Introduction To Indian Philosophy Christopher Bartley
Introduction To Indian Philosophy Christopher Bartley
Introduction To Indian Philosophy Christopher Bartley
Indian Philosophy
Also available from Continuum:
Forthcoming:
www.continuumbooks.com
2 Buddhist Origins 13
3 Abhidharma Buddhism 26
4 Sautrāntika Buddhism 35
10 Vedānta 134
11 Advaita-Vedānta 138
12 Viśis.t.ādvaita-Vedānta 168
viii Contents
Bibliography 235
Index 241
Introduction: Some Types of
Indian Religiosity
This book attempts an overview of some of the topics, themes and arguments
with which Brahminical Hindu and Buddhist Indian philosophers were
concerned between the second and twelfth centuries A.D. It seeks to describe
a variety of very different world-views. It aims to explore a variety of different
mentalities, rather than to evaluate them or to ask whether they are true. It
begins with some general considerations about the background to the different
philosophical schools and tries to explain the origins of the fundamental
separation of mentalities into the enduring-substance ontologies propounded
by Brahmins and the event ontologies, repudiating real permanent identities
formulated by the Buddhists. In broad terms, we see a dialectic between the
two mentalities: one asserting the primacy of Being and the attendant concepts
of substance, universal property, essence and the individuality of entities with
persisting identities, and the other that understands the world primarily as
consisting of ephemeral beings in a temporal process of becoming: events,
complexes, change. According to the first view, states of affairs are produced
by interactions between stable continuing entities, including enduring selves.
On the second, the world is an ever-changing flow of events, and what we treat
as individual entities are convenient abstractions out of relational complexes.
We ourselves are no less conditioned than the things in the world with which
we are involved. The first outlook has it that one fundamentally is in some
sense a soul or substantial self, a further fact over and above one’s experiences.
In short, there is a difference between you and your life. This is precisely what
is repudiated by the second outlook, according to which there are just life
histories. There is no permanent ‘real me’. Terms like ‘Self ’ are convenient
abbreviations for the ways in which embodied persons function in the world.
The different ramifications of this mentality are explored in the chapters about
Buddhism.
2 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
I am not apologizing when I say that this book is a survey of some of the
Indian traditions. The field is vast and there is so much to be explored. It is to
be hoped that readers are stimulated to consult more specialized works and
read the original sources so as to form their own views. Suggestions about
further reading are to be found at the end of each chapter.
***
In classical India, philosophy was understood as contributing to human
well-being by freeing people from misconceptions about themselves and the
world. Ultimate well-being was conceived as some sort of fulfilment outside
the conditions of space and time. Philosophies, as well as religious traditions,
understood themselves as paths to that final goal.
Where the religious contexts of those who engaged in critical, reflective and
argumentative philosophy are concerned we have to reckon with a tremendous
variety of beliefs and practices. Neither ‘Hinduism’ nor ‘Buddhism’ are really
homogenous. It is difficult to know where to begin: you can always go back
further. In the course of the second millennium B.C. the Aryan migrations
into north west of the sub-continent introduced the Vedic religious culture
and the four-fold hierarchy of varn.as (Brahmins, Warriors, Farmers and
Servants) that was superimposed on the indigenous system of jātis. It appears
that originally the ritual cult was concerned with the propitiation by offerings
of the many deities in the Vedic pantheon. Their favour thus secured would
yield mundane and supra-mundane rewards. Rituals performed by members
of the Brahmin caste were understood as yielding benefits for both the
individual and the community. But there developed an outlook that the con-
tinuation of the cosmos, the regularity of the seasons and the rising of the sun,
were not merely marked or celebrated by ritual acts but actually depended
upon ritual. What the rituals effected was too important to be left to the
choices of ultimately uncontrollable capricious divinities. So rituals came to
be thought of as automatic mechanisms, in the course of which the mention of
the deities’ names was but a formulaic aspect of the process. The relegated
gods existed only in name. The Brahmins unilaterally declare themselves the
gods in human form. From the point of view of the individual, the benefit of
the ritual was understood in terms of the accumulation of merit or good karma
that would be enjoyed at some point in the future, in this or a subsequent life
perhaps in a superior sphere of experience for those with sufficient merit.
The notion of karma is basically a recognition that one’s actions have future
consequences for one. But the consequentiality extends beyond this life. The
Introduction 3
idea is that a deliberately performed intentional action generates a residue
(good or bad) that remains with the agent until future circumstances occur
that are appropriate for its fruition in the agent’s experience. Karma does not
determine the future directly: rather, it lies in wait. It is karma that personalizes
and propels individuals through a series of births in the here and now.
The notion of repeated births (sam.sāra) is a presupposition shared by
Brahmins and Buddhists. Everyone agreed that the process of rebirth goes
on and on, is fundamentally unsatisfactory and is to be escaped from.
Whatever the quantum of good karma accumulated by an individual, it will
still become exhausted. Felicity is always temporary. Release or liberation is
always understood as irreversible freedom from rebirth. This freedom from
rebirth, the ultimate goal of religious praxis, is what is called by Brahmins
‘moks.a’ or ‘mukti’, and ‘nirvān.a’ by Buddhists, although as we shall see their
understanding of what it means is very different.
For there to be rebirth and the anticipation of future benefits, Brahmins
regarded it as essential that there be a permanent and stable identity (ātman)
to which the karma pertains, so that the instigator of the performance could
be he who enjoyed its consequences. The status of this ‘self ’ (ātman) in the
natural hierarchy of being was maintained, and hopefully improved, by the
spiritual purity of the persona with which it was associated. The system of
castes, whether the endogamous and commensal jātis that have a monopoly on
specific trades and professions or their interpretation in the varn.a framework,
is a hierarchy determined by spiritual purity. The hierarchy accords with and
expresses the cosmic order that is both natural and right (dharma). Each caste
has its own set of duties (dharma). The Brahmins insisted that it was better to
do one’s own dharma badly than that of another well. Dharma is not thought
of as a universal morality applicable and accessible to all. Rather it is a matter
of what F. H. Bradley called ‘my station and its duties’. The Brahmins’ purity
derived from obedience to the rules bearing upon every aspect of life that are
encoded in texts prescribing social and religious duties (the Dharma-Śāstras).
The orthodox Brahmin cannot choose his own values. The rules chart a safe
passage through a universe populated by dangerous forces that are looking for
an opportunity to occupy the body and mind of those who are negligent of their
observance. Spiritual purity is purchased at the price of moral heteronomy.
Daily ritual, as well as personal and social duties (dharmas), confers meaning
on the life of the orthodox ‘twice-born’ Hindu. It is clear that the mainstream
Vedic orthodoxy perpetuated by lineages of what are known as ‘smārta’
(traditionalist) Brahmins is more than a matter of personal or shared religious
4 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
allegiance. For much of its history India has been politically fragmented
into hundred of small kingdoms. In the absence of a centralized monarchical
institution, the integrating factor promoting harmonious coexistence, agreed
expectations, shared values and trust between different states throughout the
sub-continent was the Vedic religio with its established rituals, social norms
and Sanskrit language. Hence the anxiety occasioned by departures from the
common identity conferred by Vedism, which were potentially subversive of
good order.
Some aspects of the philosophical articulations and defences of this
mainstream orthodoxy (smārta), especially against the manifold Buddhist
articulations of their basic insights that there is no genuine permanence and
no persisting self, are described in the chapters on Mīmām.sā ritualism and the
Nyāya-Vaiśes.ika realistic metaphysical pluralism.
As well as ritual practice, there is the discipline of yoga, whose philosophy is
described in the chapter on Sam.khya-Yoga. Yoga aims at calming the mind so
that it may become fit for a non-discursive awareness of reality as it really is. This
begins with control of the body and develops mental discipline through medita-
tion, with a view to freedom from determination by natural causality. Obviously
such practice is consistent with participation in ritual acts, but it may be detached
from that form of religiosity in the case of those who have become convinced
that ritual practice is ultimately ineffective as a means to final salvation, under-
stood as freedom from repeated births in different spheres of experience.
The model of the human psyche is that what is called ‘mind’ (manas)
co-ordinates information received via the sense-faculties. For the most part
we are passive in relation to sensation and the feelings it evokes. In addition,
mental attention is often diffuse and not really focused. When mind and senses
are not controlled, we are living purely on the level of sensation. The ideal is
to discipline the senses by bringing the manas under the control of what is
called buddhi (usually not very helpfully translated as ‘the intellect’) and to
focus attention on one’s inner identity (ātman). Such a person is called ‘yukta’
or integrated:
When a person lacks understanding and his mind is out of control, he is subject
to the senses that are like bad horses of a charioteer. But when a person has
understanding and his mind is under control, his senses are subdued like good
horses. [Kat.ha Upanis.ad 3.5–6]
When the five sensory cognitions and the mind are stilled and reason (buddhi) is
steady, they call this the highest state. They call yoga a firm grip on the senses.
