifies.
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS B.810: THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 33
signal a relaxation of the standard constraints on definition. Indeed, it may invoke some popular view about what
definition is.65
There is further evidence of Aristotle's making the necessary liberalizing move later in Β.10. This would require him to
contrast the wider use of definition introduced in the first sentence of Β.10 with his own standard one. Thus, at 93b38
he distinguishes between the ‘one definition of definition’ just given and another one which is to follow. The complex
phrase suggests that the first definition is not a definition on the same level as the ones that follow, but is rather an
example of a definition of a different type. Since the next three are connected with proof, the first will be different if it
is not similarly proof-connected. This will be so if the first type of definition is an account of ‘What does “F” signify?’.
Since such accounts are said not to be involved directly in proof (92b32–3), they will be a definitions of a radically
different type from the three that follow.
These three arguments should incline us to favour the liberal view that all accounts of what names signify are
definitions (and so to answer question (D) in the affirmative). This view certainly has the advantage of allowing us to
give a straightforward interpretation of the first sentence of Β.10, while at the same time preserving intact Aristotle's
general constraints on definition. For (on this reading), the latter apply to definitions of things and not to definitional
accounts of what terms signify. Both versions of the restrictive interpretation, by contrast, have to give contorted
accounts of the argument at the beginning of Β.10 in order to represent Aristotle as imposing the same constraints on
definitional accounts of what terms signify as on accounts of the kinds themselves.
The first section of Β.10 seems, on balance, to favour both the three-stage view and the contention that all accounts of
what names signify are definitional. However, to secure the liberal view, one must, in addition:
(1) show that this view coheres well with Aristotle's route to resolve the aporiai in Β.7. (This issue is discussed in
the next Chapter),
(2) establish that this view coheres well with the remainder of Β.10, where Aristotle apparently introduces three
further kinds of definition, and
(3) show that this view is consistent with Aristotle's discussion in the earlier chapters (Β.8–9).
I shall attempt to establish (2) and (3) in the remainder of this Chapter. In discussing (2), I shall also examine the
further liberal claim that no account of what a term signifies is to be identified with any definitional account of the kind
signified.
65
‘It is said’ (‘legetai ’) is used in these chapters of the Analytics to describe the views of others (see Β.8, 93a 1) rather than to state doctrine Aristotle himself accepts.
34 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
When we grasp that what is signified exists, we seek an answer to the ‘Why?’ question. It is difficult to understand in
this way [via an answer to the ‘Why?’ question] things which we do not know to exist.66 We have stated the source of
this difficulty above: viz. we do not know whether or not the thing exists, except in an accidental way. (93b32–5)
It is impossible to know what a thing is, if we are ignorant that it is. Sometimes we grasp that it exists accidentally,
sometimes by having something of the thing itself . . . In the case where we know accidentally that the thing exists,
we are in a hopeless position as regards finding out what it is; for, we do not even know that it is. And to seek for
what something is when one does not know that it is, is to seek for nothing. But when one possesses something of
the thing itself, it is easier to seek. Thus, how we stand as regards finding out what something is is determined by
the way that we know that it exists. (93a20–2, 24–9)
In both passages, Aristotle claims that if one fails to know non-accidentally that the thing exists, it is difficult to
determine what the thing is (93b33–4; 93a26–7). Why is this so?
Failure to know non-accidentally that the kind exists arises because of a failure to grasp any of its non-accidental
properties (93a25–6). For, it is only if one grasps some non-accidental property that one can know non-accidentally that
the kind exists (93a26). Further, non-accidental knowledge that the kind exists is needed if one is to be able easily to
conduct a worthwhile enquiry (93a26–8). Without it, there is nothing to direct one's investigation in the correct
direction. One is seeking for nothing (93a27). If the search turns out to be successful, it will be a piece of good fortune.
For, if one fails to know non-accidentally that the kind exists, one cannot, without great difficulty, search for what it is.
In such a case, one will not have advanced at all towards knowledge of ‘the what it is’.67
66
I take ‘in this way’ to refer to progress to Stage 3 in investigation. It has been suggested that ‘in this way’ should be taken to refer rather to grasp on Stage 1 or Stages 1 and 2.
However, both these alternatives are problematic. It is not at all clear (with regard to the first option) why it should be difficult to grasp an account of what a name signifies
in cases where we do not know that the kind exists. Indeed, Aristotle envisages that this is just what we do when we do grasp an account of what the name signifies in the
case of ‘goatstag’ or indeed ‘triangle’ (cf. Α.10, 76a 33 ff.). Further, it is completely platitudinous to say that it is difficult to know a thing to exist if we do not know it to exist!
Indeed, the problem mentioned in the next lines appears to refer back to the discussion in Β.8 of the difficulty of the transition from Stage 2 to 3, and not of the difficulty of
arriving at Stage 2.
67 a
I construe 93 25–6 as making the following point: If one knows only accidentally that the kind exists one can have no grasp at all of any non-accidental property of the
kind. For, if one had some grasp on a non-accidental property of the kind, one would be able to know non-accidentally that it exists.
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS B.810: THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 35
Accidental knowledge that the kind exists involves a grasp on merely accidental features of the kind. By contrast, if one
grasps a non-accidental property of the kind, one can grasp non-accidentally that the kind exists. Both these cases are
distinguished from one in which one is completely ignorant of the kind's existence (93a20–2). For, failure to possess
non-accidental knowledge is compatible with having some idea that the kind exists, and need not make one totally
ignorant of whether it exists or not. There is at least one step in between failure to know and ignorance (see 93a20–1).
Aristotle, in Β.8, distinguishes three states:
(i) complete ignorance of whether the kind exists
(ii) accidental knowledge that the kind exists
(iii) non-accidental knowledge that the kind exists.
If one is in state (i), one cannot (on this basis) come to know what the kind is (93a20). If one is in state (ii), one can
come to know this but only with extreme difficulty because one has no clear idea of what one is seeking. Indeed, it is as
if one were seeking nothing. However, even so, it may not be impossible to find the answer, since, beginning with its
accidental properties, one may be able to work towards a grasp of its non-accidental ones. By contrast, if one is in
category (iii), it is easier to arrive at a grasp of what the kind is.
Later, in Β.10, 93b32–4, Aristotle collapses the distinction between category (i) and (ii), and makes the strongest claim
true of both (i) and (ii) together. The best one can hope for if one fails to attain category (iii) is extreme difficulty in
grasping what the kind is. This will be so if one is in category (ii). To say that those in category (i) will find this search
difficult is (of course) an understatement. But this should not cause confusion, since Aristotle, in Β.10, is considering
all who fall outside category (iii). Difficulty in search is characteristic of all except those fortunate enough to be in
category (iii).
The pressing question, for our purposes, is this: how is non-accidental knowledge that the kind exists to be achieved?
One model, suggested by the three-stage view, runs as follows. On the basis of a Stage 1 account, one knows that the
kind, if it exists, possesses some specified property.68 At Stage 2, one discovers that the kind does indeed possess this
property non-accidentally. The initial grasp on an account of what ‘F’ signifies provides a springboard from which one
can come to know non-accidentally that F
68
In such an account, one will grasp some property which the kind (if it exists) has non-accidentally. This formulation does not entail that one grasps that the kind (if it exists)
has that property non-accidentally. For, it does not require that one knows that one thinks of the property as a non-accidental property of the kind (if it exists). In this
context, I follow Aristotle in using the phrase ‘non-accidental’. This, as it stands, may include both essential and necessary features of the kind. (For further discussion of this
issue, see below.)
36 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
exists, and, thus, for a successful investigation of what F is. According to the springboard reading, grasp of a Stage 1
account is a helpful first step towards coming to know of the existence and the essence of the relevant kind.
If the springboard reading is correct, the first two stages in the case of the triangle mentioned in the first section of
Β.10 might be of the following type:
Stage 1: ‘Triangle’ signifies plane figure with three angles.
Stage 2: There are plane figures with three angles. So triangles exist.
On the basis of the Stage 1 account, the most that one can claim to know is that triangles, if they exist, are plane figures
with three angles. This can be known without having any knowledge of the existence of the triangle (Β.7, 92b16–18). At
Stage 2 one would establish (perhaps by constructive proof) that there are figures of this precise type.69 Armed with
this information one may search more easily for an answer to the ‘Why?’ question (Stage 3). For, one might seek to
detect that feature of the triangle from which its three-angledness follows.
69
On the role of constructive proof, see I. Mueller, Philosophy of Mathematics and Deductive Structure in Euclid's Elements (Cambridge, Mass., 1981) and W. Knorr ‘Construction as
Existence Proof in Ancient Geometry’, Ancient Philosophy 3 (1983), 125–47. It is one of several ways to establish existence of geometrical figures.An example of a
constructive method, beginning with two angles and one straight line, might run as follows:Construct two opposing internal angles on the line, ensuring that their combined
angle sum is less than two right angles. Continue the lines formed by the angles until they meet.This method will allow one to construct any type of triangle (and not merely
(e.g.) the isosceles), and nothing but triangles. Thus, it will give knowledge of the existence of the triangle, and not merely of some type of triangle. Aristotle is careful to
b b
separate knowledge concerning triangles from knowledge about types of triangle (cf. Post. An. Α.24, 85 9–13, also 73 31–9).Proclus, in his Commentary on Euclid's Elements 1
(384), comments on a route of this type, when he writes:If we think of a straight line with perpendiculars standing at its extremities and then think of these perpendiculars
coming together to produce a triangle, we see that . . . they reduce the size of the right angles which they make with the straight line (translation by Glenn R. Morrow
(Princeton, 1970))Here, Proclus links this method of construction with Aristotle's readiness to take the property of having angle sum equal to two right angles as one the
triangle's non-accidental properties. For, he continues:the amount taken away from the original right angles is gained at the vertical angle as they converge and so of necessity
makes the three angles equal in sum to two right anglesProclus takes this method to show, ‘in line with common notions’, that triangles have an internal angle sum of two
right angles (Post. An. Β.8, 93a33 f.), even though (in his view) the proof of the latter theorem may be given in different terms. I am indebted at this point to discussion with
Vassilis Karasmanis.
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS B.810: THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 37
There is evidence in favour of the springboard reading in Aristotle's discussion in Β.8. There, Aristotle is principally
concerned to distinguish between Stages 2 and 3, grasping that a kind exists and grasping what it is (93a28–9). Thus, he
writes:
In those cases in which we grasp something of the what it is, we proceed thus: let eclipse be A, moon C, screening
by the earth B. To ask whether the moon is eclipsed or not is to seek whether B is or is not. And that is no different
from seeking whether there is an account of it. (If B exists, we say that the moon is eclipsed.) . . . When we discover
it [viz. that B exists], we know at the same time that the moon is eclipsed and why it is eclipsed. (93a29–32, 35–6)
In this passage, Aristotle is considering someone who knows something of eclipses, and proceeds to come to know
that they exist. The discovery of their existence depends on coming to know something of their causal ancestry: viz.
they are caused by the earth being screened. This is how we discover (in this case) that the moon is eclipsed: by finding
an account of why the eclipse occurs, a relevant middle term. Before we know this, we have some grasp of what type
of phenomenon it is (e.g. a sort of light deprivation affecting the moon), but lack an account of why it occurs. In this
case our original grasp of the type of phenomenon cannot include knowledge that it exists. For, that grasp is prior to
and independent of the knowledge that the phenomenon exists. Thus, as predicted by the three-stage view, our initial
grasp of what eclipses are (e.g. deprivations of light (93a23)) is separable from our discovery that eclipses exist. So, what
does one's original grasp of eclipses consist in?
Some light is shed on this by the preceding lines. There Aristotle writes:
Sometimes we grasp that something exists accidentally, sometimes we grasp that something exists by having
something of the thing itself; e.g., in the case of thunder, that it is a certain type of noise in the clouds, or, of an
eclipse, that it is a certain type of light deprivation, or, of man, that it is a certain type of animal, or, of the soul, that
it moves itself . . . And in the cases where we possess something [of the thing], it is easier to search. Thus, how we
stand with regard to finding out what something is is determined by the way we know that it exists. (93a21–4,
28–30)
In cases where we have non-accidental knowledge that eclipses exist, we do so because we already grasp something of
what eclipses are.70 The
70
The structure of this passage is reasonably clear. Aristotle distinguishes cases where we grasp that the thing exists incidentally from those where we grasp that it exists by
having something of the thing itself (93a21–2). He then describes the difficulty involved in proceeding to knowledge of the ‘what it is’ when we only know accidentally that
a a
the thing exists (93 24–7). Next he returns to the case in which we know that the thing exists by ‘having something of it’(93 28). He concludes these remarks in the next line
a
by saying that ‘as we know that it is, so we stand to the what it is’(93 28–9). All is clear as long as one keeps separate three different uses of the verb ‘echein’ in this passage.
(a)93a21, 27, 28 (second use): having that it is/whether it is—this use is equivalent to ‘knowing that it is’(93a25, 26);(b)93a22, 28 (first instance), 29: having something of the
thing/of what it is;(c)93a28 (third use): standing in a given relation to . . .
38 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
phrase ‘having something of the thing itself ’ refers to the same stage as is marked out by the phrases ‘having
something [of the thing]‘ in 93a28, and ‘having something of the “what it is’ ” in 93a29.71 Thus, since the latter must
refer to a stage prior to knowing that the kind exists, so must the former. If so, our grasp of what eclipses are—a type
of deprivation of light—is a necessary condition for grasping non-accidentally that there are eclipses. In these cases, we
come to know non-accidentally that there are eclipses by discovering that there are deprivations of light of the
appropriate type. This is possible because armed with some information about eclipses we can proceed to Stages 2 and
3. Since this information directs our investigation into whether there are eclipses, its grasp cannot essentially involve
our knowing that the kind exists.72
71 a
The phrase ‘by having something of the thing’ in 93 22 could (in principle) refer to two distinct steps. It could refer to the information one brings, to one's encounter with
the thing, on the basis of which one comes to recognize the thing. Here, the information will serve as the springboard for coming to know that the thing exists. Alternatively,
it could refer to the mode in which one comes to know the thing: i.e. to the information one picks up in encountering the thing. The springboard interpretation is preferable
a
for two reasons:(a)It refers to the same stage as is marked out in 93 29 ff. where it must mark out a stage preliminary to knowing of the existence of the thing. For, this
a a
knowledge is arrived at in the process described in 93 30 ff.(b)The focus of the discussion is on a search for something: either to know what something is (93 27 f.) or to
a
know that it exists (93 30 ff.). But in the context of a search one needs something to guide one. Otherwise, one would not know whether or not one's search was successful.
72
How is the phrase ‘a certain type of . . . ’ to be understood? Bolton (‘Essentialism’) suggested that this phrase should be taken to refer to certain particular instances known
to be members of the kind. But this view, which requires that in knowing the relevant account one knows that the kind exists, is inconsistent with the three-stage view. There
are two other alternatives. ‘A certain’ could mean:(ii*) ‘a kind of . . . ’, as (e.g.) sharks are a kind of fishor(ii#) ‘a certain type of fish’, where ‘a certain’ is a place-holder for a
definite description to be supplied, as (e.g.) sharks are the type of fish with distinctive properties A, B, and C.In (ii*) the relevant claim is only that sharks form one
determinate kind of fish, but there is no requirement that one can now uniquely describe that type of fish. In (ii#) the claim is that the speaker can uniquely describe the kind,
using a definite description currently in his possession. (ii*) takes ‘a certain’ as part of the content grasped by the thinker, while (ii#) construes it as a proxy for a quite
a
different content he actually has.(ii*) seems preferable for three reasons:(a)The phrase ‘having something of the thing: e.g., . . ’ (93 22) suggests that what follows is itself part
of the content grasped by the thinker, not a place-holder for a fuller specification of that content.(b)In the fourth example Aristotle cites a phrase uniquely true of the soul:
‘the thing that moves itself ’. Since this is clearly part of the content of the relevant thought, it is best to interpret the other phrases as playing a similar role. Thus, sometimes
the content is a definite description, but not always. At other times an indefinite phrase will do.(c)One has succeeded in ‘grasping something of the thing/of the what it is’ if
one thinks of man as a type of animal. Nothing more specific (or conclusion-like) than this is needed.
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS B.810: THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 39
If this is correct, the enquirer's grasp on what eclipses of the moon are prior to his knowing of their existence will
simply consist in his knowing that, if they exist, such eclipses are instances of a type of light deprivation. This is the
information he would have prior to knowledge of the existence or essence of the phenomenon. But where does such
knowledge come from? An answer is provided by Aristotle's discussion of the void in Physics Δ.7, where he envisages a
person knowing (at the same early stage of investigation) that the void is a place, if there is one, which is deprived of
body (214a16–17). But here the source of the knowledge is clear. It is based on an account of what the name ‘void’
signifies:
Thus, in both cases the account of what the name signifies will give us knowledge that the kind, if it exists, has a given
property. Such accounts do not give us knowledge that the kind in question exists.
At Stage 1 one will have some idea of what it would be for there to be eclipses, but will not as yet have established that
there are any. Aristotle gives a further example of a similar predicament:
Nor is it different from asking of which of a contradictory pair is there an account: of its [a triangle's] having or not
having internal angles equal to two right angles. (93a33–5)
Here, one does not know whether triangles (as such) have or lack a given property: having an internal angle sum of two
right angles.73 When one finds a proof one will know both that this feature belongs to all and only triangles (or closed
figures with three angles) and why this is so. The proof might run as follows:
The total angles made by one line when it touches another line are equal to two right angles. The total angle sum of
a closed figure with three internal angles is equal to that made by the line touching another. Therefore, the internal
angles of such a closed figure equal two right angles.74
This proof establishes that triangles as such possess the relevant feature (cf. Post. An. Α.9, 76a5–7; Soph. El. 6, 168b2).
Thus, one would at the same
73
For, this might be a feature only of some types of triangle: e.g. isosceles triangles, or the ones one has so far drawn. One could not know, merely on the basis of a few
examples, that this is a feature of all triangles as such.
74
This form of proof follows that outlined in Euclid Elementa 1.32, which rests in turn on Euclid Elementa 1.13. Aristotle discusses it (or some near variant of it) in Meta.
Θ.9, 1051a 24–6.
40 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
time establish that triangles as such have an internal angle sum equal to two right angles, and why this is so.75
In this case, as in that of the triangle and the eclipse, one has, prior to proof, no knowledge of the existence of the
phenomenon in question. In the latter cases, knowledge of the accounts of what the names ‘triangle’ and ‘eclipse’
signify will not involve knowledge of the existence of the kind in question. In this way, the springboard interpretation
supports the three-stage view proposed by the liberal interpreter.
Let cloud be C, thunder A, quenching of fire B. B belongs to C (for fire is quenched in the clouds), and A (i.e. noise)
belongs to C also. And B is the account of A: the first term. (93b10–12)
Here, too, one discovers that thunder exists when one discovers that noise belongs to the clouds because fire is
quenched. Prior to this discovery, one will not know that thunder exists. Rather, if armed with an account of what the
term signifies, one will know only that ‘thunder’ signifies a type of noise in the clouds. This Stage 1 knowledge enables
one to conduct a successful enquiry into what exists (so as to possess non-accidental knowledge), and, at the third
stage, to discover more fully what thunder is.
In this example, the terms used in the account of what ‘thunder’
75 a
This proof rests on (a) an understanding of the nature of the straight line (see Physics Β.9, 200 17–18), and (b) an account of the triangle as a closed figure with three
internal angles, such as might be derived from an account of what ‘triangle’ signifies. This type of proof does not consist simply in giving a method to construct triangles with
a given property. It aims rather to explain why triangles, so constructed, have the features they do. Constructive proofs may establish the ‘that’ without yet establishing the
‘why’.
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS B.810: THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 41
signifies (‘a type of noise in the clouds’) belong to one thing non-accidentally because thunder is a natural unity. This
will be one of the cases specified in 93b35–7:
An account is one in two ways, one by being stitched together like the Iliad, the other by showing that one thing
belongs to one thing non-accidentally.
The latter phrase will pick out accounts like the one of what ‘thunder’ signifies.76 In this type of account, one thing
belongs to another non-accidentally. For, the account focuses on those features of thunder which need to be explained
by the presence of its more fundamental properties. This type of initial account (as emphasized above) is the one that
leads to successful enquiry and discovery of existence.
The other type of account specified in the passage cited is one which, like the Iliad, depends not on the natural unity of
a genuine kind but on a man-made unity which we create. One clear example would be that of ‘goatstag’. Here, the
account might run as follows:
‘Goatstag’ signies animals which are part goat and part stag.But in this case, unlike the previous one, the unity of
the account flows from us and not from the world. Although there is no one thing of which this account is predicated,
knowledge of it will allow us to say:
Goatstags are animals which are part goat and part stag, if there are any such animals.As in the case of thunder, we
will not know, on the basis of these accounts, of the existence of the relevant kind. In both cases, Stage 1 accounts will
provide the springboard for an investigation into the question of whether the kind exists. Indeed, at Stage 1 the
enquirer need not know which of the two types of account he possesses. In both cases, the accounts hold up a target
for an investigation into the existence of the kind signified.
Both types of account are bona fide accounts of what the names signify. They should, thus, be included among the
accounts of this type discussed in the first sentence of this paragraph (at 93a29–32). The sentence, so understood,
indicates that the paragraph as a whole is concerned with all accounts of what names signify, and not merely with that
subset of such accounts which are correlated with names for existents. If so, the paragraph as a whole provides a
context in which its first sentence should be taken as claiming that all accounts of what terms signify are definitions (in
line with the liberal interpretation).
Are there more than these two types of accounts of what names signify?
76
There may be other types of account which are relevant to this passage which are also one in this way: (e.g.) the accounts reached at Stage 3. However, since the only account
explicitly mentioned is at Stage 1, 93b 35–7 must refer (at least in part) to accounts at that stage.
42 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
In particular, would grasp of an accidental property of the phenomenon be a good case of understanding something
tied together by us? It would certainly not have the role of guiding our investigation which is played by a non-
accidental predication. Nor would it be an example of a statement which is tied together by us, since the latter are
distinguished from statements which represent accidental properties of things (Meta. Ζ.4, 1030b7–10, 12–13). If so, we
may conclude that the only cases allowed in 93b35–7 are ones which either predicate one thing of one thing non-
accidentally or are examples of ones which are tied together by us like the Iliad: e.g. that of ‘goatstag’. There appears to
be no third case.
As should now be clear, the sentence bracketed in the Ross text (93b35–7) is important for an understanding of the
first two sentences of the chapter. Indeed, the natural flow of the passage appears to be this:
(1) It is said that all and only definitions are accounts of what F is. (Premiss)
(2) There is a certain type of account of what F is which is an account of what ‘F’ signifies. (Accounts of what ‘F’
signifies are examples of a type of account of what something is.) (Premiss)
(3) It is obvious that one type of definition of F will be an account of what ‘F’ signifies (from (1) and (2)).
(4) Once one grasps that what is signified exists, one seeks an answer to the ‘Why?’ question.
(5) Accounts of what names signify can be unities in two ways: either like the Iliad or by non-accidental
predication.
The importance of (5) is clear. One type of account, like the one correlated with ‘thunder’, can lead to non-accidental
knowledge that the kind exists. This type of account involves non-accidental predication (see (5)) and guides the
enquiry in the way indicated by proposition (4). The other type, like the one associated with ‘goatstag’, cannot play this
role but is, nonetheless, a type of account appropriate for being a definition of what the name signifies. The final
sentence is important because it distinguishes these two types of account of what the name signifies.
If this is correct, the earlier lines 93b33–5 might appear something of a parenthesis:
(4′) It is difficult to proceed to an answer to the ‘Why?’ question in cases where we do not know the thing exists . . .
as has been said before.
But it would be a mistake to transfer the brackets from 93b36–7 to b33–5. For, while the earlier lines do not add directly
to the flow of the argument, they do indicate part of the role of accounts of what names signify: as Stage 1 of the three-
stage enquiry. In effect, (4′) captures the role played by some
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS B.810: THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 43
accounts of what names signify in successful enquiry, while (2), (3), and (5) emphasize that all accounts of what names
signify are definitions.
Section [C], so understood, provides additional evidence in favour of the three-stage view and of the claim that all
accounts of what terms signify have the status of being definitions. It completes the liberal interpretation of the first
paragraph. Can this interpretation be sustained in the remainder of the chapter?
Reading of Β.10
The view of Stage 1 of enquiry sketched in the previous sections gives a natural reading of the next two sections of
chapter 10, labelled as [D] to [F] in the translation offered at the beginning of the Chapter. The account of what
‘thunder’ signifies, let us assume, runs as follows:
The same account is given in more than one way, first as a continuous demonstration and second as a definition.
(94a6–7)
If so, the two types of definition cannot be identical because their aims and relations are different: the first concerns the
significance of ‘thunder’, the second the nature of thunder.
This fundamental difference can be illustrated in a different way. The constraints which govern the second type of
definition arise from the explanatory structure of the kind, while those that govern the first are based in the account of
the signification of its name. As Aristotle remarks, the latter is connected with signification, the former with proof
(93b39 ff.). Even if the very same words were used in giving both accounts, they would be used to do different things in
the two cases.
These definitions also differ in other respects. The conclusion of the syllogism given above establishes that thunder
exists. If the second definition is merely a grammatical variant of this syllogism, it too must give us the knowledge that
the kind exists. So, to understand that this definition is true is to know that the kind in question exists. It will be
grasped at Stage 3 when one already knows of the existence of the kind. By contrast, one can understand that the
account of what ‘thunder’ signifies is correct without knowing of the existence of thunder. For, the account of what the
name signifies does not give us the knowledge that the phenomenon exists. It is grasped at Stage 1 before one has
knowledge of the existence of the kind. Thus, the two definitions differ in the existential information possessed by one
who grasps them. For, they are grasped at different stages in the enquiry.
There is a further difference. The second definition consists in a specific claim about a uniquely identified kind.
Thunder is the kind of noise in the clouds with one determinate cause. That is the kind it is. By contrast, the original
account of what the name signifies is general in form:
Again, a definition of thunder is noise in the clouds. This is the conclusion of a demonstration of what it is. (94a7–9)
How is this related to the account of what the name ‘thunder’ signifies? Are they the same? They certainly appear to
use the same terms.
There are, however, differences between the third definition and the first, which mirror those already detected between
the second and the first. The first type of definition is concerned with the significance of the term ‘thunder’, the third
with the nature of the phenomenon itself. For, the third is closely connected with demonstration, while the first cannot
be (Β.7, 92 b33). Thus, the third type of definition requires features which are inherent in the causal structure of kinds
rather than in the signification of the relevant term. The two definitions are of different things: the former concerns
the significance of ‘thunder’, the latter thunder itself.
There are further differences. If one knows an account of what a name signifies, one need not know that the kind in
question exists. By contrast, if one knows something based on a conclusion of a demonstration, one must know that
the kind in question exists. For, such conclusions establish that the kind in question exists. Thus, one who possesses
the latter style of definition must know something not required for knowledge of what the term signifies. The two
definitions have different roles, because they are related to different stages in enquiry.
There is a further, semantic, difference between the two types of account. The third definition, in registering the
information encapsulated in the conclusion, refers to that very type of noise in the clouds (there mentioned) about
which certain causal truths have been established by demonstration.77 It must, therefore, be a specific claim about one
uniquely specified phenomenon: thunder. By contrast, the first definition is, as noted above, general in form, and fails
uniquely to identify the type of noise in question. While it says that thunder is a type of noise in the clouds, it does not
state which it is. Thus, the definiens as well as the definienda will be different in the two cases. Even if some of the same
terms are used (‘noise in the clouds’) at Stage 1 they are used to make an indefinite claim about a type of noise (tis),
while in the second they uniquely identify the phenomenon in question.
77
This type of definition could be stated as follows:Thunder is that type of noise in the clouds, which is caused by fire being quenched.As such, it will differ from the second
type of definition, which appears to run as follows:Thunder is the type of noise in the clouds which is caused by fire being quenched.For, in the latter, but not the former, the
causal antecedents are used to specify the relevant type of noise. In the former, it is assumed that one can specify what thunder is independently of its causal origins.
46 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
The first type of definition also differs from the fourth one introduced in 94a9–10:
What is a monad?
while the latter answers the question:
What is a ‘monad’?
This difference in form is important; for, it explains why claims concerning undemonstrables can appear among the
starting points of demonstration (Α.8, 75b31 ff., Β.9, 93b22), while claims about what terms signify can never be used
either as premisses or conclusions in such demonstrations.79 As before, the fourth type of definition concerns the
phenomenon signified and not the term which signifies. The differing connections with proof indicate a major
difference in the type of claim made in these two cases.80
If these arguments are correct, there is reason not to identify any of the three definitions discussed in 93b38–94a10 with
accounts of what names signify.81 If so, as required by the liberal interpretation, definitional accounts of what names
signify will constitute a form of definition distinct from any of the others specified in Β.10. One cannot know solely
on the
78 b
This is to take the example cited in Β.9 as an instance of an ‘immediate’(93 24): something which is a starting point for a science, such as the unit. So understood,
a
immediates will be distinct from immediate propositions (such as are referred to in Β.8, 93 36).
79
This is not to say that definitional claims about the monad (or, for that matter, the point, the line . . . ) are ever actually used in demonstrations. Indeed, as Vassilis
Karasmanis points out, such definitions are not used in Euclid's proofs (‘The Hypotheses of Mathematics in Plato's Republic and his Contribution to the Axiomatization of
Geometry’, in P. Nicolopoulos (ed.), Greek Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science (1990), 127.) However, the fact that such claims are of a form which can be used in
demonstration separates them from claims about what terms signify. For, the former (unlike the latter) are claims about how the world is (rather than about the signification
of terms). Thus, the former are part of science (understood as an organized body of claims about the world) while the latter are not.
80
The issue of the existential commitments of theses is complicated, and will be discussed in the next Chapter.
81
This was the line taken by Themistius in his Paraphrasis (p. 51, 3–26) and, with certain caveats, by Philoponus.
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS B.810: THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 47
basis of an account of what a name signifies that there is a real kind which it signifies, still less what its essence is.82
Aristotle continues (in section (H), as translated above) with a reference back to the three types of definition. This
passage is initially puzzling, since it refers to only three types of definition, while the chapter has referred to four. Worse
still, this passage seems to state a conclusion drawn from what precedes. So, why are only three definitions mentioned?
Our discussion suggests a solution to this puzzle. There are indeed four distinct definitions in this chapter, but they are
not all of the same thing. The first concerns an account of what terms signify, the last three definitions of things or
kinds. In the concluding paragraph of Β.10, the three definitions mentioned are definitions of things, relevant to the
specification of ‘what a thing is’ and connected with proof (94a15, 16–17), not accounts of what terms signify (Β.3,
90a36, Β.10, 93b38–9). After the first paragraph of Β.10, Aristotle's attention seems confined to these definitions
because he considers only accounts that are linked with proof.
Some scholars have argued that there are no more than three definitions in the whole of Β.10.83 But this is a mistake.
While it is correct that there are only three types of definition of kinds in Β.10, there are more than three types of
definition. Their mistake was to fail to see that the first type of definition (the one connected with signification) is of a
fundamentally different type from those that follow. As a consequence, they assumed that all four definitions had to be
of the same thing, and, thus, were forced to identify the first with one of the remaining three mentioned in the chapter.
But, as we saw in the preceding section, this cannot be done.
In these respects, traditional four-definition interpreters were correct. However, some made a further move which we
can now see to have been mistaken. For, they thought that if accounts of what names signify were not identical with
accounts of kinds, they would have to be about quite different items: meanings, denizens of a neo-Platonic realm,
completely distinct from the world of things. No further move of this type is required. For, as we have seen, accounts
of what ‘thunder’ signifies will mention properties which are features of the phenomenon, although they do so in
82
If one knows a real definition of the phenomenon thunder, and knows that the term ‘thunder’ signifies that phenomenon, one will be able to derive an account of what that
term signifies. For, the latter must specify some non-accidental feature of thunder (albeit in the general way indicated above).
83
Ross accepts the three definition view.
48 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
a non-specific way. Since such accounts refer (indefinitely) to (e.g.) a type of noise in the clouds, they specify in a
general way features of reality. The difference between these accounts and real definitions of thunder lies in their
differing degrees of specificity, and not in the type of entity invoked. For, in the case of thunder, the account of what
the term signifies will refer (in indefinite mode) to some non-accidental property of the phenomenon.
At this point, one can see the attraction of the three-definition interpretation. Scholars wishing to resist the other-
worldly, neo-Platonic, version of Stage 1 accounts proposed to identify the account of what ‘triangle’ signifies with some
account of the essence of triangles. But, as we have seen, this radical move was mistaken. While three-definition
exegetes were correct to insist that some definitional accounts of what names signify concern things in the world, they
should not have identified such accounts with any other definition.84 The liberal interpretation shows how accounts of
what names signify can be (in some way) about things without being identical with any real definition of the kind.
84
It should be noted that the positions occupied by the two traditional opposing views of Β.10 do not exhaust the field. If one group erred in identifying definitional accounts
of names and things, the other was mistaken in thinking that accounts of what terms signify were not concerned with real-world objects.
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS B.810: THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 49
(A) Premiss 1
Some will object that in the immediate context of 93a20–8, Aristotle is focusing on knowledge of existence and of what
the thing is (Stages 2 and 3), and not on any preceding stage. For, he begins by noting that one cannot arrive at Stage 3
save via Stage 2 (a20). In 93a21, he discusses various ways in which one can know of the existence of the thing:
sometimes by having something of the thing, sometimes accidentally. If so, the phrase ‘having something of the thing’
might be taken to describe what is involved in knowing of the existence of the thing. That is, the phrase might specify
the way in which we have knowledge (in certain cases) of the existence of the phenomenon, and as such involve
features drawn from both Stages 1 and 2. It need not be restricted to features drawn from Stage 1 (as in the
springboard interpretation sketched above). Rather, it will describe a mode of having knowledge of the thing at Stage 2.85
I have argued above for the springboard reading of 93a20–36. However, even if my interpretation of 93a20–9 were
rejected, it remains difficult to resist it in lines 93a30–6. For, there one has a grasp on eclipses which enables one to
investigate their existence. So, one must have a grasp on eclipses which is not existence-involving. Similarly with the
triangle example. Thus, even if one were to prefer the mode reading of the lines up to 93a30, the following lines would
force one to distinguish two separate elements which had previously been taken together, stages which
85
The sense of ‘knowledge’ appears to remain constant in Β.8, and there is no place for a clear distinction between ordinary and scientific knowledge in this context. ‘To have’
(‘echein ’ (93a 20, 26, 29, 30)) is used, apparently interchangeably, with ‘to know’ (‘eidenai ’ (93a 20, 25, 26, 36, b2–3)). Nor is there a gap between the use of ‘knowing’ in 93a
35–6 and in 93a 20–1.
50 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
correspond respectively to Stage 1 and Stage 2. If so, at Stage 1, one will grasp a specification of what (e.g.) ‘triangle’ or
‘eclipse’ signifies without knowing of the existence of the kind in question.
(B) Premiss 2
Some will object that Aristotle could not have allowed that an account of what ‘goatstag’ signifies could be a definition
because (in their view) in Posterior Analytics Β.7 he rules out the possibility of definitions of non-existents. If so, it will be
claimed, some version of the restrictive view must be correct. Or else, Aristotle's views in Β.7 and Β.8–10 are
inconsistent.
I shall consider this objection in the next Chapter. It should be noted, however, that its starting point lies in the
aporetic chapter Β.7 rather than in the chapters where the aporiai are resolved. Further, it assumes that Aristotle accepts
throughout Β.8–10 that there can be no definition of any kind in the case of non-existents. But, since in these chapters
Aristotle is making distinctions which aim to overcome these aporiai, it cannot be safe to assume that all Β.7 claims
remain intact. Some will have to be modified to overcome the problems raised. Thus, if (as the liberal interpreter
suggests) in Β.10 one type of definition is connected with accounts of what terms signify and another with accounts of
things, Aristotle could easily insist that only the latter be confined to existents while allowing that the former need not
be. For, in this way the requirement in Β.7 that all definitions be of existents will be shown to apply to real definitions
of existing kinds, but not to accounts of what names signify. In general, it seems (methodologically) better to see
Aristotle in Β.10 as modifying the views in Β.7 that led to aporia rather than as treating those assumptions as fixed and
secure. If so, the present objection is not powerful.
(C) Premiss 3
Some might accept the three-stage reading of Β.8, but deny that this says anything about accounts of what terms
signify. According to this view, accounts of what names signify will be introduced in Β.10 without further preparation
in the immediately preceding discussion in Β.8. Indeed, their role in successful investigation will not be discussed prior
to Β.10 save in the aporetic sections of Β.7.
If this objection is sustained, Aristotle's whole discussion of accounts of what names signify will be woefully
incomplete. For, if we exclude back references to Β.8, Β.10 leaves us in the dark about the precise role and nature of
these accounts. Thus, it seems preferable (on methodological grounds) to regard the relevant Β.10 discussion
(93b29–37) as depending on the stage of
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS B.810: THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 51
enquiry marked out in Β.8 (at 93a30–6) as prior to the discovery of existence of the phenomenon. In this way, Β.10
builds on the argument of Β.8 by showing that accounts of what names signify give us Stage 1 knowledge that (e.g.)
thunder, if it exists, is a type of noise in the clouds.
This reply can be strengthened. The first sentences of Β.10 explicitly look back to Β.8 (93a32–5). Indeed, the example
of the triangle makes clear the backwards connection. For, as we know from Β.7, knowledge of what the term ‘triangle’
signifies is separate from knowledge of the existence of the phenomenon (92b15–16). While Β.8 does not contain any
discussion of the transition from one to the other, it introduces at the relevant spot (93a29 ff.) the similar case of
establishing the existence of a feature of the triangle: its having angle sum equal to two right angles. This offers a
parallel to what is involved in establishing the existence of the triangle. If so, even though accounts of what names
signify make their first appearance in Β.10, they are best seen as located at the space prepared (and, to some extent,
indicated) for them in the argument of Β.8.
(D) Premiss 4
It may be objected that in 93a30–6 Aristotle is exclusively concerned with ‘scientific knowledge’ of the existence of
kinds. But this (it will be said) is quite consistent with someone knowing in some everyday sense of the existence of
thunder before they have scientific knowledge of its existence. Indeed, it will be suggested, this is precisely what is
envisaged in 93a20–30, where (it will be claimed) one has everyday knowledge of the existence of certain phenomena
prior to scientific proof. If so, one cannot conclude that the first stage of enquiry involves no knowledge at all of
existence. Perhaps it only falls short of scientific knowledge of existence.
It is, however, hard to sustain this objection in the immediate context of Β.8. For, the very same term is used
throughout for knowledge in 93a20–9 and a29–b2—eidenai (a20, 25, 26, 36, 93b3)—without any indication that he is
referring to different types of knowledge in different places (as the objector would require). Rather, Aristotle's claims
appear to concern the same type of knowledge (without further qualification) throughout the chapter. Thus, when at
93b15 he makes the general and unqualified claim that there can be no coming to know what something is without
proof, he appears to commit himself to the strong thesis that all routes to knowledge in these cases are through proof.
Unscientific knowledge appears absent from the present discussion. Nor is it difficult to see why. In these chapters,
Aristotle is concerned with the existence and nature of kinds, what such kinds have or are as such. It will not do for his
purposes to establish that some triangles have a given feature or that (e.g.) isosceles triangles exist. For, he is concerned
to establish not merely that some specific
52 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
type of triangle exists or has a given feature, but that there is a wider kind of which (e.g.) the isosceles is an example.
For this reason, one could not know that triangles exist merely by pointing to examples of triangles. For such examples
could not establish the existence of the wider kind, triangle, rather than of some narrower kind (e.g. scalene triangle).86
(E) Premiss 5
It was argued above that the initial account of what ‘thunder’ signifies will specify it as a type of noise in the clouds.
But, if this is correct, how can the enquirer on this basis proceed to discover the existence or nature of thunder? For,
since there are other kinds of noise in the clouds (sheep on misty mountains, cloud-covered volcanoes . . . ), how can
we discover the existence of thunder rather than of any of the other types of noise in the clouds? It appears that the
enquirer does not have the resources to discover that the relevant specific kind exists. If so, it will be said, the original
account must be more specific. Surely, there must be more content if it is to do what is required to be a springboard for
Stage 2? Perhaps we need to think of thunder as being noise in the clouds caused in a given way (if there is any such
noise), or as noise in the clouds accompanied by lightning (if there is any such thing)? Surely our thoughts at Stage 1
must have more specificity than has so far been allowed?
This objection rests on a major (and controversial) assumption: that all the information needed to determine the
extension of the relevant name will be available to the enquirer at Stage 1. However, it could well be that there are
features which determine the extension of the term, which are not available at Stage 1. Thus, if (for example) the
signification of the term is determined (in part) by the enquirer being in causal contact of a given type with the world,
the extension of the term will be fixed by features not (necessarily) accessible to the enquirer, and not grasped as part
of his account of what the term signifies. For, if external features can play some role in determining the signification of
the term, they need not be part of the Stage 1 account of what the name signifies but still could be (subsequently) used
in establishing the existence of the relevant kind. Indeed, one might at this stage exploit the causal connection to latch
on to that kind rather than another.
This objection cannot be met until we have a clearer grasp of how the signification of the name is determined (in
Aristotle's account). So we will return to this issue in Chapter 4. There is a lacuna here that needs to be filled.87
86
For further discussion of this issue see Ch. 3 Sect. 3.5.
87
Some will see immediately that larger issues concerning the role of external factors in determining signification are central to this discussion. While they are correct, I ask
them to be patient. These issues will come to the fore in Chapter 4.
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS B.810: THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 53
remaining agnostic as to whether there is one determining factor which holds that nature together).88
Aristotle's second example (93a36–b2) takes the issue further. He writes:
Let C be moon, A eclipse, B inability to cast shadows at full moon with nothing obvious in between. If B belongs to
the moon, and A belongs to B, then it is clear that there is an eclipse, but not why, and we know that there is an
eclipse, but not what an eclipse is.
According to this passage, we can know that there is an eclipse without knowing its fundamental cause. All we need
know is that there is some causal structure (or nature) present. If so, there can be no requirement that on the basis of
Stage 1 we know that eclipses, if they exist, have one fundamental cause. For, in grasping their existence, we do not rely
on its having a fundamental causal structure. Thus, it is natural to think that we must be able (at Stage 1) to grasp what
eclipses are without knowing that if they exist they have a fundamental (or determining) cause of this type.
In the case at issue, in establishing the existence of the eclipse, one needs to know something of the nature (or causal
structure) of the phenomenon. To find that eclipses manifest a specific inability of the moon, the one manifested in its
failure to cast a shadow at full moon when nothing is in between, is to find something of their causal structure.89 This
inability, of
88
It is not obvious that any reference to causal material is required at Stage 1. Perhaps one refers to causation only at Stage 2, when one seeks to establish that the kind exists.
Thus understood, causal notions would not be part of the account of what the term signifies, and would only be relevant in establishing the existence of the kinds in
question. I return to the topic in Chapter 6.
89
The phrase ‘not being able to cast shadows . . . at a full moon’ can be interpreted in more than one way. It might specify:(a)the inability of the moon—if full and if nothing is
in between—to cast shadows,or(b)the inability of the moon, when full and nothing is in between, to cast shadows.In (a), the moon may have the same conditional inability
(to cast-no-shadows-when-full) even when it is not full. In (b), by contrast, the moon will lack the relevant unconditional inability to cast shadows when it is not full. It has
the relevant inability only under the conditions specified.(A similar contrast is clearly marked by David Pears in ‘Ifs and Cans’, Questions in the Philosophy of Mind (London,
1975), 142 ff.)Of these interpretations, I prefer (a) for two reasons:(1)It specifies an inability which is present when and only when there is an eclipse. As such, it allows one
to determine whether or not any given case is one of an eclipse—provided that one can establish that the inability responsible for the current light failure is the same one as
is responsible for the failure to cast shadows when the moon is full. This makes the case closely parallel to that of the triangle discussed above.(2)In general, Aristotle appears
a
to prefer (unconditionally) to attribute to subjects conditional powers—if conditions are such and such?—to act in certain ways (cf. Meta. Θ.5, 1048 16–21). That is, he
seems reluctant to think of their capacities as coming and going depending on the circumstances in which they find themselves. For further discussion of this issue, see my
Aristotle's Philosophy of Action (London, 1984), 24 ff.In (a) there is reference to some aspect of the permanent structure of the eclipse, although not to the fundamental cause of
the relevant inability (as specified in 93b5: quenching . . . interposition). In (b), by contrast, there would be reference only to what is a cause in certain cases of eclipses, and
not in all. In neither need one know anything about the essence of the kind (if it exists).
POSTERIOR ANALYTICS B.810: THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 55
course, will not be the basic causal factor, since its presence in turn needs to be explained. (See, for the suggestion of
further explanation, 93b12–14.) But it is still an account (one logos among many (93b14)) of some aspect of the nature of
the eclipse. It is a factor which distinguishes eclipses from things that look like eclipses but are not.90
The most that could be extracted from this passage (concerning Stage 1) is the claim that if the kind exists it has some
causal nature.91 But this involves no commitment to the view that the kind has one determining feature (or essence).
While the latter may emerge as the enquiry progresses, the enquirer (at Stage 1) need only have a comparatively shallow
grasp of the nature in question. He will think of it merely as a kind with some internal causal structure, but that is all.
These passages provide some support for a shallower view of the understanding of the ordinary thinker than is
suggested by my modern essentialist.92 But they do not make it absolutely clear what is required, or why. Does one
need to grasp a feature which is, in fact, part of the essence, or will it be enough to grasp a feature which is, in fact,
necessary? Since these issues are left unresolved, there remain major gaps in Aristotle's account.
90
Ross, commenting on this passage, says (p. 631):At this point Aristotle's account takes a curious turn. He represents the question of whether the moon suffers eclipse as
being solved not, as we might expect, by direct observation or inference from a symptom, but by asking whether the interposition of the earth . . . occurs.But this
development need not seem strange. In investigating whether there are eclipses, one needs to be able to distinguish (in some cases) between eclipses and things that look like
a
(but are not) eclipses. Situated as we are, this can only be done by investigation of the relevant cause (compare the possible case discussed at Post. An. Β.2, 90 25 ff.). Indeed,
one should be able to make this distinction in all cases. For, then one will know of the existence of eclipses, and not of some subset of eclipses (e.g. those at full moon).
91
This can only be extracted if one makes an assumption stronger than those noted in n. 40 above.
92
There is no commitment to the claim, essential to (2) in my modern essentialist's account, that the kind has a determining and underlying (necessary) physical feature (see
Ch. 1, Sect. 1.2). This difference is independent of the modern essentialist's tendency to describe all non-accidental properties as essential.
56 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
93
See Ch. 2, Sect. 2.3. (A*), (D*), and (B*) are liberal answers to issues (A), (D) and (B) raised there.
94
This Chapter does not aim to provide further evidence in favour of (B*). The precise content of such definitions is only discussed in Β.8–10.
58 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
It must be ceded at the outset that not all the aporiai raised in Posterior AnalyticsΒ.3–7 are resolved by introducing the
three-stage view. Others require a fuller account of the nature of definition at Stage 3. These latter difficulties will be
discussed in Chapters 7 and 8.
Aristotle concludes Β.7 with the following very striking aporetic remark:
From this, then, it is evident that definition and deduction are not the same, and that deduction and definition are
not of the same thing; and, in addition, that definition neither demonstrates nor proves anything, and that you
cannot become aware of what a thing is either by definition or demonstration. (92b35–8)
In Sections 3.2–3.4 I shall consider the arguments which led him to these conclusions in Β.7, and in Sections 3.5–3.6
suggest that the three-stage view (as developed in Β.8–10) constitutes part of his answer to the problems raised in
Β.3–7. For, that view enables him to challenge one of the key assumptions he had made in setting up the aporiai.
In Β.7 there are several interconnected arguments in favour of a negative answer to the question:
How can you prove what a thing is? For, it is necessary for the person who knows what a man or anything else is, to
know that it exists (for, in respect to that which does not exist, no one knows what it is; you may know what the
account or name signifies, e.g. when I say ‘goatstag’, but it is impossible to know what a goatstag is). But, if you are to
prove what it is and that it is, how can you do both by the same argument? For, a definition and a demonstration
show one thing; but what a man is and that a man is are different. (92b4–11)
This argument suggests that one cannot know what a thing is if one does not know that it exists. But (it claims) one
cannot show by the same argument both that the kind, man, exists and what a man is, since an argument makes one
thing clear, and these two claims would require different conclusions. This argument aims to show that there can be no
one proof which shows both that man exists and what man is. It cannot establish that there can be no proof of what a
man is. The most it can demonstrate is that the proof of what a man is must be different from the proof that man
exists.
95 a b
I omit the first (92 35– 3), which is directed to showing the impossibility of proving what something is in any of the possible styles of proof. This argument concerns Stage
3 not Stage 1.
PREPARATION FOR THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 59
Next, we say that it is necessary for everything that a thing is to be proved by demonstration, unless it is its essence.
But being is not the essence of anything; for, that it is is not a kind. Therefore, there will be a demonstration that the
thing exists. And this is what sciences actually do. The geometer assumes what ‘triangle’ signifies and proves that it
is. Now, when you define what it is, what will you prove except what a triangle is? If so, you will know by definition
what a triangle is, but you will not know if it is. But that is impossible. (92b12–18)
This argument suggests that the definer (as distinct from the geometer who establishes the existence of the triangle)
reveals what a triangle is. But if this is so, and what the definer reveals is distinct from and independent of the proof
that the triangle exists (as argued in 92b4–11), it will be possible to know the real definition of a triangle without
knowing that triangles exist. However, this consequence is one which Aristotle takes to be an impossibility.96
These two arguments work closely together. The proof that the triangle exists must either be identical with or distinct
from the proof of what it is essentially. However, the first argument shows that these two proofs cannot be identical,
and the second establishes that they cannot be distinct. Therefore, Aristotle concludes, there can be no proof of what a
triangle is.
These arguments turn on the following assumptions:
(i) The claim that F exists is different in form from the claim that F is essentially G.
(ii) If these claims are different, it must be possible to know one without knowing the other.
(ii) is a very strong Independence Assumption, which Aristotle employs elsewhere in the aporetic chapters. Thus, in Β.3 he
argues:
To know what is demonstrable is to have a demonstration. But, since there is a demonstration of some claims (like
all triangles are F), clearly there will be no definition of this—for, that way someone would know them in virtue of the
definition without having the demonstration; for, nothing prevents him from having one without the other.
(90b9–13)
96
See, e.g.Β.8, 93a 18 ff.
60 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
In Β.4 and Β.6 Aristotle argued that whole definitions could not be demonstrated in the conclusions of the form of
syllogism he favoured.99 Conclusions of demonstrations could not be of the form:
97
In fact, Aristotle could have drawn a stronger conclusion from these premisses:No one proposition can be known by both a definitional and a demonstrative route.It is
initially surprising that Aristotle does not challenge premiss 1, but takes it as a basic datum. This argument is analysed by Barnes, Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 2nd edn.
(Oxford, 1994), 207.
98
The converse problem: ‘How can they be so related that one cannot know the demonstration without knowing the definition?’ is not one which troubled Aristotle to the
b b
same extent. This is because the Independence Problem as formulated above violates Aristotle's claim that one knows ‘the that’ before one knows ‘the why?’ (89 29, 93
a
32, 93 17 ff.).
99
I shall examine these arguments in more depth in Chapter 7.
PREPARATION FOR THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 61
If the definition is ‘equidistant from the middle’, why . . . is this what a circle is? One might say it is a definition of
mountain-gold. (92b20–22)
If what is demonstrated is not the whole definition, how does one show that it is the definiendum which has been
defined? Indeed, what makes the type of statement that can be derived by a demonstration at all relevant to the project
of definition?
The problem may be stated as follows:
Formal Problem: If the conclusion of the syllogism is different in form from the definition, how can
demonstration be of use in establishing definitions?
To establish definitions on the basis of demonstrations alone, one would need to show that:
(i) the conclusion of a demonstration is of the appropriate form to be a definition,
and
(ii) the conclusion is the definition of what is to be defined.
If the methods of general deduction or division method had been adequate, Aristotle would have solved the Formal
Problem. But, if his arguments of Β.4–6 are correct, these methods are inadequate (See Chapter 7). If so, how can one
solve the Formal Problem?100
100
This problem is important for the first argument in Β.7, 92a35–b3. This may be summarized as follows: One cannot prove what something is essentially in any of the ways in
which proof is possible. This is not possible by demonstration or by inductive argument. Demonstration has, it appears, been ruled out by the arguments of Β.3–6. Aristotle
takes it to follow from this that one cannot make clear from something which has been agreed that something else follows (92a35–7). But induction is also incapable of
establishing that everything is F since nothing is different. For, by induction, you do not prove what a thing is, but that either it is or is not (92b1). The conclusion of
induction seems to be propositions of the form:All gall-less are long-lived.based on propositions about instances of gall-less animals which are long-lived. But this method
does not yield claims of the form:All gall-less are necessarily long-lived,A fortiori, induction cannot prove that the essence of F is G. Aristotle explains this by saying that
induction does not establish conclusions of the appropriate form for definitions. The conclusions of induction are of the form:All gall-less are long-lived,and not of the
appropriate form:Men are essentially biped animals.Thus, induction is dismissed because it cannot solve the Formal Problem at 92a38–b1. For, if the form of the conclusion
is different from that of the definition, how can such a conclusion be of use in establishing definitions?
62 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
Aristotle's aporetic conclusion at the end of Β.7 is that there is no way of solving the Formal Problem which also
satisfies other basic constraints on definition.101 There is a dilemma. If one resolves this problem (by the method of
general deduction or division), one does so at the cost of failing to meet further general constraints on definition. But if
one meets the latter constraints on definition (e.g. by some other method), one fails to resolve the Formal Problem.
There is, it appears, no way of doing both.
One of Aristotle's basic goals in Β.8–10 is to solve both the Formal and Independence Problems without relying on
the methods he has shown to be inadequate in Β.4–6. His difficulty will become even clearer when we consider his
comments on a further, radically different, type of definition.
Signify
Most of the arguments of Β.7 are directed against the claim that definitions can establish what F is. In the final
argument of Β.7 Aristotle considers another proposal:
If it is the case that the definer proves either what a thing is or what its name signifies, then if a definition has
nothing at all to do with what a thing is, it could just be an account signifying the same as a name. But that's absurd.
For, in the first place, there could be definitions even of non-essences and things that do not exist—for, one can
signify even things that are not. Second, all accounts could be
101
These are discussed in detail in Chapter 7. They concern the conditions under which one comes to know that a given property is essential or explanatorily basic. Roughly,
they require that:(1)one should be able to come to know a correct definition of Fand(2)one should be able to grasp an explanatory basic property of F.
PREPARATION FOR THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 63
definitions; for, one could posit a name for any account whatsoever, so we would speak definitions and the Iliad
would be a definition. Also, no demonstration could demonstrate that this name signifies this; nor then do
definitions make this clear in addition. (92b26–34)
The proposal under discussion is that ‘a definition would signify the same thing as a name’. This view has several
merits in the context of Β.7. It seems to solve the Formal Problem. If definitions are of the form:
‘Thunder’ signies the same as ‘noise in the clouds’one would immediately grasp that the definiens was related to the
definiendum. Further, this proposal neatly sidesteps the Independence Problem. If definitions are of this form, one can
grasp them without knowing the kind exists. Even if one could not grasp what F is without knowing that F exists, one
could grasp an account of what ‘F’ means without knowing that F exists. So, this proposal avoids the problems
Aristotle noted earlier in discussing the proposal that a definition of F is an account of what F is.
However, as was to be expected, Aristotle's discussion of this new proposal consists (in part) in his arguing that if one
avoids the Formal and Independence Problems in this way, one has to surrender other basic conditions for definition:
(a) Some of the accounts derived in this way will not be proper unities, but will be like the Iliad (92b28–32).
(b) Some of the accounts derived in this way will not be of essences, since they will not be of existents.
For, accounts of this type are not relevant to the essence of the object defined (92b26–8). Further, they break the
connection between definition and demonstration; for, no demonstration can prove that:
The aporiai of Β.7 show, in effect, that there can be no one such form of definition. No one type of definition can both
link the phenomenon to the definiens (in the ways required to resolve the Independence and Formal Problems) and at
the same time satisfy Aristotle's basic requirements on definition. Accounts of what names signify can discharge the
first task but not the second. Accounts of the essence of the thing meet the second requirement but cannot resolve the
Formal and Independence Problems. The aporiai of Β.7 can only be broken if, in place of one definition, one devises a
variety of different but interconnected types of definition, severally performing the distinct tasks set for definition in
Β.7.
However, elsewhere he holds that, in the case of what is capable of being demonstrated, to achieve knowledge is to be
in possession of a demonstration. Thus, he writes in 90b9–10:
A belongs to C
but not (as yet) know that:
A belongs to C.
In such cases, we can know that ‘A belongs to C’ is true, but not (as yet) possess a demonstration. We may even know
that there is a demonstration that ‘A belongs to C’ is true, but not yet know what the demonstration is.
66 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
A is C
are different in the two cases. The first yields a grasp of truth, the second of demonstrative truth. It can be the same
proposition known and the same sense of knowledge in the two cases.102
It is instructive to note that there are at least two ways in which one can fall short of knowing by demonstration that ‘A
is C’, where this is demonstrable.
(a) One grasps a further middle term D, from which one can demonstrate that ‘A is C’, but has not yet
constructed a demonstration.
(b) One grasps some middle term B, and grasps that there is a demonstration that ‘A is C’, but has not as yet
grasped the relevant middle term (viz. D) from which such a demonstration can be constructed.
In both cases one grasps only accidentally that ‘C belongs to A is demonstrably true’. But in both one would know
non-accidentally that ‘A is C’. For, although one would know that ‘A is C’ is true, one would not know that it is
demonstrable. To grasp the latter one would need to grasp that ‘A is C’ is the conclusion of a demonstrative syllogism.
In this way, one can know that ‘A is C’ is true, but not yet know that ‘A is C’ is demonstrably
102
It is not absolutely essential that the objects of knowledge be the same. In the first, the proposition might be:A belongs to C.In the second, it might be:A belongs of necessity
to C.Aristotle does not always pay sufficient attention to the precise logical form of his claims in these passages to allow us to distinguish clearly between the two alternatives
canvassed here. For an opposing view, see Myles Burnyeat's paper ‘Aristotle on Understanding Knowledge’, in E. Berti (ed.), Aristotle on Science (Padua, 1981), 97–139.
PREPARATION FOR THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 67
true. One comes to know the latter at the third stage, after one has found a demonstration of the required form.
In this way, the three-stage view, with its clear separation between knowing that ‘A is C’ (at Stage 2) and knowing that
‘A is C’ is demonstrably true (at Stage 3), provides an unproblematic and conservative resolution of a traditional
exegetical puzzle. That it does so is further evidence in favour of attributing it to Aristotle.
Thunder exists.103
One will also know that one has the basis for a full definition of thunder, given that ‘thunder’ and ‘noise in the clouds’
have the same significance. And when one grasps that thunder is the noise in the clouds caused by fire being quenched,
the connection with the thing defined is made legitimate by (a) the efficient causal connection between noise and
extinction, and (b) the fact that ‘thunder’ signifies noise in the clouds. Thus, the account of what the name signifies
links the definiendum (thunder) with the conclusion of the relevant syllogism.104
In this account, one cannot prove that:
103
But there is still a problem. For, since there might be other types of noise in the clouds apart from thunder, one has not yet established that thunder exists (rather than some
other form of noise in the clouds). I shall return to this issue in Ch. 4 Sect 4.4.
104
If this is the role of accounts of what terms signify, they need have no greater depth than is present in the conclusion of the demonstrative syllogism. Since the conclusion
itself does not refer to the essence of the kind (as that reference is supplied by the middle term), there is no need for the account of what the term signifies to do this either.
This remark provides some support for the view (sketched in the previous Chapter, Section 2.11) that accounts of what names signify need not refer to an essence (as yet to
be discovered) of the kind in question.
68 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
Thunder exists
in the favoured apodeictic style without knowing the account of what ‘thunder’ signifies. There can be no knowledge of
Stage 2 truths without already passing Stage 1. But it is clearly possible to arrive at Stage 1 without arriving at Stage 2,
as is clear in Β.7 in the cases of ‘goatstag’ and ‘triangle’.105 Indeed, this possibility is needed to make sense of the
possibility of going on to establish that thunder exists. Thus, given Aristotle's earlier separation between Stages 2 and 3,
he is committed by this strategy to the three-stage view (as set out in the previous Chapter).
The other aspect of the Formal Problem is easily solved. It challenged one to say how conclusions of the form:
105
This is clear in Α.10, 76a 35 where Aristotle separates knowing the significance of ‘triangle’ and knowing of its existence.
PREPARATION FOR THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 69
can meet conditions on definition less demanding than those which are relevant at subsequent stages of enquiry. While
accounts of what terms signify supply answers to the:
What is it?
question (in the case of names and their significance), they need not satisfy the more stringent requirements demanded
of definitions of kinds.106 This is precisely as the liberal interpretation would predict.
These considerations also tell against the more restrictive interpretations set out in the previous chapter.107 The latter
argue that in Β.7 Aristotle rules out the possibility of accounts of what names signify being definitions. It is not just that
these interpretations take one element in an aporetic discussion as Aristotle's settled view. Worse still, their view
appears to misread the overall structure of the aporiai in Β.7. For, if I am correct, these arise because no one type of
definition can be both essence-invoking and an account of what the relevant name signifies. If so, one cannot take any
part of Β.7 to show that all definitions must meet Aristotle's own most stringent conditions on definition. Indeed, his
solution to these aporiai depends on his separating different types of definition, none of which meet all the demands set
out in Β.7. Thus, closer analysis of this chapter as a whole (so far from being incompatible with the liberal
interpretation) shows precisely why Aristotle developed the three-stage account and liberalized his conditions on
definition. He needed to do both to overcome the aporiai discussed in Β.3–7.108
106
It would, of course, have been possible to restrict Stage 1definitional accounts to those correlated with terms which signify kinds with a real essence, and, thus, to rule out
definitional accounts of what ‘goatstag’ signifies. But this move seems unattractive in the context of Β.7, where ‘goatstag’ and ‘triangle’ are treated in similar fashion. Further,
as I have argued, it is unmotivated, since Aristotle attempts to devise Stage 1 definitions which do not themselves meet his own most stringent constraints on being a
definition.
107
See Ch. 2 Sect. 2.3.
108
For the opposing view, see the discussions by Ross, Aristotle's Analytics, 635 f.; Bolton, ‘Essentialism’, 514 ff.; Sorabji, Necessity, Cause and Blame, 198; and DeMoss and
Devereux, ‘Essence’, 133–56.
70 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
Examples of A(1) are: Search for whether the moon is eclipsed or not, or whether the earth moves or not (89b26–30).
When we discover that the moon is eclipsed, we seek the answer to the ‘Why?’ question. B(1) is initially exemplified by
search as to whether or not there is a centaur or a god: When we know that god exists, we seek what it is (89b34).
Questions in B(1) focus on whether something is (without qualification), not on whether it has some particular feature.
In the first chapter, the examples of B(1) are substances (god, man, centaur). In the second chapter, some are
substances (sun, moon, earth), but some are attributes (night (90a5)). The basic demarcation between A(1) and B(1)
depends on the form of the question. In A(1) it is: Does S (a substance) possess P (a property)? For B(1) the form of
the question is: Does S exist? (or, Does S exist as a substance?).
Let us focus initially on the questions A(1) and B(1). The general form of these questions appear to be to discover
whether:
(i) there is or is not a centaur or a god, (89b32–3)
(ii) the moon is or is not, (90a5, 90a12)
(iii) the triangle sun/moon/earth is or is not, (90a12–13)
(iv) the moon is eclipsed, (90a3)
(v) there is an eclipse or not. (90a26)
Aristotle's argument strongly suggests that knowledge of existence is not required for an understanding of the terms
involved. For, the cases are ones in which (as in Β.8, 93a30 ff.109) one knows enough about what (e.g.) eclipses are to
discover if they exist, but does not yet know that they exist. One does not know at the outset that god exists. Indeed,
his ontological status might turn out to be no better than that of the centaur or goatstag!
The remaining two stages of the three-stage enquiry are also distinguished in Β.2. At Stage 2, one knows that (e.g.)
triangles exist or that the moon is eclipsed. In this, one knows that there is some appropriate middle term which
explains the fact or the existence of the triangle. To search for this is to enquire whether there is a relevant middle term
or not (90a6 f., 9–11).
Stage 3 involves the discovery of what the middle term is. For, this will answer Α.2 and Β.2. In both these stages (2 and
3), the search is directed to discovery related to the middle term. At Stage 2, the issue is whether there is one. At Stage
3, the issue is what it is. These stages are logically separable even if they happen simultaneously (90a26 ff.).
At the end of Β.2 Aristotle needs to show how enquiries of the type
109
See Ch. 2 Sect. 2.5.
PREPARATION FOR THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 71
envisaged fit into his proof theory, and how they are related to the search for definition (90a35 ff.). The three-stage
view, as set out in Β.8–10, constitutes his attempt to meet these two goals. At Stage 1, one begins with a definitional
account of what the term signifies. In the case of man (89b35), one might start with ‘man’ signifies the same as ‘a certain
type of two-footed animal’ (93a24).
Thus, one knows that man is an animal, if there is such an animal, with two-feet . . . The search for a middle term is the
search for something which explains why being two-footed belongs to animal in this case.110 Once we know that there is
some relevant middle term, we know that the phenomenon exists.111 The role of accounts of what names signify is to
hold up targets for existence proofs of this type.
But why require at Stage 2 that one knows that there is a middle term, even if the identity of the middle term can
remain veiled? Perhaps, at Stage 2, in discovering that the kind exists one discovers that it has some internal structure
even if one does not know what its basis is. Perhaps it is here that knowledge of existence and of some causal structure
is introduced, and not at Stage 1, as is suggested in the picture advanced by my modern essentialist (outlined in
Chapter 1). I shall leave the task of a more precise interpretation of what is involved at Stage 2 to Chapter 6.
If this account is correct, Aristotle can consistently hold that existence is predicated of a kind, and that existence is
established by grasping that there is a middle term. For the way to establish that the kind exists is to grasp an
articulated account of what the term signifies which allows one to ask the ‘Why?’ question, and to discover that there is
an answer to it—even if one does not yet know what it is. Indeed, it is just this which makes it appropriate for Aristotle
to introduce his proof theory to establish existence. But if he is to do this, he needs accounts of what names signify at
Stage 1 which do not involve knowledge of existence, but which provide the basis for a suitably articulated question
which existence proofs can answer. This is why Stage 1 definitional accounts of ‘man’ and ‘triangle’ are stated in ways
which do not require one to know of the existence of the phenomenon. For, they are introduced in order to allow us to
establish existence. But, if this is so, it is difficult to see why similar accounts of ‘centaur’, ‘goatstag’, or ‘god’ should not
be treated as definitions. For, they are similar in form, play the same role in investigation, and encapsulate the same
type of knowledge state.
110
The detailed nature of this enquiry is examined in Chapter 11.
111
For a contrasting view of Β.2, see A. Gomez-Lobo, ‘On the So-called Question of Existence in Aristotle, An. Post. 2.1–2’ RM 34 (1980), 71–89. Gomez-Lobo rightly
emphasizes the difficulty of finding a middle term linking a term (such as ‘man’) and ‘exist’, but concludes from this that the question is not the one articulated in Β.8 (on
which I have concentrated), but rather a different one such as: ‘Is this a man?’(p. 87).
72 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
There are two ways in which it is necessary to know (gignoskein) things in advance. In some cases, it is necessary to
assume in advance (prohypolambanein) that they exist, of some it is necessary to understand (sunienai) in advance what
the thing said is, and of others both: e.g. the fact that everything is affirmed or denied truly—one must assume that
this is so; of the triangle, one must assume that it signifies this, and of the unit both what it signifies and that it is.
For, each of these is not equally clear to us. (71a11–17)
In this passage Aristotle distinguishes two kinds of claim which can be assumed or understood prior to proof:
(i) what given terms signify
(ii) that certain things exist or are so
In some cases, such as that of the unit, one assumes in advance both what the relevant term signifies and that the unit
exists. In others, one needs to assume just what the term signifies. The difference between these two cases is that, while
the unit is a starting point for proof, the triangle can be established to exist by proof. In the latter case, knowledge of
existence is not assumed when one grasps the significance of the name (see also Α.10, 76a32–6, 76b6–9, 15 f.). And this
is as the three-stage view understands Stage 1. One grasps the significance of the terms ‘triangle’, ‘odd’, or ‘cube’
independently of and prior to grasping a proof of the existence of the features they signify.112
112
It was argued in Chapter 2, Section 2.8 that accounts of what names signify of the form:‘Thunder’ signifies a type of noise in the clouds.are never used in proof (see Β.7,
92b33). This view appears confirmed by Aristotle's remark in Post. An.Α.10, 76b35 ff.:Definitions (horoi) are not hypotheses (for nothing is said to be or not to be), but
hypotheses are used as premisses, while definitions one needs only to understand.The closest reference for ‘definitions’ in this context appears to be the accounts of what
terms signify discussed previously in Α.10 at 76a34 f., 76b7–12, 15, 17–21. It should be noted that they are introduced with the crucial ‘ti. . .’ question in 76a34 f., in a context
which clearly marks this out as a question about terms and not things. (See, for a similar use of the ‘ti. . .’ question, Post. An.Α.1, 71a14, cited in Ch. 2 Sect. 2.3.)It is
sometimes suggested by those who hold that all definitions are of things and are, thus, all related to proof that Aristotle is discussing terms and not definitions in this passage,
and that ‘horoi’ should be translated accordingly. However, a remark about terms would be a surprising addition at this stage in the argument, without any preparation in Α.10.
It seems far preferable to construe this remark as referring (demonstratively) to the definitions used in Β.10. For, these (if I am correct) do not assert existence and cannot be
used as premisses.
PREPARATION FOR THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 73
But what of the unit? Here, Aristotle says that one needs to know in advance both what the term signifies and that it is.
Are these separate stages? Or, in the case of first principles, does grasp of what the term signifies involve knowledge of
the existence of the unit? Is this a counter example to the separation between Stages 1 and 2 in the three-stage view?113
There is no reason to understand accounts of what (e.g.) the ‘unit’ signifies in this way. If accounts of what a name
signifies are as above, these will be of the form:
A thesis which asserts one or other of the parts of the contradiction—I mean, that something is or that something is
not, is a hypothesis; a thesis which does not do this is a definition. For, a definition is a thesis: the mathematician posits
the unit to
113 a b
For parallel passages, see also 76 31–6 and 93 25 f. In the latter, Aristotle distinguishes the mathematician's ‘hypothesis’ about what the monad is from the hypothesis that
it exists.
114
Differing views of the form of hypotheses are helpfully discussed by Goldin in Explaining the Eclipse: Aristotle's Posterior Analytics 2.1–10 (Michigan, 1996). I assume that, for
Aristotle, ‘to exist’ is always ‘to exist as something’. The something may be specified in categorial terms (e.g. to exist as a substance, see Meta. Δ.7, 1017a 22–30,Ζ.1, 1028a
b
10–13) or in a more specific fashion (e.g. to exist as a member of a genus of substance, with some specific differentiae, see Meta. H.2, 1042 15 ff.). At this point, I am
indebted to discussion with Paolo Crivelli.
115
For, both are starting points for demonstrations and as such propositions (72a 14–15). Further, if hypotheses are species of theses, the latter must all be propositions.
74 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
be what is quantitatively indivisible; but this is not a hypothesis, because what a unit is and that it is are not the same.
(72a18–24)116
Why do definitional theses not ‘assert one or other part of a contradiction’ and why are they separable from the
hypothesis that the unit is (or exists as) something? An example of such a definition is:
116
In this translation, I take the phrase ‘einai ti ’ to be equivalent to ‘something exists’ rather than ‘exists as something’. However, my argument for the separation of hypotheses,
theses, and accounts of what the term signifies does not rest on this. Indeed, for my purposes, this phrase could be interpreted to mean ‘to be something’ (where ‘something’
referred either to its being a substance or its being a substance of a given kind. (See n. 19.) )
117
This interpretation agrees with B. Landor (‘Definitions and Hypotheses in Posterior Analytics 72a19–25 and 76b35–77a24’, Phronesis 26 (1981), 313) in separating hypotheses as
containing assertions of existence from definitional theses, which do not. However, it is unclear how Landor secures the latter result. He writes:To posit that a unit is what is
indivisible in quantity is to affirm the definiens (‘what is indivisible in quantity’) of the definiendum (unit).If the phrase cited as definiens is used in this context, it is unclear why
the assertion that:The unit is what is indivisible in quantity.does not assert that the unit exists as what is indivisible. If he intends to say:‘The unit’ is ‘what is indivisible in
quantity’.he clearly avoids an assertion of existence, but does so only by taking this thesis to be quite different from any which could be used in demonstration.Landor argues
cogently against equating the definitional theses (and hypotheses) of 72a17 ff. with the horoi (and hypotheses) specified in Α.10, 76b35 ff. This distinction could be maintained
even if one construed the horoi of 76b35 ff. as definitional accounts of what terms such as ‘odd’, ‘even’, ‘irrational’, etc. signify. For, these definitions are not among the pre-
misses of demonstration, since they concern the signification of terms and not objects or kinds. Further, since these definitional accounts concern terms such as ‘odd’ they
are neither universal (‘all’) nor particular (‘some’) claims about members of any kind (77a3–4).
PREPARATION FOR THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 75
In certain scientific contexts one requires hypotheses (such as (i)) which assert one or other side of the contradiction.
One has to move from (iii) to (i) in contexts where one wishes to make scientific assertions about what is the case.
Since neither Stage 1 accounts nor theses make assertions of this type, they can be contrasted with hypotheses.
However, theses will differ from accounts of what the name signifies since the latter concern the signification of terms,
while the former do not. These three types of expression play differing roles in Aristotle's account. Once they are
distinguished, there is no pressure to see accounts of what names signify as encapsulating knowledge of the existence
of the kind. There can be such accounts whether or not the kind in question exists.118
118
In this argument, I have translated ‘lambanein’ as ‘assume’ or ‘posit’. If, however, ‘lambanein’ were taken rather to mean ‘to assume as immediately known without proof being
required’, then a hypothesis would not merely assume the existence of (e.g.) gold, but would assume the existence of gold as immediately known without proof being required.
If so, a thesis might itself assume the existence of gold, but would not treat its existence as immediately known without proof being required. And in this way—contrary to
my suggestion—a thesis might also involve the assumption of existence, although it would not treat the existence of (e.g.) instances of gold as self-evident and not requiring
proof. And, if so, these passages would not show that the existence of instances is not assumed by a definition of the type under discussion. They would show only that their
existence was not treated as self-evident and in need of no further scientific justification. (For this view, see Robert Bolton's paper, ‘Aristotle on the Signification of Names’,
Language and Reality in Greek Philosophy: Proceedings of the Greek Philosophical Society 1984/5 (Athens, 1985), 153–62.)This objection is ingenious, but it seems difficult to accept
that ‘lambanein’ does, in the context of these chapters, mean ‘posit as self-evident without further need of proof ’, rather than (merely) ‘posit the existence of ’ (as mentioned
a b
above). I offer two reasons:(1) This verb is very prominent in Post. An.Α.10, from which two of the relevant passages are drawn: 76 31–6 and 76 35–8. It is used at least
a b
eleven times: 76 33, 34, 76 1, 3, 6, 7, 15, 19, 20, 27, 31. In several of these cases (outside the key passages) it is hard to see how ‘lambanein’ can mean ‘posit as self-evident
b
without further need of proof ’. Thus, in 76 16 ff. Aristotle writes that demonstrative sciences posit/ lambanei which each of the attributes (i.e. attributive terms) signifies.
Thus, Aristotle writes:Nothing, however, prevents some sciences from overlooking some of these: (e.g.) from not positing (hypotheses) that its kind exists, if it is obvious . . .
and from not assuming (lambanei) what the attributes signify, if they are clear.In this passage, it is taken as a reason for not assuming what an attribute signifies that it is self-
evident that it does not exist. But if ‘lambanein’ meant ‘posit as self-evident without further need of proof ’, it would be (at very least) an extremely paradoxical reason for not
assuming as self-evident what an attribute signifies, that its existence is indeed self-evident! The passage reads far more easily if ‘lambanein’ is taken to mean ‘assume the
existence’. For, if the attribute obviously exists, to assume its existence is to understate one's cognitive stage with respect to attribute—and, thus, its self-evidence is indeed
good reason for not merely positing its existence! Thus, if ‘lambanein’ is to have a single sense throughout the passage, it is that of ‘assuming’/‘positing’ and not that of
‘assuming’/‘positing as self-evident without further need of proof ’. And this supports my initial account of the thesis/hypothesis distinction with respect to definition as one
between positing a definition, and asserting that what is defined exists.(2) The evidence for the use of lambanein as ‘posit as self-evident without further need of proof ’ is
a
inconclusive. It is true that in 76 32–4 starting points are posited, and these indeed are often self-evident and cannot be further proved. Equally it is true that one application
a
of hypothesis in 72 19–20 is to self-evident truths which are, no doubt, taken as self-evident, and without further need of proof. But none of this shows that ‘lambanein’ should
mean ‘posit as self-evident and without further need of proof ’: it only shows that some things which are posited are indeed self-evident, and without further need of proof.
Elsewhere (e.g. 76b32–4), the things that are posited (e.g. in the case of teacher) are neither self-evident nor free from the need for further proof.
76 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
These considerations support the attribution to Aristotle of a clear and general distinction between Stages 1 and 2 in
scientific enquiry. This distinction can be preserved even if in grasping the relevant definitional thesis one must know
(e.g.) that the unit exists. For the latter is a definitional account of the phenomenon, and not of the significance of the
term. Thus, even if here there is no separation between Stages 2 and 3 in enquiry, there is a further stage clearly
separated from Stage 1.
3.9 Conclusion
In this Chapter, I have argued (in answer to question (A) in Section 2.3 of the previous Chapter) that the three-stage
view (as developed in Β.8–10) is Aristotle's answer to some of the problems raised in Posterior Analytics Β.7, and that it
builds on his proposals in Posterior Analytics Β.1–2 and Α.1–2 and 10. More generally, it constitutes one part of his
strategy for showing that one can have knowledge of the signification of terms prior to an enquiry into the nature and
existence of the kind in question. This is important in the Analytics, since it allows for the possibility of scientific
investigation and discovery in both these areas. In this way, Aristotle can avoid Meno's paradox (Α.1, 71a29 ff.), which
seems to show that genuine discovery is impossible. That paradox requires that it be a condition for knowing the
signification of the relevant term that one knows of the existence or nature of the kind signified. And this is precisely
the premiss which the three-stage view rejects.119
119
There are several forms of Meno's paradox. In one, one cannot discover the nature of a kind because grasp of that is already involved in understanding the relevant name. In
another, one could not discover the existence of a kind, since knowledge of that is already involved in understanding the name. Both have the same form; one discovers
either nothing or only what one already knew. Aristotle wishes to allow that one can come to know of the existence as well as the nature of the kind. It is difficult to see how
the modern essentialist can account for one's coming to know of the kind's existence. For, that is already presupposed in his understanding the term.
PREPARATION FOR THE THREE-STAGE VIEW 77
This Chapter has given some further grounds in favour of taking all Stage 1 accounts as a type of definition (whether
or not they are of names for existents (see Section 3.6)). For, they all play one of the roles required of definition: they
link the term to be defined with an account which is the object of enquiry. Further, there is no evidence in Β.7 which
suggests that Aristotle separated definitional from other accounts of what names signify on the grounds that only the
former signify existents (Sections 3.2–3.4). His strategy appears rather to be to liberalize and diversify his account of
definition so as to allow (inter alia) that all accounts of what names signify can be a type of definition. These
considerations amount to further evidence in favour of an affirmative answer to question (D), raised in Section 2.3 of
the last Chapter.
In what follows, the three-stage view is central. For, commitment to this requires Aristotle to think of all Stage 1
accounts as capable of being understood without knowledge of the existence of the kind signified. And this claim (now
apparently secure) exercises a major influence on his discussion of signification and understanding.120
120
In the overall context of this study, it is more important to establish that Aristotle held the three-stage view than that he regarded all Stage 1 accounts as definitional.
4 The Signication of Names
4.1 Introduction
Aristotle's three-stage view of scientific enquiry, outlined in the last two Chapters, contains several claims relevant to
his account of signification:
C(1) Accounts of what terms signify play a role in guiding enquiry at Stages 2 and 3 (Β.8, 93a29–36, Β.10, 93b29–35).
Such accounts can be understood without knowledge of the existence of the kind signified. There can be
accounts of what terms signify whether or not there is an existing kind signified by the term.
According to C(1), there can be (definitional) accounts of what ‘goatstag’ signifies (Β.7, 92b6 f., cf. Β.10, 93b35–7),
which are ‘stitched together’ by us.121 There will also be definitional accounts of what the terms ‘thunder’ or ‘triangle’
signify, distinct from definitional accounts of the kinds themselves.
C(2) What is signified by a term at Stage 1 is (in some cases) the very same thing that is discovered to exist at Stage 2
(see 93b32: ‘when we discover that what is signified exists’).
C(1), I have argued, is a central feature of Aristotle's strategy in the Analytics. C(2) is a claim to which he regularly
returns both there and elsewhere.122
In addition to C(1) and C(2), there are two further relevant claims which need to be investigated.
C(3) (At least some) accounts of what names signify the same as names.
In Β.7, 92b26–8 Aristotle writes that if definition were to establish what the name signifies and not to grasp the essence
of the kind, ‘it would be an
121
See Ch. 3 Sect. 3.8.
122 b a
See, e.g. his use of ‘signify’ to capture the relation between (e.g.) names and substances, such as man and horse, in Cat. 1 25–7. In Post. An. Α.22, 83 24f. Aristotle speaks
of terms which signify substances as signifying either that thing or the type of thing it is. In all these cases, ‘signification’ links linguistic terms and substances in the world.
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 79
account signifying the same as a name’. It remains unclear, however, whether all such accounts signify the same as the
relevant names, or only some of them.
C(4) There can be several different accounts of what one name signifies. (Thus, ‘pride’ might be taken as equivalent to
‘not tolerating insult’ or to ‘indifference to misfortune’ (97b21 ff.) if pride were just one condition).
For, accounts of this type pick out non-accidental features of a kind (Β.8, 93a20–4), and there can be several distinct
non-accidental features of one kind.
Our first, and most immediate, problem is that C(1)–C(4) appear (at least at first sight) to be inconsistent. For,
according to C(1), a definitional account of what a name signifies can be understood without knowing of the existence
of the kind or object signified. But, if C(2) is correct, names on occasion signify what exists. How is this possible?
Surely, a correct account of what these names signify should involve reference to the existence of the object or kind they
signify? But if the enquirer understands this account in grasping the name, he will (contrary to C(1)) know of the
existence of the kind signified. Further, if C(3) is correct, names and the relevant accounts will signify the same thing.
But, given C(2), this is only possible if the account signifies (in some cases) a kind in the world. Thus, if the thinker
understands this account, he will surely know which kind is signified. But, if so, he will know (contrary to C(1)) that the
kind in question exists.
C(3) gives rise to a second problem. If C(3) applies to this case, ‘the account of what “pride” signifies’ will signify the
same as ‘pride’. But, according to C(4), there can be several different accounts of what ‘pride’ signifies, each picking out
a different non-accidental feature of the phenomenon. How can these claims be consistent? Must ‘pride’ be
ambiguous? Or do some accounts of what names signify fail to signify the same as the name?
Aristotle does not resolve these issues in the Analytics. While he makes a number of claims about names, their
signification, and accounts of what names signify, he does not develop a full or unified account of these issues.123
Indeed, the precise status of some of C(1)–C(4) is left obscure in that work. Is Aristotle really committed to C(3) and
C(4)? Or did he introduce them
123
This view of Post. An. Β.8–10 represents a mid-position between two opposed interpretations. Robert Bolton (‘Essentialism’) took these chapters to present Aristotle's
explicit account of the signification of kind terms. By contrast, John Ackrill did not accept that any general account of signification was even assumed in these texts
(‘Aristotle's Theory of Definition: Some Questions on Post. An. 2.8–10.’ in Berti (ed.), Aristotle on Science. The mid-position is to argue that an account of signification is
presupposed but not made explicit in these chapters.
80 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
only for specific dialectical purposes? Are they meant to apply to all accounts or only to some?124
Did he do better elsewhere? Did Aristotle develop an account of signification which sustains (at least some of)
C(1)–C(4)? Did he provide answers to any of the following questions, central for an account of signification:
(A) Under what conditions does a name signify a particular kind or object?
(B) Under what conditions do two names have the same significance?
