Coming To Terms With Images Visual Studi
Coming To Terms With Images Visual Studi
Coming To Terms With Images Visual Studi
KREŠIMIR PURGAR
Art history has lost its exclusivity over the interpretation of paintings
1
It is interesting to note that Keith Moxey attributes to Erwin Panofsky a different
role in the development of the contemporary study of visual culture than that at-
tributed to him by Antonio Somaini (2006) or Horst Bredekamp (2003), as we
shall see a little later. The paradigm shift, according to Moxey, can be discerned
much later, with art historians like Georges Didi–Huberman: “Whereas Panofsky
and Baxandall set the work against, or into, the context in which it was produced—
approaching the object of analysis as if it were inert and in need of ‘explanation’
through reference to circumstance that are more stable and less opaque—Didi–
Huberman regards the work as an active principle, one capable of generating its
own significance” (Moxey, 2008: 135). To this end, Moxey quotes Didi–Huber-
man, from a passage where the French philosopher clearly takes on what we may
call “visual studies attitude”: “One must not claim that there are historical objects
relevant to this or that duration: one must understand that in each historical object,
all times encounter one another, collide, or base themselves plastically on one an-
other, bifurcate, or even become entangled with one another” (Didi–Huberman,
2003: 131).
64 Chapter Three
and sculptures because, during the second half of the twentieth century,
artworks started to become part of vernacular culture—of the domain for
which they were not intended. This happened not as a consequence of the
problematic methodologies of visual studies or any other established or
emergent theory, but because art history dealt with historically important
objects that popular culture could not or would not do without. Even if
Davey did not come to the conclusion that it was not for visual studies to
undermine the ontogenetic specificity of artistic objects,2 I think his in-
sight that artwork needs to speak hermeneutically for itself while address-
ing the fact that the spectator deserves attention. I also find interesting his
admonition that visual studies may fall victim to its unconstrained faith in
the power of subjectivity. He writes:
In the case of the artwork, the spectator is subject to its address. In con-
trast, the designed object if treated as a sign or symptom of visual culture is
subject to the methodological regime of the spectator. The question then
arises as to how critical of reflexive methodology visual studies can be?
(Davey: 146).
2
The concept of ontogenetic difference between artistic objects and non–artistic
objects comes eventually down to the most elementary and the most difficult ques-
tion, “impossible” to answer: what is art? An even more complex question is what
is contemporary art? Moreover, how do we make aesthetical distinctions between
different types of object, not just inside and outside the realm of art, but between
various objects that unequivocally qualify to carry that label? The criterion of “in-
tended purpose” that Nicholas Davey proposes is certainly universal and one of the
most accepted distinctions between art and non–art objects. One improvised defini-
tion might then be: If it is created to be art, then it is art. If it is created to be some-
thing else, then it can’t be art. But the institutional theory of art, with George
Dickie, for example, as one of its most important representatives, puts the defini-
tion of art differently: “A work of art in a classificatory sense is (1) an artifact (2) a
set of the aspects of which has had conferred upon it the status of candidate for
appreciation by some person or persons acting on behalf of a certain social institu-
tion (the art world). The second condition of the definition makes use of four vari-
ously interconnected notions: (1) acting on behalf of institution, (2) conferring of
status, (3) being a candidate, and (4) appreciation.” (Dickie, 2007: 431). Dickie’s
definition does not disqualify the criterion of the intended purpose, but shows that
the status of art can be institutionally established just as it can be individually pro-
claimed. But it can be neither established nor denigrated disciplinarily. Discipli-
nary analysis of an object as artwork (in art history, feminist theory, postcolonial
studies, visual studies, etc.) comes only after any particular object has already been
accredited with the status of art object. Therefore, its status as art object cannot
depend on how it is valued within or by any single discipline. In other words, the
intended purpose—accepted as the classificatory term—cannot be undone.
