The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics
The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics
do we stand?
GianCarlo Ghirardi∗
Department of Theoretical Physics of the University of Trieste, and
arXiv:0904.0958v1 [quant-ph] 6 Apr 2009
the Abdus Salam International Centre for Theoretical Physics, Trieste, Italy, and
the Istituto Nazionale di Fisica Nucleare.
Abstract
We reconsider some important foundational problems of quantum me-
chanics. After reviewing the measurement problem and discussing its
unavoidability, we analyze some proposals to overcome it. This analysis
leads us to reconsider the current debate on our best theory, i.e. quantum
mechanics itself. We stress that, after the remarkable interest and the
many efforts which have lead, in the last years of the past century, to a
revival of the subject, and, more important, to new interesting results,
we are now witnessing a re-emergence of the vague and unprofessional
positions which have characterized the debate in the second quarter of
the XXth century. In particular we consider as extremely serious the fact
that a completely mistaken position concerning the real meaning of Bell’s
theorem seems to have been taken by many scientists in the field.
1 Introduction
As well known, almost one century after its formulation and in spite of its un-
precedented predictive successes in accounting for physical processes, quantum
mechanics is still at the centre of a lively debate. Everybody knows very well
the disputes between some of the great founding fathers of the theory, from N
Bohr to A Einstein to E Schrödinger to W Heisenberg, which have marked the
twenties and the thirties of the past century. The debate has been less heated in
the subsequent years, perhaps because, as stated by M Gell-Mann in his Nobel
acceptance speech in 1976:
Niels Bohr brainwashed a whole generation of physicists into believ-
ing that the problem (of the interpretation of the theory) had been
solved fifty years ago.
Actually I remember well that, at the beginning of the sixties when I started
my scientific carreer, to work on foundational issues was considered by a great
part of the scientific community a loss of time, a choice to pay more attention
to (irrelevant) philosophical issues than to precise scientific problems. Luckily
enough, the sixties were also the years in which another deep thinker, John S
∗ e-mail: [email protected]
1
Bell, by deriving the celebrated inequality that bears his name [1], has given a
tremendous imput to our understanding of reality by making clear that nonlocal
features characterize most natural processes. However, this great scientist did
not limit his considerations to the peculiar aspects of the theory stemming from
one of its most surprising features, entanglement, but has devoted many impor-
tant papers to give voice to his unsatisfaction with the conceptual and logical
status of the theory, in particular with the so-called measurement or macro-
objectification problem. His immense prestige has pushed many physicists to
reconsider such a problem and during the fall of the past century there has been
a re-flourishing of foundational investigations.
In this paper we will first of all concentrate our attention on the macro-
objectification problem and on some recent proposals to overcome it, and then
we will briefly review and analyze the positions which characterize the present
debate on this problem.
X X
|φi i ⊗ |AR i → |φi i ⊗ |Ai i ⇒ ci |φi i ⊗ |AR i → ci |φi i ⊗ |Ai i, (1)
i i
where the simple arrow denotes the time evolution and the double one denotes
the implication.
As Eq. (1) clearly shows, in the final state a superposition of macroscopically
different states appears. Now, what meaning whatsoever can we attribute to
a state which is a superposition (and not a statistical mixture) of such states?
Actually the states |Ai i of the apparatus might correspond to different locations
2
of a macroscopic pointer. How can then a macroscopic object be in a state which
does not correspond to a macroscopically definite position?
We all know the answer that the so-called ortodox interpretation of quantum
mechanics gives to our question: wave packet reduction takes place during the
process and the final state is not the one appearing at the end of Eq.(1), but,
with a probability given by |cj |2 , the state |φj i ⊗ |Aj i of the superposition.