One is then free from distractions. [ibid. 6.10–11]
Introduction 5
He should sit still as a piece of wood. Collecting his sense-faculties, he should
focus his mind steeped in meditation. He should not hear with his eyes nor see
with his eyes. He should not long for the objects of the sense-faculties. He should
focus the mind, within for it wanders in and out of the five doors and has no
stable foundation. [Mahābhārata 12.195.5f.]
Further reading
A. L. Basham, The Wonder that was India: A Survey of the Culture of the Indian Sub-Continent Before
the Coming of the Muslims, is an interesting and comprehensive overview.
Alexis Sanderson, ‘Power and Purity’, (1985) is seminal, as are some of the articles collected in Halbfass,
Tradition and Reflection, (1991). For a translation of the Bhagavad Gītā, see Johnson (1994). For
the Upanis.ads, Olivelle (1998) provides an informative introduction, texts, translations and
illuminating annotations. What is called the Moks.a-dharma (composed while Buddhism was
developing) in the Mahābhārata Book XII offers an insight into the spiritual outlook of the
Brahminical renouncers. There is a text and translation in Wynne (2009).
Gavin Flood, Introduction to Hinduism, is easily the best of the countless introductions.
Louis Dumont (1980), ‘World Renunciation in Indian Religions’ has been very influential. Dumont
argues that the key to understanding Indian religion is to be found in the dialogue between the
householder and the renouncer. The latter, he says, represents the closest Indian equivalent to the
European notion of the individual as the bearer of values. The monograph, Homo Hierarchicus, is
a fundamental contribution to Indian sociology. Olivelle (1993) is about the four stages of life.
Olivelle (1996) translates texts bearing on Renunciation in Hinduism.
On devotional religiosity see Hardy (1983), which is unlikely to be superseded. J. A. B. van Buitenen’s
‘On the Archaism in the Bhāgavata Purān.a’ (Chapter XIX of Rocher (1988) applies M. N. Srinivas’
theory about the process of ‘Sanskritisation’ to bhakti religion.
Foundations of Brahminism:
Vedas and Upanis.ads 1
Chapter Outline
Further reading 12
Questions for discussion and investigation 12
There are four collections known as Vedas, composed during the period of the
Aryan migrations into northern India (1990–1100 B.C.). They are called the
Rig-Veda, the Sāma-Veda, Yajur-Veda and the Atharva-Veda and are regarded
by mainstream orthodox Hindus as an authorless, timeless and infallible
source of knowledge about religious and social duties in harmony with the
natural universal order (dharma). Their eternal sound-units are held to have
been discerned and composed by seven primordial ‘seers’. Priestly Brahmin
families preserve the different traditions of recitation of the sacred sounds.
The basic component of each of the four Vedas is its collection (sam.hitā) of
verses (mantra), evocative of the divinities whose sonic forms they are, which
are used in rituals. Attached to each collection are the ‘Brāhman.as’ which
prescribe, describe and elucidate the purposes of the sacrificial rituals
performed by Brahmin priests and their householder patrons. They include
explanations of the meanings of the ritual actions, and posit correspondences
between aspects of the rites and features of the cosmos including the social
structure and the human body. It was believed that ritual performance orders,
sustains and perpetuates the universe, creating new time and ensuring the
regular succession of the seasons. There are also the ‘Āran.yakas’ (‘Forest
8 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
Books’) that speculate about the ‘inner’ meaning of the rituals and are closely
associated with what are called Upanis.ads. They were composed by people
who had probably renounced the actual performance of ritual. Their view is
that the mental re-enactment of the meaning of the ritual is just as effective as
its overt performance. These fascinating compositions contain many reflective,
poetic explorations of fundamental metaphysical questions. The best way to
appreciate them is by immersing oneself in the originals, translations of which
are readily accessible.
Metaphysical questions are to be found in the hymns of the Rig Veda. These
hymns celebrate and propitiate gods mostly associated with natural forces.
Their cosmogonic hymns speak of the gods such as Indra and Varun.a
establishing inhabitable space and creating sustainable order out of chaos.
They were used by Brahmins in rituals whose aim was the perpetuation of the
cosmos. The questions about Being – Why is there something rather than
nothing? Where did it all come from? – feature there, if not prominently. One
line of thought says that there is an original One, beyond being and non-being.
Another idea is that Being (sat) arises from non-Being (asat). Since nothing
comes from nothing, ‘non-Being’ probably means a chaotic, undifferentiated
state in which are no things, no names and forms, no entities and kinds, no
structures or organizing principles. ‘Being’ would then be a cosmos of differ-
entiated, identifiable, organized realities. This is apparent from the somewhat
later Chāngogya Upanis.ad 3.19.1: ‘In the beginning this world was just non-
being. What now exists came from that. It developed and formed an egg . . .’
The speculation is rationalized in the sixth chapter (6.2.1) of the same work:
‘In the beginning, my dear, this world was just being (sat), one only without
a second. Some people say, In the beginning, this world was just non-being,
one only, without a second. From that non-being, being was produced.
But how could this be? How could Being be produced from non-Being?
On the contrary, in the beginning this world was just Being, one only, without
a second’.
In this intellectual milieu, the Being of beings is understood as the source,
basis, support and final cause what there is. It is the foundational ‘something
else’ out of which the world of entities emerges or unfolds. According to
this outlook, the cosmos has immanent order and purpose (dharma)
independently of any meanings that human beings might create for them-
selves. In the major Upanis.ads (composed between 800 and 400 B.C.) this
ontic support is called the Brahman – the Absolute, timeless, unconditioned
unlimited substance that needs nothing else in order to exist. Br.hadāran.yaka
Foundations of Brahminism 9
Upanis.ad (BAU) 1.4.10 says,
‘In the beginning there was only the Brahman, and it knew only itself (ātmānam),
thinking, “I am the Brahman”. From that, everything came into being.’
It is the imperishable principle (aks.ara), the thread upon which all realities are
woven. [BAU 3.8]
Soul’s secret name is, ‘the reality of what’s real’ for the real constitutes the vital
breaths and the soul is their essence. [BAU 2.1.2]
This soul is the honey of all beings, and all beings are the honey of this soul. The
radiant and immortal person in the soul and the radiant and immortal person who
is an individual self, they are both the soul. It is immortal. It is the Brahman. It is
10 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
the whole. This soul is the lord and king of all beings. As all the spokes are fas-
tened to the hub and rim of a wheel, so to the soul are fastened all beings, all the
gods, all the worlds, all the vital breaths, and all these people. [BAU 2.5.14–5]
The cosmos is thought of as a single whole that has essence and this is what is
called the Brahman. Individual selves, microcosms versions of the cosmos,
too have essence and this is what is called ātman. If essence is indivisible, the
Brahman equates to ātman. The Brahman and ātman come to be understood
as two sides of the same coin.
Another portion of the Br.hadāran.yaka Upanis.ad puts it like this:
Explain to me the Brahman (Reality) that is plain and not hidden, the ātman that
is within all. The soul (ātman) within all is this soul of yours.
What is the soul within all?
You cannot see the seer who sees. You cannot hear the hearer who hears. You
cannot think of the thinker who thinks. You cannot perceive the perceiver who
perceives objects. The soul within all is this soul of yours. . . . That is what is
beyond hunger and thirst, beyond sorrow and delusion, beyond old age and
death. When they know this soul, Brahmins cease to desire sons, wealth, other
worlds of experience and adopt the mendicant life. [BAU 3.4–5]
Shortly afterwards there is the question of on what the cosmos depends, the
thread running through everything, the inner controller (antar-yāmin) of this
world and the next, as well as all beings, who controls them from within. It is
said that when a person knows what the inner controller is, he understands
reality (brahman), he knows the worlds, he knows the gods, he knows the
Vedas, he knows the spirits, he knows the soul, he understands the whole.
This soul (ātman) of yours, who is present within but is different from the
earth [fire air, wind & other physical features], whom the earth does not know,
whose body the earth is, and who controls the earth from within – he is the inner
controller, the immortal one. . . . This soul of yours who is present within but
is different from all beings, whom all beings do not know, whose body is all
beings, and who controls all beings from within – he is the inner controller, the
immortal. . . . This soul of yours who is present within the breath but is different
from the breath [from speech, from sight & other sensory and cognitive functions],
whom the breath does not know, whose body is the breath, and who controls
the breath from within – he is the inner controller, the immortal. . . . That is
the seer who cannot be seen, the hearer who cannot be heard, the thinker
who cannot be thought of, the perceiver who cannot be perceived. There is
Foundations of Brahminism 11
no other who see etc. It is this soul of yours who is the inner controller, the
immortal. [BAU 3.7]
About this soul one cannot say anything. It is incomprehensible for it cannot be
grasped. [BAU 4.2.4]
This soul is the Brahman – this soul that constitutes perception, mind, breath,
sight, hearing, earth, water, wind, space, dharma and adharma – this soul that
constitutes everything. [BAU 4.4.5]
The breathing behind breathing, the sight behind sight, the hearing behind
hearing, the thinking behind thinking – those who know this perceive the
brahman, the first and the last. [BAU 4.4.18, cf Kena Up. 1.2]
It is the soul that should be seen, heard about, reflected upon and contemplated.