Coming to Terms with Images: Visual Studies and Beyond 65
For one thing, Davey has certainly helped practitioners of visual stud-
ies to reflect more on the ontological fundamentals of their own discipline,
or at least to be acquainted with what never really seemed its most con-
testable ground. Let us deal with the possible consequences of his last as-
sertion: it implies that it is a regular procedure in visual studies, firstly, to
dismiss the difference between incommensurable types of visual artefacts
(“the ontogenetic fallacy”); secondly, once that has been done, every visu-
al object becomes part of (a presumably indiscriminating) visual culture
and thirdly, having entered into the domain of visual culture, artifacts are
being subjected to the free will of the spectator. Accepting the possibility
that different scholars may and will have different understandings of what
visual studies is or should be, my opinion is that this emerging discipline
can account for the second stage of the mentioned process only, namely
that every visual artifact is inevitably part of visual culture conceived in
the broadest sense.
The problem with the third stage, the primacy of the spectator, is not
that it is wrong as such, but that it does not apply to visual studies insofar
as the new discipline specifically questions what Keith Moxey calls the
“politics of identity” (2011: 121), positioning itself between the artifact
and the scopic regime understood as ideological construct. It was the in-
tention of poststructuralism to equate subjectivity, identity and gaze in
order to empower specific groups within contemporary societies so that
they could reject normative or prescriptive theories and behaviors. The
pioneering work in different areas of thought performed in this respect by
Michel Foucault, Laura Mulvey, Judith Butler and many others is all too
familiar. The question is whether visual studies subscribes to the politics
of identity and spectatorship as a presumption of the ideological, sexual or
geographical determination of the given artifact or differs from critical
theory inasmuch as it is very “visual studies” to reject such presumptions?
3
To understand fully the scope of what is apparently a very lengthy text, it may be
helpful to note that Sandywell’s theses appear as the final text in a book he himself
coedited with Richard Heywood and in which Davey’s article also appears. In this
way we may read Sandywell’s thesis not just as individual assertions on the fate
and future of the discipline of visual studies, but also as a sort of a game inspired
by sometimes more implicit and other times less implicit commentaries to the the-
ses of other authors presented in the collection.
4
The context of Sandywell’s “historicity thesis” has certainly contributed to the
vivid discussion of some time ago on whether art history and accompanying sub-
disciplines (like the traditional “discursive” variant of iconology) should be held
responsible for what has been happening in the field of visual culture or the newly
recognized field should have its own dedicated theory. Together with certain firm
beliefs that insisted on visual studies remaining linked with art history in some
respects (Hal Foster, in Smith, 2008a), it was almost unanimously claimed (Mitch-
ell, 1994; Elkins, 2003a; Bal, 2003, among others) that leaving art history out of
visual studies has led to a kind of visual essentialism—the primacy of the visual in
itself—that has consequently drawn particular attention to many non–artistic ob-
jects and therefore dismissed the importance of (art) history. The consequences of
such a move, though, remained open, with differing conclusions. Mieke Bal, in her
text “Visual essentialism and the object of visual culture”, says that “rather than
describing concrete artefacts and their provenance, as art history would do, or de-
scribing whole cultures, as anthropology would, visual culture studies must criti-
cally analyse the junctures and articulations of visual culture and undermine their
natural persistence” (Bal, 2003: 18–19). At the same time, she argues against “vis-
ual essentialism”, or the tendency in visual culture studies “that either proclaims
the visual ‘difference’—read ‘purity’—of images or expresses a desire to stake out
the turf of visuality against media or semiotic systems” (Bal: 3).
Coming to Terms with Images: Visual Studies and Beyond 67
ing, forms and rituals that are destined to be overtaken by future, hitherto
unanticipated acts of meaning” (Sandywell: 650), the notion of any kind of
unification of knowledge, let alone universalist epistemes based on the
traditional demarcation between disciplines, is highly problematic. In spite
of that, the modern history of humanities “reveals how every discipline
that has tried to conceptually delimit vision—philosophy, aesthetics, psy-
chology, sociology, poetics, phenomenology and so on—implicitly draws
upon particular images of imageing and thereby imagination” (651).