(C) Under what conditions do a name and an account have the same significance?
I shall argue in the next three Chapters that he did provide answers to these three questions which validate C(1)–C(4).
In the present Chapter, I shall trace the outline of his approach, which rests on his discussion of thought in De Anima.
This account (I shall suggest in Sections 4.2–4.4) underwrites claims C(2) and C(4). It is also consistent with C(1) and a
version of C(3) (see Section 4.5). In Section 4.6 I shall argue that his account of the signification of the relevant names
and expressions is an account of their meaning. In the next Chapter, I shall seek to secure the interpretation of
Aristotle's account of thought which is presupposed in the present Chapter. Finally, in Chapter 6, I shall complete and
assess the theory that has emerged.
Spoken sounds are symbols of affections in the soul, and written marks are symbols of spoken sounds. And just as
written marks are not the same for all, neither are spoken sounds. But what these are in the first place signs
of—affections in the soul—are the same for all; and what these affections are likenesses of—things in the
world—are clearly the same for all. These matters have
124 b
More precisely, C(3) is introduced in the context of a reductio (92 26–7), although it seems that it is not the premiss that Aristotle rejects. The examples mentioned in C(4)
are not explicitly said to be accounts of what the term signifies. Nothing (in what follows) hangs on taking the examples mentioned in Β.13, 97b 15 ff. as cases of accounts of
what names signify.
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 81
been discussed in the work De Anima, and do not belong to the present subject. (16a3–9)
Written marks and spoken sounds are signs—in the first instance—of ‘affections of the soul’, which appear to be
thoughts, in this context (16a10, 14).125 Names are signs for thoughts which are not yet combined with other thoughts
that are signs for verbs so as to make affirmations, capable of truth and falsity.
Let us begin with names, successfully applied to objects or kinds:‘Cicero’ or ‘man’.126 The written mark ‘A’ is a sign—in
the first instance—of a given thought, the thought of Cicero or of man. The significance of ‘A’ is fixed by the thought with
which it is conventionally correlated. The identity of a thought is determined by the answer to the question:‘What is this
thought about?’(or, in Aristotle's terms, by the form received in that thought (see below)). Thus, the significance of ‘A’
is fixed by the answer to the question: ‘What is the relevant thought about?’
What, in Aristotle's view, determines what the thought is about? In this passage, Aristotle says only that thoughts (all or
some) are likenesses of things in the world (homoiōmata), a topic which he notes he has discussed elsewhere (in fact, in
De Anima). He is content to point his reader to the place to look for a more detailed account of likeness (16a8–9).
In Aristotle's discussion of perception and thought in De Anima the notion of likeness plays a major role. In cases of
successful thinking and perceiving, entities in the world liken the relevant faculty to themselves. Likening is a causal
process in which the starting point is
125 a
On this account, written and spoken expressions are conventional signs of states of the soul: 16 10, 19. They are conventional signs of such states because they are both
signs (sēmeia ) and symbols (sumbola ). There may be signs which are not symbols and hence non-conventional (e.g. natural signs), and symbols which are not signs because
not semantically significant. Aristotle's mixture of conventional (symbolic) and non-conventional (likening) relations is his attempt to disentangle two separate strands
d c
confused by Plato in the Cratylus (e.g. 430 5 ff., cf. 386 ff.). For a contrasting view, see N. Kretzmann's ‘Aristotle on Spoken Sounds and Significance by Convention’ in J.
Corcoran (ed.), Ancient Logic and Modern Interpretations (Dordrecht, 1974). Parts of Kretzmann's view are convincingly criticized by Pantazis Tselemanis in ‘Theory of
Meaning and Signification in Aristotle’ in Language and Reality in Greek Philosophy (Athens, 1985), 194–9. I shall consider the remainder of his view in discussing the notion
of likeness below. Aristotle says practically nothing in De Int. about the conventional aspect of significance, and I shall follow his example.
126
Aristotle's category of names includes common nouns and proper names (e.g. ‘man’, ‘horse’, ‘Socrates’). Simple names have no relevant internal semantic structure (De Int.
16a 20–6 (see Sect. 4.3) ). It is very important to note that Aristotle does not say that all affections of the soul are likenesses of things in the world. He confines himself to
saying that ‘what affections are likenesses of are things in the world’ (16a 7 f.), which leaves open the possibility that some affections (e.g. those concerning goatstags) are not
likenesses of anything (see Sect. 4.3). In particular, he does not say that all names are related to affections which are likenesses of things in the world.
82 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
(e.g.) a particular external object.127 This process (in successful cases) results in the patient being made like the agent in
certain relevant respects.128 The efficient cause explains the relevant general features of the thought or perception: what
it is about, its object. When this occurs, the form is transferred from the agent to the patient. Likening of this type
occurs in successful cases, when the faculties involved are functioning as they should. In such cases, the objects liken
the relevant faculties to themselves in the form-transferring way. This type of process is what makes the perception or
thought the one it is.129 When this occurs, the relevant faculty receives the form of the external object.130 Likening,
therefore, is an asymmetric causal process in which the relevant object or kind (with its form) is (1) the efficient cause
of the relevant perception or thought, and (2) explains the general features of the perception or thought (what it is
about). Further, (3) likening of the appropriate kind occurs when the relevant faculties are functioning as they should.
((1)–(3) constitute the basic account of likening.131)
This account provides one central feature of Aristotle's account of names and their signification. According to De
Interpretatione 16a3 ff., the significance of a simple linguistic expression ‘A’ is fixed in the first instance by what the thought
with which it is conventionally correlated is about. Let us call this thought Θ1. If we apply the De Anima model in those
cases where the thoughts are likenesses to things in the world (in this way), Θ1 is about the object which causes that
thought in the likening (form-transferring) mode. In such cases the significance of ‘a’ will be fixed, in the
127 a b a a
For perception, see (e.g.) De An. B.5, 418 3–6. For thought (De An. 417 16–19, Γ.4, 429 13–18, 430 3–4), Aristotle applies his ‘likening model’ in both cases. This is a
a
specific causal relation in which the cause ‘likens the effect unto itself’ (cf. GC A.7 324 9–11) so that the effect is ‘made like’ the cause. In this way, the wax which receives
the imprint of the ring is likened to the ring which produces it. This means more than that it resembles the ring. For, that would be true also of marks which happened to
look like the ring, but were not produced by it in this way. I shall develop this interpretation in more detail in the next Chapter.
128
Aristotle's efficient or ‘making’ causes (e.g. the art of house-building) make the effect be a certain way (e.g. be organized in given ways), and do not merely bring the effect
a
into existence. They make objects have given properties (‘A causes B to be G’), where the latter are capable of having those properties (cf. Meta. Θ.7, 1049 5–8).
129 a
I am further assuming that for Aristotle the efficient cause is constitutive of the processes it causes (cf. Meta. Ζ.17, 1041 29–32). The result could not be thunder/a
a b
thinking of thunder unless it was caused by fire being quenched/thunder (cf. Post. An. B.10, 94 5–6, B.893 10–19). (For further discussion, see Ch. 8.)
130
This formulation rests on the assumption that there are objects with their own forms. It is not intended as a (reductive) analysis of what it is for the form to be transferred.
131
This account of ‘likening’ presupposes that objects and kinds are as they are, with their own forms, independently of our thinking about them as we do. There is, thus, a
substantial commitment to a form of realism at the basis of Aristotle's account. We are seen as living in a world in which divisions between objects and between kinds are not
the result of our choosing to classify undifferentiated matter one way rather than another. Such divisions flow from distinctions, whose existence does not rest on our
preferred mode of classification. The basis for this type of realism is discussed in Part II.
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 83
second instance, by the objects or kinds in the world which cause Θ1 in the form-transferring way. The latter step is
fundamental to determining the significance of ‘a’, since it fixes what Θ1 is about, and this in turn determines the
significance of ‘a’.
On this interpretation, names of this type for objects or kinds (e.g.) K1 will signify as follows:
‘a’ signifies the kind K1 if and only if K1 produces the thought Θ1 (with which ‘a’ is conventionally correlated) by the
likening route.
When this occurs the thinking faculty will be likened to K1 in the form-transferring way. On this account, there are two
semantically relevant relations:
‘a’ signifies IMMEDIATELY Θ1 if and only if Θ1 is the thought with which ‘a’ is conventionally correlated.
What is signified by ‘a’ is what is cited in answer to the question: ‘What is Θ1 about?’ This relation will be common to
all cases and is the prime object of signification. In certain cases where the content of the thought is produced by the
form-transferring route by a kind in the world:
132 a b
Perhaps, ‘prōton ’ might mean (i) ‘in the canonical way’ (as understood with ‘kuriōs ’: e.g. NE Θ.4, 1157 30; De An. Α.10, 403 29), and be contrasted with some less
canonical ways, perhaps not even including any relation to things in the world; or it might mean (ii) ‘with nothing in between’ (e.g. Post. An. 81b 31–5), and not be contrasted
with any other case involving words and things. Both these possible uses of ‘prōton ’ are indicated in Bonitz, Index Aristotelicus ad loc.
84 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
signification relation which reaches from our words beyond our thoughts to the world.133
This account provides a limited answer to question (A):
Under what conditions does a name (of the type discussed in De Interpretatione 1) signify a kind?
In these cases, what is signified by the name is what is discovered to exist at Stage 2 in the enquiry. This is because what
is signifiedMED by the term is a kind in the world, and this fixes the significationIMM of the term. In such cases, it is not
possible to specify what is signified by a term without mentioning the kind in the world to which it is related in the
relevant efficient causal way.134
This model vindicates C(2) in the previous section. What is signified by the term ‘man’ is a kind in the world. But the
model does not (as yet) make clear the answer to either question (B) or (C) above (even in the case of the names so far
discussed). One might, of course, conjecture (on the basis of the discussion so far) that two names (of this type) will
have the same significance if and only if they are both correlated with thoughts brought about by the same objects. But,
while this conjecture is possible, it is certainly not guaranteed by anything said so far.
Aristotle's discussion elsewhere, however, appears to support this conjecture. Thus, he writes:
Things are called synonyms when they share a name and the account of what the thing is which corresponds to the
name is the same, like animal in man and cow. Each of these is called by the same name ‘animal’, and the account of
what the object is is the same. (Cat. 1a6–10)
Objects and properties may be ‘synonyms’ on this account, but so can two
133
See also Post. An. A.1, 71a 15. Some might object that these passages might be translated without taking the ‘semantic’ relation to involve objects. Thus, the passages might
mean only that what is signified by the term (e.g. a concept in the mind) is found to be (e.g.) exemplified in the world, in which case, there need be no word-world semantic
connection. However, there is good evidence that Aristotle did conceive of the relevant semantic relations as reaching to the world. For, this explains (i) the problems he has
with names for non-existents, which on occasion seem to signify nothing (De Int. 18a 25); (ii) why he thought of particles and propositions as ‘non-significant’ (Poetics 1456b
38 ff.); (iii) why ‘is’, ‘every’, and ‘and’ have no significance by themselves (De Int. 16b 24, 20a 13); (iv) his claim that a name signifies one thing (Meta. Γ.4, 1006b 12 f.), and
that the name ‘sun’ signifies a substance (Meta. Ζ. 15, 1040a 32); (v) his claim that names are ‘symbols’ for things in the world (Soph. El. 1, 165a 6 ff.).
134
Such cases are described in some modern writings as ‘world-involving’ or ‘nonindividualist’. See, for examples, Tyler Burge's papers ‘Individualism and the Mental’ Midwest
Studies 4 (1979), 73–121, and ‘Cartesian Error and Perception’ in P. Pettit and J. McDowell (eds.), Subject, Thought and Context (Oxford, 1986), 117–36. See also Gareth
Evans's Varieties of Reference (Oxford, 1982), chs. 6–8 and John McDowell's ‘Singular Thought and the Extent of Inner Space’in Subject, Thought and Context, 137–68.
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 85
token names when (and only when) they have the same morphology and the accounts which correspond to the
relevant names are the same.135 Names are synonyms only if they have the same significance (otherwise they are
homonyms). If so, in this case, the two token names will have the same significance because they are both correlated
with one kind. In that case, the accounts corresponding to them will be the same. For, it is this feature which explains
their having the same significance, not their having the same morphology (since homonyms also have that feature).
Aristotle makes the further move of claiming that two distinct names, like ‘cloak’ and ‘garment’ (with distinct
morphology), will have the same significance provided that they are correlated with the same kind (Soph. El. 6,
168a27–32).136 Here, too, the account which corresponds to the two names is the same. Thus, it appears that two names
such as ‘A’ and ‘B’ will have the same significance provided that they signify the same object, and this will be so only if
the answer to the question ‘What is a?’ is the same as the answer to the question ‘What is b?’137
135
‘Homonymy’ and ‘synonymy’ are often taken to apply in this passage only to objects and not to names, on the grounds that only objects can have names in common while
names cannot (at least without regress!). But names can also be homonyms or synonyms in the following way: they are homonyms if they share only the name (i.e. the same
morphological unit), but differ with regard to the account of the thing which corresponds to the name; they are synonyms if they share both the same morphological unit
and account. A term can also be a paronym if its morphology is derived from another with a distinct morphological ending. On this interpretation, both objects and names
can be homonyms and synonyms, depending on whether they share, with regard to their name, only a morphological unit or something more. Thus, Aristotle will talk in Cat.
a
1 indifferently of names and objects and only distinguish between them in Cat. 2 (‘of things said’ . . . ‘of things that are’ 1 20). Elsewhere, Aristotle appears to speak of
a b a b
objects and of names as synonyms and homonyms (objects: e.g. Top. Δ.3, 123 28, Meta. Ζ.10, 1035 1 ff.; names: e.g. Topics Α.15, 106 21, b4, Θ.13, 162 38, Soph. El.
a a
5, 167 24, NE Έ.1, 1129 30). Bonitz notes both uses of these terms (Index Aristotelicus ad loc.). This can be explained (without use/mention confusion) if the
interpretation proposed of Cat. 1 is accepted; in it, both objects and names can be synonyms and homonyms. However, even if only objects can be called ‘synonyms’, it is
easy to derive an account of a synonym's name. Objects are synonyms if they share the same morphologically structured name and account. Names are synonyms if they
share the same morphological structure and are correlated with the same accounts.
136 b a a b
Indeed, on occasion Aristotle appears to refer to such cases as ‘sunonuma ’ (see Top. Θ.13, 162 37, Soph. El. 5, 167 24, Rhet. Γ.2, 1405 1, Meta. Γ.4, 1006 15–18).
137
This account suggests that the following expressions will have the same significance:‘Cicero’: ‘Tully’‘gold’: ‘the substance whose essence is atomic number 79’‘man’: ‘biped
animal’ This suggestion seems confirmed by Aristotle's discussions of the paradoxes of knowledge: Section 4. Names and definitions may, in this view, signify the same,
without names having to signify the essences which are the subject matter of those definitions. (On this issue, see App. 1.)
86 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
This line of thought suggests a way in which names and certain phrases can signify the same (C(3) above). ‘Man’ and
‘biped animal’ will signify the same if the answer to e.g. ‘What is man?’ is the same as the answer to ‘What is biped
animal?’ They will signify the same because the thoughts with which they are correlated are the same in the relevant
respect: both being brought about in the form-transferring way by the same kind in the world. Had the kinds been
distinct, the expressions could not have had the same significance, even if they had both been true of objects or kinds
which invariably co-occurred. Thus, ‘possessor of weight’ and ‘occupier of three-dimensional space’ will differ in
significance, if the essence of the two kinds is distinct. Conversely:
138 a b
See, e.g. Post. An. Β.8, 93 24–6. It is difficult to advance at all in scientific investigation when one possesses a grasp of only the accidental properties of thunder (93 31–5).
One can, of course, say things about thunder, and be in contact with thunder, but one still lacks thoughts about thunder if one only possesses an accidental account of
thunder.
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 87
of the kind. Both names and intersubstitutable accounts signify the same kinds non-accidentally.139
This model suggests a way to complete Aristotle's view of the signification of some names and of accounts of what
such names signify. There can be accounts of ‘thunder’ as ‘a type of noise in the clouds’ or ‘a type of noise
accompanied by lightning’. ‘Thunder’ will signify the same as both, provided that they are all correlated non-
accidentally with the same kind. This will be so if all three expressions are non-accidentally true of one object. It is the
latter fact, that they all signify mediately (in the way specified) the same kind, that grounds their sameness of
significance.
This model generates its own distinctive set of problems:
(i) How do names (like ‘goatstag’) for non-existents have significance?
(ii) How are statements about existence to be understood?
(iii) How are statements involving propositional attitudes to be understood?
Further, something more has to be said to account for the apparent difference in significance between distinct
accounts of the same phenomenon. For ‘noise accompanied by lightning’ and ‘noise in the clouds’ must (it seems) in
some way signify something different.
I shall argue in Sections 4.3 and 4.4 that Aristotle seeks to answer these three questions (i)–(iii) in a way which is
consistent with, and motivated by, the general pattern of the account so far developed.
and
‘goatstag’ signifies a kind of animal, which is the offspring of goat and stag.
But how can Aristotle accept accounts of this type, if he is committed to the view of signification given in the last
Section? Clearly, the signification of these terms cannot be determined by the process of ‘likening’ of
139
At this point (as in Chapter 2) non-accidental features may include essential and necessary features (including idia ). If accounts of kinds were to be confined to their
essential features, this would mark a further restriction on the type of non-accidental features involved. See the discussion in Chapters 5 and 6 of the idea of the form
being transferred.
88 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
thoughts to kinds in the world. So, how do such terms signify anything at all?
Aristotle begins De Interpretatione 2 by remarking that names themselves have no parts which signify ‘in separation’ or
‘in their own right’ (16a20 f.). Thus, in ‘Kallippos’ the parts, such as ‘—horse’, do not signify in the way they would in
the phrase ‘the fine horse’ (16a21 f.). He then adds:
It is not, however, the same for compound names as for simple ones. In the latter there are no parts which signify
anything. In the former, the parts tend to signify (bouletai), but they signify nothing when separated, as for example
‘boat’ in ‘pirate boat’ (16a23–6)
Elsewhere he notes that in ‘double words’ parts do signify (semainei) but not ‘in their own right’ (16b32 f.). Thus,
Aristotle's basic distinction is between simple names (16a23) which have no parts which signify anything (at least in the
context of such names), and compound names (like ‘pirate boat’ or ‘goatstag’) whose parts do (in some way) signify,
but nonetheless do not (in this context) signify anything ‘in their own right’. The account in the previous Section has
been of simple names. How are compound names to be represented?
Aristotle's discussion is very condensed. Indeed, it is not even clear whether ‘Kallippos’ is used as an example of a
simple name or a compound one.140 However, his brief remarks suggest that in compound names the parts contribute
to the significance of the compound whole, which is to be determined by the significance of the parts plus their mode
of combination. The ‘goat—’ plays some role in determining the significance of the compound, but does not function
as a separate signifying expression. Its role is not to signify the kind, goat, but to play a role in forming a new
semantically significant term: (e.g.) offspring of goat and stag.
In the basic case, the significance of simple names is fixed by the answer to the question: What is the thought about
with which they are conventionally correlated? This question is answered by pointing to the object or kind in the world
to which the thought is likened. In the case of compound names, the relevant thought is about the compound object
(goatstag) formed by parts connected (by the thinker). The content of his thought is not determined by a likening
relation between it (viz. the whole) and things in the world. For, that relation is blind to the internal complexity of the
relevant thought.141 Thus, the immediate significance of a compound term is a complex thought, which is about the
complex entity formed by the thinker in his mind. Such compound terms may, of course, have mediate
140
Ammonius took it to be a simple name, Ackrill a compound one.
141
It is a consequence of this account that ‘pirate boat’ is not given its significance in the same way as ‘pirate’ or ‘boat. Strictly speaking, ‘pirate boat’ is not given its significance
by the likening relation to things in the world any more than ‘goat stag’ is. For, the fact of the existence of pirate boats is not what determines the significance of the term.
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 89
significance in terms of the kinds in the world (if any) of which they are true. But they can have immediate significance
without having mediate significance. Thus, the term ‘goatstag’ has immediate significance on the basis of the semantic
contribution its parts make to the relevant complex thought, although there is no kind in the world to which that
complex thought corresponds.
Aristotle does not spell out his proposal for compound names, since his focus remains mainly on simple names (which
lack constituents which are, in any way, semantically significant). One version of his proposal would run as follows:
The immediate significance of ‘goatstag’ would be determined by the content of the compound thought (Θ), with
which it is conventionally correlated. The content of this thought will in turn be fixed by the thought contents of
simple thoughts Θ1 and Θ2 which are placed (by the thinker) in relation R (e.g. offspring of). The role of Θ1 and Θ2 is
not (in this context) to signify things in the world, but rather to serve as an input (with the content they have) to an
operation which yields a new significant thought. While Θ1 and Θ2 have the content they do because they are brought
about in the likening way by things in the world, their role in compound thoughts is not to signify those kinds. Rather,
the significance they acquire through being used to signify kinds is used by the thinker to form a new complex thought,
with which the compound term is conventionally correlated. Thus, the linguistic expression ‘goatstag’ signifies
immediately the content of the complex thought Θ: offspring of goat and stag. For, this is the answer to the question:
‘What is the thought Θ about?’
At this point, a major difference between simple and compound (or complex) names becomes evident. The
significance of the simple and compound names is fixed in radically different ways. As a consequence, while simple
thoughts must signify one object or kind in the world, compound names need not.142 For, the significance of the latter
is fixed in a way which
142
I assume that (e.g.) man and goat are unitary kinds of this type, even though they might decompose under further metaphysical analysis into (e.g.) rational animal. They are
proper unities qua genuine species of animal, with their own ‘principle of movement and rest’. By contrast, goatstag is not a unitary kind (since there are no goatstags), nor
is goatman (even if all goats and men were classified as such). For, these are not genuine kinds, but are constructs of our thoughts. At this point, Aristotle's claims about
simple names rest on metaphysically based ideas of what is to count as a genuine unitary kind.
90 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
does not depend on their being one kind in reality which brings them about in the likening way. Of course, complex
names may signify objects or kinds (mediately), but it is not a condition of their having significance that they do so.143
If this is correct, ‘goatstag’ can be significant, even if there is no kind which is mediately signified. The term has an
immediate signification: a kind of animal, which is the offspring of goat and stag. There is nothing more to the
significance of this name than is given in the account of what the name signifies. But in other cases (such as that of
‘pirate boat’) there will also be objects which are signified mediately. Similarly for complex expressions such as ‘noise
accompanied by lightning’ and ‘noise in the clouds’. While these signify mediately the same kinds in the world, they
differ in their immediate significance because the thoughts with which they are correlated are different in their
semantically relevant components.
This account will apply straightforwardly to those empty names which, like ‘goatstag’, contain semantically active
constituents. However, it cannot work for those empty names which are not semantically compound, such as, e.g.
‘void’, ‘Socrates’ (if Socrates does not exist (Cat. 13b31)) or chimera (cf. Alexander of Aphrodisias, Ad Meta. 990b14).
Does Aristotle also have a strategy for these cases?
He considers an apparently simple name of the relevant type in De. Interpretatione 8. There he writes:
If one name is given to two things which do not make up one thing, there is not a single affirmation. Suppose, for
example, that one gave the name ‘cloak’ to man and horse. Then:
Cloak is white
would not be a single affirmation. For, to say this is not different from saying:
Cloak is white
can be semantically complex even though the name itself lacks semantic parts. Presumably, the immediate signification
of the name ‘cloak’ is given by means of a combination of semantically active names (even though
143
In the case of ‘pirate boat’ or ‘author of the Ethics ’ the primary significance will be given by the complex thought with which the terms are correlated, the secondary
significance by the object in the world with which the complex thought is correlated: e.g. Aristotle. Thus, complex names and expressions have separable primary and
secondary significations.
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 91
‘cloak’ does not include these as parts). Here, the immediate signification of the name is determined by our combining
two distinct semantically significant names. However, Aristotle only commits himself to the cautious claim that if this
name is significant, its significance depends on its being correlated with many objects (in a given relation).144 Thus, the
most we can conclude is that while some non-compound names are given to one thing, others (like ‘cloak’) are not.
The significance of the latter group (if they have one) depends on the significance of complex expressions such as ‘man
and horse’ with which they are conventionally correlated. This group will include any (semantically) simple significant
empty names, since their immediate significance must be dependent on some combination of simple names (joined
together by us: e.g. ‘unicorn’ might be understood as ‘horse with horn’, etc.).
According to this model, there cannot be single affirmations when the grammatical subject, even if non-compound,
fails to signify one existing object or kind. For, in single affirmations there must be one object with which the relevant
term is correlated. Thus, the signification of empty names is fixed in a way which precludes their being used in single
affirmations, since in these cases there is no one object (of the appropriate type) with which they are correlated and
which produces the relevant affection of the soul.145 All significant empty names must be either
144
If the expression was not correlated with many objects, but was a simple empty name, it would signify nothing. This is not to say that Aristotle suggest here that no empty
name is significant (as Ackrill suspected, Aristotle's Categories and De Interpretatione (Oxford, 1963), 132). It is rather to note that unless the empty name is complex in one of
the ways indicated, it will lack significance because there is no entity in the world with which it is appropriately related. On this interpretation, the alternatives canvassed in
a
18 23–6 are as follows: either the name ‘cloak’ is treated as significant and complex, and there are several affirmations, or it is not significant (because it is not treated as
complex). In the first alternative, the first affirmation (viz. ‘Cloak is white’ (18a 25)) is equivalent both to ‘Man-and-horse is white’ and ‘Man is white and horse is white’
a
without distinction (as Aristotle says (18 21–3)), because ‘Man-and-horse’ is interpreted in the way indicated in the final sentence. In the second alternative, ‘cloak’ is not
treated as equivalent to either, and is, therefore, a simple name with no reference—and hence not significant. Ackrill's interpretation, by contrast, takes Aristotle to
distinguish between ‘Man-and-horse is white’ and ‘Man is white and horse is white’ (despite Aristotle's apparent insistence to the contrary (18a 21–3)). Further, it requires
Aristotle to treat the complex name ‘Man-and-horse’ as insignificant because empty. This is an unfortunate consequence, since Aristotle elsewhere clearly regards some
empty names (such as ‘goatstag’) as significant (as Ackrill himself notes). Nor is the suggestion (to mitigate this consequence) that ‘man-and-horse’ is an impossible object
(since no man could possibly be a horse) finally convincing. For, there is no indication that Aristotle is speaking here of impossible objects, nor any sign that he saw a relevant
difference between ‘man-horse’ and ‘goat-stag’.
145
This will be so also if there is no proper unity referred to by a given term. Thus, ‘Pride is F’ would not say one thing of one thing, if there was more than one thing which
was pride (97b 13–24). Some compound names for unitary entities can also signify one thing in the required way (cf. De Int. 20b 15–18), and, thus, form constituents of
single affirmations. But the compound name is a special case of a constituent in a single affirmation, and the basic case of the latter involves simple names.
92 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
semantic compounds (like ‘goatstag’) or compounds at the level of thought (like ‘cloak’). Both will only appear in
complex affirmations, and both are partially dependent for their significance on the simple names which comprise the
relevant complex names or expressions.
Aristotle can allow that the sentences:
It is not the case that there are animals which are the offspring of a goat and a stag
and will be true. In a similar way:
Animals which are the offspring of a goat and a stag are found in Bosnia.146
Aristotle's discussion of existential issues in De Interpretatione and Categories appears to be influenced by this account of
simple names and single affirmations.147 In single affirmations, one thing is predicated of one actual thing (non-
accidentally). Thus, in singular cases, it will follow from:
a is F
146
This is not intended as a full account of the logical form of categorical statements involving names such as ‘goatstag’. In particular, I do not investigate here whether
complex statements of this type can be accommodated within the framework of Aristotle's syllogistic (involving Α, Ι, Ο, and claims). Perhaps other machinery (e.g. drawn
from predicate calculus) is required at this point. Aristotle does not consider these issues in detail because he focuses almost exclusively on categorical statements for simple
terms. I am indebted at this point to discussions with Alex Orenstein.
147 a
In simple, single affirmations, ‘one thing is said of one thing non-accidentally’ (De Int. 18 13 f.); by contrast, there can be non-simple, single affirmations which are one by
conjunction of such claims. The simplest, and most basic, case of a simple, single affirmation involves one simple name plus a predicational tie; for, all other cases of simple,
single affirmations will involve names compounded out of a simple name. At the basis of Aristotle's doctrine of simple, single affirmations is his account of simple names.
He attempts to specify their signification independently of their role in such affirmations in virtue of his favoured likening-relation. While the De Int. is in large measure
neutral on the issue of whether, in Aristotle's view, an account of names is prior to an account of affirmations (or vice versa), his approach in general appears to favour
taking the signification of names as basic.
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 93
that
a is F
and
Thunder is loud
will entail:
148
It remains a moot point whether any class would count as a genuine unity of the appropriate type.
149
This account of one basic ingredient in Aristotle's logical square of opposition does not require that the language as a whole contain no empty terms, only that single
affirmations do not. (To complete it one requires a detailed specification of what is signified by ‘All A's’. But that lies outside the scope of this Chapter.) It should be
contrasted with Timothy Smiley's approach to these issues in ‘Syllogism and Quantification’, Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (1962), 58–72. Smiley preserves the logical square
by employing a ‘many-sorted’ logical system in which every subject term refers to an existing object. But this, at a stroke, banishes such empty names as ‘goatstag’, ‘void’, or
‘Socrates’ from the language, contrary to Aristotle's explicit examples in De Int., Cat., and Phys.
150
The variety of cases of names which Aristotle discusses in De Int. alone (‘Kallippos’, ‘Homer’, ‘goatstag’, ‘cloak’) makes it unprofitable to ask whether all Aristotelian names
are existence-presupposing. (See, for example, Michael Wedin's and William Jacobs's discussions of the claim that all singular, affirmative sentences imply the existence of a
bearer of the grammatical subject of the sentence (‘Aristotle on the Existential Import of Singular Sentences’, Phronesis 23 (1978), 179–96, and ‘Aristotle and Nonreferring
Subjects’, Phronesis 24 (1979), 282–300, respectively). There is a rich variety of cases, which can be classified initially as follows:Simple names in single affirmations
presuppose the existence of their bearer. Any name which can occur meaningfully in a single proposition entails the existence of its bearer. But there are simple and
compound names (‘Pegasus’, ‘goatstag’, etc.) which do not entail or presuppose the existence of their bearer, even if they occur in (non-single) affirmative sentences of the
form ‘a is F.’. Earlier discussions of these topics appear to overlook these complexities in Aristotle's account.
94 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
151
Aristotle may employ a similar strategy in considering a further type of complexity in the subject-place (cf. De Int. 20b15–17). One example of this type of case is:Homer is F
(e.g. a poet). (De Int. 21a24–5)Aristotle claims that in this case it does not follow thatHomer existsbecause ‘is F’ is not predicated non-accidentally of Homer ‘in his own right’
in the original sentence (De Int. 21a25–7). In that sentence ‘is F’ may be predicated non-accidentally of Homer-the-poet but not of Homer himself (as ‘good’ is predicated of
A-the-shoemaker and not of A himself in the sentence ‘A is a good shoemaker’ De Int. 21a14–16). If so, the sentence is about a complex object Homer-the-poet and not
about one object (Homer), and it will not follow from it that:Homer exists.However, Aristotle does not attempt to state under what conditions sentences are about one thing
rather than a complex, and so does not make it clear (in general terms) when the relevant existential consequences can be avoided. In this case, ‘Homer’ is presumably to be
correlated with a complex thought whose content is fixed not solely by Homer himself. But Aristotle gives no indication of why this is so. At this point, Aristotle's account
runs out. His interest is, as always, focused on the central case of simple names for one proper, natural unity. This unity need not be a metaphysical simple, but can be a kind,
like man. The key notion appears to be that of a natural unity (with its own internal structure), and not that of a metaphysical simple which resists further analysis.
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 95
occurring meaningfully in single affirmations must entail the existence of their bearer. For, their significance is fixed by
the object with which they are correlated in the likening way.
But the first of these points gives rise to a problem: if the ways in which simple and complex names signify differ to
this extent, why did Aristotle insist that knowledge of both was independent of knowledge of existence? How did he
hold on to C(1), the claim required by the three-stage view in the Analytics? Before addressing this pressing problem, I
shall consider one further relevant aspect of Aristotle's discussion: his remarks on certain paradoxes involving
knowledge and belief.
It is only to things which are indistinguishable in essence and one that all the same attributes belong.
Cicero is the same in essence as Tully, as is water as H2O. These cases are distinguished from another group of which
Aristotle writes:
it is not necessary in all cases that what belongs to the subject only accidentally is true of the thing itself
In this group will be placed attributes which do not belong to the subject in virtue of its own nature, such as:
96 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
a is F
a = the G
The G is F.
Thus, if
Koriskos is known to me, and
Koriskos = the man approaching
it will not follow that
The man approaching is known to me.154
152 a
It will also include:The musician is a man.(Meta. Δ.7, 1017 8–10)where it is not of the musician as such that being a man is predicated, but of (e.g.) Polykleitos. (Similarly with
‘The musician builds.’) When the subject is a substance or kind, properties that belong to it as such will be its essential properties. But when the subject is not a substance by
itself but (e.g.) a substance qua musician, the properties that belong to it as such need not be essential properties of the substance itself; rather, they will be properties which
belong to it qua musician; and these need not be essential properties of that substance (e.g. man), if other types of substance can be musicians (on this, see L. Spellman's
‘Referential Opacity in Aristotle’, HPQ 7 (1990), 21 ff.). This formulation does not essentially involve regarding Polykleitos the musician as a ‘kooky object’ distinct from
Polykleitos (as is suggested by F. Lewis, ‘Accidental Sameness in Aristotle’, PS 42 (1982), 2, 4–5, 7, 24, and G. Matthews, ‘Accidental Unities’ in M. Schofield and M.
Nussbaum (eds.) Language and Logos (Cambridge, 1982), 227–8, 230–5. Rather, Polykleitos is contingently identical with Polykleitos the musician, since Polykleitos may have
existed without being Polykleitos the musician.
153
Aristotle appears in this passage to think that Koriskos qua man approaching has an essence (ousia) distinct from that of Koriskos. And this supports the view that
Koriskos the man approaching is a separate object from Koriskos, one with its own essence. However, in the present context, ‘indistinguishable in ousia ’ may mean only
‘indistinguishable in some canonical account (logos ) of what they are’, and need not involve attributing a separate essence to Koriskos qua man approaching. For, in this
context, ‘being good’ and ‘being good and about to be asked’ have separate ousiai, although (presumably) both lack Aristotelian essences (properly speaking).
154 b
Aristotle applies the same strategy to the following inference pattern (179 4–6):This (statue) is mine.This (statue) is an artwork.This artwork is mine.The conclusion does not
follow, if it means that I made the statue, since I may only possess it. The example is less striking, however, since it is tempting to spot ambiguity in ‘mine’ (made by me,
‘belonging to me’). Aristotle, however, argues that, since this statue is not essentially mine, the conclusion does not follow.
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 97
This latter pattern of inference will only be valid if the identity statement is a necessary one, and the relevant terms (‘a’,
‘the G’) denote objects or their essential properties.155 By contrast, since Koriskos is not necessarily identical with the
man who approaches, it does not follow that since I know Koriskos but do not know the man approaching, I both
know and do not know Koriskos.156 More generally, if the identity in question is contingent, there will be no valid
substitution in contexts of this type.
Aristotle appears to accept the following principle as valid:
(1) S knows who a is
a is the same in essence as B
S knows who b is.
Since this principle is a general one, he should also accept:
(2) S knows that Fa
a is the same in essence as b
S knows that Fb.
For, if a and b are the same in essence, they will share all the same properties. Thus, if ‘a’ and ‘b’ signify the same
objects non-accidentally, one may substitute ‘a’ for ‘b’ in ‘knows that . . . ’ contexts. Nor should this result surprise us,
given Aristotle's account of co-signification. If ‘a’ and ‘b’ co-signify in the appropriate way, they should be validly
intersubstitutable.157
Aristotle's admittedly telegrammatic discussion of an alternative solution (which he rejects) reveals a similar pattern of
thought. He writes:
155
The crucial requirement is that the terms pick out things which are essentially identical. This relation is stronger than that of necessary identity, since certain features may
pass the latter test (e.g. having gills) but not be part of the essence of the phenomenon.
156
I prefer ‘know who—is’ for eidenai in this context to the alternative ‘be acquainted with—’, since it seems (as Sandra Peterson points out, The Master Paradox (Princeton Ph.
D. thesis, 1969), 20) that if one is acquainted with a, and a = b, then one is acquainted with b (even if one does not know one is). An alternative would be to translate the
verb as ‘to one's knowledge acquainted with—’, in which case (also) one would be to one's knowledge acquainted with Koriskos, but not to one's knowledge acquainted with
the man approaching. Peterson's own final suggestion that the immediate context itself be construed as a case of oratio obliqua (‘knows that—’) (p. 32) seems to go beyond
the text. I am indebted in this section to her excellent discussion of the relevant issues. See also her paper ‘Substitution in Aristotelian Technical Contexts’, PS 47 (1985),
249–57.
157
Sandra Peterson did not discuss the relation between the substitution principle which Aristotle accepts and the account of signification. But this connection appears a central
one in discussing oratio obliqua contexts.
98 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
Some people say that it is possible to know and not to know the same thing, but not in the same respect. When they
do not know the man approaching, but do know Koriskos, they say they know and do not know the same thing but
not in the same respect. (Soph. El. 179b7–11)
Aristotle's own proposal, presumably, allows that one may know with regard to the man approaching that he is
approaching, but not know that he is Koriskos. (In 179b30–3, Aristotle is extending his original account to cover
‘intensional’ contexts.) The alternative proposal, by contrast, will not work in some cases (179b27); presumably, those
which cannot be analysed in terms of the person knowing and not knowing the same thing in a different aspect. Thus,
he comments:
the person knows concerning Koriskos that he is Koriskos, and concerning the man approaching that he is
approaching. (179b27 f., 31–3)
In this proposal (but not in Aristotle's) one can substitute ‘Koriskos’ for ‘the man approaching’ in the context:
S does not know with regard to the man approaching that he is Koriskos
to yield:
158
The opponent might (of course) accept that S knows and does not know with regard to Koriskos that he is Koriskos. However, in this case he is not (as Aristotle points out)
employing his favoured strategy of finding a different aspect as the relevant object of belief. However, Aristotle's criticism is not by itself conclusive. His opponent might
insist that one can hold—about Koriskos—distinct attitudes to the claim ‘he is Koriskos’. For, in locutions of the form:Of a, S knows that he is F.the first place (filled by ‘a’)
appears to be extensional and outside the context of S's knowledge. If so, the opponent would not think that he had much to ‘explain away’ in this case. What Aristotle really
needed (for his purposes) was a case in which S knows that a is F and does not know that a is F (although not perhaps in the same mode).
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 99
surely one can know that Cicero is a Roman, grasp the significance of ‘Tully’, and still not know that Tully is a Roman?
Can his substitution principle avoid refutation by the very examples which led Frege to articulate his own distinctive
theory? Does Aristotle have anything further to say in his defence?159
It would be foolish to claim that Aristotle focused sharply on these issues in the passages cited or elsewhere. However,
his remarks suggest one move which mitigates the appearance of paradox. In discussing intentional action (NE/EE
1135a23–30), Aristotle separates accidental and non-accidental knowledge. Thus, he writes:
I call ‘intentional’ an action within one's power where one acts knowingly and not in ignorance of who is being
affected, with what, and for what good—and one knows each of these non-accidentally . . . for, it is possible that the
person struck should be one's father, and one know that the person is a man or one of the bystanders, but be
ignorant that it is one's father.
In this case one knows non-accidentally that one is striking a bystander or a man, but only knows accidentally that it is
one's father. This type of ignorance (accidental knowledge) is to be distinguished from cases where one has no idea that
one is striking anybody at all. If one applies this distinction to the case of simple names, one arrives at the following
position. While it is true that if one knows that Cicero is a Roman, and knows the signification of ‘Tully’, one will know
that Tully is a Roman, the premiss and conclusion will involve different types of knowledge. For, one will know non-
accidentally that Cicero is a Roman but only know accidentally that Tully is a Roman. It will not follow from the fact
that one knows non-accidentally that Cicero is a Roman that one knows non-accidentally that Tully is a Roman. Thus,
in an example of the type cited, the assailant might know non-accidentally that he is striking Cicero, but only know
accidentally that he is striking Tully. For, it is only the claim that Cicero is a Roman that plays a role in the explanation
of his intentional action.
If this is correct, the accidental knower will know (in line with the Sophisticis Elenchis substitution principle) that Tully is
a Roman (Fb), even though he does not know this in the way which would be required if he were to be able (e.g.) to act
intentionally on it. Slightly more fully, he may know Fb accidentally even though he is not able to use this knowledge in
his practical reasoning. In a similar case, on which Aristotle comments, one may know in some way (e.g.) that this mule
is sterile (perhaps on the basis of past perception or reasoning), while still thinking actively that this mule is in foal (Pr.
An. 67b5–10). Here, too, one will know that this mule is sterile (Fb) but not in the way required if one is to use that
knowledge in one's
159
Compare Nathan Salmon's strategy in Frege's Puzzle (Boston, 1982), ch. 8.
100 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
reasoning. In these cases, the subject may have knowledge that Fb even though he has not grasped this claim in the
way required for him to be able to use it in his reasoning.
Aristotle does not specify (in any further detail) the distinct ways of knowing he has introduced. However, his remarks
suggest that (in his view) one may substitute ‘a’ and ‘b’, when these terms have the same significance, in knowledge
contexts, without intolerable paradox. For, while (in the case envisaged) the thinker will know that Tully is a Roman, he
will not know it non-accidentally. He does not grasp this piece of knowledge in the way in which he knows that Cicero
is a Roman.160 His non-accidental knowledge of the latter is manifested by his ability to use it in some further way in his
thinking.161
While these remarks must remain speculative, they suggest that Aristotle had at his disposal some resources with which
to defend his approach to substitution and co-signification. In his account, the distinctions required to analyse belief
and knowledge contexts will stem from features distinctive of these particular states, not from his account of
signification. The latter will legitimize the general principle of co-substitution sketched above, and will be appropriate
in a wide variety of contexts, including modal ones. The further additions required to analyse non-accidental
knowledge will not themselves be part of his general account of signification. Thus, he can distinguish what is needed
to legitimize substitution in contexts involving (non-accidental) knowledge from what is required for his account of co-
signification. But, in making this distinction, his account is fundamentally non-Fregean.
160
Accidental knowledge need not require different objects of knowledge, as accidental causation need not require distinct processes separate from essential causes. (On this,
see my Aristotle's Philosophy of Action, 50–1.) There are certain analogies between Aristotle's strategy (so understood) and recent responses to Frege's puzzle—e.g. Nathan
Salmon's in Frege's Puzzle. Aristotle's ways of knowing correspond in some measure to Salmon's guises. Both, at least, are non-identical with Fregean senses (see Sect. 4.6).
But there are also important differences, since Aristotle appears to allow free substitution within certain propositional contexts (e.g. ‘know’), and not within others (e.g.
‘know non-accidentally’). Hence, his motivation for permitting certain substitutions is specific to certain propositional attitudes, and cannot be the result simply of the
sameness of significance of certain singular terms and a compositional semantics for attitude ascriptions (as in Salmon's proposal). There is (for Aristotle) non-accidental
knowledge of a proposition only when it is known in a given way.
161
In this way, what is known by nature can be the same as what is known by us, even if we do not grasp what is known in the same way or order as the active intellect itself
b
does (cf. Post. An. Α.2, 71 33 ff.). For, what is known can be precisely the same thing, even though it is thought about in different ways. Here, Aristotle may be following a
traditional pattern of Greek thought in which we and the gods can know the same thing, even though we do not think of it in the same way. On this general topic, see F.
Letoublon's interesting essay, ‘Les dieux et les hommes: le langage et sa reference dans l'antiquité grecque archaique’ Language and Reality in Greek Philosophy: Proceedings of the
Greek Philosophical Society (Athens, 1985), 92–9.
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 101
(A) Simple names signify (mediately) substances and kinds (on pain of being meaningless), while compound names
need not do so. In the case of simple names, the content of the thought with which the name is correlated is
determined by the kind (or object) in the world which imprints itself on us (through the likening process).
(B) In Aristotle's view, one can grasp an account of what a simple name signifies without knowing of the existence
(or of the essence) of the object or kind in question. For, at the first stage of the three stages of scientific enquiry,
one can grasp the significance of ‘triangle’ without knowledge of the existence or essence of the phenomenon.
How are (A) and (B) consistent? One can generate the appearance of inconsistency as follows:
(1) Our thoughts about a kind are individuated (in part) by the kinds which cause them. (Premiss)
(2) When we have a thought, we know which thought we have. (Premiss)
(3) When we know which thought we have, we know what individuates it. (From (1) and (2))
(4) When we have a thought about a kind, we know which kind it is which causes it. (From (3))
(5) Accounts of what the name ‘K’ signifies are thoughts about that kind (when ‘K’ is a simple name). (Premiss)
(6) In grasping an account of what ‘K’ signifies, we know which kind it is which causes the thought. (From (4) and
(5)).
If (6) is correct, in grasping an account of what ‘K’ signifies we will know which kind is signified, and therein know that
the kind in question exists. But this is plainly inconsistent with the three-stage view, as set out in Chapters 2 and 3. For,
a crucial feature of that view is that one can grasp accounts of what names of kinds signify without knowing of the
existence of the relevant kind. Are Aristotle's semantic intuitions, after all, inconsistent?
There are (at least) two ways to respond to this challenge. One is to show that (despite what has been said so far)
Aristotle did not accept (A) or (B). An alternative is to suggest that he found a way of holding these
102 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
claims without inconsistency. Of the two claims that generate the inconsistency, (A) is (at present) the more weakly
supported. For, the major argument in its defence has rested on the (so far unconfirmed) report of a connection
between names, thought, and the objects and kinds that make up the world.162 However, (A) is in fact secure (or so I
shall argue in the next Chapter). If so, Aristotle can only avoid this problem by showing that
(A) and (B) are, appearances notwithstanding, consistent. In the argument just given, (1) will be supported by the
argument of the next Chapter. (2) seems hard to reject. For, surely if we have a thought we must (in some way)
know which thought it is. (5) is an obvious truth. So, if the argument is to be broken, Aristotle must challenge the
inference from (2) to (3)? Can this be done? Did he do it?
In Aristotle's terms, one might possess an account of what ‘K’ signifies without knowing that the kind exists, if one
does not know that the signification of the name is in fact determined by that kind. In such a case one will not know
that there exists one unified phenomenon that brought about these thoughts, still less be able to distinguish that
phenomenon from all others. While the content of the relevant thought will be determined by the kind that is signified,
the thinker need not know which kind that is (in the way required to distinguish that kind from all others, either real or
imaginary). Rather, in having a thought about eclipses, she may think of them as possessing certain features which
would locate them, if they exist, in an ordered world: e.g. being a certain unified property of the moon. But, in knowing
this, she need not know everything about what makes the thought the thought it is. In particular, she need not know that
the thought in question is (constitutively) brought about by an existing kind in the world. Indeed, she may not know
whether or not this case is like that of ‘goatstag’. In brief, she need not know that the kind in question exists.
There are three reasons, implicit in our previous discussion, for thinking that Aristotle followed this route.
First, this proposal makes good sense of Aristotle's discussions of existence claims (as set out in Section 4.3) and of
existence proofs (as deployed in Analytics Β). Stage 1 accounts allow us to articulate questions in an appropriate form
for us to attain knowledge of the existence of the kind. Thus, to establish that thunder exists is to establish that noise
belongs to the clouds, by finding an appropriate middle term. In this way, one will establish that thunder is a genuine
unity.163 In doing so, one goes beyond what is required for an understanding of the name.
Second, this account fits well with Aristotle's own use of accounts of
162
For further support for (A), see App. 1.
163
See also Sect. 4.6 below. On the view sketched here, existence can be a property of objects or kinds (in Aristotle's account), and need not in general be a property of
properties. For a contrasting view, see G. E. L. Owen's paper:‘Aristotle on the Snares of Ontology’, in R. Bambrough (ed.), New Essays on Plato and Aristotle (London, 1965).
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 103
what names signify (as set out in Chapter 2, Section 2.5). If the (immediate) signification of a simple term is determined
by the thinking faculty being likened to an object, the information embedded in the account of what it signifies may be
in the form of an indefinite reference (‘a specific type of . . . ’), or of a definite description which purports, but fails, to
be unique. For, it is not this information that determines the signification of that term. If so, a thinker may grasp an
account of what the term signifies without possessing uniquely identifying knowledge of the kind signified. His account
is an account of thunder (and not of any noise in the clouds) because it is that very phenomenon which brings about
the thought, the thinker's grasp of which the account expresses. For, it is a causal connection to the relevant
phenomenon which fixes the signification of the term. But the thinker who grasps that term need not grasp everything
about the relevant thought. In particular, the individuating information about its origin may escape him.164
Third, we have been prepared (to some extent) for a move of this type by Aristotle's discussion of the paradoxes of
knowledge. For there, two terms ‘a’ and ‘b’ can have the same significance, and the thinker know the significance of
each, without his knowing that they have the same significance. His preparedness to doubt that a = b in no way
undermines the claim that ‘a’ and ‘b’ have the same significance. There can be features of the signification of these
terms (their co-signification) which are not transparent to the thinker. (In a similar fashion, since the thinker may not
know whether pride has one essence, she may not know whether or not ‘pride’ is a ‘univocal’ term (Post. An. Β.13,
97b15–25).)
These three points highlight the role played by accounts of what terms signify. The first suggests their use in searching
for knowledge of existence and essence of a kind. One example of this role is provided by Aristotle's discussion of the
enquiry into the existence of ice. If ‘ice’ signifies the same as ‘solid water’, to establish that ice exists is to establish that
solidity belongs to water.165 The question about ice's existence is now, according to Aristotle, posed in a form in which
it can be answered and knowledge gained.166 If this is correct, there is no difficulty in understanding how existence
proofs can establish that ice exists (e. g. as a substance) by establishing that solidity
164
This suggestion fills a gap in the earlier discussion of Ch. 2; see closing paragraphs of 2.8.
165
The precise form of the question is important. To establish that ice exists/does not exist (e.g. as a substance) is not (in Aristotle's account) to establish that solidity belongs/
does not belong to solid water (or ice). And this is fortunate since the latter claims are either tautologous or inconsistent.
166
Owen (in ‘Aristotle on the Snares of Ontology’) criticized Aristotle's view on the grounds that the substitution of ‘ice’ (or ‘solid water’) for ‘water’ in the sentence which states
that ‘being solid belongs to water’ made the sentence tautologous. For, it now says that ‘being solid belongs to solid water’. However, Owen's criticism rests on a mistaken
view of Aristotle's substitution rules for stage 1 accounts. (It is only if one succumbs to this mistake that one is tempted to interpret ‘exists’ in Aristotle as equivalent to the
existential quantifier, and treat ‘ice exists’ as saying that the property of icehood is instantiated (Owen, ‘Aristotle on the Snares of Ontology’ 82 ff.). Even in Post. An. Β.8
(93b 9–12), where Aristotle comes closest to Owen's suggestion, he substitutes part of the definiens (noise . . . ) for the definiendum (thunder), and not all of it. However, in
the conclusion he switches back to ‘noise’ and omits ‘thunder’, and, thus, avoids any suspicion of the difficulty Owen considers. (Further, even if he had maintained ‘thunder’
in the conclusion, this would not generate Owen's problem. The proof of existence would then conclude with the non-tautologous claim that ‘Thunder belongs in the
clouds.’)
104 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
belongs to water. For, such accounts provide the information required for a successful enquiry (of Aristotle's form)
into the nature and existence of the kind (viz. ‘ice’ signifies solid water). But it is fully consistent with this account that
‘exists as a substance’ be treated as a predicate of ‘ice’. For, it is by means of an existence proof (involving ‘solid water’)
that the simple existential claim is established. Further, even if ‘ice’ is a simple term which signifies a substance, one can
understand what ‘ice’ signifies (on the basis of an account of what it signifies) without knowing that it exists. Thus, it is
not a referential tautology to assert that ice exists.
In the account offered, the central role of accounts of what names signify is to express the thinker's understanding of
the immediate signification of a term, such as ‘man’. In the best case, his initial understanding of the term will give him
a preliminary and partial account of the kind which will be of use in his subsequent enquiry into the nature and
existence of the kind. Such accounts provide, in effect, the base camp from which we can begin our ascent to
knowledge of the kind. With the information they provide, and our methods of investigation, we will (in the end) come
to have knowledge of the existence, extension, and nature of the kind.167 But such knowledge lies in the future, and is
not part of what it is to grasp an account of what the name signifies. Further, the role of Stage 1 accounts cannot be to
fix either the reference or the extension of the term.168 For, answers to these questions will emerge in the context of
enquiry, and need not be known at Stage 1. At the beginning of enquiry, we may have thoughts about kinds (provided
by the likening model) without knowing enough about them to determine the reference (or extension) of the relevant
terms.
167 a
As Aristotle emphasizes in Post. An. Β.8, 93 21–30, the methods are restricted to finding that there is a middle term, and what it is. The information required is just what is
needed for this: two terms which can be connected in this way.
168
For a contrasting view about the function of such accounts, see Robert Bolton's remarks on their ‘essential reference fixing role’ (‘Essentialism’, 537).
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 105
(immediate) signification of the name is determined by features beyond those of which the thinker need have
knowledge in understanding the term (such as are expressed in his account of what the term signifies).
(D) (C) is possible because the signification of the name is determined by the content of the thought with which the
name is conventionally correlated, and the content of that thought is (in turn) determined by the substance or
kind in the world which produces it. The account of what the name signifies expresses the speaker's
understanding of that name by showing his grasp on the thought with which the name is correlated. But the
thinker need not know (at the outset) how the content of the thought with which the name is correlated is
determined. For all he knows, its content might be determined in the way in which thoughts concerning
goatstags are determined.
Can this proposal be secured exegetically? It certainly has merits. It shows how Aristotle can consistently hold the
three-stage view (sketched in Chapters 2 and 3) together with the account of signification and thought given in the
earlier sections of this Chapter (and the next). More generally, (A)–(D) allow Aristotle to underwrite the four claims,
C(1)–C(4), set out in Section 4.1 above, without inconsistency.
It is, however, one thing to show that Aristotle would have been well advised to follow a given route, another to
establish that he actually did so. In the absence of any explicit endorsement by Aristotle of (A)–(D), only indirect
evidence can be available. In addition to that already provided, further support can only come from evidence that
Aristotle was aware of the distinctive shape and commitments of the theory sketched in this Chapter. Is such evidence
available?
The theory (as it emerged) is complex and has two major distinctive features, which I shall label (D1) and (D2). Once
we grasp these, we can test how far Aristotle saw and attempted to make good the distinctive philosophical
commitments that this theory involves.
(D1) In the basic case, the immediate signification of a name is given by the content of the thought with which it is
conventionally correlated. However, the content of this thought does not determine the reference of the term in the
way in which Frege and many others have proposed. It is not the case that the reference is given by the object which
‘fits’ the thoughts which express the thinker's understanding of the name. For, his understanding of the name (in terms
of general descriptions) need not be sufficient to enable him to distinguish the bearer of the name from all other
objects (real and imaginary). Rather, the content of the thought is itself fixed by the object to which the thinking faculty
is likened. In this way, the ‘likening’ relation puts us (as thinkers) in contact with a genuine kind which we proceed to
investigate.
106 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
In Aristotle's theory, although the signification of a simple name is determined (fundamentally) by an object or kind in
the world, the thinker's understanding of that name need not be accounted for in terms of his grasp of the object
signified. For, in the context of enquiry, one may understand a name and then go on to discover that the object
signified exists. Nor need one (on the basis of resources available to one at the beginning of the enquiry) ‘know which’
object is signified in the way required if one is to be able to distinguish the bearer of the name from all other objects.
As far as one's understanding goes, there need be nothing to distinguish this case from one in which there is no real
object signified.
The signification of names is fixed (in Aristotle's account) by resources which outrun the thinker's understanding of
that term. Further, the conditions for co-signification depend on how the world is and not on our understanding of the
terms themselves. In these two respects, Aristotle's account of signification is distinct from any version of the widely
accepted Fregean account of meaning.169 For, Aristotle does not accept that either the signification of a term or the
conditions for its co-signification are determined by the thinker's knowledge or understanding of the term.170
The gulf that separates Aristotle's theory from Fregean ones may explain why some have doubted whether he was
interested in meaning at all.171 His account of signification is certainly not an account of meaning, if
169
I take orthodox Fregean sense theories to be committed to the following claims:(a)To grasp the sense of a term is to grasp something which determines its reference.
(b)Senses are transparent; if two senses are the same, and one grasps both, one is able to grasp that they are identical without further reflection.(c)Senses are not object-
dependent (with the exceptions of the senses of ‘I’, ‘now’, ‘this’); one can grasp the sense of a name and there not be an object to which the name refers.See, for instance, M.
Dummett, Frege (London, 1973). Revisionary interpreters of Frege—especially the ‘new Oxford Fregeans’ (e.g. G. Evans: Varieties of Reference, J. McDowell, ‘On the Sense
and Reference of Proper Names’, Mind 86 (1977) 159–85)—deny that Frege held (c), and debate the nature of his understanding of (a). I take all Fregean theories to be
committed to (b).
170
Aristotle rejects both theses (a) and (b) mentioned above. He rejects both the classical version of Frege's thesis (a) in which the understander must have a definite description
of the object before his mind, and the ‘new version’ in which the sense grasped by the thinker determines the reference of the name simply because the sense cannot be
specified without mentioning the referent. For, in Aristotle's view, one can have an account of what the term signifies (even in the case of an existent) without knowing of the
existence of the object.
171
See T. H. Irwin's ‘Aristotle's Concept of Signification’, in Schofield and Nussbaum (eds.), Language and Logos, 240–66. Others have held that Aristotle lacks a theory of
meaning because he uses the term ‘signify’ in a wide variety of ways. Thus, in some contexts it points to a word-world relation, in others to a world-world one. But why
should this feature be worrying? There is, after all, the same variety of usage in English between what Grice calls ‘natural’ and ‘non-natural’ meaning. (‘Meaning’, P.R. 66
(1957), 121–126.) A similar argument would show that there can be no account of the meaning of names in English! All that is needed is that Aristotle employ the term
‘signify’ univocally in cases where it relates (e.g.) names and objects.
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 107
all such accounts have to consist in dictionary definitions or to provide one who understands them with a way to
determine the extension of the term. But there is a more generic conception of meaning. In it, to give the meaning of a
name ‘α’ is to state something which determines those conditions under which indicative sentences containing ‘α’ are
true or false (in so far as they contain ‘α’). Frege's theory of sense is one attempt to do this, explicit definitional
accounts of meaning another. But so too is Aristotle's theory. Take the case of simple names. In Aristotle's view, ‘α’
means A (an object or kind) if and only if A is the cause (in suitable conditions) of the thought with which ‘α’ is
conventionally correlated. Thus, the indicative sentence ‘α is F’ will be true when A is F, and false when A is not F.
Further, an object will be incorrectly named ‘α’ (e.g. in non-ideal conditions) if it is other than A. Aristotle (as we saw in
Section 4.3) offers a somewhat different account of the signification of complex names. But here too he seeks to
explain how linguistic expressions can be correctly and incorrectly applied.172 Thus, ‘goatstag’ will be incorrectly applied
to goats, if the signification of that term is fixed (as Aristotle suggests) by some combination of thoughts of goats and
stags. In these ways, Aristotle's account of signification meets the conditions given above for accounts of the meaning
of names (although it is a non-Fregean theory).173
(D2) Aristotle's theory is a complex one. For, while the meaning of simple names is determined by the substances and
kinds to which they refer, the meaning of compound names is not determined in this way. For this reason, it is a
mistake to describe Aristotle's theory as one in which ‘meaning amounts to reference’. There is no need for each
significant name to have a referent (e.g. ‘goat-stag’, ‘hippo-centaur’); only simple names in single affirmations need do
so.174 While both simple and complex names signify the object of the thought with which they are correlated, they differ
precisely because those objects are themselves determined in radically different ways.175
172
For a contrasting view which appears to confine a theory of meaning to (e.g.) dictionary definitions, see Irwin's, ‘Aristotle's Concept’, 241–3. Irwin is best seen as asking how
Aristotle can be offering an account of meaning (if he is not aiming to give dictionary equivalents). I have been helped at this point by discussions with Michael Morris.
173
My claims are, of course, confined to the meaning of names and name-like expressions. They do not amount to the claim that Aristotle devised an account of meaning for all
expressions of the language. For a somewhat similar approach to the meaning of names, see Nathan Salmon's characterization of a variety of ‘naive’ theories in Frege's Puzzle,
ch. 2. It would be a major, but worthwhile, task to compare Aristotle's account of other expressions (such as predicates and relations) with that proposed by Salmon.
174
It should be noted that Aristotle rejects Plato's theory of ideas in part on this ground (cf. Alexander of Aphrodisias, Commentary in Metaphysica 82.1).
175
Hamlyn's view that for Aristotle meaning is reference can be criticized on different grounds also. For Aristotle, two terms (a, b) can have the same reference, but differ in
significance if the correct answer to the question ‘What is a?’ is different from that to ‘What is b?’ (e.g. weight, volume). In general, the view that Aristotle is offering a
‘denotational theory’ of meaning ignores the role he attributes to thought in the determination of meaning. (See Sect. 4.2 above.)
108 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
If Aristotle holds (D1) and (D2), he incurs a number of substantial-philosophical commitments. Here are three:
(PC1) He needs to provide an account of the content of thought which can stand as the basis for this type of
account of signification. For, without a theory of content and of ‘likening’, his account of signification is
(at best) incomplete.176
(PC2) He needs to explain how we come to have thoughts of this type at all. How come we are so lucky as to
have our thinking faculties likened to kinds and substances in the world?
(PC3) He needs to explain how the signification of our terms can outrun our understanding of them. How is it
possible for us to grasp a term which (in fact) signifies a kind, without being able to discriminate that kind
from all others? Can we really understand terms without having the required knowledge of what they
signify?
(PC3) has several aspects. First, Aristotle needs to show how we can have thoughts which are individuated in a
given way without knowing this fact about them. He must show how the nature of these thoughts can be
(on occasion) veiled from us. Second, he needs to show how we came to possess thoughts (with
determinate content) which are about objects, without knowing which object or kind they are about.177
Third, he should show how we can have thoughts about kinds without knowing that, if they exist, they
have an essence. How can this be, if it is a requirement that in having thoughts about kinds something of
their form is transferred? Surely this must put us in contact with their essences?
Did Aristotle accept these commitments? Did he attempt to develop a way of meeting these demands? If we find
Aristotle at work on these
176
Compare Gareth Evans's attack on the claim that all who use names understand them, or have thoughts about their referents, in the way suggested by the ‘Photographic
Model’ (Varieties of Reference, 82–100 f.). Evans, a neo-Fregean, rejects the ‘Photographic Model’ in favour of the claim that all thinkers who use a name must have the ability
to identify the referent (p. 403) and be able to ‘distinguish the object of their judgement from all other things’ (p. 89), either by having a description which uniquely identifies
(e.g.) thunder or a propensity to recognize thunder demonstratively when confronted by it (p. 93). Since Aristotle did not accept these Fregean requirements, he needs to
show how without them we can latch on to the signification of a name.
177
Some may not find (PC3) puzzling. They believe that our grasp on the signification of a term rests merely on our standing in some causal relation with the object. But the
difficulty with their view is clear. What makes it the case that this type of causal connection gives the thinker an understanding of the term. Causal impact seems not to be
enough for understanding. But if one adds to the bare causal requirement the suggestion that the thinker must be able knowledgeably to discriminate the relevant object or
kind, one has already embraced some form of the Fregean option (which Aristotle, it appears, rejects). It may appear that Aristotle is attempting to find a space for his theory
where none really exists!
THE SIGNIFICATION OF NAMES 109
projects, we will have further evidence that he held the position defined by (A)–(D). In the next Chapter, I shall argue
that he accepted (PC1) (and the first part of (PC3)), and in Chapter 6 turn to his discussion of (PC2) and the other
aspects of (PC3). If I am correct, Aristotle attempted (with no little success) to develop precisely the type of account of
thought and meaning which is required to meet (PC1)–(PC3).
5 Signication and Thought
5.1 Introduction
Several claims in the last Chapter rest on a hypothesis about Aristotle's view of the relation between a thought and the
kind or object which that thought is about. In outline, the hypothesis runs as follows: in the central case
(corresponding to a simple name in a single affirmation), what makes a thought one about an object or kind is that the
thinking faculty is likened to that object or kind in the form-transferring way. The relevant type of likening occurs (it is
claimed) when:
(i) the object or kind is the efficient cause of the thought,
(ii) the efficient cause explains the relevant general features of the thought (viz. what it is about, its content), and
(iii) the thinker's thinking faculty is functioning correctly.
In this Chapter, I shall seek to confirm this hypothesis by providing exegetical arguments in favour of these claims. If
successful, these arguments underwrite the account of signification offered in the last Chapter. My arguments will rest
on an interpretation of Aristotle's analogy between perception and thought, as this is developed in De Anima. While
this analogy is rich in detail, I shall focus only on those aspects which concern the object of thought and perception.
It should be noted that if these arguments succeed, success comes with a heavy price. The result is that we cannot
avoid the threat of inconsistency uncovered in the previous Chapter (Section 4.5) simply by denying that Aristotle held
the account of signification developed in that Chapter. The tension between it and the three-stage view (as developed
in Chapters 2 and 3) has to be resolved in some other way.
thought about or in something else of this kind.178 So, it [viz. the noetic part] must be impassive, and receptive of the
form, and potentially of the same type [sc. as the object of thought: to noeton] but not identical with it, and be related
to the objects of thought as the faculty of sense is to sensible objects. (429a13–18)
Here, Aristotle sets out several key elements of his analogy between thought and perception:
(a) both involve a part of the soul being acted on by their respective objects;
(b) in both, the relevant part of the soul receives the form (without the matter);
(c) in both, the part of the soul is potentially of the same type as the external object which acts upon it, but is not
identical with it.179
Aristotle clarifies (c) elsewhere by adding a further claim:
(d) both faculties are potentially identical with the form received (Γ.8, 431b28 ff.)
Thus, he writes:
These faculties must be identical with either the objects themselves or their forms. But they are not identical with
their objects: for, the stone does not exist in the soul, but only the form of the stone.
Aristotle has already developed (a) and (b) in discussing perception, when he wrote:
Perception consists in being moved and acted upon . . . for, it seems to be a sort of quality change (Β.5, 416b33–5,
cf. also 418a3–6)
and
178
The qualification ‘or in something else of this kind’ could be taken in two ways: (a) If the comparison between thinking and perceiving is precise, and perceiving is not a
b a
straightforward case of ‘being acted upon’ (De An. Β.5, 417 2 f., b15, 418 1–3), neither is thinking.(b) If the comparison is less precise, thinking (unlike perceiving) might
not exactly involve being acted upon by its object. In the present context, (a) is preferable, since it makes Aristotle's inference to the characteristics which perception and
thinking share immediately intelligible. By contrast, (b) would make this problematic, since it would not be clear that perception and thinking are sufficiently alike for the
inference to be valid. For, (b), unlike (a), renders it unclear why the objects of thought and perception should be similarly related to their respective faculties.
179 a
See De An. Β.5, 418 3–6: ‘the sentient subject is potentially such as the object of sense is actually. During the process of being acted upon [viz. by the object of sense] it is
unlike it, but by the end of the process it has become like it’. The object of sense in this context is the external object which causes the relevant result. By analogy, in the case
of thought, the object of thought must be (e.g.) the stone which is thought about, and not the form of the stone which is present in the mind. This is why the thinking faculty
is held to be identical with the form of the stone (when it thinks of it), and not with the external stone (to which it is likened) (cf.Γ.8, 431b 28 ff.).
112 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
Each sense organ is receptive of the perceived object without the matter (Γ.2, 425b23 f.).
(a)–(d) point to a sustained analogy between perception and thought. Although Aristotle develops this analogy
cautiously and is aware of several major disanalogies,180 it offers (I shall argue) the basis for his account of the relation
between the thinker and the object of her thoughts. In particular, his discussion of perception lays the foundation for
the four claims laid out in the previous Section. Claims (i) and (ii) are supported in Section 5.3, and claim (iii) in Section
5.4.
5.3 The Analogy Developed: Perception and Likening: Claims (I) and
(II)
While Aristotle makes extensive use of the analogy between perception and thought, he makes comparatively few
remarks about its basis. In De Anima Γ.9 he notes that the power of discrimination (krisis) is common to both intellect
(dianoia) and perception (432a15–17), and in Γ.3 says that in perceiving and thinking the soul discriminates (krinei) and
cognitively grasps (gnōrizei) (427a19–21). Since discrimination of this type involves our being correct (or incorrect
(428a3–5)), both perception and thought must involve cognitive discrimination of their relevant objects.181 My aim is to
180 a b
In De An.Γ.4 alone several disanalogies emerge:(1)The impassivity of the thinking and perceptual faculties is distinguished (429 29– 6). The latter can be destroyed by
‘excessive sensible objects’, while the former is not adversely affected by ‘highly intelligible objects’.(2)The sensible faculty involves a physical organ, and is inseparable from
a b
the body (429 26, 4–5), while neither is true of the thinking faculty.(3)In the case of theoretical knowledge of things without matter, that which thinks and that which is
a b a
thought about are identical (430 2–6). In the case of perception or knowledge of particular external objects or enmattered kinds this is not so (cf. 417 25–8, 430 6–8,
a
432 1–3). This is because, in the distinctive case of abstract thought, the relevant object does not exist independently of the thinking faculty. (See below.)Of these, (3) alone is
directly relevant to the issue of the object of thought, and is discussed below. (3) goes beyond Aristotle's identification of thinking with the relevant form (which is common
to all cases of perceiving and thinking).
181 a
In De An., Aristotle takes discrimination as a basic notion together with the capacity to move in space (Γ.9, 432 15–19). He is not attempting to give an account of what
makes it the case that a creature discriminates, but only of what it discriminates (in varying cognitive states). (For a defence of this translation of krisis, see T. Ebert in
‘Aristotle on What is Done in Perceiving’, Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 37 (1983), 181 ff.) Aristotle holds that if one discriminates A, this essentially involves one's
being able to discriminate its contrary or opposite (e.g. De An.Α.5, 411a4 f.,Γ.3, 427b5). In this, discrimination is governed by the same constraints as knowledge (cf. e.g. NE/
EE E.1, 1129a13 ff., Meta.Β.2, 996a20 ff.). If one can discriminate what is white this essentially involves being able to discriminate it from what is not white (one can ‘tell
them apart’). Similarly, to be able to discriminate this object essentially involves being able to discriminate it from what is not this object (e.g. other objects, nothing), at least
in some cases. Discrimination essentially involves being able to distinguish cognitively between different cases in some way (e.g. ‘This is A rather than not A’, ‘This is a and
that is not a’). For Aristotle, discriminating A goes beyond merely differential behavioural response to A; for, one could respond differentially to A and to not-A, but not do
so in virtue of the same discriminating capacity. That said, certain further questions remain:(a)If I can discriminate white from non-white in this way, does this require me to
be able to discriminate what is white as white? (Could I achieve this while discriminating what is white (e.g.) in terms rather of a theoretical pattern of light rays.)(b)If I can
discriminate this object from other objects, does this require me to be able to discriminate it as an object? (Does the latter require some further conceptual machinery?)These
questions are taken up in what follows.
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 113
examine the nature of the discrimination involved in both cases by considering the four claims (a)–(d) set out in the last
Section.
Aristotle's fourth claim (d) is not as perplexing as it may initially seem. It amounts only to this: a given case of (e.g.)
seeing is the one it is because it is a case in which (e.g.) blue is seen. More generally, what makes a perception one
perception is that it is of one object at one time (De Sensu 447b16–18). This is how (according to Aristotle) we
individuate perceptions: by their objects and their times. Thus, ‘perceiving’ can be identified with the form perceived;
for, the latter makes a given perceiving the one it is.
Aristotle develops this point in considerable detail in the case of thought in De Anima Γ.6. There he writes:
if one thinks of each of the halves (of a line) separately, then one divides the time also; and then it is as if they were
lengths themselves. But if one thinks of the whole as made up of halves, then one does so in a time made up of
both halves. (430b11–14)
His point is this: my thought of the line is a single (undivided) thought provided that it is of a single (undivided) object.
If I think of each of the halves of the line separately, I have two thoughts (one for each side of the division). If I make
up a line from these two halves, I have a third thought (of a divided but conjoined line) separate from any of the other
thoughts so far mentioned. The general principle is that what makes each thought the thought it is its object. Thus,
what makes my present thought the one it is that it is one of Kyoto, and not (e.g.) of the southern section of that
ancient city.
The perceiving faculty is potentially of the same type as what is perceived in that it can be made like it in some relevant
respect. Aristotle concludes De Anima Β.5 as follows:
114 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
The sentient subject is potentially such as the object of sense is actually. Thus, during the process of being acted
upon it is unlike, but at the end of the process it has been made like (homoiotai) the object and is like it. (418a3–6)
But what does the phrase ‘a is made like b’ mean? Throughout De Anima Β.5, Aristotle refers to his general account of
affecting and being affected as developed in De Generatione Corruptione Α.7. Thus, he raises one specific difficulty for the
De Generatione Corruptione account as follows:
Now, some say that the like is affected only by the like. But in the sense in which this is possible or impossible we
have already stated in our general account of acting and being acted on. (416b35–417a2)
Therefore, as we have said, a thing is acted upon in a way by the like, and in a way by the unlike; for, while it is being
acted upon it is unlike, but when it has suffered it is like, the object. (417a18–20)182
In De Generatione Corruptione Aristotle claims that if one thing affects another, they must be distinct in species but the
same in genus (distinct in form, but with the same type of matter (324a5–7)). Agent and patient (e.g. the hot and the
cold) are initially both like and unlike. They are unlike in that one is hot and the other cold, but like in that they have
enough in common for the hot to heat the cold (cf. GC 323b29–324a5). The agent brings into play the patient's
potentiality for being thus affected. A potentially hot object is made actually hot by the agency of the actually hot
object, which assimilates the cold object to itself, and makes it like it itself (viz. hot):
This is why it is indeed plausible to say that fire heats and the cold cools, and that, to speak generally, what is active
(the agent) makes the patient like itself. (324a9–11)
When this occurs, the patient is likened to the agent by being made like it in some relevant respect (De An.Β.5,
418a5–6).183 The resultant state of the patient is a liken-ness of the agent's active power. Thus, the cold is (in the state of
having been) made hot by the hot, and this is why it is actually hot.
182 b
It matters little, for present purposes, if the explicit reference in this passage is to GC or to Aristotle's earlier discussion of food and digestion (De An. Β.4, 416 5–9). For,
in the latter discussion Aristotle also employs his GC thesis to explain the truth and error in two conflicting views: ‘like is fed by like’ and ‘like is fed by unlike’ (416a 29–32).
Food is initially unlike the digestive faculty, but is made like it by digestion. Indeed, part of the point of Aristotle's introducing the case of digestion may be familiarize his
audience and readers with his GC structures.
183 a
The Greek terms reveal the importance of efficient causality: the agent makes the patient like itself (homoioun (GC Α.7, 324 10 f.)). The patient is made like the agent
(homoiotai (De An. Β.5, 418a 6)). When this occurs, something is produced (a state of the patient) which is a liken-ness (homoiōmata ) of the agent (De Int. 1, 16a 7 f.).
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 115
The role of the efficient cause is central here. Aristotle's claim is not merely that the effect is like or resembles the cause
in terms of its relevant quality. The type of likeness in question has to be understood as the result of a given type of
causal process in which the patient is likened to the agent. Objects which were always hot to the same degree without
causal contact would be like one another, but would not be liken-nesses of one another. Here, as elsewhere, the
efficient cause is an important element in the essence of the coming into being of states or things.184 Since Aristotle
identifies the result of being acted on with the activity of being acted on,185 the resultant likeness (the result of being
acted on) is essentially the result of this type of causal process.
This model commits Aristotle, in the case of proper perception, to the following view: what is seen (let us say a red
object) induces in the perceiver a result which is a likeness of the red in the object. This result could not be the one it is
unless it was produced by the red of an object in this way. Had the patient always been in a state which resembled the
redness of objects, she would not be in that type of resultant state—even if (per impossibile) she had a visual experience
whose content exactly resembled the shade of red of the red object before her. Without the efficient causal connection
she would not be in a state which was (in the relevant respects) a likeness of that red.
The causal model is central to Aristotle's account of perceiving and thinking. Thus, he writes of proper perception:
the sense is what is receptive of the forms of sensible objects without the matter, just as the wax receives the design
of the signet ring without the iron or gold, and receives the gold or bronze design, but not as gold or bronze (Β.12,
424a17–21)
In this case, it is not just that the wax resembles the signet ring by bearing the same design. The crucial point is that the
wax is causally affected by the ring, and is, thus, made like the ring in certain relevant respects. This, no doubt, is why
Aristotle focuses here (and elsewhere)186 on the analogy with wax imprinted by a ring: for, an imprint is what it is
because it is imprinted by a ring. Further, an imprint is an imprint of the type it is because it is printed in by a ring of
this type. This is the way in which the patient is likened in relevant respects to the agent.
Both these points are general. The agent not only brings it about that
184 a
See, e.g. Meta. Ζ.17, 1041 29–32. The examples of thunder and eclipse in Post. An. Β.8 fall within this general pattern: they are essentially the product of a given type of
cause.
185 a
See Meta. Θ.8, 1050 21–3. For further discussion of this point, see my ‘Aristotle: Ontology and Moral Reasoning’ (OSAP 4 (1986), 135 ff.).
186 a
See De Mem. 1, 450 31 ff. where, talking of memory, Aristotle writes: ‘the stimulus produced [viz. perception] engraves a sort of impression of the percept, just like men
who make an impression with a seal’.
116 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
the patient is in a certain state, but also (if all goes well) determines the quality of that state. Thus, the teacher does not
just cause the learner to learn something. If successful, she determines what it is that the learner learns: i.e. what it is
that is ‘printed’ on to the learner's mind. Both flow, if all goes well, from her potentiality to teach.
Aristotle proceeds to apply this model to the case of perception of proper sensibles. He writes:
Similarly, the sense, in each case, is acted upon by what has colour, flavour, or sound, not in the way in which each
such thing is called what it is, but in so far as it has a given quality and in accordance with the relevant ratio/account
(logos). (Β.12, 424a21–5)
In perceiving red, the perceptual faculty is determined in relevant respects by the red in the object before it. It is not,
with regard to proper perception, determined by other aspects of the object, such as its being a pillar box or this pillar
box, etc. When perception occurs, the perceptual faculty is made like the relevant cause in that its state is made to be a
certain way by the relevant quality of the agent.
What exactly is the nature of the internal state that is brought about? Aristotle does not spell out what the relevant
account or ratio is in this passage (424a25). Elsewhere, he speaks of movements in the patient as being proportionate
to the agent (De Mem. 2, 452b12), when there are in the patient shapes and movements similar (homoia) in some way to
things outside. He also claims that in the case of perception there is something in the patient proportionate to the form
of the sensible object (452b16 f.), but does not develop an account of what the type of proportionality is, or of whether
the relata are psychological or physiological phenomena. The most that can safely be extracted from these passages is
the claim that the quality of the relevant perceptual faculty is determined by the external object in the manner, whatever
it is, which is appropriate for that faculty.187 This measure of qualitative similarity between agent and patient does not
commit Aristotle to any particular account of its nature (e.g. in exclusively representational or physiological terms).
Thus far, we have considered only the successful interactions in which (e.g.) the teacher actually teaches the student.
This approach corresponds to Aristotle's general practice of defining capacities in terms of how they are actualized in
optimal conditions: what a thing can do is defined by what it achieves when it is operating at its most successful. For
example, one's
187
There can, of course, be similarity relations between internal states produced in this way. Thus, for example, someone may remember a name somewhat like (paromoia ) the
one they seek (De Mem. 2, 452b 5–7), or when asleep one's images may resemble people when they are only like them (De Insom. 3, 461b 19 f., 23–6). In these cases, there is
similarity between two objects without the causal interaction between them which generates ‘liken-ness’.
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 117
capacity to lift weights is defined by the maximum one can lift and one's capacity to see is defined by the smallest
object one can see (as in eye testing) (cf. De Caelo Α.11, 281a15–26). There can be other cases of lifting or seeing, which
are incomplete or unsuccessful in certain ways.188
So far, I have discussed those aspects of Aristotle's account of perception which fall under claims (a), (c), and (d) in the
previous Section. These three components, taken together, yield the following picture:
(i) What makes a perception the one it is is the form which is cognitively discriminated.
and
(ii) What makes that discrimination the one it is is what causally produces it (in optimal conditions) in the favoured
way.
It is important to take both these elements together in this manner. If one focuses exclusively on (i), one is left with no
resources to account for what makes the discrimination the one it is. If one focuses only on (ii), one might overlook the
fact that it is the presence of these causal processes that constitutively determines what is discriminated.
One aspect of this account resembles Brentano's famous claim that Aristotle's notion of ‘taking on the Form without
the matter’ essentially involves the perceiver perceptually discriminating (and, thus, being aware of) an object.
However, my conclusion is based on considerations derived from the role of discrimination as defined by (a), (c), and
(d), which are fundamentally distinct from Brentano's. In particular, they do not rest on construing ‘taking on the
Form without the matter’ as being confined to awareness of an object.189 For all that has been said, it may also
essentially involve, in the case of perception, a change in the eye jelly as well as awareness of an object. The presence of
a physiological process is in no way excluded merely by reference to discrimination of an object. Indeed, in my view,
careful consideration of the analogy suggests that some physiological process is essentially involved in perceiving,
although this is not so in the analogous case of thinking.190 (Nor should this difference surprise us, since the two cases
are related by analogy and need not be the same in all relevant respects.) Although detailed consideration of these
issues would take us far away from our present concerns, it is important to note that
188 a a
In discussing processes in Phys. Γ.1–3, Aristotle introduces goal-directedness with capacities for change, and not with individual changes (cf. 202 21–6, 201 10 ff.). This
allows that individual processes may be incomplete or inadvertent in failing to reach a goal of the type at which the capacity is directed. On this, see my Aristotle's Philosophy of
Action, 24–5.
189
As Brentano claimed when he interpreted (e.g.) ‘taking on the Form without the matter’ in terms of ‘psychical indwelling’ or ‘mental inexistence’ (Psychology from an Empirical
Standpoint trans. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrel, and L. McAlister (London, 1973), 125 n. See also his Psychology of Aristotle, trans. R. George (Berkeley, 1977).)
190
On this issue, see Sect. 5.5 below.
118 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
acceptance of one aspect of Brentano's claim does not commit one to any radical anti-materialist conclusions.
If we look for a long time at one colour—e.g. white or green—any object to which we shift our gaze appears to be
of that colour. (De Insom. 2, 459b11–13)
191
For a clear statement of Brentano's problem, see H. Field ‘Mental Representation’, Erkenntnis 13 (1978) 9–61.
192
This is a consequence of Brentano's fundamental move in understanding Aristotle: to interpret ‘taking on the Form without the matter’ in terms of the scholastic notion of
‘objective’, the immanent object of perception or thought (Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, 210 n. 6, 229 n. 23).
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 119
In this chapter, Aristotle also gives examples of perceptual illusion involving common sensibles (e.g. movement, being
one). Thus, he writes:
The same persistence of vision occurs when we turn from moving objects—e.g. fast flowing rivers; for then objects
really at rest appear to be moving. (459b18–20)
So, when the fingers are meshed one object looks (or appears) to be two. (460b20 f.)
Aristotle's discussion of these cases is rich and intricate. He envisages cases where ‘not only will one thing look or
appear to be two, but the perceiver will also think that it is two’ (460b22–3). He contrasts these cases with examples in
which one object will look to be two, but the person will not think that this is so. So there are two types of (e.g.) visually
based error:
Stage 1:One object looks to be two.The sun/moon looks to be a foot across.
Stage 2:One object seems to be two.The sun/moon is taken to be a foot across.
Let us focus on Stage 1. At the end of de Insomniis 2, Aristotle concludes:
The cause of the deception (Stage 1) is that things look to us as they do not only when the object of sense moves
the sense organ, but also when the sense is moved by itself, provided that it is stimulated in the same way as by the
object of sense (460b23–5).
The idea seems to be this: for men in fever, marks on the wall look to be (e.g.) animals because the marks stimulate
their sense organs in the same way as they would be stimulated by animals of that kind. The marks on the wall may
only bear a slight resemblance to these animals. But the fever does the rest by bringing it about that the sense is
stimulated by them in just the way it would be if there were animals there (and everything was functioning properly).