When the soul is seen, heard about, reflected upon and contemplated, the
cosmos becomes understood. [BAU 4.5.6]
Such a one is at peace, in control, unperturbed, patient and focussed for he sees
the soul in himself and he sees all things as the soul. [BAU 4.4.23]
Finally, some passages from the sixth chapter of the Chāndogya Upanis.ad that
will exercise a considerable influence on later thought, especially on the
Vedāntic systematizations of the Upanis.adic teachings. Uddālaka Ārun.i offers
to teach his son Śvetaketu how one hears what has not been heard before, how
one thinks what has not been thought of and how one understands what has
not been understood. He says that the teaching is:
From one lump of clay one understands the nature of anything that is made of
clay – the modification being a name, a taking hold by speech, while the truth is
that it just clay. (Ch.Up.6.1.4)
In the beginning there was just Being (sat), one without a second. . . . Being
reflected, ‘May I become many. Let me become productive.’ It generated heat.
Heat generated water. Water generated food. (Ch.Up. 6.2.1 and 3)
12 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
That divinity thought, ‘Let me diversify names and forms by entering those three
creative principles by means of the living self, and make each of them threefold’.
(Ch.Up.6.3.2)
Being is the source of all these creatures. Being is their support and Being is their
foundation. (Ch.Up.6.8.4)
Further reading
For Vedic Hinduism and the contents of the Vedic corpus see Jamison and Witzel (2003). This is
accessible online via Professor Witzel’s website.
Rig Vedic hymns are translated in Doniger (2005).
The Upanis.ads can be found in Olivelle (1998). There is also an OUP paperback that just has the
translation.
Essays II, V–X in van Buitenen (1988) have all been influential. Chapters I and II of Halbfass (1992) are
thought provoking about the ‘question of being’ in India.
Gautama Śākyamuni, who would become known as the Buddha, ‘the Enlight-
ened One’ probably lived in the period 450–400 B.C. Early Buddhism rejects
the notions of the Brahman and ātman, insisting that there are no enduring,
substantial realities. It teaches the essential temporality of beings. Things are
always changing. Nothing really lasts. There are no essences, no immutable
natures and universals, characterizing entities and running through reality as
a whole. It says that ritual religion is pointless and rejects the authority of the
Vedic scriptures. The attitude that self-advancement through ritual practices
is possible is a form of what the Buddha calls ‘greed’. It says that the caste
hierarchy, held by the Brahmins to be a natural fact, and the associated
deontological morality is nothing more than a system of social arrangements.
The Buddhist outlook denies that the cosmos has a single source and goal. If it
has a reason for being and an explanation for its dispositions, it is just so that
sentient beings may experience the fruits of their karmas.
Buddhists and Brahmins recognize that there are persons who remain
similar over time and whose futures are conditioned by their deliberate and
intentional decisions and actions. They differ about whether a basic principle
of identity is required to explain the continuity of such individuals. We might
depict the Buddhist as arguing that psychological continuity is enough for
14 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
sometimes argued that some of the alleged doctrinal differences – e.g. the
Mahāyānists emphasize compassion and insight, worship the Buddhas and
hold that the path to enlightenment is long and difficult – are not really
differences at all but belong to the shared heritage.
The basic principles of the Buddha’s teaching are expressed in ‘Four Noble
Truths’:
The Four Noble Truths are the key to enlightenment. But hearing is not
enough. They have to be acted upon, and this is where the path of morality and
meditation comes in. The path is said to consist in: right views, right thoughts,
right speech, right action, right livelihood, right effort, right mindfulness and
right concentration. Right views and thoughts are mind-purifying wisdom or
insight into the fleeting and unsatisfactory nature of existence; right speech,
action and livelihood are moral conduct; right effort, mindfulness and concen-
tration are understood as meditation. Buddhists insist that virtue is necessary
for the cultivation of meditation and insight. Intention (cetanā) is understood
as determining the moral quality of an action. Morality consists in deliberate
abstention from murder, theft, sexual misconduct, false speech, slander, harsh
words, frivolous talk, covetousness, malice and false views. Right livelihood
would preclude such occupations as arms-trading, dealing in drugs and alcohol
and butchering animals. Meditative concentration (samādhi) is the achievement
of tranquillity through avoidance of distractions, and by suppression of sensory
activity. Emphasis is placed upon mindfulness or exercising control through
constant self-awareness of one’s physical, mental and emotional states.
The path is the ‘middle way’ between the self-indulgent and ascetic lives,
neither of which lead to release from the desire-fuelled series of existences.
18 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
What is needed is the elimination of the basic defects of craving, aversion and
delusion.
The Buddha insisted that it is the intention (cetanā) with which an action is
performed that determines its ethical quality. He tells his followers to cultivate
attitudes of non-violence, honesty, friendliness, gentleness, compassion and
generosity. The right sorts of actions will follow. He did not provide a rulebook
stipulating particular types of ethical actions (although his followers did for
the monks) or an ethical theory. There are some basic principles: don’t
kill, don’t steal, don’t tell lies or indulge in malicious gossip, avoid sexual
misdemeanours and intoxicating substances. These are universal – not caste-
specific – in that they have moral application to everyone: I do not want to
be assaulted and can reasonably conclude that no other sane person wants
to be. There is a trend of thought running through Hinduism that there
may be ways of acting that do not generate karma. Representative here is
the idea, promoted in the Bhagavad Gītā, that since it is deliberately purpo-
sive actions that generate karma, actions done for their own or duty’s sake
without a view to the advantage of the agent will not generate karma. The
Buddha thought that karma was inescapable by sentient beings. The eight-
fold path recognizes this. It is sometimes argued that the outlook is conse-
quentialist, holding that it is overall states of affairs that have moral value.
Some ways of life have better overall consequences than others. The view is
that although the future of the stream that is your life is not your future, you
still have reason to care about its future, as well as that of all other streams. The
Buddhist path aims to promote general happiness. Since there really are
persons, it is not open to the objection that it ignores the separateness of
individuals and their integrity.
Moral conduct attenuates afflictions (kleśa) that prey upon the mind. These
weaknesses are familiar ones: ignorance in the sense of indulging oneself
in self-serving fantasies and believing whatever it suits one to believe; the
sheer selfishness that sees itself as the centre of the world; desire for sensory
gratifications; neurotic obsessions that divert attention from what matters;
an exalted opinion of one’s significance in the scheme of things. The texts
catalogue other impediments to spiritual progress, two of which we shall
mention briefly. There is attachment to rituals, central to the Brahminical way
of life, and vows, the latter being personal undertakings and commitments
such as the harsh austerities that Gautama had found useless. I think that the
word ‘kāma’ often moralistically translated as ‘lust’ or ‘sensual desires’ was
probably more specific and refers to those rituals performed by Brahmins that
Buddhist Origins 19
will produce yield benefits in this world for those patronizing them. The
Buddha thought that all ritual performances were at heart self-interested,
not to say a waste of time and effort.
The texts are rich in descriptions of and prescriptions for meditational
practices, aiming at the control and ultimately the cessation of discursive
mental activities. The Buddha described his path to enlightenment as an ascent
through a hierarchy of four stages of meditations (dhyāna) which, far from
involving ascetic rigours, are pleasant experiences:
Then indeed, having eaten enough, having got my strength back, free from desires,
free from unhelpful matters, I reached the first stage that is accompanied by thought
and reflection, which is produced by discrimination and consists of joyful happiness
and remained there. But this pleasant state did not put my mind at rest.
Stilling thought and refection I reached the second stage that is inner tranquillity,
a focussing of the mind on one point, free from thought and reflection, consisting
of joyful happiness that is born of concentration and remained there. But this
pleasant state . . .
I reached the third stage when I became detached from joy, indifferent to
pleasures and pains, attentively mindful and knew physical pleasures. But this . . .
From abandoning bliss and abandoning pain and thanks to the disappearance of
cheerfulness and depression, I reached the fourth stage that is beyond pleasures
and pains, the quintessence of equanimity and attentiveness. But this . . . [Majjhima
Nikāya 1.247]
No self
The early tradition raises queries about the coherence of the notion of the soul.
