0% found this document useful (0 votes)
169 views3 pages

The Monotone Class Theorem

The document discusses the monotone class theorem and its application. It also discusses integration. 1) The monotone class theorem states that if F is a field of subsets, then the smallest monotone class containing F, M(F), is equal to the sigma-field generated by F, σ(F). 2) The theorem is then applied to show that if two measures μ and ν agree on a field F whose sigma-field is the entire sigma-algebra, and are sigma-finite on F, then μ = ν. 3) The document contrasts Riemann and Lebesgue integration and defines a measurable function.

Uploaded by

sarang
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
169 views3 pages

The Monotone Class Theorem

The document discusses the monotone class theorem and its application. It also discusses integration. 1) The monotone class theorem states that if F is a field of subsets, then the smallest monotone class containing F, M(F), is equal to the sigma-field generated by F, σ(F). 2) The theorem is then applied to show that if two measures μ and ν agree on a field F whose sigma-field is the entire sigma-algebra, and are sigma-finite on F, then μ = ν. 3) The document contrasts Riemann and Lebesgue integration and defines a measurable function.

Uploaded by

sarang
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 3

Measure theory class notes - 1 September 2010, class 7 1

The monotone class theorem


Recall that a monotone class over Ω is a collection of subsets of Ω closed under countable increasing
unions and countable decreasing intersections. M(F ) denotes the smallest monotone class which
includes F .

Theorem (Monotone class theorem). Let F be a field of subsets of Ω. Then M(F ) = σ(F ).

Proof. Clearly M(F ) ⊆ σ(F ), since σ(F ) is a monotone class. To show σ(F ) ⊆ M(F ), we
need to show that M(F ) is a σ-field.
We first show that M(F ) is a field. Since F ⊆ M(F ), ∅ ∈ M(F ). To show that M(F ) is
closed under complementation, let

M0 = {A ∈ M(F ) : Ω \ A ∈ M(F )}

F ⊆ M0 because F ⊆ M(F ) and F is a field. Let {An }∞ n=1 be an increasing sequence of sets in
M0 with union A. Since M(F ) is a monotone class, A ∈ M(F ). Since each An belongs to M0 ,
Ω \ An ∈ M(F ). \
Ω\A= (Ω \ An )
n∈N

and {Ω\An }∞n=1 is a decreasing sequence, so Ω\A ∈ M(F ). Since A ∈ M(F ) and Ω\A ∈ M(F ),
we have A ∈ M0 . M0 is closed under increasing unions, and a similar argument shows that it
is closed under decreasing intersections. M0 is a monotone class and F ⊆ M0 ⊆ M(F ), so
M0 = M(F ). So M(F ) is closed under complementation.
We show that M(F ) is closed under finite intersections in steps. First, fix A ∈ F (only in F , for
now!), and we will show that for all B ∈ M(F ), A ∩ B ∈ M(F ). As usual, let

M0 = {B ∈ M(F ) : A ∩ B ∈ M(F )}

Clearly F ⊆ M0 , since F ⊆ M(F ) and F is a field. Let {Bn }∞


n=1 be an increasing sequence of
sets in M0 whose union is B. Clearly B ∈ M(F ), since M(F ) is a monotone class. We have
that A ∩ Bn ∈ M(F ) for all n, and since
[
A∩B = (A ∩ Bn )
n∈N

and {A ∩ Bn }∞n=1 is an increasing sequence, we have A ∩ B ∈ M(F ). B ∈ M(F ) and A ∩ B ∈


M(F ), so B ∈ M0 . M0 is closed under increasing unions and a similar argument shows that it
is closed under decreasing intersections. So M0 is a monotone class. Since F ⊆ M0 ⊆ M(F ),
we have M0 = M(F ).
We have that for all A ∈ F and B ∈ M(F ), A ∩ B ∈ M(F ). To complete the argument, now
fix C ∈ M(F ). Let
M0 = {D ∈ M(F ) : C ∩ D ∈ M(F )}
By the previous step we know that F ⊆ M0 . By the same argument as before we have that M0
is a monotone class. So M0 = M(F ). Since C was an arbitrary set in M(F ), we have shown
that if C, D ∈ M(F ), then C ∩ D ∈ M(F ).
Measure theory class notes - 1 September 2010, class 7 2

So M(F ) is a field. To show that it is a σ-field, we need to show it is closed under countable
unions. Let {An }∞ ∞
n=1 be a sequence of sets in M(F ). Define {Bn }n=1 ,

n
[
Bn = Am
m=1

{Bn }∞
n=1 is an increasing sequence of sets and each of them is in M(F ) since M(F ) is a field.
S
Since M(F ) is a monotone class, their union, which is n∈N An belongs to M(F ).
M(F ) is a σ-field, and M(F ) = σ(F ).