But why then do the marks on the wall look to us (in fever) to be animals? On one view, this would be impossible. If
the content of the appearance-state was determined in every instance by its actual cause, what would appear to the men
in fever would be the actual cause (i.e. the marks on the wall). For, these are the actual cause of their ‘looking-state’.
But if these lines look to be animals, what determines the content of the illusion cannot be its actual cause.
In the cases described of veridical perception and illusion, the movements in the sense organ are of the same general
type. The lines look to the men in fever to be animals, because their sense organs are stimulated in the way in which
they would be stimulated if they were functioning well and they were seeing an animal. Aristotle does not say whether
the
120 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
relevant movements in the sense organ are to be understood as occurring at the phenomenal or the physiological level
(see, for the latter, De Insom. 3, 461a4 ff.). As interpreters we can remain neutral on these issues since in this context
they are not Aristotle's central concern. It is enough for his purposes if (a) the relevant movements are typed by what
occurs when all is functioning well, and (b) there are movements of this type when illusion occurs. He need go no
further than this in the present context.193 (In particular, he does not need to claim that there is a common ‘narrow-
content’ representational state present in cases of perception and illusion.194)
Aristotle adds a second point in discussing these cases:
perceptions persist even after the external perceptible object has gone (De Insom. 2, 460b2–4),
and
stimuli arise from perceptions . . . in cases which have their origin in the body. (460b30)
This suggests a further condition which applies at least in some cases: The lines look to be animals/Kleon provided
that (i) the sense organ is stimulated in the way it would be if an animal/Kleon was actually there and all was
functioning well, and (ii) it is so stimulated in part because it has been stimulated by an animal/Kleon in the past (when
all functioned well). It is not sufficient for the lines to look to be Kleon that one is in the state one would be in if one
saw Kleon when the perceptual faculty was functioning as it should be. One might equally be in a state of that type
when one saw Kleon's twin brother. One must also be in that state (in part) because of one's past (successful) seeings
of Kleon.195 Indeed, this is what makes the illusion an illusion of Kleon and not of his twin brother.
193
This structure can apply both to misperceiving what is white as green, and to errors in further states which are not directly perceptual but are the result of movements set up
by perception. Thus, Aristotle distinguishes (in De An. Γ.3, 428b 18–20 and 25–8) between false perception and false imagination produced by perception. Aristotle in this
context appears to separate cases of seeing and mis-seeing A, which involve immediate processes in the perceptual faculty, and imagining A when the object is not present to
the perceiver in the same direct way. The latter correspond to his official account of phantasia ; but he uses phainetai in describing both cases.
194
I leave it open (at this stage) whether Aristotle insisted on there being one common representational state of the relevant kind. Victor Caston has argued that he was
committed to this view, in ‘Why Aristotle Needs Imagination’ (Phronesis 41/1 (1996) 20 ff.) and ‘Aristotle and the Problem of Intentionality’ (Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, 58/2 (1998), 249 ff.). The issues are complex and require detailed analysis.
195
The second condition is important in cases of twins or lookalikes. What makes it the case that I imagine (or see) Cicero coming towards me, and not his twin brother (whom
I have not met), is that it is my seeing Cicero, and not his twin, in the past that is causally responsible for my present state. This would remain the case even if I had met both
of them, provided that it was my seeing Cicero, and not his twin, that was causally responsible for my present perceptual state. This condition is relevant to the issues Caston
discusses in ‘Aristotle and the Problem of Intentionality’, 287 ff.
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 121
When is the organ functioning as it should? Is it failing to do so when the sun looks to be a foot across? Is not this just
how the sun should look from this distance? Aristotle seems to reason as follows in this case: The sense organs can
only be functioning properly when objects look to be the size they actually are.196 Thus, when the sun looks to be a foot
across, the sense organ cannot be functioning as it should because the object in question is not the size it appears to be.
Conversely, it is functioning well with regard to nearby objects which are a foot across (e.g. feet); for, it presents them
as being the size they actually are.197
However, the notion of accurate information is not, by itself, sufficient to capture Aristotle's account of the proper
functioning of sense organs. If this was all that was involved, a perceiver could equally well see (when their sense
organs function properly) red or a given mixture of white and black light (as in Aristotle's account of derived colours in
De Sensu 3, 439b19 ff.). But proper perception is of red or of green, and not of some appropriate mix of basic colours.
Why is this so? Aristotle adds a further feature to his account of proper functioning which accommodates this
difficulty. In (e.g.) visual perception, the nature of the sense organ involves transparent water in the eye jelly (De An.Γ.1,
425a4 ff.), since it is this which the relevant colour affects (De An. Β.7, 418a29-b1). The proper objects of perception are
constrained in part by the physiological substratum involved in the relevant capacity; for, this limits the content of the
relevant discrimination (in some way) to one which concerns red rather than a theory-based mix of basic colours, since
the latter cannot arise from this physical change in the transparent alone. Aristotle is concerned to
196
This teleological account explains primarily why animal sense organs function as they do in general, and only derivatively (if at all) why on occasion we humans make the
specific and distinctive discriminations that we do (e.g. between blue and green). At the level of perception an animal (e.g. a frog) would see yellow moving objects (as such)
rather than (e.g.) flies or sources of carbohydrate, even though it needs to eat flies or sources of carbohydrate to survive. Survival needs determine that we have the type of
sense organs we do (in Aristotle's account), but do not make it the case that specific animals perceptively discriminate those objects which they need for survival as such (e.g.
as potatoes, rather than as small, brown, round objects). Indeed, if the frog can survive in its actual situation by discriminating black, buzzing objects, why attribute to it
discrimination of flies? This is one of the points at which Aristotle's account differs from the version of teleological theory proposed by Ruth Millikan (Language, Thought and
Other Biological Categories (Cambridge, Mass., 1984) ). In her view, because the frog needs to eat flies to survive, the frog's visual system discriminates flies (as such), rather
than (e.g.) black buzzing dots. In this respect, Aristotle's view of the physiology involved constrains the content of perception more rigorously than Millikan's does but at the
same time allows for cross-species perceptions of the same objects.
197
This account accommodates several of Aristotle's examples in these chapters. Thus, one finger may appear to be two as the sense organ is stimulated in the way in which it
would be stimulated (when the sense organ is functioning properly) by two objects. Further, in such a case, the past experience of correct functioning may be alive, and
causally active, in the present awareness. A similar account will apply to Aristotle's examples of objects at rest appearing to move (459b 19–21), and of mistakes in colour
perception.
122 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
emphasize the constraining role of the basic physical elements in his account of the proper objects of perception (De
An. Γ.1, 425a8 ff.):
So we are left to suppose that there is no sense organ apart from water and air.
The key notion to successful functioning (in Aristotle's account) is the registering of accurate information by senses
designed to be responsive to the medium in which animals move.198199
For the reasons given above, Aristotle's account of perception is not a simple, efficient, causal one. Since it essentially
involves some teleological elements, it allows him to classify perceptual experiences in terms of their causes when (in the
ways explained) all is functioning well. In this way, one can misperceive red objects as green, when one receives the form
of green without its matter in cases of perceptual illusion. Thus, the causal element can (pace Brentano) remain
constitutive of perceptual content, even in cases of misperception or illusion. On this view, Aristotle can (as Brentano
insisted) allow that in cases of illusion the perceiver receives the form without the matter, but still take the likening
element to be constitutive of the relevant content. For, the states are individuated by what produces the relevant effect
if all is functioning well.
It will be objected that Aristotle on occasion appears to rule out the possibility of error concerning the special
sensibles. Thus, Aristotle claims:
(1) with proper objects, error is impossible (De An. Β.6, 418a12–14),
and that:
(2) sight cannot be deceived be as to the fact of colour, but (e.g.) as to what the coloured object is and where it is.
198
Aristotle speaks of perception as common to all animals (De An. Γ.3, 427b 8), and treats it across species (e.g. in De An. Γ.13, 435b 18–21) for all animals that share the
same medium. Hence, what perception discriminates (e.g. moving, black dots) will be the same (in this account) for frogs (who want to eat them), flies (who want to mate
with them), and humans (who, e.g., want to drive them out of the kitchen). In this respect, different ‘consumer’ needs in different animals do not distinguish different objects
of perception. At this point also Aristotle's account differs sharply from Ruth Millikan's with regard to the content of perception.
199
Aristotle adds to his basic account a teleological explanation of why we have sense organs of the type we do. We have vision as animals which need to move to survive, since
it allows us to see objects at a distance (Γ.12, 434b 26–8). But this requires us to see objects through a medium, which is transparent, since we live in air or water (Γ.12, 434b
b
28–30, Γ.13, 435 21–4). This teleological role explains why we have sense organs which register effects in the transparent and nothing more; for, our basic sense organs are
designed to register these changes (and nothing else). This is why our sense organs are functioning correctly when we visually discriminate red rather than a given spectral
mix of colours: for, they were not built to be responsive to the latter type of theoretical ratio. In this case we discriminate red as red. When we make accurate discriminations
with our sense organs, we are naturally well placed to survive and flourish.
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 123
200
It should be noted that (1) and (2) claim only that vision is always correct with regard to colour (as Aristotle notes in 418a14 (see also De Sensu 4, 442b8)). This need mean no
more than that there can be no mistake about the fact that the visual faculty grasps some colour. If so, Aristotle's claim of inerrancy need come to no more than this:The
visual system cannot be mistaken as to whether there is some colour which it discriminates (since it can only operate if some colour affects it).This claim does not require
that the visual system is infallible about which colour it discriminates, as it allows that it may be mistaken about which colour is before it, and thus take a pale object as green
(see Γ.3, 428b21).
201
(b) is required to mark the contrast with the case of complex seeing which can on occasion be false. (a) might be challenged as follows: ‘Why not take “a proper object” to
a
mean (e.g.) colour, and not some specific colour (in line with the interpretation offered of 418 12–14 above)?’ The reply is twofold: first, if this was what was intended, the
b
reference to ‘pale’ would be misleading in 430 30, since there could (it might appear) be error about the pale even in a non-complex judgement. (If Aristotle does not
compare seeing the pale with seeing that the pale is a man, he is not comparing like with like.) Second, in this context, the analogy drawn is that between seeing and thinking
of a specific definition or the essence of a particular object (430b 26–8, b15–17). If so, the former must also be seeing a specific object.
124 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
If (P) is Aristotle's claim, he can assert (without inconsistency) in the same passage (428b18–28) that error is possible
with regard to special sensibles, and that a special sense, in the presence of its object, etc., is always correct.
In these ways Aristotle can allow for a limited form of inerrancy in special perception within the framework of a
general account of perception which is built on efficient and teleological elements. When the special senses are
functioning well, we receive accurate information registered by senses of a type designed to work well in the medium in
which we live. There may indeed be perceptual errors whose content is determined by the likening materials outlined
above. Thus, pace Brentano, the likening account can be constitutive of the content of perceptual states, where
perceptual form is received without matter.
202
Why is proper perception the basic case? Aristotle writes that this is so because ‘those per se perceptibles which are special to each sense are most strictly perceptible in that it
is to these that the special nature of the several senses is directed’ (418a 25–6). His thought appears to be that the distinctive nature of each sense is directed towards its
special sensibles, while, since there is no distinctive sense targetted at common sensibles, the senses, with their own distinctive essences, have to work together (cf. De An.
Γ.1, 425a 31–2). Thus understood, common sensibles are only perceived by an individual sense when it works together with other senses. This perception is secondary
(according to Aristotle) because one needs to understand the individual senses with their distinctive essences before one can understand how such senses cooperate in
recognizing where special sensibles co-occur (425a 22–4).
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 125
where one object is immediately grasped as such in perception. For, in such a case the relevant perceptual discrimination
will be of one object provided that it is brought about, in favourable conditions, by one object. Similarly, perception
would be of this one yellow, bitter object (425b1–3) provided that it was brought about, in appropriate conditions, by
this one object. Causal assimilation to one cross-modal moving object explains why perception is of one such object
rather than of (e.g.) one visual object and one tactile object (in which case further inference would be required to reach
the discrimination of one cross-modal object). What is common to special and common perception is that both
involve the per se efficient causal impact of objective features on the discriminator, as captured by the causal likening
model. Accidental perception, by contrast, does not involve this type of causal likening.
Aristotle's discussion of common sensibles in De Anima Γ.1 suggests that he is thinking of them in the way suggested
by the causal model. He argues that there can be no special sense for common sensibles from the following premisses
(425a16–24):
P(1) We perceive all the common sensibles (movement, rest, shape, size, number, oneness) ‘by movement’
(425a17–18),
P(2) We can perceive these (or at least number) by the special senses (425a19 f.); for, each sense perceives one
object.203
From these premisses Aristotle concludes that there can be no special sense for, common sensibles; for, if there were
we would perceive them as we now perceive what is sweet by sight. The latter occurs when we perceive both (e.g. the
pale, the sweet) separately and—as a further step—cognize that they co-occur (425a22–7).204 We have no access via
sight to the sweetness of the object, but rather conjoin two perceptual experiences and infer that, since the pale is
sweet, we see the sweet. By contrast, in the case of common sensibles no further inferential step of this type is
required. We
203 b
Each of the five senses senses a unity: one colour, one sound, etc. An instantaneous single act of perception implies one object (De Sensu 7, 447 21 ff.), the type of oneness
a
mentioned in 425 17.
204
Error is more common with regard to common sensibles than special sensibles because, in the former case, there are additional sources of error over and above what is
involved in discriminating (e.g.) white. In particular, the judgement about which object is white allows for misidentification of two qualitatively similar particulars. Thus, there
is a type of error present in the second case that is absent from the first. Aristotle further separates this type of misidentification from errors concerning other common
sensibles, such as size and movement, which belong to (but do not constitute the identity of) the substances to which the proper sensibles belong (Γ.3, 428b 27 ff.). In the
latter cases Aristotle says that error is even more frequent, presumably because there is a still greater variety of possible sources of mistake (over and above misidentification
of the individual involved).
126 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
can have direct access to one white object P(2), since its oneness impacts on the special senses.205
If this is correct, the common sensibles will causally impact on the senses in a manner somewhat similar to that
achieved by the special sensibles. But common sensibles themselves differ from special sensibles in that their causal
impact is not unique to one sense, but can be shared by several. This is why Aristotle includes among common
sensibles one object, and not one (e.g.) visually perceived object.206 Thus, the senses can operate together in
immediately perceiving one bitter and yellow object (Γ.1, 425a31 ff.), without any inferential step (beyond what is given
in perception) identifying the visual with the tasted object.207 In the case of any individual sense organ, common and
special sensibles are per se causes of its processes or quality changes. Since the former category includes
205
This account (with its emphasis on causal impact) gives a role to ‘by movement’ which separates the case of the common sensibles perceived from those where ‘we perceive
a
what is sweet by sight’ (425 22–3), and, thus, provides an answer to those who thought (like R. D. Hicks, Aristotle: de Anima (Cambridge, 1907), 428) that it had no role
(thus understood). Hicks's alternative suggestion is to construe ‘by movement’ to mean ‘our perception of all other common sensibles depends on our perception of
movement’. But this is wholly perplexing: magnitudes and shapes may be perceived equally whether or not they are moving; number and unity are recognized by (e.g.) break
a
in continuity, and Aristotle makes no attempt to show how our perception of continuity rests on our perception of movement. In Phys. Δ.11, 219 12 ff., magnitude, time,
and movement are all instances of the continuous. Had this been the basis of Aristotle's thought, he should have claimed that we perceive movement and magnitude by the
continuous, and not continuity by movement.
206
That the object seen is cross-modal (open to several sensory modalities) is highly significant in Aristotle's account. Had the effect of one or three moving red objects on the
visual system (in his theory) been that (e.g.) the eye jelly was reddened in a distinctive way for one or three moving objects, he would have had to show (a) that what was seen
was one moving object rather than one visually appearing (modality-specific) quasi-object, (b) that this effect on vision paralleled in some undisclosed physiological way a
comparable effect on the senses of touch and hearing, and (c) that the perceiver could grasp ‘straight off ’ (without inference or reflection) that these effects were effects of
the same object. That Aristotle makes no attempt to discharge these obligations suggests that he is not understanding perception of common sensibles on precisely the same
model as perception of white, etc. Rather, in both, taking on the form involves discrimination of one, white, object.
207
This formulation is intended to be neutral as regards the question of whether there could be (satisfactory) perception of common sensibles if we had only one sense (e.g.
vision). In fact, Aristotle suggests that in such a case we would be less aware of the common sensibles (such as size) and all sensibles would seem to be of the same type (i.e.
visibles), since we would never encounter a case of an object which had size but no colour (Γ.1, 425b 6–9). This is presumably because in such a case we would lack our
perception of size and merely perceive coloured-sizes. Similarly, we would not perceive one object but one coloured-object, and, thus, lack the perceptions we currently enjoy
of one object (which we may or may not experience as coloured). As it is, we perceive each of the common sensibles (one, moving, three-dimensional object) as distinct
from coloured-one, coloured-size, coloured-shape, etc. Thus, it appears that (in Aristotle's view) for us to have satisfactory perception of common sensibles it is essential
that we have several distinct senses which operate together. When individual senses perceive one object, they do so only as a part of a unified sense faculty.
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 127
shape and size, the objects grasped by the senses in this direct way at the outset are three-dimensional objects with
their own weight and volume. In Aristotle's account, perceivers do not begin with (e.g.) purely visual, two and a half-
dimensional objects without full spatial size or weight, and then construct three-dimensional spatial objects out of
these more elementary beginnings. Rather, they are immediately given cross-modal, three-dimensional objects typically
grasped by the senses working in co-operation.208
It will be objected that the cases of common and special perception are more radically distinct than has so far been
allowed. Perception of common sensibles appears not to involve any physiological process (e.g. the eye jelly reddening)
of the type found in the case of special sensibles. Indeed, it might appear that there could be no one physiological
process of this distinctive type since the impact of common sensibles is shared by distinct sense faculties. If so, some
will conclude that the causal assimilation cannot apply to the case of common perception.
This objection is correct in one important respect. Aristotle does not spell out the type of quality change which results
from common sensibles, or the route by which it is brought about. However, he makes it clear that he thinks that in
this case what occurs must essentially involve receiving the relevant form (without the matter) of the one moving
object perceived. For, when he talks of perceptually receiving the form of a stone (Γ.8, 431b19), he must be referring to
a quality change but not one of the type involved in ‘being-reddened’ or ‘being-hardened’ by external objects. So, he
has to extend the notion of perceptually receiving the form, itself a quality change, beyond the range of the special
sensibles. Indeed, this is required if he is to apply his favoured formula of taking on ‘the Form without the matter’ to
the perception of particulars (as he wishes to do (see Β.5, 417b22 ff.)).
Consideration of the case of common sensibles shows the range of the causal-likening model. It need not be confined
to the type of physiologically based account offered for special perception.209 Indeed, it can be applied even in cases
where no physiological account of this type is offered. In the case of perception of common sensibles, several sense
organs can
208
This point is of major importance in understanding the distinctive nature of Aristotle's epistemological starting point. Unlike (e.g.) Kant, for whom the starting point is
‘inner sense’ with its not fully spatial (two and a half-dimensional) objects, Aristotle begins with fully spatial (three-dimensional) objects at the outset. Hence, his project is not
to ‘construct’ fully spatial objects from those in inner sense, or to argue that inner sense presupposes three-dimensional external objects. His starting point is a radically non-
Cartesian awareness of three-dimensional fully spatial objects.
209
For a contrasting view, see Stephen Everson's discussion of these issues in Aristotle on Perception (Oxford, 1997), 148–57. It is difficult to see how Everson can explain the
fact that Aristotle's visual perceiver sees a square object (which is red) rather than a square-red object.
128 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
together receive the relevant form of one moving object, when they discriminate one such object (in favoured cases)
under the causal influence of one continuous moving object.210 The goal of the senses operating in unison is knowledge
of the movement, size, and number of the fully spatial objects we encounter (Γ.1, 425b4 f.). When all is functioning
well, we will discriminate one moving object as one moving object.211
What is common to the account of special and common perception is the use of the idea of causal likening to explain
our discrimination of their respective objects. In this way, we can perceptually discriminate one moving object in a way
which parallels that in which we perceptually discriminate white or red. But this point of similarity allows for
considerable differences between the ways in which the likening occurs. While both may involve physiological changes
in the subject, the point of similarity does not consist in there being physiological changes of the same type. The type
of changes may vary considerably, provided that, in both, the subject discriminates the relevant objects in an
appropriate way. It appears to be this latter feature that makes both cases ones where one ‘takes on the Form without
the matter’. If so, the discussion of common sensibles supports the
210
Aristotle, in his discussion of common sensibles, regards them as per se causes of perception along with special sensibles, in contrast with accidental sensibles. Hence, he
must have believed that they, unlike accidental sensibles, make a distinctive (efficient) causal impact on the perceptual faculty. If so, the perceptual faculty has to be such as to
be responsive both to colour and sound (each via an individual faculty) and to one, shaped, moving, object (as an integrated sense faculty). (See n. 30.) Thus, there must be
a distinctive impact of one such object on the integrated sense faculty, which cannot be fully understood in terms of its impact via any one medium (e.g. light) on any one
sense (e.g. vision). The impact rather is one which can only be understood in terms of the interconnected activities of the distinct faculties working in unison. Aristotle does
not attempt to articulate in what this integrated perceptual process (kinesis (Γ.1, 425a 17)) consists. His claim is only that the perceptual faculty as a whole is responsive to
the impact of the oneness, size, or motion of an object, but not to accidental sensibles (e.g. being the son of Kleon), presumably because it is not designed to be causally
affected directly (as a perceptual system) by facts about parentage.
211
In this case, we will discriminate the object of our perception as an external object because we take what appears to us as of something else. Aristotle compares this with
seeing a picture as a portrait of someone (De Mem. 1, 450b 30 f.), and distinguishes it from seeing a picture in its own right (and not as a portrait of someone). In both cases,
the picture would be a picture of Koriskos, provided that it is caused in the right way. But what would make it true that we saw it as a portrait of Koriskos is that we viewed
it successfully with the goal of finding out about real, three-dimensional objects in the external world (and, thus, were interested in (e.g.) the causal history of the picture,
etc.). If it is not seen as a portrait, what fixes what is seen is the causal history of the picture (who it is of). When it is seen as a portrait, we need to add our interest in finding
out about the external world (via the painting) to the basic causal story. Since, for Aristotle, both these cases are examples of imagination, it cannot be correct to view
imagination as a general faculty of seeing as (as Martha Nussbaum suggested in her essay on ‘The Role of Phantasia in Aristotle's Explanations of Action’, in Aristotle's de
Motu Animalium (Princeton, 1978), 221–69). For, only the second case involves seeing the picture as a portrait, while the first does not. Further, recognition of proper and
common sensibles involves ‘seeing as’ but no imagination.
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 129
line of interpretation of ‘taking on the Form without the matter’ given above (Section 5.3ad fin.).
(d) In perception, Aristotle took proper and common sensibles to be per se causes of perception. What range of
objects is thinkable, and can they all be accommodated within one uniform account of thinking? In Γ.4 and Γ.5
Aristotle focuses on thoughts of universals (water, flesh, straight line, straightness), and does not discuss
thoughts of particulars. I shall follow his example.212 In Γ.6 he distinguishes between simple thoughts and
complex ones in ways which parallel his discussion of proper sensibles.
To consider these issues in this way is to follow the route suggested by Aristotle's analogy between perception and
thought. His discussion raises many issues, pertaining to topics as diverse as theology and materialism, which lie
outside our immediate area of concern. I shall attempt to focus (as far as is possible) solely on the issue of the content
of thought: what makes a thought the thought it is.
There is one kind of intellect, which is such as to become all things. And there is intellect of another kind, such as to
make all things. This is a type of positive state like light; for, in a way light makes potential colours actual.
(430a14–17)
What are these roles? Are they consistent? It appears that in (1) the intellect is compared with the objects perceived, but
in (2) it is compared not with the objects but with the medium (between those objects and the perceiver). How can one
thing be compared with both? For, the objects perceived and the light in which they are active are distinct.
Let us take each claim separately. (1) encourages the following line of thought: the reason why Aristotle can substitute
the active intellect and
212 b b
Elsewhere Aristotle allows for thought of individuals, such as Kleon (De An. Γ.6 430 5–6), and knowledge of particulars (Β.5, 417 26–8). These cases seem relatively
unproblematic given the analogy with perception: what makes my thought a thought of Kleon is that Kleon causally affects my thinking faculty in the appropriate way. And
this will be so if it gives me relevant knowledge of individuals in (e.g.) knowledge of who that person is. (Aristotle, however, does not specify the goal of the thinking faculty
with regard to individuals in these passages, and so offers no suggestions as to what ‘knowing who’ involves.)
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 131
objects of thought in this way is that they are strictly identical.213 Indeed, Aristotle says as much:
The knowing activity (sc. of the active intellect) is identical with its object. (Γ.5, 430a19 f.)
The active intellect just is identical with the set of its objects, the organized and intelligible world. From this
perspective, Aristotle's introduction of the active intellect as the efficient cause (like skill) of the operation of the
passive mind becomes readily comprehensible (430a11–15).214 For, since it is (when fully active) identical with its
objects, both it and its objects can equally be described as the cause of the passive mind's operation. So, while one
might have expected Aristotle to speak of the objects of thought as the efficient cause of passive thought (on the basis
of the analogy with perception) he can substitute active intellect for objects of thought in this role without
inconsistency.
How is the identity of the active intellect and the objects of thought to be interpreted? What is the significance of the
analogy between the active intellect and light in its role in colour perception? This analogy, central to Aristotle's
discussion of De Anima, must be considered in some detail.
For Aristotle, light is the activity of the transparent as such (418b10, 419a10). It is an aspect of the essence of colour (in
De Anima) to produce change in the actually transparent (419a10–12), a change of a given kind in the quality of the
light. While the eye itself contains transparent elements, colour is not defined in De Anima Β.7 by reference to the
perceiver, but rather in terms of an ability to produce change in the transparent. Light makes potential colours such as
green actual by itself (as the positive state of the transparent) being active in a given way (a way distinct from that in
which it is active when black or red, etc.). When light is active in this way and impacts on S's perceptual faculty, which
is functioning as it should, S perceives green.215
In De Anima Β.7, the picture looks like this:
ability of the object to change the change in the transparent when perception
transparent active (‘the activity of colour’)
213
I am indebted to Michael Frede for many discussions of issues concerning the active intellect. Through these I came to see that the (strong) identity of active intellect and the
object of thought (which Frede advocates in ‘La theorie aristotelicienne de l'intellect agent’, in Dherbey (ed.), Corps et Ame, 377–90) is ‘of a piece’ both with Aristotle's colour
analogy and with his Analytics -based co-determination thesis (as I understood them). For detailed discussion of the latter, see 10.5 below.
214 b
Skill is taken as a paradigm case of an efficient cause in Phys. Β.3, 195 23–5.
215
Light itself is not a quality change (alloiōsis ), but a state (hexis ). Yet it is a state which can be affected in given ways by given objects, as (e.g.) virtue is a state which is well
disposed to proper objects (Η.3, 246a 10–12, 246b 18–20).
132 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
Aristotle says little about the nature of the activity of colour in De Anima, and nothing further about the nature of the
relevant ability.216 The discussion in De Anima is (at least) consistent with the view that an object is able to move the
transparent because of a mixture of basic colours at its periphery. Elsewhere he notes that the activity of colour fills the
medium between the object and the eye, and does so instantaneously (De Sensu 447a9–11). It is this changed state of the
transparent which affects the eye in a distinctive way. But while Aristotle insists that the activity of colour is not an
effluence of bodies (particles), he offers little, if any, positive characterization of its qualities. We have to look elsewhere
for clues as to how he thought of light.
Aristotle treats sound and colour as analogous, and claims that the activity of sound occurs in the medium (Β.8,
419b6–10) between the object and the hearing. Hence, this sound needs to be distinguished from the ‘sounding’ (Γ.2,
426a7–8) which occurs in the sentient subject, when the air inside the ear is affected by the sound which enters it (Β.8,
420a10–14). For, the latter continues in existence only for as long as the hearing occurs (Γ.2, 426a15–18), while the
original sound will have a different duration.217 Similarly, colour (i.e. the colour-relevant activity of light) occurs in the
medium, but ‘colouring’ (i.e. what goes on in the eye when perception takes place) occurs in the sentient subject and
lasts only as long as she sees the colour (426a15–16).
This distinction between sound (or colour) in the medium and sounding (or colouring) in the sentient subject allows
Aristotle to conclude that the early physiologists were mistaken in thinking that (e.g.) colours could not exist without
perceivers (426a21 f.), but correct to assert that the operation of the sensible (as such) could not exist without a
perceiver. For this latter activity (viz. the colouring of the type which endures as long as seeing does) requires a
perceiver (426a21–6). Indeed, this is why Aristotle can distinguish between what it is to be a colour and what it is to be
seen (Meta. Κ.9, 1065b31–3); for, the latter involves colour affecting the percipient, while the former is its activity qua
colour (in the medium, without essentially affecting anything else).218
What occurs in the medium? Sounds are (in Aristotle's view) produced
216 b
In De Sensu 3, there are attempts at a more positive characterization of particular colours (e.g. white, black (439 15–18)). The situation is made more complicated by
Aristotle's further claim that the eye itself involves the transparent. (See below.)
217 b a
Hearing can either be hearing sounds or hearing both noise and silence (De An. Β.9, 421 4–6, cf. 422 22–4). So, in one mode hearing is the active exercise of one's
auditory capacities, even if no sound is heard (i.e. listening out for), while in another it is hearing a sound which lasts as long as the sounding does. Both of these are activities
b
of the relevant capacities, and as such must be distinct from the mere capacity to hear which is possessed by objects which can hear, but are not hearing at present (Γ.2, 425
28–30).
218
On this issue, I agree with Justin Broackes's discussion of colour in ‘Aristotle, Objectivity and Perception’, OSAP 17 (1999), 61, and with his able (and to my mind
decisive) criticisms of certain aspects of Sarah Broadie's earlier article ‘Aristotle's Perceptual Realism’ (Ancient Minds: Southern Journal of Philosophy 31, suppl. (1993), 137–59.)
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 133
by something striking against something else, and occur in their own medium (analogous to light (419b29–30)). Thus, it
is not stricken air which approaches the ear, but rather air which in some way carries sound because of its distinctive
sound-conducting capacity (what earlier commentators described as ‘to deiches’). In the parallel case, water carries sound
without air travelling through it, and without making actual waves. Further, Aristotle cannot have thought that echoes
literally involve bouncing masses of air (as both Alexander and Philoponus rightly insisted in commenting on
419b25–7).219 Rather, in this case successive bits of air between the source and the wall are shaped into a unified mass
until the air adjoining the wall transfers the sound to the wall, which in turn starts the process up again in a changed
direction. Thus, sound is a distinctive activity of the air which realizes its sound-conducting capacity, and it is this
activity which is reflected when sound affects smooth or concave surfaces (419b28). If the analogy is sustained, colour
should be an activity of the same general kind in air or water which realizes their capacity qua transparent. What occurs
in the case of colour is a continuous instantaneous activity which pervades the whole medium between source and
observer. It is because of this activity in the medium that colours are known by us. Further, this activity (like that of
sound) is not a wave of a bodily type.220
Many of the details of this account are obscure. However, Aristotle has done enough to present an outline of his
intended analogy between perception and thought. The active intellect is presented as the analogue of light, which,
when active in given ways, is the efficient cause of the perceiver's perception of red. If so, the analogy will run as
follows:
ability of the object to ‘modify’ the activity of the universal in the active thoughts of object or universal (in
active intellect intellect the passive intellect)
In the case of objects containing matter (Γ.4, 430a5–8),221 the relevant universals will exist actually only when there is an
appropriate activity in the active intellect. It is in virtue of this activity that the universals are known by us. Both colours
and universals exist independently of us in media of distinctive types, which causally impact on us and assimilate our
relevant
219
Philoponus, commenting on De An. in Analytica Posteriora, ed. M. Wallies (Berlin, 1909), p. 340, 32 f.; p. 360, 19 ff. (where he cites Alexander with approval). Philoponus
appears to think of echoes as involving the activity of sound itself being reflected. Thus, it is not only that sound involves a continuous propagation of a state which pervades
the whole medium between source and observer, but also that its activity can be redirected when it hits a wall. This Aristotelian doctrine is implicit in his own discussion of
b
echoes (De An. Β, 419 25 ff.), and his analogy with light's reflection. As Sambursky notes in ‘Philoponus' Interpretation of Aristotle's Theory of Light’, Osiris 13 (1958),
121–3, this doctrine still falls short of the Stoic innovation of sound waves of corporeal entities.
220
For a contrasting view, see Myles Burnyeat's paper ‘Aristote voit du rouge et entend un “do”: combien se passe-t-il de choses? Remarques sur De Anima, 2, 7–8’, in G. R.
Dherbey (ed.), Corps et Ame (Paris, 1996), 149–67.
221
Cases not involving matter (430a 3–5) are discussed in the penultimate section.
134 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
faculties to themselves.222 In both cases, the faculties have as their goal receiving their appropriate objects in this way,
and function correctly when they do so.
Light makes all colours actual by being affected in certain ways appropriate to its nature (Γ.5, hexis (430a15)). How does
the light of the active intellect make all universals actual by itself being appropriately affected? Aristotle's use of light
resembles (as has been frequently noted) the Platonic analogy of the sun in the Republic, which represents the role of
the form of the good. This makes each relevant object what it is (Rep. Η, 508aff.) in virtue of the latter's being located
in its own niche in an organized and intelligible world. If the analogy is sustained, what it is for a universal to be active
will be for it to occupy a given niche in an organized and intelligible order. The active intellect, so understood, will be
the organized structure in which each of the relevant universals is active. As an intellect, it is the appropriate locus, the
‘place for such forms’ (Γ.4, 429a27 f.).223 However, unlike Plato's sun, the active intellect is not itself a distinct object. By
analogy with light, its role is as the abiding and structured space in which distinct universals themselves are active.224
If this is correct, our minds (passive intellects) will function properly when they receive objects intelligibly organized in
a coherent structure of this type.225 What the passive mind receives will be forms of kinds located
222
For a somewhat contrasting view of this aspect of the analogy, see Michael Frede's ‘La theorie aristotelicienne de l'intellect agent’, 382–3.
223
This account takes the reference to light as to what is affected in given ways, and not to what can be affected in given ways. If it were the latter, the identification between
nous and noeta would come under strain. For, noeta cannot be identified with the medium in which they are active.
224 a
Aristotle immediately notes a disanalogy between light and the active intellect. The active intellect is essentially in activity, and as such has no potentiality (Γ.5, 430 17–18). If
it had possessed a potentiality, its actualization would require explanation. Since it lacks a potentiality, it is always in activity and is unmixed and separate. Thus, it differs from
a a
light, which is itself the actualization of a capacity. As Aristotle remarks, the activity of the intellect has no intermittence (430 22), and in itself is immortal and eternal (430
23).
225
Aristotle tackles related issues in the central books of the Metaphysics. It is sometimes held that there universals have only potential existence outside the mind, and only exist
actually in the mind (e.g. G. Hughes, ‘Universals as Potential Substances’ in M. Burnyeat (ed.), Notes on Book Zeta of Aristotle's Metaphysics (Oxford, 1979), 107–26 and J. Lear,
Aristotle: The Desire to Understand (Cambridge, 1988), 292). The colour analogy is consistent with these claims provided that one understands ‘universals' existing actually in
the mind’ to mean that they exist only in God's mind/the active intellect. Thus understood, the universal doghood may exist only potentially in actual dogs. For it to exist
actually the relevant universal needs not only to be instantiated in such dogs but also to fall within an intelligible order of other universals which are related in law-like ways.
If, per impossibile, there were dogs but no such organized world order, doghood would only exist potentially. (This would be the analogue of potential colours without any
light.) Particular animals may, of course, come to instantiate doghood as they develop into maturity from the foetus stage. But this means that they come to have the
potential to affect the divine mind in the way which exemplifies doghood. (This would be the analogue of things coming to have the potential to affect the light in a way
which exemplifies redness—e.g. by being painted!)
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 135
in an organized and intelligible world. If so, it will achieve its goal when we think of such objects and kinds as
occupying their appropriate place in an objective world order. Further, such objects and kinds will only be known to us
because they occupy a place in that order. As in the case of perception, the content of our passive thought will be
determined by the causal elements which produce the relevant thoughts (when the thinking faculty is functioning as it
should).226
While these aspects of the analogy seem relatively clear, others remain obscure. While it is part of the nature of the red
colour to move the light in a given way, there may be more to its nature than this. It is true that when one sees an
object as red, one sees it as such in virtue of its disposition (now realized) to affect the medium in a given way. But this
truth in no way rules out the possibility that the object has some further property (e.g.) of being red (as Aristotle
suggests in De Sensu in his theory of colour mixture and degrees of transparency (439b8–10, 439b20–440b23)). Equally,
while it may be part of the nature of a universal to move the active intellect in a given way; it does not follow that its
nature consists solely in this ability. When one thinks of an object as F, one thinks of it as such in virtue of its ability
(now realized) to fit into an organized and intelligible world order in a given way. Its playing the latter role may also
depend on the object's having a given form which does (in fact) affect the medium in the way specified. But it need
not. Perhaps to be F is just to fit in a given way into an organized and intelligible world. These ontological issues are
left unresolved in De Anima, where Aristotle aims to uncover just enough structure to account for the relation between
thought and its objects. We shall return to these ontological questions in Part II.
226
Since this is the role of the passive intellect, it must itself be capable of organizing objects in the appropriate way, and in this (at least) correspond to the active intellect itself.
This is why our intellect is said to be like the independent active intellect (NE Κ.7, 1177a 15–17) or even identical with it.
227 b
Aristotle sometimes speaks of intellect as, like knowledge, always correct (Post. An. Β.19, 100 6–8), and in De Anima notes that ‘thinking of indivisibles’ is never false (De
An. Γ.6, 430a 26–7). The first usage must refer only to successful cases of thought, and not to all cases of thinking. The latter is more problematic, but must refer to a
special doctrine of Aristotle's concerning indivisible concepts and not to his view of thinking in general.
136 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
distinction between thoughts of simples and of complexes (involving predication). Of the former, Aristotle writes:
Thought is not always something true or false. When thought is of what something is with respect to its essence and
there is no predication it is true. (Γ.6, 430b26–8)
This parallels Aristotle's discussion of the objects of the proper senses (Γ.6, 430b28 ff.) which seems to require at least:
(P) If one is in proper visual contact with a special sensible, no error is possible.
Proper visual contact requires the presence of the visible object as the immediate and controlling cause of the
perception. Since our special visual systems are set up so as to be directly sensitive to their proper objects, error will not
occur if all is functioning well. If the analogy holds, Aristotle should accept in the case of thought:
(P*) If one is in proper epistemic contact with (or genuinely thinks of) an indivisible object, no error is possible.
Here, since our noetic faculty is set up so as to be directly sensitive to its proper objects, error will not occur if all is
functioning well. Just as our special senses are such as to (e.g.) see the nature of colour, so our noetic faculty is such as
to grasp the natures of its proper objects.228 Further, since their objects are simple, the only alternative to proper
contact is ignorance, not error.229
It does not, however, follow from (P*) that if one believes one is thinking of an indivisible object (O), one actually is.
For, it is possible that one could be affected by a different simple object (Q) or by a complex object (R) in the way one
would be affected by O if the thinking faculty were
228
Neither (P) nor (P*) depends on the respective proper objects being defined as those which make this impact on us when all is functioning well. Rather, they are substantial
claims to the effect that our faculties have the capacity to be affected by their respective objects in this way.
229 b
Aristotle makes this clear in his discussion of grasp of incomposites in Meta. Θ.10, which are presumably to be identified with the simples mentioned in Ζ.17, 1041 9–11.
There, he writes that in these cases ‘falsity does not exist, nor error, only ignorance’(1052a 1–2). This is because here there is either being in touch with the incomposite or
failing to be in touch; the former is correct, the latter is ignorance (1052b 24–5). There is no room for error in the case of incomposites (including incomposite substances,
b
which are identical with their essences, and the essences of composite substances, but excluding composite substances) (see 1051 26–7). (Aristotle throws in his favoured
b
rider ‘except accidentally’ (1051 26); but it is difficult to see what this adds, since Aristotle's focus is on (inter alia ) absolute simples. Perhaps, by ‘except accidentally’ he
intends the following qualification: if error is possible concerning these matters it occurs in ways not linked to our grasping them as simples, but (e.g.) through our
misdescribing them in complex propositions or mislocating them in a genus tree (i.e. in some way which involves complexity imported by us).
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 137
functioning properly.230 Equally, it seems possible that one could be affected by a simple object in the way one would be
affected by a complex object if the thinking faculty were functioning properly. If the analogy with perception is
maintained, the thought in these cases would be of the object which would have set up an affection of this type had all
been functioning properly. However, while this would permit the possibility of error concerning simples in the thinking
faculty, Aristotle does not investigate this possibility in De Anima.231 In particular, he does not address in detail the
question of what makes two affections be of the same type. There is a further consequence of this account. If it is
correct, it does not follow that if one is (in fact) thinking of a simple object, one knows that one is. For, one need not
know that one's thinking faculty is indeed controlled in the appropriate way by an external object. How the thought is
brought about need not be transparent to the thinker. The way the thought is presented to the thinker may mask the
identity of the thought.
This point serves to illuminate one aspect of Aristotle's remarks about thought. He sometimes insists that ‘images’ or
‘phantasms’ are the means by which thoughts are presented to subjects. Thus, he writes:
Whenever one contemplates, one must at that moment contemplate with an image. (De An. Γ.8, 432a8–10)232
230
If the faculty is functioning correctly, thinking will be correct (Post. An. Β.19, 100b 6–8). Compare Aristotle's remarks on seeing (horan (De Insomniis 1, 459a 1–4)) as always
being true. In Meta. Θ.10, 1051b 31 f., Aristotle writes that for incomposites either one thinks them or one does not (error is not possible); but this does not mean that
whenever one believes one thinks of a simple one does do so. There is a limited disanalogy with the case of perceiving: thinking (of this type) conceptually requires success,
but perceiving (aisthesis ) does not. This is why the analogue of thinking is proper perceptual contact, not merely perceiving. For, ‘perceiving’ (for Aristotle) is akin to ‘being
affected in one's sense organs’, and this (unlike seeing or thinking) does not require success.
231
Aristotle writes:with regard to what is identical in species the mind thinks of it in an indivisible unit of time and by an indivisible mental act. It grasps these things accidentally
in this way, and not in so far as the latter (viz. what thinks and when) are divisible, but in so far as they are indivisible. For, there is present in the objects something
b
indivisible, although probably not separable, which makes the relevant time and the duration one. For, this applies for anything continuous. (Γ.6, 430 14–20)Aristotle holds
that in any case where we grasp a divisible unity of this type as one, our grasp of it is accidental (and not a full grasp of the kind in question, which, presumably, would
require us to grasp it as a complex). However, this accidental grasp of unity is possible because the relevant objects or kinds contain something properly indivisible (e.g. an
essence) which makes the object itself a unity (of a kind), even though it is a composite.
232
I am indebted to Michael Wedin's discussion of this passage in Mind and Imagination in Aristotle (New Haven, 1988), 113–16. He emphasizes that the role of phantasia in
this passage is to capture how the thought is presented to the thinker. However, he does not develop this point in the way I suggest, and he may not agree with a
development of the type proposed.
138 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
If one contemplates with an ‘image’ of this kind, one need not know the type of route by which the thought was
produced (De Mem. 450b25–9). Indeed, for all one knows, it might have been produced by an external object or by a
combination of one's own thoughts. When the thought is presented to a subject in an image, the subject need not
know what produced it. The presence of the ‘image’ is precisely what is required to express the fact that the way in
which the thought is presented to the subject masks its identity conditions. Thus, when Aristotle writes that the
thinking faculty ‘thinks its forms in images’ which occur simultaneously with the thought, he appears to be
emphasizing the fact that when one thinks, the precise identity of the thoughts one has need not be transparent to one.
One need not know, in thinking, that the thoughts one has are caused in an appropriate way by an appropriate object.233
Indivisibles are the analogues of the simples grasped by the special senses (430b30–2). Thinking of them is contrasted
with the kind of thinking which involves predication and may allow for further kinds of error (430b28–30). In the latter
cases, we may combine simples to form nonexistent complexes (such as centaurs or goatstags). Error is possible here
because the combinations we make are not controlled by the objects in the way that they are in the case of special
perception or thought of indivisibles. As in the case of common sensibles, when there is combination by us in addition
to the objects of the special senses, there is a further possible source of error.234
233
This is not to say that there is one state which correctly describes in the same way how all thoughts strike the subject. There may be two types of ‘image’ depending on
whether or not the thought which strikes the subject is appropriately caused by an external object.
234
If the thinking faculty malfunctions and the thinker mislocates or misdescribes A, it would be affected by complex object A in the way it would have been by complex object
B or simple object C had the faculty been functioning properly (if the analogy with perception holds). And this would be because of the operation of past thinking of B or C.
But Aristotle does not develop in De An. Γ.6 a positive account of the content of erroneous thought (since he is focusing throughout on successful cases of thinking).
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 139
In this account, the nature and content of these thoughts are (constitutively) dependent on external objects. There is
internal light (thoughts with content) because of the way in which the external objects impact on us. In this way, the
cases of thought and perception are analogous.
The analogy generates two additional theses concerning thought:
(B) In the case of simple objects our thinking can be successful because our noetic faculty is such as to be able to
grasp the nature of its proper objects.
(C) If error is possible in the case of simple objects, this is because our noetic faculty can be stimulated by an
object O in the same way as it would be by another simple (P), if all was functioning well.
There is a further consequence of (B) and (C):
(D) The thinker need not know if they are having a simple thought when they are having one.
For, as before, the thinker need not know what makes the thought the one it is. Thus, they will grasp the relevant
thought even though they do not know that the thought is one of a simple object.
(D) is important, since it shows how a thinker can have a thought which is about a given object or kind without
knowing which object or kind it is. This is precisely what is required if Aristotle is to countenance the possibility
(central to our concerns)235 that a thinker can have a thought whose content is determined by a given kind without
knowing which kind that is (in the way required to distinguish it from all other kinds, real or imaginary). Thus, it seems
that (D) offers one part of Aristotle's way out of escaping the apparent inconsistency which threatened his account in
the previous Chapter (Section 4.5).236
While (B), (C), and (D) are interesting and important claims, they are not fully developed in De Anima. The main
burden of the analogy is carried by (A), which I have interpreted as a claim about the content of thought.
My account of the analogy faces an immediate difficulty. In the case of perception, ‘receiving the relevant form’ from
an object clearly involves acquiring a form at that time. (When this occurs, the perceiver actualizes her potential to
perceive.) However, in the case of thinking, the transition (on which Aristotle focuses) is that from potentially thinking
that p (in the mode of the scholar who has acquired relevant knowledge in the past) to actually thinking that p. But this
transition does not involve the subject's acquiring a new form at all. Rather, the form itself will typically have been
235
As set out in the final Section of the last Chapter.
236
More specifically, it offers a way of addressing the first part of (PC3), set out in Section 4.6 of the previous Chapter.
140 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
acquired at a previous stage when the person originally became knowledgeable in the relevant area (cf. Γ.4, 429b7–9).
That she has originally acquired it in this way explains why she can now exercise her knowledge by herself (without the
impact of external objects which themselves produce the activity (Β.5, 417b19–21)).237
The difficulty takes the form of a dilemma. If Aristotle's discussion of thinking does not focus on the original
acquisition of a form, he is not comparing like with like. For, he is comparing the acquisition of a perceptual form with
the exercise of an already acquired thought. But, since these cases are unlike, there can (it seems) be no strict analogy
between them. However, if the strict analogy is maintained, Aristotle is focusing either on the acquisition of forms in
the two cases or on the specific efficient causes which lead to particular episodes of perceiving or thinking.238 But in
neither case can the analogy focus on what makes a thought (or perception) have the content it does. Thus, to
conclude: either the analogy is broken-backed or it does not concern the determination of content.
Aristotle does not focus throughout on the acquisition of forms. For he takes as analogous the perceiver who sees a
particular object whose form he has not previously acquired, and the thinker who has already acquired the relevant
form and is exercising his ability to think of that form (see Β.5, 417b18–19). Thus, he writes that the thinker ‘has
already become’ all of the relevant objects of thought (Γ.4, 429b8–9). They exist in his soul in some way before their
actual use (Β.5, 417b23). In actively thinking, he exercises a capacity he has already acquired. If so, Aristotle's focus
cannot be on the original acquisition of the form in question.
In fact, the situation is more complicated. For, elsewhere Aristotle compares some thinkers to a wax tablet which bears
no actual writing before it is written on (Γ.4, 430a1–2). But this suggests that the relevant objects are not present in any
way prior to actual thinking. These thinkers may have the general ability to think grammatically, but need not possess
already the specific grammatical form.
How can Aristotle cover both these cases within one common framework? His main point cannot be confined to one
which concerns either the
237
In perception and knowledge of particulars, the productive cause is particular and external. In the case of thinking, by contrast, the universals are present ‘in some way’ in the
soul, and hence thinkers can think of them when they please (Β.5, 417b 22 ff.). The universals are present ‘in some way’ presumably because the thinker has the ability to
think of them. But this is compatible with his actually thinking of them involving the universals actually impacting on him. The difference with perceiving is not that there is
no comparable receiving of the form in the two cases, but that only in the case of thinking can we put ourselves in a position to receive the form (since thinking is within our
power by ourselves).
238
This interpretation has been proposed by Michael Wedin in Mind and Imagination in Aristotle.
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 141
initial acquisition of a form or the use of a form already acquired. Further, since the causal routes involved in these two
cases are very different, his point cannot depend on there being one type of causal route involved in the production of
both types of specific thought.
How can the analogy survive the presence of these major differences? What is common to the two cases of thought
under consideration? It seems that, in both, the thinking faculty is affected by the relevant universal (whether or not
previously acquired), and that its relevant states are then causally dependent on the universal in some appropriate way
(if all is functioning well). There can be thinking of this type whether or not the specific capacity has already been
acquired.239 Since the relevant states are thoughts with contents, in both cases the contents of the relevant thoughts are
determined by the universal on which they are causally dependent. In both, therefore, what makes it the case that the
subject has the thoughts she does is that she is causally affected in some way by the external world.
This account of thought allows Aristotle to preserve his analogy with perception. In both, the content of the relevant
state is determined by the subject's being affected in some (causal) way by relevant objects in the external world. The
faculty in the two cases is likened (in differing ways) to some object. But there is an obvious disanalogy. In the case of
perception, the content is acquired at the same time as it is determined. But this need not be so in the case of thought.
However, the presence of this disanalogy does not (in any way) call into question the point of analogy. For, the analogy
is pitched at such a general level that it cannot be affected by a more specific disanalogy of this type.
It should be noted that in De Anima Γ Aristotle says very little on the more specific issue of how we come to acquire
particular thoughts. His only remarks are in Γ.8, where he says that no one can think if they have not previously
perceived (432a7 f.), and that the objects of thought are somehow present in the objects of imagination (432a8 f.). But
these remarks are not developed into an account of how we acquire specific universals.240 (It is only elsewhere that he
attempts to provide such an account. For further discussion, see the next Chapter.) His lack of detailed comment on
this topic can be easily understood if his chief focus is (as I have suggested) on the issue of the determination of
content. For, while his account
239
This preserves the parallel with perception. The capacity to see mauve or this mauve does not depend on the antecedent acquisition of either of the specific capacities
involved. It is rather a consequence of the general capacity to see a whole range of colours and coloured objects, which matches the grammarian's ability to think new
thoughts about grammatical categories and the grammaticality of particular sentences.
240
It is to the passages in Post. An. Β.19 and Meta. Α.1 which are discussed in the next Chapter that one needs to look for such an account. In this Chapter, the focus has been
on the content of perception and thought, and no attempt has been made to extend this to the content of imagination. (That awaits a further study.)
142 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
of the latter may require that some story be told about how we acquire the relevant thoughts, that story is not itself
part of the theory of content determination. It is rather a background necessary condition for the account of content
determination.
What then survives of the analogy? There are three features in the account of thought which parallel the case of
perception.
(a) It is because the universal is as it is that the thought is as it is (and not vice versa); so the universal is the
controller of the thought.
(b) The thinking faculty is affected by the universal, as the perceptual faculty is by its proper object. In both cases,
the relevant form will be received, if all is functioning well.
(c) Given (a) and (b), one can detect activity and passivity in both cases.
These conditions give content to the idea of an efficient causal process linking universal and thinking faculty.241 It will
be enough if (i) the operation of the mind is itself controlled by the nature of the external object, and (ii) there is a
causal process beginning with the object and involving the subject's activity which results in the thought. When the
thinker's thought of a universal is dependent in these two ways on a universal, the thinking faculty is causally affected
by that universal. The analogy is preserved if there is an asymmetric causal relation of the type captured by (a)–(c).
This analogy is consistent with there being major differences between the two cases. In addition to the one already
mentioned, the types of causal pattern involved in the two cases may be radically different. Thus, thought need not
involve the impact of spatial forms characteristic of perception. There need be no quasi-perceptual forms travelling
through a spatial medium from objects of thought to make a quasi-physical impact on the thinker. Nor need
perception involve only the apprehension of the type of forms characteristic of thought. Perception (unlike thought)
may involve
241
Aristotle's discussions of efficient and teleological causation are both in need of further investigation. For the former, see M. Frede's essay on ‘The Original Conception of
Cause’, in his Essays in Ancient Philosophy (Minnesota, 1987), and for the latter see my ‘Teleological Causation in the Physics ’ in L. Judson (ed.), Aristotle's Physics (Oxford,
1991). Aristotle's active efficient causes are objects whose capacities are exercised in the relevant interactions. They are, thus, essentially structured phenomena, with their
own distinctive form, and are fundamentally different from unstructured events which are used as causes in some influential twentieth-century theories, such as those of
Donald Davidson. (On this, see my Aristotle's Philosophy of Action, 30–6, 44 ff.) Putnam objects to all theories of content which involve efficient causation on the basis that
they essentially involve unstructured (Davidsonian) events, which cannot explain ‘how the constituents of events connect with subsentential parts of speech’ (‘Aristotle after
Wittgenstein’, in R. W. Sharples (ed.), Modern Thinkers and Ancient Thinkers (London, 1993), 124). His objections do not engage with Aristotle's use of efficient causation,
since Aristotle is opposed au fond to the Davidsonian account of events and causation.
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 143
a detailed story about a medium and the physical organ involved in the acquisition of the perceptual form. Indeed, the
main lines of the analogy could be preserved even if perceptual forms were essentially spatial, and noetic forms
essentially non-spatial.242
242
It is, in any event, a mistake, from an Aristotelian viewpoint, to expect all the relevant causal processes to involve physical elements of the kind present in the case of special
perception. Indeed, there is no indication of the presence of this precise type of physiological change in the case of the common sensibles. It is enough there that the activity
of the senses is causally controlled in some (unspecified) way by the external object. Neither in this case nor in that of thought need there be a physical impact of precisely the
type found in the case of special perception.
144 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
thoughts. For, our thoughts and reality are both instances of the same activity of the same intellect.
However, this (no priority) interpretation243 cannot be reconciled with the causal account of the determination of
content which (I have argued) Aristotle favours. For, the content of thought, and not merely acts of thinking, is
causally determined by the world. Thus, when Aristotle talks of the world imprinting itself on us and our psychological
states, he is embracing a form of realism inconsistent with the no-priority interpretation.
If this is correct, we cannot avoid filling the two gaps mentioned above.244 However, before turning to Aristotle's
attempts to do this, there is one further objection to my account which should be considered.
in the case of things without matter the very same thing is the knower and the known (Γ.4, 430a3 f.)
In these cases (unlike those which involve matter) the thing known appears not to be even potentially present in any
material object. If so, how can the causal model be appropriate? What is the cause?
It would, clearly, be a major undertaking to spell out Aristotle's account of thought of entities of this kind. My aim is a
modest one: to sketch how the analogy with perception can be preserved in such cases.
According to Aristotle, the relevant universals exist in the active intellect alone, and are not even potentially present in
material objects (430a3–8). Thus, they may be seen as analogues of those general features of the light which are
characteristics of the medium and not of the objects which give rise to its activity. Such features might include relations
between actual colours (comparative brightness, colour matching, colour composition, spectral position), which are
features of the colours themselves rather than of the coloured objects (e.g. pillar boxes) which are disposed to produce
them. While there could not be such colours unless there were objects with such capacities, the properties of colours
themselves could be conceived as activities of the light independently of the objects which generate
243
For talk of no-priority theories, see Ch. 1 Sect. 1.3.
244
Further, if the no-priority view is to be rejected, one needs to explain why Aristotle invoked the active intellect at all at this stage in his enquiry. I return to this question in
Chapter 10.5.
SIGNIFICATION AND THOUGHT 145
them. Thus, colour science can focus on colours and their properties and not on the objects which give rise to them.245
The analogy, so understood, would run as follows. When we think theoretically, our thoughts are (e.g.) of the essence
of flesh or water because of the features these universals possess solely in virtue of their presence in the active intellect.
But what does this mean? Perhaps, no more than this: The essence of water is what it is because it occupies a given
position in the intelligible order (e.g. because it occupies a given slot in that order, related to the slots occupied by (e.g.)
hydrogen and oxygen). These thoughts would, of course, be matter-dependent because we could not have them unless
the enmattered kind existed. But in thinking of water's essence, we may focus only on its structural relations (whether
taxonomic or explanatory) with other features in the intelligible world, and not on the enmattered kind itself.
Theoretical science (like colour science) focuses on features which are in this limited way separable from material
objects.
Is this story consistent with Aristotle's remarks in De Anima? Some of his remarks suggest this type of model. Thus, in
Γ.7, 431b12–15, he writes:
Abstracted objects, as they are called, the mind thinks of as if it was thinking of the snub-nosed—qua snub-nosed, it
could not be thought of apart from flesh, but qua hollow, if it were actually so conceived, it would be thought of as
apart from the flesh in which hollowness resides.
When one thinks of the snub-nosed as such (as when one thinks of man) one cannot think of this apart from the
body/matter, or without the assistance of the perceptual faculty (Γ.4, 429b13–17). But when one thinks of it solely as
hollow one ignores its physical properties, and focuses solely on something with a geometric shape in abstract space. In
this way, the hollow is an object with its own place in an intelligible world. Although it is not in reality separable from
material objects, it is something whose nature depends on its standing in its own niche in abstract space (the distinctive
light of the active intellect).
If the analogy with light is understood in this way, objects which are (in this way) separable from matter can assimilate
the passive thinking faculty to themselves.246 In this way, Aristotle's discussion of mathematical entities
245
In De Sensu 3, Aristotle discusses colours in this type of way when he talks (e.g.) of ‘the multiplicity of colours being due to the fact that the components may be combined
in various ratios’ (440b 18 ff.), and rejects other views of their composition (e.g. 439b 25–440a 6). This appears to be an essay in colour science.
246
When so grasped they are grasped as separable from matter, unlike our thoughts of water which are of what is inseparable from matter. Because they are separable features,
they cannot be analysed (at least without qualification) as the realizations of capacities of physical objects. For, when considered as unmixed with matter they could not be
seen as essentially the realizations of material capacities. And this is why Aristotle does not regard them as existing potentially in the matter, but as essentially features of the
active intellect itself.
146 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
and essences in De Anima can exemplify a pattern of efficient causal and teleological factors similar to that he detects in
cases where the relevant universal is essentially enmattered. His treatment of these issues, although somewhat sketchy,
need not be inconsistent with his basic analogy between perception and thought.247
247 b
His remarks on these issues in De Anima are incomplete. Thus, in Γ.4, 429 19–22, he asserts that we do have such thoughts of essences and purely mathematical objects,
but does not say at all clearly how this is achieved. I have merely sketched a model which preserves some analogy with the case of perception. It would take us far from our
present study to examine these issues in detail. For further discussion of related issues, see Edward Hussey's essay in his (commentary on) Aristotle's Physics III–IV (Oxford,
1983), 182–4, I. Mueller's ‘Aristotle on Geometrical Objects’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 52 (1970), 156–67, and J. Lear's ‘Aristotle's Philosophy of Mathematics’, PR
91 (1982), 161–93.
6 Understanding, Thought, and Meaning
6.1 Introduction
In Chapter 4, we detected an apparent inconsistency in Aristotle's account of signification. The problem arose because
he held the following two claims:
(A) Simple names must signify (mediately) substances and kinds (on pain of lacking all significance), while
compound names need not. In the former case, the content of the thought (with which the name is correlated)
is determined by the kinds in the world which imprint themselves on our psychological states.
(B) One can grasp an account of what a simple name signifies without knowing of the existence (or of the essence)
of the object or kind in question. For, at Stage 1 of the three stages of scientific enquiry, one can grasp the
significance of (e.g.) ‘eclipse’ without knowledge of the existence or essence of the phenomenon (as was argued
in Chapters 2 and 3).
It seems hard to deny that Aristotle held both (A) and (B). Indeed, the grounds for attributing (A) to him have been
strengthened by the argument of the last Chapter. Did he find a way to hold both consistently?
In Chapters 4 and 5, we found some evidence of the route he attempted. To recapitulate: his account of signification
(for a simple name) rests on the content of the thought with which that name is conventionally correlated. In these
cases, content is (constitutively) determined by the form of the object or kind on which the thinker (in having this
thought) is causally dependent.
However, the thinker who has this thought need not know which object or kind it is which makes that thought the
thought it is. He need not see through to the fundamental determining conditions of the thought in question. Its basic
nature can be (to some degree) obscure to him.248
This account raises several urgent questions. One stems from the discussion of Chapter 5.
248
See Ch. 4 Sect. 4.6; Ch. 5 Sect. 5.7.
148 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
(A) How can an enquirer come to have thoughts of this type at all?
This question is pressing because it might seem mysterious that the enquirer could come to have any thoughts of the
relevant type, or that her thinking faculty could be ‘likened’ in this way to kinds in the world.249 Dissolution of this
mystery does not require an analysis of the ‘likening’ relation. It will be enough if we can show how a process of this
type can come about.250
A second question presses hard on the first:
(B) How can a thinker come to have a thought which is about a determinate kind without knowing which kind it
is?251
The appearance of paradox is not dispelled by Aristotle's claim (noted above) that the content of the relevant thought
need not be completely transparent to the thinker. For this does not explain how she could come (in the first place) to
have a thought about an object (in the world) without knowing which object it is about. That still seems mysterious.
Two other questions remain to be considered. One, which concerns semantic depth, was raised in Chapter 2:252
(C) How can an Aristotelian thinker grasp a thought about a kind without (at least) thinking that, if the kind exists,
it has an essence?
In the terms of the previous discussion: how much of the relevant form does the thinker need to grasp in order to
have a thought about a kind? Indeed, it might seem that this question has become more pressing as a result of the last
Chapter. For, the thinker must receive something of the form in question if she is to think about the relevant kind. It is
not enough for her to stand in any (undemanding) type of causal relation with it. How can she grasp the form without
knowing something of the essence or underlying structure of the kind?
A further question concerns knowledge of existence, and arises from the discussion of Chapters 4 and 5:
(D) How can an (Aristotelian) thinker grasp a thought about a kind without knowing of the existence of the kind?
249
This is (PC1) of the final Section of Chapter 4. For similar misgivings see Putnam's Reason, Truth and History (Cambridge, 1981), 50–1.
250
This distinction grounds the difference between reductive and (e.g.) supervenience theories in the philosophy of mind. See, for this distinction, the Introduction to D.
Charles and K. Lennon (eds.), Reduction, Explanation and Realism (Oxford, 1992). In the present context, we are seeking to make it non-mysterious how a concept can be
acquired. But this does not demand an analysis of concept acquisition in terms which do not refer to concepts. Nor is there an attempt to reduce the notion of form to more
basic notions. The relevant notion of form is further elucidated in the account of definition given in Chapter 10 Sections 10.1–2.
251
This is (PC3) of the final Section of Chapter 4 come back to haunt us!
252
See also App. 1.
UNDERSTANDING, THOUGHT, AND MEANING 149
While we have taken this possibility as a datum in previous Chapters, we still need to explain in detail how this can
occur.
In Section 6.2 I shall seek to answer these questions ‘at one go’ through an analysis of Aristotle's account of the route
to the possession of thoughts of kinds (on the basis of perception). If successful, this Section will support the
attribution to Aristotle of the theory outlined in Chapter 4. In Section 6.3 I shall assess what is distinctive about his
theory (as it has emerged in Chapters 2–5) and in Section 6.4 examine the distance that separates it from that of my
modern essentialist. It will become clear that (unlike the latter) the basis for Aristotle's essentialist claims lies in his
metaphysics and not in his account of language or of the thought of the ordinary thinker.253
Many memories form a single experience. And from experience or from the completed universal that has come to
rest in the soul (the one apart from the many, whatever is one and the same in all these things) arises the starting
point of skill and knowledge—of skill if it deals with how things come into being, of knowledge if it deals with what
is the case. (100a5–9)
The outline is clear: memory yields experience and the latter gives rise in turn to thought of universals, the starting
point of knowledge (100b12–15). But the details are obscure. For, we need to know what is involved in experience, and
how it differs from memory, from thought, and from knowledge. What is involved in ‘a universal coming to rest in the
soul’? Further, and central to an answer to question (A), we need to understand the nature of the transition from
experience to thought.
The text itself is problematic. I have translated the second sentence neutrally:
from experience or from the complete universal that has come to rest in the soul (100a6–7)
253
See Ch. 1 Sect. 1.6.
150 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
in which experience involves grasp of the complete universal, (and the ‘or’ is epexegetic254), or alternatively:
(b) from experience, or from the complete universal . . .
In (b), ‘or’ could be a corrective ‘or rather’, and the whole phrase mean:
(b1) from experience, or rather from the complete universal that has come to rest in the soul255
Alternatively, the ‘or’ might serve to indicate two separate ways in which the starting point of skill and knowledge
might arise:256
(b2) from experience or from the complete universal that has come to rest in the soul arises the starting point of
skill and knowledge . . .
It is not clear that the Analytics phrase by itself supports either an (a)- or a (b)-style reading. Experience, for all that is
said there, could either be of universals or of particulars. Perhaps it will be argued (in support of a (b)- style reading)
that experience cannot involve a grasp of whole universals, since if it did there would be no further step beyond
experience required to attain the starting point of knowledge and skill. However, this consideration is not decisive. For
perhaps something more than a universal ‘standing in the soul’ is required as a starting point for knowledge. Maybe this
requires universals to be connected with each other in some further way (as perhaps is indicated in 100b1–3). If so,
experience may enable one to grasp solitary or disconnected universals, but one will still lack the starting points of
knowledge.
There is, however, a closely parallel passage in Metaphysics. Α.1 which strongly favours a (b)-style reading. There,
Aristotle writes:
Skill comes to be when from many notions (ennoēmata) of experience one universal judgement about similar objects
is formed. To have a judgement that when Kallias was ill of this disease this helped, and similarly for Socrates, and
many others, is the task of experience. But to judge that something is beneficial for all people of a certain type,
marked off into one class, when they are ill of this disease—e.g. to phlegmatic or bilious people when burning with
fever—is the task of skill. (981a5–12)
Aristotle notes that experience is as good a guide to action as skill, and that men with experience can be more
successful than those who lack it
254
See, e.g. Barnes, Aristotle's Posterior Analytics (Oxford, 1975), 253: ‘the connective “or” is presumably epexegetic—i.e.’ Also, Ross, Aristotle's Analytics, 674: ‘from
experience—i.e. when the whole universal has come to rest in the soul’.
255
See, e.g. J. H. Lesher ‘The Meaning of Nous in the Posterior Analytics,’Phronesis 18 (1973), 59: ‘ “from experience, or rather from the universal . . . ” is perhaps preferable’.
256
And this could be taken to mean that both are alternative routes to both skill and knowledge, or that one is a route to skill, and the other to knowledge.
UNDERSTANDING, THOUGHT, AND MEANING 151
but possess only general accounts of the same phenomena (981a12–15). His reason is revealing:
This is because experience concerns particulars, while skill concerns universals, and actions and productions are
concerned with individuals. (981a15–17)
In the first of these passages Aristotle distinguishes the things noticed in experience (‘notions’) from the genuine
universals (981a16, 21) involved in a universal judgement about similar cases (981a7 f.). If the distinction holds, the whole
universal which rests in the soul cannot be grasped by experience, but must be the object of a distinct faculty. And this
clearly favours a (b)-style reading.257
What then are the ‘notions of experience’, and why are they not universals? Aristotle's example concerns judgements of
the form:
This worked for Kallias and Socrates . . . when they suffered this disease
and is contrasted with judgements about what works for all people of a certain type (e.g. phlegmatic) with a certain
kind of disease (e.g. fever). The many notions of experience appear to essentially involve claims of the form:
257 a
Is it (b1) or (b2) which is to be preferred? While Aristotle speaks of experience making skill (Meta. 981 4), the role of experience is not confined to the acquisition of skill.
Thus, the acquisition of grasp of starting points in (e.g.) astrology stems from experience of astrology (Pr. An. Α.30, 46a 18–21). Perhaps experience and the universal's
lodging in the soul by a different route (e.g. by teaching) are both routes to knowledge and skill. But the ‘or’ may be better understood in this context as the corrective ‘or
rather’, as Aristotle appears to emphasize that the canonical route to thought lies through memory and experience.
258 a b a
Indeed, this is one reason why experience differs from memory (100 3 f.). The latter in this context concerns only the retention of past instances (monē (99 36, 100 3)),
while the former has a dynamic quality which goes beyond past cases. Indeed, this is why we should listen to the unproved sayings of the experienced who see clearly what to
do in a given situation (NE/EE 1143b 11–14).
152 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
terms what the relevant likeness consists in. Her ability comes to no more than her being able to say: ‘This individual
(Socrates) is like that one (Kallias) in (e.g.) that respect’ (pointing to some demonstrated feature of Socrates).259
Similar remarks may apply to her grasp of this illness or this medicine. In each case, the relevant person with
experience has no more grasp on illness or medicine than is given by her ability to discriminate particular instances on the
basis of their being like other particular cases.260 She will lack the conceptual sophistication required to understand the
illness as (e.g.) fever of a general type, in terms which do not essentially involve reference to other particular cases. Thus,
she will not grasp universals, if the latter are to be understood as wholly general and completely abstracted from
particular cases. But precisely this understanding of universals seems to be what is suggested both by the examples
given in Metaphysics Α.1 and by the phrase ‘the universal . . . the one over and above the many’ (as used in Post. An. 100a
6 f.). For, the latter clearly expresses the idea of a universal as something to be understood without any essential
reference to particular cases.261
The person with knowledge (981a29 f.) possesses a fully conceptual grasp on the type of illness involved, while the one
with experience lacks this and can only spot similarities between particular cases (without being able to say in purely
descriptive terms what the similarity consists in).262 Some might describe both as having the concept of the relevant
illness,
259
The person with experience has the ability to identify objects (and other phenomena) without having thoughts about the kind of object in question. Thus, they can identify
objects without using ‘sortal concepts’, if the latter require general thoughts about the kinds of objects involved. Of course, one cannot have Aristotelian thoughts about
objects without invoking the sortal notions. Indeed, this is how the thoughts of the master craftsman differ from the judgements of those guided only by experience. (See
also n. 260 below.)
260
In this way, the master craftsman will come to grasp a variety of specific kinds. One account of this process runs as follows: Given his general understanding of (e.g.)
‘animal’, and his skilled interaction with particular animals, specific kinds will become visible to him. If so, it is not merely that he groups certain animals together for his own
purposes (e.g. guarding the house, ploughing the field, etc.). Rather, he will distinguish separate kinds, with distinctive natures, when in the course of his activity he finds that
some (e.g.) eat, move, breathe in one way, others in another. His kind concepts will not be merely the pragmatic ones (recommended by conceptualist writers), designed
simply to serve his needs and purposes. But neither will they be formed (as some professedly ‘realist’ writers urge they should be) solely by looking at distinct patterns of
causal connections, without reliance on any grasp of the relevant genus: (e.g.) animal. For, some grasp of the latter is required, in this account, to uncover specific animal
261
This marks an important difference from Putnam's account, with its essential use of indexicals. (See Chapter 1.)
262 a
Elsewhere, Aristotle characterizes the former as a case of thinking, and distinguishes it from particular-directed perceiving and imagining. (See De An. Γ.8, 432 12 f., Β.5,
417b 23–5). In this Section, I take knowledge (of the relevant type) to involve thought as its starting point, and understand both to be distinct from lower-level, particular-
directed states (such as experience ).
UNDERSTANDING, THOUGHT, AND MEANING 153
since both can discriminate instances when confronted by them, but this labelling is misleading. Aristotle's point is this:
the content of a knowledgeable person's thoughts is fully general, involving universals which contain no essential
reference to particular cases, but the person with experience alone enjoys a distinctive type of content, essentially
constituted by reference to particular cases.263 He emphasizes the relevant difference as follows:
we think that master craftsmen in each craft are more worthy of honour and know in a truer sense and are wiser
than manual workers, because they know the causes of what is done, while the latter, like lifeless things, do what
they do, as fire burns—but while lifeless things perform each of these by nature, manual workers perform them
through habit (Meta. Α.1, 981a30–b5)
The manual workers have experience and react on its basis without grasp on the relevant universals. From the
perspective of the thinker, they are like a natural force because they lack a proper understanding of what they are
doing.
Aristotle's discussion of thought and experience shows how we can come to have thoughts about kinds in a non-
mysterious way. We do not (in his view) merely find ourselves with rich thoughts about man, thunder, and eclipse. We
acquire such thoughts when we step beyond experience and grasp the relevant universals. Thus, the doctor might
move from realizing that this medicine works for this illness to a view about the type of illness in question and the type
of medicine it is (Meta. Α.1 981a11–12). Such transitions arise from the successful operation of experience in ‘low-level’
skill, and give rise to the thought that there is a unified kind before one.
What does the doctor need to understand if she is to grasp the relevant universal? Can she know that she is in touch
with a genuine nature in the world, while lacking theoretical ideas about what the basis for such a nature is? Can she
believe that the term ‘dropsy’ latches on to a distinct nature in reality, while having no view as to whether there is one
underlying feature (its essence) which holds the kind together?
There is good evidence for a positive reply to this question. Aristotle insists that the craftsman needs a grasp ‘sufficient
for his task’(NE Α.7, 1098a30 f.), and distinguishes this from that of the geometer (or scientist). In the case of the
doctor, her aim is to use her skill to restore the patient to health (see Meta. Ζ.7, 1032b18 f.). For this, she must have
some idea of what health is, but she does not need to understand it in terms of basic science (e.g. as a mixture or
imbalance of heat and cold) as a Pythagorean
263
For this distinction, see Evans, Varieties of Reference, 124, 158, and A. Cussins, ‘The Connectionist Construction of Concepts’, in M. Boden (ed.), The Philosophy of Artificial
Intelligence (Oxford, 1990), 23.
154 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
doctor would.264 Her conception of her goal may be a functional one, defined in terms of the patient's ability to
perform certain tasks in a satisfactory way. She need not even consider the possibility of a deep scientific account of
health. It is not needed for the purposes of producing the result at which she aims (NE/EE Ζ.4, 1140a10–13).
Similar remarks any apply to her grasp on the type of illness in question. She may understand that if the patient has a
given condition he will have (or develop) certain other features as well. In this way, his temperature or lethargy may
serve as a ‘litmus test’ for the presence of other features of the same condition. If she can isolate the feature in
question she will know that other features are also present. In this respect, her state is like that of the person described
in Posterior Analytics Β.8 as knowing that there are eclipses because he knows that there exists, as a phenomenon, a
specific inability of the moon: to cast a shadow under certain specified conditions. He has a test which will enable him
to tell whether an eclipse is occurring, and whether other features of eclipses will follow, but need not know that there
is any fundamental scientific cause of such occurrences. The latter idea is not needed for his purposes.
The skilled doctor may also understand that if she treats one feature of the patient's condition in one way, other
features will react in a given way. At the level of the universal, she will see the condition, dropsy, as containing a set of
interlocking capacities. On this basis she will know that if she does one thing to it, a certain result will follow. Indeed, it
is just this type of knowledge which enables her to realize that she is dealing with an objective kind with its own
‘internal principle of change and rest’ (Phys. Β.1, 193b3–6). For, it is a kind of illness with its own distinctive set of inter-
locking causal capacities, whose presence is not explained by her activity.265 Indeed, as she will see, these features of the
illness limit what she can do for the patient.
The skilled doctor, of the type envisaged, will be able to teach (Meta. Α.1, 981b7 f.). For, she will know, on the basis of
her understanding of the illness, why it is best to treat a given type of condition in one way rather than another. She will
also have similarly based ideas about what can and cannot be usefully done for patients with this condition. She will be
interested to find out when her inability to cure patients arises not from her
264
In the Hippocratic writings, doctors who take as their starting points (or basic postulates) the hot, the cold, the wet, and the dry are frequently attacked. It has been
suggested that Philolaus is one of those attacked in this way (see G. E. R. Lloyd's ‘Who is attacked in On Ancient Medicine ?’, Phronesis 8 (1963), 108–26, and C. A.
Huffman, Philolaus of Croton (Cambridge, 1993). Those attacked required the doctor to understand diseases in terms of a small number of starting points, drawn from basic
physical theory. In their view, skills had to be based on theoretically supported postulates of this type.
265
This distinguishes natural kinds from artefacts.
UNDERSTANDING, THOUGHT, AND MEANING 155
lack of skill (for perhaps that could be remedied), but from the nature of their condition.
What has been said about the doctor will apply to any master craftsman. A skilled carpenter will come to think of
certain kinds of wood as (by nature) having certain interlocking features, which can be used in given ways in his work.
He will think of elm as one type of wood amongst many, with differing natures, useful for different purposes. Part of
his skill will consist in knowing which type of wood is best suited for what type of purpose. But neither the doctor nor
the carpenter need have any views about what, if anything, holds together the varying features of the illness, health, or
the wood (e.g. that these possess one underlying feature, molecular or evolutionary, which explains their possession of a
number of inter-locking causal capacities). However, while they may never have raised this issue, they, nonetheless,
have the idea of a determinate natural kind, with its own distinctive features, existing independently of themselves.
These resources provide an answer to question (C). The skilled craftsman may grasp the kind without thinking of it as
possessing an underlying essence of a scientific kind. His grasp on the kind is not of a proto-scientific type, as would be
exemplified by one who described the kind as one with an underlying essence yet to be discovered. There is no need
for his thoughts to have that degree of depth. For, while he aspires to know everything about the kind that he needs
for his skill, he need not know any biological or molecular theory about the wood's structure or historical evolution
(nor even that there could be any such theory).266
There are several heroes (and heroines) elsewhere in Aristotle's thought whose role corresponds to that of the master
craftsman. The virtuous know how to act and can explain why they act in that way, but need not know the
fundamental principles concerning human well-being which make their mode of action correct. Indeed, they may have
no view as to whether there are any underlying principles of this type. Thus, they will lack the kind of explanation of
why what they do is correct which the ethical philosopher might provide.267 Similarly, the orator (discussed in the
Rhetoric) may know how to argue without knowing the basis of his practice in a theory of logical validity. Equally, he
may know what the emotions are and how to engage with them without having the beginnings of a scientific account
of their nature or essence.268 All of these can have thoughts about kinds or
266
This is not to say that the skilled artisan cannot be interested in the deeper understanding of the kind which the scientist can provide. Indeed, he may be prepared to defer to
the scientist's greater knowledge in some cases. However, that said, he can grasp the significance of the kind term without even imagining that there is a deeper form of
understanding to be had of the kinds with which he interacts. (See also Chapter 13.)
267
On this, see (for instance) my Aristotle's Philosophy of Action, 185 n. 21.
268
On this, see J. M. Cooper's ‘Aristotle on Emotion’ in D. J. Furley and A. Nehamas (eds.), Aristotle's Rhetoric (Princeton, 1994), 205–9.
156 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
phenomena without thinking that they must possess basic, unifying, determining features. The master craftsman does
not stand alone.
So, how is the transition made from experience to thought? Aristotle says that we grasp the first universals by
induction (100b4), and notes that in this way perception instils the universal (100b5). He also says that ‘we perceive the
universal’ (100a17), but does not spell out any of these remarks in detail. Induction, in this context, presumably refers
to a cognitive process which leads from particular cases to universal;269 but this tells us nothing until we know the
nature of the process itself. Barnes remarks that: ‘Aristotle nowhere gives [an account] of how such concepts as man
are derived from data of perception’.270
It is certainly true that Aristotle nowhere gives a detailed account of how such a derivation will go. However, he does
provide some indications. The first stage will involve experience (as discussed above), focusing on specific
discriminations of particular cases. The relevant transition is from this to a grasp on a universal, which involves no
essential reference to particulars. The end product will not simply be an abstraction from experience, since the
universals must cohere among themselves in an organized way (100a11-b2). Consequently, one cannot justify the
resulting universals solely by reference back to experience. For, there are additional, explanatory, constraints present at
the level of thought which are not present in experience.
This account does not make the transition mysterious. Reflection on what is common in the particular cases of illness
one has confronted and treated, and how they differ from other somewhat similar cases, gives an initial impetus
towards grasping the relevant universal and seeing its connections with, and distinctions from, other related universals.
Initially, one may introduce a term (e.g. ‘dropsy’) as a way of labelling the instances one thinks of as examples of one
type of illness. One may grasp some of the symptoms which one has found in general terms (nausea and lethargy
followed by fever), and also note which medicines work for which patients. For, one is concerned to see which types of
treatment work for which patients and which do not, and to find some way of representing
269
As Barnes remarks: ‘perception instils the universal by induction simply because our first grasp of universal A depends on our having perceived a quantity of individual A's.
Thus construed 100b 3–5 says no more than that concept acquisition proceeds from the less to the more general’ (Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 256). This appears to be the
case in the acquisition of universals also (NE / EE Ζ.3, 1139b 28–30; Ζ.11, 1143b 1–5).
270
Barnes, Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 255. He rests this conclusion on the correct claim that ‘it is hard to see how . . . man could be either a proper or a common sensible’. But
we can only draw his conclusion if we ignore the role of experience in Aristotle's account. Barnes is drawn to do this because he believes that experience itself involves
universals and universal judgements (Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 255), ‘perceiving things as A's’. But this seems over-hasty in the light of the clear distinction in Meta. Α.1
between universals and the notions grasped by a person with experience.
UNDERSTANDING, THOUGHT, AND MEANING 157
271
The process is not merely a causal one. It provides the thinker with some justification for having the thought contents he does. (See, for further discussion, Ch. 13 Sects. 13.5
and 13.7.)
272
More would be required if one were attempting to analyse ‘likening’ in terms of the conditions under which one came to acquire the relevant concepts. But there is no need
to see Aristotle as engaging in that task. His goal need only be to make it intelligible how we can come to have such concepts.
273
At this point, my task is to show how these claims are (1) mutually consistent and (2) consistent with Aristotle's general account of concept acquisition. It cannot be proved
(by more direct evidence) that Aristotle proceeded in this way. The account may be taken as one which offers the best explanation of Aristotle's claims in this area.
158 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
of symptoms, which she does not recognize as those of a known disease. She finds that some treatments work in some
cases, and begins to note some similarities between the cases that can be treated in this way. She may speculate as to
whether what had initially appeared to be a set of unconnected and disparate symptoms is (in fact) the manifestation of
one unified condition, with a variety of interconnected features. This is merely a hypothesis on her part (perhaps one of
many), since she lacks the evidence required (by her lights) to sustain the claim that these symptoms are thus
connected. For example, she does not (as yet) know how the varying aspects of the condition affect one another,
whether there is a common course the illness follows, or how far its various aspects can be treated in the same way. So,
she cannot as yet determine whether the cases before her are instances of the same condition (with complications) or
of a number of different conditions.274 Nonetheless, on the basis of her limited experience of the disease, she has a
hunch that there is one such condition, with its own causal structure, common to all the cases before her, which she
calls ‘dropsy’. She could say:
Dropsy is the unified medical condition, if there is one, with the following symptoms . . .
Something further would be required to establish the existence of one condition: e.g. repeated successful manipulation
of symptoms (‘if I do this, that will happen . . . ’), some understanding of how different aspects of the illness are
interconnected, or a prognosis of how the illness develops in standard cases. Without this, the doctor will be able to
formulate an account of what ‘dropsy’ signifies (which she uses in her hypothesis275) without knowing of the existence
of dropsy.
In this case, let us imagine, the doctor's hypothesis is correct and there is indeed a unitary disease of the type indicated.