Sandywell argues, following very clearly the fundamental paths of the
social–critical wing of visual studies (Mirzoeff, 2002, 2011a, 2011b; Stur-
ken and Cartwright, 2006) that any critically engaged programme of visual
studies must recognize the “plurality and heterogeneity of practices of
seeing”; insofar as “individuals see with their senses, cultures ‘envision’
through their collective memories, metaphors and technical diagrams. Ra-
ther than naturalizing ‘seeing’ we should think in terms of changing ‘scop-
ic regimes’” (Sandywell: 651–2).
On the same path, but with the inclusion of the deeper historical time-
line, is the standpoint of Antonio Somaini, who thinks that study of visual
culture should not be confused with its imminent effects—spectacularization,
simulation, panopticism, control society—even though their discernment
and analytical elaboration are, not without reason, almost automatically
attributed to the disciplinary field of visual studies (Somaini, 2006: 27).
According to him, visual studies should be “a genealogical enterprise”,
because everything that enters into its analytical scope has a history of its
own, the contemporary transformations and epistemological ruptures that
inevitably occur in transhistorical enterprises notwithstanding. Pointing to
a historical timeline on which contemporary visual culture can be defined
as year zero, he traces the origins of the interdisciplinary study of the visu-
al as far back as modern art history—to an era when discourses on the
regimes of visibility had been established:
5
In the study of images, numerous attempts have been made in order to better
grasp their manifold nature. The “new art history”, as one of the pioneering efforts
made in that direction, provoked significant turbulence in the discipline of art his-
tory and proved to be a successful attempt to “modernize vision” within the estab-
lished politics of artistic value. Although never officially proclaimed as a distinct
sub-discipline within traditional art history, the inclusivity of its methods, which
embraced the emergent understanding that all visual phenomena influence art to
some extent, meant the new art history was far from not being recognized or meta–
theoretically acknowledged. The best approach to its differences and specificities
in comparison to traditional methods within the discipline is through individual
authors’ approaches, as in Baxandall (1972), Alpers (1983) or Moxey (1991, 1994,
2001 and 2013). Excellent attempts to conceptualize and delimit the field are to be
found in Bal and Bryson (1991) and Harris (2001).
Coming to Terms with Images: Visual Studies and Beyond 69
inquiry’, ‘methodic perspective’ and the like now takes centre–stage as part
of a radically reflective hermeneutics of cultural orderings” (Sandywell:
655).
The crucial point, then, of understanding what visual studies is and
which epistemological direction it is going to take would be to try to an-
swer the question of on behalf of whom this new discipline is speaking, or
rather who is speaking through it: is it a spectator who is always, as Nicho-
las Davey contends, under the influence of various determinants that exist
independently of the object of study and therefore make it impossible for
him (the spectator) to grasp the artwork’s address (Davey: 147)? Is it
composed of social and cultural formations, that are historically unstable
and that ask us to constantly shift from the Cartesian belief in the power of
images and visibility at large to the contemporary fear of images and of
their power to control and monitor us (Jay: 1993)? Or is it the image or
artifact itself (whether “artistic” or “designed”) that we should mainly ac-
count for whenever there is a dispute over meanings and interpretations?
Concerning the last question, we should bear in mind that Mitchell’s ty-
pology of images, from his Iconology (1984), as well as the concept of
“metapictures” from Picture Theory (1994), were both attempts at paving
the way for the new hermeneutics of seeing, where images alone would
have the necessary abilities to not just address the spectator, but to “speak”
for themselves. The position that visual studies has eventually taken is
based on the assumption that images speak through themselves as well as
emanating meaning through the spectator and the culture that he or she is
immersed in. The project of visual studies aims at clarifying the radical
impossibility of either subsuming the shifting notions of contemporary
visual epistemologies in a single disciplinary frame or taking immutable
sides in the discussion of how images generate meaning.