Is it the same as experiences? Is it non-experiential in character? Is it the pos-
sessor of experiences? The first view reduces self to transitory states, but it is
meant to be constant. The second is literally self-defeating. Such an entity could
never have the awareness, ‘I am’. The third view treats experiences as contingent
properties that the self might lack. So in that case the self might sometimes lack
the awareness, ‘I am’ [MahĀnidĀnasuttanta in DIghanikĀya II 67].
As an example of the sort of understanding of selfhood that the Buddha
repudiates, let us look at Chāndogya Upanis.ad 8.7.1:
The soul that is free from evils, wrong, free from old age and death, from sorrow,
from hunger and thirst, whose desires and intentions are ever realised, that is what
is to be discovered, that is what is to be understood. When someone discovers that
and understands it, he obtains all worlds and all his desires are fulfilled.
According to this Upanis.adic outlook, the soul is the key to the meaning of
life and ultimate well-being. The Buddha thought that the mentality to which
such thinking belongs is basically self-interested. He undermines it by saying
that there is no such thing as the soul: all we can say is that there are temporal
streams of experiences and ethical consequentiality. There is no difference
between you and your life – you are the same as your life-history. You do not
go through phases: there is just a succession of phases. It makes no sense to
ask, ‘what if my early upbringing had been different?’ because the question
would be about another stream of experiences.
If what we call the person is the stream of thoughts, who is thinking them?
The Buddhist view is that intrinsically self-aware subjectless thoughts are
thinking themselves, as well as each other. They do not need illumination
by consciousness belonging to a persisting subject. They form a continuous
entity by knowing their immediate predecessors and successors. William James
characterized a ‘no-self theory’ as follows: ‘Each pulse of cognitive consciousness,
each Thought, dies away and is replaced by another. The other, among the
Buddhist Origins 21
things it knows, knows its own predecessor . . . saying: “Thou art mine, and
part of the same self with me.” Each later thought, knowing and including
thus the thoughts which went before, is the final receptacle of all that they
contain and own. Each Thought is thus born an owner, and dies unowned,
transmitting whatever it realized as its Self to its own later proprietor’ (The
Principles of Psychology, Volume I, p. 339).
The early Buddhist tradition reductively analysed what we understand as
persons into processes consisting of five impersonal components (skandha):
It is apparent from the Pāli Canon that views about the nature of ‘the Self ’ –
what humans really are – were as multifarious during the Buddha’s time as
they are today. When fear of death perturbs the human spirit, we look for
something to hold on to that will exist in the future – or perhaps it won’t. Some
may think of ‘the self ’ in personal terms as the complex of experiences that
lasts for a while, others may understand it as a transcendental subject that is
exempt from worldly life and destined to exist for ever. It is this belief that
there is some sort of lasting self that is one of the varieties of grasping that only
lead to distress.
An early and popular scripture, the Snake Sutta in the Majjhima Nikāya,
echoes the Upanis.adic ethos:
The unenlightened person thinks of the body as his, as what he is, as his Self. He
sees feelings as his, as what he is, as his Self. He sees perceptions as his, as what
he is, as his Self. He sees thoughts as his, as what he is, as his Self. He sees
volitions and habits as his, as what he is, as his Self. He regards what he has seen,
heard sense known experienced, pursued and considered as his, as what he is, as
his Self. And there is the attitude, ‘The world and the soul are the same, and after
death this is what I shall be – permanent, enduring, eternal, immutable and I shall
exist like that forever.’ This view he regards as his, as what he is, as his self. . . . But
the enlightened persons does not think in these terms and so is not anxious about
what does not exist.
The point seems to be that identifying anything finite and transient, such as a
stream of embodied experiences, as a persisting personal identity (an obstacle
to enlightenment called ‘sat-kāya-dr.s.t.i’) is bound to lead to unhappiness and
anxiety. Thoughts and feelings just happen. In reality there is no one to whom
they happen. There is just a ‘bundle of perceptions’. The more sophisticated
understanding of oneself as a transcendental subject, really exempt from
worldly life and destined to exist forever, only leads to worry too. Will it really
continue? The enlightened person does not think in terms of either of these
egocentric frameworks, and that is the key to living without anxiety, without
obsessive self-concern. The key to happiness is not just altruism, but the
realization that there are no selves. The radical nature of the vision should
not be underestimated. Returning to the Snake Sutta:
When someone who does not have the view that the world and the soul are the
same, and that after death he will be permanent, enduring, eternal, immutable
and that he will exist like that for ever hears the Buddha’s teaching about
the abandonment elimination of theories, opinions and attachment to them, the
Buddhist Origins 23
teaching that aims at the suppression of clinging obsessive attachments, the
relinquishing of possessions, the end of craving, the cultivation of dispassion
and the extinction of greed, hatred and delusion – he does not think, ‘I shall be
annihilated. I shall be destroyed. I shall no longer exist.’ He is not distressed and
confused. He is not anxious about something that does not exist.
A much later work called the Questions of King Milanda relates a dialogue
about the no-self doctrine between Menander, the Greek king of Bactria in
what is now Afghanistan in the second century B.C., and a Buddhist monk
called Nāgasena. The text appears to be directed against a ‘personalist’ trend in
early Buddhism according to which the interactions of the five constituents of
personality (skandhas) produce a persisting individual that is reborn.
The monk says that he is called ‘Nāgasena’ but that is only a name, a label, a
conventional usage. It does not mean that there is a personal entity. The King
replies that this implies that in that case Nāgasena lacks parents, teachers
and superiors in the monastic order. It also rules out agency and moral
responsibility. At this point Nāgasena introduces the simile of the chariot,
which is made up of wheels axle, and chassis. The chariot is neither identical
with any one of its parts nor with their sum. The word ‘chariot’ is a conven-
tional designation for the collection. That is to say, if the chariot is dismantled,
we have collection of parts, not a chariot. Likewise with people. The name
‘Nāgasena’ is a conventional designation for a mental construction out of
the five constituents of personality. No person is found, as opposed to being
constructed. There is no further fact over and above the fleeting components
of the stream of experiences. (This perhaps overlooks the fact that the chariot
is the parts plus a structure.) Nevertheless, there is sufficient continuity within
the stream for us to make sense of agency and moral responsibility. The
Buddhist position is that moral responsibility does not require postulation
of a permanent self that is the subject of experiences. If we are to be happy,
we should be concerned about the future, even though it is not the future
of my self.
The tradition has it that the Buddha deliberately left a number of questions
unanswered. They include whether or not the world is eternal, whether or
not the world is infinite, whether self and body are the same, whether or not
enlightened beings (Buddhas) exist after death (a question that can be seen
as making the mistaken assumption that there are entities with determinate
identities).
In refusing to answer such questions the Buddha cannot be saying that
he does not know, for the Buddhas are omniscient. Rather, he is saying
that there is nothing to know. From the Buddhist point of view, such questions
24 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
The Vaibhās.ikas say that there are realities external to minds and that they are
directly perceptible. The Sautrāntikas say that there are realities external to minds
and that they are inferable from the occurrence of mental representations. The
Yogācāras deny that there are any realities external to minds. The Mādhyamikas
deny that there are any intrinsic natures.
Further reading
Bechert and Gombrich (1984) is a collection of essays covering all forms of Buddhism, and is
beautifully illustrated.
Buddhist Origins 25
Rupert Gethin’s Foundations of Buddhism is comprehensive. It is now supplementary to his invaluable,
Sayings of the Buddha. Walpola Rahula, What the Buddha Taught, is a classic, written from a
Theravādin point of view. Steven Collins, Selfless Persons, is indispensable for early Buddhist
(Theravādin) representations of persons. Richard Gombrich, How Buddhism Began, puts many
things in context. Jayatilleke (1980) is informative about Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge.
Edward Conze’s Buddhist Scriptures is a useful collection that contains the Questions of King
Milanda.
Bronkhorst (2000) contains translations of much original material and connects early Buddhism with
the Jaina renunciatory tradition. For the latter Jaini (1979) and Dundas (1992) are fundamental
contributions.
Mark Siderits, Personal Identity and Buddhist Philosophy, is a stimulating discussion of eastern and
western reductionist accounts of the self. So is Chapter Five of Paul Williams, Altruism and
Reality.
Chapter Outline
Ontology 27
Perception 31
Ethical consequentiality 32
The personalists (Pudgalavāda) 33
Further reading 34
Questions for discussion and investigation 34
Ontology
Sarvāstivāda means ‘the theory that everything exists’. The questions ‘What
exists?’ or ‘What is there?’ cannot be answered by merely listing objects. We
need a classification of types of existents. Moreover, there has to be some
criterion or standard of judging what really exists and that criterion here is
irreducibility: nothing that is composed of parts is authentically real. The basic
elements in which all mental and material phenomena consist are called
dharmas. They are so called because they support (dhāran.ād < dhr.) their own
identity. Each dharma has a fixed essence or intrinsic nature of its own
(svabhāva). It is this possession of a permanent, fixed identity that differenti-
ates the dharmas from the macroscopic aggregates. Svabhāva means intrinsic
nature consisting in a specific inherent characteristic or power (svalaks.an.a).