She was, in fact, interacting with one disease, without knowing that she was doing so. Her interactions with the kind,
although not sufficient (by her lights) to generate knowledge of its existence, are sufficient to give her thoughts about
it. So, at the end of a successful enquiry she will be entitled to say that she was right all along about dropsy. She has a
thought of one unified kind throughout, even though (at the outset) she does not know that this is so. At the
274
Since there could be other illnesses in her immediate vicinity which she could not tell apart from dropsy, her methods may not be reliable even in her situation. She could be
very lucky in her hypothesis.
275
For this use of hypothesis see Post. An. Β.9, 93b 24 f. These issues are discussed in Ch. 3, Sect. 3.8. See also the discussion of Stage 1 accounts in Ch. 2 Sect. 2.9.
UNDERSTANDING, THOUGHT, AND MEANING 159
outset her thinking faculty is ‘likened’ to the kind, even though she does not know that this is the case.276 As is required
to answer question (D), raised in Section 6.1, she has a thought about dropsy without knowing that there is, in fact,
such a kind.
But what does she possess when she first has a thought about dropsy? She does not have (at this stage) the practical
ability to tell (by her own lights) that the cases before her exemplify one separate condition, rather than (for example)
several different conditions with overlapping and somewhat similar symptoms. Thus, she need not have the resources
to distinguish this illness from all others, real and imaginary. Indeed, she may even think it equally probable (for all she
knows) that the cases before her exemplify several conditions rather than one.277 Of course, she knows that if there is a
common condition, all or many of these are cases of it. But since she does not (as yet) know that there is a common
condition, she is not able knowledgeably to discriminate those cases which do have the illness in question. All she can
say is that if there are any cases of dropsy, these (or some of them) are they. But she does not as yet know that these are
cases of dropsy.
Her hypothesis is that there is one type of illness which all (or many) of these cases share. Further, she has latched on
(through her interactions with the kind) to some of its genuine, non-accidental, features. In this way, something of the
nature of the illness has impressed itself upon her.278 It is the fact that this is so that makes her thought one about
dropsy. Because of the impression the kind has made on her, she has latched on to enough of its features to go on to
search (in the mode discussed in Chapters 2 and 3) for answers to questions about its existence and essence. She has, in
effect, a point of access to an epistemic trail which culminates (if all goes well) in knowledge of the existence and nature
of the kind with which she is interacting.279 But she does not have this latter knowledge at the
276
One should distinguish between the conditions required for likening and those required for likening plus knowledge of the existence of the kind.
277
She also lacks the resources to distinguish the type of situation in which her hypothesis is correct from those (which could easily arise) in which it is not, even though she may
be lucky enough to be in a situation where her hunches are correct. For this reason, although she can, as it happens (in her actual situation), reliably pick out cases of dropsy,
she seems to lack knowledge. For, there are (as she may be aware) many ‘proximate’ situations (indistinguishable by her from this one) in which her hunch would be
mistaken.
278
We can understand in this way the significance of Aristotle's cautious phrases in Post. An. Β.8, 93a 22 and a
29.
279
One might propose that such accounts determine the reference of the term in the following way:‘T’ signifies a kind K for thinker S if and only if S, when using ‘T’, has in his
possession an account A, which provides him with information on whose basis alone he can (given his methods) come to have knowledge of the existence and nature of K.
That is, ‘T’ might signify the kind about which the thinker would come to have knowledge on the basis solely of the account he then possesses (plus his epistemic methods).
The epistemic methods in question would be those involved in arriving at Stages 2 and 3 of successful enquiry.This proposal is committed to the claim that:‘T’ signifies a
kind K (for S at t) if and only if S would come to have knowledge of K in a given way on the basis of information S possesses at t.But, even if this proposal were
extensionally correct, it would not tell us what makes it true that ‘T’ signifies K at a stage before S comes to have knowledge of it. For, the fact that he would come to have
knowledge of K in the future cannot be what makes it true that he then signifies K. If so, this proposal appears to be a consequence of the correct theory of signification-
determination, and not its basis. Nor is it clear that the proposal is even extensionally correct. For, presumably, ‘T’ could signify K, even if S was not able (given his methods)
to come to have knowledge of its existence or essence (e.g. if the kind was too complex for S to analyse).
160 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
beginning of her enquiry. Her case shows that it is possible to arrive (as Aristotle requires) at Stage 1 without yet
achieving Stage 2. In this way, his account can be acquitted of the charge of inconsistency.
The master craftsman will, of course, often be able to make the transition to Stage 2 of enquiry. He may come to have
good reason to believe that he has grasped a genuine universal. This will happen if (for example) he can interact
successfully with the kind, predict what will happen if he acts in one way rather than another, piece together what types
of effect one type of treatment has, detect the course of a given condition, and differentiate it from other close cases. In
this way, he will see its position as one among several universals which form the basis for an interconnected map of
illnesses and treatments.280
Naturally, he can make mistakes. In some cases, he may think that a series of instances have one common set of
interlocking capacities when they do not. Thus, he may mistakenly ‘lump together’ elm and beech wood. But in both
cases the idea of there being an objective kind with its own distinctive nature plays a central role in his thinking.
Further, when he is right, there seems to be no reason to deny him knowledge of the existence of the kind.
Aristotle emphasizes the possibility of mistakes arising in the acquisition of thoughts. Thus, in Physics Α.1 he writes:
What are at first clear to us and obvious are things which are rather confused. Later the elements and principles of
these become known to us by analysis. This is why we advance from these [sc. confused] universals to specific ones.
For, the whole [sc. which embraces all the specific cases] is more known in the light of perception, and the universal
is a whole of a type; for, the universal embraces many things as parts. (184a21–6)
280 b
In this Section, I have not addressed the question of how one comes, in Aristotle's account, to grasp the first universals as such (100 3–5). While my concern has been with
the mastery of such concepts as man or animal, I have not sought to account for one's grasp on animal as a first principle. On the latter issue, see Ch. 10 Sect. 10.6.
UNDERSTANDING, THOUGHT, AND MEANING 161
These universals, which have parts, must be contrasted with the indivisible infimae species (such as man) discussed in
Posterior Analytics 100a15 ff. Aristotle gives no examples of the compound universals he introduces in Physics Α.1, but
compares this case with that of the name ‘kuklos’, which signifies a whole in a confused way (since it is a homonym
signifying both a circular object, such as Stonehenge, and a geometric circle) which definition divides into more specific
elements. Cycle, by analogy, would be a confused universal initially grasped if the person who grasped it did not
distinguish between the two. Elsewhere, as we have seen, Aristotle offers the example of pride. One might begin by
thinking of pride as one thing, even though it subsequently turned out that there was no one phenomenon involved: e.
g. if there was no common account of why some proud people were indifferent to misfortune and others could not
tolerate insults (Post. An. Β.13, 97b23–5). In both cases, one has arrived at a compound universal and entertains a
confused thought because there is no unitary set of capacities of the required type in the cases before one.
However, although such mistakes are possible, the master craftsman will frequently get it right. In these cases, he will
grasp a genuine thought of a kind and know that the kind exists. In the terminology of the earlier account, he will
successfully achieve both Stages 1 and 2.
281
Traditional Fregeans hold that the sense of a name is what is grasped by the thinker, and that this semantically determines the reference (e.g. by giving a definite description
which uniquely fits the object). Revisionary Fregeans take the sense to be what the thinker grasps and to be what is (metaphysically) determined by the reference (since the
sense, in their view, just is a mode of presentation of the referent). Thus, in their view, the thinker who knows the sense of a term knows which object it refers to. Aristotle,
in effect, separates what the thinker grasps (as expressed by the account of what the name signifies) and the thought itself (which is determined by the object or kind in the
world). In this way, he can allow a thinker to grasp a name without possessing distinguishing knowledge of its object.
162 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
interacts), without knowing of its existence. It is only at Stage 2 that she (by her own lights) achieves this knowledge
and, thus, comes to know (in the Fregean mode) which object it is that she is thinking of. In this way, she makes the
transition (as she sees it) from not knowing to knowing of the existence of the kind. (It would make nonsense of how
she sees the transition to insist that she knew all along of the existence of the kind without knowing that she knew.282)
Aristotle is able to characterize the thinker's progress in this way because he does not accept that grasping an object in
thought involves ‘knowing which’ object it is that is grasped (in the way required to distinguish it from all others).283
This is because, as is clear in the case of the craftsman, the account of content determination is not identical with an
account of what the competent thinker knows. Semantics is one thing, epistemology another. The thinker can be
‘likened’ to the kind when she engages with instances of it, spots some similarities between cases, and gains some
information about what the illness is like. But this does not require her to be able knowledgeably to discriminate the
kind which is the causal source of her information. Nor does it require her to be able to tell who has the illness, or that
certain cases are cases of the illness. The most she need know is that these (or some of them) are cases of the illness, if
there are any cases of it. While the content of her hypothesis is ‘informed’ by the illness in question, she is not (as yet)
in a position to know either that the illness exists or that certain people are suffering from it.
It is sometimes said that there are only two types of account of thought and signification. Either one attributes to the
thinker thoughts about an object or kind solely in virtue of his standing in a causal relation with it or one requires that
he possess discriminating knowledge of the object or kind in question,284 such as might enable him (fallibly) to
discriminate the object or kind from all others.285
Aristotle's strategy appears to differ from both of these accounts. For, while he does not accept the latter (Fregean)
option, he does not accept the first one either. Thus, he does not think that to grasp the signification
282
Aristotle gives no indication at all of this type of formulation. His view seems to be that at Stage 1 one lacks knowledge of the existence of the kind, not merely knowledge
that one knows. Nor is this surprising. Aristotle's view of knowledge appears to require some grasp by the thinker on something which makes the relevant claim true (Post.
b
An. Α.2, 71 10–12). Thus, his account of knowledge involves some component other than merely following a route, which (in fact) reliably leads to knowledge.
283
For a contrasting claim, see John McDowell's formulations in ‘Singular Thought and the Extent of Inner Space,’ 140.
284
Gareth Evans presents these alternatives in Varieties of Reference, 83.
285
See Evans' comments on Russell's Principle in Varieties of Reference, 106 ff. McDowell emphasizes the fallibility of the relevant knowledge in ‘Singular Thought and the
Extent of Inner Space’, 141.
UNDERSTANDING, THOUGHT, AND MEANING 163
of a kind term is simply to stand in some bare causal connection with the kind (which may, as a result, mean nothing to
the thinker). The relevant type of connection has to be one in which something of the nature of the kind is made
manifest to the thinker. They will engage with the kind in such a way that they gain some information about it, even if
their information is not enough to enable them to tell that kind apart from all others (even ones in their immediate
vicinity). They are in a position to form a hypothesis about the kind, even though they lack the type of knowledge on
which the Fregean insists.286
Aristotle, further, has no reason to accept the characterization of the information gained by the thinker which is
offered by a proponent of the bare causal thesis.287 For, the information the Aristotelian thinker gains is constitutively
tied to the kind which causes it. It is the imprint which that kind with its nature makes on him.288 There need be no way
of specifying how things are with the subject (‘internally’) in these cases which does not advert to the external world, as
it is presented to the subject. The qualifications (of the ‘if it is’ form) do not require a separate form of internal content
such as may be needed to allow an internalist account of knowledge.289 Rather, they express a measure of epistemic
reservation about whether the world is as it appears to be. Thus, there need be no ‘distinct and separate’ form of
content which captures their role.
In Aristotle's account, the signification of terms is determined by features separate from those which determine our
knowledge of the objects in question. Given this separation, he has no need of any of the following strategies:
(i) to define a separate form of internal content as the focus for internalist constraints on knowledge (as in the
dual-component theory)
(ii) to insist that the thinker knows which object he is signifying (in either the orthodox or the neo-Fregean style)
(iii) to hunt for some version of a reliabilist account of knowledge to accommodate externalist elements in the
account of meaning
286
For objections to the pure causal theory of reference, see Gareth Evans's paper ‘The Causal Theory of Names’ (PASS 47 (1973), 187 ff.). In it, he cites the example of
‘Madagascar’, first attached (in some variant) to part of the mainland of Africa, and then (as a consequence) mistakenly transferred by the Portuguese to the offshore island
that now bears the name.
287
See, for example, Colin McGinn's ‘The Structure of Content’ in A. Woodfield (ed.), Thought and Object (Oxford, 1982), 230. He separates two components of meaning, one
dependent on a causal connection with the object, a second ‘conceptually disparate and . . . independent’ (p. 230). Each component aims ‘to specify the whole of a part of
meaning’ (p. 231).
288
For the basis of these formulations, see Ch. 5 Sect. 5.2.
289
It will become even clearer in Chapters 7–10 that the information gathered by the understander cannot be characterized without reference to the external world.
164 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
(iv) to allow that one grasps the significance of a term by standing in some bare causal relation with the object or
kind
In his view (as this has emerged in the past Chapters) one can understand a name without knowing which object it
denotes (in the Fregean manner), but one cannot understand it solely in virtue of standing in any type of causal
connection with the object. One understands a name for a kind when one receives sufficient information about its
nature (from engagement with its instances) to be able to form a hypothesis about it which (in favourable conditions)
one can substantiate. The nature of the kind is (in some measure) given to one in one's experience of individual cases,
even though one is not in a position then to know that this is so.290 For, it is only at a later stage that one can come to
know of the existence and nature of the kind.
Aristotle's approach stems from his interest in our understanding of the names we use in enquiry. Here, our
understanding of our terms (what we know about their bearers) is determined by factors different from those which
fix their signification. For this reason, Aristotle's account of the signification (or meaning) of names is not to be
identified with an account of our understanding of their signification (or meaning).
290
At least in the case of kinds grasped through perception. It would take a further study to see whether and in what way this style of account applies to terms for triangles and
other mathematical entities. Since there is no obvious analogue for perception in this case, it may be that one requires a fuller description of the phenomenon than in the
perceptual case. Perhaps one needs the type of description of triangle as ‘closed three-sided figure’ mentioned in Chapter 2.
291
See Ch. 1.
UNDERSTANDING, THOUGHT, AND MEANING 165
process set out above. When she has grasped such a form, she has been ‘likened’ to the kind in question. However, the
thinker, in grasping such a thought, need not know whether there is (in reality) a kind which brings this thought about,
or that the cases before her are actually cases of one condition. This by itself is sufficient to distance Aristotle's account
from that of the modern essentialist (as set out in Chapter 1). For, his doctor can understand the term ‘dropsy’ without
knowing of the existence of the kind. It is not a requirement on his mastery of the term that he ‘knows which’ kind it
signifies.292
(2) The doctor's knowledge can be distinguished in a second way from that required of the understander by my
modern essentialist (as introduced in Chapter 1). She need not possess the idea of a proto-scientific kind, of a kind
(that is) with one core feature which explains the rest. For, this goes considerably beyond what is required for her to
grasp the concept of dropsy, or of man. Indeed, she can know of the existence of the illness without thinking of it in
that way. At these stages, she can have thoughts of a natural kind without any of the semantic depth required for
thought of kinds as endowed with explanatorily basic properties. There is no need for her to think of man or dropsy as
proto-concepts in a master science (like physics) in order to master the relevant thought or know of the existence of
the kind.
Both (1) and (2) stem from a common source. Aristotle (as I have emphasized) develops his account of what names
signify in the context of a thinker's enquiry into the nature and existence of a kind. At the initial stage of such an
enquiry, one can understand a term for a natural kind without knowing of its existence or its hidden essence, or even
that if it exists it has such an essence. No doubt, at a later stage in enquiry we will know of the existence and nature of
the kind. But this further knowledge is not essential to our initial mastery of the terms. Most modern discussion
focuses on what is involved in understanding a term once an enquiry is well advanced (or completed). But Aristotle
concentrates on the absolute minimum required for the understanding of a term, as exemplified by what the thinker
knows at the beginning of the enquiry.
(3) In order to grasp the significance of a kind term, one must have a general thought about the kind which is the
causal source of one's information. Such general thoughts mark the imprint of the kind on us (when we are ‘likened’ to
it). We do not grasp the significance of the term when we refer to the kind simply as ‘the kind of which these are
instances’. For,
292
The argument for this is given in Section 6.2. My modern essentialist has a Fregean understanding of the ‘knowing which’ requirement. However, as mentioned in Chapter
1 Section 1.3, others might think to interpret the knowledge requirement differently (in a reliabilist fashion). I have presented some considerations against this view in
Section 6.2 above. The doctor appears to signify dropsy even in cases where she only has a hunch that it is one genuine condition.
166 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
this phrase could also be used by a person with experience who lacks a thought, and merely has the ability to pick out
its instances. If his thought is to be of a kind, it has to involve more than this. In particular, for Aristotle, it has to
involve the understanding of the kind as a distinctive type of phenomenon, occupying its own slot among many other
such kinds. In Aristotle's formulation, one needs to think of man as a certain distinctive kind of animal. It is not
enough to think of man as the kind of which these are examples.293 For, that would not distinguish a thought about
man from a thought about animal.
This third difference stems from the care Aristotle takes in separating thought and experience. From his perspective,
the ordinary person's dealings with examples may give him good grounds for thinking that there is indeed a kind of
this type with which he is interacting. But his grasp on the kind must be general and cannot be constituted simply by
his grasp on the phrase ‘that of which these are examples’. He needs some general way to characterize the causal
source of his information, although this need not involve any claims about its hidden determining basic features.294
To summarize (1)–(3): We may, in Aristotle's view, at the beginning of an enquiry be agnostic or mistaken about the
basic internal features of the kind with which we interact. Indeed, we may not know that the kind has a basic internal
feature at all. So, it is no objection to Aristotle's account that we, as thinkers, ‘very often have the structure of the
things we refer to dead wrong’.295 For, all that is required is that we have received enough information from our
interactions with the kind to be in a position from which we can come to have knowledge (in time) of its existence and
basic structure. There is no requirement that we already have that knowledge at the initial stage in our enquiry.
While this account is attractive, it comes with a high cost. If one accepts it, one cannot develop from a study of our
ordinary linguistic knowledge
293
Thoughts at Stage 1 of enquiry cannot (in Aristotle's account) contain indexicals referring to particular instances of the kind. For the level of conceptualization he requires of
us as thinkers precludes reference to individual cases. In Aristotle's view, to refer to a kind as ‘that kind, the one these instances instantiate’ would not (even in successful
cases) distinguish between the kinds man, animal, and mammal. In his account, more is needed to latch on to one kind, such as grasp on some features which are (i)
necessary properties and (ii) locate the kind as (e.g.) an illness or a metal, with its own slot in a relevant genus. Nor is the situation improved if we add that ‘instances are of
the same kind if they are governed by the same laws as these’. For, this mode does not differentiate man, mammal, and animal, since these are all (presumably) governed by
laws (albeit different ones). (Further, the master craftsman need have no notion that there are laws at all, even though he grasps the existence of the relevant kind.)
294
Since thought (and knowledge) is concerned with universals, the role of examples (in Aristotle's account) can only be to give evidence for the existence of a kind designated
by the term. They cannot play a constitutive role in our understanding of the kind term kind itself. (Contrast the view of the modern essentialist, as set out in Ch. 1 Sect.
1.4.)
295
Putnam, ‘Aristotle after Wittgenstein’, 129.
UNDERSTANDING, THOUGHT, AND MEANING 167
(or pre-scientific thought) the resources necessary to render coherent metaphysical essentialist claims (as my modern
essentialist does in Chapter 1). The basis for the coherence of such claims has to be found elsewhere.
We are now at the turning point in our investigation. Aristotle's discussion of natural-kind terms does not involve (I
have argued) attributing to the ordinary thinker thoughts with the degree of semantic depth required by my modern
essentialist. He cannot render essentialist claims coherent on the basis of the linguistic knowledge or a priori thoughts
of the ordinary thinker. His justification has to be found elsewhere, in an independent metaphysical account of essence
and necessity. In the next part of the book, I shall examine how far he succeeded in this project.
fundamentally misconceiving its nature? Some thought of it as a ratio of elements, or a certain type of harmony, and
lacked the resources to think of it as an actuality of a certain type of body (in the correct Aristotelian fashion). Perhaps
they belonged to a community, all of whose members lacked the resources to have Aristotelian thoughts about the soul
because they all misconceived its nature. However, notwithstanding their errors about the nature of the soul, they used
the term ‘soul’ to signify the soul. Had they failed to do so, Aristotle could not have argued that they had false beliefs
about the soul. (Or so the objection runs.296)
It is important to note that Aristotle (as I interpret him) is not vulnerable to the full force of this objection. First, he
allows that some thinkers can grasp only accidental features of a kind, while still using the relevant term meaningfully.297
However, this is only because the significance of the name is fixed by its being correlated with thoughts caused in the
form-transferring way by the relevant kind. Many people can use a natural-kind term without the proper style of
account, provided that the significance of that term is determined in the way indicated in Chapter 4. Second, to possess
an account of (e.g.) soul requires only that one has a grasp on some of its nature. It does not require that one be correct
about the precise theoretical specification of that kind: e.g. as an actuality. It is enough that one thinks of the soul as a
starting point, or substance, ‘which moves itself ’298 or ‘by which one perceives and moves’.299 For, these formulations
pick out some part of the distinctive nature of the soul.300
If there is to be a counter example to my interpretation, it will be given by describing a situation in which all of a society
(according to Aristotle)
296
Travis Butler, ‘On David Charles’ Account of Aristotle's Semantics for Simple Names', Phronesis 42 (1997), 21–34. The final move in Butler's argument could easily be
questioned. Perhaps Aristotle is intent on making the best sense he can of his predecessor's failed attempts at thoughts about the soul. For him to make sense of their views
does not require that those views (as expressed by them) make sense.
297
See Post. An. Β.8, 93a 25–7.
298 a
See Post. An. Β.8, 93 24.
299
See De An. Α.2, 403b 26 f.
300
I take Aristotle's basic understanding of ‘soul’ in De Anima to be ‘a starting point (arche ), that which makes things alive’(see Α.1, 402a 6, Α.2, 405b 11 f., Β.2, 414a 4, 12,
Β.4, 415b 8). This is further expanded in terms of ‘what makes things grow, perceive, think, move’. It is because the soul is understood in this way that all can discuss it, no
matter what their metaphysical views may be. So understood, there is no real question as to the existence of the soul (provided there are living creatures). Aristotle further
argues, dialectically (Α.1, 403a 29 ff.), that if one thinks of the soul in these ways, one cannot regard it as (e.g.) a harmony. For, to do so is to give up on the soul's role as a
self mover or starting point (Α.4, 407b 34 f., 408a 15 ff.). The formulations given in Β.1, in terms of ‘first actuality of living body’, are Aristotle's first attempts at a general,
a a
theoretically defensible, statement (logos ) of what the soul is (412 5 f., 413 9 f.: they are revised and made more precise in Β.2–3). While they do not constitute an account
of what the term ‘soul’ signifies, they do capture in Aristotle's terminology (via the idea of substance) the (generally shared) idea of the soul as a starting point. Although
earlier thinkers did not use this terminology, Aristotle takes them to have (tacitly) accepted this idea (no matter what else they said) if they allowed (in line with majority
opinion) that the soul is a starting point.
UNDERSTANDING, THOUGHT, AND MEANING 169
use a term to signify (e.g.) the soul, but none of them grasps anything of its proper nature. Thus, no one would locate
the kind in its correct genus (as a substance)301 or grasp any of its non-accidental, distinctives features. Aristotle's
discussions of earlier views of the soul do not provide such a counter example. For, as he emphasizes, he takes over
from his predecessors the characteristics that distinguish the soul (see De An. Α.1, 403b26 f.). Further, even if some of
his predecessors, on occasion, rejected the view that the soul is a substance, Aristotle gives no indication that this was
ever the majority view. Indeed, he is at pains to point out that when they thought of the soul as a ratio or harmony, they
were at odds with popular views about its nature.302
But could there be a counter example of the required type? Could Aristotle accept that a term might signify (e.g.) the
soul when no one (at that time) had a thought of the appropriate type about it? If everyone's thoughts picked out only
accidental properties, what would make their thoughts ones of the soul, rather than of (e.g.) some other, unrelated, and
possibly nonexistent entity (e.g. being an animal south of the Danube . . . )? Their understanding of the term would not
be linked with the right kind. They would not have sufficient access to the relevant form to count as having a thought
about the soul. Indeed, for this reason, their term would lack determinate significance. They would lack the
information required to carry out an investigation into the existence or nature of the relevant kind.303
This point can be generalised. To have an (Aristotelian) account of what a name for a kind signifies requires that one
thinks of it as located in an appropriate genus and possessed of some of its non-accidental properties. Thus, it is not
enough that one thinks of gold as something yellow and malleable, if one lacks the idea of the distinctive,
interconnected nature of gold as a kind of metal.304 For, in that case, one's term ‘gold’ would signify not gold, but
whatever is yellow-looking and malleable by us.305 Aristotle's
301
They would (in Aristotle's view) have succeeded in placing the soul in the right genus if they saw it as a starting point, even if they did not employ precise Aristotelian
terminology of ‘ousia ’ and ‘entelecheia ’.
302 b a b
See De An. Α.4, 407 32–408 34, esp. 407 34 ff.
303
This is not to say that Aristotle could not take such a group to be intending to talk about something of which he had a thought. But this would not require him to think that
they did in fact have a name which determinately signified that object or kind. It would rather be that he interpreted them thus to give them a determinate thought, even
when they lacked one.
304
Locke, Essay on Human Understanding, III. ix. 17. Locke lists a number of particular properties of ‘colour, weight, fusibility, and fixedness which . . . gives it the right to the
name (gold), which is therefore its nominal essence’. According to his account (Essay III. x. 18–19), we observe simply ‘a complex . . . of properties’ and have no genuine
grasp of the nature to which they belong (although we aim to fill this gap by invoking the idea of ‘the real essence’, ‘whereof we have no Idea at all’).
305
Similar points could be made about a society made up entirely of people who judged by experience not by thought. For, what would make their judgements be about gold
rather than anything that looked to them a given way?
170 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
master craftsman grasps that there is one nature (with which he interacts) in which these differing features are
interlocked. His understanding is manifested in an indefinite number of claims he can make about how the metal will
react in different situations, and what he can and cannot do to it. His grasp on the metal allows him to track gold
through a variety of actual and possible situations. This understanding grounds his ability to think of gold as a genuine
kind of metal, with its own non-accidental properties, and to signify that kind by the term ‘gold’.
In these respects, Aristotle demands more of one who masters a natural-kind term than does Locke. There is no way,
in Aristotle's account, of picking out a kind without the type of understanding enjoyed by the master craftsman: of a
kind, with a distinctive nature occupying a distinctive slot in its genus. But Aristotle does not require that at this stage
one must have the idea of a fundamental (physico-chemical) determining feature or hidden scientific structure (as
suggested by my modern essentialist). His position is importantly distinct from that occupied by my modern
essentialist and from that which Locke made his own.306 Both fail to appreciate the importance of the type of grasp on
the nature of kinds which Aristotle's master craftsman enjoys. For, he has an understanding of kinds which is more
than merely a grasp on a number of properties but does not involve the postulation of a (possibly) unknown basic
scientific essence.
306
Thus, one cannot go directly from finding difficulties with one of these views to acceptance of the other. For, to do so is to pass over Aristotle's attractive mid-position.
However, Locke made precisely this mistake in his attack on the abuse of words by Scholastic philosophers in Essay III. x. 19. So, too, does my modern essentialist in
moving directly to his own account from his rejection of the Lockean account of natural-kind terms as ‘a bundle of descriptions’.
UNDERSTANDING, THOUGHT, AND MEANING 171
the term signifies. If more is added, the additional features are not part of the account of what the name signifies. That
will remain the same throughout all stages of scientific enquiry, and will be non-committal with regard to the existence
and underlying structure of the kind.
There is an alternative version of the three-stage view. In this version, each name is originally introduced with a non-
existence-committing account of the type mentioned above. Later, as knowledge increases, the account of what the
name signifies will evolve to include additional information about the existence and even the essence of the kind. Such
information may be a feature of the later accounts, but not of the earliest one. On this view, the non-existence-
committing account will be an element in the most minimal type of account of what a name signifies, but not in
subsequent more developed ones. The essential nature of such accounts will change over time.
Does Aristotle opt for the first or second of these replies? It is not clear whether in Posterior Analytics Β.10 he is
claiming that each person's account of what a name signifies always retains a non-existence-committing core or only
that the original account of what a name signifies (when that account is first developed) always does.
The latter is the more cautious (and convincing) claim. To challenge it, one would need to find a case where knowledge
of the existence of the kind was presupposed in the type of account given when a name is introduced. This would not
be like the case described above in which the doctor points to examples and says: ‘These are instances of dropsy, a
condition with features A, B, C . . . if anything is’. For, there she could not justifiably simultaneously introduce a name
for a kind and presuppose the latter's existence.
But could there be cases where the account of what a name for a kind signifies is introduced in a way which
presupposes knowledge of the existence of the kind? Surely a master craftsman could discover the existence of a
separate kind of wood and only subsequently devise an account for the name he gives it. Here the name, and its
account, would be introduced for a kind already known to exist. (Perhaps our ancestors already knew of the existence
of some separate kinds, which they then dubbed as ‘horse’, ‘man’ . . . ) In such cases, there would not be the same type
of first stage of enquiry as is present in the doctor's investigation into dropsy.
Are there then two groups of natural-kind terms? One group functions like ‘dropsy’, the other like ‘man’ or ‘horse’?
While both may be grasped at the craftsman level without any idea of a scientific essence, only the former are non-
committal with regard to knowledge of existence? Is Aristotle focusing exclusively on the first type and (mistakenly)
ignoring the second?
This objection is powerful. It must be ceded that some names could be
172 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
introduced as names of kinds already known by the name-introducers to exist. In such cases, there is no ground for
insisting that the account of what the name signifies is neutral with regard to knowledge of existence. However, in such
cases the existence of the kind would be originally grasped by the master craftsman with an expression like ‘the kind
with the following features G, H, K . . . ’. At a stage prior to his introducing the name ‘teak’ he would need to have
established that these features cohered in the way required if there is to be a kind. Thus, prior to his introduction of the
name, he would need to establish that there is in fact a genuine unified kind with this feature. There would, thus, be a
hypothetical stage prior to his establishing the existence of the kind. This case could be described as one in which the
craftsman began with ‘a name-like expression’ (e.g.‘the kind with features A, B, and C) and then moved on to Stage 2.307 It
so happens in this case that a name-like expression rather than a name is introduced at Stage 1.
A similar story can be told in the case of ‘man’ and ‘horse’. It was surely a discovery that there was a kind which
contained individuals of different sizes, ages, colours, and sexes. This could not be established just by looking at
instances. Further, this would be a discovery whether or not one introduced the kind with the name ‘man’ or with a
name-like expression ‘kind with features G, H, K . . . ’. There will be a gap between Stage 1 and Stage 2 wherever one is
not justified in asserting solely on the basis of examples that there is a genuine kind before one. Given the constraints
on Stage 2, this will be so in every case.
307
See Post. An. Β.10 and 14.
UNDERSTANDING, THOUGHT, AND MEANING 173
According to Aristotle, at Stage 2 the enquirer has knowledge of the existence of the kind. The latter includes
knowledge (in general terms) of what treatments work and what their effects are, what will happen if a person with the
disease eats certain foods, the likely course of the condition if there is no intervention, etc. When the enquirer has this
information, she is entitled to claim to know that the kind exists. For, she has the type of sustained interaction with the
kind (conceived as a kind) required for this claim.
This stage can be separated from earlier and later ones in the same way. At Stage 1, one will have had considerably
more limited interaction with the kind. One may have been in contact with instances of the kind, but is not yet entitled
to claim to know that they form a natural grouping. For, one will not have the type of grasp on the interdependence of
symptoms required for this claim. More specifically, one will have no appropriate ground for the claim that the cases
before one form a unified kind of disease, rather than several. One will merely see a number of apparently similar
symptoms in a variety of cases. On this basis, one may conjecture that all are cases of dropsy, but need not know that
this condition actually exists.
At Stage 2, the doctor will have appropriate grounds for the claim that there is a unified condition before her, although
her grounds will not be as strong as the ones available at Stage 3. For, at the final stage, she will have an explanation (of
the appropriate type) of why the features of the condition hang together as they do, of why the condition arises, and of
why its course is as it is. When one has information of this type about the kind, one's knowledge claims about it will be
indefeasible. This knowledge will arise from the deeper type of interaction one has with the kind at Stage 3. For these
reasons, Stage 3 considerations appear to have authority over those available at Stage 2.308
308
At least in cases where there is a unified essence. For further complications, see Ch. 12, final Sects.
309
Putnam, ‘Aristotle after Wittgenstein’, 132, 134.
174 SIGNIFICATION, UNDERSTANDING, AND THOUGHT
that when one grasps the term ‘dog’, one form is transferred from the kind to the thinker. But this need not be so. In
some cases, there is not one form which is transferred but several, even though the thinker does not distinguish them.
(Indeed, in some cases, the differences may only emerge at Stage 3.)
It is not clear, however, that this is an objection to Aristotle's account (as presented here). In the case Putnam
describes, ‘dog’ could be like ‘pride’, a homonym between ‘evolutionary-dog’ and ‘molecular-dog’ (with their differing
accounts). Two forms might be transferred in different cases, even though speakers did not initially distinguish
between them. There are two forms transferred because there are two separate kinds in reality, each of which impacts
at different times on thinkers.
Putnam's examples would constitute an objection to Aristotle's actual account only if it were clear that the term ‘dog’
(as originally acquired) is (i) determinate in all respects and (ii) applicable both to evolutionary and molecular dogs. For,
this would mean that one and only one determinate form was transferred at the outset. Indeed, some will say that only
one form is transferred since thinkers (ex hypothesi) did not distinguish between these two types of dog. However,
Aristotle need not accept either that one determinate form is transferred or that the original thinkers are the final
arbiters on this issue. Indeed, he denies these claims.310 There could be two homonyms as there would be in the case of
pride (if there were no one explanation of both the types of pride mentioned in Posterior Analytics Β.13, 97b15 ff.). The
fact that thinkers confuse two types of pride in no way shows that they master one determinate form. What determines
that they grasp two names rather than one rests with reality and not with their pre-scientific intuitions.
Putnam's objection may arise from a deeper source. If there were no fact of the matter about which essences natural
kinds possess, their forms could not be individuated using Aristotle's resources. For, these depend on there being one
underlying essence which does the required work of demarcating kinds and individuating their forms. In the absence
of any such metaphysical constraint, it will rest with us to divide kinds as we decide. However, if this is Putnam's point,
it is an objection to Aristotle's metaphysical picture rather than to the theory of significance he built on these
foundations.311 (I shall return to the metaphysical issue in Chapter 13.)
310
This point also highlights the gap which divides Aristotle's picture and Locke's. For, the locus of authority for questions of significance lies (in his picture) with the world and
not with the reflective judgements of the ordinary speaker.
311
Putnam may well think that since we can only individuate the relevant forms using our conceptual resources, such forms cannot provide the basis for an account of our
thoughts or concepts. I attempt to unpick this style of argument in Chapter 13 Section 13.4.
UNDERSTANDING, THOUGHT, AND MEANING 175
6.6 Conclusion
According to my modern essentialist, the theory of meaning (or the theory of thought) enables us to render intelligible
essentialist claims. Nothing is required from a further metaphysical account of essence. In Aristotle's theory, the
situation is reversed. Far fewer demands are made of the theory of meaning. The ordinary thinker need have no notion
of the kind as possessing a hidden essence (or basic determining feature) yet to be discovered. Aristotle has to make
essentialist claims intelligible in a fundamentally different way. In his view, problems in metaphysics cannot be resolved
by attributing profound metaphysical intuitions to the ordinary thinker.312 They need to be addressed in their own
terms.
312
In the terminology of Chapter 1, Aristotle is not a modern essentialist of either a conventionalist or a democratic Kantian type. He could, of course, be an élitist Kantian,
for whom it is the thoughts of the idealized thinker (and not the pre-scientific one) which constitute truth in a given area. (See Chs. 10 and 13.)
This page intentionally left blank
II Aristotle on Denition, Essence, and Natural
Kinds
This page intentionally left blank
7 Denition and Demonstration: The Difculties
Raised in Posterior Analytics Β.3–7
7.1 Introduction
At the beginning of Β.8 Aristotle writes:
We must consider again which of these points is correct and which is not, and what a definition is and whether
there is in some way demonstration and definition of what a thing is, or in no way at all. (93a1–3)
A new start is required because he had reached an impasse at the end of the previous chapter:
From these considerations, it is evident that definition and deduction are not the same thing, and that deduction
and definition are not of the same thing; and as well as that, that definition neither demonstrates nor proves
anything, and that you cannot become aware of what a thing is either by definition or by demonstration. (92b35–8)
Aristotle proposes to avoid some of these difficulties by replacing the method of general deduction (and of division)
with a method based on demonstration.313 Thus, he writes:
One way of doing this is the way just examined—proving what a thing is via something else (i.e. another definition).
For, in the case of deducing what a thing is, the middle term must state what the thing is, and in the case of what is
proper, the middle term must be proper. This means that you will be proving one account of what it is to be the
given thing, but failing to prove another. Now, that this could not be a demonstration was said earlier: rather, it is a
general deduction concerning what it is. But let us say in what way a demonstration is possible, speaking again from
the beginning. (93a9–17)314
313
Some of these difficulties (as argued in Chapters 2 and 3) can be overcome by drawing the distinctions required by the three-stage view. However, others can only be met
by developing a more detailed account (i) of how demonstration, definition, and deduction are connected, and (ii) of how we acquire knowledge of the relevant essential
definitions.
314
The argument runs as follows (where S stands for ‘the cause is to be represented as a middle term’, V for ‘the method of general deduction is used’, and W for ‘the method
of demonstration is used’):[S → [VvW] ]But the method of general deduction is inadequate as a means of demonstrating the cause. Therefore:[S → W]So, if ‘P’ stands for ‘to
know what something is is the same as to know the cause of its being’, and RR for ‘the cause is something else and demonstrable’, the whole structure of the argument is
this:[P → [R → S] ] & [S → W].Further, since P is well supported, one can infer not only that:[P → [R → W] ]but also that W is true when R is true: the method of
demonstration is required to represent the cause in cases where this is different.
180 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
If both premisses contain what a thing is, the account of what it is to be that thing contained in the middle term will
be prior. (91a25–6)
A Φ def all C.
where ‘C’ is a term designating man, and ‘A’ designates what it is to be a man (e.g. two-footed animal).316 Of this case,
he notes:
If this is to be established by a syllogism, then ‘A’ must be predicated of all ‘B’. (91a28 f.)
315 a
Aristotle divides a number of cases relevant for his enquiry in 93 5–7.
316
By ‘φ def ’ I intend ‘belongs definitionally to’, and by ‘φ nec’ ‘belongs necessarily to’.
DEFINITION AND DEMONSTRATION 181
A Φ def all B.
B Φ def all C.
A Φ def all C.
Aristotle notes:
There will be another account [viz. of what C is] as the middle term317 [viz. an account in the form B φ def C,
intermediate between A Φ def B, and A Φ def C], which will also state what man is. So, you are assuming what one
has to prove. For, B will be what man is as well. (91a30–2)
317
Reading toutou rather than touto with the MSS and Barnes, and taking this to refer to A. Ross reads touto and takes this to refer to B, translating ‘This—viz. B—will state
the essence of man’.
318
It is important to note that in Β.4 Aristotle is concerned with conclusions which give definitions such as:Being a two-footed animal Φ def all men.He is not focusing on the
b
target he had previously taken in Β.3 in which the relevant conclusion was:A Φ necessarily to all C.where A was being two-footed, and C was being an animal (90 34–6).
These conclusions are not of the right form to be definitions, because they lack the appropriate predicational tie found in true definitions (‘in a definition, it is not the case
b
that one thing is predicated of one thing’ (90 34 f.)). In Β.4, by contrast, he is envisaging syllogisms whose conclusions are definitions of the form:A Φ def all C,where C is
the term to be defined, and the predicational tie:A Φ def all B,is appropriate for definition.
319
This mode of argument is apparent elsewhere in this chapter. In 91a33 ff., Aristotle writes:We must enquire in the case of two propositions and in what is primitive and
immediate. For, then what is being said becomes clear. Those who prove through conversion what soul is (or what man is) . . . postulate what was set out at the beginning;
for example, if someone were to require that soul is what is explanatory of its being alive, and that this is a number that moves itself; for, it is necessary to postulate that soul
just is a number that moves itself, in the sense of it being just the same thing. (91a33–8)The syllogism at issue here appears to be this:A Φ def all B.B Φ def all C.A Φ def all
C.In this case, the A-term is ‘being self-moved number’, the B-term ‘being explanatory of life’, and the C-term ‘being soul’. Aristotle insists that if:A Φ def all Cis proved,
one must assume that:B Φ def all Cinstantiates the right type of unity (91b1). But this will only be so if it is true that:B Φ def all C.If this were not so:A Φ def all Cwould not
follow, even if one assumed:A Φ def all B.As he notes, unless it is also true that:B Φ def all Cone cannot be assured of the right type of unity in the minor premiss. He then
cites the example of being an animal and being a man given above. For, here, while it is the case that:Being an animal Φ all menthis does not instantiate the required unity of
definition. The terms do not convert, and the statement is not one of identity.
182 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
In assessing this argument, it is important to note that in seeking for a definition of C's. Aristotle is looking for
something which (i) is possessed by all and only C's, and (ii) is included in the essence of C (91a15–17). (Let us call this
factor ‘A’). These are stringent demands. (i) requires ‘A’ and ‘C’ to convert (be true of all and only the same objects),
and so excludes the possibility that ‘A’ might extend further than ‘C’, as ‘animal’ extends further than ‘man’. (ii) requires
that ‘A’ should belong in the specification of C's essence (see 91b1, 7), and not merely pick out a necessary feature of C.
Thus, ‘A’ could not be ‘being capable of laughter’ even though all and only men have this capacity.
One possible reply to Aristotle's first argument in Β.4 would run as follows:
Aristotle deploys several arguments against this type of reply. The first runs as follows:
If you do not assume in this way by doubling up [viz. by taking both premisses as definitions], it will not be
necessary that A is predicated of C in the account of what it [viz. C] is, if, although A is predicated of B in what it
[viz. B] is, B is not always predicated in the what it is of the various things it is predicated of. But both premisses do
contain the what it [viz. C] is: therefore B will have to hold of C in what it [viz. C] is. (91a21–3)
A Φ def all B.
B Φ nec all C.
A Φ def all C.
will not be universally valid. Indeed, he offers a counter example in the penultimate section of this chapter, in which:
320 a
Barnes, in his commentary (p. 199), discerns a stronger argument at work in 91 22–3:[A Φ def all B] and [not[B Φ def all C]] ⊢ [not[A Φ def all C]].However, it is not
obvious that this is needed for Aristotle's argument at this point. It is not required to block the claim that one can demonstrate:A Φ def all C.by arguments of this form. Nor
is it needed to allow Aristotle to conclude—as he does later in Β.4:if you do not assume this, you will not deduce that A is what it is to be CFor, this relies only on the claim
that one cannot demonstrate:A Φ def all Cunless one has:B Φ def all Camong one's premisses.So, where does Barnes detect the stronger thesis at work in this chapter? He
offers two texts in support of his claim:[a] What a thing is is proper to it and predicated in the what it is. These [viz. what a thing is] necessarily convert. For, if A is proper to
a
C, it is clear that it (viz. A) is also proper to B, and B to C. So, they are all proper to one another. [91 15–18]But this in no way supports the claim that:A Φ def all B ⊢ B Φ
def all A. (A: being rational, B: being a man).All that it supports is:A Φ all B ⊢ B Φ all A.Since the next sentence (91a18–21) raises a different point concerning the transitivity
of ‘belonging in the what it is’, there is no support for the stronger thesis in these sentences.[b] Both will contain the what it is. Therefore B will hold of C in the what it is
[91a24–5].But it seems to be pressing the text too hard to see the following argument at work here:Suppose A φ def B, A φ def C, and not (B φ def C). By conversion, A φ
def C yields C φ def A. Since φ def is transitive, C φ def B follows from C φ def A and A φ def B. By conversion, B φ def C—which contradicts the original supposition.
Further, this interpretation cuts 91a24 f. off from the preceding sentence which gives its ground:It is not necessary that A Φ def all C, if A Φ def all B, and it is not the case
that B Φ def all C.For, this appears to be an argument merely for the weaker thesis, and not for the stronger one which Barnes detects.
184 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
If you do not assume in this way [viz. an essential middle term], you will not have deduced that A is what it is to be
C [viz. that C Φ def to A] . . . But if you do assume in this way, you will already have assumed what it is to be C: viz.
B. Hence, it has not been demonstrated: for, you have assumed what was set at the beginning. (91b7–11)
What conclusion can be drawn from this argument? There are at least two options:
(a) (more cautiously) Some definitions of this form can be demonstrated in this way, but some cannot.
DEFINITION AND DEMONSTRATION 185
(b) (more radically) No definition of this form can be demonstrated in this way because the conclusion is of the
wrong form to be the conclusion of a demonstrative syllogism.321
It seems clear from the examples given in Β.8 that Aristotle preferred the latter option.322 So, what grounds did he have
for rejecting (a)? Perhaps Xenocrates actually held that some (but not all) definitions can be demonstrated by the
method of general deduction. Indeed, one can imagine him arguing for this view as follows:
In my favoured syllogism:
A Φ def all B.
B Φ def all C.
A Φ def all C.
the A-term is ‘being a self-moved number’, B is ‘being explanatory of life’, C is ‘soul’. I agree, of course, that:
B Φ def all C
is assumed, and not proved. But this just shows that not all definitions of C can be demonstrated in this way. Some are
prior, and these cannot be proved. However, one has good reason to believe them to be true, since from them true
conclusions of the form:
A Φ def all C
actually follow. Thus, there could be demonstrative conclusions of the form:
321
This option would be compatible with allowing that some definitions are deduced. Deduction differs from demonstration in not capturing the relative priority of premisses
and conclusions.
322 a b b
For the relevant conclusions (93 30 f., 93 2 ff., 93 10 ff.) contain claims of the form:Eclipses happen to the moonorNoise occurs in the cloudswhich are not definitions of
either eclipses or thunder.
186 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
Xenocrates' point could be put like this. In Β.4 Aristotle showed that one could not both:
(1) have demonstrations whose conclusions state definitional connections:
and
(2) have in these demonstrations definitional minor premisses which are themselves (at the same time) proved:
In Β.8 Aristotle's favoured demonstrations lack definitions in both premisses and conclusions. But why drop both (1)
and (2) together? Why not give up (2), accept that there are some assumed definitions, but insist that one can
demonstrate some other definitions from them?
Some of Aristotle's arguments in Β.6 provide an answer to this form of objection. Indeed, they appear to be directed
against the type of position envisaged by Xenocrates in this (imagined) reply.
323
Aristotle begins Φ.6 as follows:Can one actually demonstrate what a thing is essentially on a supposition as follows:[1] What it is to be F is composed from the elements
which are in the essence of F and are peculiar to F.[2] Being G, H, I are the only things in the essence of F and are collectively peculiar to F.So[3] Being G, H, I is the
definition of being F. (92a6–9)Now, in this case, the assumption is a special one—one concerning the nature of definition (1). But not all of Aristotle's examples in this
chapter are of this form. Thus, his second example runs as follows:One might prove [sc. a definition] from a supposition as follows: if being bad is being divisible, and for
things which have a contrary being their contrary is contrary to them, and the good is contrary to the bad, and the divisible to the indivisible, one might prove that the good
is indivisible. (92a20–4)In this case there is no assumption about the nature of definition itself explicit in the argument. And so, whatever arguments Aristotle employs against
the latter case should be arguments against the general proposal of arriving at a conclusion of the form:A Φ def all C.from a premiss which contains a definitional term of
the form:B* Φ def all C*.where B* and C* are systematically connected (in a definitional way) with B and C.
DEFINITION AND DEMONSTRATION 187
As in a deduction you do not assume [as a premiss] an account of what it is for something to be deduced (for the
proposition on which the deduction depends is always part or whole), similarly it is not necessary for an account of
what it is to be F to be in the deduction; this should be kept separate from what is assumed in the premisses; and,
just as in answer to someone who asks whether something has been deduced we say, ‘This is what deduction is,’
similarly in answer to someone who says that what it is to be F has not been deduced we say: ‘That is right, since
this is what we assumed it is to be F’. Hence, deductions must be made without assuming accounts of what
deduction is or accounts of what it is to be particular things. (92a11–19)324
324
I understand 92a13–4 to say that no particular definition (e.g. a definition of F) need be included among the (relevant) premisses (as they are in the method of general
deduction). Rather, this sentence claims, such definitions should be established separately from such premisses and be used to confirm claims of the form: the definition of
F has been deduced. If this definition is to be established by a syllogism, the latter should not contain it among its premisses.I interpret the passage as referring to particular
a a a
definitions and not the definition of definition for three reasons:(1)In the immediate context (92 7, 9, 24) the phrase ‘what it is to be something’ refers to particular
definitions, such as may appear in the syllogisms of general deduction. It would be a major shift of levels to begin to talk now of the definition of definition.(2)Such a shift of
levels would be unmotivated in the present context. For, there is no indication that the method of general deduction either was or should be concerned with the definition of
definition. For all that Aristotle says, it aimed only to establish particular definitions.(3)A shift of levels is not required to sustain the analogy with deduction. For, that can be
preserved even if Aristotle is comparing particular definitions with the whole practice of deduction. There would still be a common element: in neither is it legitimate to
assume in advance what is to be established by the syllogisms at issue. In this way the analogy can be maintained without using the whole practice of definition as an element
in the comparison.
325
Barnes, Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 212.
326
Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 213.
188 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
(c) Still others have thought that Aristotle is insisting that if anyone wanted to demonstrate a definition they
should hold back the definition of definition in order to produce it later if challenged.327
There is, however, an alternative, more charitable, reading of this passage, and of the analogy which it suggests
between deduction and definition. Aristotle need not be taken to argue that one can never have premisses of the form:
F is defined as . . .
among one's antecedents. He is arguing rather that if one does so, one is resting on a prior and independent
understanding of what F is, which is not based on, and cannot be justified by, our understanding of this syllogism
(92a13–18). Further, if our understanding of the definition of F depends on our grasp of any type of syllogism, the
latter cannot be one which includes among its premisses definitions of F. Syllogisms more basic than these will be
required to underwrite our grasp of that definition (92a18–19).
On this interpretation, Aristotle is not arguing that we must always exclude propositions which define deduction from
the class of those from which we reason. Rather, he is saying that not all deductions can involve premisses of this type,
because our understanding of what deduction is is itself grounded in an understanding of syllogisms which do not
contain any such premisses (92a18 f.). By analogy, he will claim that our grasp of the definition of F cannot itself be
grounded in an understanding of syllogisms which include a definition of F among their premisses. For, the latter will
presuppose an account of what F is and cannot ground it. Further, if our understanding of what F is is based on any
syllogism, it cannot be one which includes this definitional connection among its premisses.
Aristotle (on this interpretation) will not simply be saying that we must always ‘hold back’ the relevant definition in
order to produce it later if challenged. Rather, he is claiming that our way to establish what F is (if the case is analogous
to that of deduction) cannot be based on a syllogism in which that definition is assumed. For, that definition has to be
secured on independent grounds. Indeed, Aristotle appears to push the analogy further (in 92a18–19). In the case of
deduction, one cannot establish what it is to be a deduction on the basis of premisses which include a definition of
deduction. Rather, we understand what this is by pointing to particular deductions (which do not include any definition
of deduction) and saying, ‘This is what deduction is’. In this way we grasp what deduction is on the
327
These criticisms assume that (pace n. 12) Aristotle is concerned with the definition of definition in this passage. However, one might devise variants of these criticisms even
if Aristotle is concerned only with particular definitions in this passage.
DEFINITION AND DEMONSTRATION 189
basis of deductions which do not themselves contain definitions of deduction. By analogy, we should grasp what the
definition of F is on the basis of a deduction which does not contain among its premisses any particular definition of
what F is. That is, our grasp of what F is (like our grasp of what deduction is) should rest on our understanding of a
deduction which does not contain the relevant definition among its premisses. If so, we must be able to grasp the
definition of F on the basis of some deductions whose premisses do not contain a definition of F. In both cases, the
relevant definition (whether of deduction or of F) will be understood on the basis of deduction which does not
contain it.328
If Aristotle accepts both these points, he is embracing a Definitional Constraint of the following form:
the appropriate method for coming to know a definition should give us grounds for the claim that this definition is
correct, and do so in a way which essentially involves the use of deduction (of some kind).
But why should Xenocrates accept these constraints? Perhaps he thought that we can just ‘see’ that certain definitions
are correct without any further support. Or perhaps he believed that these claims could be justified from resources
independent of deduction or demonstration. Why should Xenocrates accept Aristotle's analogy with deduction?
Aristotle's best reply would be to show that the preferred route to establishing particular definitions must involve
deduction of some kind. His third and fourth arguments in Β.6 engage in some measure with these issues. The third
aims to show that definitions are not demonstrated within the method of general deduction. He argues for this
conclusion as follows:
This is the case, even if you prove from a hypothesis in the following way:‘(1) That which is bad is, definitionally,
that which is divisible, and (2) For things which have a contrary being their contrary is being contrary to what they
are, and (3) The good is contrary to the bad, and the indivisible to the divisible, so it follows that being good is
being indivisible’. For, here, too, you are assuming what has to be proved. Someone will say that what is assumed is
a different term [viz. ‘bad’ and not ‘good’], and also that in demonstrations one assumes that this is true of this. But
I shall reply that you do not assume in a demonstration the same thing as the conclusion or something that has the
same account as the conclusion and converts with it. (92a20–7)
328 a a
On this understanding, ‘the something’ syllogized in 92 19 refers either to any deduction (as in 92 16) or to the type of deduction from which one can read off the
definition of F. Aristotle leaves the limits of the analogy unclear. Did he, for example, require that the premisses involved in establishing the definition of F should lack all
definitions (or only the definition of F)? The stronger requirement would parallel his injunction against including any premiss concerning the nature of deduction in a
deduction which shows the nature of deduction. The answer to this question is to be found (if at all) in his positive account in Β.8 and the following chapters.
190 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
What is the point of this argument?329 Why does it tell against Xenocrates? Consider the type of syllogism which he
favours:
in a genuine demonstration, the B-term is not the same as the A-term, nor is it a term with the same definition as
the A-term which converts with it. But in the first premiss of the case proposed:
A Φ def all B.
the A-term (being a self-moved number) has the same account as the B-term (being explanatory of life); for, the
account of the A-term is given by the account of the B-term. If so, this syllogism is not a demonstration (as I
understand them), since it violates certain structural constraints required of demonstrations.
But how deep does this argument go? Why should Xenocrates accept that definitional syllogisms have to be
demonstrations of a type which Aristotle accepts? Aristotle's point can perhaps be put as follows. Although Xenocrates
assumes that:
329
For a discussion of hypothetical syllogisms in the Topics, see P. Slomkowski's, Aristotle's Topics (Leiden, 1977).
DEFINITION AND DEMONSTRATION 191
A Φ def all C
could be equally basic. So, there appears to be no priority involved.
If this is correct, Aristotle is assuming that a definition should reveal what is prior in the relevant account and capture
what is (in some sense) basic about the kind in question. He is further assuming that the relevant type of priority will
only be captured in a demonstration. That is, one must be able to establish, in grasping a proper definition, what the
relevant basic or prior features are by showing how the relevant conclusion:
A Φ def all C
is underwritten by a more basic connection formulated in the premisses. In arguing thus, Aristotle is proposing a
Priority Condition as part of his general Definitional Constraint:
The appropriate method for arriving at a definition of C should legitimize the claim that some feature is prior to all
other features of C.
Xenocrates has two options at this point. Either he can reject the requirement that definition should capture what is
prior or he can show how to meet this requirement without dependence on demonstration. Aristotle does not consider
the first option. He must have assumed that definitions should capture what is prior in the approved way, and perhaps
that Xenocrates himself would have accepted this.330 But what of the second? Did Xenocrates have good reasons,
independent of demonstration, for taking the B-term as the more basic? Could he have found some? Certainly none
are provided. Nor is it easy to see how intuition could play this role. For, Aristotle is seeking a method which should give
us good reason to believe that certain features are basic. Merely stating truly that they are will not give us the required
knowledge. As we will see in the next Chapter, demonstration, with its connections with explanation, offers a route to
establishing what is prior to what.331
Before that, there is one further consideration relevant to definition introduced in Β.6.
330
For further discussion, see Ch. 10 Sect. 10.3.
331
In Β.8, Aristotle refers back to this passage where he notes:For, in the case of what a thing is, it is necessary for the middle term to give what a thing is . . . Hence, you will
a
prove the one but not the other instance of what it is to be the same object. Now, that this way will not be a demonstration was said earlier. (93 11–14)Here, too, he
comments that in a syllogism of the form:A Φ def all B.B Φ def all C.A Φ def all C.one will prove the conclusion and not the minor premiss, even though both give an
account of what it is to be C. His comment in Β.6 deepens our understanding of this latter point. A and B in this syllogism have the same account (logos) and are convertible.
But the presence of this feature prevents this deduction from being a genuine demonstration.
192 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
And in both these cases—if you prove by a division or by this kind of deduction in this way—there is the same
puzzle: Why will man be a two-footed terrestrial animal and not animal and terrestrial and two-footed? For, from
the assumptions there is no necessity that what is predicated turn out to be a unity. It could be like the case of
someone being musical and literate. (92a27–33)
A Φ def all B.
B Φ def all C.
A Φ def all C.
one is merely assuming that the B-term marks out a unity, and has no proof that this is so. Thus, he is introducing a
further condition, which might be called the Unity Condition as part of his Definitional Constraint:
The appropriate method for arriving at definitions should legitimize the claim that the definiens is a unity.
In Xenocrates' example, what is it that establishes that the soul is a self-moved number, and not self-moved and
number? As before, the element crucial for definition is assumed and not established by Xenocrates' method.
Aristotle employs similar arguments in Β.5. in considering the method of division. These allow us further insight into
the Unity Condition, and, more generally, into his Definitional Constraint. He had discussed the method of division in
Prior Analytics Α.31, where he provided a clear example:
One of the criticisms he employed there (Pr. An.A.31, 46b2–11) is repeated in Posterior Analytics Β.5, 91b24–7. In
division, Aristotle notes, one cannot prove that:
332 b a b
In Pr. An. 46 20–2, 46 37– 2, Aristotle argued that division is contrary to the general form of the syllogism. In a syllogism of the form required for division:All men are
animals.All animals are either mortal or immortal.All men are either mortal or immortal.the middle term (animal) is greater in extension than the first term (man). By
contrast, in the standard syllogism the middle term is less in extension than the first term. Further, the conclusion of the division syllogism is not sufficient to show that all
men are mortal. This is merely assumed (46b2–11). But what is the significance of violating these conditions on the general form of the syllogism? Perhaps it appears
important because, in these syllogisms, it is presupposed that man belongs to the genus animal (46b5–8), and this is not established by the method.
194 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
to grasp the necessity of true definition (91b24–6). Therefore, it fails to explain what is essential for the kind, and so
what is relevant for its definition.
Aristotle makes a further point, directly relevant to the Unity Condition. If one defines man as follows:
one has no reason for taking the definiens to be a genuine unity. What reason is given by this method for thinking that
this definiens is a genuine unity while musical literate thing is not (cf. 92a30–3)?
A defender of the method of division might attempt to reply to this criticism as follows: If one could establish
(possibly per impossibile) by this method that:
7.5 Summary
By the end of Β.7, Aristotle has in place the Simple Condition and the Definitional Constraint. Further, he has argued
that neither the method of division nor that of general deduction have the resources to meet the requirements set by
the Simple Condition. If they were the only methods available whereby we can arrive at definitions, we would not be
able to
196 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
‘become aware of what a thing is either by definition or demonstration’(92b35–8). What is needed is a method which
meets the Simple Condition and simultaneously satisfies the other aspects of the Definitional Constraint. This, as I
shall argue in the next Chapter, is precisely what Aristotle was attempting to discover in much of the remainder of the
Analytics.
Although the method of general deduction fails, it has one major advantage. It offers a simple way of establishing
definitions, because its conclusions are definitions. If this method fails, it might appear that one cannot use deduction
or demonstration in establishing definitions. For, if their conclusions do not contain definitions, they will not be
relevant to the definitional task. At the end of Β.7 Aristotle has arrived at an impasse. Either one uses a method (like
that of general deduction) which has definitions in the conclusion but which violates the Definitional Constraint and
the Simple Condition. Or, alternatively, one may satisfy these requirements but fail to generate the type of conclusions
needed for definitions.333 This is the dilemma that needs to be broken in Β.8 and the following chapters. We shall follow
Aristotle's attempts to do so in the next Chapter.
The Definitional Constraint and the Simple Condition have been introduced as conditions on how we come to know a
definition of a particular kind. However, it is natural to enquire whether these epistemic conditions rest on a
metaphysical conception of what features are relevant for a good definition. This question too will be addressed in the
next Chapter.
333
See Chapters 2 and 3 for further consideration of the Independence and Formal Conditions. These focus on the problems encountered if the syllogism's conclusion is not
a definition.
8 Demonstration and Denition: Aristotle's Positive
Views in Posterior Analytics Β.8–10 and Β.16–18
8.1 Introduction
Aristotle needed to find a method to establish which features of a kind define it. The definitional features, thus
secured, should be (in some way) prior and sufficient to underwrite the unity of the kind. His method should
essentially involve the use of demonstration. In this way, he could satisfy the Simple Condition and Definitional
Constraint, which he employed in his criticisms of the methods of general deduction and division.
In the context set by Β.3–7, Aristotle's aim was even more precisely defined. He had to achieve these goals in a way
which was not vulnerable to the Formal and Independence Problems (as set out in Chapter 3). Thus, he had to show
how demonstration could be of use in the definitional task, even though the relevant demonstrations did not have as
their conclusions definitions of the kind.334
Part of Aristotle's solution has already been considered.335 The conclusions of the relevant syllogisms need not contain
both definiens and definiendum, provided that they are systematically connected to the term to be defined. The relevant
link is provided by the Stage 1 account of what the term signifies. Thus, if ‘thunder’ signifies the same as ‘a certain type
of noise in the clouds’, the demonstrative conclusion:
334
The phrase ‘definitional task’ is intended to be neutral at this point as between two options: the task of searching for definitions, and the task of laying out definitions once
discovered. Demonstrations cannot contain both the term defined and its definition in the conclusion.
335
See Chs. 2 and 3 above.
198 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
springboard for an investigation into the existence and nature of the kind.336
The stage is now set for Aristotle's attempt to satisfy his own Simple Condition and Definitional Constraint. I shall first
consider his discussion in Β.8, 93a16–b14. Investigation of the demonstrations used there (Section 8.2) and in Β.16–17
(Section 8.3) will enable us to understand part of his strategy for connecting definition and explanation in Posterior
Analytics Β. But the resulting picture is more complicated than it might at first seem (Sections 8.4 and 8.5).
336
More precisely, they fulfil two roles:(a)They give the basis for an appropriately articulated two-term statement which is the starting point for a search for the relevant middle
term (which explains why the two terms are so connected).and(b) They indicate an as yet not fully specified type of (e.g.) noise, which can be specified further at the second
and third stage of enquiry.
337
The precise logical form of these syllogisms has been the subject of much discussion. I assume (for present purposes) that they are in the Barbara form, and contain no
singular terms. Thus, I prefer to construe reference to the moon as to (e.g.) the moon in certain stages of its career.
DEMONSTRATION AND DEFINITION 199
In these examples, although an effect is demonstrated, the conclusions do not contain definitions.338 Even when the
term being defined (e.g. ‘eclipse’) appears in the conclusion, the latter is not a definition of eclipse (or even of eclipse of
the moon).
Why is this method preferable to that involving general deductions? In these demonstrations, the middle term (e.g.
‘fire-quenching’) specifies the efficient cause of:
(1) an eclipse of the moon
and
(3) noise occurring in the clouds
We can answer the ‘Why?’ question by giving the efficient cause of the phenomenon specified in the conclusion.
The causal order displayed in these demonstrations is relevant to the issue of priority encapsulated in the Simple
Condition. In the case of thunder, the quenching of fire is causally more basic than the occurrence of noise in the
clouds, because the former is the efficient cause of the latter.339 This asymmetry is captured in syllogism (2), but not in
the syllogisms of the method of general deduction. For, in the syllogism:
338 b a
In this syllogism, I take the conclusion reached at 93 10 f. not to be of the form:Thunder is noise in the clouds.It should be noted, however, that in Β.10, 94 7–9, Aristotle
might appear to take this to be the conclusion ‘of the demonstration of the what it is’. Is Aristotle's view inconsistent? Perhaps Aristotle is not over-concerned with the
precise nature of the syllogism involved. (On these issues, see J. L. Ackrill, ‘Aristotle's Theory of Definition’ in Berti (ed.), Aristotle on Science, 359–63.)However, in Β.10, 94a8
‘this’ can refer either to the phrase ‘noise in the clouds’ or to ‘thunder is noise in the clouds’. The former seems preferable because it keeps the terms of the syllogism the
a
same as those specified in 94 4–7:‘noise’, ‘fire being quenched’, ‘the clouds’. To suppose otherwise is to deprive ‘the clouds’ of the status as a separate term which it clearly
a b b
has in 94 4 ff. and 93 9 ff.There remains a problem concerning the substitution of ‘noise’ and ‘thunder’ in 93 9 ff. But this is a different issue, related to the permissible
substitution of names and (parts of) accounts of what names signify.
339
In this Chapter, I use interchangeably as translations for ‘aition’, ‘cause’, ‘causal explanation’, and ‘explanation’. This issue is discussed in more detail in Chapter 10.
200 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
premiss as prior to the conclusion. By contrast, through the practice of demonstration we grasp that a feature is
definitionally prior because it is prior in the order of efficient causation. The quenching of fire is the start of a causal
process which culminates in noise occurring in the clouds.
Why, for Aristotle, should our definitional practices depend on our way of explaining phenomena? It is not merely that
we know that certain features are definitionally prior because they are causally prior (Β.8, 93a3–5). Rather, as he remarks
in Posterior Analytics Α.2, 71b31:
The order of definitional priority is determined by the order of causation. Fire being quenched is definitionally prior to
noise in the clouds because it is causally prior. It is the efficient cause. What it is to be something (as captured in the
definition) and the basic relevant cause are one and the same (Β.2, 90a14–15).340 The dependence of our practice of
definition on that of explanation reflects a metaphysical interconnection between essence and causation.341
We were prepared for a connection between defining and explaining by Aristotle's remarks in Posterior Analytics Β.6.
There, he suggested that there can be no account of particular definitions in terms independent of demonstration.
Since demonstration captures the order of causation, there can be no account of particular definitions which is
independent of the causal order.342 In giving demonstrations we track, in the case of a kind, the metaphysical order of
causation back to one cause of all its relevant necessary features. Had the order of causation not been connected in this
way to the theory of definition, it would be (at least, epistemically) possible for there to be an alternative route to find
what is definitionally prior. For, if definitional priority were not determined by causal priority, it would be (in principle)
possible for us to come to know the former by a route independent of the latter. Aristotle, as we noted above, does not
seriously consider the possibility of an alternative epistemic route of this type. So, his preference for the method of
demonstration is, it appears, based on his assumption that the order of definition is metaphysically dependent on the
order of causation. This is why we need to engage in demonstration to establish correct definitions.343
340
Equally, since ‘thunder’ is taken to be equivalent in meaning to ‘noise in the clouds’, the quenching of fire is also definitionally prior to thunder.
341
I use the terms ‘practice of defining’ and ‘practice of explaining’ to separate what we do in giving definitions/explanations from the subject matter of such definitions and
explanations: essences and explananda / explanantia (or causes/effects).
342
See Ch. 7.
343
It may be objected that Aristotle's discussion of nous in the final chapter of the Analytics shows a route to grasp definitions which is independent of the theory of
demonstration. I shall argue in Chapter 10 that this is not so. However, the present focus is restricted to the preceding chapters of Post. An. Β.
DEMONSTRATION AND DEFINITION 201
Aristotle's remarks elsewhere suggest the same view. In Β.16 (98b19–21) he contrasts the syllogism which demonstrates
the cause:
It is clear that being screened by the earth (B) is the cause of the eclipse (A) and not vice versa: for, B is specified in
the account of A, so that it is obvious that the latter is known via the former and not vice versa. (98b21–4)
The order of efficient causation is clear because it is captured in the order of definition. But this, as we can now see, is
because the order of definition is determined by the order of causation. The stars' position is definitionally prior to
their failure to twinkle because the former is the efficient cause of the latter.344 Here, too, the interdependence of our
practices of definition and explanation reflects a metaphysical connection between essence and explanans/cause.
Other features of Aristotle's method rest on the same view. His ‘immediate propositions’ are a case in point (see Β.8,
93a36). We reach, in giving explanations, an immediate proposition when there is no further cause which connects
(e.g.):
(1) deprivation of light and the earth screening (93a30–6)
344 b
In Β.16, 98 22 ff. Aristotle writes:That the eclipse is not the cause of its being in between but the latter of the eclipse is clear; for, being in between is in the definition of
eclipse, so that the latter is known by means of the former and not vice versa.This might appear to take the order of definition to explain the order of causality (in opposition
to the thesis developed above). However, Aristotle notes in this passage not that A causes B because A is used to define B, but rather that it is obvious that A causes B because
A is used to define B. Obviousness is an epistemic notion, which reflects the order of our knowledge. But this is fully consistent with the line of interpretation developed to
understand Β.8–10, which concerns the metaphysical order of definition.
202 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
or
(2) noise and fire being quenched.
If there were a further cause, our investigation would be incomplete until we discovered it (93b12–14). Immediate
propositions are bedrock from a causal point of view. They describe a direct, unmediated, causal connection. No
further cause can be invoked to account for the connection they express.345 In Β.8 two features are central to the
examples of demonstration:
(1) In discovering the answer to the ‘Why?’ question, we trace the pattern and order of efficient causation.
(2) In discovering the answer to the ‘Why?’ question, we find at the end of our enquiry an immediate proposition.
At this point, there is no further causal relation to be discovered relevant to the effect in question.
In both examples, the relevant causal pattern is one of efficient causation. By following this, we come to know the
essence of the phenomenon in question. Here, what is definitionally prior (viz. the essence) is determined by what is
causally prior.
A further example of this order of determination is suggested by Aristotle's identification of the essence with the cause
(Β.290a14–15, see also the epistemic version in Β.893a3–4). If one traces back the relevant causal line from the effect,
one will find one feature (the cause) which explains why (in the case of thunder) noise occurs in the clouds. This feature
will also explain why thunder possesses its other necessary properties: why it is accompanied by lightning (for
example), or why it is noisy. For, the presence of these properties will be explained because the fire, when quenched,
produces noise and lightning. In this way, there is one efficient cause which brings about all the other necessary
properties of thunder. This efficient cause would be discovered whichever of the relevant necessary properties
345
In these examples of immediate propositions, we find two distinct phenomena which are immediately related. The cause in these cases is other than the phenomenon caused
(93b 19, cf. 93a 7), as fire being quenched is other than noise. As such, immediate propositions of this type are different in kind from the cases discussed in Β.9, where Aristotle
is concerned (93b 21–5) with primary objects which are identical with their causes, or essences. It is crucial to separate immediate or primary objects (which are identical with
their essences (93b 21–5)) from immediate propositions which state unmediated (causal) connections between distinct phenomena. (There may be a class of immediate
propositions which are concerned with the relation between primary objects and their essences. If so, they will be a subclass of immediate propositions, whose other species
will involve cases where the kinds or objects are distinct from their causes, but are non-mediately connected with them.) These two sets of cases are distinct, and confusion
results if they are conflated. For a contrasting view, see R. Bolton's paper ‘Definition and Scientific Method in Aristotle's Posterior Analytics and the Generation of Animals ’, in
A. Gotthelf and J. Lennox (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology (Cambridge, 1987), 138–42.
DEMONSTRATION AND DEFINITION 203
had been the starting point of one's enquiry. For, it is the common cause of all the relevant features. Thus, the essence
is the one cause of all the kind's derived necessary properties.
Aristotle, armed with the method of demonstration, can satisfy the requirements of his own Simple Condition.
Thunder is a unity because there is one common efficient cause which explains the presence of its necessary properties.
It is because fire is quenched that there is noise in the clouds, noise accompanied by lightning, etc. The presence of this
prior feature underwrites the unity of the kind. Similarly in the case of man. Aristotle had asked: why do all the
following properties belong to man:
their force. The reasonable conclusion might have been that Aristotle's own requirements could not be met. Perhaps
he should have jettisoned them and retained either the method of general deduction or division.
The grounds for Aristotle's preference for the method of demonstration have now become clear. He can use it to
establish particular definitions because it will show which features are the causally basic, unifying features of the kind.
Features cannot be known to be prior in this way unless they are seen as the basis for demonstrative explanation of the
appropriate type. Without this, there would be no way to know which features are definitional. As Aristotle comments
in his concluding remarks in Β.8:
In cases where the cause is different from the effect, it is not possible to know what it is without demonstration, but
there is no demonstration of it.(93b18 f.)
Through giving demonstrations, we can use the notions of causal priority and of one unified cause to capture what is
definitionally prior and to underwrite the unity of the definiendum. Further, the success of this method is non-accidental,
since its epistemic virtues reflect the metaphysical dependence of definition on causation. In these respects, it is clearly
preferable to the method of general deduction.
Aristotle's basic model has many gaps. In the cases so far considered, he has focused on examples involving efficient
causation. Can this model be extended to cases involving other types of cause (see Sect. 8.5)? Nor have we understood
other central aspects of the model. Why are certain features taken as the explananda? What constrains the appropriate
causal connections? However, despite these gaps, we can reach an interim conclusion: In Aristotle's account causal
priority (of some form) determines (in some measure) what is definitionally prior. In this way, our practice of definition
rests on, and is partially determined by, our practice of explanation.
In the next Section, I shall investigate further the type of causal explanation which Aristotle employs in these contexts.
It will soon become apparent that the connection between defining and explaining is more complicated than has so far
been suggested. For, it turns out that it is appropriate to use certain forms of causal explanation because they are the
right ones to yield definitions.
of these passages may shed more light on the procedure he employed to satisfy the Definitional Constraint. For,
several aspects were left obscure in Β.8–10.346
In Β.16–18 Aristotle considers two questions about causal explanation:
(A) If the explanandum is present, is the explanans always present?
(B) If the explanans is present, is the explanandum always present?
In Aristotle's own terminology, the relevant question is as follows:
(A*) If there is an eclipse, is there always a screening by the earth?
(B*) If there is a screening by the earth, is there always an eclipse?
As he puts it, do the relevant terms (‘eclipse’, ‘interposition of the moon’) convert? We might say: is the occurrence of
the explanans (considered as a type) both necessary and sufficient for the occurrence of the explanandum (as a type)? (cf.
98a35–b4)
Aristotle's answers are cautious but revealing. One of his examples is biological. He asks:
Why do trees shed their leaves? If this is because of solidification of the sap, then if a tree sheds its leaves,
solidification must belong to it. And if solidification occurs, in a tree, not just in anything you like, it must shed its
leaves. (98b36–8)
Aristotle's requirement that the terms involved be equal in extension and convert cannot apply to all the cases of causal
explanation he considers.347 For, when the Athenians come to be at war with the Persians because they are the first to
attack (Β.11, 94b1 f.), the two terms cited (‘being at war’ and ‘being the first to attack’) do not convert. Since a war of
this type needs at least two opponents, the aggressors and those who respond to aggression, not all who are at war can
be the aggressors.348 More generally, there are many different ways to come to be at war. So, the question is acute: Why
is conversion required in the particular examples cited in Β.16?
It is not immediately clear that the terms cited in the example above (‘sap solidification’, ‘leaf loss’) do convert. Do
trees (or even broad-leaved trees) lose their leaves only when their sap solidifies? Aristotle is raising exactly this question
when he asks:
346
Thus, it is not clear whether all or any of the terms convert.
347
Barnes argues powerfully that conversion is not the rule in all demonstrations (Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 258–9). The substantial issue is whether there is any non-trivial
group of demonstrations which require conversion.
348 b
Another example of a causal explanation which does not meet this stringent requirement is given in Post. An. Β.17, 99 4–5 in his discussion of the causes of longevity in
different species.
206 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
is it true that if the explanandum (e.g. plants shedding their leaves) holds, the explanans also holds (e.g. their sap
solidifying)? (98a36–8; see 98b30–2)
Surely there can be different explanations of why such trees lose their leaves. Perhaps, as Aristotle comments:
It is necessary that something explanatory is present, but not that everything which might be a cause is present.
(98b30–1)
In some cases, sap solidification might lead to leaf loss, in others the use of pesticide or the presence of disease (as
there might be various explanations of why people are at war).349
There is a related question about the sufficiency of the proposed explanations. Why is it that if trees' sap solidifies, they
must shed their leaves? Surely we can explain why some trees shed their leaves by saying:
without thinking that in every case when a tree's sap solidifies it will lose its leaves?
Aristotle has offered an answer to these questions given (in part) in the words already cited:
if solidification occurs, in a tree, not just in anything you like, it must shed its leaves. (98b36–8)
His concern is to explain why (e.g. broad-leaved) trees as such and universally (98b34) lose their leaves. He aims to find an
explanation of why this happens to all such trees solely in virtue of their being such trees. Hence, if their sap could
solidify without their leaves falling, one would not have explained universally why trees of this kind as such lose their
leaves. One might, of course, have explained why these trees in certain conditions (e.g. when grown near a chemical
plant) lose their leaves, but one could not explain why all broad-leaved trees as such do so.350
This strategy can be used to defend Aristotle's view that this type of explanation should provide necessary conditions
for the occurrence of the effect. He is aiming at giving an explanation of the following form:
In all members of one kind K, a feature F which belongs to them as such always has one and only one cause C.
349
Equally, there could be a case where trees shed their leaves from differing causes on differing occasions: e.g. in some cases because of chemical pollution, in others because
of sap solidification. One cannot avoid this problem solely by limiting the cases in question to those involving trees (as Barnes suggests, Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 253).
350
Contrast the case of the Athenians coming to be at war with the Persians. There might well be no explanation of why the Athenians came to be at war, solely in virtue of
their being Athenians. One would typically need to refer to something they had done (e.g. supported the Milesians), and not just to their nature.
DEMONSTRATION AND DEFINITION 207
In all broad-leaved trees, leaf loss (if it belongs to them all in virtue of their being broad-leaved trees) will always and
only occur because of sap solidification. Explanations of this form will fail if some such trees' sap can solidify without
their shedding their leaves. For, then, sap solidification alone will not account for their leaf loss. Equally, they will fail if
some of their leaves can fall without their sap solidifying. Explanations of the desired form will apply to all actual and
possible cases of broad-leaved trees losing their leaves. Otherwise, they cannot apply to all these trees solely in virtue of
their being such trees, but only to such trees in certain conditions.
Aristotle clarifies his favoured explanatory structure further in Β.17, 99a23–9. He notes that ‘shedding leaves’ applies to
all vines, but that it extends further to figs and other types of tree. Thus, he writes:
Shedding leaves [viz. B term] holds universally of all figs [D term]—for, I call universal that with which they do not
convert, and primitive universal that with which severally they do not convert, but with which, taken together, they do
convert and have the same extension. (99a32–5)
In this case, shedding leaves will be the primitive universal which applies to all and only trees of a given type (e.g. broad-
leaved trees) which comprise the class of figs, vines, etc. What needs to be explained is why:
351
This will be a case of a per se 2 predication: i.e. one where it is in the nature of A to belong to B. By contrast, per se 1 predications are those where it is in the nature of B's
that A's belong to them.
208 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
where the feature to be explained is one which belongs to the kind per se, the explanans must also belong to that kind in
the same way. So, the explanans and explanandum must convert, because both are to be understood as belonging per se to
the same kind. In this way, the explanations at issue are able to meet the convertibility requirements.
This form of explanation of why leaf-shedding of this type occurs in broad-leaved trees will invoke the fundamental
essence of this type of leaf-shedding.352 The explanatory syllogism will be the basis of an account of what this type of
shedding leaves is. As Aristotle says:
What is shedding leaves? The solidifying of sap at the connection of the seed. (99a28 f.)
352
It might also be in the nature of broad-leafed trees to shed their leaves. In that case, there would be a per se 1 predication as well. However, this is not required in this
context. One per se connection is enough for Aristotle's purposes.
353
This claim is only that if a predicate belongs to its subject primitively, it is coextensive with it. This does not entail the far stronger claim (favoured by Zabarella in Opera Logica
(Frankfurt, 1608) ) that if a predicate belongs to two subjects non-primitively, it must belong to a common kind which embraces these two subjects primitively. Some
predicates may not belong primitively to one proper subject at all. At best, like longevity, they may belong only to a conjunction of such subjects. Zabarella's proposal is
effectively criticized by Barnes (in Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 258), who concludes that primitiveness plays no role in generating commensurate universals. If my weaker
construal of primitiveness is correct, primitive universals will be commensurate, and explananda of this sort will lead to definitions.
DEMONSTRATION AND DEFINITION 209
and kinds (such as primitive universals) which are specified in such a way as to ensure their convertibility.
Nor need this method be confined to the definition of properties. If the feature to be explained is one which is used to
differentiate the kind, the explanation will advert to the basic essence of the kind. Explanations of this type may result
in definitions either of the feature or the kind. This is because the explananda are either the differentiae of a kind or a
property which is itself defined as belonging to that kind. In the former case one will arrive at the essence of the kind,
in the latter at the definition of the feature which belongs to the kind.
If we find structural explanations we will uncover definitions because their explananda are per se connected (in the ways
indicated). It appears that, at this point, the practice of explanation depends on that of definition. For the per se
connections the former invokes rest on definitional connections between feature and kind. Indeed, this is what
distinguishes this form of explanation from the type involved in explaining why the Athenians come to be at war with
the Persians.
This appearance is, I shall argue, confirmed by Aristotle's more detailed discussion of this form of explanation in the
remainder of Β.16 and Β.17.
In one kind, one feature F of the appropriate type has one and only one cause C
emerges in Aristotle's discussion of a variety of cases which appear to threaten it. In the first group, leaf-shedding turns
out not to be a unified phenomenon because there are two different explanations of why it can occur in what is one
kind. Here, we should distinguish between natural and diseased leaf-shedding. If we find ‘two accounts or more [of the
phenomenon], it is clear that what we are seeking is not a single thing but several’. For example, if intolerance of insult
and indifference to fortune have a different account, there will be two types (eide) of pride (97b13–25). The absence of
one feature jointly necessary and sufficient to explain all cases of pride would show that there are in fact two types of
pride. Here, Aristotle accepts a principle of the following form:
P(1) If objects ki . . .kn are the same in species and there is a different explanation of why they possess a given
property, there is more than one property to be explained.
210 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
Aristotle maintains the principle of conversion of cause and effect by separating various types of effect.
In a second group of cases, leaf-shedding might turn out not to belong per se to just one kind, such as figs. It belongs
instead per se to a wider kind which involves figs and other trees as well. Aristotle gives a mathematical as well as a
biological example.354 Here, his strategy is to find a wider kind to which the relevant feature primitively belongs per se. In
this way, he maintains his basic thesis that for one kind there is one explanation of the relevant phenomenon by
introducing a wider kind to which the feature belongs per se.
The second type of case has the following structure:
A Φ all B.
B Φ all and only D.
A Φ all D.
354
It runs as follows:(1)Having external angles equal to four right angles applies to all triangles.Here, the feature to be explained applies more widely than to the class of
triangles. Aristotle's response is to argue that having external angles equal to four right angles applies to a larger group consisting of triangles, quadrangles, and perhaps
others. Thus, we should say (according to Aristotle):(2)Having external angles equal to four right angles applies to group G consisting of triangles, quadrangles . . .Group G,
which consists of triangles, quadrangles, etc., is co-extensive with the things that have external angles equal to four right-angles. Thus, the middle term which explains why
(B) is true will also be co-extensive with this larger group. For, the latter is the group to which the property of having an angle sum equal to four right angles applies as such.
355
This pattern is also to be found in the biological cases of leaf-shedding mentioned above.
DEMONSTRATION AND DEFINITION 211
Here, B is the cause of A's being D, but not of everything which is D. Aristotle introduces the case as follows:
But 356 indeed in some cases B is the cause of D's being A [with emphasis on the D]. In such cases A must extend
further than B. If it did not, what reason is there for B to be the cause of this [viz. of A's belonging to all D]?
(99a35–7)
A Φ all E.
while denying that:
E Φ all A. (99a39–b1)
For, if E's formed the same group as D's (viz the E* group) and:
A Φ all E*s.
were true, there would be commensurate universals of the form:
356 a a
I read in 99 35 ff., ‘τοiotaς δὲ ὴδD’ (or ‘τοις δὲ’) rather than ‘τοις δὴ’ as in the MSS, and take this to introduce a second case (distinct from that discussed in 99 30–5,
where all the terms convert when the appropriate group is specified). The second case introduced in 99a 36 cannot have this feature since the A and B terms do not convert.
