1 MWG Chapter 1 Preference and Choice
1 MWG Chapter 1 Preference and Choice
1 MWG Chapter 1 Preference and Choice
Karel Janda
1
1. WARP satisfied
2. B includes all subsets of X up to 3 elements.
Then ∃! rational % |C(B) = C ∗ (B, %)∀B ∈ B.
Implications of homogeneity of degree 0 and Walras’ law for price and wealth effects.
Prop. 2.E.1 If the Walrasian demand function x(p, w) is homogeneous of degree 0, then
for all p and w
Dp x(p, w)p + Dw x(p, w)w = 0.
Prop. 2.E.2 If the Walrasian demand function x(p, w) satisfies Walras’ law, then for all p
and w
p · Dp x(p, w) + x(p, w)T = 0T .
Prop. 2.E.3 If the Walrasian demand function x(p, w) satisfies Walras’ law, then for all p
and w
p · Dw x(p, w) = 1.
2
Originally: p, w → x(p, w).
Change p → p0 ⇒ w0 = p0 · x(p, w).
Wealth adjustment is ∆w = ∆p · x(p, w).
Prop. 2.F.1 Suppose that the Walrasian demand function x(p, w) is homogeneous of degree
0 and satisfies Walras’ law. Then x(p, w) satisfies WARP if and only if the following
property holds:
For any (Slutsky) compensated price change from an initial situation (p, w) to a new price
wealth pair (p0 , w0 ) = (p0 , p0 · x(p, w)) we have
(p0 − p) · [x(p0 , w0 ) − x(p, w)] ≤ 0,
with strict inequality whenever x(p, w) 6= x(p0 , w0 ).
Slutsky (or substitution) matrix: S(p, w) = Dp x(p, w) + Dw x(p, w)x(p, w)T
meaning
s11 (p, w) · · · s1L (p, w)
S(p, w) = .. .. ..
,
. . .
sL1 (p, w) · · · sLL (p, w)
where slk (p, w) = ∂x∂p
l (p,w)
k
+ ∂xl∂w
(p,w)
xk (p, w).
Prop. 2.F.2 If a differentiable Walrasian demand function x(p, w) satisfies Walras’ law,
homogeneity of degree 0, and WARP, then at any (p, w) the Slutsky matrix S(p, w) is
negative semidefinite.
Prop. 2.F.3 Suppose that the Walrasian demand function x(p, w) is differentiable, homo-
geneous of degree 0, and satisfies Walras’ law. Then p · S(p, w) = 0 and S(p, w) · p = 0 for
any (p, w).
To be remembered:
1. WARP ⇔ Compensated Law of Demand.
2. Compensated Law of Demand ⇒ negative semidefinite Slutsky matrix.
3. WARP does not imply symmetry of Slutsky matrix.
3
3.2 MWG 3.C Preference and Utility
Example 3.C.1 The Lexicographic Preference Relation.
Assume X = R2+ . x % y if [x1 y1 ∨ (x1 = y1 ∧ x2 ≥ y2 )].
Def. 3.C.1 The preference relation % on X is continuous if it is preserved under limits.
That is, for any sequence of pairs {xn , y n }∞ n n
n=1 with x % y ∀n, x = limn→∞ x , and
n
y = limn→∞ y n , we have x % y.
Thm. Equivalently, % on X is continuous if ∀x ∈ X upper contour set and lower contour
set are closed.
Example 3.C.1 continued: Lexicographic preferences are not continuous. Consider se-
quences of bundles xn = ( n1 , 0), y n = (0, 1). ∀n xn y n . But limn→∞ y n = (0, 1) (0, 0) =
limn→∞ xn .
Prop. 3.C.1 Suppose that the rational preference relation % on X is continuous. Then
there is a continuous utility function u(x) that represents %.
Def. A point p is a limit point of the set E if every neighborhood of p contains a point
q 6= p|q ∈ E.
Def. Closure of E is Ē = E ∪ E 0 , where E 0 is a set of all limit points of E.
Def. Two subsets A and B of a metric space X are said to be separated if both A ∩ B̄ and
Ā ∩ B are empty, i.e., if no point of A lies in the closure of B and no point of B lies in the
closure of A.
A set E ⊂ X is said to be connected if E is not a union of two nonempty separated sets.
max u(x)
x≥0
s.t. p · x ≤ w.
2. Walras’ law
4
4. Continuous (if function, upper hemicontinuous if correspondence).
5. Differentiable ⇔ the determinant of the bordered Hessian of u(·) is nonzero at x(p, w).
3. Quasiconvex; that is, the set {(p, w) : v(p, w) ≤ v̄} is convex for any v̄.
4. Continuous in p and w.
min p · x
x≥0
s.t. u(x) ≥ u.
Prop. 3.E.1 (Relationship between EMP and UMP) Suppose that u(·) is a continuous
utility function representing a locally nonsatiated preference relation % defined on the
consumption set X = RL+ and that the price vector is p 0. We have
1. If x∗ is optimal in the UMP when wealth is w > 0, then x∗ is optimal in the EMP
when the required utility level is u(x∗ ).The minimized expenditure level in this EMP
is exactly w.
2. If x∗ is optimal in the EMP when the required utility level is u > u(0), then x∗ is
optimal in UMP when wealth is p · x∗ . The maximized utility level in this UMP is
exactly u.
1. Homogeneity of degree 0 in p.
5
3. Convexity/uniqueness: If % is convex, then h(p, u) is a convex set; if % is strictly
convex (⇒ u(·) is strictly quasiconcave), then there is a unique element in h(p, u).
Prop. 3.E.4 Suppose that u(·) is a continuous utility function representing a locally non-
satiated preference relation % and that h(p, u)consists of a single element for all p 0.
Then h(p, u) satisfies the compensated law of demand ∀p0 , p00 :
1. Homogeneous of degree 1 in p.
3. Concave in p.
4. Continuous in p and u.
Note: For a fixed p̄, e(p̄, ·) and v(p̄, ·) are inverses to one another.
Prop. 3.G.2 Suppose that u(·) is a continuous utility function representing a locally nonsa-
tiated and strictly convex preference relation % defined on the consumption set X = RL+ .
Suppose that h(·, u) ∈ C 1 at (p, u). Then
6
2. Dp h(p, u) is a negative semidefinite matrix.
4. Dp h(p, u)p = 0.
Prop. 3.G.3 (The Slutsky Equation) Suppose that u(·) is a continuous utility function
representing a locally nonsatiated and strictly convex preference relation % defined on the
consumption set X = RL+ . Then for all (p, w), and u = v(p, w) we have
Prop. 3.G.4 (Roy’s Identity). Suppose that u(·) is a continuous utility function representing
a locally nonsatiated and strictly convex preference relation % defined on the consumption
set X = RL+ . Suppose also that the indirect utility function v(·, ·) is differentiable at (p̄, w̄).
Then
1
x(p̄, w̄) = ∇p v(p̄, w̄).
∇w v(p̄, w̄)