Mitchell’s distinction between the meanings of the words image and pic-
ture, Sebastian Egenhofer states that a “picture exists or, rather, persists
through time. The image, however, is always only given in the present of
the beholder. It is the beholder’s gaze that awakens the phenomenon in the
existing material” which is the reason why images (in the widest sense)
are ontologically settled in a kind of twofold “scandalous” and constantly
shifting mode of being characterized by “nonsynchronicity” (Egenhofer,
2013: 190). This nonsynchronicity means that images can only be com-
prehended taking into account the historical and conceptual gap existing
between the time of the construction of the singular image and the time of
the perception of it. Since we are never able to grasp an image’s “immedi-
ate present” and its “sensual evidence”, this shifting character, this “in-
commensurability”, is for Egenhofer the true nature of the image, definite-
ly something more like a happening than “only” a being. Keith Moxey
points to the same thing, stating that
the experience of the image is distinct from the time that surrounds it. A
work can stop us in our tracks, so to speak, and insist that we acknowledge
a form of perception that differs from that of the context in which it ap-
pears. [the idea of] Difference thus attempts to capture the perceptual awa-
reness that temporalities precede our presence and depend on it (Moxey,
2013: 5).
low the path established by the linear logic from creation to consumption,
as consumption is a feature of “symbolic exchange”, in which the differ-
ence between objects (whether “artistic” or “designed”) is replaced with
their semiotic equivalents (Baudrillard, 1976). Signs cannot exit the semi-
otic order and regain the status they had prior to meaning generating pro-
cesses.
This linear development of the qualities of images is clearly absent
from the “Seven Theses on Visual Culture” proposed by Barry Sandywell,
making their fragmentary structure a more nuanced theoretical tool. How-
ever, what is shared by Curtis and Sandywell is their insistence on the un-
stable character of the artifact, its susceptibility to various determinants of
culture, geography and time. In both approaches, images and artifacts are
explained more like receptors of different influences than emanators of
specific intrinsic qualities, thus sharing a firm anti–essentialist stance. The
problem, then, is how we conceptualize and make use of these mecha-
nisms of transaction, which are capable of transforming any kind of visual
communication into politically charged utterances understandable to all.
One of the functions of visual studies should be precisely to uncover
“conditions of visibility [that] are not themselves visible” (Sandywell:
656), because knowing how cultural formations are made, how they trans-
form vision into visuality, how one has to deal with the everyday transac-
tions of images/artifacts, are all symptoms of the economy of pleasure and
should be dealt with in political as much as in artistic or aesthetic terms.
Sandywell shows a great deal of faith in visual studies’ ability to perform
precisely this kind of social anamnesis, where visual artifacts should take
the role of the main antagonist and allow us to know not primarily what
and how we see—as this has already been performed by other disciplines,
such as psychoanalytic theory, semiotics or cognitive sciences—but how
we come to see and not to see the realities of everyday life. The crucial
problem for visual studies, then, as I stated earlier, is the following: should
it let images and artifacts speak for themselves, or should it speak on be-
half of them? Do the images alone, or does the study of images, have the
potentiality for the new visual rhetoric that Sandywell envisions as one of
the key transdisciplinary domains within the new visual studies?
ical status of images and artifacts in visual studies comes to the fore: if this
discipline, as I argue, claims to have retained what Nicholas Davey calls
the “ontogeny of the visual”, and if images flow in a linear fashion from
the moment of creation to the moment of their immersion into the socially
determined realm of “imagery”, where they become open to every possible
interpretation—as Curtis contends—how exactly can “what has been made
socially and historically be ‘unmade’ through critique and social transfor-
mation”, as Sandywell would like it to? Is it not perhaps the case that the
process of the unmaking of the meanings and statuses of the image or arti-
fact can only be carried out by dismissing the ontogenetic difference be-
tween art and non–art, a difference visual studies should subscribe to un-
less it wants to be accused of the “ontogenetic fallacy”? The paradox is
contained in the following: on the one hand visual studies contends that
images should freely cross disciplinary boundaries, that popular TV series
and masterpieces of art should be explained in the same context of con-
temporary visuality (Elkins, 2003a) and that meaning is not intrinsic to
any visual artifact, and hence cannot be explained in terms of “natural
consciousness”, as Egenhofer has demonstrated. But at the same time, it is
not the artifact itself that can perform this multidisciplinary and transdisci-
plinary critique, hidden within the contingent power of images that visual
studies wishes to awake.