This assumption is fundamentally inconsistent since it contemplates two
contradictory evolution laws for physical systems: one, which is linear and de-
terministic, governing the evolution of microsystems, and one, which is nonlinear
and stochastic, holding when macroscopic systems enter into play. Why should
macrosystems not to be governed by quantum mechanics? Are they not built
up of elementary constituents (electrons, protons, neutrons) which are subjected
to the laws of quantum mechanics? But this is not the whole story. In fact,
on the one hand, we know very well that there are macroscopic systems whose
properties can be understood only in terms of quantum theory, while, on the
other, even if we would be inclined to accept two different evolution principles,
we cannot avoid to recognize that there is nothing, absolutely nothing, in the
theory which allows us to locate the split identifying which systems obey the
linear equation and which ones do not. As lucidly summarized by Bell [2]:
To conclude this section we remark that the above ideal scheme of measure-
ment (such measurement processes are usually denoted as ‘of the first kind’) is an
extremely idealized one: in practice, the final apparatus states are not strictly
orthogonal, we cannot control all degrees of freedom characterizing them, a
macroscopic object cannot be isolated from the environment, no apparatus is
exempt from malfunctioning, etc. Some scientists maintain that it is just re-
sorting to such an idealized description as the one of Eq.(1) which leads to
the inconsistencies we have just discussed. As a paradigmatic example we will
mention a sentence [3] by H. Primas:
If you really want to discuss measurements of the first kind you may
try your luck. But remember that measurements of the first kind are
unrealistic and completely irrelevant for experimental science. Re-
place in all books and philosophical treatises on quantum mechanics
the word ‘measurement’ by the proper expression ‘measurement of
the first kind’ and add a footnote: measurements of the first kind
are idealizations which never play any role in experimental sciences.
Our next step is to prove that this position is plainly wrong and that the
macro-objectification problem cannot be avoided. To this purpose we will briefly
recall the argument of a recent paper [4] in which the problem has been tackled
in its full generality.
3
3 A completely general measurement scheme
To exhibit an explicit proof of the last statement of the previous section, let
us consider a microsystem which we assume can be prepared in two orthogonal
states |ui and |di (typically we can think of the two spin states of a spin 1/2
particle corresponding to a definite value of σz ), and in their equal amplitudes
superposition |u + di = √12 [|ui + |di]. We consider also a statistical ensemble
E{|AR , αi, p(α)} of apparata, devised to measure precisely the observable σz .
We have resorted to an ensemble of apparata just because we cannot have full
control of all their degrees of freedom. The state |AR , αi corresponds to the
‘ready state’ of the apparatus, let us say one for which the macroscopic pointer
of the apparatus ‘points, at 0’, while the index α distinguishes situations differing
for uncontrollable degrees of freedom such as the precise state of the molecules
of the pointer, and so on1 . The quantities p(α) are the weights of the various
subensembles of the statistical ensemble characterized by the macroproperty
AR . Completely in general, when we will resort to expressions of the type
|X, µi we intend to indicate a situation of the macro-apparatus corresponding
to what we perceive2 as ‘the pointer point at X’ and all other relevant variables
are summarized by the symbol µ. Let us denote as X the set of all such states for
all possible values of µ. We will not require orthogonality of states corresponding
to macroscopically different situations, but, obviously, we have to impose that
two such states are, to a large extent, “distinguishable”, a fact that we will
characterize by imposing:
√
infµ∈X ,ν∈Y k |X, µi − |Y, νi k≥ 2 − η, η ≪ 1. (2)
Let us go on with our assumptions. We put the system in one of the two
states |ui or |di into interaction with the specific apparatus in the state |AR , αi,
and we assume that the quantum evolution during the measurement is governed
by a unitary operator U (ti , tf ). Let us denote as |F, u, αi and |F, d, αi the
final states obtained when we trigger the apparatus in the state |AR , αi by the
microstates |ui and |di, respectively:
U (ti , tf )[|ui ⊗ |AR , αi] = |F, u, αi; U (ti , tf )[|di ⊗ |AR , αi] = |F, d, αi. (3)
JU− = {α : |F, u, αi ∈ −
/ U}; JD = {α : |F, d, αi ∈
/ D}, (4)
and their complements JU+
= CJU− , +
JD = CJD−
. The physical meaning of these
−
sets should be clear. For instance JU represents the subset of those apparata
(actually the set of the α’s) for which, in spite of having being triggered by the
microstate |ui, their final statevector does not belong to the set U, i.e. the one
for which the pointer ‘points at U’. For α in such a set the apparata did not
register correctly the fact that the system we are interested in is in the state
|ui. The meaning of the other three sets, is obvious. We can now formulate
1 Note that we can include in α also degrees of freedom which are external to the apparatus,
make reference to a situation in which the position of the pointer is a geometrical point, but
to one in which it lays in a quite narrow interval on a graduated scale.