There must, therefore, be a break between these two passages. Since in the MSS ‘δε’ and ‘δη’ are both written in the same way, there is no better evidence for the present text
a
than for my emendation. On the standard reading nothing is added by saying that B is the cause of D's being A, since this is already implicit in 99 30–3.
357
I translate ‘ti māllon aition estai touto ekeinou ’ as ‘why is this [viz. B] rather the cause of that [viz. D's being A]?’, and understand the implied contrast to be ‘rather than B's being
the cause of something other than D's being A’. The contrast should not be with ‘rather than D's being A being the cause of B’. As Ross (Aristotle's Prior and Posterior Analytics,
673) and Barnes (Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 258 ff.) note, Aristotle has several good reasons to rule out the latter possibility.
212 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
and there would be one explanation of why A belongs to all D and all E (99b1 f.). But if E is (as we shall assume) a
unified group distinct from D (with its own separate explanation), there will not be commensurate universals of the
form:
But will E be some one thing? We must enquire into this. Let it be C. (99b3 f.)
This caveat prevents one from concluding that E must be a unified group simply because it plays the specified role in
explanation. E might turn out not to be a unified kind, but one which requires further division. Alternatively E might
fall below the level of unified kinds. Aristotle's preferred form of explanation (of per se features via necessary and
sufficient conditions) is itself constrained by the demand that the feature to be explained belong to a genuine unity.358
In this type of case, there is one property to be explained (e.g. longevity), but the explanation is different for different
animals (e.g. quadrupeds and birds). The absence of one feature necessary and sufficient to explain the presence of this
property in all cases forces us to distinguish between the kinds in question. There can indeed be, as Aristotle says:
several explanations of the same thing, but not for things of the same sort.(99b4–6)
There will be differences between the kinds of object under investigation in all cases where the same property is
present but its presence is differently explained.
In this case, Aristotle commits himself to a further principle:
P(2) If the same property belongs to objects ki . . .kn but its presence is differently explained, objects ki . . .kn must
differ in species (or in genus).
This thesis is also a reflection of his fundamental principle that for one kind K there is one and only one explanation of
one genuine feature F. Here, this principle is used to differentiate kinds and not features. If the explanation is different
for:
358 a
There is no need to interpret these lines as indicating ‘Aristotle's awareness of the weakness of the preceding lines’ (as Barnes suggests in his note on 99 38, Aristotle's
Posterior Analytics, 257.) They show rather the complexity of the conditions he required of the appropriate explanation.
DEMONSTRATION AND DEFINITION 213
A Φ all E.
and
A Φ all D.
the kinds involved must be distinct (99b2–4).
In the third group of cases, one would not arrive at a definition of longevity, because it does not belong per se to one
kind. Cause and effect fail to convert. There is no one element which explains longevity in kinds D and E.
Explanations of this type cannot reveal the structure or definition of longevity. Nor need they generate definitions of
the varying kinds (D and E), unless the relevant feature happens to be among the differentiae of these kinds. Although
acceptance of P(2) forces one to separate and eventually define kinds when there are two explanations of the presence
of one property, it need not lead us directly to a definition of either kind or feature. We do not automatically have in the
third case a structural explanation of either the property or the kind.
This leads us to focus on a crucial point. The explananda in structural explanations are ones which belong to all the
relevant kinds per se. Either the property is defined in terms of its belonging to a given kind, or the kind is defined in
terms of its possessing certain properties. This type of explanation is distinguished (in part) by the fact that its
explananda are definitionally connected. The explananda have to be of this type if they are to fit the convertibility
schemata required if we are to discover essences by this route. When this is not so (as in the third case), we will no
longer arrive at definitions of either property or kind. We need to think of (e.g.) leaf-shedding as leaf-shedding-in-
these-trees for it to be the type of primitive universal required as an explanandum. In this way, Aristotle's favoured type
of structural explanation appears to rest on explananda provided by our practices of definition (via their concern with
the notion of primitive universals).
However, the arguments of 8.3 and 8.4 are incomplete. Aristotle needs to make clear how the practice of definition
selects various features as the appropriate explananda. For, without that addition, some might interpret Aristotle as
follows: In relying on definitional connections in arriving at the relevant explananda we are merely using results which
are, at basis, dependent on our practice of explanation. No doubt, we can rely (epistemically) on definitional
connections in looking for the explananda. But what makes these connections definitional is their (e.g.) being the
immediate consequence of one underlying common cause. Similarly, it may be said, convertibility should be seen as the
consequence of the presence of this type of causal structure. It need not be motivated by independent non-explanatory
definitional resources. Perhaps our practice of definition rests throughout on that of explanation (without reciprocal
support).
In the next Chapter, I shall seek to make good this lacuna. The relevant explananda are (in at least some cases)
determined by aspects of the theory of definition, independent of the requirements of explanation. But to see this one
needs a fuller grasp on the role of definition in Β.13–15.
There are, nonetheless, further reasons (prior to Β.13 ff.) to think that, for Aristotle, constraints implicit in our practice
of definition are at work in determining the relevant pattern of explanation. Such constraints are not confined to the
explananda, but also underlie some of the requirements placed on the explanans. Consider cases where there are several
causal stories which explain the same phenomenon: efficient, teleological, grounding, etc. (Β.11, 94b27 f.). Here,
Aristotle suggests that there can be efficient and teleological explanations of the occurrence of thunder (94b31–4), and
notes that this problem arises for a variety of natural phenomena (94b34–6). What makes one of these causal stories the
right one to yield the definition of the kind or feature in question?
Since Aristotle identifies the answer to the ‘What is it?’ and the ‘Why?’ questions (Β.2, 90a15), it is natural to think that
only one of these causal stories gives us knowledge of the appropriate type of what the kind is. Definitions aim to give
us knowledge of what the kind or substance is (see Β.3, 90b16, Topics Ζ.4, 141a27 ff.). In the case of thunder, the
efficient cause (fire being quenched in the clouds) makes it fully intelligible to us why thunder has the other genuine (or
per se) features it has: being a noise, being accompanied by lightning, occurring under certain atmospheric conditions.
The first two are consequences of fire being quenched, the third points to the surrounding circumstances required for
fire to be quenched. By contrast, the teleological cause cited (to threaten those in Hades (94b33–4)) would not make it
clear why thunder occurs in the clouds or in certain atmospheric conditions, even if it explained why thunder was
noisy. Only one of these explanations makes the nature of the kind fully intelligible to us in the way required to answer
the ‘What is F?’ question.
This thesis can be generalized. In Aristotle's view, the efficient cause
DEMONSTRATION AND DEFINITION 215
gives the basic essence of some phenomena, the teleological cause of others (Meta. Ζ.17, 1041a28–30). This can be true
even if there is always one type of efficient and one type of teleological cause for the same phenomenon. Thus, anger
may always be brought about by (e.g.) an insult, and aim at revenge (De An. Α.1, 403a31 ff.). The latter constitutes the
essence of anger, since it is this which makes the phenomenon fully intelligible to us. Once we understand that anger
aims at revenge, we see that it has to be brought about by something which the angry person wishes to repay (e.g. an
insult). This is because revenge has to involve reacting adversely to some wrong done. By contrast, if one knew only
that a person was in a state brought about by an insult one would not thereby know that the person was looking for
revenge. In order to know that, one would also need to know some further facts about their psychology. Only the
teleological cause is sufficient by itself to make the phenomenon of anger fully intelligible to us.
A similar story can be told about the nature of (e.g.) houses, where there is one efficient cause (the art of house-
building) and one teleological cause (safety for goods, etc.), each of which by itself can explain (in some way) all the
relevant features of a house. However, only the teleological cause tells us ‘what a house is’. Why? Not solely because it
is a common cause of all the relevant features of the house.359 For, so too (ex hypothesi) is the efficient cause. There must
be further constraints at work beyond those generated by the practice of explanation alone.
In the case of the house, the further element could be introduced as follows. If one had only the efficient causal story,
something would remain unclear: why the art of building is the kind of art it is. One would merely take for granted (as
an unexplained datum) why this art functions as it does. The teleological account is preferable because it shows why
the efficient cause is as it is. Only one of these causal stories makes the nature of the phenomenon fully intelligible to us
in the way required to answer the ‘What is F?’ question. Here, background assumptions about the requirements of
good definition select which causal story is the relevant one for definitional purposes.360
Elsewhere, Aristotle appears to represent our practice of explanation as dependent on that of definition. Consider his
contention that there cannot be explanatory chains of infinite length (Α.19, 82a7 f).361 He argues for this as follows: If
there were such chains, one could not arrive at knowledge of what the kinds are or of their definitions (Α.22,
82b37–83a1). Rather, definitions must be of finite length if we are to grasp them (see also 83b4–8). This argument is, at
first glance, weak. Why would it follow from the fact
359 a
See, e.g. Meta. Η.2, 1043 15 ff.
360
For further discussion of this point, see Ch. 10.
361
I am indebted at this point to discussion with Henry Mendell.
216 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
that definitions cannot be of infinite length that demonstrations cannot be? What prevents there being explanations of
infinite length which do not begin with definitions? Why should definition play this central role in the practice of
demonstration?
The argument of the previous paragraph suggests an answer to these questions. Demonstrations, as Aristotle
conceives them, must begin with statements which concern the essences of the kinds in question. For, this is a
constraint on what demonstrating is. To demonstrate is to give an argument which begins with a statement about a
causally basic (non-demonstrable) feature which can answer the ‘What is F?’ question. Thus, the demonstratively basic
statement must be finite in length; for, otherwise it could not make the phenomenon fully intelligible to us. If
demonstrations are to meet this requirement, they must begin with definitions which reveal the relevant essences.
This argument is revealing. Aristotle does not attempt to show that every science must contain a set of basic
propositions which are underivable from the remainder, and then argue that these propositions must be definitions
which can satisfactorily answer the ‘What is F?’ question. That is, he does not impose a structural constraint on
demonstration, and argue that only a subclass of knowable propositions can meet it.362 Rather, he begins with the
substantial claim that demonstrations must begin with statements concerning essences, which (if they are to answer
satisfactorily the ‘What is F?’ question) must be knowable by us. If so, the practice of demonstration is once again
constrained by considerations drawn from our practice as definers.
These requirements serve to make the relevant type of structural explanation more determinate. The cause and effect
convert, and both should belong per se to the kind. The cause cited must provide the basis for an answer to the relevant
‘What is F?’ question. That is, there must be one non-complex feature which is the common cause of (e.g.) the kind's
other per se properties. Further, the nature of the common cause should not
362
For a contrasting view, see Robin Smith's paper ‘Immediate Propositions and Aristotle's Proof Theory’, Ancient Philosophy 6 (1986), 47–55. Smith argues convincingly that
Aristotle's arguments in Post. An. Α.19–22 cannot depend on the claim that every regress of propositions must end in a basic set of premisses which are self-evident or
epistemically immediate. For, Aristotle claims only that the starting points are definitions which reveal essences, and makes no reference to the epistemic notion of self-
evidence in this passage. However, Smith concludes from this that the relevant starting points must merely be ones not deducible from any other true proposition, and then
notes that there is no obvious step from this claim to any which concern (non-demonstrative) knowledge of definitions. On my view, the starting points are non-demonstrable
because they are not the causal consequences of any further claim. Also, if they are to be starting points of demonstration, they must (a) be non-demonstrable and (b) state the
relevant basic essence. If the relevant essences are the objects of non-demonstrative knowledge (as emerges in Post. An. Β.8–10), the starting points of demonstration will
themselves be capable of being known non-demonstratively.
DEMONSTRATION AND DEFINITION 217
stand in need of any further explanation. Rather, it should serve to make the whole phenomenon fully intelligible to us.
These latter requirements follow from the demand that the relevant basic cause be used as the basis of the definition of
the phenomenon.
Essences, in this account, are the starting points of demonstration and answer the ‘What is F?’ question. This
conception of essence (and of definition) explains other features of Aristotle's explanatory practices. Thus, he insists
that demonstrations must begin with one common cause and not a conjunction or disjunction of separate causes. These
claims are natural if what is sought is the essence of the kind, a single cause which can provide the basis for the ‘What
is F?’ question. Without this assumption, there would be nothing amiss with finding several separate causes for each of
a kind's per se features. If we aim at definition, we will not be content with uncovering a conjunctive cause. For, that
would fail to make all aspects of the kind transparent. In particular, it would not explain why all its features are
interconnected in the way they are.
If this is correct, Aristotle's overall strategy can be formulated in terms of a mutual dependence between our practices
of definition and of demonstration. While some of his claims about defining follow from his views about explaining,
the constraints he imposes on structural explanation are (in some measure) grounded in the practice of definition.
Each of these practices is incomplete without resources drawn from the other.
If this general picture is correct, Aristotle's account of the interdependency of the practices of definition and of
demonstration involves a further thesis: the co-determination of essence and causation. Essences play a central role in
a certain style of causal explanation, but the relevant type of causal story itself involves essences. This metaphysical
thesis grounds Aristotle's epistemological claim that in knowing the answer to the ‘Why?’ question we know what the
kind in question is. We achieve knowledge of essences by tracing back a certain pattern of explanation to its roots in a
particular type of cause. But the relevant type of explanatory structure is one in which essences must be the basic
explanantia. Essences and structural causation stand or fall together.
These constraints arise from the practice of offering structural explanations. But, at crucial points, such explanations
involve features drawn from our practices of definition. Thus, the relevant explanatorily basic feature is selected
because it satisfies additional definitional constraints. The appropriate explanatory picture cannot be completed
without the assistance of features drawn from the theory of definition.363
There is a further feature of Aristotle's account. In it, some kinds possess certain of their features in virtue of their
belonging to wider-ranging kinds. The sub-kinds will be made what they are by their possessing distinctive unifying
explanatory features which account for their possession of their distinctive necessary properties. Equally, the kinds to
which they belong will be made what they are in the same way. Thus, both genera and species will be essentially defined
by reference to that feature which is central in the relevant type of explanation of their possession of their other
necessary properties. Thus, in addition to theses (1)–(3) above, Aristotle is committed to a further claim:
363
For future discussion of Β.2, 90a 14ff., see Ch. 10 Sect. 1.
220 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
Aristotle require that the properties which species possess are unique to that species?
(D) More generally, how is Aristotle's method of definition by genus and differentia connected to definition by causal
essence of the type discussed in this Chapter. Are these different types of definition? If so, how can the notion
of definition be dependent (in the ways suggested) on the account of explanation?
I shall examine questions (A), (C), and (D) in the next Chapter in considering Aristotle's further views of definition in
Posterior Analytics Β.13–15. Question (B) will be discussed in Chapters 10 and 11.
9 Towards a Unied Theory of Denition: Posterior
Analytics Β.13–15
9.1 Introduction
In Aristotle's account, definition and explanation are mutually dependent. His route to satisfy the Simple Condition
and the Definitional Constraint (set out in Chapter 7) essentially involves the use of features drawn from the practice
of explaining. But, as was argued in the last Chapter, the type of explanation at issue is itself constrained by the need to
define the relevant phenomenon. Neither definition nor explanation can be completed without resources drawn from
the other.
This form of interdependence between the practices of explanation and definition underlies the epistemological route
which (in Aristotle's view) leads the enquirer to discover the essences of the kinds under investigation. In his three-
stage view of scientific enquiry, Stage 3 involves explanation. Here, the enquirer discovers the essence by finding the
feature which explains why the kind is as it is. It should be no surprise that this is so, since the type of explanation
involved is itself constrained by features drawn from the practice of definition.
Does this interpretation cohere with Aristotle's discussion of definition in the intervening chapters of Posterior Analytics
Β.13–15? This question is pressing, because these chapters have sometimes been taken to contain elements
inconsistent with the explanation-involving account I have proposed of Β.8–10. In particular, it has been suggested
that:
(1) In Posterior AnalyticsΒ.13–15, Aristotle developed a separate epistemic route to answer questions concerning
existence, definition, and essence which does not involve the explanatory concerns prominent in Β.8–10 and
Β.16–18.
(2) In Posterior Analytics Β.13–15 Aristotle's metaphysical conception of the essence and definition of genera and
species is independent of the explanatory concerns introduced in Β.8–10 and Β.16–18.
Discussion of the issues raised by these claims will enable us to consider questions (A), (C), and (D), raised at the end
of the previous Chapter. For,
222 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
we shall investigate how the relevant genera and species themselves are determined and by what route their essences
are discovered. Further, we shall examine the issue (raised but not resolved in the last Chapter) of what determines the
relevant explananda in structural explanation.
How the what it is is placed in definitions (horoi)364 has been given above, as has an account of the way in which there
is or is not a demonstration or definition of the same thing. Let us now say how we should hunt out365 the things
that are predicated in the what it is. (96a20–3)
These sentences reveal the aim of Β.13: to hunt out the things that are predicated in the what it is. This goal, however, is
capable of being understood in several ways, as can be shown by considering possible answers to the following
questions:
(1) Is Aristotle in Β.13 concerned with the same definitions (or accounts of what something is) as have been
discussed in Β.8–10? Or is he concerned with different accounts of what something is, independent of, and
perhaps prior to, the explanation-involving definitions proposed in Β.8–10.366
364 b b
‘Horos’ may mean either ‘term’ (as Barnes and Ross interpret it here) or ‘definition’ (for the latter use, see Β.8, 93 38 and Β.13, 97 25). In the context of the present sentence
a
(96 20–2), the latter seems preferable for three reasons:(a)This sentence, so understood, precisely summarizes some of the results achieved in Β.8–10 (as is to be expected
given Aristotle's explicit back reference to ‘what has been said before’). Aristotle, in those chapters, had initially asked in what way there is a definition of what something is
(93a1–2), and concluded by noting several ways in which there are definitions of what something is (94a11–14).(b)So understood, it represents Aristotle as recapitulating
several of his major concerns from Β.10, where he considered both how what a thing is can be set out in definitions, and how definitions are related to demonstrations. (For
the latter, see Β.10, 94a14–16, 17–19, where the terminology is strikingly similar to that employed in the first lines of Β.13.)(c)By contrast, in the conclusion of Β.10, Aristotle
was not concerned with the narrower issue of how to express definitions by means of the terms used in demonstration. Indeed, some of the definitions considered in Β.10 are
not set out in demonstrative terms at all (94a9–10, 16–17). Even when Aristotle does consider in this chapter the relation between definition and demonstration, he does not
a
focus on the question of the relation between parts of the definition and specific demonstrative terms (see 94 1 ff.).
365 a a
For similar uses of ‘thereuein ’ meaning ‘look for’, see Post. An. Α.31, 88 3 ff., Pr. An. Α.30, 46 10–12.
366
Barnes and Ross favour the first alternative, Bolton the second (in ‘Division, définition et essence dans la science aristotelicienne’, Revue Philosophique 2(1993), 197–222).
Bolton is led to his view by noting two difficulties in the first: (a) There is a mismatch between the demonstration-based definitions of Β.8–10 and those of Β.13, in that
demonstration can be used to establish the presence of features beyond the essential ones specified in Β.13 definitions (e.g. necessary ones). (b) It is not possible to line up all
the definitions offered in Β.13 with any one type of Β.8–10 definition. I shall argue with regard to (a) that there are resources already implicit in Β.8–10-style definitions
which restrict their range to essential features, and that these draw on features only made fully explicit in Β.13. (For an indication of Aristotle's awareness of the relevant
difference, see Β.8, 93a 11–13, although it is not fully developed there.) With regard to (b), I shall argue that while sections of Β.13 may be concerned with several of the
types of definition specified in Β.8–10, these passages are not inconsistent with the earlier discussion.
TOWARDS A UNIFIED THEORY OF DEFINITION 223
(2) If Β.13 does discuss the same definitions as Β.8–10, is its role merely to offer an (epistemological) path to
discover the elements which have already been marked out as definitional by the considerations advanced in
Β.8–10? Or does it add additional (metaphysical) constraints to the account of what something is beyond those
already clearly specified in Β.8–10? If the latter, how are these additional features related to the earlier account
of what something is?367
In this Chapter, I shall argue that while Β.13 discusses the same definitions as Β.8–10, it spells out some (metaphysical)
constraints on definition which have been assumed, but not made explicit, in the earlier chapters. These latter
constraints, rightly understood, are not only fully consistent with the explanation-involving view of definition
developed in the previous Chapter, but actually amplify and deepen it. Taken together, they constitute a unified theory
of definition and explanation. If this is correct, Β.13 is not concerned with some distinct type of definition independent
of (or prior to) the explanation-invoking account developed in Β.8–10. Rather, it is permeated by the very same
explanatory concerns as underlie the earlier discussion of definition. This, at least, is what I shall attempt to establish.
The first two sentences of Β.13 set up a presumption that Aristotle remains concerned with the definitions he
discussed in Β.8–10. For, he appears to refer back to an earlier discussion of how essential features are to be placed in
definitions, and to represent Β.13 as intended to show how we should ‘hunt out’ the elements involved in those
definitions. His target now appears to be to work out how to discover the elements involved in (at least some of) the
definitions discussed in Β.8–10. He may, of course, give prominence to features of these definitions which have not
been emphasized earlier. But, nonetheless, the initial presupposition must be
367
Barnes agrees that the task of Β.13 is to arrive at Β.8–10-style definitions (Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 230), but argues that the chapter fails to do this because it does not
succeed in marking out only essential features (as opposed to necessary ones), and rather merely rests on assumptions about which features are essential (e.g. p. 231). I shall
argue that while Β.13 does depend on certain assumptions about definitions which are present in Β.8–10, it specifies the ingredients of definition in terms not fully explicit in
the earlier chapters.
224 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
that in Β.13 Aristotle is still concerned with the definitions discussed in Β.8–10.
It is, however, far from obvious that Β.13 implements this project. Indeed, the main exegetical problem becomes clear
immediately,368 when Aristotle's introduces his method of finding out what is predicated in the what it is to be something
(96a22–3) in a way which reveals the ousia, or nature, of the phenomenon (96a34 f.).369 It appears to be the following:
Collect a group of general terms Ai . . .An, each one of which extends further than what is being defined, but which
as a group apply to all of and only what is being defined.
Thus, Aristotle writes:
such things must be taken up to the first point at which just so many are taken that each will belong more widely but
all of them together will not belong more widely; for, necessarily this will be the nature of the object (96a32–5)
He gives as an example the triple (three), to which (in his view) the following properties belong:
being a number, being odd, being prime in both ways (not being measured by number, and not being compounded
from numbers) (96a35)370
Each of these properties belongs to other numbers, as (for example) being prime in this way belongs to the pair as well
as the triple. But taken together all belong to nothing but the triple (96b1).
Aristotle claims that this account will show what it is to be the triple (96b4) and what its nature consists in (96b6), and
do so by giving the relevant differentiae of the genus (as specified in 83a24 ff.). He argues for the latter claim as follows:
368 a b b b a a b b
Β.13 is divided as follows in my discussion:(a)96 20– 14: Section 2.(b)96 15–25: Section 3.(c)96 25–97 2, 97 23– 5: Section 4.(d)97 5–26, together with Β.14 and 15:
Section 5.
369 a a b
‘Ousia’ may be specified in this context as the genus or as a differentia of the genus (Post. An. Α.2, 83 39 ff.; cf. 83 24–5). See also the discussion of Β.9, 93 26–8 in the
next Chapter, where (it is argued) ousia should also be separated from the cause of the differentiae being as they are.
370
These definitions of prime and prime* depend on the claim, which Aristotle regards as plausible, that one is not itself a number but a measure of number (cf. Meta. N.1,
1088a 6–8). We do not need to assess his grounds for this claim, since the issues raised here, such as concern differentiae, are at a far higher level of generality. I take ‘prime’
and ‘prime*’ as jointly one final differentia : being prime+ (96a 38, b1). Thus, in 96a 36 ff., I take the phrase to mean ‘we take the property of both prime and prime*’. I am
indebted here to discussion with Vassilis Karasmanis.
TOWARDS A UNIFIED THEORY OF DEFINITION 225
If Ai . . . An were not what it is to be the triple, it would extend further and be a genus (either named or unnamed);
in which case it will belong to other things than the triple. But Ai . . . An does not extend further than the triple. So, it
must be the nature (ousia) in question. (96b6–14)
This passage might suggest that Aristotle is recommending the following procedure to determine what something
essentially is:
Take a group of terms which individually extend more widely than the kind under definition, and then extract that
set of terms which, when taken together, are uniquely true of the kind in question.
This route might appear to offer a way to discover that a kind exists and to reveal its ousia (the nature of the kind) by
listing a set of properties whose conjunction is co-extensive with the kind. Species and genera, thus introduced, need
not be individuated in ways which involve their explanatorily basic features. If this is so, the methods advocated in
Β.13–15 would be distinct from, and independent of, the explanation-invoking account of definition and scientific
enquiry we considered in the last Chapter. However, if there are two independent methods for arriving at definitions, it
will be an unexplained coincidence if the definitions they generate are (ever) the same. There is no reason to expect the
two methods to lead to the same answer to the question ‘What is F?’
I shall argue that the appearance of an independent route is illusory. First, I shall seek to show that there is no
inconsistency between Aristotle's discussions of definition, in Β.8–10 and Β.13–15. Second, I shall argue that this
hypothesis is confirmed by other aspects of Β.13, 14, and 15 (sections 2–5). Together Β8–15 give a unified account of
definition.
There are two points of detail to be noted about the passage already cited (96b6–14). First, in introducing the
discussion, Aristotle says that the terms Ai . . . An:
extend beyond the kind in question, but do not extend beyond the genus (96a24 f.)
However, he does not say what counts as a genus or explain the significance of the restriction he introduces. There is a
gap in the story: How are the relevant genera themselves determined?
Second, Aristotle does not say which set of properties (whose conjunction is co-extensive with the kind) form part of
its being. There will regularly be a wider set of co-extensive properties, including non-essential but necessary ones (e.g.
in the case of two, being prime+, less than three, and half of four, etc.), whose conjunction is co-extensive with the
kind. So, how are the properties confined to those which fall within the nature (ousia) of the kind in question?
Aristotle gives some clue as to the answer to the latter question when he writes:
226 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
Such things would be taken up to the point at which first just so many are taken that . . .(96a33)
and
the nature is the last predication to hold of the atoms (96b12 f.)
For, these lines suggest that there is an ordering of terms which, if followed, will enable one to arrive at a point from
which one can first capture (e.g.) what it is to be two. Beyond that, while there may be other terms whose overlap
applies to all and only dyads, these will not be part of the relevant essence. But what fixes the relevant ordering? And
what determines what appears on the list? Can either or both of these questions be answered without invoking the
explanation-based concerns of Β.8–10?
These questions can be raised in a more precise form by focusing on Aristotle's favoured mathematical example: What
determines that the order in the case of the triple runs as follows:
number
odd
prime+: a combination of prime (not being measured by other numbers) and prime* (not being the sum of two
numbers).
For example, why is odd prior to prime+? It is important to note that not all prime+ numbers are odd (since two is an
exception). Since odd does not subsume prime or prime* (since that requires that all members of the lower group belong
to the higher group, i.e. that all primes are odd), the priority relation cannot be that of subsumption.371
Two features seem to be at work here. The first, and most obvious, is that there are fewer members of the group
prime+ than of odd. But it is doubtful whether this by itself can separate those terms which are part of the being of the
thing from those which are not. For, on this basis, one could replace being prime+ with being prime+ and less than
fifteen, etc., or being prime* with being prior to four in the number series.
The second feature is more important. Odd precedes prime in Euclid's definitions of features of number. Nor was this
order unmotivated, since given a list of odd numbers one can extract a list of those which are prime (on the basis of a
method known in antiquity as ‘Eratosthenes'
371
Barnes suggests that Aristotle is employing the relation of subsumption here and elsewhere in the chapter (Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 231, 234), although he notes that
Aristotle's examples are not all cases of subsumption. This latter fact should (I think) be taken to show that Aristotle is not in fact employing subsumption here (in which all
members of a lower group (e.g. prime+) belong to the group higher on the tree (e.g. odd)), but is relying on some different ordering principle. I suggest an alternative
principle in this Chapter.
TOWARDS A UNIFIED THEORY OF DEFINITION 227
sieve’).372 If one also knows that two is the only even prime, one can find all prime numbers by this route. Further, if
one knows that two and three are the only primes*, one can detect all primes+ in this way. There is, therefore, a
method for detecting primes+ if one has already separated odd and even numbers, but there is no similar method for
detecting odd and even numbers on the basis of a list of prime+ and non-prime+ numbers. For, there is no similar
way to recover odd or even numbers from a list of primes+ or non-primes+. The latter distinction plays no part in the
method for finding which numbers are even or odd. Thus, there is a significant asymmetry between odd and prime+:
Knowing which numbers are odd is a step in a mathematical procedure towards discovering which are prime+, while
knowing which are prime+ is not a step in a procedure towards discovering which are odd. This order of derivation
justifies placing odd higher than prime+ in the list of differentiae.
Prime+ is better suited to playing the role of an intermediate differentia than the more complex prime and less than fifteen,
because the method for selecting prime+ odd numbers pays no attention to what is above or below fifteen.
Eratosthenes' sieve works indifferently above and below this number. The notions involved (prime, odd, prime*) are
ones which should apply (in principle) to an unbounded set of numbers. Indeed, their status as differentiae is
underwritten by their role in marking out genuine groups in this way across the whole number series. The species of
prime+ odd numbers is marked out by a differentia (being prime+), whose status (and relative position) as a differentia is
legitimized by its role in a general arithmetical practice.
The problem raised by the argument of Β.13 can now be stated in a clearer form. Since definitions in the style of
Β.8–10 and those generated by the differentia model just considered relate to the nature of the objects involved, the
results of the two methods should be systematically related. Indeed, if this were not so, there would be a crucial
equivocation in Aristotle's account of the nature of (e.g.) the triple. However, the difficulty is that we have not yet seen
how the trick is to be turned.
The hypothesis I wish to investigate runs as follows. The relevant differentiating features are the ones explained by the
fundamental essence uncovered by the methods of Β.8–10. Thus, the essence of the triple (if
372
This method of finding odd prime numbers was called the ‘sieve’ by Eratosthenes (Iamblichus, In Nicomachi Arithmeticam Introductionem, ed. H. Pistelli (Leipzig, 1894), 1.13,
2–4). The ‘sieve’ works on odd numbers as follows: Set out a list of odd numbers:3, 5, 7, 9, 11, 13, 15, 17, 19, 21, 23, 25 . . .The sieve then subtracts all numbers divisible by
three (and also presumably five and seven) to give a list of prime odd numbers:3, 5, 7, 11, 13, 17, 19, 23 . . .
228 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
there is one) will explain why prime+ (understood as a combination of prime and prime*) belongs to odd number. The
full definition of the triple would be as follows:
prime+ odd number with basic feature k, which explains in the appropriate way why prime+ belongs to odd
number
If this is correct, the relevant differentiae will have two roles:
(a) They will fit into a pattern of mathematical procedures of the type sketched (a general derivational pattern
which applies to all numbers).
and
(b) They will be explained in the appropriate way by the underlying essence.
Differentiae, so understood, will be ways of being members of a higher group which simultaneously meet conditions (a)
and (b). They will mark out genuine kinds at varying levels of generality in a general, non-ad hoc, way which satisfies
condition (b). As such, differentiating features of this type fall within the nature of the triple (96b11). Indeed, there will
be just as many differentiae in its nature as are required in the descending order to mark out the triple (in the approved
way).
This hypothesis has considerable advantages in the context of Β.13. Not merely does it render consistent Aristotle's
two explicitly related discussions of definition in Β.8–10 and Β.13; it also shows how one can come to grasp all the
relevant terms in the definition of the triple on the basis of one's grasp of the relevant genus/ differentia structure. For,
the latter will offer a way of ‘hunting out’ some of the features which are part of what it is to be that kind. Armed with
this information one can proceed (in Β.8–10 style) to grasp the remaining features which are definitional of the kind,
by answering the ‘Why?’ question in the appropriate way.
This hypothesis fills a gap left in the last Chapter. While Β.8–10 were concerned with the explanandum and explanans in
demonstrations, they did not (as was noted) spell out in detail why certain features are selected as the relevant
explananda. The genus/ differentia structure, as demarcated in the present hypothesis, fills this gap: The appropriate
explananda are (i) necessary properties of the kind and (ii) features specified in a pattern of derivation of the type
exemplified by the mathematical case. This account will clarify which of the terms explained by the essence in this case
are part of the definition: those which also fit into a pattern of differentiation of the type indicated by condition (a). As
was suggested above,373 the explananda are partially chosen on the basis of considerations which flow
373
See Ch. 8 Sect. 3, 4, and 5.
TOWARDS A UNIFIED THEORY OF DEFINITION 229
from the practice of definition (as features which differentiate the genera in the required way).374
In Β.8 Aristotle began his search for an answer to the ‘Why?’ question with an initial grasp of the thing itself. In the
case of man, this was given by representing him as an animal of a certain type (93a24). But it was not made explicit in
that chapter why this was chosen as the starting point, or what made this the correct initial account (among non-
accidental properties of the kind). The present hypothesis offers us a way of answering this question. ‘Animal of a
certain type (e.g. tame biped)’ will be taken as the initial stage of enquiry because it is this description which locates
man in its proper position in a genus/species tree. In the case of the triple, the initial account would specify it as odd
prime* number, and, thus, locate it in its own niche in a genus/species tree. Full definitions will contain features of this
type which are subsequently explained by the relevant essence.
This account, if correct, has further significant consequences for our understanding of Aristotle's schema of genera
and differentiae, as introduced in Β.13–15. His method will presuppose that there are features of the kind which are ways
of being a higher-order kind (according to an appropriate pattern of derivation) but which are themselves explained by
the underlying essence of the lower-level kind itself. Thus, the differentiating features will be those definitional features
of the kind which are explained by the essence in the appropriate way. Not any sort of differentia will do this. Indeed, the
result will only be achieved if the differentiation scheme in question is one which latches on to features which are part
of the being of the kind (as Aristotle remarks in Β.13, 97a11–14). Thus, the appropriate differentiation scheme in the
Analytics must meet two constraints:
(D.a) It must be part of a general scheme of classification in which lower-order kinds are introduced by general, non-
ad hoc, operations on higher-order ones.
and
(D.b)It must point at each level to features which are appropriately explained by the essence in question.
This account of differentiae is explanation-involving in one crucial respect. In being differentiae in accordance with being (i.e.
essence 97a12 f.) the relevant predicates must not only locate the kind in its own niche in a natural order but do so in a
way which points to genuine features of the kind
374
Other terms explained by the essence (e.g. unique specific ones) would not be included in the definition (even though they are necessary properties of the kind) because they
do not fit into the differentiae structure.
230 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
(appropriately explained by the essence). Thus, what counts as a differentia is delimited (but not wholly determined) by
what is explained by the essence in the appropriate way. It is, of course, a substantial claim that there are features which
can play both these roles, and a substantial recommendation that the relevant differentiation structure should be
constrained by both these requirements.375 For, the differentiating scheme not only points to a system of derivation of
lower-from higher-order kinds, but also does so in a way which refers to non-accidental features of the relevant kinds
which are explained by their essences.
In the arithmetical case it should come as no surprise that the differentiation scheme picks out non-accidental features
of (e.g.) the triple. For, the pattern of derivation (odd, prime+) is one which rests on general properties of numbers
(unlike being prime and less than fifteen, etc.). Given a system of this type, it is no accident that the features of the
triple marked out are the non-accidental ones explained in the appropriate way by its essence. The system of
differentiation appears designed to select non-accidental features of the numbers.
The hypothesis developed in the last few paragraphs is attractive. It renders the claims of Β.13 consistent with those of
Β.8–10 (as promised at the beginning of Β.13), and explains why the differentiation scheme in Β.13 is in line with being
(or essence (97a13)). It also has interesting general implications for Aristotle's theory of definition and classification.
However, it can only be secured (from an exegetical viewpoint) if we can see why he took definition and differentiation
to be connected in the way suggested. There would have been a major gap in his theory if he had given no explanation
of this connection. Fortunately, the next section of Posterior Analytics Β.13 appears to provide the type of explanation
required (or so I shall argue).
When you are dealing with a given subject [of enquiry], you should divide the genus into what are the first atoms in
species—e.g. number into triplet and pair, then attempt to give definitions of these (e.g. of straight line, circle, and
right angle);
375
One might ask why it should be a derivative feature (and not the answer to the ‘why?’ question itself) which is the one which marks out the species in the descending tree?
Aristotle, of course, focuses on cases where predicates extend beyond the kind (96a 24), and so will not be the unique essence (to ti en einai ), and locates the differentiae
amongst these in the case in point. It does not follow from this alone that the differentiae will always extend beyond the kind, or that it will always be a derivative feature
which fills the role of the differentia.
376
As Barnes comments: ‘if it has a coherent interpretation, it remains to be found’ (Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 213).
TOWARDS A UNIFIED THEORY OF DEFINITION 231
and, after that, having grasped what the kind (genus) is (e.g. whether it is a quantity or quality), consider its proper
affections through the first common elements.377 For, properties of things that are compounded from the atoms will
be clear from the definitions, because definitions and what is simple are the principles of everything, and properties
belong non-derivatively to the simples alone, and to the other things derivatively. (96b15–25)
This passage contains many difficulties. I shall begin by offering an interpretation which represents it as a natural
extension of 96b4–14. It runs as follows:
In examining a given subject matter such as numbers (holon ti), one should divide it into its first atomic species (e.g.
two, three), and then try to formulate a definition of these. At this point one will avail oneself of terms like prime, odd,
and prime*. A suggestion for a full definition of two might be:
377
The proper affections could (grammatically) be either those of the genus or of the whole area under discussion. However, this issue need not detain us since one genus is
taken here to cover one whole area of the appropriate type.
378 a
In De Caelo 286 6 ff., Aristotle notes a further feature of three: It has a beginning a middle and an end. Theon (46.14–8, 100.13–101.10) makes the same claims about
three, and also notes that it is called ‘perfect;’ but for other reasons. The differentiae ‘perfect’ might be added to odd/even . . . as differentiae of numbers (see Iamblichus, In
Nicom. Arithm., 31–3).
232 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
specify what is distinctive of five as opposed to seven. Thus, the account of differentiae does not yet adequately
distinguish between many of the infimae species of number.
While the existence of this problem (discussed acutely by Pacius) does not challenge the general thesis of the
interdependence of differentiation and definition in Β.13, it would, nonetheless, be less than satisfactory if it could not
be resolved using the resources which that thesis allows us. One attempted solution would be to use the different
modes of composition (sunthesis) involved in five and seven to determine (in some measure) the relevant infimae
species (e.g. five will be composed from one concatenation of common numbers, seven from two). On this account,
Aristotle will not hold that all the properties of five or seven are themselves the properties of the primary ones,
provided that they are either properties of two or three or features of the way two and three are combined in their case.
If so, the relevant features would belong to the derived species in accordance with (kata) the nature of the simples
(96b24 f.),379 even though they are not all properties of simples.
Let us focus on the case of five. If its relevant properties were (e.g.) being odd, prime, and non-prime* and the product
of only one concatenation of the basic elements, five would be marked out by features which individually extend
beyond it, but which collectively do not (in line with Aristotle's injunction in 96a32 ff.). These features are ones which
either belong to two and three, or result from how they are combined to form five. Thus, they need not be (as Pacius
apparently thought) confined to ones which belong to two and three, provided that their presence can be explained on
the basis of the properties of two and three (including their powers of combination). This method can be generalized
to cover all other numbers.380
379
Barnes discusses this proposal first made by Pacius, critically (Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 233), and rejects it. Pacius is taken to commit himself to the view that (e.g.) the
quintuple's properties are confined to those of the triple and pair (e.g. odd/even, prime/ non-prime), without considering their modes of combination. If this were his view,
he would have been unable satisfactorily to distinguish between five and seven. But there seems no reason to interpret ‘kata ’ in 96b 24 to mean that all properties of the
quintuple are ones which belong to the pair or triple. Perhaps rather they are consequences of the properties of the pair and triple plus their mode of combination. (Pacius'
own formulations are actually fairly cautious. He commits himself only to the view that those properties that belong to both primary and derived species belong to the latter
derivatively ‘in so far as (quatenus ) they are composed from the primary’. This does not require him to make the mistake of thinking that all features of derived species are
shared by primary ones. However, since he offers no view on any features of the derived species which are not shared by the primary ones, his account is at best incomplete
(Barnes, Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 338)).
380
Examples of the differentiae might be:Four: even, non-prime, non-prime*, the result of one concatenation of basic elements.Five: odd, prime, non-prime*, the result of one
concatenation of basic elements.Six: even, non-prime, non-prime*, the result of two concatenations of basic elements.Seven: odd, prime, non-prime*, the result of two
concatenations of basic elements.Eight: even, non-prime, non-prime*, the result of two concatenations of basic elements . . .These differentiae would (in line with Aristotle's
own injunction in 96a32 ff.) individually extend beyond the relevant number, but collectively extend no further than it. (I include this list merely to show how such a system
might work, not to claim that Aristotle actually had such a proposal ‘in mind’, when writing this passage.)The relevant essences would be the essence of four, five . . . These
could, but need not, be understood as (e.g.) the result of concatenating two and two, two and three . . .
TOWARDS A UNIFIED THEORY OF DEFINITION 233
If this line of interpretation is correct, Aristotle's discussion of numbers has achieved two goals:
(1) He has shown how one can arrive at a view of the relevant genus and its specific features by examining the
definitional properties of two of its central cases.
(2) He has also shown how the other members of the genus can be marked out using these specific features (odd,
even) together with the mode of combination of the common elements.
In the case of numbers, we can see why the initial differentiating features of individual numbers selected by these
methods will be the ones explained by their distinctive essences. In the case of two and three, being odd, even, prime+,
etc. were selected precisely because they played this role. In derived cases, there is a similar pattern. For example, if
being the product of two and three is the essence of five, this will explain why it is odd (as it is not the product of two
even numbers) and prime (given that is odd, and not divisible by three). Since the additional features used to
differentiate five (e.g. its being non-prime*, the result of one concatenation of basic elements) depend on its being the
product of two and three, these too will be explicable by its distinctive essence.
Within this conception, the genus of number is held together by a common thread: the features used in the definition
of derived species can be seen to be the result of applying a series of operations to a small number of basic elements (e.
g. two, three). Derived species (e.g. five, six . . . ) fall within one genus provided that their differentiating properties
depend on the definitional features (odd, prime . . . ) and modes of combination of the basic elements.381 Further, in
their case, the essence itself may be based on
381
These cases show that it is a mistake to attempt to line up all of Β.13 with any one of the Β.8–10 definitions, or to criticize Aristotle if this cannot be done. The fact that his
discussion is not limited to one of the Β.10 definitions does not show that he is talking about some other form of pre-demonstrative definition. In Β.13 Aristotle is pursuing
the more general goal of showing how ideas about genus and differentiae can play a role throughout successful enquiry into essence and definition. Thus, at some points he
focuses on definitions which correspond to conclusions of demonstrations, at others on full definitions which correspond to complete demonstrations. (The discussion of
simples is reserved for Β.19.)
234 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
some specific combination of two and three. Thus, there are three features involved in the arithmetical case:
(1) The general differentiating properties are shared by all numbers (e.g. odd/even, prime/non-prime, etc.).
(2) The additional differentiating features come from the mode of combination of the basic elements.
(3) The essence itself may be determined by facts about the combination of the basic elements.
Between them, these features generate the distinctive type of order to be found in the genus of number. Members of
that genus are bound together by their shared possession of these three features. But this is a special kind of ordering,
with its own distinctive properties. Aristotle needs to show that this idea of genera and differentiae can extend beyond
the case of number to areas where the derived species are not composed from basic elements. In such a case, one
would expect to find (1) but not (2) or (3) at work. Thus, he needs to devise a way of showing how certain species are
differentiated which does not rest on the principle of composition.
Divisions in accordance with differentiae are useful in this procedure . . . they are useful in deducing what something
is (96b25–7)
Why does Aristotle reintroduce the method of division in the context of Β.13? What has changed from Β.5? Why is
division useful in a way comparable to the distinctions marked out in the case of numbers?
If the mathematical case provides a partial parallel for the biological one, one would expect to find in the latter an
analogue of condition (1). Thus, one should be able to organize a given subject matter by focusing on some special
cases of individual species (e.g. man, horse . . . ) and attempting
TOWARDS A UNIFIED THEORY OF DEFINITION 235
to define these in the explanatory style of Β.8–10. For example, one might define man as an animal capable of walking
on two feet, with its own distinctive soul. On this basis, one would attempt to derive a view of the distinctive features
of the genus, animal, as (e.g.) what is capable of movement, breathing, reproduction . . . In this way, one would hope to
devise a system of differentiae which met two conditions:
(a*) They fit into a general and non-ad hoc procedure for deriving genuine kinds from other genuine kinds.
(b*) They are themselves explained in the relevant syllogism which incorporates the essence.
If the relevant differentiae point to ways of being members of the higher group which meet condition (b*), they will be
(as Aristotle says) useful in ‘deducing what something is’. For, they will point to the features to be explained by the
essence. Indeed, it is because differentiae are of the type indicated by (b*) that they can play this role. That Aristotle
emphasizes this use of differentiae strongly suggests that he sees their role as the one required by (b*).
Aristotle does not, however, say much that is relevant to condition (a*) in the biological case. As a result, we are given
little indication of what is to replace composition from basic elements among specific differentiae in this case. He does,
however, make an important point, when he writes:
It makes a difference which of the predicates is predicated first: e.g. to say animal tame two-footed or two-footed
animal tame. For, if everything is made up out of something, and tame animal is a unity and man is made up out of
this and the differentia (two-footed), it is necessary to postulate by dividing. (96b30–5)
Aristotle emphasizes that it makes a difference what the relevant order is. This is because if [A + B] is a unity, and man
is made up of [A + B] + C (with C as its differentia), it is necessary to postulate by dividing. This claim involves two
aspects:
(i) The differentia C takes one from a unity to a unity (e.g. man).
and
(ii) To explain what man is is to explain why C belongs to [A + B]: Why does biped belong to tame animal?
Reference to the distinctive essence of man will answer the latter question by pointing to a feature which explains why
bipedality belongs to the class of tame animals. The latter formulation gets the problem in the right form to be
answered.
But why is this so? Would not the essence of man also explain why
236 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
tameness belongs to the class of biped animal? What determines that this is the order of the differentiae?
Aristotle suggests that if tame is the first differentia, this is because it divides the whole genus of animal while biped does
not. Being a biped is a way of being footed, as being split-winged is a way of being winged (96b31f., b38 ff.), and so is
only a differentia among footed animals. But this remark does not take us very far. While this pattern of thought may
explain why biped comes after tame, it says nothing about the relative positions of (e.g.) tame and footed as differentiae.
Since all animals can be placed in the categories tame/wild, footed/footless, why begin with one rather than another?
The best clue is provided by clause (i). At each level, in Aristotle's view, one must have a properly unified kind, and not
an ad hoc or unnatural collection of different kinds. Thus, tame animal is allowed as a species only if it is a unity.382
Footed animal would be excluded if it did not form a genuine unified kind, but allowed of too much variation within
its members. For similar reasons, aquatic, terrestrial, and aerial would be excluded, if they contain species too far apart
to form a unified kind.
It is clear that there are background ontological assumptions about genuine unified kinds at work here. Indeed, the
procedure of division is constrained by these assumptions. Its role is not to determine the unity of a kind (as it was in
the account criticized in Β.6), but rather to organize in some systematic way unities established by other means. Nor
can division alone secure the appropriate ordering. Rather, it is itself constrained by two factors:
(a) It must begin with a unity (e.g. tame animal).
and
(b) It must add a further term (as a differentia) which generates a unified lower kind. Further, the presence of the
relevant differentia will in turn be explained by the essence of the kind in the appropriate way.
Thus, the relevant differentiae will take us from unity to unity in a way which marks out the features to be explained at
the lower level.
These conditions, taken together, mirror some of the constraints on differentiae in the mathematical case. Genuine
biological differentiae will be features with two roles:
(a*) They will fit into a pattern of biological practice for deriving species of the kind indicated.
382
I take it that these cases are only included exempli causa, and are not intended to correspond to Aristotle's own favoured views. On wild and tame as differentiae, see PA
Α.2.
TOWARDS A UNIFIED THEORY OF DEFINITION 237
and
(b*) They will themselves be explained in an appropriate way by the underlying essence.
(a*) refers to the required procedure for moving from unities to unities by means of differentiae which are themselves
explained at the lower level. What is missing here is an account of the type of differentiae which will allow for this
procedure. We are given no indication of what is to replace those features which depend on the combination of the
basic elements (two and three) to distinguish species which are wild, four-legged, etc. In effect, we lack any clear idea of
what the relevant type of differentiae will be, or of the nature of the order they define. So, no analogue is provided of
conditions (2) and (3) in the arithmetical case. We are, however, told that division by differentiae is to mark out by
divisional methods a descending sequence of genuine unities, and to do so in line with (a*) and (b*). If this goal is
satisfactorily achieved, no unity will be excluded. Division, if successful, will allow us to see all relevant unities as part
of a hierarchical structure of kinds with (at least) some basic shared differentiae.383
383
Later (97a35-b6), Aristotle envisages the following structure of kinds:(A) animal(B) bird fish(C) split-winged whole-wingedwhere level-B kinds are genuine unities because
they are arrived at from a genuine unity (A) plus a differentia (e.g. being winged). One can then establish (if the schema of differentiae is adequate) that these are all the unities
there are, provided that at the final stage—C—there is no further genuine differentia (i.e. there is no further genuine sub-kind to be marked out)—since what falls below this
level is the same in kind as the level, and differs in a way not relevant to classification of kinds (because not explained by relevant reasons). In a complete differentiae system,
no level will be missed out. For, if it was, one would not be able to grasp all the kinds by the favoured route:unity A/animal [genus] + differentia 1 → proper unity BIf one
skipped level B, and proceeded as followsunity A/animal [genus] + differentia 2 → proper unity Cone would have the following division groupings at level C:split-winged
animals: whole-winged animals and wingless animalsand would overlook the unified kind of winged animals (birds). So, this procedure would ignore one kind with just the
required type of unifying feature. A differentia term is correctly used in a sequence only if it is introduced at a point where no genuine kind is previously overlooked (winged
animal). But this depends on prior assumptions about what are genuine kinds and an appropriate order of derivation, which this account does not generate or guarantee.
238 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
This sketch (albeit incomplete) of the role of genus and differentiae offers some insight into Aristotle's idea of using the
genus to establish what belongs in the definition of sub-kinds. In an optimal case, one would be able to establish the
distinguishing features (ta sumbebēkota) of the subspecies by seeing them as elements in a genus/ differentiae tree of the
appropriate kind. This is because the differentiae are themselves selected (in part) because they pick out what is to be
explained by the essence in question (in the way required for definition). This will be so whether the differentiae are
general ones, such as tame/wild or footed/non-footed, or specific ones which mark out differences between (e.g.)
tame and footed animals.
The pattern at work in this account further exemplifies the thesis of the interdependence of definition and explanation
introduced in the previous Chapter. The explananda accounted for by the essence are (in part) demarcated by
definitional concerns which arise from our practice of defining by genus and differentia. But the pattern of
differentiation itself is (in some measure) based on a view of what is to be explained on the basis of the essence in
question. The same type of interdependence of explanation and definition is present here as in Β.8–10 and Β.16–18.
If this is correct, we can establish which features are the ones which follow from the essence and are part of the
definition, in two ways. They will emerge either as the explananda to be derived from the essence of a sub-kind in the
favoured way, or as the products of an appropriate genus/ differentia tree. These two routes arrive at the same
destination. In the favoured model of explanation (the one required for definition), the explananda are those features
which not only follow from the essence but also fit into an appropriate structure of genus and differentiae. But, in turn,
an appropriate structure of differentiation into genus and species will itself essentially involve the presence of features
to be explained by the essence. Thus, if one possesses an appropriate differentiating procedure one will arrive in the
case of man at (e.g.) biped tame animal. But equally if one begins with the essence of man (e.g. possessing a given kind
of soul) and proceeds via an appropriate scheme of explanation one will arrive at these same features as the explananda.
Nor is this an accident. The two discussions of definition, in Β.8–10 and Β.13, fit together because they both exemplify
a common perspective in which the practices of definition and explanation are mutually interdependent. They were
made for one another.
Aristotle's concepts of genus and differentiae, so understood, are partially based on his conception of explanation. Taken
together, they provide a picture of a given area of investigation as an organized whole in which:
(a) Genera are kinds, all of whose sub-kinds can be ordered in an intelligible fashion using differentiae.
TOWARDS A UNIFIED THEORY OF DEFINITION 239
(b) Differentiae take one from kind to sub-kind in an intelligible way which picks out those features of the sub-kind
which differentiate the sub-kind from its kind and are explained by its essence.
In this conception, differentiae mark out genuine unities by specifying some of their defining features in a way which
shows them to be intelligibly related to higher-order kinds. Further, these features are the ones to be explained by the
appropriate answer to the ‘Why?’ question. Genera are groups of objects which can be differentiated in this way.
animal
bird
species of bird (e.g. split-winged bird)
At each stage, Aristotle asks what properties belong to the relevant kinds and why:
240 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
we must extract a common property and ask what things this follows, and what qualities follow it: e.g. in the case
having a manyplies and lacking incisors, it follows animals with horns. And we should also enquire what animals
having horns follows. For, it will be clear why (e.g.) having a manyplies belongs to them: because they have horns.
384
For a view of this sort, see J. G. Lennox's ‘Between Data and Demonstration: The Analytics and the Historia Animalium, in A. C. Bowen (ed.), Science and Philosophy in
Classical Greece (Pittsburgh, 1989), Ch. 12, and ‘Divide and Explain: The Posterior Analytics in Practice’ in Gotthelf and Lennox (eds.) Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology,
90–116.
TOWARDS A UNIFIED THEORY OF DEFINITION 241
answers are different. In (i), Aristotle is assuming that there is a kind, such as horned animal, which lacks a common
name (unlike ‘bird’ (98a7)). These species might be described by a phrase (such as ‘wingless quadruped’ or ‘horned
animal’) or by several names joined together.
In this passage, Aristotle relies on a structure of genus and differentiae which is already in place, and which marks out (e.
g.) horned animals and goats as species in a descending tree.385 In this case, unlike that discussed in the first part of
Β.14, ‘horned animal’ is not itself a name. But, nonetheless, there is a genus and differentia structure which yields
questions at the right level such as:
385
Aristotle is envisaging three stages:(a)Establish ∀x [Fx → Hx], where ‘Hx’ means x has manyplies.(b)Establish ∀x [Gx → Fx], where ‘Fx’ means x is horned.and
finally:(c)What animals have F?An answer to (c) might be: type A (goats), one of the kinds which are F (e.g. 99a32–5). If so, there is no essential use of commensurate
a
universals or counter-predication in this passage. These features enter at a further stage (cf. 99 32–6) where one reaches the end of the explanatory project. Similarly, in Β.17,
b
99 5 ff., while all birds may have a given property, possession of this property need not be confined to birds (e.g. possession of a gut of a given kind), provided that not all
animals possess a gut of this kind (cf. HA Β.17;cf. 508b14–17). It is not required that the universals at this stage belong exclusively to birds (cf. 99a32–5), but some could
apply to (e.g.) fish as well. Thus: ‘Why do all birds have a gut of a given kind?’ might be an acceptable problem, even if fish also had such a gut.
242 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
also clear in Β.15. Aristotle notes that for a problem to be one problem, there must be one shared explanatory feature
(whether numerically or in genus).386 Thus, as in Β.16 and 17, if the middle terms picking out the explanatory feature
are different, either the relevant property to be explained is different or the objects differ in kind.387 But this can only be
because it is a condition on the kind being one that there is one essence which explains why it possesses its relevant
properties. (Otherwise the property will turn out to be one ‘by analogy’ as in the cases discussed in Β.14.388) This
constraint is underwritten by the explanation-invoking account of differentiation developed in Β.13. If kinds are
differentiated by features which are explained in an appropriate way by the kind's essence (in line with requirement (b*)
above), there will be one kind only if there is one essence of the appropriate type.
These claims clearly reflect the explanatory concerns manifested in Aristotle's method of differentiating genera and
species. Kinds, sub-kinds, and differentiae are all selected (in part) on the basis of their role in explanation. This pattern is
to be found throughout Β.16–18, where difference in relevant middle term (cause) spells difference either in the
property to be explained or the kind under explanation. But, as I have argued, it is also present in the earlier chapters,
Β.13–15, where kinds are individuated and differentiae selected (at least, in part) in line with the demands of explanation.
Given this picture, it is no surprise in Β.15 that if the relevant
386
This chapter is interestingly discussed by J. G. Lennox in ‘Aristotelian Problems’ (1994). He argues (contra Ross and Barnes) that these two cases exhaust the ones in which
the problem is the same. In Lennox's view, cases where the answers to problems are related because they ‘fall under’ one another are not ones where the problem is one (98a
29–34). Whichever way this issue is resolved makes no difference to the issue presently under discussion.
387
See Ch. 8 Sect. 8.5.
388
At the end of Β.14 Aristotle draws the following picture:
where there is an analogy between the cases because they belong to different genera. Aristotle remarks that some things will belong to:human qua bonedand to:fish qua
spined, etc.‘as if these were one common nature’, although they are not. By contrast, within one genus or species, there will be just such a common nature. So, if the idea of a
common nature is an explanatorily based one, Aristotle will here too be relying on explanation-based concerns in his conception of the appropriate genus/species trees. For
further discussion of the notion of ‘common nature’, see Chapter 12. In the immediate context of the Analytics, it seems clear in the light of the rest of Β.14 and 15 that this is
an explanatory notion.
TOWARDS A UNIFIED THEORY OF DEFINITION 243
explanatory middle term differs (and the property remains constant), the kinds (and the problems involved) must also
be different. For, differentiation and explanation are tied closely together throughout this account.
389
For instance, Aristotle does not consider the following questions:(1)How far do the concepts of genus and differentia apply. If thunder is to be understood as noise in the clouds,
b
is noise the genus, and in the clouds the differentiating term (specifying the place where; cf. Meta. Η.2, 1042 21)? Does something similar apply to the account of eclipse as
deprivation of light (where deprivation is understood as like a genus).(2)How far does this account of definition cohere with definitions outside the Analytics of substance which
use the concepts of matter and form?(3)Can the explanation-involving system of classification suggested in Β.13–15 be applied to any case other than mathematics? Does it
work in the biological domain?
244 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
examine further the precise nature and basis of Aristotle's thesis of the interdependence of definition and explanation,
and consider a major exegetical challenge based on an interpretation of the final chapter of the Analytics. For, many see
Aristotle as advancing in Β.19 a fundamentally different, indeed opposite, view on these issues.
10 Explanation and Denition: The Basic Model
Reconsidered and Rened
10.1 Introduction
The last two Chapters have uncovered a common structure. In Aristotle's view, the practice of definition (as
characterized in the Analytics) cannot be fully specified without the use of resources drawn from the practice of
explanation. But the latter, in turn, is incomplete without the support of material taken from the former. The two
practices are mutually dependent. Neither can stand alone.
To recapitulate: the priority and unity of the definiens cannot be captured without recourse to our causal explanatory
practices, as these are revealed in demonstration.390 But equally the relevant types of explananda and explanantia cannot
be determined without assistance from the practice of definition. Thus, the explanantia are (a) features specific to the
kind in question, (b) unities which it could not lack, and (c) ones which make the nature of the kind fully intelligible to
us. In a similar way, the explananda (in the case of substances) are features which differentiate the kind in an appropriate
genus/ differentia tree.391 The per se connections which are to be explained are delimited (in part) by our practices of
definition. But here too definition does not stand alone. For, a feature can only be a differentia if it is explained in the
appropriate way by the essence of the relevant phenomenon. Both definition and explanation have a role to play in the
determination of differentiae. Neither is complete by itself.
These remarks show the importance of Aristotle's introductory remarks in Β.2. He writes:
In all these cases it is clear that what it is and why it is are one and the same. What is an eclipse? Privation of light
from the moon caused by the earth's screening. Why is there an eclipse? Or ‘Why is the moon eclipsed?’ Because
the light fails when the earth screens it. What is a harmony? An arithmetical ratio of high and
390
See Ch. 8 Sect. 8.2.
391
See Ch. 9 Sects. 9.2–4. These features will be important elements of the form transferred from the kind to the thinker. (See Ch. 6 Sects. 6.1, 4–5.)
246 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
low pitch. Why does the high pitch harmonize with the low? Because an arithmetical ratio holds between them.
(90a14–21)
(2) Privation of light from the moon brought on by the earth's screening.
In this case, the ‘Why?’ question is posed as follows:
(4) Because light failure belongs to the moon brought on by the earth's screening.
The definition contains three elements: the efficient cause (the earth coming in between), what the efficient cause
brings about (e.g. light failure), and what is affected by the efficient cause (the moon: to proton paschon). The definition is
complex:
392
For rejected alternative understandings, see Ch. 8 Sect. 8.5.
EXPLANATION AND DEFINITION 247
Causally structured definitions of this type will be appropriate where ‘the cause is different’. In some cases, the relevant
cause might be a teleological one (e.g. preservation, in the case of a house). In others, it might be the grounding cause
introduced in the mathematical cases in Β.11 (94a24–34). The second case introduced in Β.2 appears to be of this type,
since the arithmetical ratio explains why there is a harmony of high and low notes of a certain kind.393 In these cases the
definition gives a structural description of the phenomenon, which picks out its causally salient features: the relevant
cause, its effect, and the object affected. But, as becomes clear later, the relevant type of causation is constrained by
demands which flow from the theory of definition.
The Analytics, so interpreted, articulates a unified account of these definitions. Its completed definitions may refer to
differentiation through genus and differentia, and to the unique, causally basic essence of the kind. These will have two
dimensions:
(a) they will reveal the explanatorily basic feature of the kind,
and
(b) they will locate the kind in a wider context of other species within the same genus, at its appropriate point in a
genus/species tree.
So understood, there is no contrast or tension between definition by genus and differentia and definition by causally
basic feature. Both can be elements in one unified definition because both play a mutually supportive role in an
appropriate constitutive causal story. Nor is their integration an accident. The differentiae are demarcated (in part) by
their role as the explananda in the relevant causal story. But equally the explananda are themselves (in part) selected
because they are differentiae which locate the particular kind in a wider system of classification. Some have argued that
Aristotle offers several distinct theories of definition, which fail to form a unified whole: definition by genus and
differentia, definition by basic causal feature, and definition by matter and form.394 However, in the Analytics, the first two
are integrated parts of one account of definition.
Interdependence between the practices of explanation and definition is
393 a
In Β.11, Aristotle notes cases where the teleological cause gives the basis for the relevant definitional account (94 22–23), and others in which ‘given so an so, it is necessary
that this is so’(94a 21–2). Since Aristotle does not (in this passage) separate out the material cause, it is unclear whether the latter kind of cause is simply the material cause in
disguise or whether it extends more widely. (Similarly with the mathematical example in 94a 27 ff.) However, in all the cases mentioned the cause (specified by the middle
term) is prior to the effect (as specified in the conclusion) in one of the three causal patterns specified. Further, there is no case in Β.11 where the essence is said to be prior
without the support of an efficient, grounding, or teleological causal story.
394
See J. M. LeBlond's paper ‘Definition in Aristotle’, repr. in J. Barnes, M. Schofield, and R. Sorabji (eds.) Articles on Aristotle 3: Metaphysics (London, 1979), 63–79.
248 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
matched by a further metaphysical claim: that essences and the explanantia and explananda cited in structural
explanation are co-determined. That is, if truths about the latter are determined, so are truths about the former (and
vice versa). Indeed, a feature can only be essential if it is the per se structural cause, and can only be the latter if it is
essential. The thesis of the co-determination of essences and explanantia concerns the structure of reality rather than
our practices of definition or explanation.
Several questions naturally arise about these claims:
(1) What is the importance of Aristotle's claim that our practices of definition and explanation are interdependent?
(2) What is the basis of the constraints on definition, which are later made determinate by the theory of
explanation?
(3) Does the interdependency of our practices of definition and explanation rest on the co-determination of
essence and explanantia? Or vice versa? Or is neither more basic?
(4) Can the unified account of definition be extended to include the case of definition via matter and form?
I shall consider questions (1), (2), and (3) in the next three Sections, and (4) in the next Chapter. The parallel theses of
interdependency and co-determination have epistemological consequences. For, we can come to know that certain
features are essential by seeing their role as unified and immediate causes in a given form of explanation. There is no
need for a special faculty of intuition to give us insight into the modal nature of reality. For, essences can be discovered
by carrying through the distinctive type of explanatory project set out above. There is, however, a major objection to
this line of interpretation. Many think that Aristotle, in the final chapter of the Analytics, develops an account of nous as
a source of information about first principles, or about modal reality more generally, which can be acquired without
any interest in explanation. I shall address this exegetical objection in Section 10.6.
are mutually interdependent in this way, what defines a kind must be the same thing as what is required for it to exist.
There is no possibility (in Aristotle's account) of these two coming apart. The definitional constraints are incomplete
without the addition of material drawn from our practice of explanation.
The significance of Aristotle's claim becomes clearer if we consider the consequence of separating the theories of
definition and of explanation. Once this happens, two questions become pressing. Why should the answer to the ‘What
is F?’ question be the same as that to the question of what is required for F's existence? Indeed, why assume that the
answer to the latter question has any relevance to the definition of the kind?
Once these questions are raised, one immediate response will be to say that we should stipulate that the explanatorily
basic feature constitutes the definitional essence of the kind. This stipulation may reflect our preferences as definers,
but need not register any further metaphysical truth.395 We choose to make the explanatorily basic features into
essential ones. Our choice, of course, is not an arbitrary one, since we may reasonably wish to have definitions which
pick up explanatorily basic features and trace the explanatory connections in reality. But, nonetheless, it is we who
convert explanatorily basic features into definitional ones.
This response rests on two assumptions. First, it presupposes that we, as definers, possess a determinate model of
definition, quite independently of how the world is. In this model, our crucial definitional notions (such as may involve
priority and unity) are complete without any assistance from the world. We merely note which features in the world
satisfy our definitional model and conclude that they are (for that reason) definitional of the kind in question. We have
a perfect definitional net (complete no matter what area it is used in) which allows us to make the explanatorily basic
features we find in reality essential ones.396 Second, this response requires us to be able to specify which features are
explanatorily basic without any reliance on our practices of definition. There is just one pattern of explanation, marked
out in ways independent of definition, which leads us to the definitions we seek.
395
See the arguments deployed by Richard Sorabji (in Necessity, Cause and Blame, 213–16) to secure a connection between definitional essence and explanatorily basic feature,
once one has introduced an account of definition and explanation which are conceptually independent of one another. Both his major arguments for the identification of
definitional essence and explanatorily basic feature turn on the unsupported claim that what is explanatorily basic should be definitional. Richard McKirahan also engages
with this issue when he seeks to explain the necessity of definition in Principles and Proofs (Princeton, 1992), 107 ff. But I am unable to see how he establishes the necessity
of true definition from the resources he deploys.
396
See, for the use of this analogy, David Wiggins's Sameness and Substance (Oxford, 1981), 141.
250 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
As we have seen, Aristotle rejects both assumptions. In his view there is no possibility of making determinate our
definitional practices without invoking our explanatory ones. For this reason his account of definition is not a
conventionalist one. Further, for similar reasons, his account of explanation is not one in which we grasp what is
explanatorily basic in the required way without dependence on the constraints drawn from our practices of definition.
There is no gap between definition and explanation which needs to be filled by stipulation. Aristotle's approach to
these issues is not that of the conventionalist.
There is an alternative response to the questions raised above. If one recoils from conventionalism, but continues to
separate our practices of definition and explanation, one will be drawn to say that certain features are essential,
independently of their role in explanation. If so, it will seem natural to assume that definitional features (which are such
independently of their explanatory role) can (in principle) be grasped as such in ways independent of our explanatory
practices. There must be a route to knowledge of what has to be the case, the metaphysical structure of reality, which is
not (essentially) dependent on our practices of explanation. It will be a discovery that features which figure in definition
are the explanatorily basic ones. For, their having the latter role is not (in any way) what makes them essential.
Aristotle, if I am correct, must reject this response, one most often associated with Plato. For, it too rests on the
assumption that it is possible to determine what is definitional independently of our practices of explanation. Both
Platonist and conventionalist assume that our definitional practices are complete (or completable) without materials
drawn from our understanding of the world's causal order. But it is precisely this assumption that Aristotle rejects. In
his view, since our definitions cannot be completed without the use of materials drawn from our explanatory practices,
there is no gap of the relevant kind between definition and explanation. The conventionalist and Platonist both attempt
to fill a non-existent space.
For the Platonist, intellectual intuition by itself reveals to us the modal structure of reality. Once explanation and
definition are separated, there is need for a non-explanation-based route (of this type) to grasp what is definitional. But
no such intuition will be required in Aristotle's account. By contrast, we will (in his view) come to understand what
features are essential by understanding the world through the lens of our interconnected practices of definition and
explanation.397 Thus, knowledge of essences will not depend on any special (and somewhat mysterious) form of
metaphysical intuition. For, Aristotle does not see the need to divorce
397
See Ch. 10 Sect. 10.1.
EXPLANATION AND DEFINITION 251
our practices of definition and explanation in the way which generates the need for intuitive knowledge of essences.398
Aristotle's insistence on the interdependency of our practices of definition and explanation is attractive. Once these
practices are separated, we seem trapped (as in Chapter 1 Section 1.3) between an unacceptable form of Platonism and
an unmotivated form of conventionalism. Aristotle avoids both extremes. Indeed, from his viewpoint, they share a
common false assumption: that a full and determinate account of definition can be completed without dependence on
our explanatory practices. Once this assumption is made explicit and undermined (in the way Aristotle does in the
Analytics), one can resist the temptation to succumb to either of these implausible positions.
Aristotle's idea may be attractive, but is it defensible? We have yet to grasp its basis, examine its consequences, or assess
its strengths and weaknesses. Thus far, we have merely noted the differences between his view and that of the standard
Platonist and conventionalist alternatives. We require a deeper understanding of his own viewpoint and its strengths
and weaknesses. We also need to ‘unpick’, in a more sustained manner, the two alternatives he rejects. In the remainder
of this Chapter, I shall consider some of the origins, motivations, and consequences of Aristotle's view. In the final
Chapter, I shall attempt to assess its merits, and compare them with those of the conventionalist and Platonist
alternatives (see Ch. 13 Sect. 13.2).
398
The Platonist picture encounters a further difficulty at the metaphysical level. If one's starting point is a theory of definition (complete independently of truths about the
causal structure of the world), it remains unexplained why the defining features (so understood) should provide the basis for the relevant form of causation. Why should the
defining features be the very ones which are the basic explanatory building blocks? Could they not be definitional and fail to have any causal role at all? Something further is
required, once definition and causation are separated, to explain why essences are (in reality) per se or fundamental causes. Perhaps the world was set up by some kindly
providence (or demiurge) to ensure that this was the case. Without a metaphysical justification of this sort, there is no guarantee that essences of the type specified have any
role in our understanding of the world.
252 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
The purpose of definition is ‘to make something known’ (Ζ.4, 142a32–3). For this reason, the best type of definition
should be through terms which are ‘prior and more intelligible’ (Ζ.4, 141a29–33, 142a7 ff.), because what is sought is
one permanent definition of the thing in question. The relevant type of priority is exemplified by that of the point over
the line, and of both over the cube (141b5–8). For, the point is (like the other examples Aristotle cites) the principle of
what follows it (141b8 ff.). This, no doubt, is why it is to be used at the beginning of the demonstrations characteristic
of teaching and learning (141a29–31). The point is prior absolutely (141b27 ff.), and because it is the starting point of
our investigation. In definition, we are engaged in a practice which aims to capture certain features in their proper
order. There is, in Aristotle's account in the Topics, an order of priority which the best form of definition should
capture.399
But what is the basis for such an order? Aristotle claims that there should be a single definition of each thing because
each thing has one essence (Ζ.4, 141a35 f.), and that this is why definition should be by means of what is prior and
better known. The basic starting point (in these cases) is the one thing which is what it is to be each thing. Once we
grasp this the whole phenomenon becomes known to us. Hence, the order of knowability is grounded in there being
one feature which makes the thing what it is. Aristotle, in introducing a version of the unity condition we have seen at
work in the Analytics, shows that his definitional constraints are grounded in views about the unity of the object.
But what is the essence in question? What makes it a unity? How are essences to be known? Indeed, more generally,
what is the basis for talk of absolute priority, if understood as capturing the order of nature? In the Topics, Aristotle
makes little progress in spelling out answers to these questions. He does suggest that genus is prior to differentia and
that both are prior to the species defined (Ζ.6, 144b8–11), and that good definitions should locate species within a
genus/ differentia structure (Α.5, 102a31 ff., Ζ.6, 143a29 ff.). Thus, he follows the tradition of using the method of genus
and differentiae in definition (Α.18, 108b5, 29; see also Δ.1, 120b11–12, 121a7,
399 b
There is also a different order of knowability dependent on where we begin (Ζ.4, 141 17–22, b35 ff.). Aristotle raises objections to attempts to give definitions on the basis
of this latter order of knowability (such as the Meno-style definition of ‘plane’ as ‘limit of solid’ (141b 22)). Indeed, he rejects such an attempt because it fails to meet the
b a
requirements he imposes on good definitions (being essence-revealing (141 23–5), capturing what is the appropriate unity (141 35 f.), tracing the desired form of priority
a b
(141 32–4)). (The considerations he adduces parallel those used in Post. An. Β.7 (92 26 ff.) against treating accounts of what names signify as definitional.) However, the
existence of a definitional practice of the type Aristotle criticizes shows that some were prepared to accept answers to the ‘What is it?’ question which did not meet his own
stringent conditions. Such people might be amongst those who ‘say’ that all answers to the ‘What is it?’ question are definitional (Post. An. Β.10, 93 b 29).
EXPLANATION AND DEFINITION 253
Δ.2, 122b1–2). But he does not say what makes something a genus or a differentia, or how these are to be known. These
notions, together with those of absolute priority and of requisite unity, are left indeterminate. Questions such as: ‘Is
being a wingless mortal animal a unity?’ are left unaddressed. As a consequence, the nature of the essences captured in
good definition remains underdetermined.
In Posterior Analytics (prior to Β.8) Topics-style claims are used in what Aristotle describes as ‘general’ or ‘logical’
discussions (Α.21, 82b35 f., Α.22, 84a7 f., Α.32, 88a18 ff.). Definitions at this level satisfy the requirements set in the
Topics: they are of essences (83a24 f.), concern genus and differentia (83b1 ff.), and make the thing defined known to us
(83b5–7). As becomes clear in Posterior Analytics Β, such definitions must involve prior factors and be of unities. But, as
we saw above, Aristotle argues in Β.3–10 that these constraints cannot be met (or even be made fully determinate)
without the addition of material drawn from our practice of explanation.400 His crucial move is from the ‘logical
syllogism’ to the method of causal demonstration (in Β.8), from a ‘logical’ to a distinctively ‘analytical’ discussion.
Without the further material thus introduced, Aristotle would have had no way of satisfying the logical conditions he
had set himself. Indeed, the relevant ideas of priority and unity would have remained indeterminate.401
There are several layers in Aristotle's thought about definition. The Topics is concerned with the most general (‘logical’)
notions, as set out above. In the Analytics, these are made more determinate by the addition of material drawn from his
account of causal explanation. At the next level, the causal-definitional scheme of the Analytics is made even more
determinate by the use of notions designed to interpret the physical world, such as matter, form, process, and goal.
Definitions of substances at this level can only be secured if matter and form are added to the conceptual stock of the
Analytics. But these will be more determinate versions of the types of definition introduced in the Topics and refined in
the Analytics.402
400 a
On this, see Chs. 7 and 8. Aristotle distinguishes ‘logical’ from ‘analytical’ in Post. An. Α.22, 84 7–8, where the latter invokes material drawn from the theory of
a
demonstration (84 10 ff.). The ‘analytical’ can be distinguished from the ‘logical’ and the ‘physical’ since (unlike the former) it is concerned with explanation but (unlike the
a
latter) is not concerned with explanations specific to the details of a particular subject area. Thus, Ζ.17 might move from the logical to the analytical at 1041 28 ff., without
as yet reaching the level of the physical.
401
This reflects the claims of Chapters 8 ff.
402
At the most specific level, one would expect to find particular physical theories about particular types of phenomena employing the general framework arrived at through
these stages of determination to analyse particular kinds or types of phenomena (such as biological kinds, eclipses . . . ). These too should be placed within the general
framework set by the levels above them in the relevant hierarchy.
254 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
What is the epistemic status of Aristotle's claims about definition in the Topics? He is concerned with issues which are
not peculiar to individual sciences, but which are the principles of everything (101a37 ff.). His definitions are ones
which will be accepted by all who are ‘intellectually in good condition’ (Ζ.4, 142a9–11), and are not dependent on any
particular experiential route or scientific discipline. Thus, his definitions reflect a generally held theory, available to
anyone who thinks properly about these issues. All competent thinkers will have a theory of the world as containing
kinds, standing in natural genera, with essences, which are prior and unities (in the ways suggested). They will also
think of definition as what captures the essences in question.403 Indeed, they are competent thinkers because they think
of the world and definition in this way.404
The ‘logical’ level of thought, derived from the Topics, exercises an important influence on Aristotle's argument in the
Analytics. Recall, for example, his criticisms of Xenocrates (as developed in Chapter 7). Aristotle objects that
Xenocrates cannot satisfy the requirement that good definitions should be of prior features which underwrite the unity
of the kind. But why should Xenocrates accept this assumption? Perhaps he should reject it, and cling to his original
account of definition nonetheless.
Aristotle offered no explicit defence of the relevant assumption in Posterior Analytics Β. As in the Topics, good definition
is understood to be that which captures what is prior in the order of nature. This is taken as a background assumption
which all competent participants in this discussion are bound to accept. It is not the type of claim which anyone (who
knows what definition is) can reject. Xenocrates cannot maintain his position merely by denying that definition has to
be of prior unities. For, if he had done this, he would no longer have been engaged in a (competent) discussion about
definition.405 Here, the background ‘logical’ theory is at work
403
The epistemic status of these claims will depend on their expressing generally held intuitions, elements in a simple (non-scientific) theory to which all (in good epistemic
condition) will subscribe. They will be a priori (not dependent on any particular type of experience) and may be taken as constitutive of what it is to be a definition. This
formulation does not require these claims to be ‘analytical’ components of the meaning of the term ‘definition’ or to be known on the basis of the meaning of this term
(‘analytically certain’, as Owen suggested in ‘Tithenai ta phainomena’). More needs to be said on this issue, but its proper consideration lies outside the present study.
404
It is not the case that the world is thus and so (solely) because this is what competent thinkers think. However, this leaves open the possibility that while thinkers are in good
intellectual condition because they see the world in a given way, the world is the way it is because this is how thinkers in good condition see it. This latter possibility is a
version of the no-priority view, discussed above.
405
It is the kind of remark no one would make unless defending a thesis! (See NE 1.5, 1096a 1–2.)
EXPLANATION AND DEFINITION 255
setting the standards against which both Xenocrates and Aristotle's own proposals are to be judged.406
It may be objected that certain definitions do not (on Aristotle's own admission) encapsulate the relevant type of
priority. Some may lack the requisite priority (e.g. the definitions of half and double (Topics Ζ.4, 142a27 ff.)), since
neither can be defined without the other. Others might be of objects such as white man which lack an appropriately
unified cause (Meta. Ζ.4, 1030b12 f.). If so, perhaps Aristotle's use of explanatory materials is restricted merely to one
subset of definitions, such as might be given of substances or natural kinds. Perhaps he has a general theory of
definition which is quite independent of these concerns.
However, Aristotle regards definitions which do not involve priority or unity as special cases (Topics 142a32 f.),
derivative and peripheral examples which do not share the salient features present in the case of substances (Meta. Ζ.4,
1030b6 f.). If the argument given above is correct, one can see why this is so. Definitions of relations or improper
unities will fail to manifest the type of priority and unity required by the ‘logical’ theory of definition. Definitions of
substances are (justifiably) taken as the central case of definition (in part) because they reveal and make determinate the
very features required by the general theory of definition.407 It is not that Aristotle invokes explanatory concerns merely
to accommodate one subset of cases (involving substances or natural kinds) where explanation is particularly
appropriate. Nor is it that he merely stipulates that such cases are to be taken as the central instances of definition. It is
rather that they are central because they meet the basic requirements of the general theory of definition.
406
Similar remarks may be appropriate in considering Aristotle's use of ‘logical’ material in the earlier sections of Meta. Ζ. Many of his claims there (such as concern definition
and priority) might be taken as ones on which all participants to the discussion should agree. Frank Lewis has called such assumptions ‘big-tent’ ones: open to all, no matter
what their particular theories may be (‘Metaphysics Zeta: A Budget Tour’ (unpublished MS)). These issues require further detailed investigation.
407
It is consistent with this claim that definitions of substances may be preferred to other definitions (such as those of eclipse or thunder) which also exemplify the relevant
unity and priority conditions on other grounds (such as ontological basicness).
256 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
without reference to such phenomena. In the Analytics, the terms invoked in structural explanation (as discussed in
Chapter 8) specify substances and features (such as essences) which belong per se to substances.408 So, there can be no
stating what structural explanation is without invoking essences in the world. Such explanations cannot be regarded
simply as projections from us on to a neutral reality. For, if essences are features of the world, and serve as per se causes
(in the favoured case corresponding to unqualified demonstration), such causes (explanantia) also must be things in the
world. So understood, essences and causes cannot be merely projections from our practices of definition and
explanation on to the world. For, those practices themselves cannot be understood without reference to real-world
phenomena such as essences and kinds.
Does it follow from these considerations alone that the metaphysical co-determination of essence and causation is
prior to and more basic than the interdependency of our definitional and explanatory practices? Not immediately.
Perhaps neither thesis is prior to the other. Maybe we cannot specify our definitional practices without reference to
essences or characterize what essences are independently of our definitional practices. Perhaps, equally, we cannot say
what explanation is without mentioning real-world explanantia, or specify the latter without reference to explanation.
Perhaps Aristotle thought that there was no way to say whether the interdependency of our practices was more or less
basic than the interconnection of essence and per se structural cause?409 Did he give reasons for taking one thesis as
prior to the other?
Aristotle, I shall argue, held that the relevant metaphysical thesis is not dependent on the interdependency of our
practices of definition and explanation. Indeed, he intended to use the former to justify the latter. Here are three
reasons for this view:
(1) In the Analytics, Aristotle argues for the interdependency thesis by showing that our definitional practices are
not sufficient (without the assistance of explanatory material) to provide adequate definitions. The
interdependency thesis is not something that he can simply take for granted on the basis of existing definitional
and explanatory practices. Indeed, his proposal seems to be a response to problems which he saw in the
accounts of definition offered by earlier thinkers.410
408 a
For the use of this structure in analysing the example of eclipse, see Barnes's discussion of 73 34 in ‘Aristotle's Posterior Analytics’, 2nd edn. (Oxford, 1994), 113.
409
This form of no-priority view is discussed earlier in considering the role of the active intellect, in Chapter 5. (See also Ch. 1.)
410
In Chapter 7, we discussed his criticisms of Xenocrates, and more generally of the methods of division and general deduction. It is tempting to see the interdependency
thesis as Aristotle's way of addressing certain problems which he detected in the approach to definition taken by Socrates (as illustrated in the Meno) and by Plato elsewhere.
Their methods, when they stayed at the ‘logical’ level, did not contain resources sufficient to establish definitions. Further, because their methods did not essentially involve
causal/explanatory considerations, they could not sustain claims about the priority and unity of definition. If this is correct, Aristotle's remarks on definition in the Analytics
constitute his attempt to resolve the problems about definition which had troubled his predecessors. These issues require further study elsewhere.
EXPLANATION AND DEFINITION 257
But what is the basis for his position? In Β.2, 90a14–15 Aristotle relies on the claim that there is an obvious connection
between what a thing is and why that thing is as it is. Thus, he takes it as evident that there is a direct connection
between something's being the thing it is and a certain type of causal story: one which explains its internal structure. In
effect, he assumes at the outset that there is a fundamental connection between the basic essence of the thing and the
causally basic starting point in the relevant form of causal explanation. Indeed, what it is to be the basic essence of the
thing is (inter alia) to be a per se cause of a given type. If so, Posterior Analytics Β begins with what appears to be a
metaphysical thesis linking being and causality. His aim, therefore, is to give an account of definition and explanation
which reflects this metaphysical interconnection.
(2) What are Aristotle's grounds for the metaphysical co-determination thesis, which is taken as basic in the
Analytics? Does he argue for it on metaphysical grounds. Or does he elsewhere depend on the assumed
interconnection of our practices? A metaphysical defence of this thesis would require him to show that:
Aristotle, I shall suggest, defends (1) and (2) by direct metaphysical argument. While the full investigation of these
topics would require an extended treatment, I shall merely sketch an outline of Aristotle's approach.411
411
I have defended parts of this sketch in ‘Teleological Causation in the Physics ’, 111 ff. However, other parts require a fuller discussion of Aristotle's views on chance and
efficient causation. My sketch of the latter topic has been considerably influenced by discussions with Lindsay Judson.