The meanings of images could maybe be undone, reversed, reformulat-
ed or situated in a completely different location within the fabric of social
interactions, but the operations required to activate these mechanisms can-
not come from within images themselves, as it is not they that are able to
start the operation of reformulation: it is the power of critique of images
that ignites the power of images. In my opinion, this statement is not just
the foundation of the new visual studies, but also of the pictorial turn and
several theoretical approaches that have gained prominence over the last
couple of decades. The only response to the admonition of Nicholas Da-
vey about the methodology of visual studies and its general neglect of dif-
ferences in the values and epistemological levels of images is to face visu-
al studies with its own genealogies and the ideologies that have shaped
over time what still seems to be contestable or at least unknown territory.
One of the recurring topics in relation to the self–legitimization and
self–reflection of visual studies is the question what is an image? The par-
adoxical nature of the discipline contained in the mentioned twofold paral-
lel process developed out of the attempt to demarcate the area of study on
the one hand, together with an attempt to define the principal objects of
study on the other. It was argued during the Stone Summer Seminar, orga-
nized by James Elkins in Chicago in 2008, that, in order to resolve this
Coming to Terms with Images: Visual Studies and Beyond 75
parallelism, in which the discipline and its object may never come to terms
with each other, continuing to deal with strictly separate sets of problems,
it would be necessary, if not plausible, to answer the essential or essential-
ist questions about images, then at least to create a sort of taxonomical
grid in which different kinds of image would strive to find their ontologi-
cal ground.6 One of the assessors of the seminar’s discussions, Klaus
Sachs–Hombach, himself an author of different attempts to classify imag-
es and an initiator of the extremely influential German wing of the general
theory of images, commented that nobody would doubt that it is quite im-
possible to differentiate and classify images according to clear–cut met-
alevel categories and asked: why would we need such categories to begin
with? Sachs–Hombach points to what I consider to be a very symptomatic
issue in relation to the doubts existing around visual studies when he says
that “within art history we have different theories of art, but we do not
question the status of art history or art science”. The reason why the lack
of a consistent taxonomy of images is still considered to be a problem has
to do with the fact that “image science is not yet established as a proper
academic science” (Sachs–Hombach, 2011: 229). He then enlists “five
tentative theses” that may help to institute a viable image science (Bildwis-
senschaft) and which I give here in a very digested form:
6
One of the most recent attempts (one of enviable breadth) to tackle those issues
was the seminar organized by James Elkins within the activities of the Stone
Summer Institute in Chicago in 2008, titled interrogatively What is an Image?
Over seven days, the most prominent scholars from the theory and history of art,
philosophy and other related disciplines gathered to discuss the proverbial cluster
of questions on the ontologies and modes of being of images. The subsequently
published volume (What is an Image, edited by James Elkins, The Pennsylvania
State University Press, 2011) gathered the standpoints of the participants (Mitchell,
Boehm, Mondzain etc.) and was accompanied by various assessments from theo-
rists who were not present at the seminar but later on made their commentaries on
topics raised during discussion and also presented additional theoretical opinions
on issues not always directly raised by the participants in the seminar. Incredibly
heterogeneous in viewpoints and scope, but still extremely informative, the volume
has proven to be a veridical reflection of the basic impossibility of answering the
question of the ontology of images and, in my opinion, remains a good example of
fluidity in theoretical conceptions within and about visual studies.