4
our final assumption. By taking advantage of the fact that the function p(α)
is a probability measure on the set on which the index α runs, we can define a
measure by the formula:
Z
µ{X } = p(α)dα. (5)
α∈X
µ{JU+ ∩ JD
+
} > 1 − 2ǫ, ǫ ≪ 1. (7)
which is near to 1.
Having made precise our assumptions and notation we can now proceed as
follows. Let us trigger those apparatuses for which α belongs to JU+ ∩ JD +
(i.e.
those which register correctly both the state |ui as well as the state |di) by the
state |u + di. The linear nature of quantum mechanics implies, from Eq. (3):
1 1 1
U (ti , tf ) √ [|u+di⊗|AR , αi ≡ √ ]U (ti , tf )[|ui+|di]⊗|AR , αi = √ [|F, u, αi+|F, d, αi].
2 2 2
(8)
Let us now raise the question: does the final state of Eq.(8) belong to the
set U of states? The answer is no, because its distance from the state |F, d, αi
is:
1 1 1 1
k |F, u+d, αi−|F, d, αi k=k √ |F, u, αi+(1− √ )|F, d, αi k≤ √ +1− √ = 1,
2 2 2 2
(9)
while, according
√ to Eq.(2) a state belonging to U must have a distance almost
equal to 2 from any state belonging to the set D of states corresponding to a
macroscopically and perceptively different situation from the one which is, by
assumption, associated to the perception ‘the pointer points at U’. The same
argument can be followed to prove that the final state cannot belong to D or to
any other set of states corresponding to a definite position of the pointer.
The conclusion should be obvious. Having assumed that we have an en-
semble E{|AR , αi, p(α)} of macro-apparata which allows us reliably (but not
perfectly) to know whether the microstate triggering them is either |ui or |di,
then the large majority of such apparata (i.e. all those characterized by an α
belonging to the set JU+ ∩ JD +
, whose measure is near to 1), when triggered by
the superposition |u + di ends up in a state which cannot correspond to any
definite position-perception concerning the macroscopic pointer. The macro-
objectification problem cannot be overcome invoking measurement processes
more realistic than the von Neumann one: it is the very possibility of mea-
suring an observable with an acceptable level of reliability and the assumption
of the unrestricted validity of quantum mechanics which imply that the same
micro-macro interaction leads almost always to a perceptually nondefinite sit-
uation when the triggering state is the superposition of different eigenstates of
the observed quantity.
5
4 Decoherence
A quite popular proposal which has been put forward to overcome the macro-
objectification problem is based on the consideration of the unavoidable and
uncontrollable interaction of any macroscopic body with its environment. A
sketchy way of summarizing this proposal is the following. Let us consider a
state which is a linear superposition of two macroscopically different states of a
macro-object S:
|Ψ(sys) i = α|M i + β|N i. (10)
One then takes into account the above mentioned unavoidable interactions
of S with the environment, which we suppose to be described by the state |E0 i
at the initial time. Such interactions and the subsequent evolution lead to a
state of the system+environment which we will express as:
6
If we now evaluate the reduced statistical operator, taking into account the
orthogonality of the states of the environment we have:
ρ(Red,sys) ≡ T r(env) ρ(sys+env) = |α|2 |M i⊗|EM ihEM |⊗hM |+|β|2 |N i⊗|EN ihEN |⊗hN |.