The svabhāva of earth atoms is solidity, that of water atoms is fluidity and
that of fire atoms heat. It is the svabhāva of consciousness to apprehend
objects. The svalaks.an.a is not other than whatever it characterizes. An object’s
‘having’ svabhāva means that its identity is not determined by anything
else. It means self-sufficiency or independent subsistence. The presence of
svabhāva is held to permit the uniquely individuating definitions of the
basic elements proposed by the endlessly ramifying Abhidharma catalogues:
‘differentiation from the natures of others is in virtue of svabhāva’
(Abhidharmakośa 1.18).
Other Buddhist philosophical traditions see a problem here. The basic
elements are said to have intrinsic natures. But intrinsic nature is construed as
28 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
Dharmas, the elements of all mental and material phenomena, are manifest
as the cosmos. They momentarily exercise their power in causal complexes.
Since their existence does not depend upon anything else, they are basic and
irreducible. The Sarvāstivādins distinguish between the primary and irredu-
cible existence (dravya-sat) that belongs to the dharmas and the conventional
or nominal existence (prajñapti-sat) that belongs to their products. Dharmas
as primary realities exist in what we call past, present and future – but strictly
Abhidharma Buddhism 29
speaking, they exist timelessly or eternally. Their momentary occurrence as
the world of our experience is the exercise of their causal efficacy (kāritram)
that is also termed ‘svalaks.an.a’. A parallel distinction is drawn between
absolute or ultimate truth and reality (paramārtha-satya) and conventional
truth (sam.vr.ti-satya). The latter is the world as it is understood by finite beings
participating in conditioned causal processes. The former means reality as it is
itself, as understood by the Buddhas, who are omniscient beings.
Some assumptions lie behind the Vaibhās.ika view:
i) All mental acts, including memories and expectations, have existent objects
external to the mind. If past and future phenomena are cognized, they exist.
Memories and future expectations have real objects.
ii) The subject-object relationship in awareness requires two real terms.
iii) To be is to cause an awareness: anything that is the object of an awareness exists.
iv) We cannot escape the consequences of past actions.
[Past and future dharmas exist] because a cognition has a real object. When there
is an object, there arises a cognition. When there is no object, there arises no
cognition. If past and future dharmas did not exist, there would be cognitions
with unreal objects as their objective support (ālambana). Therefore there would
be no cognition of the past and future because of the absence of objective
supports. If the past were non-existent, how could there be future effects of good
and bad actions? For at the time when the effect arises, the efficient cause of its
actualisation (vipāka-hetu) would not exist. That is why the Vaibhās.ikas hold that
past and future exist. (Abhidharmakośa-bhās.ya 5.25ab)
The Sarvāstivādins say that everything – past, future and present – exists. By
contrast, the Vibhajyavādins say that only the present exists, as well as past
actions that have not yet yielded their consequences. What will be future, and
actions that have borne fruit do not exist. (Abhidharmakośa-bhās.ya 5.25cd)
(We shall be looking at the developed Vibhajyavāda view in the next chapter.)
A reality that is past has ceased due to impermanence. A reality that is future has
not originated. A reality that is present has originated and not yet ceased. When
basic realities (dharmas) exercise efficacy, this is called the present. If dharmas do
not yet exercise it, this is called the future. If efficacy has gone, this is called the
past. (Abhidharmakośa-bhās.ya 1.20)
The Vaibhās.ika view is that what we experience as the present is the exercise
of efficacy (phala-āks.epa-śakti) – the power of projecting effects that belongs
to a complex of dharmas. Svalaks.an.a is the same as specific function or
30 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
Perception
Where our interactions with the world about us are concerned, the Vaibhās.ikas
are direct realists. Macroscopic combinations of the atomic factors are the
causes and direct objects of awareness (an.u-sam.caya-vāda). Consciousness
is thought of as a blank page and is not affected by external reality. It reveals
objects without undergoing any change in its own constitution. This view
is called nirākāra-vāda and it means that our perceptions of objects are
unmediated by mental images, representations or ideas that fall as a veil
between mental acts and external reality.
mind is that by which we grasp thoughts. This covers thinking about our
experiences of objects and states of affairs that are not present to the senses.
Ethical consequentiality
It is difficult to see how we could lead ethical lives if only the present were real.
The extension of causality to future consequences is a condition of ethical
being. Moreover, we all know that the past may return to haunt us. The
Buddhist insistence upon the importance of morality as the path to liberation
is apparently challenged by two of its own tenets: All conditioned things
(sam.skārā) are impermanent. All phenomena (dharma) are impersonal.
If ethically significant intentional actions are conditioned events, and thus
transitory and impersonal, how can they have subsequent effects in lives?
Buddhists believe that liberation is not possible for those who do not accept
that what is conventionally called (prajñapti) self is only a stream of compon-
ents of personality. Unenlightened people mistakenly believe in an identity that
is a further fact over and above the transient flux of embodied experiences.
From this attachment to the soul arise the afflictions such as grasping, aversion
and delusion. In fact, the notions of self and individual personal agency are
but conventional human constructs. The underlying reality of what we call
the person is a complex of components (skandhas) that admit of yet further
reduction into the real basic elements. Nevertheless, a causal chain of embod-
ied experiences is sufficient for the origin of the delusion that is personality.
It is the intentional actions of conscious beings alone that are responsible for
the arising and organization both of the sphere (loka) of creatures and of the
environments in which they may experience the consequences of their actions.
This is intended to exclude God, Time, the Soul or Prime Matter as causes of
the cosmos. Intention (cetanā), which is a mental phenomenon (dharma)
occurring in a stream, qualifies an action as ethically good or bad. But how do
actions have long-term consequences? The answer is that an intentional action
has both public expression (vijñapti-dharma) and a discrete feature called
avijñapti-dharma. The latter embeds itself in a stream of experiences and
remains there until circumstances are appropriate for the actualization (vipāka)
of its efficacy in that stream. This avijñapti-dharma is charged with the moral
quality of the public action from which it has arisen. The location of avijñapti
in an experiential series requires what are called ‘possessions’ (prāpti). The
latter belong to the class of those basic elements that are neither material nor
Abhidharma Buddhism 33
mental (citta-viprayukta-dharma) and are necessary if any phenomenon is to
adhere to the experiential stream in which it occurs. The avijñapti-dharmas
also account for settled commitments such as the Buddhist discipline and
dispositions of character.
As long as we think in selfish terms, the series of births does not cease. Selfishness
stays in the heart while there is belief in the soul. No other teacher in the world
propounds the unreality of the Self. So there is no path to peace other than your
teaching.
stability for a while. Vasubandhu responds that if this ‘something’ were really
supervenient upon the constituents from which it emerges, it would be
knowable. If it is not a newly emergent entity, it is reducible to the constituents
and there is no point in positing it. Our experience can be explained as a
continuum of mental (and physical events) and there is no need to posit any
sort of self as the subject that owns the experiences.
Further reading
L. Pruden (1988) is an English version of Louis de la Vallée Poussin’s French translation of the
Abhidharmakośabhās.ya.
E. Frauwallner, Studies in the Abhidharma Literature, especially Chapter VIII, is a rich source of
information.
P. S. Jaini (2001), Section IV, contains some influential articles.
Alexis Sanderson, ‘The Sarvāstivāda and its Critics’, is illuminating. (This may be accessed via
Professor Sanderson’s website.)
James Duerlinger’s Indian Buddhist Theories of Persons, translates Vasubandhu’s critique of the
Pudgalavāda soul theory in the Abhidharmakośa.
The last chapter saw brief references to the Vibhajyavāda tradition. This out-
look became prominent and acquired the name ‘Sautrāntika’. They maintained
that only the Pāli Suttas, not the Abhidharma texts, were the authentic words
of the Buddha. They think that the Vaibhās.ikas have obscured the simplicity of
the Buddha’s original teaching and introduced the notion of permanence in
the guise of svabhāva. Hence they taught a doctrine of radical momentariness
(ks.an.ika-vāda), and simplified the ontology of the Vaibhās.ikas. They reject the
36 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
Ethical consequentiality
The Sautrāntikas account for karmic continuity by saying that an intentional
action, albeit instantaneous, is a ‘seed’ that initiates a transformation in an
experiential series (citta-sam.tāna-parin.āma-viśes.a). Its fruition is either
reward or punishment. The originating cause need not last until its effect is
realized since it is not a sustaining cause – like parents who are necessary for
the origination but not the continued existence of their offspring. They argue
that if an action continued to exist until its fruition, it would have to be eternal.
But if it ceased to exist, it could not produce anything. A seed initiates a series
beginning with germination. The fruit arises as the culmination of the series,
rather than directly from the seed. But it still needs the seed to start the process.
