Chap 2
Chap 2
Projective planes
principles developed at this time still form the bases of most computer created
photorealistic images even nowadays. The basic idea is simple. To produce a
two-dimensional drawing of a three dimensional scene fix the position of the
canvas and the position of the viewers eye in space. For each point on the
canvas consider a line from the viewers eye through this point and plot a dot
according to the object that your ray meets first (compare Figure 2.1).
By this procedure a line in object space is in general mapped to a line in
the picture. One may think of this process in the following way: Any point in
object space is connected to the viewpoint by a line. The intersection of this
line with the canvas gives the image of the point. For any line in object space
we consider the plane spanned by this line and the viewpoint (if the line does
not pass through the viewpoint this plane is unique). The intersection of this
plane and the canvas plane is the image of the line. This simple construction
principle implies that – almost obviously – incidences of points and lines are
preserved by the mapping process and that lines are again mapped to lines.
Parallelism, orthogonality, distances and angles, however, are not preserved
by this process. So it may happen that lines that were parallel in object space
are mapped to concurrent lines in the image space. Two pictures in which this
construction principles are carried out in a vary strict sense are reproduced
in Figure 2.2.
14 2 Projective planes
A!
B!
C!
C !!
PSfrag replacements !!
B
A!!
invariant under projection. This two volume book contains fundamental ideas
of projective geometry such as the cross-ratio, perspective, involution and the
circular points at infinity, that we will meet in many situations troughout the
rest of this book. Poncelet was the first one who consequently made use of
elements at infinity which form the basis of all the elegant treatments that we
will encounter later on.
Definition 2.1. A projective plane is a triple (P, L, I). The set P are the
points, and the set L are the lines of the geometry. I ⊆ P × L is an incidence
relation satisfying the following three axioms:
(i) For any two distinct points, there is exactly one line incident with both of
them.
(ii) For any two distinct lines, there is exactly one point incident with both of
them.
(iii)There are four points such that no line is incident with more than two of
them.
2.2 The axioms 17
unique
PSfrag replacements PSfrag replacements
line PSfrag replacements
unique
line line
point unique point such points
such points such points point exist
exist exist
Observe that the first two axioms describe a completely symmetric rela-
tion of points and lines. The second axiom simply states that (without any
exception) two distinct lines will always intersect in a unique point. The first
axiom states that (without any exception) two distinct points will always have
a line joining them. The third axiom merely ensures that the structure is not
a degenerate trivial case in which most of the points are collinear.
It is the aim of this and the following section to give various models for this
axiom system. Let us first see how the usual Euclidean plane can be extended
to a projective plane in a natural way by including elements at infinity. Let
E = (PE , LE , IE ) be the usual Euclidean plane with points PE , lines LE and the
usual incidence relation LE of the euclidean plane. We can easily identify PE
with R2 . Now let us introduce the elements at infinity. For a line l consider the
equivalence class [l] of all lines that are parallel to l. For each such equivalence
class we define a new point p[l] . This point will play the role of the point at
infinity in which all the parallels contained in the equivalence class [l] shall
meet. This point is supposed to be incident with all lines of [l] Furthermore
we define one line at infinity l∞ . All points p[l] are supposed to be incident
with this line. More formally we set:
!
• P = PE ∪ {p[l] ! l ∈ LE },
• L = LE ∪ {l∞ },
! !
• I = IE ∪ {(p[l] , l) ! l ∈ LE } ∪ {(p[l] , l∞ ) ! l ∈ LE }.
It is easy to verify that this system (P, L, I) satisfies the axioms of a
projective plane. Let us start with axiom (ii). Two distinkt lines l1 and l2
have a point in common: If l1 and 2 are non-parallel euclidean lines, then this
intersection is simply their usual euclidean intersection. If they are parallel
it is the corresponding unique point p[l1 ] (which is identical to p[l2 ] ). The
intersection of l∞ with an euclidean line l is the point at infinity p[l] “on”
that line. The second axiom is also easy to check: the unique lines incident
to two euclidean points p1 and p2 is simply the euclidean line between them.
The line that joins a euclidean point p and an infinite point p∞ is the unique
line l through p with the property that p∞ = p[l] . Last but not least the line
18 2 Projective planes
incident to two distinct infinite points is the line at infinity l∞ itself. This
completes the considerations for Axiom (i) and Axiom (ii). Axiom (iii), is
evidently satisfied. For this one has simply to pick four points of an arbitrary
proper rectangle.