(14)
Such a statistical operator is the one associated to the statistical mixture of
the states |M i and |N i with statistical weights |α|2 and |β|2 , a fact which would
render legitimate the replacement of the original pure state of the system with
the corresponding mixture:
1 1
E{ √ [|M i + |N i], √ [|M i − |N i], |M i; |β|2 , |β|2 , (|α|2 − |β|2 )}, (16)
2 2
corresponds precisely to the same statistical operator of Eq.(14), but it still
contains embarassing superpositions of macroscopically distinguishable states.
Actually, the decoherence approach to the measurement problem has been
repeatedly criticized (see, e.g. [6] ) and, moreover, the most serious proponents
of this solution have plainly recognized that the situation which we have outlined
is puzzling, and have proposed (vague) ways out from the puzzle. The most
paradigmatic example can be found in an important paper [7] by Joos and Zeh,
which clearly admidts the arbitrariness of choosing one statistical mixture (the
most reasonable from a perceptual point of view and the one corresponding to
wave packet reduction), among the infinitely many which are possible:
7
• The local description is assumed and the specific choice of a basis can
perhaps be justified by a fundamental underivable assumption about the
local nature of the observer ... and his way of perceiving,
• No unitary treatment of the time dependence can explain why only one of
these dynamically independent components is experienced,
• The difficulty in giving a complete derivation of classical concepts may as
well signal the need of entirely novel concepts.
As a final remark we would like to stress that the most recent attempts to
achieve important technological improvements based on quantum mechanics -
such as Quantum Cryptography, Quantum Teleportation and Quantum Com-
putation - deal unavoidably with individual physical systems and they make a
systematic use of wave packet reduction at the individual level as an important
resource. Unless one ignores these fundamental aspects of modern research one
has to face the necessity of breaking the linear nature of quantum mechanics at
an appropriate stage.
8
5.1 Bohmian Mechanics
The formal aspects of the proposal put forward in his celebrated papers [10] by
D Bohm in 1952 can be summarized as follows:
• The quantum description of the state of a physical system is incomplete;
for a complete specification one has to add to the wavefunction also the
positions of all particles which constitute the system under examination
(the positions are the hidden variables of the theory because we are able
to prepare any desired wavefunction, but we have no way to control at
which point of the support of the wavefunction the particle actually is -
and the theory assumes that it has a precise position),
• The initial state of a system is fully specified by the assignment of the
initial wavefunction in configuration space Ψ(q1 , q2 , ..., qn , 0) ≡ Ψ(qi , 0),
and the initial positions Qi (0), (i = 1, 2, ..., n) actually occupied by the
constituents particles,
• There are two linked evolution equations in the theory. The wavefunction
evolves according to the standard quantum equation. Then one defines,
in terms of the wave function, a velocity field vB,k (Qj , t) for each particle
and considers a first order (in time) differential equation for the positions
themselves. In formulae:
The theory exhibits some nice features. First of all, in virtue of the continuity
equation satisfied by Schrödinger’s wavefunction one immediately proves that if
one defines the position density distribution ρ(Qk , t) = |Ψ(Qk , t)|2 one has the
so called equivariance property:
This equation tells us that if one has an ensemble of particles whose initial posi-
tions are distributed according to the modulus square of the initial wavefunction,
then, by letting the particles evolve along the uniquely defined trajectories en-
suing from the differential equations for the positions, one recovers at any time
the position density distributions predicted by quantum mechanics.
The theory is purposedly equivalent to standard quantum mechanics but it
can be shown to imply that macroscopic objects end up, with the correct prob-
abilities, in those positions that are assigned to them by the standard theory
enriched with the reduction postulate. In short the theory solves the measure-
ment problem in a perfectly consistent way.