Although the series and the result depend upon the seed as the originating
cause, we do not say that the seed is either annihilated or that it is eternal.
Likewise an intention initiates a series of mental events from which the con-
sequence results. The series requires the initial intention and the consequence
arises from the series. The intention is neither annihilated, nor is it eternal.
(i) The logical reason (hetu) must really be a property of the subject (paks.a) of the
inference.
(ii) The logical reason must be present in some instance (sapaks.a) other than the
subject of the inference, which is similar to that subject in that it too possesses
the property that is to be proved (sādhya).
(iii) Whatever lacks the property to be proved also lacks the proving property or rea-
son. There must be no instances (vipaks.a) where the proving property occurs and
the property to be proved does not.
Take the inference that sounds (paks.a) are impermanent (sādhya) because they
are products (hetu). [Invariable association: Whatever is produced is imperman-
ent.] Here the sapaks.a could be something uncontroversially impermanent
such as a pot that also exhibits the property of being a product. It is open to us
to cite an actual instance illustrating the joint absence of the property to be
proved and the logical reason. The atmosphere would be a negative example
because it both lacks impermanence and is not produced by effort.
Sautrāntika Buddhism 41
The Ālambana-parı̄ks.ā
According to the Vaibhās.ika direct realists, the objective ground (ālambana-
pratyaya) of a thought is the reality in the world that it is about. According to
this theory, an objective ground is both the extra-mental cause of an idea
and the provider of its representational content. An hallucination is not an
objectively grounded thought in the sense that it has content but it is caused by
some defect in the perceptual system. Dignāga agrees that for something to
qualify as the objective ground of an awareness, it must be both the cause and
the representative content of that awareness, but he does not accept that such
causes have to be extra-mental realities.
In his Ālambana-parīks.ā, Dignāga argues against the Vaibhās.ikas that their
realistic atomic theory actually leads to the admission that the direct objects of
perceptual awareness are internal mental forms and not mind-independent
realities. The Vaibhās.ikas hold that we directly perceive structured masses
of real atoms of various kinds and that these cause our perceptions. Like
Sautrāntika Buddhism 43
Vasubandhu, Dignāga questions the possibility of atomic aggregation. But
even granting that collections of atoms may cause mental representations, the
atoms do not figure in the subjective content of awareness. A compound of
clay atoms may cause the perception of a pot, but we do not see such a cluster
of atoms. The atoms do not enter into the content of the representation:
what we have is an experience of a solid, coloured extended object. It could
be argued that a conglomerate of atoms does constitute the representative
content. But the problem here is that conglomerates are not real and so fail to
qualify as causes of ideas. Dignāga concludes that only an idea (a mental rep-
resentation that appears as if it is about something external) can be the support
of another idea. The cause of a mental representation can be another represen-
tation: thoughts may arise from other thoughts rather than from external
objects. An idea may bring about another idea and be sufficiently like it to mir-
ror its representational content. Although it seems that the conclusion is an
idealist one, Dignāga is not an idealist. He believes that the momentary par-
ticulars exist independently of minds, but the direct objects of acquaintance
are their representations in consciousness. He wants to persuade us that our
shared, conventional framework of representations is just that, and that our
thoughts and concepts do not mirror reality as it is in itself. The goal is to
encourage us to realize that our everyday attachments, and our thinking in
terms of ourselves as persisting individual subjects confronting a world of
already established propertied objects awaiting our descriptive understanding,
are really just matters of conventional construction. Once such realization is
achieved we are in a position to detach ourselves from our basically self-
centred concerns and follow the path of insight and compassion leading
towards enlightenment.
Even if the atoms are the cause of sensory cognition, since the cognition
does not represent them, the atoms are not the intentional object (vis.aya) of the
cognition (just as the sensory faculties are not).
Although the atoms are the cause of the manifestation of the thought-form, their
nature is not grasped by cognition (just as the nature of the sense faculties is not).
It makes sense that when a thing produces a cognition that represents it as it is,
that thing is the objective support. It has been stated that such is the originating
condition. But the conglomerate of atoms does not qualify as such
because it is not a reality – like the experience of the moon seeming double.
In the case of seeing the moon as double owing to a sensory defect, although
the moon appears double in awareness, it is not the direct object of awareness.
Likewise the conglomerate is not the objective support because it cannot be the
cause since it does not exist as a real entity.
The external things called ‘atom’ and ‘conglomerate of atoms’ are not the
supports of awareness, because although the atoms cause the awareness they do
not feature in its representative content, and while the conglomerate appears as
the content of awareness, it is not its cause.
Some hold that the aggregated form is the instrumental cause of the cognition.
The form of the atom is not the object of awareness, in the same way that its
solidity is not.
While there are no differences between the atoms that make up objects, it
may be said that the differences between perceived objects emerge from the
different formations of atoms. But this is not the case because (according to
the opponent) the atoms that are the only true realities do not have different
dimensions. The differences between the forms of objects operate on the level of
human conventions. Conventional modes of differentiation do not apply to the
atoms. Everyday objects are posited by the human mentality.
Pots etc exist only as human conventions because if the atoms are taken away
the cognition whose form derives from them is lost. But this does not happen in
Sautrāntika Buddhism 45
the case of what is truly real. Therefore it is intelligible that the direct objects of
sensory perceptions are not realities external to minds.
But the knowable internal form, which appears as if external to the mind, is the
direct object because it has the form of awareness and is its support.
Although there are no external objects, an internal reality, an idea appearing as if
external, is the objective support.
The internal mental form is the objective support of awareness since it both
supplies the manifest image in the cognition of the object, and produces the cog-
nition of the object. (The internal form both supplies the manifest image belong-
ing to the cognition (which the atoms do not) and is the cause (which the
conglomerate qua unreal, cannot be)).
Dharmakı̄rti
Dharmakīrti identifies belief in a substantial, permanent and personal self as
a form of ignorance, indeed enchantment. This ignorance is a genuinely
effective occurrence that brings about a complex of a specific mentality and
behavioural dispositions (sam.skāra). Belief in the self is inherited from mis-
taken constructions of selfhood in previous lives. From mistaken adherence
to belief in the self arise the moral defects (kleśa) such as desires, infatuations
and antagonisms. The settled condition that is attachment to the self is
expressed in first personal thoughts: ‘The innate belief in a personal reality
is expressed in I-thoughts such as: “May I be happy, may I not suffer.” ’
Attachment to self is inextricably associated with the notion of ‘mine’ and
this inevitably generates desires – we want things to go well for ourselves.
It automatically generates hatred and aversions towards whatever is felt to
be inimical to one’s own interests – often what are imagined to be other selves.
Striving for personal happiness conceals the true nature of the moral defects
so we do not see them for what they are. As long as there is clinging to
self, there is rebirth. But following the Buddhist path, including repeated
meditation on the unreality of the person and the way in which belief in the
self ’s reality causes suffering and frustration, on the impermanence and
non-substantiality of phenomena, gradually eliminates misunderstanding
and the consequent moral defects. Interiorization of and insight into univer-
sal non-substantiality, seeing the truth, are the proper functions of a purified
mind. Philosophy helps by revealing that nothing real can be permanent. We
are captivated by an inherited and shared web of conceptualization
(kalpanā). But the validity of the teaching that dispels our enchantment
(moha) is known by its fruits.
46 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
Metaphysics
Dharmakīrti agreed with Dignāga that in the final analysis objective reality
is a flux of momentary particulars (svalaks.an.a) that are inexpressible and
incommunicable as such. By virtue of their configurations in relation to the
cognizing subject, they determine the differences in the representative content
of cognitions. Each svalaks.an.a has its own causal effectiveness (arthakriyā).
Dharmakīrti develops Dignāga’s view. Instead of saying what is real by
specifying some type of entities (e.g. the svalaks.an.as or the dharmas), he uses
a criterion: only what is causally effective is real. Nothing permanent can be
causally effective either successively or in the present because it cannot engage
in processes of change. Each particular has specific location, time and form. If
something does not perform useful activity, then it is not a real entity, since it
satisfies the criteria for non-existence; but if it does perform useful activity,
then it is not permanent. This criterion of reality rules out the existence
of anything supposedly eternal and unchanging such as God, the soul and
its permanent consciousness, the sounds of the Vedic scriptures, the eternal
relation between Vedic words and their meanings, universals and primal
material nature (prakr.ti) that is inert prior to its plural manifestation as the
cosmos. The question about the reality of otherwise of permanence is central
to the dialectic between Buddhists and Brahmins, some aspects of which we
will be examining in later chapters.