Fig. 2.6. Sketch of some lines in the projective extension of euclidean geometry
What is the smallest projective plane? Axiom (iii) tells us that it must
at least contain four points, no three of which are collinear. So let us start
with four points and search for the smallest system of points and lines that
contains these points and at the same time satisfies axioms (i) and (ii). Let
the four points be A, B, C and D. By axiom (ii) any" pair # of these points
has to be connected by a line. This generates exaclty 42 = 6 lines. Axiom
(i) requires that any pair of such lines do intersect. There are exacly three
missing intersections. Namely those of the pairs of lines (AB, CD), (AC, BD)
and (AD, BC). This gives additional three points that must necessarily exist.
Now again axiom (i) requires that any pair of points is joined by a line. The
only pairs of points that are not joined so far are those formed by the lastly
added three points. We can satisfy the axioms by simply adding one line that
contains exactly these three points.
The final construction contains seven points and seven lines and is called
the Fano Plane. There are a few interesting observations that can be made in
this example.
• There are exacly as many lines as there are points in the drawing.
• On each line there is exactly the same number of points (here 3).
• Through each point passes exactly the same number of lines.
Each of these statements generalizes to general finite projective planes, as
the following propositions show. We first fix some notation. ! Let (P, L, I) be
a projective plane. For a line l ∈ L let p(l) =! {p ∈ P !pIl} be the points
on l and for a point p ∈ P let l(p) = {l ∈ L!pIl} be the lines through p.
Furthermore, we agree on a few linguistic conventions. Since in a projective
plane the line l that is at the same time incident to two points p and q is
by axiom (i) uniquely determined we will use a more functional rather tham
set-theoretic language and simply speek of the join of the two points. We will
express this join operation by p ∨ q or by join(p, q). Similarly, we will call the
unique point incident with two lines l and m the meet or intersection of these
lines and denote the corresponding operation by l ∧ m or by meet(l, m). We
also say sat a line l contains a point p if it is incident with it.
20 2 Projective planes
PSfrag replacements
q l
a4
a3
a2 b4 m
a1 b3
b2
b1
p
Fig. 2.8. The proof that all lines have the same number of points.
Lemma 2.1. If for p, q ∈ P and l, m ∈ L we have pIl, qIl, pIm and qIm
then either p = q or l = m.
Proof. Assume that pIl, qIl, pIm and qIm. If p '= q axiom (i) implies that
l = m. )
(
Lemma 2.2. Every line of a projective plane is incident with at least three
points.
Proof. Let l ∈ L be any line of the projective plane and assume on the contrary
that l does contain less than three points. Let a, b, c and d be the points of
Axiom (iii). Assume w.l.o.g. that a and b are not on l. Consider the lines a ∨ b,
a ∨ c, a ∨ d. Since these all pass through a they must be distinct by axiom (iii)
and must by Lemma 2.1 have three distinct intersections with l. )
(
Lemma 2.3. For every point p there is at least one line not incident with p.
Proof. Let p be any point. Let l and m be arbitrary lines. Either one if them
is does not contain p (then we are done), or we have p = l ∧ m. By the last
lemma there is a point pl on l distict from p, and a point pm on m distinct
from p. The join of these two points cannot contain p since this would violate
axiom (i). )
(
Theorem 2.1. Let (P, L, I) be a projective plane with finite sets P and L.
Then there exists a number n ∈ N such that |p(l)| = n + 1 for any l ∈ L and
|l(p)| = n + 1 for any p ∈ P.
Proof. Let l and m be two distinct lines. Assume that l contains k points. We
will prove that both lines contain the same number of points. Let p = l ∧ m
2.3 The smallest projective plane 21
The number n of the last proposition (which was the number of points
on a line minus one) is usually called the order of the projective plane. The
following proposition relates the order and the overall number of points and
lines in a finite projective plane.
Theorem 2.2. Let (P, L, I) be a projective plane with finite sets P and L of
order n. Then we have |P| = |L| = n2 + n + 1.
Proof. The last proposition proved that the number of points on each line is
n + 1 and the number of lines through each point is also n + 1. Let p be any
point of the projective plane. Each of the n + 1 lines through p contains n
additional points. They must all be distinct, since otherwise two of these lines
intersect twice. We have alltogether (n + 1) · n + 1 = n2 + n + 1 points. A
similar count proves that the number of lines is the same. )
(
So far we know two examples of a projective plane. One is the finite Fano
Plane of order 2, the other (infinite example) was the projective extension of
the real numbers. Our next chapter will show, that both can be considered as
special examples of a construction that generates a projective plane for every
number field.