The primitive ontology of the theory emerges clearly from the given picture:
all particles of the Universe have at all times perfectly defined positions, they
move along precise trajectories in such a way to reproduce the position density
distribution of standard quantum mechanics. In the case of micro-macro inter-
actions, macroscopic systems end up, in turn, in the precise positions predicted
9
by quantum mechanics plus the wave packet reduction postulate. Obviously,
one has to assume that all measurements reduce essentially to position mea-
surements, just as it happens when we consider a system with a macroscopic
pointer, from the position of which we can infer the outcome of the measure-
ment. What the theory is about are the positions and they match perfectly
our perceptions concerning macroscopic systems. Using Bell’s terminology, the
positions are the beables of the theory, and everything is built up from them.
10
• According to this prescription a nucleon (or an atom) suffers a localization
about every 108 years, and, consequently, microscopic systems are prac-
tically unaffected, while a macroscopic object, containing an Avogadro’s
number of particles, suffers a localization about every 10−7 sec.,
• The statistical operator obeys an equation of the Quantum Dynamical
Semigroup type,
• The theory is, in principle, testable against quantum mechanics.
The conclusion should be obvious: the proposed universal dynamics leaves
all quantum predictions for microsystems unaltered but it accounts for wave
packet reduction with probabilities in agreement with the quantum ones and
for the classical behaviour of macroscopic systems, as well as for our definite
perceptions with them.
In the simplified version we have presented the theory suffers of a serious
limitation: the localizations break the symmetry character of the wavefunction
for identical particles. This feature is easily corrected as firstly shown in[14].
Before coming to consider the ontology of the model we mention that much
more formally elegant (even though physically equivalent) variants of the theory
have been presented [14, 15]. They are based on the formalism of stochastic
differential equations of the Ito or Stratonovich type.
Let us now come to discuss the PO of the theory. A first proposal has
been put forward by Bell himself in his presentation of the GRW theory at the
Imperial College meeting celebrating the centenary of Schrödinger’s [9]:
This assumption that ‘what the theory is fundamentally about’ are the local-
izations themselves has been characterized as ‘The flashes ontology’ in refs.[8]
and [16, 17, 18]. An alternative ontology has been proposed in [19] and has
been subsequently characterized as ‘the mass density ontology’. This assumes
that what the theory is about, what is real ‘out there’, is the mass density in
3-dimensional space:
N Z
X
m(x, t) = dr1 , ..., drN δ(ri − x)|Ψ(r1 , ..., rN , t)|2 . (21)
i=1 R3N
This concludes our description of two ways out from the macro-objectification
problem. As already mentioned there have been many other interesting attempts
aiming at the same result. We have concentrated our attention on these two
because they are precise models which, at the nonrelativistic level, account on
the basis of a unique universal dynamics both for the behavior of microscopic
systems, as well as for the reduction process which takes place during mea-
surement procedures. Bell has qualified them [5] as ‘exact’, a term by which
11
he intended which are precisely formulated and which neither require nor are
embarrassed by a conscious observer. Bohmian Mechanics has been discussed
many times and there are also entire books devoted to it. Concerning the GRW
theory there is an extensive literature (which can be found, e.g., in [13]) in which
many physically interesting aspects of the theory are analyzed.
12
the other ‘exact’ theory we have presented qualifies itself as a rival theory of
quantum mechanics which, in principle, can be tested against it. So, let us
pass to analyze some of the critical remarks adressing the dynamical reduction
program.
to ref.[20].
13
7 Relativistic generalizations
Bell in one of his last papers, after having discussed Bohmian Mechanics and
the GRW theory has stated [5]:
The real problem now is which one of these two exact theories admits
a relativistic generalization
14
8 Quantum computation, nonlocality and real-
ism
Quite recently, an attitude which we see as an attempt to revive the Copenhagen
position emerged in connection with two quite different subjects, i.e., on the
one side, the investigations concerning the promising and interesting field of
quantum computation and, on the other, some theoretical and experimental
analyses of quantum nonlocality. Let us proceed to discuss them.