412
Such causes will not merely necessitate their effects but also show such effects to be consequences of the nature of the causes. It cannot be enough for A to cause B that the
former necessitates the latter. The causal connection needs to be one which is intelligible to us in the light of the natures of the causes. For a contrasting view, see Richard
Sorabji's suggestion that Aristotle analyses ‘cause’ in terms of necessitation alone (Necessity, Cause and Blame, Ch. 1).
258 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
Aristotle argues for a connection of this type in his discussion of cases of chance and accident or coincidence
(sumptoma) in the Physics. He considers examples where two distinct ‘streams’ of causal processes happen to intersect at
a given place and time. For example, one individual chooses to go to market for his own purposes, while a second
individual (or set of individuals) go there for their own separate goals. The two streams intersect ‘by chance’ when the
two individuals meet.413 Here, as Aristotle insists, there is no per se cause of the intersection of the two processes. For, in
such cases there is neither a mind nor a nature (Β.6, 198a1–13) aiming at (e.g.) the repayment of the debt, which brings
about these effects simultaneously. In the case of natural (non-intentional) processes, the absence of a nature of the
appropriate type entails the absence of a per se cause.414 Indeed, more generally, intersections of this type can have only
incidental causes (see Meta. Έ.2, 1027a7 f.).415 But this is because in the basic case there are natures acting as per se causes
of the relevant effects. At this point, Aristotle is assuming that there is a metaphysical connection between causation
and nature, not dependent on our explanatory or definitional practices. Indeed, his basic picture is of a world
comprising simple natures (grounded in essences) as per se causes, standing in regular causal connections with one
another. This viewpoint, and the corresponding account of chance, is a metaphysically driven one.
413 a
Similarly, it may happen that one causal process results in the development of sharp teeth, another in the development of flat teeth (Phys. Β.8, 199 23 ff.). What is a chance
a
or automatic result is that (in the theory under discussion) both processes happen at the same time and in the same place (199 27, 30). For further discussion of this
passage, see my ‘Teleological Causation in the Physics ’, 111 ff.
414
It is fully consistent with this that the intersection is itself necessitated by antecedent conditions, such as the combined ‘event’ of A's being at P at t and B's being at P at t.
However, such a combined event would not be a per se cause because it is not itself a nature or (in the case under discussion) the result of anyone's plan. Even if the world is
fully necessitated, there will be examples of occurrences which lack per se causes. For a contrasting view, see Richard Sorabji's analysis of these passages in Necessity, Cause and
Blame, Ch. 1. It is to be noted that occurrences of the type envisaged could remain coincidences even if (possibly per impossibile ) they happened frequently. If so,
infrequency may be a sign of ‘chance’ but cannot constitute it. (These issues are illuminatingly discussed by Lindsay Judson in ‘Chance and “Always or for the Most Part” ’,
in Judson (ed.), Aristotle's Physics, 78 ff.)
415
A detailed analysis of Meta. Έ.2–3 lies outside the scope of the present work. Naturally, I am drawn to the view that ‘those principles and causes which do not come to be’
(1027a 29–32) are ones which come to be without a per se cause of the appropriate type (viz. a nature or planning mind). This view, along with several alternatives, is
discussed by Lindsay Judson in ‘What Can Happen When You Eat Pungent Food’, (in N. Avgelis and F. Peonidis (eds.), Aristotle on Logic, Language and Science (Thessaloniki,
1998) ). I am indebted to Lindsay Judson for several helpful discussions of these issues.
EXPLANATION AND DEFINITION 259
Anyone who asserts this does away with ‘by nature’ and ‘nature’ itself. For, whatever arrives at some goal by a
continuous movement from an internal starting point happens ‘by nature’. The result is not the same for each, but
yet it is not a matter of chance; but what occurs always tends towards the same goal, if nothing intervenes. (Phys.
Β.8, 199b14–18)
His basic point is this: If one removes talk of goals, one undermines talk of natures and natural processes. For, the
latter are essentially defined in terms of goals. Thus, both can be understood as essentially composed of parts which
are for the sake of a goal, which will be achieved if nothing intervenes. This is what natures and natural processes are.
Both are to be defined in terms of the goals of their respective stages or parts. His defence of teleological causation
stops at this point. If it were not a genuine form of causation, the world would contain no natures and no natural
processes. As required by the co-determination thesis, what it is to be a given thing and what it is to be a given type of
cause stand or fall together.416
Both these claims are made and supported on metaphysical grounds. In the next Chapter, I shall argue that the second
claim is central to Aristotle's discussion of substance in Metaphysics Ζ, Η, and Θ. There too the interconnection of our
practices of definition and explanation is given a metaphysical basis in the relation between being and causation.
(3) Nor should Aristotle's preference for giving priority to metaphysical theses surprise us. For, in speaking of
knowledge and perception, he says that they are:
the measure of things because we get to know something by them. Thus, they are measured by reality rather than
themselves being the measurers of reality. (Meta. .2, 1053a31 ff.)
We have knowledge precisely because our states match up to reality. The relevant test lies with nature not with us or
with our practices. For the latter are tested by nature itself.417
This perspective is evident in the case of the type of enquiry envisaged in the Analytics. For, here we may go on
investigating until we come finally
416
For further discussion of this, and related issues, see my ‘Teleological Causation in the Physics ’.
417
I examine no-priority interpretations of Aristotle's ethical writings in my ‘Aristotle and Modern Realism’, 135 ff.
260 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
to uncover the basic cause (Β.8, 93a12–14). Here, it is nature which determines the end of our enquiry. What really is
the case is not limited to what we think (or even can think) now. We may perhaps be led to discover new causes beyond
those we now grasp (or even can grasp). Equally, we may come to see that our present views are in some ways
mistaken or inadequate (see, for example, Β.13, 97b14 ff.). In these ways, what we come to think will be determined (if
all goes well) by how the world is.418 Indeed, in some cases our enquiries will be incomplete simply because we cannot
find in reality the features we seek.419 Here, our practices answer to the world. Authority lies there and not with our
practices of definition and explanation.
If our definitional practices are incomplete without material drawn from our explanatory ones, and the latter rest on
our ability to track per se causes in the world, it follows that our definitional practices are incomplete
418
I take it to be a constitutive feature of no-priority interpretations that they take what the world is to be identical with what is thinkable. For this allows for the very same
principles to govern our thought and the world we think about. But is ‘what is thinkable’ limited to what is thinkable by us now or can it also include what is thinkable by us
in ideal conditions. The latter is required to allow for enquiry. But, if so, what limits what is thinkable in ideal conditions? Surely these limits come from the world and not
from us. (Similar concerns will arise if one introduces the ideal thinker in ideal conditions. What constrains what he/she thinks, apart from how the world really is?)
419
See Ch. 12 Sect. 12.6 ff.
EXPLANATION AND DEFINITION 261
without the use of material drawn from our grasp on the world's per se causal structure. Conversely, if our explanatory
practices are incomplete without material drawn from our definitional ones, and these in turn rest on our grasping
essences in the world, our explanations rest on our ability to grasp essences in the world. Thus, we should add to the
diagram above, two diagonal arrows:
to capture the dependence of our definitional practices on the causal structure of the world, and that of our
explanatory practices on our grasp of essences.
This interpretation allows us to understand more securely some of Aristotle's problematic remarks about thought and
its objects. Indeed, his discussion in De Anima seems to illustrate (in a vivid way) three points which are central to our
present concerns.
(1) One of his claims in De Anima (noted in our earlier discussion)420 runs as follows:
(A) Our (passive) intellects function properly when and only when objects of a given type impact on us.
(B) Our (passive) intellects function properly when and only when we think of objects as organized in an
intelligible and general structure.
(C) The active intellect is identical with a properly organized, general, and intelligible structure of thinkable objects
(such as kinds).
(A) requires that we are causally influenced in our thinking by objects and kinds in the world. In the order of
explanation (with regard to the content of our thought), as in the model developed in the last Section, priority is given
to the world. Further, as required by (B), a thinker must be able to locate the kind in its appropriate niche in an
organized and intelligible structure. (For, this is how thought differs from experience.421) Indeed, in successful and
completed thought the thinker will be able to give definitions of the kind which are dependent in the ways specified on
his practices of explanation.
But (B) does not by itself establish that it is an essential feature of a kind that it occupies a given slot in the structure of
the world. Nor does it
420
See Ch. 5 Sect. 5.4.
421
See Ch. 6 Sect. 6.2.
262 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
underwrite the idea that the structure of the world is an intelligible and organized one. The most that (A) and (B) can
guarantee is that we cannot think of a kind save as occupying a given place in the cosmos.
How does Aristotle sustain (C)? In De Anima he introduces at this point the active intellect, which he identifies with the
objects of thought (including kinds and their essences). If this identity could be sustained, he could argue that kinds are
essentially individuated by their position in an intelligible structure in the following way:
(D) It is a condition of our thoughts being the ones they are that they are thoughts of kinds located in an organized
cosmos.
(E) A similar condition obtains for the thoughts of the active intellect.
(F) The thoughts of the active intellect are identical with the kinds of which it thinks.
So (G) Those kinds must be essentially individuated by their position in an organized and intelligible cosmos.
But what is the basis for (F)? Why should anyone identify the organized cosmos with the activity of the active intellect?
Why regard the world and a certain form of mind as identical or as constructed on identical principles? One answer
would be given by the no-priority interpretation, just considered. But we have seen reason both here and in Chapter 5
to reject this reading of Aristotle.422
If Aristotle accepts the co-determination thesis, he has an alternative way to support his conclusion ((G) above). For, if
the essences of kinds are per se causes of a given type, kinds will be individuated by features which play a basic role in
the world's causal order. Further, that order will be an intelligible one because the starting point for the relevant causal
connections will lie in those essential features which make the kinds the ones they are. These causal connections will be
completely perspicuous to us because they follow from the kinds' essences. (This claim rests on the presence of the
downwards diagonal arrow from explanatory practice to essence.) In this way, the kinds will be wholly intelligible to us.
For, their derived features will be seen to be causally dependent on their essences and to be made what they are by
being so caused. (A similar story can be told for the genera to which species kinds belong.423)
If this is correct, the world's causal order will be intrinsically intelligible,
422
According to the no priority theorist, the world (as we grasp it) is governed by the same principles as our minds because no sense can be made of a world in categories other
than those that govern our minds. Indeed, what we understand and the world so understood are identical. It makes no sense to ask whether these principles come from us
or from the world. No sense can be made of giving priority to either side of the equation.
423
See Ch. 9 Sects. 9.2 and 9.3.
EXPLANATION AND DEFINITION 263
exemplifying the type of knowability we seek.424 While Aristotle's talk of the active intellect may encapsulate (in a vivid
way) his view that the world is intelligible, its role will not be to explain that intelligibility. On the contrary, it is because
the world's order is an intelligible one (in the ways underwritten by the co-determination thesis) that it can be
understood in terms of the active intellect. While talk of the latter may introduce a high-level or theological description
of an ordered and intelligible world, it is one available only after the hard work of metaphysics has been done. It is not
an alternative way of doing that work.
While, according to the co-determination thesis, essences are (by metaphysical law) per se causes of a given type, they
could not play this causal role unless they were unities with their own distinctive natures. It would be (at best)
misleading to suggest that (for Aristotle) essences could be defined simply in terms of what plays a given causal role.
For, in his account, the relevant causal role can only be played by essences, features which make the relevant kinds
what they are. For similar reasons, it would be (at best) misleading to represent Aristotle as defining essences solely in
terms of what is able to fit into an organized and intelligible world (see 5.7). For, in his view, it is only essences, with
their own distinctive features, which can fit in this way into such a world. In this respect, the co-determination thesis
serves to clarify some of the metaphysical issues left unresolved in his discussion of colour and the active intellect.
(2) There is a second way in which De Anima provides a model for Aristotle's metaphysical (co-determination) thesis
and for his contention that our practices of defining and explaining are interdependent. In De Anima, Aristotle treats
colours and the objects of thought as parallel. Colours (in his account) are real features of the world which impact on
us, but ones which only impact on us because we are creatures with a certain form of sensibility. In a similar way,
essences are features of the world which impact on us only because we engage in a certain form of thought. We can
now see why this is so: we can only grasp essences of this type because we have definitional and explanatory practices
of the type indicated. In neither case need the limited accessibility of the respective objects impugn their reality.425 Both
colours and the world's intelligible causal order are objective features, even though they are accessible only to those
with specific definitional and explanatory practices or visual capacities. (This claim follows from the downwards
vertical arrows linking the top and bottom levels of the diagram).
(3) There is one further point of comparison between Aristotle's discussions of thought and colour. In his view, our
capacity to see can only be
424
See Ch. 13 Sect. 13.3 for further discussion of the type of knowability involved here.
425
See Ch. 5 Sect. 5.2. This issue is illuminatingly discussed by Justin Broackes in ‘Aristotle, Objectivity and Perception’, 61 ff.
264 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
understood in terms of our responsiveness to colours in the medium. Similarly, our capacity to think of essences will
be (for him) grounded in our responsiveness to the causal order around us. For, the type of understanding we seek (as
encapsulated in the general theory of definition) cannot be made fully determinate without reference to how the world
actually works. Our practices of definition depend on our being sensitive to causal patterns in the world. Just as we
cannot make sense of visual perception without reference to colours existing in the medium, so we cannot make sense
of the type of intelligibility we seek in definition without reference to the structure of the world. (This claim follows
from the downwards diagonal arrow linking definitional practice and the per se causal structure of the world).
We can now see why, in Aristotle's account, our minds and the world must work on the same principles. For, our
practices of definition and explanation are dependent (in the ways indicated) on the intelligible order of the world. That
said, we would not have been able to grasp that intelligible order (or certain features as definitional) had our practices
of definition and explanation not been as they are. For, we can only discover, for example, what is the basic essence of
a kind because we see it as the starting point in an appropriate form of explanatory account. If we had lacked
definitional and explanatory practices of this type, the intelligible structure of reality would have escaped us.
In these three ways, Aristotle's discussion of thought, colour, and the active intellect sketches vividly, if incompletely,
the metaphysical and epistemological picture which he draws more fully elsewhere in terms of the interdependency and
co-determination theses. Taken together, these two discussions present a distinctive and ingenious philosophical
position, which will be investigated in detail in the final Chapter. There is, however, an immediate exegetical concern
which must be addressed. Some will object that, whatever the philosophical plausibility of the position that has
emerged, it cannot be Aristotle's own. For, they will say, in Posterior Analytics Β.19 he developed an account of our grasp
of first principles which appears to be completely independent of our practices of
EXPLANATION AND DEFINITION 265
explanation.426 If this is correct, they will have challenged (in a most effective way) one of the central interpretative
claims of the last three chapters. It is time to consider their objection in detail.
426
There has been considerable debate about whether in this chapter Aristotle is concerned with grasp of immediate (or simple) entities or with grasp of the immediate
propositions of science. Barnes concludes ‘I feel obliged to concede that Aristotle did not realize that he was vacillating between two stories’ (Aristotle's Posterior Analytics,
260). Ross, in effect, took the same view, finding evidence for Aristotle's concern both with the acquisition of concepts (Aristotle's Analytics, 675) and with knowledge of the
premisses of demonstration (p. 675), and not fitting these two together in a unified way. Modrak (Aristotle: The Power of Perception (Chicago, 1987), 162) claims that Aristotle
did not distinguish between primitive concepts and indemonstrable propositions, while, earlier, Kahn suggested (‘The Role of nous in the Cognition of First Principles in
Posterior Analytics 2.19’, in Berti, (ed.) Aristotle on Science, 391, 395) that he was correct not to distinguish because ‘there is no gap between a propositional and conceptual
b
view of principles’. The difficulty arises because Aristotle begins by talking about immediate propositions (99 17, 21), but later speaks of grasp of universals and of
a b
universals standing in the soul (100 6, 15, 17, 2, 3). However, it is not clear that this debate is a real one. The mathematician who grasps the simple unit understands that it
is indivisible in quantity, and, thus, understands an immediate proposition of the relevant science. In grasping a basic external universal of this kind, a basic proposition of
b
science becomes known to one. Indeed, Aristotle claims just this when he argues that nous grasps the immediate propositions of science (100 9–14), and also (as the
starting point of knowledge (100b 15)) grasps certain universals (100b 5–8). It is not merely a pun to the effect that nous grasps both types of starting point. Aristotle has
indicated that he has reason to think that in grasping the basic universal, one grasps an immediate and basic proposition of science.
427
For a recent statement of this view, see Michael Ferejohn's The Origins of Aristotelian Science, (New Haven, 1991), 4–5.
428
For the epistemological Platonist, intuition is best seen as a separate faculty, distinct from our ability to think discursively. It is not to be understood merely as a distinctive
exercise of our thinking faculty. For my characterization of Platonism, see Ch. 1 n. 37.
266 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
So, for example, we can come to have an intuitive grasp on the definition of animal, free from all concern with
explanation. Since the activity of nous is described as ‘more accurate’ and ‘truer’ than knowledge (100b8, 11), nous
emerges as a high-grade form of perception, which enables us to see the starting points of demonstration without any
assistance from our explanatory practices. If we add:
(3) The activity of nous not only does not involve (in its nature) discursive thought, but also does not depend on
the latter for its epistemological credentials,
we must conclude that nous by itself provides the foundation of our knowledge of definitions and of essence. Indeed,
what makes something essential will be independent of its role in explanation. If so, Aristotle will reject in Β.19 both
the interdependency and the co-determination theses. Either he changed his mind or he did not hold these theses in
the first place.429
I shall challenge the attribution to Aristotle of the combination of claims (1), (2) and (3) which is required by the
Platonist reading of Β.19. The relevant sections of this chapter are best understood as rejecting (at least) claim (3), and
as exemplifying certain central aspects of the interdependency thesis sketched above. Thus, I shall argue that Aristotle
does not commit himself to the view that an intuitive grasp of the nature of primaries is the basis of our knowledge of
definitional truths.
One might initially challenge the contention that Aristotle commits himself in Β.19 to (1) on the basis of the reading of
100a3 ff. offered in Chapter 6. There are two questions which Aristotle might be addressing in Β.19. One is:
(A) How do those things which are starting points become known?
Another is:
(B) How do those things which are starting points become known as starting points?
Question (A) can be answered by giving an account of how (e.g.) the biologist comes to know what the animal is,
which does not provide him with the resources to know that this is the starting point of biology. If Β.19 is
429 a b
In Ch. 6 Sect. 6.2 I interpreted the earlier sections of Β.19 (especially 100 3– 1) as being concerned with the acquisition of concepts (at the level of thought). However, as
was noted there, this account did not engage with the issue of how we come (in Aristotle's view) to grasp something as first principles (or first universals). It is the latter issue
which we must now address.
EXPLANATION AND DEFINITION 267
concerned exclusively with question (A), it will not offer a way to grasp (e.g.) animal as a starting point of the relevant
science. The latter could be done by invoking the practice of demonstration, and by finding out what is first in the
relevant series of demonstration. If so, since nous would not grasp first principles as such, there would be no intuition-
based answer to question (B). Thus, there would be no evidence in Β.19 in favour of claim (1).430
It is plausible, as was noted in Chapter 6, to see Aristotle as concerned in large measure in Β.19 with question (A).
Several considerations favour this view:
(1) He focuses initially on the general issue of how we grasp universals such as man and animal (100b1–3). While
some of the latter are immediates (i.e. the most general universals), others are not (e.g. man (100b1)). The issue
under discussion here appears to be: ‘How are any universals grasped?’, not ‘How are some grasped as starting
points?’ In answering the first question one will consider (inter alia) those universals which are starting points,
but one will not need to consider them as starting points.
(2) In Β.19, 100a10–b4, Aristotle sketches an account of how we arrive at a grasp of universals via perception,
memory, and experience.431 It seems that:
(1) We grasp universals for species such as man (infimae species)432 by a method which is essentially dependent on
perception, memory, and experience. In grasping this, we grasp man as an animal of a given kind. We have a secure
grasp on these universals when and only when we grasp several of them together in this way (100a12–14).433 We
could not properly grasp the universal man, conceived of as an animal of a given kind, unless we also grasp animal,
and perhaps other members of the same genus also.
430
This line of reply would be attractive to an interpreter who thought that the whole of Β.19 was concerned exclusively with the acquisition of concepts. This interpreter would
b a b
seek to account for the problematic lines 100 1 ff in the way used in Ch. 6 Sect. 6.2 to analyse 100 3– 1.
431
See Ch. 6 Sect. 6.2.
432
Man is given as an example of an ‘indivisible’ (adiaphora ) in 100a 16–b 2. Man is an infima species. ‘Adiaphora ’ is used elsewhere for infimae species (97b 31; 97a 37).
433
Barnes emends the text to read ‘until a position of strength is secured’ reading ‘alke ’ for ‘arche ’, as he claims the latter ‘makes no sense’ if understood to mean ‘principle’
(Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, 254). But his emendation is not required. The text as it stands may be understood to mean ‘until the initial point of rout is regained’ (with Pacius
and Ross), or ‘until the original arrangement is regained’ (as Michael Frede once suggested). On these readings, Aristotle's crucial point is to emphasize the regaining of a
secure position/ formation on the relevant part of the battlefield.
268 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
(2) We grasp first, or basic, universals, e.g. animal,434 in a fundamentally similar way, through perception and
induction.435
Thus, we might conclude that Aristotle in Β.19 is offering a sketch of how we grasp universals, not a specific account
of how we grasp first principles as first principles. Perhaps in Β.16–18 he addresses these latter issues. For, there,
explanation requires us to accept the existence of progressively higher-order species until we arrive at genera which are
not themselves species of higher genera. On this basis, we can see that animal is a primary term, and determine what in
a completed science is to count as a primitive universal. Nous, by contrast, may enable us to grasp those things that are
the starting points of explanation, but we will not grasp them as starting points. We do the latter as the result of our
study of the relevant pattern of demonstration.
(3) In the light of (1) and (2) one might read the first sentence of Β.19 as asking the question: ‘How do we come to
have knowledge of those things that are first principles?’ and not ‘How do we come to know them as first principles?’
For, the structure of science will show which are the first principles. The task of Β.19 (on this account) is to show how
we come to grasp those things which are (in fact) first principles. But we will know on independent, explanation-
involving, grounds both what it is to be a first principle and what legitimizes the claim that certain features are first
principles.
However, these three points are not sufficient, by themselves, to rule out the Platonist reading of Β.19. For, Aristotle
ignores (after the first sentence of Β.19) considerations of demonstration, and focuses on an ordering of universals,
apparently established without reference to demonstrative concerns. There must be, it seems, a non-demonstrative
route to grasp what is first and what is subsequent in a series of universals (100a13,b1–5). If so,
434
In this context, ‘ta prota ’ (100b 4) must refer to most general universals such as the example given: animal (100b 3), and not scientific principles. ‘Ta prota ’ is used in this
way elsewhere (76a 32). This interpretation preserves the parallelism with grasp of infimae species, such as man (100b 1). General universals (unlike infimae species ) are
b
described as ‘without parts’, since they are not parts of a more general whole (cf. Meta. Δ.3 1014 6 ff).
435 b
‘For, it is clear that it is necessary to grasp the most general universals by induction. For, indeed it is in this way that perception instils the universal’ (100 2–5). Induction is
frequently used to describe the way we grasp universals from knowing particulars, and, thus, can refer to the same type of process (involving memory, experience, and grasp
of universals described in 100a 4–15). There may be no further step involved in grasping the most general universals beyond those involved in grasping the more specific.
b b a
Aristotle emphasizes that the two processes are similar: both involve a stand being made in the same way (100 2–3), both involve perception (100 4–5, 100 15 f.). On
this reading, ‘kai gar ’ is translated ‘for, indeed’, and not ‘for, perception also . . . ’ If ‘kai ’ were translated in the latter way, this would mean ‘since induction is involved in the
relevant process beginning with particulars, this is the way in which perception also makes its contribution—namely by (i) perceiving . . . and (ii) in doing this, giving
perceptual information about universals as an input to induction’ (see below).
EXPLANATION AND DEFINITION 269
there will be a route to grasp what is primary which is independent of the practice of demonstration. So Aristotle, in
Β.19, must be engaging with question (B) as well as question (A). Since he appears to do this without invoking our
explanatory practices, it is reasonable to conclude that he is invoking Platonist intuition to do so.
The situation is, in reality, even more complex. If Aristotle is answering both questions (A) and (B) in this way, he must
accept that we can grasp some basic definitions, the ones from which science will begin, independently of our
explanatory practices. Indeed, he seems to countenance (in the main sections of Β.19) the possibility of our grasping all
definitions (whether basic or derived) without assistance from our explanatory practices. We grasp not merely Stage 1
accounts of what terms signify in this way, but also correct definitions of (e.g.) the kind itself.436 Surely, for this, we need
Platonist intuition into the nature of things?
There is another way to resist the Platonist reading of Β.19. Its most controversial claim can seem its most innocuous
one: (3). I shall argue that our discussion of Β.13–15 has given us good reason not to attribute (3) to Aristotle. He
approaches the issues raised in Β.19 forearmed with a characterization of the appropriate type of genus/ differentia tree,
which requires him to base the operation of nous on antecedent (discursive) explanatory practices. If so, there is not
merely no reason to see Aristotle as invoking Platonist intuition in Β.19; there is reason not to do so.
Aristotle's discussion of differentiae in Β.13 shows what is involved in grasp on primary genus terms, such as animal. In
that account, one sees man as a member of the genus, animal, from which it is differentiated by features explained by
its essence. The differentiae in question distinguish members of the relevant genus in a way dependent on their
explanatory essences. Animal is the first term in its genus because the other species can be derived from it in a system
of differentiation (of this type).437
If this style of account is presupposed in Β.19, the inductive process (specified in 100b4) will track the pattern of
differentiation, which constitutes the relevant genus/species structure. In the case at hand, one will see animal as the
prime term because all others members of the relevant domain can be defined as animals of a given type. They are
defined in terms of the distinctive ways in which they discharge their animal nature: move/breathe/eat/reproduce, etc.
The features which differentiate animals will be the ones explained by their own distinctive essences (qua animals of
type A). Prime terms, such as animal, are important precisely because they define the relevant subject matter in a way
436
So understood, Aristotle begins Β.19 with an account of the acquisition of concepts on the basis of experience (See Ch. 6), but ends with a description of our definitional
grasp of primary items (in the world). The chapter represents an overview of several stages, elsewhere separated.
437
See Ch. 9.
270 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
which marks out what is explanatorily important. They can be grasped as primary when the other members of their
domain are seen as dependent on them in this way.
We are now in a position to sustain a thoroughly non-Platonist interpretation of the relation between the inductive
process and the operation of nous in Β.19; one fully consistent with Aristotle's discussion in Β.13–15. Nous may grasp
that (e.g.) animal occupies a certain niche in an organized system of definition and explanation. But it does so as a
result of seeing animal as playing a central role in that system. Nous will recognize the results of (or the next step in) an
inductive process which is grounded in a discursive understanding of this system of definition and explanation.438
When we have become immersed in grasping this system, we may know how ‘to go on’ to see the primary terms. But
the latter will be grasped as primary precisely because we see them as providing the basis for this definitional and
explanatory structure.439
On the view just outlined, there is a striking analogy between the role of primary universals and that of the essences of
substances. Both define their respective subject matters (the genus, the kind) and also explain why those subject
matters have the features they do (i.e. why members of the genus (or kind) have certain differentiating features). They
are both simultaneously explainers and definers of their respective objects. (Indeed, this is just as was to be expected
given the interdependency of our practices of explanation and definition.440)
438
In a similar way one could grasp that the unit exists because of the way one comes to have knowledge of it. Thus, one could come to know of its existence when one sees
that its existence is required if the pair and triple are to exist. Alternatively, one might know of its existence via perception of particulars and induction: if there are objects
which are single entities, the unit exists. We are aware of many such particular entities, and hence can infer that the unit exists. This process is facilitated in the case of the unit
because there is no further, distinct, essence of the unit to be grasped—as the cause and the unit are the same (Post. An. Β.9). So, there is no chance of the unit turning out to
be two distinct phenomena under investigation (unlike (e.g.) pride (97b13–25)). In both cases, we can grasp with confidence that the unit exists independently of seeing it as
the first element in a science.L. A. Kosman argued that nous does not involve grasp of the existence of the starting points (‘Understanding, Explanation and Insight in the
Posterior Analytics’, in E. N. Lee, A. P. D. Mourelatos, and R. M. Rorty (eds.), Exegesis and Argument: Phronesis, Suppl. 1 (1973), 384) on the basis of a reading of Post. An. Ι.13.
But the inference is faulty, since nous may grasp that primitive universals exist on the basis of a previous inductive procedure.
439
So understood, intuition need not be construed as a separate faculty, but may be taken simply as a distinctive exercise of a general faculty of reason. What is crucial for
present purposes is that the activity of nous is supported by discursive thought in the ways suggested.
440
In a similar way, the common axioms which concern equality and inequality (Α.10, 76a41, Α.11, 77a32) define the subject matter of (general) relations, and explain why other
derived relations are as they are. Similar remarks will apply to common axioms about ratios and proportions, which are relevant not only in mathematics but also in other
sciences as well (see Nicomachus, Arithmetike Eisagoge, 18; Iamblichus, De Communi Mathematica Scientia ed. N. Festo (Leipzig, 1891), 18–20). It is interesting to note that
Proclus regards such axioms as common principles, studied by ‘the science of being qua being’ from which ‘several sciences get their common propositions’ (Commentary on
the First Book of Euclid's Elements, ed. G. Morrow (Princeton, 1970), 9.19).It might seem that the principle of non-contradiction does not fall easily into this pattern. For, as it is
used as the basis for proof, it might be thought to define no distinctive subject matter. However, one might reply that ‘logical’ principles of this type define the nature of
coherent speech and thought (Meta. Γ.4, 1006a22,b5–11). While a proper consideration of this topic would take us far away from our present task, one can see how the
combined definitional/explanatory approach could be extended to this area also.
EXPLANATION AND DEFINITION 271
A non-Platonist reading of Β.19 may be possible. But why should we accept it? There are several reasons for doing so.
First, it is natural to take the genus/species structure (invoked in 100b2–4) as the one uncovered by the methods
discussed in Β.13 and employed in Β.14. Otherwise, Aristotle would have provided no account of the type of
definitional structure introduced in Β.19. However, if this is correct, Β.19's genus/species structure will rest on a
system of differentiae permeated by explanatory considerations (as required by the argument of Chapter 9).
Second, in this account, nous can operate in a non-discursive manner without undermining induction's claim to be a
process essentially involving discursive thought and inference. Nous can see certain objects in a given way provided
that its operation arises out of and its results are constrained by a preceding inductive process. It sees what it sees
because it is grounded in the preceding inductive stages. Thus, although it is itself non-discursive, its success is
grounded in discursive reflection and inference.
Third, in this account, induction and demonstration remain distinct, but closely connected. The inductive procedure
picks out the explanatorily relevant features of kinds in a hierarchical structure. But, as was noted in Chapter 9, it is
precisely this structure which is relevant for explanation. In this way, we mark out derived species by means of features
which are themselves related to their explanatory essences. It is, thus, no accident that the first terms in a genus of this
type are the ones relevant for the starting points of demonstration. For, they are chosen because of their distinctive
position in a differentiating system which itself rests on explanatory considerations. Although induction does not itself
directly involve demonstration, it is permeated by our explanatory concerns. This is why induction can give us a route
to grasp the structures relevant for explanation, even though induction itself does not involve the formulation of
demonstrations.
If this non-Platonist reading is accepted, nous can only grasp certain features as the first elements in a science on the
basis of an explanation-involving procedure of induction. Its epistemic authority will be derived from the process of
induction on which it rests. Thus, nous will grasp as first principles items whose status is vindicated by their role in an
272 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
explanation-based system of differentiation of the type set out in Β.13–15. Neither those chapters nor Β.19 is
committed to any version of epistemological foundationalism about first principles.
This non-Platonist reading of Β.19 rests on a metaphysical basis. What makes primary universals primary is their central
role in an interdependent system of definition and explanation. They mark out a subject matter in a way which makes
clear its metaphysical and causal structure. If so, Aristotle's discussion in Β.19, so far from undermining his earlier
picture, in fact confirms it.
It will be objected that Aristotle's insistence on the epistemic superiority of nous (100b8 ff.) commits him
(notwithstanding our previous remarks) to a Platonist account of the role of intuition. This objection can be met. Let
us grant that from the perspective of the completed science, one in which everything is set out in its proper order
matching the hierarchic structure of reality, the primitives (such as the dyad or animal) will be known before anything
else. Even so, this truth reflects the order of nature, not the order of our coming to know what is the case (71b31–72a5).
Similarly the observation that primaries are better known than their consequences (72b26–32) need exhibit nothing
more than their role (in a completed science) in supporting a wide variety of consequences. Finally, Aristotle's remark
that nous is more ‘accurate than knowledge’ (when it grasps immediate starting points of science) need only mean that
what it grasps is closer to the relevant basic principles of science (100b8;cf. 86a13–21). In a completed science one will
rely most on first principles since these support a wide variety of consequences. They will sustain more weight than any
particular conclusion drawn from them.
None of these claims shows that we must come to know primary terms before we know the others or that they are
immediately believable (or self-evident). For, in the ways indicated, we can come to know that claims about primaries
are (a) about first terms (b) about existent objects, and (c) particularly significant, without having started our enquiry
with claims which concern first principles. There is no need to attribute any special epistemological authority to nous (in
our enquiries) to allow for its special status in Β.19. For, that may flow from its distinctive role and objects in a
completed science, and not from its intrinsic epistemological powers.
To conclude: Aristotle's account of our grasp of first principles in Β.19 is dependent, in the ways indicated, on our
engagement with the explanation-based system of genus/species differentiation outlined in Β.13–15. Thus, first
principles have their special status because they play a central and distinctive role in Aristotle's interdependent stories
of differentiation and explanation. We see certain items as primary when we understand that they play a central role in
this story.
EXPLANATION AND DEFINITION 273
441
I shall examine below the extent to which Aristotle carried over this specific aspect of his Analytics account into his biological writings. An affirmative answer does not
commit one to the further claim that Aristotle sought to implement the whole Analytics picture of a fully axiomatized, complete, science in his biological writings.
11 Substance, Denition, and Essence
11.1 Introduction
To what extent did Aristotle employ in the central books of the Metaphysics (Ζ, Η, Θ) the strategy he develops in the
Analytics to tackle issues concerning definition, essence, and explanation? This question can be subdivided and made
more precise. Did he answer the question ‘What is substance?’ in a manner which meets the requirements for adequate
definition set in the Analytics (noted in Chapter 7)? Are the practices of definition and explanation interconnected in the
Metaphysics as they are in the Analytics?
I shall argue for an affirmative answer to both these questions. Aristotle's answers to questions such as ‘What is man?’
satisfy his own Definitional Constraint and Simple Condition.442 Further, his discussion throughout reflects the
interdependency of definition and explanation which is argued for in the Analytics. In both works, the account of
definition is made determinate by the addition of causal material. Indeed, in general, we gain further insight into
Aristotle's strategy in Metaphysics Ζ, Η, and Θ if we see it in the light of his Analytics account of definition and
explanation. Or so I shall suggest.
Aristotle notes in Posterior Analytics Β.9 that his method of demonstration and definition applies not only to the cases of
substance/attribute pairs discussed in Β.8, but also to a wider category. Thus, he distinguishes two relevant kinds of
example:
(1) In some, the thing and its cause are the same. Here, there will not be a separate middle term (or cause).
(93b21–5)443
442
See Ch. 7 Sects 7.3–7.4. Aristotle typically focuses on examples (such as man) in considering the ‘What is substance?’ question. He supposes (I shall assume) that if he can
provide a satisfactory answer to a range of specific ‘What is . . . ?’ questions for particular substances he will have the resources (e.g. matter, form . . . ) to give a general
answer to the ‘What is substance?’ question. His answers to such specific questions will be metaphysical (and not scientific) provided that they maintain the degree of
generality (and independence of empirical detail) required in metaphysical enquiry.
443 b
In 93 21–5 Aristotle refers back to cases where the cause is not different. He now specifies such cases as those where the what it is is not different, and the objects are
immediate or starting points with respect to the what it is. In these examples, the thing and its essence will be identical, as the unit and the essence of the unit are identical.
The grammatical subject, however, is the thing (viz. the unit) and not its essence; for, its existence is hypothesized and it is it which ‘has’ an essence (93b 23, 24–5). Further, it
is objects not essences which are referred to in the two adjacent sentences (93b 21, 93b 25–8). So, in 93b 21–5 Aristotle is referring (in subject place) to things which have
essences, and distinguishing cases where the thing and its essence are not separated or distinct.
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 275
(2) In others, the thing and its cause are distinct. Here, there will be a middle term which is the cause of the thing
being as it is. (93b25–8)444
However, Aristotle does not develop this suggestion or show how it can be applied to cases such as that of man
(mentioned in Β.1, 89b34). Is he attempting to implement this suggestion in the Metaphysics? If so, his discussion should
exhibit (at least) three structural features.
SF(1) There should be a division between substances which are identical with their causes, and those which are
not (to match his claims in Posterior Analytics Β.9).
SF(2) There should be an Analytics-style interdependence between the explanatory story uncovered in SF(1) and
the answer to the definitional ‘What is F?’ question. Each should depend on the other.
SF(3) There should be, in the case of composite substances, a basic unifying causal feature which explains the
substance's possession of its other genuine properties in the way in which, for example, quenching of fire
explains why noise belongs to the clouds.
SF(1) introduces the idea of a hierarchy of substances, SF(2) connects the practices of definition and explanation, while
SF(3) provides a metaphysical basis for that connection.445 Within this model, the definition of a composite substance
could not be completed without reference to a
444 b
In 93 25–8, Aristotle is concerned with objects or kinds where there is a middle term—where, that is, there is a cause separate from the object/kind which makes it the
object/kind it is. In this sentence, ‘ousia ’ refers to substances or kinds, and not to the essences of such substances and kinds. For, it is the latter which are the cause of the
substance (or kind) being the substance (or kind) it is.‘Ousia ’ is used in this way in Post. An. Β.2. Therefore, the middle term is sought for the existence of ousiai such as
a a
man, earth, sun, or triangle (90 8–10). And what is sought is the answer to the ‘Why?’ question which gives the essence (90 14–15). Ousiai, elsewhere, are exemplified by
b b
man (83 2–6) and other particular species (73 7). If so, in Β.2 substance and essence are also to be regarded as separable, and the latter can be placed in a middle term with
respect of the former. Thus, if, for example, man and the essence of man were to be different (Meta. H.3, 1043b 2–3), man would be placed within the class of entities
where the cause is different from the composite (which is caused to be as it is). By contrast, if soul and the essence of soul are identical, they would be placed in the category
b
marked out by the preceding sentence (93 21–5).
445
I have discussed a version of the explanatory approach and some alternatives, in ‘Matter and Form: Unity, Persistence and Identity’ in T. Scaltsas, D. Charles, and M. L. Gill
(eds.), Unity, Identity and Explanation in Aristotle's Metaphysics (Oxford, 1994), 75–105. The present Chapter marks an attempt to develop the explanatory approach further,
and to connect it with the interdependency thesis developed in the previous Chapters.
276 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
feature which explains (in the favoured structural way)446 why the composite substance is as it is. At the metaphysical
level, this feature should be explanatorily (and ontologically) more basic than the composite and not an abstraction
from it.
In this Chapter, I shall argue that each of these structural features plays a prominent role in the argument of the
Metaphysics. Section 11.2 focuses on the role there of SF(1), and Sections 11.3–11.5 on that of SF(2) and SF(3). In
Section 11.6 I shall consider some more general consequences of the resulting picture for the metaphysical account of
substance that Aristotle presents in Metaphysics Ζ, H, and Θ.
It is clear that in respect of the things that are said in themselves and primary, each thing is identical with its essence.
This sentence recalls the ‘starting points’ mentioned in Posterior Analytics Β.9 whose essences are immediate. But in Z.6
Aristotle is as reticent as in Β.9 as to what objects fall within this category. While he notes that it is now easy to see how
one can decide whether Socrates is identical with his essence, he does not give us an answer (1032a6–8). But it emerges
in Z.11 that the soul is the primary substance (1037a5), and this is distinct from
446
See the account of structural explanation in Chapter 8. This form of explanation places constraints on both the explananda and the explanans. The latter should answer the
‘What is F?’ question, the former be per se connected, and in the favoured case of substances include a differentia term.
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 277
man or animal, which is a composite of soul and matter (1037a6–8).447 Soul is the primary substance in the case of
living animals since it is identified with form and essence (1035b14–16). Indeed, Aristotle claims that form is, in
general, to be identified with essence (cf. Z.7, 1032b1–2, 14). Since essence is also to be identified with primary
substance (1035b15), form is established in this way as primary substance.
Aristotle explicitly draws the conclusion that, in the case of living animals, soul is the primary substance and is identical
with its essence. Thus, he writes in H.3 1043b2–4:
Soul and the essence of soul are identical, man and the essence of man are not, unless man is soul.
According to this passage, soul is a primary substance, and man qua composite of matter and soul is not. It is only in
the former case that the substance is identical with the essence. The structure set out in Posterior Analytics Β.9 is
enriched in these chapters by the introduction of form (and in the case of man, soul) as the leading candidate for the
role of primary substance.
If Aristotle is implementing the proposal contained in Analytics Β.9, there should be different types of definition for
composite and for primary substances. The former should resemble the complex definition of thunder given in Β.10
(94a5):
This definition includes other essential features of thunder as well as the answer to the ‘Why?’ question (sometimes
identified with what it is to be thunder). The definition of man should include, by analogy, both the answer to the
‘Why?’ question (e.g. the soul) and other essential features of man which are explained by that answer. Further, if he
follows the Analytics pattern, Aristotle should sometimes be tempted to speak of the soul alone as what man is, and
sometimes to include other essential features also. For, in the Analytics both the cause of thunder and the cause plus
other features are on occasion referred to as what thunder is.448
Composites are defined in precisely this way in Metaphysics Z.10–12.
447
Here too Aristotle preserves some detachment on the question of Socrates, noting that ‘Socrates’ may refer either to the soul or to the composite. In the former case,
Socrates is identical with his essence, in the latter, not.
448 a
Thus, in Post. An. Β.2, 90 31–3, Aristotle says that to know the answer to the ‘Why?’ question is to know what a thing is. Later, knowledge of what a thing is includes both
the answer to the ‘Why?’ question and other features of thunder (cf. Post. An. Β.10, 94a 5–6). Correspondingly, sometimes the answer to the ‘What is it?’ question seems
aligned with the discovery of the answer to the ‘Why?’ question (Post. An. Β.2, 90a 15, Β.10, 94a 9–10). But elsewhere it is construed more broadly to involve other features
also (Post. An. Β.10, 94a 5).
278 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
Aristotle insists that it is a mistake to attempt to define them without reference to matter:
for, some things surely are this form in this matter or these things being so. (Z.11, 1036b23 f.)
Thus, man (or animal) cannot be defined without reference to movement, or to the parts of man being in a certain
condition (1036b28–30). The definition of man should include reference to his form (or soul) and his matter (body,
arranged in a given way). The former might be identified with what it is to be a man (strictly speaking), but the full
definition will include form plus matter. In a similar way, what it is to be an eclipse might be given by referring to the
earth standing between sun and moon, even though a full definition will also include deprivation of light (Post. An. Β.8,
93a23–32). On occasion Aristotle, in these chapters (e.g. Z.10, 1035b14–16), speaks of the soul alone as ‘the essence of
the composite’. This is in line with our prediction. For, in the Analytics model full definitions can be represented as
including both the essence (construed narrowly as the basic answer to the ‘Why?’ question449) and other (derived)
essential features of the substance. The relevant full definition will include both prior and posterior elements (as do the
full Analytics definitions of thunder and eclipse). Thus, there is no difficulty in accepting that form is prior to matter
and (at the same time) that a full definition of the composite should include both.
These chapters, therefore, reveal the first structural feature-(SF1)-required if Aristotle is to follow the Analytics model.
As suggested by Posterior Analytics Β.9, some substances are identical with their essences, while others are not. Those in
the first category are primary, those in the second derivative. Aristotle advances this discussion in two ways. He
identifies, in the case of substances, form with essence, and suggests that while certain substances (e.g. soul) are
identical with their essences, composites of matter and form (e.g. man) are not. These two additions, which introduce
basic elements from his own physical theory (viz. matter and form), allow Aristotle to apply his Analytics style of
definition to the case of substance. With their assistance, he can develop the hierarchy of substances required to justify
his schematic claims in Posterior Analytics Β.9. Souls are primary
449
Attention to the variety of types of definition available in the Analytics makes it no surprise that Aristotle can sometimes restrict definition to the form of composite
substances, while elsewhere including their matter. On this problem, see the papers of Michael Frede (‘The Definition of Sensible Substances in Metaphysics Z’, in D. T.
Devereux and P. Pellegrin (eds.), Biologie, logique et métaphysique chez Aristote (Paris, 1990, 113–29) and Michael Ferejohn (‘The Definition of Generated Composites in
Aristotle's Metaphysics ’, in Scaltsas, Charles, and Gill (eds.), Unity, Identity and Explanation, 291–318). The Analytics structures show how form of a composite substance can
be logically prior to matter, even though a full definition of the composite turns out to contain both.
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 279
substances, identical with their essences, while man is a non-primary substance compounded from soul and matter.450
These chapters reflect other Analytics-based concerns. In Z.10 Aristotle states that while there is a defining account of
universals, there cannot be a definition of particular composite substances (1035b34 ff., esp. 1036a4–6). He returns to
this theme later, in Z.15, 1039b27 ff:
There is no definition or proof of perceptible substances, because they have matter whose nature is such that it is
capable of being and not being.
One of his arguments is that once such things are no longer immediately before one, definition and proof are
impossible (1040a1–4). This is, presumably, because one cannot know that they exist when they are unperceived, since
they might have perished in the meantime. His discussion recalls the strictures on definition from the Analytics, where
definitions are said to be always of universals (Β.13, 97b25). One can only have definitions of things one knows to exist
(Β.8, 93a19–20). If one does not know whether things exist, one cannot know what they are (93a26–7). In the required
order of search, one cannot seek what things essentially are before one discovers that they exist (93b32).451 If one makes
the additional (and no doubt controversial) assumption that since particular composites are perishable one cannot
know that they exist unperceived, it follows that one cannot define particular perceptible substances (presumably
because definitions should remain valid whether or not the substance is before one's gaze). Thus, the Analytics'
constraints on definition, which connect it firmly with scientific proof, together with these further assumptions about
perishable substances, compel Aristotle to reject the possibility of defining particular perceptible substances, such as
Socrates or Kallias. If composite perceptible substances can be defined, it appears that these must be construed as
examples of universals (such as man or horse), which can be the subject matter of Aristotle's science (cf. Post. An. Β.17,
99a21–4, 30–7), and not as particulars (Z.10, 1035b27–31).452
Do the Analytics' strictures on definition shed light on the debate over the existence and nature of particular forms?453
Aristotle certainly
450
Michael Ferejohn emphasizes Aristotle's use of ‘physical’ as well as ‘logical’ material in these chapters in ‘The Definition of Generated Composites’.
451
See Ch. 2 Sects. 2.2–2.5.
452 b a
Aristotle talks not only of particular substances, like Socrates or this man, but of particular composites ‘taken universally’ (Z.10, 1035 27–31, Z.11, 1037 5–7). In speaking
b
of man, he is concerned with particular composites seen in abstraction from what makes them particular. I take ‘as universal’ to modify ‘a certain composite’ in 1035 30 to
designate the composite ‘as universal’, which is composed from a universal form and a type of matter. Such a composite is an enmattered kind. I have been fortified in this
reading of 1035b 27–31 by discussion with Myles Burnyeat.
453
The case for particular forms is developed in recent books by Irwin, Frede and Patzig, and Witt. (T. H. Irwin, Aristotle's First Principles (Oxford, 1988), 250–9; M. Frede and
G. Patzig, Aristoteles: Metaphysic Z (Munich, 1988); C. Witt, Substance and Essence in Aristotle (Ithaca, 1989).) Others who have taken this line include Albritton, Sellars,
Heinaman, Lloyd, Frede, and Whiting (R. Albritton, ‘Substance and Form in Aristotle's Metaphysics ’, Journal of Philosophy 54 (1957), 699–708; W. Sellars, ‘Substance and
Form in Aristotle’, Journal of Philosophy 54 (1957), 688–99; R. E. Heinaman, ‘Aristotle's Tenth Aporia’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 61 (1979), 249–70; A. C. Lloyd,
‘Necessity and Essence in the Posterior Analytics ’, in Berti (ed.), Aristotle on Science ; M. Frede, ‘Substance in Aristotle's Metaphysics ’, in A. Gotthelf (ed.), Aristotle on Nature and
Living Things (Pittsburgh, 1985), 17–26; J. Whiting, ‘Form and Individuation in Aristotle’, HPQ 3 (1986), 359–77). The existence of general forms is explicitly defended in
b a
the Analytics (Post. An. Α.24, 85 15–18). Aristotle's formulation of explanatory claims there invokes universals (Post. An. Β.17, 99 21–4, 30–7), and apparently does not
include singular terms referring to particulars (see G. Patzig, Aristotle's Theory of the Syllogism, tr. J. Barnes (Dordrecht, 1969), 4–8). Particular forms, however, may play their
own distinctive role in explanation. In GA 5 they are used to explain individual genetic differences (as J. M. Cooper argues, ‘Metaphysics in Aristotle's Embryology; in D.
Devereux and P. Pellegrin (eds.), Biologie, logique et métaphysique chez Aristote (Paris, 1990), 79–84). Presumably, at least some perceptual forms are particulars (De An. Β.5,
417b 22–5).
280 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
sometimes talks (even in the central books) in terms which suggest that he accepts the existence of particular forms
(as, for example, when he speaks of this soul, the soul which is Socrates, in Z.11, 1037a6–10). However, even if he
does, it does not follow that particular forms can be the objects of definition. For, even if there are both particular and
universal forms, it may be that only the latter are the objects of definition and of scientific knowledge. When one
approaches these issues with the Analytics' perspective in mind, the crucial issue is not whether Aristotle thinks that
particular forms exist, but rather (i) what particularizes them, and (ii) whether, and in what ways, such forms are prior
to general forms.454
It is tempting to see the Analytics as providing the outline of an answer to (ii). There, general forms alone can be used
in explanation. As such they must be prior in account and in knowledge (cf. Z.1, 1028a31–3), and, thus, the primary
beings. Particular forms (if any such were to be found in the Analytics) would be derivative, and differentiated by
reference to the matter the general forms enform (the form of Man-in-this-matter, as is perhaps suggested in
Metaphysics Z.8, 1034a5–8). If the Metaphysics follows this pattern, general forms will be explanatorily basic, and
particular forms the result of such forms being instantiated in given quantities of matter.455 Indeed, if the answer to the
‘What is F?’ question is the same (in
454
Some proponents of particular forms regard Aristotelian general forms as abstractions (Frede and Patzig Aristoteles: Metaphysic Z), while others view them as real entities
(Irwin, Aristotle's First Principles 262–3). This issue is raised by Whiting (‘Metasubstance: Critical Notice of Frede-Patzig and Furth’, PR 100 (1991), 638 f.). Both groups
can agree with the defender of the priority of general forms on the following claims: (i) Analytics -style definitions are of general forms; (ii) there are particular forms; (iii)
knowledge requires general forms. The key issues on which these parties divide concern (i) the relative priority of general and particular forms, and (ii) the ontological status
of general forms.
455 a
Forms (whether particular or general) are prior to composite substance (whether individual or taken universally) (cf. Z.3, 1029 5). If so, forms cannot be defined as the
forms of composites (or of the-matter-in-a-composite); for, this would be to treat the composite as explanatorily prior to the form.
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 281
the Metaphysics) as the answer to the ‘Why?’ question, and the latter answer is tied (in the Analytics style) to explanation
concerning universals, the relevant primary substances must be general forms.
It would be no small task to establish that this line of interpretation is correct. There are several steps that might be
challenged. Some will deny that Aristotle (in the Metaphysics) holds that general forms are explanatorily prior (or prior in
account) to particular ones. Maybe the latter are basic in the explanation of the particularity of particular composites.
Others will argue that Aristotle (in the Metaphysics) did not accept the inference from the explanatory priority of general
forms to their ontological priority.
The proper consideration of these responses lies outside our present project. However, it is a major advantage of the
present approach that it brings into sharp focus two crucial questions. First, is the explanandum in the Metaphysics the
particularity of particular substances or their unity?456 For, if it is the latter, the explanans should be general (e.g. the
essence it shares with other members of its kind: the essence of the kind). Second, if the explanantia are general, does it
follow that they are prior in being to particular forms? If we could answer these two questions, we would have the basis
for progress on the much-disputed issue of the role of general and particular forms. For, we would see more of
Aristotle's motivation in this discussion.
However, while these questions are (I suspect) answerable, I shall not pursue them further here. Instead, I shall focus
on Aristotle's discussion of the unity of particulars, and leave open the issue of whether he also attempts to explain
their particularity.457 My aim is only to show the Analytics model at work in Metaphysics Z, H, and Θ, and not to argue for
(or against) the suggestion that particular forms are needed in this context. Indeed, this seems to follow Aristotle's own
preoccupations. In Z.2–12 his concern seems to be to preserve (in the case of substances) his Analytics connection
between definitions and universals and to secure his favoured hierarchy (Post. An. Β.9). The issue of particular forms is
not, it seems, a major interest in these chapters.
While the discussion of Z.4–12 appears to follow certain aspects of Aristotle's methods in the Analytics, there are
several departures from that
456
The question of unity may be asked about particulars as follows. Granted that this is a particular, what makes it a unity? (Answer: The Form F it possesses is combined in a
given way with its matter.) This question does not involve the question: What makes this particular a particular? Indeed, in the former, its particularity is taken for granted.
The question of unity can be taken either diachronically or synchronically. Aristotle (I shall assume) intends his answers to apply diachronically as well as synchronically.
457
If he does aim to explain the particularity of particular substances, he will do so by invoking (in line with the explanatory approach) particular forms. So understood,
particular forms are required if Aristotle is adopting the radical version of the explanatory approach which aims to explain the particularity of particulars.
282 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
model which might initially be surprising. For example, while definitions are said to be of one thing (Z.4, 1030b9–10,
Z.12, 1037b26), and regularly conceived in the genus-species mode (1037b20–2, 1030a12 ff.), Aristotle does not
immediately employ the explanatory machinery he developed in the Analytics to answer the following question:
Why is two-footed, wingless, animal a unity? (Z.12, 1037b13–15:cf. Post. An. Β.6, 92a29–30)
One might have expected him to seek a middle term which explains why two-footed belongs to animal, in the manner
proposed in the Analytics Β.8.458 But instead he suggests in Z.12 that in the phrase ‘two-footed animal’, ‘animal’ refers
to either nothing or nothing differentiated over and above the species (1038a5–8), and that in certain cases the final
differentia will be one thing alone (1038a25 f.) which gives one unique essence (and, presumably, entails all the other
differentiae). This suggestion does not invoke the Analytics model of seeking a unifying answer of the appropriate type to
the ‘Why?’ question (which is only introduced in Z.17). Indeed, Aristotle's explanatory approach to definition is not
deployed at all in Z.12.
Why is this so? In Z.4–12 Aristotle is attempting to answer the ‘What is F?’ question while using only some of the
resources at his disposal. First, he deploys the general constraints on definition developed in the (explanation-free)
parts of the Analytics (and the Topics) to claim that definition is of essence, is of one thing, and is connected in some way
with genus and differentiae. Second, he argues, on the basis of his physical writings, that form is a plausible candidate for
the role of essence in the case of substance. But these two moves do not take him very far. He has not as yet articulated
a clear and determinate idea of form or essence which is to meet these conditions. How is the form of man itself to be
conceived? Is it, for instance, merely the unanalysable what it is to be a man? Without the explanatory material introduced
in Z.17, Aristotle does not have the resources required to specify the kind of form involved. Neither here nor in the
Analytics can the definitional task be completed without the addition of material drawn from the theory of explanation.
Z.12 exemplifies a similar incompleteness. Aristotle suggests that one secures the unity of definition by finding one
final differentia which entails all the others. But this proposal cannot apply (at least straightforwardly) to the case of man,
considered as two-footed, wingless, animal (1037b33). For, being two-footed does not imply being wingless (consider
birds). It also does not work if man is considered as mortal, two-footed, wingless
458
See Ch. 7 Sect. 7.4.
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 283
(see Post. An. Β.6, 92a29 ff.).459 Further, if one devised one complex predicate (such as ‘mortal-wingless-two-footed’)
which did entail all the rest, one would still need to show that this complex predicate was itself a proper unity. Either
the Z.12 model fails to apply to many relevant cases or it presupposes the type of unity it is attempting to establish.
Either way, it fails. Prior to Z.17 Aristotle has no way satisfactorily to resolve the issue of unity raised in Z.12. It is
small wonder that he returns to it later in H.6 with the explanatory material in place (see Sect. 11.4).
Why does Aristotle proceed in this way? If he were following the Analytics model, one would expect him to motivate
the introduction of explanation-based material in Z.17 by showing the incompleteness of attempts at definition
without it. As in the Analytics, he should argue for the interdependency of the practices of definition and explanation by
showing that the former by themselves are incomplete. The gaps in the account offered in Z.4–12 constitute one
argument for that claim. Another (as I shall argue in the next Section) is provided by his suggestion in Z.13–16 that
definitional concerns by themselves generate an impasse, which can only be broken by the introduction of explanatory
material in Z.17. In this way, one can understand the pattern of argument throughout Z as (in large part) directed to
establishing the interdependency of definition and explanation. In effect, Aristotle is arguing for the two structural
features SF(2) and SF(3) introduced above.
459
These issues are discussed by A. Falcon in ‘Aristotle's Rules of Division in the Topics : The Relation between Genus and Differentia in Division’, Ancient Philosophy 16/2
(1996), 377–88.
460 a
See, in particular, Aristotle's arguments in Z.15 against the view that (e.g.) ‘the sun’ can be defined as ‘what revolves around the Earth’ or ‘what is hidden at night’ (1040 29
ff.). I discuss these in App 1 n. 7.
284 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
of argument is particularly revealing. Aristotle begins with the claim that substance, unlike universals common to
several kinds, is specific or unique to the kind in question (Z.13, 1038b9–11).461 This point by itself generates the central
problem. Since no substance can be composed of universals or of other substances, every substance must be
incomposite. But if this is so, none can be captured in a formula (1039a14–19), since there can only be formulae of
composites. So, there can be no definitions of substances.
This line of argument forms the basis for large parts of the discussion in Z.14 and 15. In Z.14 Aristotle states that if
there were universal forms of a Platonic type, either particular species would be comprised of them or they would be
different for each species (1039b7–8). In the former case, they would not be unique. In the latter, they would be unique
to the relevant species but unknowable (1040a24 f.) and not describable in language (1040a10 f.). One either uses
universals common to many things to describe substance (in which case one fails to capture the uniqueness of an
essence) or one can only specify the particular type of substance by a demonstrative (in which case it is not knowable in
the appropriate scientific mode). If every type of substance is incomposite, none can be described in terms of a general
formula (Z.13, 1039a17–19).
Aristotle considers a possible reply to this dilemma, in Z.15:
universals may apply separately to many things, but taken all at once they apply to this substance. (1040a14–16)
This remark immediately recalls one of the suggestions discussed in Posterior Analytics Β.13.462 In the Metaphysics it is
rejected on two grounds. If the components of man (e.g. animal and two-footed) are separable universals, then
everything that is predicated of man will also be predicated of them (qua components of man). So, man will not be the
unique bearer of the relevant set of properties, since (e.g.) animal will bear the same set of properties (1040a16–21).463
Further, this proposal makes every
461
This understanding of Z.13 follows the outline pioneered by Michael Woods in ‘Problems in Metaphysics Z, Chapter 13 ’, in J. M. E. Moravcsik (ed.), Aristotle: Critical Essays
(New York, 1967), 215–38, and further developed in his ‘Universals and Particular Forms in Aristotle's Metaphysics’, OSAP, suppl. 1991, (Supplement), 41–56. A similar
b
overall interpretation of Z.13 is developed by A. Code in ‘No Universal is a Substance: An interpretation of Z.13, 1038 8–15’, Paideia (1978), 65–76, and in M. Burnyeat
(ed.), Notes on Book Zeta of Aristotle's Metaphysics (London, 1979), ad loc. While I have followed the generalist reading of Z.13, problems similar to the ones I discuss will
arise within a particularist interpretation of this chapter: ‘What is unique to the particular in question?’; ‘How is this knowable?’.
462
This case is discussed in Ch. 9 Sect. 9.2.
463
This argument does not look robust. If animal does share the properties of man (e.g. being two-footed, etc.), why not say that it only shares these properties derivatively qua
participating in the composite man? If so, it would possess these properties in a different way from that in which man does. But perhaps Aristotle has a reply to this: If one
understands the role of animal in this way in the composite man, it is no longer prior to man (contrary to the hypothesis of 1040a 17–18). To meet this reply, the objector
would need to separate various kinds of priority (explanatory, ontological, etc.), and this would far outrun his simple strategy of listing all the relevant universals in an
unstructured way.
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 285
component prior to man, since they need not be destroyed if the composite is destroyed (1040a21–2). But this gets the
relevant priorities wrong. Not every component of the composite should be prior to man in this way. Some should be
(e.g. possessing a soul of a given kind), but others should not. This proposal, by making all components prior, does not
capture the kind of priority required of definition.464 Merely to conjoin all the universals present in a composite is to
give up the idea, central to the Analytics style of definition, of there being some prior basic feature at the centre of the
account. At this point, the Analytics' constraints on definition are to the fore.
These chapters set the target for Aristotle's own investigations. What is sought (to define a composite substance) must
be (in some way) a non-complex unity,465 which is in the relevant sense prior and specific to the kind of substance in
question. The challenge, raised in Z.13, is to show how a non-complex, prior feature of this type can be knowable at
all. Aristotle notes (tantalizingly) that ‘in some way there can be definition, and in another not’ (1039a21 f.). Presumably,
he thinks that although substance is incomposite in some way, it can still be the object of definition. He now needs to
show how such definitions would be knowable. Does he use the Analytics model to help him at this point?
There is considerable reference to the Analytics in Z.17, which marks the beginning of Aristotle's most systematic
attempt to apply the explanatory style of definition to substance. Indeed, Aristotle indicates in 1041a23–30 that his goal
is to apply his explanatory model to the case of composite substances. In this passage he uses his favoured Analytics
example of thunder (cf. Post. An. Β.8, 93b8–12, Β.10, 94a2–9) to illustrate his approach to composite substances.
He introduces his discussion by describing seeking the essence through asking the ‘Why?’ question:
The question is: Why does something belong to something else? And that it belongs has to be clear; otherwise, you
are not asking anything. Take, for example, the question:
Why does it thunder?
[This is equivalent to:]
464
Thus understood, this passage is fully consistent with Aristotle's position in Post. An. Β.13. Definition merely by listing a set of shared universals fails to capture what is
explanatorily prior. Listing shared universals either captures no priority or only the wrong kind of priority (in which all universals are equally prior).
465
This entity could not be a property, since substances are prior to properties in Aristotle's hierarchy of being (Z.13, 1038b 23 ff., cf. Z.1, 1028a 30 ff.).
286 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
In the case of thunder, something which comes into being, the efficient cause gives the relevant answer: fire being
quenched (as we know from the Analytics). And on this basis we can construct a full definition:
466
I construe ‘logikos’ as referring to a manner of proceeding which is based on considerations of a general kind, not based on principles particular to a given science or subject
b
matter (cf. Post. An. Α.21, 82 35 with Barnes's note.). By contrast, considerations are ‘phusikos’ if they are specific to a given subject matter. (On this, see my discussion in
Aristotle's Philosophy of Action, 128 n. 27.) In 1041a 31 ff. I agree with Ross (Aristotle's Metaphysics, II. 223) in construing ‘the other cause’ as naturally referring to the final
a a
cause, and, thus, take the whole sentence 31–2 to elucidate the same distinctions as are marked out in the sentence 29–30. Frede and Patzig, by contrast, (Aristotle's
Metaphysic Z, II. 312–3) take ‘the other cause’ to refer to the formal cause alone, and contrast this with both efficient and teleological causes (as introduced by ‘this sort of
cause’ in a31). Thus, they see Aristotle as contrasting here the formal causes of (e.g.) mathematical objects with the efficient and final causes to be found in what comes into
being and passes away. However, the preceding context does not mention mathematical (or other timeless) objects, but focuses rather on the transitory examples introduced
a b
in 29. Further, in the subsequent lines, Aristotle's concern in using the phrase ‘the being/existence’ (at 1041 5–6) is with similar cases of transitory objects. Thus, it is
a
natural to understand this phrase in 32 to apply to the same type of case. In general, in this passage, Aristotle appears to focus on a limited set of cases (‘some . . . some . . .
’ in a 29), and not to aim at a general taxonomy of all cases of substances.
467
The exact form of the C-place is unclear. I prefer ‘clouds in k’ to preserve their appropriate generality. By the inelegant symbol ‘Φ nec’ I intend ‘belongs necessarily to’.
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 287
468
See, e.g. Michael Ferejohn's paper mentioned above (n. 8).
288 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
explanatorily basic one must also answer the definitional question (1041a26 f.). Nor should this be a surprise, since it is
a constraint on Analytics-style ‘structural’ explanation that the explanans should tell us what the kind in question is.469
In the Analytics, there is one feature (in the case of thunder and of eclipse) which answers both definitional and
explanatory questions. Indeed, the two questions are so connected that neither can be answered without the other. If
this model is to be transferred to the case of substances (as seems to be the aim of Z.17), there must be one feature
which provides the basis for an answer to both definitional and explanatory questions. Since these questions are
interlocked, if form is the answer to one, it must be the answer to the other.
But is this type of explanatory approach to definition in Z.17 merely an isolated fragment in the argument of the
central books of the Metaphysics? Are SF(2) and SF(3) confined to this chapter? It appears not. Large parts of the next
books constitute an attempt to implement this approach (or so I shall argue).
The proposal introduced in Z.17 needs to be unpacked further. We need to understand the reference of house in the
question:
We can only make progress with this question if we know how ‘some definite thing’ is to be understood. Further, we
need to understand how the phrase what it is to be a house functions in the answer. For, while we have reason to believe
that this refers to a feature which is the teleological cause, we do not know how to specify this in any detail. If Z.17
gives a blueprint for further work, it does not tell us how to carry through the project. These gaps are filled in H.2 and
beyond in a manner which carries further the explanatory approach to definition (or so I shall argue).
In H.2 Aristotle begins by discussing the differentiae of matter: composition, time, position, etc. (1042b11 ff.). This is
precisely the type of move he should make if he is pursuing the explanatory approach. In the Analytics he sought (in
investigating substances) differentiae as explananda which belong per se to the kind in question and mark it out from the
relevant genus.470 If one construes matter as a genus (or analogous to one), the relevant differentiae should mark out the
matter involved in the substance.471
469
See Ch. 8 Sects. 8.3 and 8.4.
470
See Ch. 9 Sects. 9.2 ff.
471 a
Aristotle insists on the close connection between matter and genera in Z.12, 1038 5 ff. On this, see, e.g., R. Rorty, ‘Genus as Matter: A Reading of Metaphysics Z-H’, in
Exegesis and Argument: Phronesis, suppl. 1 (1973), 393–420.
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 289
In the case of house, the relevant differentia of the matter (bricks and stones) is arranged thus (1043a7 f.). Aristotle
immediately notes that the final cause may be added as a differentia in some cases (1043a8 f.), and that in this case it
would be a covering for possessions and bodies (1043a16–18, 32 f.). Indeed, Aristotle goes on to speak of ‘being a
possessions-protector’ as the activity, form, and shape of the house. From these materials he can construct a full
definition of house:
House = bricks and stones arranged thus as a covering for possessions and bodies.
Aristotle suggests that some differentiae may be causally more basic—the cause of each thing being what it is
(1043a2–4).472 In the present example, the final cause will play this role: being a possessions-protector. So, one can now
reframe the question raised in Z.17 as follows:
Why are bricks and stones (the matter) arranged thus (in given spatial arrangements, with a roof, etc.)?
The answer will invoke the basic form: In order for it to be a possessions-protector. For, it is its being this which
explains why the bricks and stones are arranged as they are.473 Further, it is because houses are essentially possessions-
protectors that they contain bricks and stones which are arranged thus; for, this kind of matter possesses the right
capacities to be a possessions-coverer, because it is water resistant, unmoved by wind, etc.
Definitions of this type could be related (by the methods of Post. An. Β.10 94a1 ff.) to a syllogism such as:
472 a
Aristotle writes that:‘it is amongst the differentiae that something must be sought which is the cause of each thing being what it is’ (1043 2–3). That this refers to one of the
a
differentiae (or at least some limited set of these) is confirmed by Aristotle's subsequent introduction of the final cause (1043 9), which is invoked in giving the activity of the
house (‘to be a covering for belongings and bodies’, 1043 16–17). Quasi-substances, like houses, are used as the nearest analogies for genuine substances (1043a 4–7).
a
473
The connection between the matter (bricks, planks . . . ) and the relevant feature (being arranged thus) should be a per se one, if the Analytics -style account is to be preserved
in its entirety. That is, being arranged thus should belong to such bricks, planks, etc., and to nothing else. Either the relevant matter is defined as that to which being arranged thus
belongs (perhaps in favourable conditions) or being arranged thus is defined as something which belongs to matter of this type. On this view, the relevant matter would form
the grouping to which being arranged thus belongs. This group might be (e.g.) house-material matter. Bricks and planks would form species of matter of this type. Compare the
case of deciduous trees and (e.g.) figs, discussed in Chapter 8 Section 8.3.
290 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
is replaced by:
Why does being arranged in a given way belong to these bricks? (1043a7–8)
In both cases, the answer is discussed by isolating a causally basic phenomenon, in the first case an efficient, in the
second a teleological cause (as was predicted in 1041a29–31; see also 1044b1). In both, there is an immediate causal
connection in the major premiss. It is because the bricks are used as a possessions-coverer that they are arranged thus.
No further intermediate cause is being sought.
Analogous moves may be made in the case of man. The Z.17 question:
Why does being a man belong to this body with this feature (e.g. this shape)?
474
In this syllogism, both the A- and B-terms are to be taken as species-form terms. Thus, in the major premiss, being arranged thus is taken as a consequential part of the form,
derivative from being a possessions-coverer. Both of these are predicated of the relevant matter in the minor premiss and conclusion.
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 291
Why does being two-footed belong to this body (with this feature)?
The answer would be that being a biped belongs to this body because its having two legs is required by what it is to be
a man. On this understanding, the relevant type of soul serves as the teleological cause which explains why the body
has given features.
If this account is correct, the unity of the composite substance, man, will depend on there being one basic feature (e.g.
a soul of a given kind) which belongs immediately to the relevant matter. This feature should have the following
properties:
(a) It should be linked immediately to the relevant matter in such a way as to explain why the matter is as it is.
(b) It should explain why the relevant matter is possessed of certain necessary, per se, properties (e.g. being a biped).
(c) It should constitute what it is to be the composite substance.
(d) Its unity should be basic and not further analysable. Thus, it should be a non-complex cause (of the
appropriate type) specific to the kind in question.475
In the Metaphysics, since the relevant structure of explanation in the case of substances is teleological, the form must be
the non-complex teleological cause which explains why the matter is possessed of certain features (such as being two-
legged). Thus, the matter will be organized in the way required for the relevant type of movement (walking, running)
characteristic of man. The relevant form will be that feature specific to the kind which explains why its other properties
are as they are. It will be discovered by uncovering its basic role as in the explanation of the structure of composite
substances.476 Although simple causal features (such as souls) are not the subject matter of enquiry in the way
composite substances are (cf. Z.17, 1041b9–11), they will be discovered by successfully tracing the ‘Why?’ question
back to its ultimate teleological source, the non-complex cause of the thing being what it is (H.2, 1043a3 f.).477
475
It should be noted that the unity of the soul, so understood, is compatible with its having parts, provided that the soul cannot be reductively analysed into its parts. That is,
the soul may have parts provided that what it is to be a part is to be understood as (metaphysically) dependent on the unity of the soul.
476 a
In the next Section I consider further the way in which the soul operates as a final cause (in commenting on H.6, 1045 31–3).
477
In this case, the syllogism would run as follows:Being two-footed belongs to being what it is to be a man.Being what it is to be a man belongs to this body.Being two-footed
belongs to this body.Soul of kind S can replace being what it is to be a man. As in the previous note, both the A- and B-terms (being two-footed, being what it is to be a
man) would point to aspects of the form of man, which are predicated of the relevant matter (whether this be particular matter or matter of a given type). The B-term would
indicate something sufficient to make this matter a human being (although it would not, of course, be sufficient to account for the existence/presence of this matter). In this
way, Aristotle could answer (in a metaphysical mode) the question ‘What is man?’ (which is raised in 1041b1, and is the immediate focus of the present discussion). This
answer is, of course, not the one the biologist would give, since her concern (unlike the metaphysician's) is not with what it is to be a man, conceived of merely as that feature
(whatever it may be) which explains why this body is a man/two-footed. Rather, she aims to spell out what it is to be a man in biological terms (See E.1, 1025b8–10). The
metaphysician, by contrast, could reasonably be satisfied with this style of account since his goal is to outline a style of account which can apply to all substances. (For a
contrasting view, see Robert Bolton's paper ‘Science and the Science of Substance in Aristotle's Metaphysics Z’, PPQ 76 (1995), 454–7).In De An. Β.2 Aristotle envisages an
alternative but similar syllogism. It appears to run as follows (413a13 ff., cf. 414a4 ff.):Being alive belongs to soul.Soul belongs to matter of a given type.Being alive belongs to
matter of a given type.The matter in question is unified by its possession of the capacity for life. Thus, the connection in the conclusion is a universal per se one (See Ch. 8
Sect. 8.3). As in the case of planks and bricks, there may be differing species of this matter.
292 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
This line of thought is developed further in H.3 and H.4, where Aristotle states that while composite substances are
definable, the primary elements from which they are composed are not (1043b28–31). Primary elements are compared
with the indivisible elements from which other numbers are composed (1043b34 f., 1044a1 f.). Thus, the primary
substance (soul) in the case of living creatures must (at least) be a non-composite entity, which lacks the kind of
internal structure possessed by composites (see 1043b30 f.).
We are now in a position to understand Aristotle's reply to the aporia he set out in Z.13–16. This arose because it was
difficult to see how if forms are non-composite they are knowable. Aristotle now has a solution: they are knowable
because they are discovered to be the basic cause which explains why, in the case of man, being two-footed belongs per
se to animal or matter of a given type. In a successful investigation of composite substances, one will find the specific
differentiating cause which explains why the composite is (in other respects) as it is. The basic causal feature must be
specific to the kind; for, otherwise it could not explain (in the appropriate way) why all and only members of a given
kind have some necessary property. As in the Analytics, one will conclude one's search with the discovery of
fundamental commensurate universals, unique to the kind in question. The differentiating cause will be universal in the
sense that it is present in all and only members of the relevant kind. But it will not be a universal of the type which
extends more widely than the kind (Z.13–15).
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 293
For, the latter will not yield the one basic (prior) simple entity required. Further, the relevant form or essence will be
knowable on the basis of its role in the (appropriate type of) teleological explanation of the internal workings of a
composite substance. The form in question must be capable of explaining why the other features of the substance are
as they are. Thus, it could not be an invented simple such as man* (an invented indivisible form), since the latter could
not make the other specific features intelligible in the required way (Z.17, 1041a19–20). In Z.13 Aristotle asked how a
form specific to one kind only could be knowable. Now we can see his answer.
It is significant that in H.4 Aristotle explicitly introduces one of his favoured Analytics examples (the eclipse of the
moon (H.4, 1044b9 ff.)), and compares it with the case of man (as, in Z.17, thunder is compared with man). In the case
of the eclipse, the cause or form is only present in the definition if one invokes the efficient cause. As Aristotle notes:
What is eclipse? It is deprivation of light. But if ‘by the Earth's coming in between’ is added, one has the account
which includes the cause. (1044b13–15)
In this case, the efficient cause is a unique phenomenon necessary and sufficient to explain the eclipse of the moon.
The analogy with the case of man is closely drawn. The form is the essence, which is identified with the teleological
cause (1044b1). Thus, even if non-composite, the essence can be discovered by uncovering the specific differentiating
entity which is explanatorily basic; for, one can come to know it by detecting its distinctive causal role.478
In this Section, I have suggested that in Z.17 Aristotle introduces his Analytics explanatory theory in order to determine
more precisely the type of form required for definition. This material is introduced because Aristotle's definitional
project, begun in Z.4–12, cannot (in his view) be completed without the assistance of material drawn from the practice
of explanation. For, the latter enables us to grasp the nature of the form, which is prior and an incomposite unity (in
part) because it is a non-complex cause. Without recourse to the practice of explanation, we cannot overcome the
aporiai of Z.13–16.
At the metaphysical level, the notion of form, thus understood, is held in place by two sets of conditions: it is the
feature which answers the ‘What is F?’ question (Z.4–12) and at the same time supplies the basic cause in
478 a
In H.4 Aristotle suggests that the matter of man may be the ‘catamēnia ’ (1044 35), but also notes the importance of finding the matter which is unique to the thing in
question (1044b 2–3). Elsewhere in these chapters the body appears to be the relevant matter (H.5, 1044b 29–31, H.3, 1043a 34–5, Z.17, 1041b 7). In H.4 Aristotle is giving
examples of candidates for causes, rather than specifying them precisely. Indeed, throughout this discussion Aristotle seems more concerned to outline the general structure
than to be precise about the detailed place-holders in his scheme.
294 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
the relevant teleological pattern (Z.17 ff.). Further, this metaphysical conception provides the basis for an epistemic
route to the discovery of the form. For, we can come to know it on the basis of its basic causal role. In these ways,
Aristotle's discussion of form exemplifies the co-determination of essence and causation which we uncovered in the
Analytics.479
Indeed, he ends the chapter by claiming to have found an answer to this question:
looking for the cause of one thing is the same as looking for the cause of it being one thing. (1045b19 f.)
In the light of the account offered above, one would expect him to deploy his favoured explanatory model of
definition (as captured in SF(3)) to
479
Thus, it exhibits Structural Feature 3-SF(3)-mentioned in the Introduction to this Chapter.
480
Aristotle is not always clear on how to categorize ‘arranged thus’ or ‘two-footed’: whether as matter or as activity/form. Sometimes they are taken as activity/shape
a a
compared with matter (cf. 1043 5, 8). Sometimes they are omitted, and the shape/activity is specified using only the basic activity (possessions-covering/soul (1043 16–18,
b
a34–5)). Sometimes they are described ‘as matter’ to the basic activity of the soul (cf. H.3, 1043 10–13). This suggests that the notions of matter and form are
relational:‘arranged thus’/‘two-footed’ is form with respect to body/bricks, but matter with respect to soul/possessions-covering. A certain degree of fluctuation in
terminology should not disturb us at this point.
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 295
address these issues. I shall argue that this is indeed the case, although the content of the chapter is elusive and has
been subject to a variety of different styles of interpretation.
Aristotle introduces his favoured case of man as a two-footed animal, and then writes:
if—as we say—one [presumably, animal] is matter and the other shape [presumably, being two-footed] and the one
is potentiality, the other actuality, what is sought would no longer seem to be an insuperable problem (aporia). For,
this is the same problem one would have if the definition of cloak were ‘rounded bronze’. For, this name would be a
sign for this definition, so that what is being sought is the cause of the bronze and the rounded being one. So the
problem has gone away, because one is the matter, the other is the shape. What then is the cause of what is potentially
F being actually F (in the case of things that come to be) besides what makes it so, the efficient cause? For, nothing
other is the cause of what is potentially a sphere being actually a sphere; rather, this [viz. the cause] is what it is to be
for each of them singly. (1045a23–33)481
According to the explanation-involving model of definition, one would expect Aristotle to proceed as follows. If one
considers the issue of unity using terms such as:
matter: shape
potentiality: actuality
there is no longer an insuperable problem, because one can see how to resolve it. The question is now in answerable
form and we can discover what is sought: what makes it the case that (e.g.) potentiality and actuality are paired in such
a way as to form a composite unity. The answer appears to be: because they have the same teleological goal which
determines their essence. This goal, it appears, is intrinsic to the basic actuality (e.g. soul of a given kind), and at the
same time determines the nature of the matter (body or animal), which is as it is for the sake of the goal.
Aristotle's claim marks a further step in the development of his
481 a
On this reading, ‘this’ in 1045 33 refers to the cause mentioned in a32. Thus, both matter and form will share the same cause (e.g. the same goal), although not necessarily in
precisely the same way. For, the goal might belong immediately to the form and only derivatively to the matter. If so, although they share the same goal, their essential
natures may differ in some way. (On this point, I have been assisted by Lewis's note on my earlier formulation. See Lewis, ‘Aristotle on the Unity of Substance’, PPQ 76: 3/
4 (1995), 260 n. 53, commenting on a less cautious claim in my paper.) On the dissolutionist view ‘this’ would refer not to the cause but to the fact of what is potentially a
sphere being actually a sphere (viz. to there being a unified substance), which would give the essence of both actuality and potentiality as abstractions defined by their
contribution to a unified substance.
296 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
teleological analysis of substances.482 Had he simply followed the account sketched in Z.17 and H.2–3, he should have
expanded talk of shape to include fundamental features of man (such as possession of the relevant soul). The shape, so
understood, would determine the nature of the relevant matter, which is as it is for the sake of such a soul.483 However,
Aristotle makes the further move of introducing a goal intrinsic to the basic actuality (e.g. the soul) which makes that
actuality what it is. There is, it appears, a goal which determines the nature of the actuality and of the required matter.484
This goal is the explanatory basic feature at the centre of Aristotle's account. If the explanatory approach is to be
developed in this way, Aristotle will need next to elucidate what this basic feature is.
There is, however, an opposed interpretation of this passage, which represents Aristotle as rejecting the explanation-
involving account. It runs as follows.
If one invokes as basic notions:
matter: shape
potentiality: actuality
no further explanation of their unity is required, because no genuine problem remains. Nothing more could be said to
explain the unity of a composite substance, precisely because these notions themselves are abstractions from that of a
unified member of a kind.485
482
This line of interpretation, sketched initially in my paper ‘Matter and Form’, has been developed further by Lewis in ‘Aristotle on the Unity of Substance’, PPQ 76 (1995),
222–65. While our approaches are similar, Lewis is more confident than I about the possibility of establishing the explanatory reading of Aristotle's project on the basis of
H.6 alone.
483
So understood, the proposition:Soul of a given type belongs necessarily to body of type S.would be explanatory bedrock, an immediate proposition (in the language of the
Analytics).
484
Aristotle did not need to make this further move to maintain the basic outline of the explanatory approach. That could have been defended while taking the actuality (and
not its internal goal) as the relevant starting point. Aristotle may have introduced the relevant internal goal to illuminate the nature of the relevant actuality in a specifically
teleological way. For discussion of similar cases, see my ‘Aristotle: Ontology and Moral Reasoning’, 135–40.
485
Elements of the dissolutionist line of interpretation can be detected in claims such as:potentiality and actuality are the same thing present together in that full activity which is
nothing other than the manifestation of the one entity that both are' (L. A. Kosman, ‘Substance, Being and Energeia’, OSAP 2 (1984), 144)orAristotle compares asking for an
explanation of why potentiality and actuality are one with asking for an explanation of why anything is one. No answer is needed . . . because the explanation of the thing is at
the same time an explanation of its being one. (M. Burnyeat, Notes on ETA and THETA (Oxford Subfaculty of Philosophy, 1984), 44–5.)However, neither Kosman nor the
London Group opt wholeheartedly for the dissolutionist view. Other passages in these works suggest a somewhat different version of the non-explanatory account,
described below as the ‘quick-fix’ approach (see n. 486). Wilfred Sellars (‘Aristotle's Metaphysics: An Interpretation’, in Philosophical Perspectives (Springfield, 1967, 118)) appears
to adopt the dissolutionist viewpoint without qualification.
486
LeBlond made this suggestion in ‘Definition in Aristotle’, 63–79. See also Ch. 10 Sect. 10.1.
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 297
On this view, Aristotle, so far from attempting to perfect the explanatory approach in these chapters, is in fact
abandoning it.