76 Chapter Three
Even though they are more elaborate in the original form, if still admit-
tedly “sketchy”, to use Sachs–Hombach’s own word, there is a line of
thought discernible in the five statements that points to the conception of
image studies as a kind of anti–theory, one that is left to be shaped and
paradoxically explained by what it studies instead of trying to conceptual-
ize its object in the tradition of critical theory and the identity politics that
flourished along its path. Few questions appear immediately: what theory
would not want to at least address, if not fully explain, every phenomenon
that it may find interesting? What epistemology would deliberately con-
fine its universe to the restricted horizon of knowledge only because a
more established discipline already claims some of the objects that a new-
er discipline wants to account for? What discipline would introduce itself
without a disruptive redefinition of existing theoretical and terminological
apparatuses? Or, are precisely these tactics of indetermination the only
way to establish a new structure of knowledge with the image as a consti-
tutive element, an element that every ideology, artistic style, fashion trend
and visual artifact whatsoever claims as its own?
To deal properly with what appears to be the ontological ground of im-
age science, we must recall the already foundational in–disciplinarity of
visual studies that Thomas Mitchell opted for in his text “Interdiscplinarity
and Visual Culture”, where he stated that we must make a distinction be-
tween “top–down” interdisciplinarity, a “comparative, structural formation
that aims to know the overarching system or conceptual totality within
which all the disciplines are related” and the kind of “compulsory” inter-
disciplinarity characteristic of studies in gender, sexuality and ethnicity
that is “improvised out of a new theoretical object and a political project
with its attendant urgencies. They are knowledge projects, but they also
have more or less explicit moral and political agendas” (Mitchell, 1995:
540–44). In his more recent, reassessed idea of it he stated that, no matter
Coming to Terms with Images: Visual Studies and Beyond 77
iconicity is not a quality of the object, but of a way of looking at the world
which not only implies that any object can possibly become an image, but
also—inversely— that every image we are looking at can only be seen as
an image because it is rooted in a pervasive iconicity which serves as a ma-
trix for potential images to come (Alloa, 2011: 149).
If this is true, he adds, then the classical distinction that ruled western
ontology, the distinction between a difference in degree and a difference in
essence, will effectively collapse. From the point of such a “phenomeno-
logical turn”, this would not raise just the problem of philosophy losing its
foundation and firm theoretical ground; the whole modern project of im-
ages, informed by functions, meanings and concepts of representation,
would then lose its specificity, its “sovereign realm”, a domain where the
rules of iconicity alone once governed and where the idea of a universal
Coming to Terms with Images: Visual Studies and Beyond 79
7
Emanuel Alloa has subsequently elaborated more on his thesis on “intensities” in
an article where this new theoretical urgency is explained in continuation of a dis-
course about three possible impulses inherent to the iconic turn: archeological,
poetical and epistemic. In this way, he suggests that the need for the re–working of
traditional concepts of the image has to be part of the parallel process of the re–
working of image theories as well. According to Alloa, such a process may consist
of the redefinition of iconology as “symptomatology”, and analysis based on the
disciplinary “extensity” of visual phenomena may become an exercise in “intensi-
ties”, while firm indications and values may be better explained as contingencies,
as in the relation of “indicative” and “subjunctive” (Alloa, 2012: 144–159).
80 Chapter Three
References
van Alphen, Ernst (2005) “‘What History, Whose History, History to
What Purpose?’ Notions of History in Art History and Visual Studies”;
in Journal of Visual Culture, vol. 4, no. 2: 8.
Alpers, Svetlana (1983) The Art of Describing: Dutch Art in the Seven-
teenth Century; Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Alloa, Emmanuel (2011) “Intensive, not Extensive”; in James Elkins (ed.)
What is an Image, The Pennsylvania State University Press.
—. (2012) “Iconic Turn. Alcune chiavi di svolta”; in Lebenswelt no. 2.
—. (2013) “Visual Studies in Byzantium: A Pictorial Turn avant la lettre”;
in Journal of Visual Culture, no. 12: 3.