People working in quantum computation have repeatedly put forward the
idea that what quantum mechanics is about is not ‘something existing out there’,
but only and exclusively ‘our information’. A paradigmatic example of this
attitude appears in a paper by A Zeilinger [40]:
• The distinction between reality and our knowledge of reality, between reality
and information, cannot be made,
• Bell’s result suggests that the concept of reality itself is at stake,
• There is no way to refer to reality without using the information we have
about it.
Leaving apart the tautological structure of the last sentence, I believe that
the best response to the first has been given in a recent paper [41]:
The distinction between reality and our knowledge of reality, not only
can be made; it must be made if the notions of knowledge and infor-
mation are to have any meaning in the first place.
To further illustrate the discussion about the recent positions taken by some
scientists we consider it appropriate to mention a recent exchange of views
between D Mermin and the present author [42, 43]. Mermin asserts that the
present status of quantum computation is completely satisfactory on the basis
of the fact that:
• ... all gates, including the measurement gate, alter the state associated
with the incoming Q-bits in a well defined, generally discontinuous manner
which is precisely defined by the state,
• ... in spite of the fact that there remains the distinction between linear,
invertible, unitary gates with output state fully determined by the imput,
and nonlinear, irreversible, measurement gates, with output state stochas-
tically determined by the input, ..., the action of both types of gates are
fully determined, with nothing left to the discretion of the theoretical physi-
cist.
We perfectly agree on these statements, but we stress that they amount
simply to a way of evading the real problem. In fact Mermin himself stresses
that:
it is through the readings of 1-Qbit measurement gates, and only
through such readings, that one can extrect information from a quan-
tum computer ... measurement is essential at both ends of a quantum
computation. ... the ‘user’ which looks at a visual display or a print
out [plays the fundamental role in the process].
15
Here one can see, on the one side, the plain recognition that the very practice
of quantum information and computation requires to accept the validity of two
different and incompatible dynamical principles. On the other side, one ignores
completely the fact that while we know everything about the working of the
unitary gates used to implement our algoritms, we have an extremely vague idea
of why and when individual physical processes occur which are not governed
by the (usually) assumed universal laws of quantum mechanics and actually
contradict it. This is, in essence the criticism to Mermin that we have raised.
He has replied [44] and, besides making various remarks he has made quite clear
his position:
I stress that the state and the unitary transformations it is subject
to are mathematical abstractions that enable one to compute ... the
probabilities of the readings of the final measurement gates. Math-
ematical abstractions do not require stochastic ‘hits’ originating in
unknown physical processes or interactions with gravitons to be reset;
they are reset by us, when we acquire more information and want to
calculate what we expect to experience next.
This sentence makes explicit reference to the GRW theory and to the pro-
posals by Penrose of relating wave packet reduction to gravity. We believe that
one cannot ignore that these alternative theories represent serious attempts to
account consistently, in physical terms and not by vague verbal assumptions,
for what ‘we will experience ... next’.
To conclude this first part of our comments we would like to mention that the
idea that quantum mechanics deals simply with ‘information’, is not new. For
instance it was put forward during the discussions concerning the decoherent
histories approach to quantum mechanics when it has been suggested to look at
them exclusivively with reference to IGUSes (information gathering and using
systems). Bell has considered this position and he has made clear [5] that he
was inclined to reject any reference to information unless one would, first of
all, answer to the following basic questions: Whose information?, Information
about what?
This remark allows to focus in a precise way the two incompatible positions
which characterize the present debate which, in our opinion, echoes the one of
more than 60 years ago. In fact, e.g., Mermin himself, has recently taken a quite
precise position [45] concerning the issue under discussion:
16
the same problem both with reference to Leggett’s proposal as well as for a
somewhat extended class of nonlocal theories and have proved once more their
incompatibility with quantum mechanics. Even experimental tests of Leggett’s
model have been performed, confirming the crash with quantum predictions.