Dharmakīrti follows Dignāga’s epistemology: only sensory perception and
inference are means of knowing (pramān.a). Knowledge is reliable cognition in
so far as it contributes to the successful accomplishment of some purpose. It
may also reveal something new: but to Dharmakīrti’s mind, the instrumental
function is primary and matter of fact truths are revealed in practice. Although
like Dignāga he refuses to accept that testimony and language can be epistemic
authorities in their own right – they are primarily thinking here of the absolute
authority that the Brahmins ascribe to the uncreated Vedic scriptures – in fact,
he says that language may be an instrument of knowing in the derivative sense
that it communicates what are already established to be useful truths about
what is to be sought after and what avoided. The Buddha, and the scriptural
records of his teachings, are sources of knowledge in that they reveal things
that would be otherwise unknown, and tell the truth about what should be
pursued and what eschewed.
As we have seen, according to the Sautrāntika outlook there are no permanent
realities. To be real is to be causally effective and that implies the capacity for
Sautrāntika Buddhism 47
change. But they take it for granted that were there anything permanent
it could neither act nor change. Dharmakīrti says that there is no such thing
as a permanent means of knowing (nityam. pramān.am) such as the Vedic
scriptures or a divine intelligence because knowledge operates in a world of
changing realities. A means of knowing cannot be unchanging because it is
concerned with impermanent objects. Whatever happens as part of a process
cannot be permanent and unchanging. Something permanent could not be a
means of knowing about what is impermanent because it could not depend
upon assisting factors such as objects, subjects and instruments in the case of
the knowing process. The means of knowing are such because they enable us
to achieve our goals in a world of ever changing realities.
Dharmakīrti’s theory about the relation between perception and the world can
be understood in terms of the triad: sensation – image – concept. A cluster of
svalaks.an.as has the power to produce the sensation of blue. Blue impressions
produce an awareness having two aspects: a blue mental image (ākāra) and the
blue mental image’s being aware of itself. The image copies the impressions.
Constructive mental activity (kalpanā), conditioned by traces of prior experi-
ences, interprets the image and produces the thought (vikalpa) that something
is blue. This thought enables us to think, act and communicate. The external
particulars are only the indirect objects of the thoughts that they cause. But
the unique instants behave in such a way that we can organize them under
unifying concepts. While our concepts, involving the association of names
and general properties with the given, do not copy the fluid play of the real
particulars, they represent it indirectly as a map does as territory. We do
not directly know reality as it is in itself because we are primarily aware of
images, some of which are converted into concepts, derived form sensory
impressions. In short, there is a gap between the way our minds work and the
way things work.
Sense perception on its own has no practical application because it does
not discriminate anything. Assuming that the senses are operating normally
and environmental conditions do not obstruct them, it cannot be either true
or false because truth and falsity apply only to conceptual mental states.
Perceptual sensation applies to reality as it is in itself (vastu) before we start to
thinking about it. But it is only when an aspect of reality has been mentally
discriminated in a perceptual judgement (adhyavasāya) that we can act in rela-
tion to it. Judgements using concepts enable successful activity (i.e. are reliable)
when they are causally related to the real particulars constituting events.
A vikalpa is a concept that the mind constructs out of the data given in
sensory awareness. Cognitions involving apparently shared features of objects
are conceptual interpretations based on experiences of particulars. Conceptu-
alization involves generalizations but there are no objective generalities.
Sautrāntika Buddhism 49
Objective reality is strictly ineffable, since it includes no general features. Like
Dignāga, he wants us to realize that our conventional ways of understanding,
integral to which is the notion of individual subjectivity, in the final analysis
disguise the truth.
But to find our way around successfully, we need to make discriminations
using concepts and words. Some concepts, and elaborated conceptual schemes,
apply more adequately than others to objective reality: i.e. they work better for
us in leading to successful activity. Vikalpas interpret and organize the data of
sensation, making them intelligible and serviceable. The store of human
concepts, built up from impressions derived from a beginningless series of
previous experiences, is transmitted down the generations via shared language.
While some complex concepts ultimately derive from sensory impressions
and mental images formed from them, others, especially the idea that there is
a persisting soul, are just produced by the creative imagination.
A problem arises when people overlook the purely conventional nature of
what are only human ways of thinking and suppose that they correspond
to objective realities. It is a natural mistake to suppose that our concepts
are copies of reality or that our representations mirror reality as it is in itself.
Error occurs when conceptual thought takes its own forms to correspond
directly to reality. Since reality consists of momentary unique particulars,
general concepts cannot represent it as it is in itself. Moreover, stable concepts,
enshrined in language, encourage us to think that there are stable realities.
A much-quoted verse (354) from the Chapter on Perception of the
Pramān.avārttika reads:
Later thinkers sometimes read this in an idealist sense, but that it not
Dharmakīrti’s meaning. He means that the oppositions between the perceiv-
ing subject, objects and thoughts are functions of the way our minds work and
not genuine realities. It is we who contrast subjects and objects, thinking them
external to each other. The differentiation of subjects, acts and objects of cog-
nition within the one mind appears because of inherited influences of previous
ideas in a beginningless and uninterrupted stream of experiences. Positing
oneself as an individual thinker facing a world of objects is a kind of selfishness
that Buddhist practice aims to eliminate. Since the polar notions of object and
subject are interdependent, by exposing the falsity of one, we can expose the
50 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
falsity of the other. Once a person has really understood that the conventional
view of reality as consisting of enduring objects existing independently of the
mind of the individual perceiver is false and that our thoughts are not copies of
reality, they can come to understand that selfhood and its attachments is an
illusory construct.
Logic
As we have seen Dharmakīrti thinks that while immediate sensation relates
directly to reality that consists of unique instantaneous particulars, the mental
images (ākāra) and concepts (vikalpa) that they cause and in terms of
which we interpret what is given do so indirectly. But Dharmakīrti does
not think that our concepts are imaginary inventions, although some are.
The instantaneous actualities behave in such a way that we can organize
them under concepts. Although the natural regularity (svabhāva-pratibandha)
52 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
between smoke and fire or that between something’s being an oak and its
being a tree holds primarily between two concepts, it also reflects a real state
of affairs that causes us to make the connection between the concepts.
Dharmakīrti says that inference does not grasp the realities directly in that it
operates by determining the object in a mental representation that is not itself
the object. But because the representation of the object is causally related to
the real objects, we can make reliable inferences.
The key feature of a valid logical inference is the invariant association
(vyāpti) between the logical reason (hetu) and what is to be established
(sādhya). Dharmakīrti says that the invariant association of As with Bs (which
he also calls avinābhāva –‘sine qua non’) must be guaranteed by a natural
regularity (svabhāva-pratibandha). The theory of natural regularity attempts
to underpin some forms of inseparable connection in the absence of objective
universals. We know that the connection between the logical reason and the
property to be proved could not be otherwise when the connection is either
that between cause and effect (kārya-hetu: e.g. fire and smoke) or a case of
shared nature (tadātmya /svabhāva-hetu – if something is an oak, then it is a
tree). This necessary relation is the natural regularity. So we may infer from
the fact of something’s being an oak that it is a tree and from the presence of
smoke to the presence of fire. This principle is applied in characteristically
Buddhist arguments like, ‘If something is produced, it is perishable by nature’.
While Dignāga seems to have been content to allow that the idea of
invariable association is the product of a finite range of observed instances,
as well as the lack of counterexamples (adarśana-mātra), Dharmakīrti wants
to strengthen the basis of inference because the inductive approach is insuffi-
ciently general and leaves open the possibility of our discovering exceptions in
the future. His teacher Īśvarasena thought that our constant association of the
logical reason (hetu) and that which is to be established (sādhya) was based
merely on the fact of our not having observed any exceptions to the rule
(adarśanamātra). Dharmakīrti thought that this made the basis of inference
too fragile: why should we not discover an exception in the future? Moreover,
we have not surveyed every relevant instance. We do not know that there is no
instance where the hetu occurs and the sādhya does not. We just have not
come across one so far. This is why he argued that the inseparability of hetu
and sādhya had to be grounded in the natural order of things. This means that
the presence of the logical reason guarantees the presence of the property to be
proved. There can be no counterexample.
Sautrāntika Buddhism 53
We saw that causal connection is one of the two forms of natural regularity
between the logical reason and what is to be proved. A causal relation is
understood through positive and negative perceptions. The causal connection
between smoke and fire is known when we find that smoke, which had not
been present, appears when fire is introduced and that when the fire is
extinguished, the smoke disappears.
Dharmakīrti applies this in a proof of the existence of streams of experience
other than one’s own. He argues that we have inferential knowledge of other
minds. Given that in one’s own case there is observation of the phenomena of
language and behaviour immediately after volition or intention, and given that
they are not observed in the absence of volition, one knows from one’s own
case that there is a cause-effect relation between volition and the occurrence of
actions. The causal relation is established purely because we are cognizant of
the relations between intention and action and know that where there is no
intention there is no action. Seeing that actions separate from us occur even
when we have not framed any intention, we infer intentions elsewhere to be
the cause of those other actions. Thus other minds are established. Just as I
know from my own case that certain actions are preceded by certain thoughts,
so I may analogously infer that similar patterns of speech and behaviour on the
part of other people show that they are separate streams of experiences.