An application of the monotone class theorem


Theorem. Let Ω be a set and A a σ-field on it. Suppose µ and ν are measures on (Ω, A ). Let
F be a field on Ω such that σ(F ) = A . Suppose µ and ν are σ-finite on F and agree on F .
Then µ = ν.1

Proof. Let {Ωn }n∈N be a disjoint collection of sets in F whose union is Ω and such that each µ(Ωn )
is finite. Since ν(Ωn ) = µ(Ωn ), ν(Ωn ) is also finite. We will show that for all A ∈ A and n ∈ N,

µ(A ∩ Ωn ) = ν(A ∩ Ωn )

Fix n and consider the set


{A ∈ A : µ(A ∩ Ωn ) = ν(A ∩ Ωn )}
This includes F (since A ∩ Ωn ∈ F ) and is a monotone class (since finite measures respect
increasing unions and decreasing intersections), and so includes M(F ) which equals σ(F ) = A .
For any A ∈ A , X X
µ(A) = µ(A ∩ Ωn ) = ν(A ∩ Ωn ) = ν(A)
n∈N n∈N

Directly dealing with sets in a σ-field is often hard - we may not have a nice description of all sets
in the σ-field. The above theorem tells us that to show that two measures are equal on the σ-field,
it suffices to check equality only for sets in a field which generates it (provided the measures are
σ-finite on the field), which is likely to be easier since we may have an explicit description of the
sets in the field.
Note that the measure being σ-finite on the field is important. It is possible to have two σ-finite
measures on (Ω, A ) which agree on F but are not equal: For example, consider (R, B), and let
D1 and D2 be countable dense subsets of R such that D1 ∩ D2 = ∅. Consider µ1 , µ2 : B → [0, ∞]R̄ ,

µ1 (A) = |A ∩ D1 |
µ2 (A) = |A ∩ D2 |

It is easy to see that µ1 and µ2 are measures. µ1 is σ-finite; we can take the cover by finite-measure
sets to be
{{x} : x ∈ D1 } ∪ {R \ D1 }
1
This follows from the uniqueness part of the Carathodory extension theorem, but we give a proof anyway.
Measure theory class notes - 1 September 2010, class 7 3

Similarly, µ2 is also σ-finite. We can take our field F to be all finite disjoint unions of intervals
of the type (a, b]. σ(F ) = B. For A ∈ F , we have µ1 (A) = µ2 (A) = ∞ if A is nonempty and
µ1 (∅) = µ2 (∅) = 0. So µ1 and µ2 agree on F but are not equal (since, for example, µ1 (D2 ) = 0
and µ2 (D2 ) = ∞).

Integration
To define the Riemann integral of a function f : [a, b] → [c, d], we divided [a, b] into small intervals,
and approximated the region under the graph of [a, b] on each of these small intervals by a rectangle.
This way we can approximate the area under the graph of f by the sum of the areas of these thin
rectangles.
Rb If this quantity tends to a number z as the partition of [a, b] becomes finer, we say that
a
f (x)dx = z. To be able to approximate the value of f on a small interval by a single value, we
would like that f does not vary too much on that interval. Riemann integration works well for
continuous functions (and also some other functions like piecewise continuous ones).
Lebesgue integration takes a different approach. Instead of dividing the doman, we divide the
range (say [c, d] as above) into intervals A1 , A2 , . . . An , where n is large, so that each interval is
small. We can pick a point ai in each Ai , and approximate the integral of f by
n
X
ai (length of f −1 (Ai ))
i=1

Note that unlike in the case of Riemann integration, here taking ai as an approximation for any
value in Ai is reasonable, since Ai is a small interval, regardless of what f is! So this approach is
likely to work better, provided we can assign a length to f −1 (Ai ). This is one of the motivations
for developing measure theory. We now define the class of functions for which the f −1 (Ai ) will
have length defined, in a more general setting.

Definition. Let Ω be a nonempty set and A a σ-field on it. f : Ω → R is said to be measurable


if for any interval I ⊆ R, f −1 (I) ∈ A .

It follows that for a measurable function f , for any Borel set B ⊆ R, f −1 (B) ∈ A (as usual, since
the collection of Borel sets for which the inverse image belongs to A has all intervals and is closed
under complements and countable unions).
When (Ω, A ) = (R, B), then every continuous function is measurable, since the collection of all
open intervals in R generates B too.

You might also like