This line of research is, in our opinion, quite interesting and deserves to be
pursued. However, the above facts - i.e. the supposed ‘naturalness’ of the re-
quests and the persisting incompatibility with quantum mechanics - have given
rise to a very peculiar type of argument. In a sketchy way it can be summarized
as follows: the derivation of Bell’s inequality is based on two assumptions: Lo-
cality and Realism. Accordingly, the experimental violation of Bell’s inequality
requires to abandon at least one of these assumptions. Since giving up locality
along the ‘natural’ way suggested by Leggett does not eliminate the crash of
such proposals with quantum theory, the experimentally tested incompatibility
gives a clear indication that one has to give up the assumption of realism. This
argument, combined with the already emerging opinion, coming from the quan-
tum computational community, i.e. that the concept of reality itself is at stake,
has seen the adoption of this point of view by many, even extremely brilliant
physicists [40, 47, 51].
We would like to make some remarks on this point. First of all we will call
attention on the factual irrelevance of the argument. Secondly we will stress,
and we consider this an extremely important point, that the just mentioned
papers take a completely mistaken attitude towards the real meaning of Bell’s
work. Let us proceed to present the just mentioned criticisms.
In agreement with these remarks one cannot claim that the program of
building up a ‘fully realistic nonlocal theory’ equivalent to quantum mechanics
is not viable, an important counterexample of what has been suggested in the
above mentioned papers. But this remark is by no way the most relevant one,
actually it turns out to be rather marginal. What really matters is the fact that
the derivation of Bell’s inequality in no way whatsoever needs an assumption of
realism. In spite of this fundamental fact, which everybody can verify by going
carefully through the proof, a large part of the scientific community shares the
completely wrong opinion that realism is among the basic assumption needed
for the derivation of Bell’s result. Bell himself has stressed this aspect and has
remarked [52] that it is extremely difficult to eradicate this prejudice5 :
5 It has to be remarked that deterministic hidden variable theories assume that the com-
plete specification of the state of the system implies that all physical properties are actually
possessed by the systems prior to any measurement process. This is equivalent to the request
of realism discussed by the above mentioned authors
17
My own first paper (Physics 1, 195 (1965.) on this subject starts
with a summary of the EPR argument from locality to determin-
istic hidden variables. But the commentators have almost universally
reported that it begins with deterministic hidden variables.
This being the situation we must conclude that in no way whatsoever Bell’s
inequality has something to do with realism. It simply identifies in a straightfor-
ward and lucid way that what quantum phenomena impose to us is to accept the
unescapable fact that natural processes involving entangled states of composite
and far-away systems turn out to be unavoidably non-local. If one is keen to
consider the possibility of giving up realism he can very well try his luck, but for
sure such a big price is not necessary, and even not suggested, by the quantum
nonlocal correlations.
The question whether Bell’s theorem involves some request of realism has
been discussed and proven once more to be unjustified by various authors [53,
54, 55].
We would like to conclude this analysis of some of the most relevant issues of
the foundational investigations on quantum mechanics by expressing our worries
concerning the fact that there are some indications that 80 years of lively debate
on the conceptual problems of our best theory by the most brilliant physicists
of the last century are facing a serious risk of being cancelled by those scientists
who Mermin has qualified as the Q-computation crowd or by those who derive
from experimental results inspired by not strictly convincing theoretical models
unjustified conclusions concerning such an important issue as the one of the
reality of the world around us.
References
References
[1] Bell J S 1964 Physics 1 195
[2] Bell J S 1989 Themes in Contemporary Physics II ed S. Deser and R.J.