Bal, Mieke (2003) “Visual essentialism and the object of visual culture”;
in Journal of Visual Culture 2: 1.
Bal, Mieke and Bryson, Norman (1991) “Semiotics and art history”; in Art
Bulletin 73 (2).
Baxandall, Michael (1972) Painting and Experience in Fifteenth–Century
Italy: A Primer in the Social History of Pictorial Style; Oxford: Clar-
endon Press.
Belting, Hans (1997) Likeness and Presence. A History of Image before
the Era of Art; Chicago: The Chicago University Press.
—. (2005) “Image, Medium, Body: A New Approach to Iconology”, in
Critical Inquiry, Vol. 31, No. 2.
Boehm, Gottfried (1995) “Ikonische Wendung”; in G. Boehm (ed.) Was
ist ein Bild; München: Wilhelm Fink.
—. (2006) “Unbestimmtheit: Zur Logik des Bildes”; in Bernd Hüppauf
and Christoph Wulf (ed.) Bild und Einbildungskraft, Munich: Wilhelm
Fink.
Boehm, Gottfried and Mitchell W.J.T. (2009) “Pictorial Versus Iconic
Turn: Two Letters”; in Culture, Theory and Critique, 50 2–3.
Bredekamp, Horst (2003) “A Neglected Tradition? Art History as ‘Bild-
wissenschaft’”; in Critical Inquiry, Vol. 29, no. 3.
Bryson, Norman (1988) “The Gaze in the Expanded Field”; in Hal Foster
(ed.) Vision and Visuality; Seattle: Bay Press.
Castoriadis, Cornelius (1987) The Imaginary Institution of Society; Cam-
bridge: Polity Press.
Cometa, Michele (2008) “Iconocrash”; in Roberta Coglitore (ed.) Cultura
visuale, paradigmi a confronto; Palermo: Duepunti edizioni.
Crary, Jonathan (1992) Techniques of the Observer. On Vision and Mo-
dernity in the Nineteenth Century; Cambridge Mass. and London: MIT
Press.
Coming to Terms with Images: Visual Studies and Beyond 81
Curtis, Neal (2011) “Three Realms in the Activity of the Image”; in Social
Research, vol. 78, no. 4.
Dadejík, Ondřej and Stejskal, Jakub (eds.) (2010) The Aesthetic Dimen-
sion of Visual Culture; Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars
Publishing.
Davey, Nicholas (2013) “Hermeneutical Aesthetics and an Ontogeny of
the Visual”; in Ian Heywood and Barry Sandywell (eds.) A Handbook
of Visual Culture, London: Berg.
Derrida, Jacques (1978) “The Dangerous Supplement”; in Of Grammatol-
ogy, translated by Gayatri Spivak. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Uni-
versity Press.
Dickie, George (2007) “What is Art? An Institutional Analysis”; in Steve
Cahn and Aaron Meskin (eds.) Aesthetics. A Comprehensive Antholo-
gy, London: Blackwell.
Didi–Huberman, Georges (2003) “Has the Epistemological Transforma-
tion Taken Place?”; in Michael Zimmermann (ed.) The Art Historian:
National Traditions and Institutional Practices, translated by Vivian
Rehberg; Williamstown, MA: Clark Art Institute.
Elkins, James (2001) The Domain of Images; Cornell University Press.
—. (2003a) Visual Studies. A Skeptical Introduction; London: Routledge.
—. (2003b) “Nine Modes of Interdisciplinarity for Visual Studies”; in
Journal of Visual Culture, 2003–2.
—. (2011) (ed.) What is an Image; The Pennsylvania State University
Press.
Grau, Oliver (2003) Virtual Art. From Illusion to Immersion; translated by
Gloria Custance, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Harris, Jonathan (2001) The New Art History: A Critical Introduction;
London and New York: Routledge.