This alternative, dissolutionist, interpretation might be supported by a reading of the final lines of the chapter
(1045b17–23). These run as follows:
But—as has been said—the final matter and the shape are the same and one, the one potentially the other actually
(energeiai: dative), so that it is similar to investigate:
The dissolutionist interpreter may cede that the apparently explanatory question raised in 1045b18–20 seems to be an
important and sensible one: What is the cause of unity? However, she will conclude that these appearances are
misleading, since in the final sentence Aristotle clearly says that there is no other cause of the unity of what is potentially
F and what is actually F apart from the efficient cause. In her view, this means that if one excludes the efficient cause,
there is no cause of unity at all. Rather, the unity of the composite substance is to be taken as basic and not in need of
further explanation.
However, if the final sentence is interpreted in the way the dissolutionist interpreter suggests, it flatly contradicts the
earlier passage (1045a30 ff.) in which Aristotle makes the far more cautious claim that there is no cause of what is
potentially F being actually F except the one essence of both. For, in the earlier passage, there may be a cause (other than
the efficient one) of the relevant unity of the composite substance: (e.g.) the presence of a form, identified with the
teleological goal, which determines the nature of the matter. The explanatory interpreter, by contrast, can avoid this
inconsistency if he can show that the final sentences of H.6 mean only that (if one excludes the efficient cause) there is
no cause of unity of substance
298 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
distinct from the relevant actuality and potentiality (since these encapsulate all the causal features required to explain the
unity of the composite substance). Can this explanation-involving interpretation of the final sentences of H.6 be
sustained?
The argument in 1045b18–22 is highly compressed, but (it appears) runs as follows:
(1) Each thing is one thing (hen) of a given kind (ti). (Premiss)
(2) The matter is the thing in potentiality, the form is the thing in actuality. (Premiss)
(3) It is similar to seek the cause of one thing being something and of it being one thing. (from (1) and (2))
(4) (3) follows from (1) and (2) since one thing is something because matter and form are joined as potentiality and
actuality. But when matter and form are joined in this way there is one thing present.486
The key premiss is (2). In what way is the form the thing in actuality? According to the dissolutionist interpreter, this
means that the form is the composite substance seen as actuality, while the matter is the composite substance seen as
potentiality. On this interpretation, the notion of one composite substance is taken as basic. By contrast, the explanatory
interpreter sees (2) as claiming that the form is the thing in actuality, because the thing (e.g. man) is to be identified (in
strict use of H.2, 1043a27 f.) with the form (as the man in actuality). On this view, the actuality is taken as basic and the
matter is understood as potentially that actuality, where the latter is identified with the thing itself (i.e. the man).487 Thus,
the distinctive soul will be what makes man one thing and the thing it is. For, when matter and form stand to each
other as potentiality and actuality, the actuality makes the composite what it is (e.g. man) and ensures that it is one
thing. Thus, the actuality determines that the relevant matter is as it is.
Several considerations favour the explanatory interpretation of H.6. First, the questions raised in 1045b18–20 appear to
be genuine ones. Indeed, ‘What is the cause of the unity of the composite?’ is the very question which Aristotle had set
himself in Z.17 and H.2–3. It would be surprising
486 b
This case is immediately contrasted with that of objects which lack matter and are as such one without qualification (1045 23). The latter group, which include (e.g.) forms,
are mentioned here (as in 1045a 36–b 7) to distinguish them from things involving matter, which are (in the present context) Aristotle's main concern. Things without matter
can be described as immediately one because they are free of the problems of unity which arise in discussion of enmattered things. For a somewhat contrasting view, see
Verity Harte's ‘Aristotle's Metaphysics H.6: A Dialectic with Platonism’, Phronesis 41/3 (1996), 289–97.
487
I am indebted to Michael Frede for advice on the interpretation of this sentence. For a somewhat contrasting view, see Theodore Scaltsas's discussion (‘Substratum, Subject
and Substance’, Ancient Philosophy 5 (1985), 232–3).
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 299
if now, with no detailed preparation, the question was declared to be a pseudo one. Second, it does not seem that the
theorists whose views are discussed in 1045b7–17 are asking a nonsensical or pseudo question. Rather they are raising a
genuine difficulty (viz. that mooted in 1045a30–3) in a way which makes it ‘aporetic’, because (so formulated) it is
difficult to resolve.488 Once the question is correctly framed one can find a feature which explains the relevant unity: the
common essence of the matter and form, which reveals the former as potentially F and the latter as actually F. For the
form is the teleologically basic feature which explains why the matter is as it is.
In H.6, according to the explanatory interpreter, Aristotle introduces the notion of actuality as part of his explanation
of the unity of a composite substance. So understood, matter and form will be shown to be unified because both are
essentially directed to the same intrinsic goal. Indeed, talk of actuality and potentiality indicates (on this account) the
ontology required to make these claims perspicuous.489 If so, Aristotle's task in Metaphysics Θ will be to show how these
notions can be used for this purpose, and to make clear the idea of the intrinsic goal of the relevant actuality.
If Aristotle tackles these issues in Metaphysics Θ, he will be following (and deepening) the explanatory approach. By
contrast, if he is a dissolutionist, his strategy in Metaphysics Θ will be very different. For, then he will conclude at the end
of H that:
There is no difficulty in seeing how:
potentiality: actuality
matter: form
are unified to form a unified composite substance. For, these notions are themselves abstractions from the more basic
notion of a unified substance. Indeed, actuality is just that which together with potentiality yields a substance of this
type.
If so, this is, effectively, the end of his enquiry, since he has shown that the issue of unity is a pseudo question. All he
can do in Metaphysics Θ is confirm (once again) that there is no genuine issue of unity.
488
That is, so formulated, the question produces perplexity. This might be because, so formulated, it leads to two conflicting answers, each of which has something to be said
for it (Top. Z.6, 145b 17 ff.). There is no requirement that aporiai can only be resolved by showing that there is no genuine question to answer. Indeed, usually, when there
b b
are aporiai there are genuine issues to resolve. See, e.g., the use of aporiai in the discussion of acrasia (NE/EE H.1, 1145 3 f., 21 f., 1146 6–8).
489
This is not to say that the ontology is solely defined in terms of the relevant goal as ‘whatever plays a given role A’ in an appropriate structure. There is more to talk of
actuality than is determined in this way.
300 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
Which of these routes does Aristotle follow in Metaphysics Θ? I shall argue, in the next Section, that he goes on there to
develop the explanatory approach in ways required to fill the gaps left in H.6. If this is correct, Aristotle pursues the
explanatory account from Z.17 to the end of Θ.
all things are not said to exist actually in the same way, but only by analogy . . . for the relation is either that of
process to potentiality or substance [ousia] to some specific matter.
In H.6 Aristotle appeared to introduce talk of actuality and potentiality to clarify the relation between matter and form
in a compound substance. But now it looks as if he is employing the latter to illuminate the former. The relevant
potentiality (in a unified substance) is one which stands to its actuality as matter stands to its composite (e.g. the statue
of Hermes (1048a30–3,b2–5)). If so, the notion of the unity of a composite substance will be the basic one. If so, both
matter and form will be conceived as abstractions from the notion of a unified composite. No account will be given of
either except in terms of its role in a unified substance. If this is correct, Aristotle has abandoned the explanatory
approach to the definition of substance.
Has Aristotle really discarded his explanatory strategy? If he is to maintain it, he must show how talk of potentiality and
actuality can render perspicuous the unity of a composite substance. Also, he must elucidate the idea of an intrinsic goal
of the actuality introduced in H.6. Is he doing either or both of these in Θ.6–10?
The analogy between the potentialities and actualities involved in processes and in substances holds the key to
Aristotle's discussion. For our purposes, there are two crucial questions. What is the basis for the analogy? And, why is
it merely an analogy? Aristotle's answers to these two questions are (I shall suggest) the ones required by the
explanatory approach to definition.
Consider the case of processes. The relevant potentiality will be defined
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 301
as one for a given type of process: (e.g.) the potentiality to be made into a house.490 The resulting type of process will be
the one it is because of its goal: the house being built. If processes differ in goals, they will be numerically distinct even
if they always co-occur.491 Since the process is defined by its goal (end point), the potentiality is essentially the
potentiality to reach that end point. Here, the end point or goal defines the nature both of the process (to move
towards that end point) and of the relevant potentiality. In a favoured Aristotelian example, house-building is defined
as the process it is by its goal (viz. the house being built), and the potentiality thus exercised is defined as the potential
to achieve this goal (viz. to build a house).
If substance is to be understood analogously, there should be a goal which reveals both its nature (conceived as
actuality) and the relevant potentiality (its matter). Thus, both actuality and potentiality will be defined (directly or
indirectly) in terms of the goal of the actuality (as suggested in H.6, 1045a31–3). Indeed, it is because actualities and
potentialities can be perspicuously represented in this way that they are introduced as the entities required in Aristotle's
teleological account of substance.
Does Aristotle sustain the analogy between substances and processes in this way? Does the relevant actuality have an
appropriate internal goal? There are reasons for returning an affirmative answer to both questions.
(1) In the case of processes, the goal is its end point. By contrast, in the case of substances (as in that of activities) the
goal is immanent (1048b21–3). Thus, the goal of being a house is realized when there is a house (1050a26 f.). Once this
goal has been achieved, a house can persist for a long period. By contrast, in the case of processes, once the goal has
been realized, the relevant process is over. As Aristotle hastens to explain, the goals are of a different type in the two
cases (1048a18–36). This is why
490 a
See Phys. Γ.1, 201 16–18. I have defended this account elsewhere (Aristotle's Philosophy of Action, 19–27). For a contrasting account, see Mary Louise Gill's discussion
(Aristotle on Substance, 186–94). My view rests on construing the relevant capacities for change as essentially dynamic capacities of substances. Others, by contrast,
understand Aristotle to attempt to account for processes without taking such dynamic capacities as basic. Philosophical discussion of this issue requires study of the
adequacy of definitions of change which do not rely on the presence of dynamic capacities (e.g. Can such accounts separate changes from a succession of distinct states, or
from ‘Cambridge’, relational, alterations which are not genuine changes?). These issues raise exegetical problems concerning Aristotle's answers to Zeno's paradoxes of
change. In my view, Aristotle employed dynamic properties of substances to answer Zeno's challenge, and this is why he accepted capacities for changes as basic. But a full
defence of this suggestion is a major, and separate, undertaking.
491 b a
An example of this is, I believe, teaching and learning (Phys. Γ.3, 202 5–22), which differ in goals (202 21–4). See my discussion of this (Aristotle's Philosophy of Action, 11
ff.).
492 b a
An example of this is, I believe, teaching and learning (Phys. Γ.3, 202 5–22), which differ in goals (202 21–4). See my discussion of this (Aristotle's Philosophy of Action, 11
ff.).
302 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
processes essentially unfold through time, while substances (like activities) endure. This difference between them is a
result of a difference in the relevant types of goal.
(2) The internal goal in the case of the actuality of the soul is life (1050a35 ff.). If the soul is conceived as the being
which actually possesses the capacity for life, its goal is life. For, it is because its goal is life that the relevant actuality
(being actually capable of life) is as it is. Indeed, the term ‘actuality’ can be predicated of the internal goal (e.g. life) or
that which is intrinsically directed to that goal (e.g. the soul) (1050a21–3).492 Once we conceive of form as actuality (and
matter as potentiality), we can see how both of them are what they are in virtue of being appropriately connected with
this goal.493 In this way Aristotle can sustain the analogy with processes. For, there too the relevant goal determines
both the actuality and the potentiality.
While Aristotle defends the analogy between substance and process in this way, he also points out areas of disanalogy.
(3) The relevant potentialities and actualities are related in different ways in the two cases. (This is discussed in Θ.8.)
Since the actuality in the case of substance does not occur in another thing or in itself as another thing (1049b5–8), it
cannot be related to its potentiality in the same way as an active potentiality is related to a passive one in the case of
processes.494 For, in the case of substances, the relevant interaction cannot involve efficient causation as may occur
between distinct subjects of change.495 For, the latter always operate in another object or in themselves considered as
another object (e.g. a doctor healing himself (Phys. Β.8, 199b31, Meta. Δ.12, 1019a17–18). Thus, there must be an
important difference between the type of explanation appropriate in these distinct cases.
(4) The other relata (capacity for change: matter) differ in ways which reflect the difference in types of goal in the two
cases. In the case of persisting substances, the relevant capacity of the matter is to be a man and not to become a man. In
many cases, the capacity to become an F will be lost when one is an F (e.g. a man). Once one is a fully-fledged man,
one can no longer become what one already is (while still remaining that thing). This is precisely how the capacities
essentially involved in being and
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 303
becoming differ.496 So, the type of potentiality which matter is will differ from the potentiality to become an F (which
capacity belongs as such to a subject of change).497 Matter will rather be essentially the potentiality to be an F.
Aristotle in Θ.6–8 uses these points to clarify the distinctive types of potentiality and actuality present in composite
substances. Since his strategy depends on pointing to their distinctive roles in explanation, he is (it appears) carrying
forward the explanatory approach to definition initiated in Z.17 and H. Thus, in 1048b7–9 cited above, he should be
seen as claiming that there is a unified substance when (and only when) there is a potentiality of type (2) tied to an
actuality of type (1) in virtue of their sharing one teleological goal. If so, actuality and potentiality are the basic elements
in Aristotle's ontology precisely because they are what is
304 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
needed to account (in an explanatory way) for the unity of a composite substance.
There is one further aspect of the explanatory approach to be considered. In Aristotle's account, the relevant actuality
is a simple, indivisible, entity specific to the relevant kind which explains the presence of the other differentiae of its
matter. But what kind of simple entity is involved in talk of (e.g.) immediates (1045b2–4), simples (1041b9–11), or
incomposites (1043b35)? If he is following the explanatory approach, the relevant actuality will be central to the relevant
answer to the ‘Why?’ question. The relevant simple incomposite feature will be one which explains all the other
relevant features of the composite. Indeed, the simplicity in question need amount to no more than the requirement
that there be one basic cause or starting point (as in Post. An. Β.9, 93b21–2), which does not permit of further causal
analysis. The simplicity at issue need be no more demanding than this.498
In this account, Aristotle's approach to definition depends (in Metaphysics Z, H, and Θ, as in the Analytics) on the view
that the same answer should be given to the questions ‘What is F?’ and ‘Why is F as it is?’ Indeed, if the argument of
Sections 11.3–11.5 is correct, definition by matter and form is a special case of the general account of definition
developed in the Analytics. It differs only in introducing the concepts of matter and form (drawn from Aristotle's
physical writings) to specify the terms required in an Analytics style of (teleology-involving) definition of composite
substances. Aristotle does not, as LeBlond suggested, introduce at this point a further separate form of definition (over
and above definition by causal basis and definition by genus and species).59 Properly understood, these are all instances
of one general, explanation-involving, form of definition which permeates Analytics and Metaphysics Z, H, and Θ alike.
If we see Aristotle as following this explanatory approach to definition, we gain further insight into the basic nature of
form. So understood, it is the answer to the question ‘What is this substance?’ while at the same time being a
fundamental feature in a teleological account of why the substance is as it is. Since it is a major claim that there is one
thing that can play both these roles, Aristotle needed to develop an account of form which showed how it could play
both these roles simultaneously.
This approach puts constraints on the notion of form. Forms, so understood, have to be capable of playing a certain
role both in teleological explanation and in definition. For example, the form of man could not be the simple
indefinable Man*, if the latter were not capable of playing the required role in the explanation of why man is two-
footed that (e.g.) being rational does. Thus, even if it is true that he takes form to be (in some sense) a ‘basic’,
‘primitive’, or ‘undefined’ element,500 its nature is tightly
306 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
constrained by the demand that it play a given role in explaining why the substance as a whole is as it is.
The constraints on definition (introduced in Z.4–12) are incapable by themselves of making fully determinate the
relevant notion of form. As we saw above, they need to be supplemented by explanatory concerns in Z.17 and beyond.
Taken together, they rule out the possibility of defining form merely as (e.g.) ‘whatever occupies a given explanatory
role’. For, what is sought is a feature which answers the ‘What is F?’ question by accounting for the presence of the
ability to play a given explanatory role. Only then will the definition make the whole nature of the kind fully
transparent. There can be no account of form (as was to be expected in the light of the interdependency thesis) which
renders it incapable of playing both the required definitional and explanatory roles.501
The distinctive nature of this interpretation may become clearer if it is compared with two other accounts that have
gained currency in recent years. One might be termed (as above) the dissolutionist approach, the second (perhaps
somewhat pejoratively) the ‘quick-fix’ strategy.502 Both reject the view that the theory of definition (in the case of
substance) requires any support from the theory of explanation.
According to the dissolutionist, the starting point for metaphysical investigation is the unity of a persisting composite
substance (whether Socrates or man) and not the form. In this account, matter (potentiality) and form (actuality) are
(interconnected) abstractions derived from the basic notion of one unified substance. If so, there is no real question
about the unity of the composite. It is taken for granted at the outset.503
A partial analogy may help to make the dissolutionist account clearer. In it, unified composite substances are analogous
to sentences when taken (as for example by Frege) as the basic units in semantic theory. There, a predicate is that
which together with a subject yields a sentence, while a subject is that which together with a predicate yields a sentence.
It is a mistake to try to explain the unity of a sentence in terms of an independently specified type of interconnection
between subject and predicate (for
SUBSTANCE, DEFINITION, AND ESSENCE 307
the relevant interconnection is itself dependent on the unity of the sentence).504 It would be a similar mistake (according
to this view) to attempt to explain the unity of a composite substance by means of an independently specified type of
connection between matter and form. For the relevant relata are all abstractions from the basic notion of one
composite (e.g. the sentence).505
If I am correct, Aristotle has serious objections to the dissolutionist project. First, the dissolutionist, in giving up the
idea of form as the starting point for explanation, severs the connections between the answers to the ‘What is F?’
question and to the relevant ‘Why?’ question. If so, he is forced to surrender the constraints on definition which flow
from the interconnections between definition and explanation (on which, if Sections 11.2–11.5 are accepted, the
central argument of the Metaphysics turns). If so, he leaves the relevant notion of definition unconstrained. For, if form
is not understood as what explains the relevant composite and its matter, what makes some features of the composite
substance its form? Indeed, it seems as if (on this view) it is we who decide which of the range of possible abstracta is to
be the form.506
Similar objections apply to the ‘quick-fix’ interpretation. In this account (unlike the dissolutionist's), actuality and
potentiality are introduced independently of the notion of the unity of a composite substance, but without any further
elucidation. It is claimed that, once they are introduced, one can see immediately that their interconnection will give rise
to the appropriate type of unity.
This interpretation, however, fails to offer a perspicuous account of the type of unity in question. It merely introduces
two unanalysed terms (‘the correct relata’), and says that when they are correctly related there is the appropriate type of
unity. But this suggestion appears empty until we know (at least) what either the ‘correct relata’ or ‘the correct relation’
is. Indeed, nothing prevents form (so understood) from being the simple unanalysable (Platonic) man*. Aristotle's
notion of form must be more constrained than this.
308 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
The ‘quick-fixer’ may reply that the ‘correct relata’ in the case of composite substances are analogues of potentiality and
actuality in the case of processes. But what now is the basis of this analogy? Deprived of all connection with
teleological explanation, the notions of form and actuality (so understood) appear unconstrained and obscure. For,
they no longer figure as the central planks in an account of the unity of the composite anchored in an explanation of
why the latter is as it is. Indeed, it is hard to see why anyone should believe that (so understood) they pick out features
of reality.
Metaphysics Λ.508 These issues raise difficult and important questions about Aristotle's views on substance and
definition, which cannot be considered here.
12 Biology, Classication, and Essence
12.1 Introduction
In the preceding Chapters, I have argued that Aristotle developed one, explanation-involving, account of definition. The
interdependency between his account of the practices of definition and of explanation, uncovered in Chapters 8 and 9,
rests on two claims:
(A) At the centre of each definition there is reference to one causally basic feature which explains the presence of
other necessary features of the phenomenon.
(B) The definition is completed by the addition of reference to differentiating features, themselves parts of the
nature of the phenomenon, whose presence is explained by the basic causal feature specified in (A).
These two claims provide the basis in the Analytics for an integrated approach to definition and classification. In the
Metaphysics both play a role in Aristotle's account of definition and of essence. Are they also at work in his biological
writings?
If Aristotle remains committed to (A) in his biological studies, he will look for definitions which refer to one causally
basic feature of the required type.509 If he adheres to (B), he will attempt to uncover a system of differentiae which
captures parts of the nature of the relevant kinds in the way suggested above.510 More precisely, he will look for
differentiae which:
(a*) fit into a general and non-ad hoc procedure for deriving genuine kinds from other relevant kinds
and
(b*) are themselves explained by the basic underlying feature of the kind.511
Does Aristotle do either? In the Analytics Aristotle gives no example of a full definition of an animal kind. Nor does he
point to any empirical science
BIOLOGY, CLASSIFICATION, AND ESSENCE 311
which can be ordered within a genus-differentia structure of the type he proposes. While he gives biological examples, he
does not show how the science (as a whole) can correspond (even roughly) to the model of the Analytics. Still less does
he establish that it does so. Are these gaps filled in the biological works? Or does Aristotle give up the Analytics account
of definition and classification when confronted by the complexities of real science?
Aristotle's remarks in his initial discussion of biological classification in De Partibus Animalium Α.2–3 render doubtful
his continued adherence to claim (2). He had suggested in the Metaphysics that there should be one differentia which
marked out the species (cf. Ζ.12, 1038a25 f.), and implied the presence of all the rest.512 But now he prefers an
alternative in which correct division is by multiple differentiae (642b21, 643b9), applied to the genus simultaneously. It is
not immediately apparent how simultaneous differentiae of this type are to fit into the Analytics model, with its step-by-
step priority relations (as marked out in Post. An. Β.13).513
Does Aristotle still adhere to (A)? In the Metaphysics (as was argued in the last Chapter) he developed a teleological
account of the internal structure of composite substances, in which the essence is the single basic teleological cause of
the substance being as it is. Do biological kinds correspond to this model? If they do not, his methods for establishing
the unity of kinds (and substances qua members of kinds) will be in danger of collapse.
These two issues raise further questions about Stages 2 and 3 of the three-stage view, as presented above.514 For, they
bring into sharp focus two problems:
(1) What is required (at Stage 2) to establish the existence of a kind?
(2) Are there in the biological domain essences of the type required by Stage 3 of the Analytics model? Did
Aristotle think there were?
Did Aristotle succeed in classifying biological kinds and uncovering their essences in the ways proposed in the
Analytics? Did he develop that
312 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
general framework further and make it more precise? Or, alternatively, did he surrender the whole project, and despair
of maintaining in this area the paradigm of definition and classification to which he is committed in the Analytics?
I shall argue that some parts of the biological writings constitute a substantial vindication of ideas developed in the
Analytics (and Metaphysics), but that others expose certain aspects of that model as deeply problematic. The route to
classifying and establishing the existence of biological kinds can be seen as Aristotle's development of the account
given in the Analytics. But his account of what is involved in establishing the unity of a kind involves a major
modification of his Analytics model of definition. It is no exaggeration to say that the study of biological kinds
precipitated a crisis in Aristotle's thinking about definition. Nor was it one which he could easily or painlessly resolve.
Indeed, it is not immediately clear that he succeeded in resolving it all.
So, perhaps the right procedure is this: [a] so far as concerns the attributes of those groups (genera) which have
been correctly marked off by common usage—groups which possess one common nature apiece and contain in themselves species
not far removed from one another [my emphasis] (I mean birds, fishes, and any other group which though it lacks a name
yet contains species generically similar)—to describe the common attributes of the group all together; and [b] with
regard to those animals which are not covered by this, to describe the attributes of each by themselves; e.g. those of
man, and of any other such species. (644b1–7)
The passage contains the following thought. Certain genera have been correctly marked out by common usage: those
that (i) possess one common nature, and (ii) contain species not far removed from one another. It appears that there will
be one genus if and only if it contains (i) a distinctive common nature and (ii) species not far removed from one another.
This passage, however, is elusive. It does not say what is to count as
BIOLOGY, CLASSIFICATION, AND ESSENCE 313
one common nature of the appropriate type. Nor does it determine when species are not far removed from one
another. Aristotle does state that:
it is practically by resemblance of the shape of their parts, or of their whole body, that the groups are marked off from
one another—as groups of birds, fishes, cephalopods, testacea (644b7–11)
and notes further that within these groups (genera) the parts differ only by ‘the more or the less’, by being (for example)
larger or smaller, softer or harder (644b13–16). But these remarks also are vague. It is not clear whether resemblance in
shape of parts constitutes (in the central cases) sameness in nature, or whether it is rather that members of the same
genus, marked out on different criteria, do in fact generally have similarly shaped parts.
Nor are Aristotle's remarks elsewhere on this topic in De Partibus Animalium free from obscurity. He writes in Α.2 that
the name ‘bird’ is given to one type of likeness, ‘fish’ to another (642b14–16), and in Α.3 that birds are marked out from
fish by many differentiae (643b12–14). But it is not clear whether he is concerned here with likeness in any feature
whatsoever, or only in some favoured or more basic set of features (and, if so, which), or with likeness overall. Do all
likenesses count equally, or only some? The passage remains unclear.
At the end of De Partibus Animalium Α.5 Aristotle notes that the parts of the body ‘are for the sake of some action’
(645b16–17) and exist for the sake of their natural function (b19–20). Relevant actions include generation, growth,
copulation, waking, sleep, locomotion (645b33 ff.). Do these functions define similarity and difference in parts of
animals independently of their shape? If so, does Aristotle propose (as a further thesis) that if animal parts serve the
same function, they will resemble each other in shape? Or does he construe shape as definitionally basic, and hold as a
further thesis that if animal parts resemble one another in shape, they tend to have the same function?515 516
In De Partibus Animalium Α.5 Aristotle appears to take actions to be definitionally prior to the organs (or instruments)
which perform the actions. For he writes:
314 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
When actions are for different goals, the organs differ in the same way as the actions. Similarly, if one action is prior
to another, the part to which it belongs will be prior. (645b28–32)
If priority between actions determines priority between organs, this is (presumably) because actions are definitionally
prior to organs. Indeed, to regard organs as instruments (as he does in 645b15–17) indicates that their goal or purpose
is constitutive of their identity, and that any similarity in shape is secondary. Thus, what makes an axe what it is is the
purpose for which it is designed. This will be so even if some are more like hammers in shape and size than other axes
(645b18 f.). All axes, no matter what their shape, will differ by the more and the less provided that they fulfil the same
general function. Similarly, animal parts in different species will differ by the more and the less provided that they too
fulfil the same general function. Thus, feathers in birds will differ only by the more and the less because they all play a
similar role in the overall activities of birds (its complex action (645b17), involving assisting flight, protecting the
animal, etc.) in somewhat different ways.
This provides us with a route to understand Aristotle's remarks at the beginning of De Partibus Animalium Α.4:
While groups that differ only by excess (the more and the less) are placed in one group, those that are only similar
by analogy are placed in different groups. I mean, bird differs from bird by the more and the less, as one bird's
feathers are long, another's short, while birds and fish are similar only by analogy (for the bird, feathers, for the fish,
scales). (644a16–22)
So interpreted, birds will differ from each other by the more and the less because they act in the same way, even though
their organs differ in shape. By contrast, birds will differ from fish because they have different characteristic actions,
and their parts can be similar only by analogy. Thus, parts will be similar only by analogy even if they are identical or
very similar as regards shape (644a24 f.), provided that they play roles in different characteristic actions (e.g. the legs of
birds and humans, or blood in different genera of animals).
If this is correct, in De Partibus Animalium Α.4 Aristotle is not beginning with a non-theoretical idea of similarity in
shape and deducing from it similarity in genus (as the first lines might suggest). For, birds (and birds' feathers) will
differ from each other only by the more and the less because they are birds and feathers, items marked out in terms
which depend on their possessing distinctive characteristic actions. Several features favour this view. First, it explains
why Aristotle can allow that parts which are similar in shape are analogously related (644a24 f.), when they belong to
different species. Second, it explains why in some cases difference in shape indicates difference in organ, while in
others the organ is the same and differs only in the more and the less (643a1–3). In the former, but not the
BIOLOGY, CLASSIFICATION, AND ESSENCE 315
latter, the organs differ because they fulfil differing activities. Had Aristotle employed shape as the criterion for
sameness/difference of an organ, he would have divided kinds in ways which do not respect these relevant, indeed
essential, features (643a27–9;cf.642b12–20).
These passages suggest that Aristotle is relying on a theory of the nature of a genus, in which similarity in characteristic
activity plays the central role. But the theory is not spelled out in these passages, since Aristotle does not say which
actions play this role, or whether features other than characteristic activity can be equally central in genus
determination. To this extent, the idea of a common nature is left indeterminate. Similarly, his remark that the first task
of the biological writings is to describe the properties which belong per se to each group of animals (Α.5, 645b1–3)
remains indeterminate because he has not precisely defined the groups involved. In the language of Posterior Analytics
Β.13, he needs to set out more precisely the appropriate differentiating characteristics which separate different groups
of animals.
Aristotle refers, at the beginning of De Partibus Animalium Β.1, to the Historia Animalium (646a8–10). And it is there that
he focuses most insistently on these issues and develops his own views most fully. He writes in Historia Animalium Α.6,
491a9 f.:
our goal is to establish first the differences that exist and the properties that belong to all.517
To detect the relevant differentiating characteristics is the way to discover what the genera and species are. Thus, in this
passage, he is recalling the goal of De Partibus Animalium Α.5: to describe the properties which belong per se to kinds, as
marked out by their relevant differentiae. This follows the general prescription concerning the role of historiai: to discover
what properties genuinely belong to which objects, so that one can more easily devise appropriate explanations (Pr. An.
Α.30, 46a23–7). Historiai are, thus, essential first steps towards causal explanation, and ones which
316 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
involve determining which genera and species, in reality, differ from each other (as in the immediately preceding
passages of Historia Animalium Α.6 and De Partibus Animalium Α.4), and which properties genuinely belong to each kind
or sub-kind.518 So, we may raise, in considering Historia Animalium, two more specific questions:
(a) Does Aristotle succeed in clarifying the notion of a common nature, as introduced in De Partibus Animalium, in the
way required to separate differing genera and species of animals? (Or, in the language of Historia Animalium,
how far does he delimit the type of differentiae required for this task?)
(b) Does Aristotle succeed in marking out (in outline) the basis for species differentiation within a genus?
Positive answers to (a) and (b) would enable us to grasp what determines the basic system of differentiation at work in
the biological writings. We should then be in a position to see how far Aristotle's biological classificatory scheme fulfils
the two demands (a*) and (b*) of the Analytics paradigm. Does his use of the notion of common nature provide the
basis for a non-ad hoc procedure for deriving genuine kinds, which points to features to be explained by the causal basis
of the kind? Further, one may ask how far his use of the notion of common nature is of assistance in establishing the
existence of a genus or species. Is it sufficient (or necessary) for knowledge of the existence of a genus or species that
one knows it to possess a common nature of some type (possibly so far unspecified)? Is this what is required to know
(in the terminology of the Analytics) that there is a cause or unifying principle which explains why (e.g.) fish exist in the
way they do, even if one does not know precisely what the cause is?519
animals, soft-shelled animals, ‘softies’ (types of cephalopod), and insects (490b7–14), (these last four are bloodless).
How did Aristotle arrive at this classification? Why did he exclude certain other candidates from the category of great
genera (490b15–491a6)?
Aristotle's earlier discussion in Historia Animalium Α.1–5 has laid the foundation for these claims. Birds have been
marked out as feathered fliers (490a6–7, 12–13), fish as gilled and (generally) finned, footless swimmers (489b23–6).
Most of them take in and emit water, and cannot live apart from it (487a15–20). Cetacea are also swimmers, but lack
gills and instead have a blowhole (489b2–4). Also, they are viviparous (489a34). Insects, so-called because of the
insections in their bodies (487a32 f.), do not take in air, although they live and get their food on land (487a31 f.). By
contrast with birds, flying insects have membranous wings (490a9–11). The ‘softies’ (cephalopods) are swimmers, who
have feet and fins, which they use for swimming (490a2–4). The soft-shelled animals (crustacea) are all aquatic and
capable of locomotion whether by swimming or walking (487b15–18), while many types of hard-shelled animals
(testacea) are aquatic but stationary (487b14), take in neither water nor air, but obtain their food in the water (487a25 f.).
Aristotle, it appears, has provided a justification for treating these genera as correctly marked out by common usage.
He has done this by showing how these kinds exhibit genuine differences in the following respects:
(a) type of locomotion: walking, flying, swimming, stationary;
(b) method of breathing: some take in air or water, others do not;
(c) method of eating: where the animals find their food. (cf.487a22–7).
In some cases modes of locomotion are the basic ingredients. Fliers are divided according to their method for doing so
(feathers, membranous wings). In others, modes of breathing are basic (gills, blowholes, etc.). But each of these kinds is
marked out using divisions within the life functions (locomotion, breathing, eating, etc.). It appears that it is these
affections and actions that provide the basis for Aristotle's classification at this point (cf. De Partibus Animalium Α.5,
645b33 ff.). To have a common nature is (at least) to have a distinctive way of fulfilling some of these basic life
functions.520
318 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
The central role of differentiae of this type is illustrated by other aspects of Historia Animalium Α.1–5. The discussion of
parts follows the pattern of De Partibus Animalium: if the genus is the same, animals will differ by the more and the less
(HA, Α.1, 486a22 ff.). By contrast, if features belong to different genera, they will only be analogically similar
(486b20–2). But, as before, the genera (such as bird and fish) appear to be taken as already determined. As in De
Partibus Animalium, sameness and difference rest on sameness and differences in genus (and presumably, therefore, on
difference in basic soul function).
Aristotle lists, in addition to differentiae with regard to part, differences in respect of life, activities, and dispositions (HA.
Α.1, 487a11–14). These cases also reveal some structure. Aristotle begins with water and land animals, but then breaks
this classification down further in terms of patterns of feeding and breathing (487a14–b8). Differences in locomotion
and reproduction, by contrast, are taken as basic, and not further analysed into more basic categories (487b8–32,
489b19 ff.). Similarly, in characterizing what is shared by all animals, Aristotle focuses on eating and digestion
(488b29–489a8) and reproduction (489a8–16), but mentions touch only in passing (489a17–19). Thus, certain activities
(such as feeding, moving, breathing, and reproducing) are taken as the central ones in characterizing differences
between animals.
The central role of this favoured set of differentiae becomes clearer when Aristotle considers cases of groupings which
fail to yield great genera. Wingless quadruped is briefly canvassed as a possibility in Historia Animalium Α.6, 490b19 f.,
but not used elsewhere as a genus. By contrast, viviparous quadruped and oviparous quadruped are retained as
relevant genera, although neither are great genera. Why is this? Aristotle notes that wingless quadrupeds divide into the
viviparous and oviparous (490b20 f.). But while these are nameless groups, their namelessness cannot be the crucial
factor. For, the immediate subdivisions within the retained genus of viviparous quadruped are similarly nameless
(490b31 ff.). The relevant point here seems rather to be that the species within the suggested genus of wingless
quadruped would be dissimilar in a certain crucial respect: method of reproduction (see PA Α.4, 644b4–5). Further,
Aristotle notes that viviparous animals all have hair, while oviparous ones have scales (490b21–3), pointing to a feature
which is the analogue of hair in other animals (GA E.3, 782a16–19).
In this example, Aristotle is relying on two ideas. If one has a genus, the species which comprise it should perform
basic life functions in a basically similar way (e.g. reproduction). Further difference in mode of reproduction is
sufficient to show that there are different genera in the case of quadrupeds. Both show that Aristotle is concerned to
secure his favoured genera on the basis of a unified common nature—in which shared ways of performing certain
basic functions are of central importance (here,
BIOLOGY, CLASSIFICATION, AND ESSENCE 319
locomotion and reproduction).521 In the case of a unified genus there is a distinctive way of moving, reproducing,
feeding, and breathing. Difference with respect to one of these life functions undermines the unity of the genus.
If this is correct, a theory of what constitutes a common nature is at work in selecting the great genera in I.6, and
deselecting others. Aristotle is not proceeding merely by counting up differentiae and seeing which animals share many of
them. He is focusing rather on certain basic soul features which determine the great genera, and viewing subspecies as
ones which perform these functions in roughly similar ways. This makes far clearer what a ‘common nature’ is: an
organized collection of methods of moving, reproducing, feeding, and breathing.
A similar background theory is at work elsewhere in the Historia. Aristotle throughout employs a formula to associate
animal kinds with given features:
In these cases, Aristotle uses features concerning locomotion and reproduction as the basis for his divisions between
animals. Subsequently, when he divides genera into species, he often does so by distinguishing the ways in which the
animals reproduce (internally, externally, viviparously, etc.). He does, of course, draw further subdivisions (as at Β.17,
507a34) within the groups marked out in this way. Thus, for example, he distinguishes among viviparous quadrupeds
those that have horns but lack teeth in both jaws. But this latter demarcation is required because (in this context) he is
focusing on differences between types of stomach. Similarly, when he distinguishes:
he does so in a context where these organs are the subject matter.523 In general, his basis for differentiation remains
organized natures with distinctive means of reproduction and locomotion.524 Thus, throughout these sections,
Aristotle's divisions rest (in the main) on differing ways of fulfilling the basic functions of reproducing, moving,
breathing, and growth (PA. Α.5, 645b33–5). Differences in these functions mark out distinct genera, whether great or
small.
Aristotle, in discussing the common nature of animals (in HA. Α and Β), takes as basic, locomotion, breathing, and
reproduction. Once great genera have been marked out in these terms, he can distinguish differing sub-kinds in a
similarly structured way. After fish have been introduced as gilled, finned swimmers (Α.5, 489b24–5), Aristotle uses the
following differentiae further to divide the genus:
(a) four-finned vs. two-finned vs. no-finned: Β.13, 504b27–35
(b) covered vs. non-covered gills: Β.13, 505a1 f.
(c) single vs. double gills: Β.13, 505a8 f.
(d) few vs. many gills: Β.13, 505a10–12
Thus, he can separate (on the basis of differentiae of this type) several major species within the genus of fish (such as
selachia (505a1), muraena (504b34, cf. 489b24–6), eels (504b32, cf. 489b24–6)), as well as other smaller species (such as
the mullet, parrotwrasse, perch, rainbowwrasse, carp,
BIOLOGY, CLASSIFICATION, AND ESSENCE 321
dogfish, swordfish, tapefish, and fishing frog, all discussed in De Historia Animalium Β.13).
Fish have certain features in common (in Aristotle's account). They are blooded (505b1 f.), and have a bladder (506b5),
although this may be differently placed in different fish (HA Β.15). All have a gut of a given type (a feature they share
with birds (508b14)), although they differ from one another in the number they possess (508b15–25). Aristotle notes
that varieties of fish differ in these respects (at the level of species: e.g. angelfish, skate, pipefish, goby, burbet, etc.). But
they are, nonetheless, all varieties of fish because they all carry out similar functions (e.g. nutrition of a given type) in
similar ways, and possess the basic differentiae of fish (as gilled or finned swimmers).
Aristotle, by employing intuitions of this type about common nature, is able to vindicate the popular assumption that fish
form one genus of animal, one whose species share similarity in function and in functionally related structural features.
Against this background, he can proceed to mark out further major differences between fish: some, the scaly fish, are
oviparous, while others are viviparous (Β.13, 505b2–4)—for instance, the selachia.525 Indeed, he calls ‘selachia’ footless
creatures which have gills and are viviparous (Γ.1, 511a4–7).526 They form a proper grouping with their own distinctive
sexual differentiae (.11, 538a29) and bone structure, which reproduce in a distinctive manner (.5, 540b5 ff., Ζ.10, 564b15
ff.). Here, too, Aristotle focuses on reproduction to distinguish lower-level types of fish, even though they all breathe
and/or move in the way distinctive of fish. The genus has a common nature because all fish perform the same basic
soul functions in similar ways.
Once this common nature has been established, Aristotle can distinguish between fish by contrasting their ways of
performing other soul functions: generation (Γ), perceiving, hearing, sleeping (Δ), reproducing (E, Z), eating (Θ),
migrating (Θ.12 ff.), hibernation (Θ.15), flourishing (Θ.19), illness (Θ.20), adaptation to their environment (I.37). Of
these, procreation and eating are the most basic (in Aristotle's view):
One part of the life of animals consists in actions concerning procreation, another in actions concerning food. For,
it is on these two activities that the interests and life of all are fixed. (HA. Θ.1, 589a2–5)
322 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
Elsewhere he notes:
The habits of animals are all concerned with breeding and rearing of young, or with obtaining food . . . These habits
are modified so as to suit cold and heat, and the variations of seasons. (Θ.12, 596b20–4)
Aristotle, in discussing these activities, frequently begins his account by saying what all fish have in common: they all
lack testicles (509b3, 25), none have breasts or milk (521b25 f.), all lack visible sense organs (533a34 f.), all sleep (537a1),
and all feed on spawn (591a7). He then proceeds to note that differing kinds of fish perform these functions differently.
Aristotle's discussion of the eating habits of fish in Historia Animalium Θ.1–12 provides an example of the relevant
aspects of his method.527 In Θ.2 he is mainly concerned to note differences in eating patterns between the different
types of fish he has already marked out on separate grounds such as:
(a) types of gill: grey mullet, scarus, selachians, dentex528
(b) types of fin: conger, muraena, bass, gilthead, eels529
(c) types of gut or gall: amia, red mullet, goby530
(d) types of skin: tunny531
(e) types of breeding or spawning pattern: saupe, phycis, rock fish, sargue, channa, sea perch532
BIOLOGY, CLASSIFICATION, AND ESSENCE 323
As before, distinct modes of breathing, moving, digesting, and reproducing play a central role. Aristotle shows how
distinctive ways of finding food can be mapped on to types of fish already distinguished in terms of other soul
functions. Thus, he confirms his earlier classification by showing how those distinctions are related to other differences
in eating pattern. There are only three cases of fish species added in Θ.2: the dascyllus (591a14), melanurus (591a15),
and the peraeas (a24). All the rest have been already marked out in terms of other soul functions. Indeed, this is the
general pattern in Aristotle's discussion of migration, hibernation, flourishing, and adaptation. In nearly all cases, the
types of fish attributed different kinds of (e.g.) migratory pattern have been distinguished in terms of his basic
differentiae. While he is prepared to add four further types of fish to his list at this point (e.g. black bream, 598a10;
weaver, 598a11; braize, 598a13; sea cuckoo, 598a14), the remaining twenty-four have already been marked out on other
grounds. Aristotle underwrites popular distinctions between species of fish by noting their relevant basic natures
(modes of moving, breathing, digesting, and reproducing), while occasionally showing how further sub-groups differ in
eating or migratory patterns. His theory of soul function directs his enquiry and helps him to vindicate popular claims
of this type.
In the passages considered, Aristotle has used his theory of soul function to mark out fish as a genus and to draw
further differences within this genus. Elsewhere in Historia Animalium he employs the same resources (in a somewhat
different way) to separate different types of aquatic animal. Some live and feed in water, take in water and emit it (e.g.
fish), while others live and feed in water but take in air not water and breed away from water (e.g. otter, beaver,
crocodile) (Α.1, 487a18–20). Some, again, obtain their food in water, but take in neither water nor air (e.g. shellfish, sea
anemones (487a23–6)). Aristotle uses different modes of breathing and location of food to distinguish different types
of water animal. As he remarks, these are connected since no water animal which takes in sea water gets its food from
land (487b3–5). Thus, breathing and mode of nutrition play a decisive role in separating out animals which share the
same habitat and in marking out different ways of being aquatic.
Aristotle, in his subsequent discussion of aquatic animals (HA Θ.2), is forced to further refinement by examining the
activities of the dolphin (589a31–b28, 590a13–18). This case is problematic because the dolphin takes in and discharges
water by its blowhole, while also inhaling air into its lungs (589b5 f.). Since it takes in and emits both water and air, it
could be classified as both aquatic and terrestrial (589b7–14). Aristotle, faced with this problem, distinguishes further
(prosdioristeon (589b13)) between aquatic animals as follows: some take in water (via their gills) for the same purpose as
respiration—to cool their blood, while others, which take in water for
324 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
the different purpose of obtaining food, do not use water to cool the blood but expel it via their blowhole (589b15–18).
These latter animals are aquatic in a different way from fish. Difference in breathing separates differing ways of being
aquatic: one type of animal breathes by taking in water, the other by taking in air (Θ.2, 590a14).533 Fish and dolphins,
however, both take their food from the water, and so can be distinguished from animals which breathe like fish but
obtain their food on dry land (the water newt (589b25–8)). Here, too, Aristotle uses difference in basic soul functions
(breathing, eating, and locomotion) to distinguish different ways of being aquatic. Once again, it seems that his
investigations rest on a powerful background theory of what is to count as a common nature. When two animals without
a common nature can both be characterized as aquatic, the latter term needs further clarification.534
Aristotle, it appears, in Historia Animalium is working with a set of assumptions about what it is to have a common nature:
it is to possess the same organized set of soul functions involving (typically) locomotion, breathing, reproducing, and
eating. To establish the existence of a great genus is to establish that there is an organized and distinctive set of soul
functions of this type. Species are differentiated (in large part) by their differing ways of performing the same set of
soul functions. Thus, to establish that a species exists is to establish that there is a nature which performs the set of
soul functions characteristic of the genus in a distinctive manner.535 In this case (as in that of the genus) one grasps that
there is a common nature, even if one has not as yet grasped what that nature is: what the basis for the difference in
soul function is.
If this is correct, Aristotle's project in the Historia Animalium is not that of determining the relevant genera and species
merely by collecting a ‘large group’ of counter-predicable properties, and then using division to
BIOLOGY, CLASSIFICATION, AND ESSENCE 325
establish the species. Nor does he merely seek those general differentiae which are distinguished by continuous variations
of their sensible affections.536 The significance he attaches to differences in basic soul functions shows that he is making
major assumptions about what features are important in establishing genuine common natures. His enquiry is, in
effect, the progressively more systematic elucidation of controlling concepts of this type, one which results empirically
in differentiation into kinds and sub-kinds.537 It involves both empirical data and a powerful background theory.538
326 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
In these respects, Aristotle's pattern of differentiation follows the model set out in Posterior Analytics Β.13. The
differentiae will be features which are themselves parts of the nature of the kinds to be investigated. Further, the method
is not an ad hoc one, since it is based on a few closely related basic concepts which are used to differentiate the relevant
kinds (as is required by (a*) above). If there is an answer to the ‘Why?’ question which explains the presence of these
differentiating features, all the essentials of the Analytics model will have been retained.
The biological works do not satisfy, however, all the desiderata proposed in the Analytics. The Historia Animalium does
not provide a complete taxonomy of all animals, an exhaustive, hierarchic classification. For, the account (as has often
been remarked) is incomplete in many respects. Aristotle's apparent aim in the Historia is to provide the basic outline
for a system of classification rather than to carry it through in every detail. Further, the classificatory scheme (involving
multiple simultaneous differentiae) does not (as was noted above) correspond precisely to the hierarchical scheme of
differentiae (odd, prime, prime*) set out in the discussion of Β.13.539 However, that said, Aristotle aims to provide the
resources (via his theory of common nature and soul function) for locating biological kinds within a classificatory
scheme which retains several aspects of the Analytics model. This goal is to be achieved mainly by invoking the
concepts of common nature and soul functions. This account has interesting consequences for our understanding of
the three-stage view and of the general aims of the Historia Animalium. (See the next Section.)540
presence of a common nature at this stage in the investigation requires one to know that there is a unifying cause at
work, even though one need not yet know what it is. Stage 2 takes us beyond Stage 1, where we lack knowledge of the
existence of the kind. For, at Stage 2 we know that the kind exists and have some grasp on its internal structure.
How should Stages 2 and 3 be connected? There are two points of connection suggested by our earlier discussions:
(a) What is discovered at Stage 3 should provide the basis for the common nature discerned at Stage 2 (as the
teleologically basic feature or (perhaps) shared type of material basis: (e.g.) degree of heat). If so, it is no
accident that the genera and species marked out at Stage 2 match those which science explains, since the latter
fills out and further explicates the guiding conception of a shared nature already implicit at Stage 2. If this
notion had not been invoked at the second stage, and the genera and species had been marked out (e.g.) by
counter-predication and division, it would have remained unexplained why Stages 2 and 3 are parts of one
enterprise. If genera and species were determined by the method of counter-predication alone, there would be
no reason why there should be any overlap between these kinds and those with the same Stage 3 essence.
There would be no reason to believe that pre- and post-scientific classification would march in step as well as
they seem to do (in Aristotle's account).
(b) In some cases, authority may rest with Stage 3 considerations in determining the nature of kinds. If there are
not one but several distinct basic causes of apparently similar cases, the kinds involved will differ. Thus,
Aristotle writes in discussing pride:
if we do not come to one but to two or more accounts, it is clear that what we are seeking is not a single thing but
several. (Post. An. Β.13, 97b13 f.)
If there is not one thing common to all proud people, there are distinct types of pride. Thus, difference in internal
cause (e.g. indifference to fortune, not brooking dishonour) forces difference in species of pride. However, this will
only be so if at Stage 2 genera or species are marked out in such a way as to be revisable in the light of Stage 3
considerations. This could not be so if genera and species are marked out by the empiricist method of counter-
predication and division alone. For, in that case there would be no reason to accept that Stage 3 considerations should
possess the authority to correct pre-scientific classifications. The two enterprises might simply study distinct subject
matters. By contrast, the
328 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
assumption of a common nature at Stage 2 is precisely what gives authority to the results of Stage 3 enquiry, if—as in
the case of pride—there turn out to be two or more distinct causes at work.
At Stage 2 one can establish that a kind exists by showing that it has a distinctive nature—even if one does not know in
detail what this is. To establish that something of this type has a distinctive nature, it is sufficient to establish that it is
an organized teleological structure. One may well be unaware at this point of what the basic teleological cause is.
In the biological examples, one could establish the existence of such a structure by showing that there is an animal with
an organized set of distinctive basic soul functions involving locomotion, nutrition, breathing, or reproduction. In this
way one could establish that a relevant differentia belonged to a wider genus in the way required to establish that one is
confronted with an organized structure. Counter-predication by itself may provide evidence that there is an organized
nature before one. But the presence of a common nature explains why, in some cases, there is counter-predication of
the relevant type. Thus, one knows in the case of animal species and genera that such kinds exist when one knows that
there is an appropriate type of organized nature.
Reflection on Aristotle's method in the biological works serves to illuminate some issues left unresolved and obscure in
the Analytics. It is only in these writings that he spells out what is required to establish the existence of distinct genera
and species. He is not merely following a pre-set Analytics model of scientific investigation. He is rather struggling to
make that model at once more precise and more powerful, with the assistance of additional conceptual machinery
based on the notions of common nature and soul function.541
It is clear, once Stage 2 is conceived in this way, why Aristotle should have laid out kinds and their features in the
precise way he did in the Historia Animalium as a preliminary to causal explanation (HA Α.6, 491a9–11). He needed to
set out the differences that exist between kinds and the properties that belong to each of them (491a9 f.), and then to
discover the fundamental causes of these kinds possessing these properties. The basic causes will be the essences of
the kinds themselves (at their varying levels), which explain—at Stage 3—why the kinds have the properties they do.
One cannot carry through this type of explanation without having the explananda in correct form. We need to grasp the
properties which genuinely belong to things in a successful ‘historia’ of this kind (Pr. An. Α.30, 46a24–6). We cannot do
this if we do not mark out (prior to Stage
BIOLOGY, CLASSIFICATION, AND ESSENCE 329
3) the distinct genera which possess per se attributes or the attributes which belong to such genera (PA Α.5, 645b1–3). If
we do not achieve this, we will not easily find the relevant explanatory syllogisms. Thus, it is an essential preliminary for
explanation of this type that one grasp genuine kinds and their non-accidental properties. This is what grasping the
relevant ‘the that’ consists in.542
So understood, Aristotle has two aims in this historia. To separate distinct genera and (where required) species and to
determine which properties belong per se to them. His project is not merely to list differentiae and note their co-
occurrence (as a preliminary to causal investigation). Nor is the Historia Animalium simply a collection of general
features which can be used to distinguish different types of animal.543 For, these suggestions ignore the use which
Aristotle makes of differentiae in classifying distinct genera and species of animals. One should not conclude from the
incompleteness of the taxonomy provided in the Historia that Aristotle had no interest in classifying the genera and
species to which general features belong.
Aristotle could not have limited his goal to (e.g.) collecting differentiae if his explanations were to follow the model set
out in Posterior Analytics Β.16–18.544 For, that can most easily ‘get under way’ if one has one genuine kind and one
genuine property as explananda. If there are two distinct explanations of why what is apparently one grouping has what
is apparently the same property, there must be either two genuine kinds or two distinct properties.545 At the pre-
explanatory stage (as in Post. An. Β.13–15) one's aim is to grasp the relevant unitary kinds and their genuine features.
One can sustain the belief that one has grasped a kind of the type needed in explanation (cf. Post. An. Β.17, 99b2–4) if
one has grasped one common nature. Further, without the idea of one common nature, one could indefinitely divide
kinds into further subspecies (e.g. salmon more than one foot long/less than one foot long) and offer explanations of
why the distinct pseudo-kinds had their particular properties. The constraints imposed by the theory of common nature at
Stage 2 prevent explanations of this form ‘freewheeling’ out of touch with genuine kinds.
330 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
It should be no surprise, once Stages 2 and 3 are understood in the way suggested, that Aristotle's discussion of
taxonomic issues in Historia Animalium is incomplete. It is only when the explanatory task is completed at Stage 3 that
these issues can be finally resolved. It would not have been possible for Aristotle to have produced a complete
taxonomy (even if—per impossibile—all the relevant historiai had been completed) without considering the basic
explanatory questions addressed in De Partibus and De Generatione Animalium.
The overall model of classification in the Historia Animalium retains, as has been argued, many aspects from the
Analytics. Further, the concession that kinds are demarcated by many simultaneous differentiae does not by itself
undermine the basis of the Analytics approach to the nature of differentiae or to the unity of kinds. Man may fall under a
variety of differentiae: (e.g.) two-footed, two-armed, straight-stander (PA Α.3, 644a7–11), and there still be one essence
which explains all these other features (as the causally basic differentia). Further, these will all be differentiae of the
appropriate type provided that they are explained by the relevant essence (answer to the ‘Why?’ question). In the case
of fish and birds, the genera will be marked out by a variety of features which provide the basis for further (posterior)
differentiation into species. The centre of the Analytics model is preserved provided that there is one basic teleological
causal factor of the required type. In the next Section I shall investigate the extent to which this crucial assumption is
vindicated in Aristotle's account of fish.
since fishes have a swimming nature, as is stated in the account of their essence . . . they have no separate limbs
attached to their bodies. Since they are essentially blooded animals, they have fins because they are swimmers, but
lack feet since they do not walk on land. (PA Δ.13, 695b17–23)
Other aspects of the life of fish are explained in terms of their distinctive nature as swimmers, living in water and not
on land.547 This is why they have gills and not lungs to cool their internal heat (PA Δ.13, 696a34 ff.; cf. De Resp. 10,
476a12–15); for, gills allow them to admit water for these purposes. Similarly, they have fluid eyes in order to see long
distances under water and to counteract the adverse effects of water on their visual capacities (PA Β.13, 658a4–7).
Since their habitat contains fewer objects to strike against, they lack eyelids (658a7–10). Further, because they live in
water, they need to eat quickly with little mastication to prevent ingesting too much water with their food (PA Β.17,
660b11 ff., Γ.14, 675a6 ff.), and so have small tongues and sharp teeth.
These remarks follow the pattern set out in some of Aristotle's (occasional) general comments about the internal and
external parts of animals. He writes:
Just as each animal is equipped with those external parts which are necessary for its manner of life (bios) and its
movements (kinesis), so it is with their internal parts. (PA Γ.4, 665b2–5)
The distinctive parts of fish should be just the ones required for its distinctive manner of life and movement as a
swimmer in water. Elsewhere Aristotle writes, in an apparently similar vein, that:
It is clear that the body as a whole must exist for the sake of some complex action. (PA Α.5, 645b16 f.)
If the relevant action is swimming in water, this should explain, as in the passages cited, why the external and internal
parts are as they are. Further, Aristotle seeks to explain why fish as a genus perceive, eat, and breathe as they do in
terms of their pattern of movement in water. Here, too, he follows the model set out as the ideal in De Partibus
Animalium Α.1, 640a33–5.
The best way of putting the matter would be to say that because the essence of man is what it is, therefore a man
has these parts; for, he could not exist as a man without them.
The essence is given by reference to the creature's soul, which constitutes its form (PA Α.1, 641a18–20). In the case of
animals, the relevant parts of the soul will be determined by their capacities for movement, perception,
332 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
and digestion or nourishment (641b5–8). In the case of fish, it seems that the essence is constituted by its ability to
swim in water, and this explains why the other parts of its soul and its body are as they are. One teleologically basic
feature appears to be determinative of the other distinctive necessary properties of fish.
Fish form a genus, with a distinctive set of properties, intermediate between properties common to all animals and
those limited to given species of fish (PA Α.5, 645b22–4). Aristotle attempts to specify what is common to a wide range
of animals, and then to note the relevant variations. In the latter cases, he notes (Β.2, 648a14–16):
It should be supposed that the variations in parts either are to be referred to the functions of each of the relevant
creatures or their essence or bring some advantage or disadvantage.548
Thus, in considering bones (PA Β.9), he claims that they are similar in all viviparous animals, although bigger and
harder in animals which, like the lion, are more violent in their lifestyle (655a10–12). Birds have bones, but they are
weaker than the bones of vivipara (655a17–19), presumably to allow them to fly more successfully (cf. PA Β.16,
659b8–12, Δ.12, 694a10–12). Here, Aristotle points to features which explain the relevant variations distinctive of the
genus or species in question. This pattern of explanation is standard throughout De Partibus Animalium Β, Γ, and.
Aristotle specifies general types of flesh, eyes, hair, tongues, teeth, mouths, horns, hearts, lungs, stomachs etc., notes
which types of animals (e.g. all land creatures, blooded animals, vivipara, viviparous quadrupeds, etc.) possess them
and then points out variations which he seeks on occasion to explain. Thus, selachia differ from other fish in having
spines made of cartilage (655a23 f.), partly in order that they can move in a more supple way, and partly because ‘all the
available earthy material has been used to construct their skin’ (655a25–8). While the variations may be specific to one
kind of animal (e.g. the elephant (Β.16, 658b33 ff.)), or shared by a genus of animals (fish (Β.13, 658a4 f.)), Aristotle
seeks to explain their presence by reference back to the distinctive nature of the animals involved.
Aristotle's method of analysis suggests that the basic features of distinct genera and species are those aspects of the
movement and lifestyle which explain why kinds possess their other distinguishing relevant properties. The distinctive
aspect of the fish is their ability to swim in given ways, and this is used to explain why they possess gills, fins, fluid eyes,
small tongues, and sharp teeth. They fall within the wider grouping of blooded animals (PA Δ.13, 695b20 ff.), but the
wider grouping is not itself a genus (presumably) because the varieties of blooded animal are too diverse, lacking one
uniform type of life and movement (HA Α.6, 490b16 ff.). Being blooded sets
BIOLOGY, CLASSIFICATION, AND ESSENCE 333
limits on what type of further physical features fish possess (‘if they have four fins, they cannot have legs’ (PA Δ.13,
695b21 ff.)), but does not explain why they have fins rather than legs. The specific explanation of why fish have (e.g.) no
separate limbs attached to their bodies (i.e. no legs) depends on their distinctive movement and lifestyle. Being blooded
may be part of the nature of fish because it sets constraints on the bodies fish will have. But it need not be part of the
essential nature of fish (as given in their definition) because it does not explain the presence of the specific qualities
which fish possess.
In these ways, Aristotle follows the pattern of explanation set out in the Analytics, and further modified (in the case of
substance) in the Metaphysics.
are viviparous (such as selachia GA Β.1, 732b22), while others are oviparous (732b22–4). Similarly, he finds (among
footed animals) that not all quadrupeds are viviparous (or oviparous (732b16–19)). His conclusion is that we cannot
correctly divide the relevant types of reproduction on the basis of differing means of locomotion (732b24–6), since the
cause of the former lies in differing degrees of internal heat and fluidity (732b31 f.). Thus, selachia are more fluid in
their internal composition than other fish which are hot and solid (733a8–10), and this explains why the former are
internally viviparous and the others are not. The relevant differentiae are related to the heat and fluidity of their bodies,
and not to their differing patterns of swimming (cf. GA Γ.3, 754a23 ff.). The differing means of reproduction ‘criss-
cross’ over and within the animal genera marked out on grounds of locomotion (and other soul functions), and cannot
be explained in terms of them.
Aristotle's problem is that his teleological and causal explanations do not have as a common starting point one basic
feature (as they should according to the Analytics account). Some begin with claims about animals' bodily properties or
the environments in which they live. But these are not referred back to the essential unifying feature of one type of
swimming. Not all explanations begin with the essence of the fish.
Aristotle had prepared the way for some deviations from his favoured Analytics model in De Partibus Animalium Α.
Thus, in Α.1, 640a34–6, he had noted that if we cannot explain certain properties in terms of the essence alone, then:
the nearest must be done: viz. that there cannot be a man at all otherwise than with them, or that it is well that man
should have them. (640a35–b1)
Further, he had remarked that actions and organs may be present because they are necessitated by the presence of
others, without one set being prior to the other (PA Α.5, 645b33–4). However, these concessions do not fully capture
the extent to which he has deviated from the Analytics paradigm. Fish (of certain types) are oviparous and lack
adequate means of reducing food simply because this is how their bodily nature is composed. The relevant starting
point for this explanation is a given fact about their bodily composition, not a set of related soul functions. Similarly, in
discussing reproduction, variation between animals is explained in terms of their differing degrees of heat and fluidity,
and not their distinctive types of locomotion, breathing, or digestion. Aristotle does not attempt to show that it is
necessary (or good) that fish have these bodily properties in order to survive. Rather, he takes as basic the presence of
such bodily features, and explains why fish—given that they possess these features—necessarily have others as well.
BIOLOGY, CLASSIFICATION, AND ESSENCE 335
moving in way A, reproducing in way B, having a digestive system of type C, and having heat of type D
into a genuine unity? What distinguishes this group from (e.g.):
musical, grammarian?
In the Analytics, this question was answered by finding one feature which explained why (e.g.) fish moved in way A,
reproduced in way B, breathed in way C.549 Indeed, this was what secured the unity of the kind in question. The
difficulty is to see how this solution can work for the common nature of fish, as this is understood in the biological
writings.
336 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
These problems are not confined to the study of fish. Aristotle, in discussing why elephants possess long trunks (PA
Β.16, 658b33 ff.), takes as basic their great size. While he notes elsewhere that this is a source of protection (PA Γ.2,
663a5–7), he makes no attempt to show that it is best, or even good, that they have precisely the size they do. Rather,
their specific size is taken as a basic datum in the relevant explanation.550 Similarly, in large animals the presence of
surplus earthy matter is taken for granted, while Aristotle comments that nature makes use of this surplus for further
purposes of its own (PA Γ.2, 663b31 ff.). ‘Material nature’ plays a role as a starting point in these explanations. (See, for
the phrase ‘material nature’, PA Γ.1, 640b28 f.)551
Did Aristotle, in his biological writings, fail to find a way of satisfying his own Analytics requirements for the unity of
the relevant kinds? Fish turned out not to have the simple, unifying, essences which his theory predicted that they must
have. They appear to lack the one teleological cause which explains their heat, faulty digestive system, and mode of
movement. In place of one unified cause, we find a series of distinct and apparently unrelated causes serving as the
starting points for different explanations.
This problem goes deep. If there is no one basic teleological cause of the required type, how can Aristotle mark out the
kind's essence? In the Analytics we uncovered the essence by finding a basic cause of the relevant type. Essence and
causation fitted together, precisely because there was one unifying cause of the appropriate type. Without it, Aristotle
could not use his favoured mode of answer to the definitional ‘What is F?’ question.
Aristotle's problem is not confined to issues of definition. The absence of an appropriate answer to the ‘Why?’
question threatens to undermine his approach to classification. The presence of a unified essence was required (in the
Analytics) to ground the claim of certain features to be differentiae.552 His system of classification will be undermined if
there is no one unifying cause of the appropriate type.
There is, it appears, a crisis in Aristotle's project. In biology, his favoured area of investigation, he failed to find the one,
unitary, causal feature whose (postulated) existence provides the basis of his account of definition in the Analytics and
the Metaphysics. Are we, at this point, witnesses to the collapse of a brilliant research programme?
Aristotle's difficulties stem from his commitment to three assumptions:
BIOLOGY, CLASSIFICATION, AND ESSENCE 337
(Assn A) The unity of a kind is determined fundamentally by the presence of a unifying feature, prior to all else,
which is explanatorily basic (as indicated in Chapters 8–11).
(Assn B) The favoured mode of explanation for natural biological kinds is teleological (as indicated in Chapter 11),
and the form is the teleologically basic explanatory feature.
(Assn C) The answers to the ‘What is F?’ and the ‘Why is F as it is?’ questions are the same (in the ways indicated in
Chapters 8–10).
He cannot, having made (Assn C) countenance mysterious simple entities (e.g. an unanalysable soul of the fish) as the
basis for his answer to definitional questions. Essences have to be features capable of fitting into a causal story of the
appropriate type.553
Aristotle, on the basis of these three assumptions, must have believed that (in the case of fish) there would turn out to
be a basic teleological feature which (i) explains the presence and character of the remainder of their other genuine
properties, and (ii) defines what it is to be a fish. But real life failed to live up to his philosophical expectations. Aristotle
could, of course, have regarded his investigations of fish as incomplete, and held on to the possibility of discovering
the vital unifying feature. But at times (as in GA Β.1, 732b28 ff.) he appears confident that the explanations he invokes
in terms of heat and bodily composition are genuine and that they cut across his favoured soul-function style of
demarcation (in terms of locomotion or breathing, etc.). If so, at this point he seems to surrender the idea that there is,
in this case, the type of unitary essence which his metaphysical and scientific picture requires.
Is this difficulty one which damages Aristotle's whole account of natural kinds and their essences? Or can it be isolated,
or rendered innocuous, in some way? Perhaps in the biological works he followed a radically different approach from
the one developed in the Analytics or the Metaphysics? The problem, however, cannot be evaded merely by saying that
biology is one thing, metaphysics another. For, the present dislocation threatens to undermine the connection between
Aristotle's model of science in the Analytics and his favoured example of an explanatory science: biology. Further, if his
metaphysical picture requires a basis for the unity of kinds inconsistent with the findings of his biological science,
surely he must reject (or limit) that picture itself?
In the next Sections I shall consider several responses to this difficulty, based on readings of parts of the biological
works, and assess the modifications they require in Aristotle's account of essence (as we have understood it).
338 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
766b13 ff., 3, 767b11–24.) In such cases, the presence of the matter would explain why not everything goes as it should.
The matter would interact with the form in irregular and unpredictable ways in such a case. There are, thus, several
ways in which matter could act as an explanatory starting point consistent with the form playing the role required of it
in the conservative account.
This general approach would, no doubt, have been attractive to Aristotle. However, it is clear that it involves a major
departure from the Analytics paradigm. For, what is at stake in the biological examples is the survival of the fish as the
fish. There may well be modes of survival which might be enjoyed, if the internal natures of fish were somewhat
adjusted, involving different, or additional, modes of breathing, reproducing, etc. But these would not all be modes of
survival of the fish, since some of the changes would be too radical for their continuing as fish. That genus would have
ceased to exist, and another have taken its place. Equally, man, if made more godlike, might enjoy a different form of
flourishing. But this would not be human well-being, since the creatures involved would no longer have the relevant
human capacities, and would have ceased to be the complex unity of nous and emotions which makes up human
nature (NE Κ.8, 1178a19–21). What, then, are the limits of well-being for humans or survival for fish?
There is a dilemma. Either survival for the fish requires (in the first instance) the survival of all of its present existing
soul functions or it requires the survival of only some of them. The first alternative takes as basic and prior the
continued existence of the genus (the fish) and not its form. Thus, its central notion (the survival of the genus as fish)
is far removed from the independent unifying essence which serves as the starting point in the Metaphysics or Analytics.
For, that was prior to all else (such as the composite), and not derivative from it. However, if the second alternative is
preferred, one needs to determine which features are required for the fish to survive. What is needed is a further
unifying concept which can determine what is required for survival as a fish. More generally, one would need the
resources to mark out an ecology of natural groupings of soul functions, differentiated without any reference to the
composite organisms they enform. But the expectation is disappointed. Aristotle fails to provide the basis for, or even
the merest sketch of, this type of account. Indeed, at crucial places in his story, it is the common nature of the whole
organism (and not features of its form alone) that provides the starting point of his account.
But did Aristotle, nonetheless, attempt the conservative route? There are reasons for thinking that he did not. Had he
done so, he should have made great efforts to isolate the contribution of the form, emphasizing that while it is essential
that fish reproduce in some way, it is not essential that they reproduce in the specific way they do. (Any mode would be
good
340 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
enough provided that it resulted in the relevant form being transferred.) However, there is no evidence of his drawing
the crucial distinction between fish reproducing in some way and reproducing in the precise way they do. Further, had
he followed the conservative strategy, he should have distinguished most carefully between the differing roles played by
factors cited in teleological and in material explanation. But Aristotle does not do this. Thus, for example, in discussing
the gills of fish, he first invokes degree of heat to explain the strength of their movement, and then uses the latter to
explain why some fish have numerous rather than few gills (PA Δ.13, 696b18–21). Similarly, in the case of the elephant,
its mega-size and exceptional capacities are both invoked in (apparently) the same way in the explanation of why it has
a trunk (Β.16, 658b34, see 659a7 f.). Degrees of heat are taken as explanatory givens on the same level as soul functions,
pattern of movement, or being a land animal.
Aristotle, it appears, did not take even the first steps along the conservative road. If he saw the difficulty, he did not
tackle it by tinkering with the details of the Analytics account. If he had a solution, it must have been a more radical one.
An alternative suggestion runs as follows: perhaps Aristotle maintained assumptions (A) and (C) but rejected (B), and
took the material base (and not formal features such as pertain to soul function) as essential and explanatorily prior.555
However, this strategy, even if it could provide a satisfactory resolution to the issues of unity, runs strongly contrary to
Aristotle's insistence in De Partibus Animalium Α.1 and 5 that the soul is prior to matter in biological explanation
(640b25 ff., 641a28 ff., 645b30 ff.). Nor can it do justice to the central role given to teleological explanation in his
biological writings (e.g. 640a3 ff., 642a14 ff.).
But perhaps Aristotle should have taken this route. Was his mistake to look for the explanatorily basic feature in the
wrong place? Perhaps he should have replaced his teleologically based account with a material account, phrased (as
today) in terms of genetic code, DNA structure, or capacity for interbreeding. Surely one of these would have enabled
him to find the simple unifying feature demanded by the Analytics model? His mistake (as we can see with the benefit
of hindsight) was not to have looked in the right place for the basic unifying feature his favoured model of definition
required.
There are, however, reasons to doubt whether Aristotle's favoured model, even thus modified, can apply to biological
taxa. Interbreeding occurs between distinct species, particularly among plants, fish, and amphibians. Hybridization is a
common feature of the animal and plant kingdoms. Man naturally produces man (as Aristotle emphasized (Phys. Β.3,
194 b29–32). But there is, it appears, as much intra-species genetic as morphological variation. Indeed, possession of
genetic variety enables a species to survive in changing environmental circumstance. Thus, there may be considerable
variation within species in ‘genetic code’, with differing gene combinations yielding the same phenotype.556 There is as
much similarity between the DNA of some dogs and that of wolves or cats, as between the DNA of two different
types of dog.557 There is reason to doubt that the genetic code will provide the simple unifying feature required for
Aristotelian definition.
Did Aristotle opt for an even more radical alternative? Did he reject all of Assumptions (A), (B), and (C) and take as
basic the idea of a common nature shared by all fish, consisting solely in the way they move, reproduce, breathe, and in
their possession of certain morphological and material features. If so, the notion of a common nature will be the result
of reflection based on examples of particular kinds of animals which are seen to form a natural grouping. But there will
be no need to establish the existence of
342 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
a unifying common cause to underwrite the unity of the kind. The authority for determining that there is a genuine
kind will rest not with explanation or scientific method, but with common-sense observation and classification. The
source of the relevant authority will be popularly held, well-entrenched views (endoxa) about kinds.
If Aristotle were to have adopted this most radical alternative, he could have said (in the Analytics) that:
biped animal
is a clear case of a common nature, while:
musical grammarian
is not, without defending the first claim by finding a basic feature which explains why being biped belongs to animal.
That is, he could have taken at face value our intuitions about common natures without requiring that they be
legitimized by scientific practice. If so, the locus of authority would lie with common beliefs rather than with scientific
knowledge. Had he accepted this strategy in biology, he would have departed from, indeed rejected, his Analytics model
of explanation and definition.
There is good reason to believe that Aristotle did not proceed in this way. In his discussion of ‘the great genera’ in De
Partibus Animalium Α.4 he reconciles himself to standard beliefs provided that they are correct. Since in De Partibus
Animalium Α Aristotle emphasizes the importance of scientific reasoning, causality, demonstration, and form (e.g. Α.1,
640a1–6, 34 ff., 642a14 ff.), he appears to take as correct only those popular claims which are underwritten (in some
way) by his scientific or metaphysical theory. Nor does he think that common opinion has achieved the proper method
for analysing the relevant natural phenomena (Α.1, 639b7–10). There are, in Aristotle's view, additional constraints
introduced by the more rigorous and accurate study of nature itself, which can override popular opinion in certain
areas.558
This dilemma has deepened. The authority for kind determination cannot rest solely with popular opinion. It can and
should be corrected (according to Aristotle) by scientific method and informed discovery. But, in the case of biological
kinds, those methods failed to uncover the unified essences which should (according to the Analytics model) determine
the nature of the relevant kinds. Worse still, as indicated above, they give reason to believe that no such unifying
essence is to be found. Although biological species are central cases of natural kinds, they appear to lack the non-
complex feature which Aristotle took elsewhere as the source of unity of genuine kinds. Was he mistaken to attempt to
assimilate biological
BIOLOGY, CLASSIFICATION, AND ESSENCE 343
species to his favoured model for natural kinds, the one which applies to the eclipse, to water, and to gold?
cause would constitute some aspect of the essence (in line with Assumption (C)), even though it is not the starting
point for all explanations of necessary features of the kind. Other features (such as concern material composition or
environment) would provide starting points for other important explanations, provided that they fitted together with
the teleological cause in ‘one common nature’. Thus, there would be a variety of connections between soul function
and matter, some beginning with the former, others the latter, provided that they were all parts of one common nature.
Did Aristotle pursue this approach? If he did, how did he articulate the idea of ‘fitting together’ in one common
nature? In his discussion of fish, he explains the presence of fins and absence of legs on the basis partly of their nature
as swimmers, partly of their being blooded (PA Δ.13, 695b17–23). Fish have fins because they are swimmers. Given
that they are also blooded, they lack legs. Hence, the resulting features of fish are the outcome of a number of
interlocking causal features. The fish, as a swimmer, needs to carry out certain activities. Given the matter it possesses,
it can only perform these activities if it has certain bodily features and not others. While the relevant matter could have
been used for several different purposes, in the fish it is used for certain specific purposes and not others. In this case,
both material and formal natures are constrained by each other. Here, they ‘fit together’ in so far as their mutual
interaction determines parts of the nature of the relevant kind.
Nor is this structure confined to fish and their fins. Aristotle remarks, in discussing the elephant, that its front feet are
used exclusively to support its immense weight, while in other lighter four-footed animals front feet are used in place
of hands to grasp objects (PA Γ.3, 659a23–5). Given this use of its front feet, and its need to reach air quickly, the
elephant must have a trunk of a given type: one which can be used for breathing and for grasping. Here, several
individual features (weight, need to grasp, need to breathe under water) combine to determine one outcome. As was
noted, certain aspects of the matter are taken as basic (e.g. weight (659a7)). Nature, in effect, does the best it can with
the material at its disposal (IA 704b15–16). But the matter, so used, plays a role (together with the formal nature) in
explaining certain distinctive features of the kind's nature.
This form of analysis is relevant to the other problematic cases raised above. The material nature can (together with
the formal nature) explain why fish have eggs which are white and small, or why they eat in a gluttonous way. Both
material and formal features interact to produce the distinctive outcome. Thus, fish need to reproduce, but the way in
which they do so is the product of their distinctive matter. In this way, their formal nature combines with their degree
of heat to produce the distinctive nature of their progeny. Similarly, fish need to eat, but the way they do so is the
BIOLOGY, CLASSIFICATION, AND ESSENCE 345
product of their distinctive physical constitution. Here, too, formal and material natures interact to produce the
relevant outcome.
In this account, the unity of a kind will consist (partly) in the interaction of its explanatory features (whether formal or
material) to determine some of its derived features. The notion of one common nature will not be grounded in the
unifocal pattern, favoured in the Analytics, but instead in the interaction of several separate causal factors. The resulting
unity might be termed an interactive unity, because it rests on the distinctive interconnection of several causal features,
and not on the presence of one common cause or starting point.
Biological natures, so understood, will not conform to the Analytics ideal, but neither will they be the result solely of
common sense reflection. When all goes well, Stage 2 claims to detect natural groupings will be vindicated by the
discovery of interlocking connections of the type indicated. As in the Analytics, the relevant unity will be underwritten
by some explanatory structure. On occasion we may discover that we have mistakenly lumped together as one two
kinds, with distinctive formal or material natures. Thus, although Aristotle relaxes his Analytics account of unity, he is
not driven to accept any of the radical solutions canvassed in the previous Section.
However, this said, Aristotle must, nonetheless, be prepared (on this account) to take as an explanatory starting point a
given material nature, whose presence in an organism is not further explained. As a consequence, he must accept that
there is no one starting point which is (i) explanatorily prior to all else in the way the Analytics model suggested, and (ii)
the ground of the kind's unity. The nature and unity of biological kinds will no longer be made perspicuous through
and on the basis of one explanatorily basic feature. Nor can Aristotle simply take such a feature as the basic essence of
the kind.
How significant are these departures from the Analytics model? Aristotle, as we saw above, envisages biological
investigation as starting from a differentiation of animal kinds into a variety of common natures (Section 12.5). The
biologist will seek for the interacting formal and material natures which produce these kinds' distinctive features. The
relevant material base (in successful cases) will play a role in underwriting the groupings with which we begin. In effect,
the biologist is seeking to vindicate (or undermine) the types of common nature we mark out on the basis of our
observation and practice as farmers, breeders, etc. He is not attempting here to explain de novo why a given type of
matter is present in this type of animal.
These differences are major ones. Biological investigation is anchored in our practices and intuitions about what is to
count as a common nature. The type of unity sought will be one which underwrites in some explanatory way (at least
some of) our ordinary classifications. For this reason,
346 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
biological taxa cannot be fully assimilated to the theoretical paradigm defined in the Analytics. Indeed, it should be no
surprise, since our biological terms were not introduced in a way governed solely by that ideal.560 In the biological case,
progressive understanding of the idea of a common nature generates the type of interactive unities sketched above. It
will not lead to kinds unified in the style of the Analytics, unless there happen to be such kinds which underwrite our
everyday biological classifications into (e.g.) dogs and horses.561
Notwithstanding these differences, Aristotle's understanding of biological kinds still reflects certain features of his
Analytics account. He can continue to distinguish between explanatorily basic and derived, necessary, features of the
kind. Further, he can still treat some explanatorily basic features as essential, provided that they fit into a genus-wide
system of explanatorily relevant features.562 There may indeed be cases where (in the absence of one basic explanatory
feature) it is not determinate whether (e.g.) mode of breathing or reproduction is essential or merely necessary. But,
nonetheless, the explanatory structure of biological kinds approximates (in certain respects) to the Analytics paradigm.
For, a set of relevant starting points, individually and jointly, still determines the kind's other necessary features.
12.11 Conclusion
In the previous Section, I sketched one way in which Aristotle's Analytics model could have been modified to
accommodate his recalcitrant biological discoveries. Further, I noted some (far from conclusive) evidence of the
presence of an approach of this type in Aristotle's biological writings. It would be worthwhile to investigate this issue
further, but
BIOLOGY, CLASSIFICATION, AND ESSENCE 347
that major undertaking lies outside the scope of the present project.563 However, for present purposes, there is a prior
and more general question which needs to be addressed. If anything of the type suggested is (even approximately)
correct, how (if at all) was Aristotle justified in surrendering, in his biological writings, some central parts of his
Analytics account of the unity of kinds? What entitled him to offer respectively interactive and unifocal accounts of the
unity of biological kinds and meteorological kinds?
Aristotle's silence on these issues is unnerving. Did he remain quietly (or perhaps grimly) optimistic that some future
science would eventually succeed (where his had failed) in discovering Analytics-style unifying essences? Or was he
transfixed by the problem, accepting that his theory had fragmented, with different types of definition for different
types of kind? Did he think that he had an adequate theoretical justification for some departure from his Analytics
paradigm? Or was it simply that (some-what pragmatically) he followed the Analytics model when he could and settled
for a modified approach when he could not?
In the final Chapter, I shall consider these issues further. While some aspects of Aristotle's theory of essence and
natural kinds are unaffected by these difficulties, others remain on the danger list. The crisis has not yet passed.564
13 Aristotle's Essentialism
13.1 Language, Thought, and Essence
There is one claim on which Aristotle and my modern essentialist (as introduced in 1.2) agree:
(A) The world falls into natural kinds with their own essential properties.
However, they differ in their understanding of (A) and in the grounds they offer for its truth.
For my modern essentialist, (A) is underwritten by our practice as ordinary (non-scientific) thinkers of individuating
kinds of objects in terms of their explanatorily basic features. The source of claims about essential features lies in our
pre-scientific conventions and intentions. His claim could be expressed as follows:
(B) It is because we (as pre-scientific thinkers) have such conventions that we treat certain features of kinds as
essential.
My modern essentialist is a conventionalist. But his position is a species of a wider genus, whose defining claim may be
presented as:
(C) It is because we (as pre-scientific thinkers) think as we do that we divide the world into natural kinds with their
own non-accidental features.
(C) does not make it a matter of convention that we think as we do. Perhaps we could do no other. But common to (B)
and (C) is the claim that the world (as we find it) is as it is (in some crucial respects) fundamentally because of the way
we think.565
Aristotle, as I argued in Chapters 2–6, does not attribute to ordinary thinkers intentions or beliefs of the required depth
to sustain either (B) or (C). In his view, ordinary thinkers can grasp terms for natural kinds without thinking of those
kinds as possessing a fundamental and determining feature of the relevant type. In particular, the master craftsman can
grasp a genuine kind term while lacking the idea of its possessing this type of hidden, basic, scientific structure
(Chapter 6). While the idea of such a
ARISTOTLE'S ESSENTIALISM 349
structure may emerge later in our practices, it is not (in Aristotle's view) a requirement for understanding a natural-kind
term.
Aristotle's reasons for rejecting (B) and (C) carry a further consequence. If the ordinary thinker can grasp natural-kind
terms without thinking of them as possessed of a determining scientific feature, the latter idea cannot be one which we
need for our basic understanding of the world. In particular, it cannot be a principle of the type which simultaneously
defines what it is to be a thinker and the world of which we think. Thus, Aristotle rejects what I termed in Chapter 1
the democratic version of Kantianism. For, according to that view, it makes no sense to ask whether principles such as
these come from us or from the world. We cannot sustain the idea of separate contributions made respectively by us
and the world.
In Aristotle's view (as I interpret him), the source for claims about natural kinds and their essences does not lie (in any
of these ways) in our thoughts as ordinary thinkers. If such claims are to be vindicated, they will be sustained from
resources in metaphysics rather than the theory of thought or language. In his account, the burden of proof is carried
by the metaphysician and not by the intuitions of the ordinary thinker. The question is: How is this to be done?
assumption that our own thinking contains within itself (independently of how the world is) the determinate intuitions
about definition which the conventionalist requires. The very notions which are essential to definition (such as unity
and priority) cannot be made determinate without dependence on the world and its causal structures. Further, in
accepting (H), Aristotle rejects the view that the world's intelligible patterns are there to be grasped by anyone
irrespective of their definitional and explanatory practices. The type of intelligibility we find in the world cannot be
grasped by those who lack our definitional and explanatory practices.566 In this way, Aristotle escapes the fatal
oscillation between Platonism and conventionalism described in Chapter 1 (Sections 1.3 and 1.4).
These points can be placed in a wider philosophical perspective, which allows us to grasp more securely the questions
at issue. Platonism (as I characterize it) is committed to three claims:
(i) The world exists independently of us, complete with its own kinds and essences.
(ii) The world, its kinds, and its essences are visible to any proper thinker whatever their definitional or
explanatory practices may be.
(iii) Our grasp on the relevant type of essences cannot depend essentially on our having certain definitional and
explanatory practices.