Finkelstein (Singapore: World Scientific) p 1
[3] Primas H 1991 Symposium on the foundations of modern physics 1990, Dis-
cussion Sections ed K.V. Laurikainen and J. Viri (University of Turku, Fin-
land)
[4] Bassi A and Ghirardi G C 2000 Phys. Lett. A 275 373
[5] Bell J S 1990 Phys. World 3 33
[6] Adler S 2003 Stud. Hist. Phil. Mod. Phys. 34 135
[7] Joos E and Zeh H D 1985 Z. Phys. B 59, 223
[8] Allori V, Goldstein S, Tumulka R and Zanghı́ N 2008 British J. Philos. Sci.
59 353
[9] Bell J S 1987 Schrödinger–Centenary Celebration of a Polymath ed C W
Kilmister (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
18
[10] Bohm D 1952 Phys. Rev. 85 166, 1952 Phys. Rev. 85 180
[11] Pauli W in Born M 1971 The Born Einstein Letters (New York: Walter
and Co)
[12] Ghirardi G C, Rimini A and Weber T 1986 Phys. Rev. D 34 470
[13] Ghirardi G C and Bassi A 2003 Phys. Rep. 379 257
[14] Pearle P 1999 Phys. Rev. A 59 80
[15] Ghirardi G C, Pearle P and Rimini A 1990 Phys. Rev. A 42 78
[16] Tumulka R 2006 AIP Conference Proceedings 844 ed A. Bassi et al
(Melville, New York: AIP) p 340
[17] Tumulka R 2006 Proc. Roy. Soc. London A 462 1897
[18] Tumulka R 2006 J. Stat. Phys. 125 821
[19] Ghirardi G C, Grassi R and Benatti F 1995 Found. Phys. 25 5
[20] Hagar A 2007 Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 38 906
[21] Bub J 1997 Interpreting the Quantum world (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press)
[22] Penrose R 1996 Gen. Relativ. Gravit. 28 581
[23] Penrose 2000 Mathematical Physics 2000 (London: Imperial College)
[24] Marshall W, Simon C, Penrose R and Bouwmeester D 2003 Phys. Rev.
Lett. 91 130401
19
[34] Pearle P 1990 Sixty-two Years of Uncertainty ed A. Miller (New York:
Plenum)
[35] Ghirardi G C, Grassi R and Pearle P 1990 Found. Phys. 20 1271
[36] Dove C and Squires E 1995 Found. Phys. 25 1267
[37] Dowker F and Henson J 2004 J. Stat. Phys. 115 1327
[38] Dowker F and Herbauts I 2004 Classical Quant. Grav. 21, 2963
[39] Dowker F and Herbauts I 2005 Found. Phys. Lett. 18, 499
[40] Zeilinger A 2005 Nature 438 743
[41] Daumer M, Dürr D , Goldstein S, Maudlin T and Tumulka R 2006 AIP
Conference Proceedings 844 ed A. Bassi et al (Melville, New York: AIP) p
129
[42] Mermin D 2006 Quantum Inf. Processes 35 239
[43] Ghirardi G C 2008 Found. Phys. 38 1011
[44] Mermin D 2008 arXiv:0808.1582
[45] Mermin D 2002 Quantum [Un]speakables ed R.A. Bertlmann and A.
Zeilinger (Berlin: Springer) p 271
[46] Leggett A J 2003 Found. Phys.33 1496
[47] Gröblacher S, Paterek T, Kaltenbaek R, Bruckner C, Zukowski M, As-
pelmeyer M and Zeilinger A 2007 Nature 446 871
[48] Branciard C, Ling A, Gisin N, Kurtsiefer C, Lamas-Linares A and Scarani
V 2008 Nature Physics 4 681
[49] Paterek T, Fedrizzi A, Gröblacher S, Jennewein T, Zukovski M, Aspelmeyer
M and Zeilinger A 2007 Phys. Rev. Lett. 99 210406
[50] Colbeck R and Renner R 2008 Phys. Rev. Lett. 101 050403
[51] Aspect A 2005 Nature 438 745
20