Jay, Martin (1993) Downcast Eyes: The Denigration of Vision in Twenti-
eth–Century French Thought; Berkeley: University of California Press.
—. (2002) “That visual turn: The advent of visual culture”; in Journal of
Visual Culture, 1(1).
—. (2002) “Cultural relativism and the visual turn”; in Journal of Visual
Culture 1(3).
John of Damascus (1975) Contra imaginum calumniatores orationes tres,
ed. B Kotter; Schriften des Johannes von Damaskos, vol. 5. Berlin:
Walter de Gruyter.
Lacan, Jacques (1977 a) Ecrits: A Selection; London: Routledge.
—. (1977b) The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis; London:
Penguin Books.
Latour, Bruno (2002) “What is Iconoclash? Or is There a World Beyond
82 Chapter Three
the Image Wars?”; in Bruno Latour and Peter Weibel (ed.) Iconoclash
– Beyond the Image Wars in Science, Religion and Art, Karlsruhe:
Center for Art and Media.
Mirzoeff, Nicholas (ed.) (2002) The Visual Culture Reader, second edi-
tion; London and New York: Routledge.
—. (2009) An Introduction to Visual Culture; London and New York:
Routledge.
—. (2011a) An Introduction to Visual Culture second edition; London and
New York: Routledge.
—. (2011b) The Right to Look. A Counterhistory of Visuality; Durham:
Duke University Press.
Mitchell, W.J.T. (1986) Iconology: Image, Text, Ideology; Chicago: Uni-
versity of Chicago Press.
—. (1994) Picture Theory: Essays on Verbal and Visual Representation;
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
—. (1995) “Interdisciplinarity and Visual Culture”; in Art Bulletin no. 77
(4).
—. (1998) Last Dinosaur Book; Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
—. (2002) “Showing Seeing: A Critique of Visual Culture”; in Journal of
Visual Culture (1).
—. (2005) What do Pictures Want; Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
—. (2005a) “There Are No Visual Media”; in Journal of Visual Culture 4
(2)
Moxey, Keith (1991), “Semiotics and the social history of art”; in New
Literary History, 22 (4).
—. (1994) The Practice of Theory. Poststructuralism, Cultural Politics,
and Art History; Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press.
—. (2001) The Practice of Persuasion. Paradox and Power in Art History;
Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press.
—. (2011) “Lost in Translation”; in James Elkins (ed.) What is an Image,
The Pennsylvania State University Press.
Nancy, Jean–Luc (2005) The Image – the Distinct; New York: Fordham
University Press.
Pinotti, Andrea (2008) “Stile e verità. Una prospettiva riegliana”; in En-
gramma, no. 64, April–May.
Rancière, Jacques (2009) “Do Pictures Really Want to Live”; in Culture,
Theory and Critique, 50 2.
Rorty, Richard (1967/1992) (ed.) The Linguistic Turn – Essays in Philo-
sophical Method; Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Sachs–Hombach, Klaus (2011) “Theories of Images. Five Tentative The-
ses”; in James Elkins (ed.) What is an Image, The Pennsylvania State
Coming to Terms with Images: Visual Studies and Beyond 83
University Press.
Sandywell, Barry (2013) “Seven Theses on Visual Culture: Towards a
Critical–Reflexive Paradigm for the New Visual Studies”; in Ian Hey-
wood and Barry Sandywell (eds.) A Handbook of Visual Culture, Lon-
don: Berg.
Smith, Marquard (2008) “Visual Studies, Historiography and Aesthetics”,
Interview with Keith Moxey; in Marquard Smith Visual Culture Stud-
ies: Interviews with Key Thinkers; London: Sage.
Smith, Marquard (2008a) Visual Culture Studies. Interviews with Key
Thinkers; London: Sage.
Somaini, Antonio (2006) “On the ‘Scopic Regime’”; in Leitmotiv, no. 5.
Sturken, Marita and Cartwright, Lisa (2001) Practices of Looking: An In-
troduction to Visual Culture; New York: Oxford University Press.