For the Platonist, we grasp the relevant type of kinds and essences by seeing them in nature. What makes certain
features essential is independent of our definitional practices, and a proper understanding of what it is to be essential
should register this fact. Reality and essence are mind-independent in two distinct ways: (1) their existence is not
dependent on the existence of any mind, and (2) their nature can be grasped by any mind whatsoever, no matter what
its definitional or explanatory practices may be.
Aristotle (as is argued in Chapters 7–12) is not a Platonist (so understood). He rejects the second and third aspects of
the Platonist account by denying that the type of intelligibility uncovered in constitutive explanation can be understood
from a perspective innocent of the relevant definitional and explanatory concerns. The type of intelligibility we
discover in nature cannot be grasped without reliance on practices of definition and explanation such as ours. But,
nonetheless, the patterns we uncover in essentialist explanation are there to be discovered. In effect, Aristotle rejects
the Platonist claims (ii) and (iii) above, while holding on to the basic realism embedded in claim (i).567 In his view, there
are essences whose
ARISTOTLE'S ESSENTIALISM 351
existence does not in any way depend on our explanatory/definitional practices, even though we cannot grasp them
independently of those practices.568
If Aristotle rejects Platonism, he is not thereby driven to accept the standard conventionalist alternative. According to
the latter, the type of intelligibility registered in essentialist claims is introduced by us and is grounded in our practices
of explanation and definition. The conventionalist rejects each of the Platonist claims. He will maintain:
(i*) It is not the case that the world's intelligible structure exists independently of us and our own system of
definition and explanation.
and
(iii*) The intelligibility we detect in the world is a reflection of our own definitional and explanatory practices.
Simply put, if there are essences in nature, it is we who made certain features essential.
Aristotle denies the third conventionalist claim. As we noted in Chapter 10, the theory of definition (in the Analytics)
cannot be completed without reference to how the world is, with its necessitating patterns of causation. The relevant
form of intelligibility is not merely a projection from us on to an intrinsically unintelligible world. For, we cannot fully
specify the type of intelligibility we seek without reference to the necessitating patterns that are to be found in the
world. In Aristotle's view, the world's intelligible causal structure is something that exists independently of us and our
system of explanation. Thus, while he rejects the Platonist claims (ii) and (iii), he does not do so at the cost of slipping
into the standard conventionalist alternative. It is a strength of his position that he combines acceptance of the first,
and most important, Platonist claim with a rejection (shared by the conventionalist) of the remaining two Platonist
contentions. As elsewhere, he seeks to ‘unpick’ and retain the best elements from strongly opposed theories.
Aristotle's commitment to (F) and (G) also serves to distance his view from the form of Kantianism sketched in
Chapter 1. According to my élitist Kantian, it makes no sense to ask what contribution comes from us and which from
the world. Aristotle, by contrast, seeks to answer this question by saying that both we and the world make separable
but incomplete contributions to the full account of good definition. Since it makes sense to
352 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
distinguish these components, his view cannot be assimilated to that of the Kantian.569
These points can be made diagrammatically. Both conventionalism and Platonism are bipolar alternatives, made up of
two distinct and complete ingredients:
(1) our thoughts □:□ the world
In conventionalism, we do the work in constructing a model of intelligibility which we then project on to the world. In
Platonism, the world does all the work, offering to us its own type of intelligibility, complete and perfect in itself. We
make no contribution but that of registering what there is. For that reason, the world's intelligible patterns can be
grasped by any thinker whatsoever (provided that they have the resources to see what there is). There is no need of any
particular definitional or explanatory practices to see what reality contains.
By contrast, Kantianism (as I have characterized it) is unipolar. There is no coherent question to ask about whether the
relevant form of intelligibility flows from us or from the world. For, there is no way (in principle) of distinguishing
between the world as we think of it and the thoughts we have about it. They are not merely governed by the same
constraints, but are (strictly speaking) identical. In a diagram, this view might be expressed by one shape (and one of
beguiling simplicity!):
(2) □: our thoughts of the world = the world we think about
Aristotle seems to accept neither bipolar nor unipolar model. He does not think that either we or the world
individually construct the type of intelligibility we seek. For, although his account of definition begins with our
practices it cannot be completed without reference to the causal structures we find in reality. Nor would the latter be
fully intelligible to any who lack the relevant definitional and explanatory practices. It is not that there is no coherent
question to be asked concerning the origin of the relevant type of intelligibility. Rather, it is the product of two
separable but incomplete contributions made by us and the world (and its causal structures). There are two elements in
a harmonious whole:
(3) our thoughts
the world
Thus, Aristotle's viewpoint cannot be assimilated to any of the standard options set out in Chapter 1. He is neither a
modern essentialist, nor a Platonist, nor a projectivist, nor a Kantian.
There are two further claims which are needed to complete Aristotle's account of essence and definition:
ARISTOTLE'S ESSENTIALISM 353
(I) Essential features form the natures of kinds, and as such are distinct from merely necessary properties which
belong to those kinds because they flow from their essences.
The essential features are those which meet the definitional constraints: the basic essence is a unity, the causal source of
those necessary features which differentiate it from other kinds (in the favoured definitional way). Features will be
merely necessary if (i) their presence is derived from the relevant causal source but (ii) they do not differentiate the kind
in the favoured definitional style.
To (I) should be added one further claim:
(J) There are some genuine biological natural kinds.
(A) and (D)–(J) constitute the central planks of Aristotle's essentialism. We have seen them at work offering distinctive
answers to the two questions raised at the beginning of our investigation:
(1) What makes statements of the form: ‘Man is essentially rational’, true?
and
(2) How can we come to know that such statements are true?570
Claims about essences are not to be understood in any of the Platonist, conventionalist, or Kantian ways described
above. Thus, Aristotle's attempt to answer the metaphysical question (1) cannot be assimilated to any of the three
options discussed in Chapter 1.571 Nor, in his view, do we come to discover such essences by following a method which
is either wholly a priori or wholly a posteriori. Rather, the type of essence-involving explanation (as described in
Chapters 8 ff.) involves both a priori (such as may concern the general notion of definition) and a posteriori elements
(the latter drawn from an understanding of causation in this world). Neither element can be made fully determinate
without the assistance of the other.572 Here, too, Aristotle's viewpoint differs from the three options set out in Chapter
1.
Are Aristotle's views defensible? They seem to be coherent, but do they
354 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
withstand rational criticism? Are they properly motivated? Is there something they fail to capture?
this is the doctrine that some attributes of a thing (quite independently of the language in which the thing is referred
to, if at all) may be essential to the thing, and others accidental.574
Quine takes commitment to ‘Aristotelian essentialism’ to be a bad thing. There is good reason to reject any view which
makes this commitment. But why? What is so bad about Aristotelian essentialism? Do Quine's criticisms engage with
Aristotle's actual views about the essences of kinds?
Quine sometimes complains that Aristotelian essentialism involves a form of ‘favouritism’ towards certain traits of the
individual, an attitude Quine permits himself to describe as ‘invidious’.575 For, the Aristotelian is committed to taking
some descriptions as ‘somehow better revealing the “essence” of the object’. But why is this form of ‘favouritism’ a
mistake? Aristotle has given a number of arguments in favour of treating some features as essential and others as
accidental, based on his commitment to claims (D) and (E) above. Indeed, he attempts to show that ‘favouritism’ of
this type is not merely justified, but is in fact required if we are to make sense of our talk of definition and of kinds.
If ‘favouritism’ need not be a vice, why is Aristotelian essentialism (by Quine's lights) ‘invidious’? Quine speaks,
somewhat gloomily, of the ‘meta-physical jungle’ of Aristotelian essentialism,576 and indicates his wish to be rid of it.
However, although Aristotle's views on essence may seem
ARISTOTLE'S ESSENTIALISM 355
complex, they are far from confused. So, why call for the logging companies? Why cut down this intriguing and
beautiful piece of ancient woodland? Is Quine an ‘ecological vandal’?
Quine offers two reasons. One takes as its starting point the rich and elusive ontology of possible worlds, deployed in
modern discussions, to capture notions of essence. Here, we find talk of world-bound individuals, world-bound
properties, and of individuals existing in different possible worlds. Quine, plausibly enough, finds these notions
obscure and perplexing. However, none of them is required to underwrite Aristotle's actual talk of essence. He needs
to advert only to the individuals, kinds, features, and properties (and their combinations) which make up this world.
What Aristotle insists on is attention to the varying ways in which these features are attached to objects and kinds (as
suggested by the copula-modifier view set out in Appendix 2). Thus, Aristotle can agree with Quine that all of reality is
exhausted by the actual world with its objects and features, but not accept his further claim that all true/false
statements are about what is actually-instantiated in this world. For, there will also be true claims about what is
naturewise-instantiated (and what is possibly-instantiated) by the relevant objects. Aristotle's proposal, as it stands,
allows us to talk of essence and possibility without becoming entrapped in the elusive possible-worlds machinery of
modern discussions.
Quine has, I suspect, a further reason for wishing to be rid of Aristotelian essentialism, one indicated by his remark
that (for Aristotle) essential features are so ‘independently of the language in which they are referred to’. For Quine,
there is simply no way to grasp ontological issues independently of the ways we use to describe reality. There can be no
way of knowing which features are essential independently of our language, with its own system of definition,
explanation, and classification. Indeed, from his perspective, we can make no sense of the idea that certain features are
essential to an object (or kind) without using our own linguistic practices (of definition, classification, and explanation).
However, Aristotelian essentialism, as Quine characterizes it, demands that we do just that. Hence, it must be rejected.
The crucial move is in the penultimate sentence. Why think that Aristotle requires us to make sense of the idea that
certain features are essential without using our practices of definition and explanation? Quine, it appears, thinks that
Aristotle must be committed to (what I have described as) Platonism, the view that we can ‘see’ (without any
dependence on language at all) what is essential and what is not. But, if my interpretation is correct, Aristotle differs
from the Platonist on precisely this point. For, while he will accept that:
(i) The world exists independently of us, complete with its own kinds and essences.
356 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
To talk of specific Differences in Nature, without reference to general Ideas and names is to talk unintelligibly. For I
would ask anyone, What is sufficient to make an essential difference in Nature, between any two particular Beings,
without any regard to some abstract Idea, which is looked upon as the Essence and Standard of a Species? (An
Essay Concerning Human Understanding III. vi. 5)
Locke concludes from the fact that we cannot grasp which differences are specific ones without dependence on our
system of classification and naming that there are no specific differences existing independently of us in nature. But
why does his conclusion follow? Aristotle, it should be clear, would not accept it. For, while he will agree with Locke
that:
(iii*) Our grasp of the relevant type of essences depends on our having certain definitional and explanatory
practices.
he will not conclude that:
(i*) The world does not exist independently of us, complete with its own kinds and essences.
For, he does not make the assumption, crucial to Locke's argument, that:
(P) If a claim is graspable only from the point of view of our practices of definition and explanation, it must fail to
be an objective claim about a reality existing independently of ourselves.
ARISTOTLE'S ESSENTIALISM 357
In Aristotle's account, it does not follow from the fact that certain features are visible only from within the perspective
of our definitional and explanatory perspectives that they are not features of reality. This point is already clear in the
analogy he draws between thought and colour perception.577
Both Locke and Quine (in their differing ways) fail to recognize the possibility of the distinctive mid-position, which
Aristotle sought to occupy. Quine argues from a justified rejection of Platonism (as I have characterized it) to the
inevitability of some form of conventionalism. Locke, by contrast, argues from the unobjectionable premiss (iii*) to the
(implausible) rejection of realism about kinds and their essences. Thus, both Locke and Quine fail to address the
position actually occupied by Aristotle. For, he was concerned to outline a position which combined a (plausible)
realism about essences with the acknowledgement that we can only have knowledge of essences through a route
dependent (in some measure) on our practices of definition. In this way, he combines the most attractive Platonist and
conventionalist claims ((i) and (iii*)) in one unified theory.
our practices of definition and explanation, must be too parochial to be required for a grasp on objective reality.
Aristotle does not share the objector's conception of the problem, or the empiricist starting point which motivates it.
For him, as we have seen, perception is of cross-temporal moving objects.578 Experience will add a preliminary mode of
classifying objects in a demonstrative-based way as (e.g.) this illness, this man, this disease.579 If all goes well, we will
arrive at the understanding of the master craftsman who grasps what can and cannot be done with the objects he
confronts, and aims to learn where limitations in what can be done stem from him and where from the nature of the
kind itself, such that no extension of his skill could change it. The nature of the kind is what makes some things
possible and others impossible for him. At this point, talk of natures intersects with our ordinary practices and
interactions with the world. Far from being part of an isolated, cut-off, game, they are basic to the understanding we
have as craftsmen of the world around us.
The master craftsman will raise questions such as: ‘Why is it that if I do this, that happens?’, ‘What is it about the
nature of the kind which explains why this happens after that?’ These questions concern the nature of the kind itself,
what can and what cannot (in principle) be changed and why. In asking these questions, the master craftsman aims to
make the kind's necessary properties and his dealings with them intelligible to himself. For, he wishes to know what it
is about this kind which makes certain things inevitable and others avoidable. While his grasp on the nature of the kind
is incomplete, it represents a step in the direction of the type of understanding achieved in a successful definitional
answer to the ‘What is F?’ question. Both aim to make the nature of the kind perspicuous to us. In this way, our
definitional and explanatory practices arise naturally out of the master craftsman's understanding of his subject matter.
The master craftsman plays two roles in this account. It is through his understanding that we first have access to kinds,
their natures, and their necessary features. These notions are embedded in his understanding of his dealings with the
world (as encapsulated in such sayings as: ‘That cannot be done, because . . . ’; ‘There is no point in trying that . . . it
has to be done this way.’). They cannot be dispensed with unless we are also prepared to surrender the type of
understanding which the master craftsman has of the world. For, his understanding essentially involves a modality-rich
grasp on reality. The concepts of kind, nature, and necessity employed in the theoretical discussion of the
metaphysician are rooted in the judgements of the master craftsman. It is through his involvement with kinds,
ARISTOTLE'S ESSENTIALISM 359
whether as carpenter or farmer, that we first gain access to the natures which the metaphysician studies.580
Secondly, the craftsman's understanding of natures is not exhausted by a series of claims of the form:
explanation. But surely, it will be said, this perspective cannot legitimize realist claims about kinds and essences. Does
not realism require that we be able, no matter what our definitional or explanatory practices may be, to ‘see’ the world's
modal structure? Surely, if something is real, it cannot be accessible only to those who make particular assumptions
about the nature of definition.
But why must a realist make this assumption? In Aristotle's account, the master craftsman (and not the low-level
artisan) grasps genuine kinds as such. This is because he understands that their instances share an interconnected set of
properties, which neither he nor anyone else can change. Without his engagement with the world we would lack the
grasp we have on genuine kinds. No such understanding can be achieved by the person who stays at the level of
experience. Further, without the master craftsman's practical engagement with kinds, we would not latch on (in the
appropriate way) to the modal properties we need to grasp the fundamental nature of things. While we could lay out a
map of what such structures might be, we would lack a proper understanding of their constituting the natures of kinds.
They would represent an abstract topology and not an account of the physical world we inhabit.
At this point, we can invoke Aristotle's favoured analogy with colour perception. There are two points of comparison.
First, without the master craftsman's understanding of kinds, we would be like those who are colour blind: unable to
see what is there. As we need a properly functioning visual system to grasp colours, so we need the master craftsman's
understanding to latch on to kinds. As the former does not undermine the realism of our colour judgements, so the
latter need not undermine the status of our judgements about kinds. Second, without our experiential engagement with
colours, we would not achieve an understanding of what colours are. We might have a grasp of (e.g.) properties of light
reflectance, but we would not be able to understand what it is to be coloured. Similarly, without our craft engagement
with kinds, we could map out an abstract topology containing interconnected scientific features. But the latter would
not amount to a world containing genuine kinds. For kinds, as we understand them, are ones of the type involved in
our craft engagement with the world.584
There is, in any event, good reason to interpret the judgements of the master craftsman realistically. For, he is up
against a reality which limits what he (or anyone) can do, and which makes him act in some ways not others. Indeed,
his understanding of that reality is what explains
ARISTOTLE'S ESSENTIALISM 361
why low-level artisans act as they do. There is a further reason to take his judgements as descriptions of an
independent reality. For, if all goes well, they will be underwritten by the interlocking theory of essence and causation,
which we have seen at work in a variety of contexts and situations. The latter makes the nature of the kind fully
intelligible to us in the ways indicated above. In this way, the realism of Aristotle's account of essence and nature is
supported from below by the master craftsman's grasp on kinds and from above by the interlocking theory of essence
and causation. Both have important roles to play. The latter exhibits the metaphysical depth of the idea of nature. The
former ties the theory to genuine kinds in the world, and prevents the theory being a purely abstract one, cut off from
our practices, containing relations which we do not fully understand.585
Objection 3: Can we not envisage different classifications generating incompatible definitional claims? The master
craftsman's conception of gold is dependent on the kind's having a nature, which he cannot change and which will
limit and confine his possible activities. This nature can in turn be investigated by the metaphysician. But surely a
tribesman could have a term ‘ggold’ which picked out all and only yellow metals found in a given place. Now, we might
say, for the tribesman it is a necessary feature of ggold that it is yellow. But this will not be a necessary feature of our
gold. Surely these are incompatible essentialist claims, both generated from different initial classifications of reality? If
so, our talk of essence looks to be a reflection of our interests, not a way of capturing reality.
This objection permits of a simple answer. In the case described, the essential features do not belong to the same kind.
For, the tribes-man's kind is ggold, not gold. Thus, this is not a case of inconsistent claims about the same kind, but
rather one in which there are consistent claims about different kinds. In a similar way, one can say that there are two
separable kinds, dogs and ddogs, if the former are defined solely in terms of their evolutionary history, the latter their
molecular composition.586
But this form of reply is, in some cases, over-concessive. For, it is not obvious that the tribesman, just now described,
has grasped a natural-kind concept at all. His claims about ggold do not stem from any grasp on the internal nature of
any kind, since his classification (for all he knows) may cut across several kinds. Nor do they arise from a craftsman's
understanding of the interconnected set of dispositions. Even if he has latched on to a feature of the genus metal, he
has not as yet acquired the thought of a natural kind or a natural-kind term.
362 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
Objection 4: But surely, it will be said, Aristotle must accept the following counterfactual claim:
[C] If our definitional practices had been different, the world would have contained different kinds and essences.
If so, he must think that we could have adopted equally good, but different, definitional practices, which would have
led us to detect other kinds and other essential features. However, if so, his claims about essences will flow (in the final
analysis) from us and our definitional practices and not from the world. Once again his position appears to collapse
into a form of conventionalism.
In Aristotle's account, our definitional practices contain ideas of unity and priority which can only be made determinate
by reference to the world and its causal patterns. Indeed, his basic claim is that our definitional practices cannot be fully
specified without dependence on the determinate causal patterns we find in reality. We do not, in his view, have a set of
world-independent definitional practices which we can alter independently of how the world is. Rather, the world plays
a role in determining which definitional practices we have. So, how could our definitional practices have been different?
Does the possibility of such differences lead inevitably to conventionalism about essences and kinds?
There seem to be three possible routes to support [C], which should be considered:
(i) Our definitional practices might have lacked the ideas of priority or unity.
(ii) Our definitional practices might have contained these ideas and been complete, in a wholly a priori fashion,
without any reference to the world and its causal structures.
(iii) Our definitional practices might have latched on to different causal patterns in the world.
Do any of these possibilities in fact threaten the realism of Aristotle's account? It is far from clear that they do.
If our definitional practices had been different in the way suggested by (i), we would not have defined kinds with
essences at all. Indeed, where would our idea of essence (or essence-revealing explanation) have come from?587 We
would have been as if colour blind, incapable of detecting
ARISTOTLE'S ESSENTIALISM 363
what is there to be seen. If so, the possibility of (i) does not support [C] above.
What of (ii)? Surely our definitions could have been completed in a wholly a priori fashion, without reference to the
world, in the manner favoured by Plato (independently of all connections with a posteriori causation)? If so, the world
would have contained different kinds and different essences. While both Plato and Aristotle wished to be realists, does
not this possibility undermine their claims? Surely here we are forced to collapse into conventionalism?
Aristotle's reply, if what has been said so far is correct, is a distinctive one. In his view, Plato's project (if successfully
carried through) would amount to no more than an abstract description of a possible world, not to an account of
genuine kinds (as we encounter them). It would be like a piece of abstract geometry, not a description of real space.
For, it would not be grounded in the understanding of natures around us, first acquired through our craft engagement
with the world, and deepened by our grasp on the world's causal patterns. Even if Plato's abstract model could be
mapped on to the real world in some way, it could not by itself provide an understanding of the natures of genuine
kinds. For those, we need grounding in causal patterns in reality.
And (iii)? In one case, if our definitional practices had been different in the way indicated, this would have been
because the world itself contained different kinds and essences. In such an eventuality, [C] would be true, but its truth
would not undermine the basic realism of Aristotle's account. For, the world would contain kinds and essences other
than those it now does, because its causal structure would have been radically different from those we now encounter.
But could we not, consistent with the world as it now is, have devised quite different kinds? What is the special
significance of (e.g.) our biological kinds, the ones we understand via the notion of common nature? Could we not
equally well used kinds based on material causes, such as those legitimized by a new molecular biology? Surely we
could dispense with teleologically based kinds of the type Aristotle envisages? I shall consider this objection further in
discussing biological kinds below. It is in this area that some of the severest tests of the stability of Aristotle's position
are to be found.
There is no individual parcel of Matter, to which . . . Qualities are so annexed as to be essential to it, or inseparable
from it. (An Essay Concerning Human Understanding III. vi. 6)
As soon as one considers objects merely as parcels of matter, rather than as pieces of gold or tigers:
the thought of anything essential to any of them instantly vanishes. (III. vi. 4)
There is no way (Locke claims) of deriving Aristotle's distinctions between natural kinds from the differing properties
of matter. If so, there can be no real essences of the type Aristotle envisaged.
This line of criticism is not powerful. First, even in cases where one cannot derive higher-order demarcations from
lower-order ones, there seems no reason to doubt the reality of the higher-order kinds. For, the higher-order
demarcations are marked out by considerations (such as those which concern teleological explanation) which are not
present at the lower level. It is a widely recognized feature of non-reductionist strategies that there need be no perfect
capturing of the ‘shape’ of higher-order demarcations at the lower level.588 Descartes and Locke appear to rest on the
assumption that the only genuine kinds are either present at the lowest physical level or reducible to such kinds. But
there is no reason either to believe this assumption oneself or to attribute it to Aristotle.589 Indeed, there is reason to do
neither.
What is more interesting are the assumptions which drive Descartes' argument. There are three:
(1) All genuine explanation must begin with principles that are clear and distinct.
(2) The principles of matter such as extension and movability are of this sort.
ARISTOTLE'S ESSENTIALISM 365
(3) The Aristotelian principles which govern movement, life, or animals are not of this sort.590
It would be a major undertaking to attempt to unpack and make clear Descartes' own conditions for perspicuous
explanation. Was he tempted by the view that all proper explanations of the physical should be instances of the
mathematical method, and as such graspable a priori, without dependence on empirical means?591 But, whatever the
precise details of Descartes' own position, there is a general line of response available to Aristotle: to challenge the
assumption that our explanatory starting points must enjoy the type of perspicuity on which Descartes insists, a
perspicuity far removed from the one that characterizes our dealings with the kinds around us. His starting points have
the status of an abstracted pure geometry, not those of a science dealing with the world we understand. For Aristotle,
as we have seen, the master craftsman, not the geometer, provides a model of the type of perspicuous understanding
to which we, as metaphysicians, aspire. Aristotle's project begins with what is ‘familiar to us’ and ends with an account
of what is ‘familiar by nature’. As suggested above, the kind of intelligibility we aim for (in a completed science) will be
recognizably of the general type as we, as master craftsmen, engaged at earlier stages of enquiry with the kinds that
surround us. This is why the notion of ‘what is familiar . . . ’ is the same in these two contexts. Thus, even if the
idealized type of understanding which Descartes sought is possible, it is not part (in Aristotle's view) of a proper
understanding of the world.592
366 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
Aristotle's reply comes into sharper focus when we consider his discussion of the role of nous in grasping first
principles.593 Nous grasps certain features as first elements in a science on the basis of an explanation-involving
procedure of induction. Its epistemic authority is derived from, and vindicated by, the process of induction on which it
rests. As such, nous's grasp on first principles (as reported in Post. An. Β.19) depends on seeing their role in sustaining a
pattern of explanation and differentiation of the type set out in the preceding chapters of the Analytics. There is no need
for the special type of familiarity (demanded in Descartes' rationalistic model) to account for our grasp of first
principles.
many of the Individuals that are ranked into one sort, called by one common Name, and so received as being of
one Species, yet have Qualities depending on their real Constitutions which are as different from one another as from
others, from which they are accounted to differ specifically. (III. vi. 8)
The kinds marked out by biology do not correspond precisely to the ones found at some lower level. Not merely are
they not deducible from them, but their divisions do not map precisely on to those made at the level of fundamental
science. Thus, Locke concludes, the kinds we mark out in biology are not genuine kinds. At best, they represent
shadows cast by our own interests as classifiers and namers.
But Locke's argument is not strong. In Aristotle's view, kinds can be real enough, even if they are not mappable on to
demarcations marked out in, and motivated by, fundamental physical science. As before, shapelessness at some
underlying level is no bar to the reality of the biological kind in question. It is sometimes assumed that if the kinds
demarcated in ordinary experience (such as dogs or cats594) cannot be reduced to ‘fundamental’ physical kinds, they
must be dismissed as illusory, constructs of our language, mere façons de parler.595 But Aristotle rejects this viewpoint.
Biological kinds can be genuine even if they do not reduce to more basic ones. Failure of reduction is, in his view, no
bar to reality. It is only some unquestioned reductionist dogma that can make it seem to be so.
ARISTOTLE'S ESSENTIALISM 367
If this is correct, the arguments deployed against essentialism concerning biological kinds by Locke and Descartes are
ineffective. Indeed, they fail to engage successfully with the position Aristotle actually adopted.596
in one essence of the appropriate unifying type. For the reality of the kind can be guaranteed without recourse to one
essence.
But if things are that easy, why search for one essence in other cases? How can Aristotle rest content with the lack of a
unifying cause in these cases, when in others he seeks for one? Surely, if ideally unified kinds were to be devised in
biology, he would be forced to prefer these to the biological kinds he discusses (such as fish, elephants, and dolphins).
Could he have held on to his favoured taxa in the face of other alternatives which conform more fully to his ideal?
Conversely, if there are no biological kinds of the latter type, can he avoid regarding biology as a failed science?
The question is: can Aristotle reasonably rest content with the type of interactive common-nature kinds he uncovered
in his biological studies? Can he justifiably stop at this point, without having found scientific kinds with Analytics-style
unified essences? If the latter were to be found, could he resist regarding them as a ‘better class’ of kind?
Aristotle's idea of a biological common nature is grounded in our ordinary dealings with the world, the ones
exemplified in our activities as farmers or fishermen, breeders or hunters. These are the kinds we are interested in
understanding. Indeed, it is through our involvement with them that we acquire our thoughts about what it is to be a
kind, as well as our grasp on specific kinds (such as animal, sheep, and dog.) Our craft involvement with these is our
point of access to kinds whose natures we seek to discover. If these kinds play these two roles, Aristotle has reason
enough to retain them even if they only approximate to his Analytics ideal. These are our kinds, the ones we want to
understand. For, such understanding will deepen and extend the knowledge we have as master craftsmen of the kinds
involved.
From this perspective, Aristotle's discussions of biological and non-biological kinds form a unified whole.598 In the
latter, but not the former, we find a unitary feature which makes the whole kind intelligible to us. This discovery
recognizably extends the type of understanding which the craftsman has of his subject matter. In the former, by
contrast, an extension of his understanding leads to the interactive kinds discussed in the last Chapter. We will only find
unitary Analytics-style starting points in biology if we give up trying to make our kinds thoroughly intelligible to us. But,
as we have seen, we have (in Aristotle's view) strong reasons not to take this step. For, we are interested in both cases
in extending our craft-based understanding of the relevant kinds.
Is there a further Aristotelian reply? If the analogy with colour perception holds, we may not be capable of abstracting
too far from our original starting point in craft involvement with our kinds. For, to do so would be
ARISTOTLE'S ESSENTIALISM 369
to lose the type of intelligibility we seek. It is not that there is a truly objective world which exists somewhere
inaccessible to us beyond our range. It is rather that, as in the case of colour, aspects of what is really objective can only
be grasped by creatures with the type of experience we possess. So understood, the idealized scientific story (in which
colours are replaced by wave lengths) cannot constitute a complete picture of the world. For, it cannot capture the
nature of the kinds or colours with which we interact.599
This point can be pressed further. If we were to abandon our kinds in pursuit of the scientific ideal, the resulting
account would be (at best) partial and (in the extreme case) one we could not fully understand.600 Indeed, in the latter
case, it might threaten our understanding of what it is to be a kind. While we may postulate entities which exemplify
our theoretical ideal of unity, their necessary features need be nothing more than the product of our theorizing. In the
limiting case, such idealized kinds will not possess natures of the type which limit (directly or indirectly) what we or
other kinds (with which we can interact) can do.601 If so, we would lose our understanding of what it is to be a kind
endowed with genuine necessary properties. While we might develop, in complete abstraction, a beautiful ‘logical’
picture of the world, it would not be one which contained kinds whose natures were intelligible to us.
If this is correct, Aristotle can resist the drive towards a scientific account of kinds, with ideally unified Analytics-style
essences. He can insist on the necessity of retaining certain of the kinds we understand as craftsmen, on pain of losing
our basic understanding of what it is to be a kind. We cannot, in the world as we find it, rationally detach ourselves
completely from our involvement with these kinds (the ones with which we and others causally interact). There are
important limits on the distance we can travel from our starting point in pursuit of this scientific picture.602 The world
will not
370 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
be fully intelligible if we abstract ourselves completely from the point of view, which is grounded in our craft
engagement with objects and kinds. If so, Aristotle cannot dispense with his biological kinds even though they fail to
live up to the standards he set in the Analytics.
This line of reply has the advantage of explaining Aristotle's use of colour and skill as analogues for the active intellect,
in De Anima Γ.5. Both indicate the kind of intelligibility he seeks, one manifested initially in the understanding of the
master craftsman and tied permanently (in some measure) to that perspective. However, while this line of thought
seems attractive, it could only be sustained by a deeper study of Aristotle's grounds for resisting reduction.603
essence and explanation, what makes it true that (e.g.) the composite man is prior to body and mind, rather than the
latter being prior to the former?604 Indeed, it might turn out that the distinction between essence and necessity is a
misguided one. It cannot be simply assumed that we possess determinate and justified notions of the necessary and the
essential. This needs to be established.
Second, claims of the form ‘It is necessary that man is rational’ or ‘All men are necessarily rational’ can (in principle) be
understood in more than one way. They might be interpreted (in Lockean fashion) as rooted de jure in our classificatory
conventions. Alternatively, they might be taken (as Aristotle does) to reflect de facto metaphysical necessities. The latter,
but not the former, are sometimes described as non-trivial necessities.605 If we focus solely on sentences such as:
It is necessary that P
or
a is necessarily F,
these alternatives (and the questions they raise) are overlooked. Nor can we assume that non-trivial essentialism is in
good order as it is. For, it is certainly conceivable that our practices might have developed so as to conform to some
other (e.g. Lockean) ideal, which dispensed with nontrivial essentialist claims (so understood). If so, one needs to show
that our apparent commitment to non-trivial essentialism is justified. But where we need justification, the quietist
provides none.606
There is one further point: Aristotle provided an elegant and rich metaphysical theory of essence, necessity, and
explanation to underwrite our
372 DEFINITION, ESSENCE, AND NATURAL KINDS
ordinary modal notions. Even if no such theory were strictly required (despite the remarks in the last paragraphs), it
would still be desirable. For, it gives us a deeper understanding of the relevant notions than the quietist can provide. If
quietism is to be defended, its advocates must show that Aristotelian metaphysically grounded theories are either
impossible or undesirable. But these are major claims, themselves in need of sustained argument. They cannot be
defended merely by declining to answer a set of naturally arising questions.
13.7 Conclusion
Aristotle developed a distinctive account of essence, nature, and necessity. It has four basic, separable, features. The
first pair concern thought and meaning, the second metaphysics:
(1) It does not require the ordinary thinker, in grasping a natural-kind term, to have access to proto-scientific ideas
of kinds, conceived as possessing an underlying physico-chemical structure.
(2) It does not require the ordinary thinker, in grasping a natural-kind term, to know of the existence of the
relevant kind.
(3) In it, our practices of definition and explanation are interdependent. Further, this interdependency rests on the
metaphysical thesis of the co-determination of essence and causation.
(4) In it, theoretical practices of definition and explanation are grounded in the activities and understanding of the
master craftsman. Indeed, we cannot, on pain of losing the very intelligibility we seek, abstract ourselves
completely from this original starting point.
(3), its central metaphysical claim, appears not to be vulnerable to the objections considered in this Chapter, and to
have some advantages over its current major competitors, conventionalist, Platonist, Kantian, and quietist alike. That
said, it is, in some respects, incomplete and in need of more detailed examination and development. Indeed, further
work is required on both metaphysical claims.607 Nonetheless, Aristotle's four claims are not mere relics from the
prehistory of metaphysics. Rightly understood, they are still a living and thought provoking contribution to the subject.
Appendix 1
If ‘man’ signifies one thing (as it does), let this be ‘two-footed animal’. I mean by ‘signifying one thing’ this. If man is
that (e.g. two-footed animal), then if anything is a man, that (e.g. being a two-footed animal) will be what it is to be a
man. (Meta. Γ.4, 1006a31–4)
terms which specifies a non-accidental feature of a genuine kind. (For similar reasons, ‘goatstag’ will fail to signify one
thing in the appropriate way.)
In the argument, (1) together with these semantical assumptions supports (2). The relevant account of what the term
‘man’ signifies (viz.‘two-footed animal’) (i) will have the same significance as ‘man’, and (ii) will specify a non-accidental
feature of the kind. Indeed, it will only have the same significance as ‘man’ because it fulfils (ii). Identity of signification
between these linguistic items rests on man (the kind signified) having the non-accidental feature mentioned in the
relevant account. On this basis Aristotle can move from (1) to a claim about the real world in (2). For, his criterion for
the identity of signification rests here on claims about the natures of kinds.610
It should be noted that, while the name and the relevant account have the same significance, it does not follow that
‘man’ signifies the fundamental essence of man, what it is to be a man. Aristotle is making the following points:
(3) ‘Man’ signifies one thing: the same thing as ‘two-footed animal’ signifies.
(4) ‘A’ and ‘B’ signify one and the same thing if and only if to be a two-footed animal is part of what it is to be a
man.
But it does not follow from (3) and (4) that ‘man’ signifies part of what it is to be man. For, (4) is concerned only with
the conditions under which ‘man’ and ‘two-footed animal’ signify one and the same thing, and says nothing about the
precise signification of the term ‘man’. Thus, (3) and (4) are fully consistent with ‘man’ signifying a kind which has a
distinctive nature, and do not require the term to signify that distinctive nature itself. One can only derive the stronger
claim if one adds the following premiss:
(5) To signify a kind which has a non-accidental feature is to signify that non-accidental feature.
But there is no evidence that Aristotle made this further (highly controversial) assumption in this passage.611 It is
enough for his purposes that the term does indeed signify one kind with its own distinctive nature.612
Our earlier discussion of accounts of what names signify brings into focus two further issues in the immediate context:
(i) One may grasp a stage 1 account of what some term signifies without knowing of the existence of the kind. It is,
therefore, no surprise to find in (2) the
ARISTOTLE ON THE PRINCIPLE OF NON-CONTRADICTION 375
phrase ‘if anything is a man’ in 1006a33. For, it can be used to indicate the possibility (which Aristotle countenances
elsewhere) of one's grasping this type of account without knowledge of the existence of the kind.
(ii) The account of what ‘man’ signifies will (typically) specify some non-accidental feature of man, but not the (basic)
essence of the kind. ‘Two-footed animal’ plays precisely this role (see Meta. H.3, 1043b2–4), as this is a feature of man
required by his essence (a given type of soul). It is again no surprise that in the immediate context the phrase ‘what it is
to be’ can extend beyond the essence to other features. For, in 1006b13 ff. it and similar phrases are used to specify (the
essenceless) what it is not to be a man. The term can naturally apply to features such as the one mentioned: being a
two-footed animal.
To summarize: Aristotle's line of thought rests on several assumptions about signification:
(A) ‘Man’ signifies one thing.
(B) ‘Man’ signifying one thing requires that ‘man’ can be correlated with one type of account of what that term
signifies: one which specifies a non-accidental feature of the kind.
(C) One can grasp an account of what ‘man’ signifies without knowing of the existence of the kind or of its basic
essence.
(A) and (B) require that the name ‘man’ signifies something which has a nature of the relevant type. In this case, the
kind signified will have as a non-accidental feature being two-footed. This follows, as we have noted, from Aristotle's
account of what it is for the name and account to have the same significance (granted that ‘man’ signifies one thing).
(C) reflects the semantic shallowness of stage 1 accounts.
In the dialectical context of Meta. Γ.4, (C) is important. In it, neither name nor account should specify the basic essence
of the kind. For, Aristotle's argument should work not only against those few who reject the PNC but accept (e.g.) that:
(D) ‘Man’ signifies the essence of man.
It should be effective against those who hold that:
(E) ‘Man’ signifies a kind, which has an essence.
If the argument turned on (D), its value, considered as a defence of PNC, would be slight. For, sceptics about PNC
could easily escape refutation by rejecting (D). Perhaps, they will say, ‘man’ signifies one thing, and that one thing is a
kind which has an essence. But they may see no reason to accept that the name signifies the essence itself.
The shallowness of (E) should not surprise us. It is precisely what is required in contexts in which one should make as
few (controversial) assumptions as possible. Indeed, it would be a mistake to invoke (D) at this point, with its
‘scientific’ assumptions about the basic essences of kinds. Since Aristotle is engaging with the sceptic at a ‘logical’
(logikos) level of discussion, he should use an account of what the term signifies which avoids semantically deep (and
controversial) assumptions of this type. Indeed, the existence of such contexts provides him with a further
376 APPENDIX 1
motivation (over and above those noted in Chapters 2, 4, and 6) for ensuring that stage 1 accounts are semantically
shallow.613
Assumptions (A) and (B) remain important as the argument develops. In Meta. 1006b28 ff. Aristotle writes:
If it is true to say of something that it is man, it must be a two-footed animal (for this is what ‘man’ signifies). If this
is necessary, it is impossible that the same being should not be a two-footed animal . . . It is, therefore, impossible
that it should be true to say that the same thing is a man and not a man.
those who argue in this way do away with substance and essence. (a20–1)616
ARISTOTLE ON THE PRINCIPLE OF NON-CONTRADICTION 377
Why are his opponents forced to this extreme? If they accept the proposed account of what it is to signify one thing (as
encapsulated in (A) and (B)), terms like ‘man’ can only fail to signify one thing if they completely fail to signify a
genuine kind. Aristotle expects that his opponents will remain faithful to this account of what it is to signify one thing,
but will deny that terms like ‘man’ signify one thing by claiming that there are no such kinds in reality. Rather, in their
view, ‘man’ will signify in the way ‘pale’ does. When their approach is generalized, all predications turn out to be of the
latter type (accidental: see 1007a21–2). There will be no actual cases which fulfil the agreed conditions for signifying
one thing.
Aristotle's reply is that if all predication is accidental, there will be no primary subjects (1007a33 ff.). If there are no
substances, all sentences with prospective subject terms will dissolve into several parts said accidentally of each other
(1007a35–b1). However, in his view, this is not possible. Accidents can be predicated of each other only if both belong
to one substance (1007b3–5, 15–16). Therefore, if predication is possible, there must be substances (or kinds) to stand
as the basic subjects of sentences in which ‘one thing can be said of one thing non-accidentally’. But there can be such
sentences only if the subject term signifies one thing, and this (in turn) will only be possible if there is a genuine kind
which ‘man’ signifies.
Aristotle's attachment to his account of what it is to signify one thing (as encapsulated in (B)) is a permanent feature of
this discussion. In his view, terms like ‘man’ will only cease to signify one thing if there are no genuine kinds. But the
latter, he claims, is not possible. Significant speech requires that the language's basic subjects signify one thing
(1006a21–23,a31–b12). However, such signification will not be possible if PNC is rejected. Hence, he concludes,
conformity with PNC is required for any who engage in significant speech (at least for certain central elements in their
language).617
In Aristotle's account, ‘man’ has the same significance as ‘two-footed animal’ because both signify the same kind and
do so in a non-accidental way. If this were not so, the relevant account could specify an accidental feature of the kind.
One further consequence should be noted: if ‘man’ signifies its kind in this way, the term could not retain its present
significance and apply to anything else. For, if it did so, it would only specify this kind accidentally, and would not
signify the same as the non-accidental description (‘two-footed animal’). If so, there can be no case in which ‘man’
retains its present significance and signifies a different kind from the one it actually does.618 ‘Man’ could not retain the
significance it presently does were
378 APPENDIX 1
it not correlated (non-accidentally) with the very kind with which it is now linked. But this is precisely what we should
expect if (for Aristotle) the signification of this name is fixed by the identity of the kind with which it is correlated (by
‘likening’, as suggested in Chapter 4 Sections 4.1 and 4.2). For, that model makes it impossible for the signification of a
name to remain constant if the name is ‘likened’ (in different contexts) to different kinds. In these respects, Aristotle's
discussion of what it is for a name and account to signify one thing coheres well with the way in which (in his view) the
signification of such names is determined (as interpreted in Chapter 4).
Appendix 2 Essence, Necessity, and the Copula
Theaetetus thrives.
—the name and the rhema (verb). The latter expression has three roles:
(1) It signifies something (e.g. thriving).
(2) It co-signifies time.
(3) It is a sign (in affirmations) of being said of something else.
The verb (in addition to signifying the state of thriving) signifies when ‘thriving’ is predicated of Theaetetus, and asserts
that ‘thriving’ is predicated of him. Of its three semantic roles, only the first is referential. The expression does not in
addition refer to a time, or to a special binding agent. Rather, through (2) and (3), ‘thriving’ is asserted to be true now
of Theaetetus.
These three semantic roles need not be played by one word alone. The verb can be replaced by a participle and the
copula, as in the sentence:
Theaetetus is thriving.
Here, the copula performs the second and third roles:
(2) It indicates tense (e.g. now).
(3) It signifies a combination. (16b24)
It does not, in Aristotle's view, signify ‘being’ by itself (16b21). Its role is to express the combination of the items
referred to: Theaetetus and health. The copula indicates that there is now a combination of health with Theaetetus.
In De Interpretatione 19b19 ff. Aristotle appears concerned to emphasize that ‘is’ is a third item in sentences along with
terms such as ‘man’ and ‘just’. It predicates in addition that ‘just’ is true of man, in the way in which all verbs signify, in
addition, time. In the copula we have a word which lacks signification on its own, but which has this type of additional
signification when combined with ‘just’. It signifies the combination of ‘man’ and ‘just’, and is co-predicated along with
the term ‘just’. Thus, its role appears more closely linked with ‘just’ than with ‘man’. For, it co-predicates with the latter
and not the former.
Aristotle is developing a grammatical picture, in which the copula is aligned syntactically and semantically more closely
with the predicate term (in this case,
380 APPENDIX 2
‘just’) than with the subject.619 This is certainly how he was taken by the ancient commentators Alexander and
Ammonius. Thus, Alexander wrote (In Analytica Priora. 369.12–14): “ ‘to be” is not a term, but is added to the
predicate terms in the analysis of the sentences into terms’ (see In. Apr. 16.7–10).‘The predicate term is that to which
“is” is added’ (In. Apr. 406.32–4). Similarly, Ammonius writes “ ‘to be” is adjoined to the predicate term . . . ’ (In Apr.
23.27–8).620
In Aristotle's subject/predicate analysis of these sentences, the copula has a role (or series of roles) within the
predicate. One such role is suggested in Aristotle's discussion of negation. In his view, the sentence ‘A is just’ has two
opposites:
(1) A is-not just
and
(2) A is not-just.
(1) denies to A the positive state of justice, while (2) asserts of A the negative state of not-being-just. Corresponding to
the latter is a further denial:
(3) ‘A is-not not-just’, which denies to A the negative state of being-not-just (cf. De Int. 19b27 f.).
The negated copula (in (1) and (3)) has the distinctive role of denying to A a given state (whether positive or negative).
In effect, it is a sign of the separation of that state from A. In these cases, Aristotle adds ‘not’ to the verb or copula
(21b19–23). If he were to employ a negation operator governing the whole sentence, it would be derivative from this
central case.
Aristotle seeks to distinguish (1) and (2) in a variety of ways. Thus, for instance, in cases where no object is marked out
by the grammatical subject, he takes (1) to be true, but (2) to be false. In his view, while imagined or fictional objects
may be truly denied the positive state of being just, they cannot be truly asserted to possess a given negative state.621
Such objects cannot possess either positive or negative states but they can be truly denied to possess such states.622
ESSENCE, NECESSITY, AND THE COPULA 381
The copula is crucial for Aristotle's analysis of modal sentences such as:
Addition 1 is made to the terms ‘white’ and ‘man’, Addition 2 to ‘is’ or ‘is not’, now taken itself ‘as a subject’. In
Addition 1, ‘is’ acts as an indicator of the way in which man and white are connected (by combination rather than
division). In Addition 2, ‘is’ is like a subject because, although it does not indicate an actual
382 APPENDIX 2
subject, it is modified by ‘possible’ and ‘not possible’. The latter indicates how the two genuine subjects (white and
man) are combined, when white possibly-belongs to man.624 The manner of the combination of the basic subjects is
progressively specified at the two levels. At the first, it is said to be that of connection (rather than separation), at the
second the form of connection is further clarified (as possibly-connected/not possibly-connected/essentially-
connected, etc.).
Aristotle compares his use of modal notions with his use of ‘true’ and ‘false’. In a simple affirmation, such as:
Theaetetus is a man
the predicate term ‘man’ is said to be true of Theaetetus. In modal sentences such as:
a is F
the ‘is’ functions to indicate the feature F's belonging to a (by affirming ‘F’ of a). This claim is then modified to form:
F possibly-belongs to a
F necessarily-belongs to a.
If the first claim is taken as equivalent to:
F really-belongs to a
in the next two sentences ‘really-belongs’ is modified in different ways. In this way, ‘necessary’ and ‘possible’ are added
to make affirmations of the subject (22a7 ff.). In affirmative modal cases, the modal addition (functioning in addition)
indicates a predicate's being combined in a given way with the subject (22a11–14).625
ESSENCE, NECESSITY, AND THE COPULA 383
If one takes ‘possible’ and ‘necessary’ as copula-modifiers in this context, one can explain Aristotle's complex
discussion of the role of negation in modal contexts. The negation of:
A is-possibly wise
is
A is-not-possibly wise
and not:
A is possibly not-wise.
Why? Because at the level defined by Addition 2 one added ‘possibly’ to ‘is’ to form the
A is-possibly wise.
To negate this, one should go back to the previous level, and replace ‘possibly’ with ‘not-possibly’ to form:
In the actual world, Theaetetus is an Athenian, but in some possible world he is a Theban.
Here, we need to make sense of talk of possible worlds, and to consider whether Theaetetus is the same individual in
the two worlds in question.628
Aristotle's copula-modifier view differs from the first two options in not introducing world-relativized objects or
world-relativized properties. Nor is it a variant of the third option since it takes as basic the relation within the sentence
between subject and predicate. It is not to be understood as involving reference to possible worlds. In Aristotle's
account, the modal terms are syntactically adverbs, focusing on the modes/ways in which features are related to
objects. In place of modal properties or world-bound individuals, one has a variety of ways in which non-modalized
properties can belong to objects. His strategy allows him to keep the ontology simple (i.e. restricted to this world's
objects or combinations of such objects and non-modal features which belong to objects in this world), and to treat
modality (along with tense and negation) as ways in which these features belong to the relevant objects. His account of
the logical structure of modal sentences reflects his relatively uncomplicated ontology.629 For, he has no need of
possible
386 APPENDIX 2
objects, possible properties, or possible worlds to account for the truth of sentences involving possibility and
necessity.630
Aristotle's logical grammar captures in a perspicuous way his metaphysical claims (as set out in Chapters 7–10). To
recapitulate: essential features, in Aristotle's view, are simply the ones which belong definitionally to a kind. Thus, in the
case of a given kind A:
(E) ‘A is-essentially F’ is True if and only if F is the feature which makes the kind A the one it is (in the ways
discussed in Chapters 7–10).
A's necessary properties are ones whose presence follows (whether always or for the most part) from A's being F.
Necessary properties will be ones whose presence is explained by A's being F. Thus:
(N) ‘A is-necessarily P’ is True if and only if A's being P follows either always or for the most part from A's being F.
A's possible properties (e.g. being Q) are those properties whose possession by A is consistent with A's necessary and
essential features.‘A is-not Q’ does not follow from A's possessing its essential or necessary features.
(P) ‘A is-possibly Q’ is True if and only if it is consistent with A's essential and necessary features that A is Q.
Aristotle, it should be noted, usually takes A's possible properties also to be ones which are neither necessary nor
essential.631
ESSENCE, NECESSITY, AND THE COPULA 387
It is not that Aristotle attempts to read his metaphysics directly from his favoured logical grammar.632 It is rather that it
is an advantage of the latter that it expresses in a perspicuous way the metaphysical realities (as he sees them).633 The
latter requires neither possible worlds, nor possible-world-bound objects or properties. All that is needed is that certain
causally basic features make those kinds the ones they are (in the way captured by his co-determination thesis).
This page intentionally left blank
Bibliography
Ackrill, J. Aristotle's Categories and De Interpretatione (Oxford, 1963).
—— ‘Aristotle's Theory of Definition: Some Questions on Post. An. 2. 8–10’, in E. Berti (1981), 339–58.
Albritton, R. ‘Substance and Form in Aristotle's Metaphysics’, Journal of Philosophy 54, (1957), 699–708.
Alexander, in In Analytica Priora, ed. M. Wallies (Berlin, 1883).
—— in In Aristotelis Metaphysica Commentaria, ed. M. Hayduck (Berlin, 1891).
Ammonius, in Analytica Priora I, ed. M. Wallies (Berlin, 1899).
Avgelis, N. and Peonidis, F. (eds.). Aristotle on Logic, Language and Science (Thessaloniki, 1998).
Balme, D. M. ‘Aristotle's Use of Differentiae in Zoology’, in S. Mansion (1961), reprinted in Barnes, Schofield and
Sorabji (eds.) 1, 183–93.
—— ‘Genos and Eidos in Aristotle’, Classical Quarterly, NS, 12 (1962), 81–98.
—— Aristotle's De Partibus Animalium I and De Generatione Animalium I (With Passages From II. 1–3) (Oxford, 1972).
—— ‘Aristotle's Use of Division and Differentiae’, in A. Gotthelf and J. G. Lennox (eds.) (1987), 69–89.
Bambrough, R. New Essays on Plato and Aristotle (London, 1965).
Barnes, J. Aristotle's Posterior Analytics (Oxford, 1975), 2nd edn. (Oxford, 1994).
—— ‘Grammar on Aristotle's Terms’, in M. Frede and G. Striker (eds.) (1996), 175–202.
—— Schofield, M. and Sorabji, R. (eds.). Articles on Aristotle 1: Science (London, 1978), 3: Metaphysics (London, 1979).
Berti, E. (ed.), Aristotle on Science (Padua, 1981).
Boden, M. (ed.), The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence (Oxford, 1990).
Boghossian, P. ‘What the Externalist Can Know A Priori’, PAS 97 (1997), 161–75.
Bolton, R. ‘Essentialism and Semantic Theory in Aristotle: Posterior Analytics II. 7–10’, Philosophical Review 85 (1976),
515–44.
—— ‘Aristotle on the Signification of Names’, Language and Reality in Greek Philosophy: Proceedings of the Greek Philosophical
Society 1984/5 (Athens, 1985), 153–62.
—— ‘Definition and Scientific Method in Aristotle's Posterior Analytics and the Generation of Animals’, in A. Gotthelf and
J. Lennox (eds.) (1987), 120–66.
—— ‘Aristotle's Method in Natural Science’, in L. Judson (ed.) (1991), 1–29.
—— ‘Division, définition et essence dans la science aristotelicienne’, Revue Philosophique 2 (1993), 197–222.
—— ‘Aristotle's Conception of Metaphysics as a Science’, in T. Scaltsas, D. Charles, and M. L. Gill (eds.) (1994),
321–54.
—— ‘Science and the Science of Substance in Aristotle's Metaphysics Z’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76 (1995), 454–7.
390 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Bolton, R. ‘The Material Cause: Matter and Explanation in Aristotle's Natural Science’, in Kullman and Follinger
(1997), 97–124.
Bonitz, H. Index Aristotelicus (Berlin, 1970).
Bowen, A. C. (ed.), Science and Philosophy in Classical Greece (Pittsburgh, 1989).
Brentano, F. Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, trans. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrel, and L. McAlister (London, 1973).
—— The Psychology of Aristotle, trans. R. George (Berkeley, 1977).
Brewer, B. Perception and Reason (Oxford, 1999).
Broackes, J. ‘Aristotle, Objectivity and Perception’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 17 (1999), 51–113.
Broadie, S. Nature, Change and Agency (Oxford, 1982).
—— ‘Aristotle's Perceptual Realism’, in J. Ellis (1993), 137–59.
Brody, B.‘Why Settle for Anything Less than Good Old-Fashioned Aristotelian Essentialism?’, Nous 7, (1993), 351–65.
Burge, T. ‘Individualism and the Mental’, Midwest Studies 4 (1979), 73–121.
—— ‘Cartesian Error and Perception’, in P. Pettit and J. McDowell (1986), 117–36.
—— ‘Intellectual Norms and Foundations of Mind’, Journal of Philosophy 83 (1986), 697–720.
Burnyeat, M. (ed.), Notes on Book Zeta of Aristotle's Metaphysics (Oxford, 1979).
—— ‘Aristotle on Understanding Knowledge’, in E. Berti (1981), 97–139.
—— Notes on ETA and THETA (Oxford Subfaculty of Philosophy, 1984).
—— ‘Aristotle voit du rouge et entend un “do”: combien se passe-t-il de choses? Remarques sur De Anima, 2, 7–8’, in
G. R. Dherbey (1996), 149–67.
Butler, T. ‘On David Charles' Account of Aristotle's Semantics for Simple Names’, Phronesis 42 (1997), 21–34.
Carriero, J. P. The Second Meditation and the Essence of the Mind', in A. O. Rorty (ed.) (1986), 199–221.
Caston, V. ‘Why Aristotle Needs Imagination’, Phronesis 41/1 (1996), 20–55.
—— ‘Aristotle and the Problem of Intentionality’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58/2 (1998), 249–98.
Charles, D. Aristotle's Philosophy of Action (London, 1984).
—— ‘Natural Kinds and Natural History’, in D. Devereux and P. Pellegrin (eds.) (1985), 145–67.
—— ‘Aristotle: Ontology and Moral Reasoning’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 4 (1986), 119–44.
—— ‘Aristotle on Hypothetical Necessity and Irreducibility’, PPQ 69 (1988), 1–54.
—— ‘Teleological Causation in the Physics’, in L. Judson (ed.) (Oxford, 1991), 101–28.
—— ‘Supervenience, Composition and Physicalism’, in D. Charles and K. Lennon (eds.) (1992), 265–96.
—— ‘Aristotle on Names and Their Signification’, in S. Everson (ed.) (1994), 37–73.
—— ‘Matter and Form: Unity, Persistence and Identity’, in T. Scaltsas, D. Charles, and M. L. Gill (eds.) (1994),
75–105.
—— ‘Aristotle and Modern Moral Realism’, in R. Heinaman (ed.) (1995), 135–72.
BIBLIOGRAPHY 391
—— ‘Metaphysics Λ. 2: Matter and Change’, in M. Frede and D. Charles (eds.) (2000), forthcoming.
—— and Lennon, K. (eds.), Reduction, Explanation and Realism (Oxford, 1992).
Chiba, K. Aristotle on Explanation: Demonstrative Science and Scientific Inquiry (Hokkaido, 1992).
Clark, P. and Hale, B. (eds.), Reading Putnam (Oxford, 1994).
Code, A. ‘No Universal is a Substance: An interpretation of Ζ.13, 1038b8–15’, Paideia, 2nd Special Issue, (1978), 65–76.
—— ‘Aristotle's Investigation of a Basic Logical Principle: Which Science Investigates The Principle of Non-
Contradiction?’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 16 (1986), 341–58.
—— and Moravcsik, J. ‘Explaining Various Forms of Living’, in M. Nussbaum and A. O. Rorty (eds.) (1992), 129–46.
Cooper, J. M. ‘Metaphysics in Aristotle's Embryology’, in D. Devereux and P. Pellegrin (eds.) (1990), 55–84.
—— ‘Aristotle on Emotion’, in D. J. Furley and A. Nehamas (eds.) (1994), 193–210.
Corcoran, J. Ancient Logic and Modern Interpretations (Dordrecht, 1974).
Crivelli, P. ‘Notes on Aristotle's Conception of Truth’, in M. S. Funghi (ed.) (1996), 147–59.
Cussins, A. ‘The Connectionist Construction of Concepts’, in M. Boden (ed.) (1990), 368–440.
Descartes, R. Philosophical Writings, ed. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch, 2 vols (Cambridge, 1985).
Detel, W. Aristoteles Analytica Posteriora (Berlin, 1993).
—— ‘Why All Animals Have a Stomach: Demonstration and Axiomatization in Aristotle's Parts of Animals’, in W.
Küllman and S. Follinger (eds.) (1997), 63–82.
DeMoss, D. and Devereux, D. ‘Essence, Existence, and Nominal Definition in Aristotle's Posterior Analytics II.8–10’,
Phronesis 33 (1988), 133–54.
Devereux, D. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), Biologie, Logique et Métaphysique chez Aristote (Paris, 1990).
Dherbey, G. R. (ed.), Corps et Ame (Paris, 1996).
Dummett, M. Frege (London, 1973).
Dupre, J. ‘Biological Taxa’, Philosophical Review 90 (1981), 66–91.
Düring, I. ‘Aristotle's Method in Biology’, in S. Mansion (1961), 213–21.
Ebert, T. ‘Aristotle on What is Done in Perceiving’, Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 37 (1983), 181–98.
Ellis, J. (ed.), Ancient Minds: The Southern Journal of Philosophy 31, suppl. (1993).
Eustratius, In Analyticorum Posteriorum Librum Secundum Commentarium, ed. M. Hayduck (Berlin, 1907).
Evans, G. ‘The Causal Theory of Names’, PASS 47 (1973), 187–208.
—— Varieties of Reference (Oxford, 1982).
Everson, S. (ed.), Companions to Ancient Thought 3: Language (Cambridge, 1994).
—— Aristotle on Perception (Oxford, 1997).
Falcon, A. ‘Aristotle's Rules of Division in the Topics: The Relation between Genus and Differentia in Division’, Ancient
Philosophy 16/2 (1996), 377–88.
392 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Ferejohn, M. ‘Definition and the Two Stages of Aristotelian Demonstration’, Review of Metaphysics 36 (1982), 375–95.
—— The Origins of Aristotelian Science (New Haven, 1991).
—— ‘The Definition of Generated Composites in Aristotle's Metaphysics’, in T. Scaltas, D. Charles, and M. L. Gill (eds.)
(1994), 291–318.
Field, H. ‘Mental Representation’, Erkenntnis 13 (1978), 9–61.
Fine, K. ‘Essence and Modality’, Philosophical Perspectives 8 (1994), 1–15.
Forbes, G. The Metaphysics of Modality (Oxford, 1985).
Fortenbaugh, W. W. Theophrastean Studies (New Brunswick, 1988).
Frede, M. ‘Substance in Aristotle's Metaphysics’, in A. Gotthelf (ed.) (1985), 17–26.
—— Essays in Ancient Philosophy (Minnesota, 1987).
—— ‘The Definition of Sensible Substance in Metaphysics Ζ’, in D. T. Devereux and P. Pellegrin (eds.), Biologie, logique et
métaphysique chez Aristote (Paris, 1990), 113–29.
—— ‘Aristotle's Notion of Potentiality in Metaphysics θ’, in T. Scaltsas, D. Charles, and M. L. Gill (1994), 173–93.
—— (ed.), Aristotle and Moral Realism (London, 1995).
—— ‘La Theorie aristotelicienne de l'intellect agent’, in G. R. Dherbey (1996), 377–90.
—— and Charles, D. (eds.), Metaphysics Lambda: Symposium Aristotelicum (Oxford, 2000).
—— and Patzig, G. Aristoteles Metaphysik Ζ (Munich, 1988).
—— and Striker, G. (eds.), Rationality in Greek Thought (Oxford, 1996).
Funghi, M. S. (ed.), Studies in Honour of F. Adorno (Florence, 1996).
Furley, D. J. and Nehamas, A. (eds.), Ethical-Political Theory in Aristotle's Rhetoric (Princeton, 1994).
Garber, D. ‘Semel in Vita: The Scientific Background’, in A. O. Rorty (ed.), Essays on Descartes' Meditations (Berkeley,
1986), 81–116.
Gill, M. L. Aristotle on Substance: The Paradox of Unity (Princeton, 1989).
Goldin, O. Explaining the Eclipse: Aristotle's Posterior Analytics 2. 1–10. (Michigan, 1996).
Gomez-lobo, A.‘On the So-called Question of Existence in Aristotle, An. Post. 2. 1–2’, Review of Metaphysics 34 (1980),
71–91'.
—— ‘Definitions in Aristotle's Posterior Analytics’, in D. O'Meara (ed.) (1981), 25–46.
Gotthelf, A. (ed.), Aristotle on Nature and Living Things (Pittsburgh, 1985).
—— and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology (Cambridge, 1987).
—— ‘Historiae 1: planatarum et animalium’, in W. W. Fortenbaugh (ed.) (1988), 100–35.
—— ‘The Elephant's Nose: Further Reflections on the Axiomatic Structure of Biological Explanation in Aristotle’, in
W. Kullman and S. Follinger (eds.) (1997), 85–95.
Granger, H. ‘The Scala Naturae and the Continuity of Kinds’, Phronesis 30 (1985), 181–222.
Hamlyn, D. W. Aristotle's De Anima II and III (Oxford, 1968).
BIBLIOGRAPHY 393
Harte, V. ‘Aristotle's Metaphysics H.6: A Dialectic with Platonism’, Phronesis 41/3 (1996), 276–304.
Heinaman, R. E. ‘Aristotle's Tenth Aporia’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 61 (1979), 249–70.
Hicks, R. D. Aristotle: de Anima (Cambridge, 1907).
Huffman, C. A. Philolaus of Croton (Cambridge, 1993).
Hughes, G. ‘Universals as Potential Substances’, in M. Burnyeat (ed.) (1979), 107–26.
Hussey, E. Aristotle's Physics III–IV (Oxford, 1983).
Iamblichus De Communi Mathematica Scientia, ed. N. Festo (Leipzig, 1891).
—— In Nicomachi Arithmeticam Introductionem, ed. H. Pistelli (Leipzig, 1894).
—— Introductio Arithmetica, ed. R. Hoche (Leipzig, 1866).
Irwin, T. ‘Aristotle's Account of Signification’, in M. Schofield and M. Nussbaum (eds.), Language and Logos (Cambridge,
1982), 241–66.
—— ‘Aristotle's Concept of Signification’, in M. Schofield and M. Nussbaum (eds.) (1982), 240–66.
—— Aristotle's First Principles (Oxford, 1988).
Jacobs, W. ‘Aristotle and Nonreferring Subjects’, Phronesis 24 (1979), 282–300.
Judson, L. (ed.), Aristotle's Physics (Oxford, 1991).
—— ‘Chance and “Always or for the Most Part” in L. Judson (ed.) (1991), 73–99.
—— ‘What Can Happen When You Eat Pungent Food’, in N. Avgelis and F. Peonidis (eds.) (1998), 185–203.
Kahn, C. ‘The Role of nous in the Cognition of First Principles in Posterior Analytics 2. 19’, in E. Berti (1981), 385–414.
Karasmanis, V. ‘The Hypotheses of Mathematics in Plato's Republic and his Contribution to the Axiomatization of
Geometry’, in P. Nicopoulos (ed.) (1990), 121–35.
Kirwan. C, (ed.), Aristotle, Metaphysics Γ, Δ, Ε (Oxford, 1971).
Knorr, W. R. ‘Construction as Existence Proof in Ancient Geometry’, Ancient Philosophy 3 (1983), 125–47.
Knuuttila, S. Modalities in Medieval Philosophy (London, 1993).
Kosman, L. A. ‘Understanding, Explanation and Insight in the Posterior Analytics’, in E. N. Lee, A. P. D. Mourelatos,
and R. M. Rorty (eds.) (1973), 374–92.
—— ‘Substance, Being and Energeia’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 2 (1984), 121–49.
Kretzmann, N. ‘Aristotle on Spoken Sounds and Significance by Convention’, in J. Corcoran (ed.) (1974), 3–21.
Kripke, S. Naming and Necessity (Oxford, 1980).
Kullman, W. and Follinger, S. (eds.), Aristotelische Biologie (Stuttgart, 1997).
Kung, J. ‘Aristotle on Essence and Explanation’, Philosophical Studies, vol. 31 (1997), 361–83.
Lagerlund, H. Modal Syllogistics in the Middle Ages (Uppsala, 1999).
Landor. B. ‘Definitions and Hypotheses in Posterior Analytics 72a19–25 and 76b35–77a4’, Phronesis 26 (1981), 308–18.
Lear, J.‘Aristotle's Philosophy of Mathematics’, Philosophical Review 91 (1982), 161–93.
394 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Millikan, R. Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge, Mass., 1984).
Modrak, D. Aristotle: The Power of Perception (Chicago, 1987).
Moravcsik, J. M. E. (ed.), Aristotle: Critical Essays (New York, 1967).
Morrow, G. (ed.), Commentary on the First Book of Euclid's Elements (Princeton, 1970), 9. 19.
Mueller, I. ‘Aristotle on Geometrical Objects’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 52 (1970), 156–67.
—— Philosophy of Mathematics and Deductive Structure in Euclid's Elements (Cambridge, Mass., 1981).
Nicopoulos, P. (ed.), Greek Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science (Dordrecht, 1990).
Nussbaum, M. C. Aristotle's de Motu Animalium (Princeton, 1978).
—— ‘Saving Aristotle's Appearances’, in M. Schofield and M. Nussbaum (eds.) (1982), 267–94.
—— and Rorty, A. O. (eds.) Essays on Aristotle's De Anima (Oxford, 1992).
O'meara, D. (ed.), Studies in Aristotle (Washington, 1981).
Owen, G. E. L. ‘Tithenai ta phainomena’, in S. Mansion (ed.) (1961), 83–103.
—— ‘Aristotle on the Snares of Ontology’, in R. Bambrough (ed.) (1965).
Pacius, J. In Porphrii Isagogen et Aristotelis Organon Commentarius Analyticus (Frankfurt, 1597).
Parker, R. ‘Sex, Women and Ambiguous Animals’, Phronesis 29 (1984), 174–87.
Patterson, R. Aristotle's Modal Logic (Cambridge, 1995).
Patzig, G. Aristotle's Theory of the Syllogism, trs. J. Barnes (Dordrecht, 1969).
Pears, D. ‘Ifs and Cans’, Questions in the Philosophy of Mind (London, 1975), 142–92.
Pellegrin, P. La Classification des animaux chez Aristote (Paris, 1982),
trans. A. Preus, Aristotle's Classification of Animals (Berkeley, 1986).
—— ‘Aristotle: A Zoology without Species’, in A. Gotthelf (ed.) (1985), 95–115.
Pelletier, F. J. and King-Farlow, J. (eds.), New Essays on Aristotle (Calgary, 1984).
Peterson, S. L. The Master Paradox (Princeton Ph.D. thesis, 1969).
—— ‘Substitution in Aristotelian Technical Contexts’, Philosophical Studies 47 (1985), 249–57.
Pettit, P. and J. McDowell (eds.). Subject, Thought and Context (Oxford, 1986).
Philoponus in Analytica Posteriora, ed. M. Wallies (Berlin, 1909).
Putnam, H. Philosophical Papers, 3 vols. (Cambridge, 1975).
—— ‘Meaning and Reference’, in S. P. Schwarz (ed.) (1977), 119–32.
—— Reason, Truth and History (Cambridge, 1981).
—— ‘Aristotle after Wittgenstein’, in R. W. Sharples (ed.) (1993), 117–137.
—— ‘Comments and Replies’, in P. Clarke and B. Hale (1994).
Quine, W. V. ‘Grades of Modal Involvement’, in Ways of Paradox (New York, 1956), 156–174.
—— ‘Reference and Modality’, in From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, Mass., 1964), 139–159.
Rorty, A. O. (ed.), Essays on Descartes' Meditations (Berkeley, 1986).
396 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Rorty, R. ‘Genus as Matter: A Reading of Metaphysics Z-H’, in E. N. Lee, A. P. D. Mourelatos, and R. M. Rorty (eds.)
(1973), 393–420.
Ross, W. D. Aristotle's Metaphysics, 2 vols. (Oxford, 1924).
—— Aristotle's Prior and Posterior Analytics (Oxford, 1949).
Salmon, N. Reference and Essence (Oxford, 1982).
—— Frege's Puzzle (Boston, 1982).
Sambursky, S. ‘Philoponus' Interpretation of Aristotle's Theory of Light’, Osiris 13 (1958), 114–26.
Scaltsas, T. ‘Substratum, Subject and Substance’, Ancient Philosophy 5 (1985), 215–40.
—— Charles, D. and Gill, M. L. (eds.), Unity, Identity and Explanation in Aristotle's Metaphysics (Oxford, 1994).
Schiffer, S. Remnants of Meaning (Cambridge, 1987).
Schofield, M. and Nussbaum, M. (eds.), Language and Logos (Cambridge, 1982).
Schwartz, S. (ed.), Naming, Necessity and Natural Kinds (Cornell, 1977).
Sellars, W.‘Substance and Form in Aristotle’, Journal of Philosophy 54 (1957), 688–99.
—— ‘Aristotle's Metaphysics: An Interpretation’ in Philosophical Perspectives (Springfield, 1967), 73–124.
Sharples, R. W. (ed.), Modern Thinkers and Ancient Thinking (London, 1993).
Sidelle, A. Necessity, Essence and Individualism: a Defense of Conventionalism (Ithaca, 1989).
Slomkowski, P. Aristotle's Topics (Leiden, 1977).
Smiley, T. ‘Syllogism and Quantification’, Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (1962), 58–72.
Smith, R. ‘Immediate Propositions and Aristotle's Proof Theory’, Ancient Philosophy 6 (1986), 47–55.
Sorabji, R. Necessity, Cause and Blame (London and Ithaca, 1980).
Spellman, L. ‘Referential Opacity in Aristotle’, History of Philosophy Quarterly 7 (1990), 17–33.
Themistius, Analyticorum Posteriorum Paraphrasis, ed. M. Wallies (Berlin, 1900).
Theon smyrnaeus, Expositio Rerum Mathematicarum, ed. E. Hiller (Leipzig, 1878).
Tselemanis, P. ‘Theory of Meaning and Signification in Aristotle’, Language and Reality in Greek Philosophy: Proceedings of the
Greek Philosophical Society 1984/5 (Athens, 1985), 194–203.
Upton, T. ‘Naming and Non-Being in Aristotle’, Proceedings of the Catholic Philosophical Association 59 (1985), 275–88.
—— ‘Aristotelian Hypothesis and the Unhypothesized First Principle’, Review of Metaphysics 39 (1986), 283–301.
Waterlow, S. Nature, Chance and Agency (Oxford, 1982).
Wedin, M. ‘Aristotle on the Existential Import of Singular Sentences’, Phronesis 23 (1978), 179–96.
—— ‘Singular Statements and Essentialism in Aristotle’, in F. J. Pelletier and J. King-Farlow (eds.) (1984), 67–88.
—— Mind and Imagination in Aristotle (New Haven, 1988).
BIBLIOGRAPHY 397
Whiting, J. ‘Form and Individuation in Aristotle’, History of Philosophy Quarterly, 3 (1986), 359–77.
—— ‘Metasubstance: Critical Notice of Frede-Patzig and Furth’, Philosophical Review 100 (1991), 607–39.
Wiesner, H. J. (ed.), Aristoteles Werk und Wirkung (Berlin, 1985).
Wiggins, D. Sameness and Substance (Oxford, 1981).
—— ‘Putnam's Doctrine of Natural Kind Words’, in Clark and Hale (ed.) (1994), 201–15.
Witt, C. Substance and Essence in Aristotle (Ithaca, 1989).
Woodfield, A. (eds.), Thought and Object (Oxford, 1982).
Woods, M. ‘Problems in Metaphysics Ζ. Chapter 13’, in J. M. E. Moravcsik (ed.) (1967), 215–38.
—— ‘Particular Forms Revisited’, Phronesis 36 1 (1991), 75–87.
—— ‘Universals and Particular Forms in Aristotle's Metaphysics’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy (1991,
Supplement), 41–56.
Zabarella, J. Opera Logica (Frankfurt, 1608).
This page intentionally left blank
Index Locorum
Categories; 1a6–10: 84; 1a20: 85; 1b25–7: 78; 13b31: 90
De Interpretatione; 16a3–8: 80–1; 16a8–9: 80–1, 114; 16a10: 81;
16a14: 81; 16a19–26: 81, 88; 16b6ff: 379; 16b21–5: 84,
379; 16b32–3: 88; 18a13f: 92; 18a18–23: 90–2; 18a23–7:
84, 90–1; 19 b19ff: 379; 19 b27f: 380; 20a13: 84;
20b15–18: 91, 94; 21a14–16: 94; 21a24–5: 94; 21a25–7:
94; 21a32f: 92; 21b19–23: 380; 21b26ff: 381; 22a7–10:
382, 383; 22a11–14: 382
Prior Analytics; 24b16–18: 380; 29b29ff: 381–2; 29b36–30a2:
384; 46a10–12: 222; 46a18–20: 151; 46a23–7: 315, 328;
46a37–b2: 193; 46b2–10: 192–3; 46b20–2: 193; 67b 5–10:
99
Posterior Analytics; 71a11–17: 27, 72–3, 76, 84; 71a29ff: 76;
71b10–12: 162; 71b28–72a5: 65, 100, 200, 272; 72a9: 203;
72a14–24: 73–6; 72b26–32: 272; 73a34: 256; 73b 7: 275;
73b26ff: 207; 75b31ff: 46; 76a4–7: 39; 76a 31–6: 25, 34,
68, 72–6, 268; 76a41: 270; 76b1: 75; 76b 3: 75; 76b6–12:
72, 75; 76b15–16: 72, 75; 76b16–20: 72, 75; 76b27: 75;
76b31: 75; 76b32–4: 76; 76b35–8: 72, 75; 77a3f: 75, 270;
77a32: 270; 78a37f: 201; 81b 31–5: 83; 82a7f: 215;
82b34–83a1: 215, 283, 286; 83a24ff: 78, 224, 253;
83a39ff: 224; 83b1ff: 253; 83b 2–8: 215, 253, 275;
84a7f: 253; 84a10ff: 253; 85b9–13: 36; 85b15–18: 280;
86a13–21: 272; 88a3ff: 222; 88a 18ff: 253; 89b26–30: 60,
65, 70; 89b32–3: 70; 89b 34–5: 70, 71, 275; 90a3–7: 70;
90a8: 53; 90a9–11: 70, 275; 90a12–13: 70; 90a14–21: 24,
200, 202, 214, 219, 245–6, 257; 90a26–7: 70; 90a31–3:
277; 90a35–6: 28, 47, 71; 90b9–13: 59, 65; 90b14–17: 28,
30,
400 INDEX LOCORUM
115; 424a 21–5: 116; 425 a4ff: 121; 425 a8ff: 122;
425 a 16–20: 124–5, 128; 425 a 20–7: 124–5, 126;
425 a 31– b 3: 124–5; 425 b 4ff: 128; 425 b 6–9: 126;
425 b23ff: 112; 425b28–30: 132; 426 a15–18: 132;
426a21–6: 132; 427b5: 112; 427b8: 122; 427b8–11: 135;
427b13ff: 123; 428a10–12: 317; 428b18–20: 118, 120,
123; 428b21: 123; 428b25–30: 120, 123, 125; 429a13–18:
82, 111; 429a26: 112; 429a27f: 134; 429b4–5: 112;
429b7–9: 112, 140; 429b13–17: 144–5; 429b16–22: 140,
146; 430a 1–2: 140; 430 a2–9: 82, 112, 133, 144;
430 a 11–14: 129, 131; 430 a 14–17: 129–30, 134;
430a17–18: 134; 430a19f: 131; 430a22: 134; 430a23:
134; 430a26–7: 135; 430b5f: 130; 430b11–14: 113;
430b14–20: 123, 137; 430b26–30: 123, 136, 138;
430b30–2: 123, 138; 431b12–15: 145; 431b19: 127;
431b28ff: 111; 432a1–3: 112; 432a7f: 141; 432a8–10:
137, 141, 152; 432a15–19: 112; 434b26–30: 122;
435b18–24: 122
De Sensu; 439b8–10: 84; 439b15–18: 132; 439b19ff: 121;
440b18ff: 145; 442b8: 123; 447a9–11: 132; 447b16–18:
113; 447b21ff: 125
De Mem; 450a31ff: 115; 450b25–9: 138; 450b30f: 128;
452b5–7: 116; 452b12: 116; 452b16f: 116
De Insomniis; 459a1–4: 137; 459b11–13: 118; 459b18–21: 119,
121; 460b2–4: 120; 460b20–5: 119; 460b30: 120; 461a4ff:
120; 461b19ff: 116; 461b23–6: 116
De Respiratione; 476a12–15: 331
Historia Animalium; 486a21–5: 313, 318; 486b20–2: 318;
487a11–14: 318; 487a15–20: 317, 323; 487a22–7: 317,
323; 487a31–3: 317; 487 b3–5: 323; 487b14: 317;
487b15–18: 317; 489a8–16: 318; 489a17–19: 318;
489a34: 317; 489b2–4: 317; 489b19ff: 318; 489b23–8:
317, 320, 322, 330; 490a2–4: 317; 490a6–7: 317;
490 a 9–11: 317; 490 a 12–13: 317; 490 b7–14: 317;
490b16ff: 332; 490b19–23: 318, 321, 325; 490b24–7:
319; 490b31f: 318; 491a5ff:
INDEX LOCORUM 403
331; unity of kind 334, 335, 339, 341–4, 345, 347, 357, become 302, 303
367 processes (kinesis) 300–3, 308
Formal problem 60–2, 67–9 see Independence problem Principle of non-contradiction 373–8
forms; and actuality 302; and explanation 305; particular and projectivism 256, 352
general 279–81, 284, 292 quietism 370–2
Fregean 99, 100, 106, 107, 161–3, 165; traditional and signification 2, 25, 52, 78–80, 84, 101, 168, 169; and causation
revisionary 161 52, 103, 147; immediate and mediate 81, 82; and likeness
genera 219–21, 230–3, 238; and differentiae 224, 226–9, 231, 81, 105, 377; and meaning 106, 107; and thought 81,
232, 234–43, 247, 252, 269, 282, 283, 288, 310–15, 104, 105; and understanding 106
318–20, 323, 324, 326, 328, 329, 336; and species 219–21
generation and reproduction 313, 318–21, 323, 333, 334, 341
goatstag 25, 27, 28, 41, 89, 90, 102 see names, empty
historia 326, 328, 329
hypotheses 72–6 see also theses
imagination (phantasia) 119, 120, 137–9, 141
Independence; assumption 59; problem 58–60 see also Formal
problem
induction 268–70
intelligibility, of the world 263, 264, 349–52 see active intellect
Kantians 11, 13, 15, 372; democratic 10, 349; elitist 10n21,
13, 351–3 see no-priority thesis
knowledge 65–7, 149, 152; accidental and non-accidental 34,
35, 99, 100; and substitution 95–100; knowing which
108, 139, 147, 148, 158, 159, 162, 164; scientific 51, 52
liberal interpretation 28, 30–2, 43, 77; and restrictive
interpretation 28–30, 32–3
light 131, 133, 134, 144, 145
likening 108, 110, 114–16, 165
locomotion 313, 317, 319, 323, 331, 334, 335
logical level 253, 254, 279n9, 286n25, 375–6
matter 291, 308, 338, 339; and form 253, 257, 278, 289, 295,
296, 304, 307
material cause 343
meaning 1, 2, 4, 8, 15, 19, 106, 109, 372 see also signification,
names
memory 149, 151
Meno's paradox 76
more and less, the 314
names; compound 88–90, 91, 107, 147; empty 89, 91, 92; and
existence 92–5, 102, 103; meaning of 107; simple 80–7,
89, 95, 101, 104, 107, 147, 167
no-priority thesis 15, 143, 144, 256, 260n29, 262, 350 see
Kantians
nous 250, 265–72, 366 see active intellect
perception 110, 112; accidental 125; analogy with thought
110–12, 129, 135, 138–43, 145, 146; common 124–8,
130, 156; and content 118; and discrimination 112, 117,
153; and error 118–24; and form 117, 128, 142; and its
medium 129, 132, 133; and physiology 117, 118, 121,
122, 128; proper 115–18, 128, 130, 131, 156
Platonism 13–15, 249, 266, 270–2, 350–3, 355–7, 363, 372
potentiality; and actuality 295, 296, 298–302, 304; to be and to
408 GENERAL INDEX
Kosman, L. 270n49, 296n44 Ross, D. 23n2, 26n6, 29n12, 31n15, 69n1642, 47n35, 55n42,
Kretzmann, N. 81n5 150n7, 181n5, 211n24, 222n1–3, 242n23, 264n37, 267n44,
Kripke, S. 6n4, 10n19, 11n22, 13, 13n28, n31, 14, 15n38, 286n25
16n40 Salmon, N. 6n5, 13, 13n30, 14n35, 99n39, 100n40, 107n53
Kung, J. 18n47 Sambursky, S. 133n42
Lagerlund, H. 387n15 Scaltsas, T. 298n46
Landor, B. 74n25 Schiffer, S. 366n31
Lear, J. 134n48, 146n70 Sidelle, A. 6n6
LeBlond, J. 247n5, 305 Sellars, W. 280n12, 296n44
Lennon, K. 148n3, 364n24 Slomkowski, P. 190n17
Lennox, J. 240n21, 242n23, 319n14, 325n28, 329n34, 336n43 Smiley, T. 93n29
Lesher, J. 150n8 Smith, R. 216n29
Letoublon, F. 100n41 Sorabji, R. 29n12, 69n16, 249n6, 257n23–5
Lewis, D. 13n31 Spellman, L. 96n32
Lewis, F. 96n32, 255n17, 295n40–1 Themistius 27n8, 46n33
Lloyd, A. 280n12 Tselemanis, P. 81n5
Lloyd, G. 154n17, 346n52 Wedin, M. 93n30, 137n55, 140n61
Locke, J. 3, 5, 10n20, 13, 169n58, 170, 356–7, 364–7, 371 Whiting, J. 280n12–13
Mackie, J. 10n20 Wiggins, D. 12n25, 249n7, 369n38
Mackie, P. 6n6 Witt, C. 279n12
Marcus, R. B. 5n2 Woods, M. 284n20
Matthews, G. 96n32 Xenocrates 185–92, 254–5, 256n21
Mendell, H. 215n28 Zabarella, J. 29n12, 208n20
McDowell, J. 17n42, 84n14, 106n49, 162n38–9
McGinn, C. 17n42, 163n41
McKirahan, R. 249n6
Millikan, R. 121n19, 122n21
Modrak, D. 264n37
Moravcsik, J. 305n60
Morrow, G. 36n21
Mueller, I. 36n21, 146n70
Nicolopoulos, P. 46n31
Nicomachus 270n49
Nussbaum, M. 128n34
Orenstein, A. 92n27
Owen, G. 102n43, 103n36, 254n14
Pacius, J. 232, 267n44
Parker, R. 324n26
Patterson, R. 387n15
Patzig, G. 279n12, 286n25
Pears, D. 54n41
Pellegrin, P. 329n34
Peterson, S. 97n36–7
Philolaus 154n17
Philoponus 27n8, 46n33, 133n42
Plato 13, 81n5, 107n54, 250–1, 256n21, 350–3, 357, 363
Preus, A. 329n34
Proclus 36n21, 270n51
Putnam, H. 5–7, 9–11, 17n42, 142n64, 148n2, 152n14,
166n48, 173–4, 341n49, 346n53
Quine, W. Van 3, 5n2, 354–7, 386n12
Rorty, R. 289n30