According to Dharmakīrti, the non-apprehension (anupalabdhi) of an
entity that is in principle perceptible (dr.śya) establishes the absence or non-
existence of that entity. This applies to the problem of other minds: from the
fact that we do not perceive them it does not follow that they do not exist
because they do not fall under the category of the in-principle perceptible. But
the case of the Brahminical concept of the Self (ātman) is different. Those who
believe that the Self is a basic reality characterize it as something that should
be uncontroversially knowable. Dharmakīrti and other Buddhists focus on the
problems of disentangling the soul from the personality and its experiences.
They reason that it is never known, although it is described as the sort of
thing that is knowable. This non-apprehension proves its non-existence. The
same pattern of reasoning is applied to the notion of Prime Matter (prakr.ti),
which is supposed by Sam.khyas and Vedāntins to be the ultimate source
and underlying cause of all material products. But the fact that we do not see
supernatural entities, such as ghosts, does not prove that they do not exist
because they are by nature inaccessible to normal perception. This applies to
anything inaccessible to perception by virtue of space, time or its nature.
54 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
Further reading
Satkari Mookerjee, The Buddhist Philosophy of Universal Flux is about both Dignāga and Dharmakīrti
and the many disputes between their school and the Naiyāyika, Mīmām.saka and Sām.khya realists.
M. Hattori, Dignaga, On Perception reconstructs some of the first chapter Pramān.a-samuccaya and
covers much more than perception.
R. Hayes, Dignaga on the Interpretation of Signs, has translations of chapters II and V of the
Pramān.a-samuccaya.
There is a translation and exposition of the Ālambana-Parīks.ā in Tola and Dragonetti (2004).
For the text of the Pramān.avārttika see Pandeya (1989). For that of the Nyāyabindu see Svami
Dvarkadasa Sastri (1994).
Kajiyama (1998) translates a work belonging to the Dignāga-Dharmakīrti tradition.
John Dunne, Foundations of Dharmakirti’s Philosophy contains detailed treatments of ontology,
epistemology, logic and the philosophy of language. There is a valuable Appendix of translations.
Siderits (1991) deals with the philosophy of language, especially the apoha theory, which
has attracted much scholarly attention in recent years. The Nyāya response is to be found in
Uddyotakara’s commentary on Nyāya-Sūtra 2.2.63. (Jha (1984), p. 1034 ff.)
Sautrāntika Buddhism 55
The articles in Tom Tillemans, Scripture, Logic and Language combine philosophical acuity and
philological expertise.
Vincent Eltschinger, Penser l’autorité des Écritures does much more than that and is a mine of
information about Dharmakīrti’s intellectual context and religious concerns.
Bimal Matilal, Perception, relates Buddhist representationalism to modern concerns.
Claus Oetke (1994), Trairūpya, puts Dignāga’s logic in context, tracing its antecedents and relating it to
Nyāya and Vaiśes.ika parallels.
Chapter Outline
Verses from Nāgārjuna’s Ratnāvalı̄ 60
Refutation of Objections 65
Further reading 67
Questions for discussion and investigation 67
Nāgārjuna (c. 150–200 A.D.) was a monk trained in the Abhidharma tradition,
which tried to delineate the basic structures of reality as understood from the
ultimate point of view. He repudiated this enterprise that involved categor-
izing mental and material phenomena into types of basically real elements
(dharma) having essential natures (svabhāva). Sometimes when Nāgārjuna
says that he is not offering a theory of his own, he may have the Abhidharma
taxonomical activity in mind! Nāgārjuna holds that supposition that things
have unchanging and enduring natures, either at the fundamental or macro-
scopic level, only encourages us to become attached to them. He thought
that the Sarvāstivādins were in effect aspiring to make statements about
reality as a whole from a totally objective point of view. Nāgārjuna denies that
any such perspective is attainable by us unenlightened beings. There is no
point in our even attempting to distinguish between ultimate truth and
conventional truth.
His argumentative strategy is to list the possible propositions about some
subject-matter. He then examines them and shows that they are inconsistent
or lead to erroneous or unwanted conclusions. So he denies all of them. Using
this method, he tries to show that our theories and conceptual constructions
Nāgārjuna and Madhyamaka Buddhism 57
cannot capture reality. Since we are not Buddhas, we can attain no grasp of
reality as it is in itself.
His most significant philosophical works include the Madhyamaka-kārikās,
the Vigrahavyāvartanī and the Ratnāvalī. His thought is the subject of a long
exegetical tradition that continues to this day. He is sometimes difficult to
understand. This is because we do not always know the specific questions
to which his statements are the answer. The most important commentator
is Candrakīrti (600–650 A.D.) who wrote the Prasannapadā. Śāntideva’s
(700–750) Bodhicāryāvatara, describing the Bodhisattva’s path to final
enlightenment is another influential work.
According to the Abhidharma traditions, the basic elements (dharma)
have intrinsic natures or essences (svabhāva). Intrinsic nature was thought
to be timeless, self-sufficient, independent of all else and unchanging. (The
last predicate is crucial.) It is the possession of such permanent identity that
distinguishes the basic elements from the temporary conditioned aggregates
that are the objects of everyday thought and language and grounds the distinc-
tion between ultimate reality and conventional reality. Nāgārjuna insists that
neither everyday objects nor the dharmas can have intrinsic natures. If they
had, there would be no change. Reification, the investiture of states of affairs
and objects with persisting identities, comes naturally to us. But in truth,
everything is empty of intrinsic nature (svabhāva-śūnya). Emptiness (śūnyatā)
must always be understood as meaning ‘absence of essence’. It does not mean
non-existence. He often says that what we normally consider things, and the
concepts with which we carve up reality, are neither real not unreal. That is to
say, while our discursive conceptual schemes and the entities that they posit do
serve our purposes to an extent, they cannot be the whole truth.
There are no entities with having intrinsic natures that have arisen either from
themselves, or from other things, or from both themselves and others, or from no
causes. [MMK 1.1]
The origination of intrinsic nature from causes and conditions is not intelligible.
Intrinsic nature produced by causes and conditions would be created. But
how could intrinsic nature be created? For intrinsic nature is uncreated and not
dependent on anything else. [MMK XV, 1–2]
Since there is no entity (dharma) that has not arisen dependently on others, there
is no entity that is not empty of intrinsic nature. [MMK XXIV, 19]
us in the right direction by recommending a way of life that he had found led
to enlightenment, had to use some language. He did not say anything positive
about nirvān.a because it is not a state, thing or entity.
Paradoxes and inconsistencies in our ways of thinking show that we cannot
formulate a complete and correct description of reality ‘as it is in itself ’
independently of any particular perspective. In the Madhyamaka-kārikās,
Nāgārjuna subjects what realists take to be basic concepts such as those of
causality, motion, time, agency, self and substance to criticism. He shows that
they are cases of reification and conceptual construction. He thinks that it is
pointless to entertain the possibility that our limited conceptual capacities
and schemes can capture the ultimate truth. We cannot step outside the
world, look at it from the outside and make definitively true statements about
it as a whole. We cannot frame an absolute conception of reality and we are
wasting our time and spiritual possibilities in seeking to. We cannot formulate
a correct and comprehensive ontological theory from a totally objective
‘Olympian’ point of view, which is what the Abhidharma attempts to do. This
is one meaning of what he calls, ‘the emptiness of emptiness’. Emptiness is
not ‘a reality’ and there is no essence of emptiness.
Living well is happiness, and freedom from rebirth is the ultimate good. Trust in
the Buddha’s teaching and insight are the means to that good. If he has trust, a
person may share the path. If he has insight [into emptiness], he knows truly.
Of the two, insight is the most important, but trust comes first. [4–5]
One who does not transgress the path because he is led by his own desires,
antagonisms, anxiety and delusions is to be considered trusting. [6]
(The wise person reflects upon the moral value of his actions. He avoids
violence and killing, theft and sexual misconduct. He controls his tongue to
avoid lying, cruel words and malicious gossip.)
The interactions of the five components (skandhas) arise from the sense of
personal individuality (aham. kāra). Personal individuality is not a genuine reality.
If the seed of something is unreal, how can its sprout be real? [29]
When it is seen that the components are unreal, the sense of individuality is given
up. From the giving up of that, the skandhas no longer function. [30]
Just as one sees the reflection of one’s face in a mirror, although it is not the real
thing, so one conceives individual personality on the basis of the components,
although it is not a genuine reality like the reflection of one’s face in the mirror.
[31–32]
Just as there appears no reflection of one’s face without a mirror, so without the
five components individual personality does not appear. [33]
While there is grasping at the components, there is the thought ‘I’. When there is
belief in personal individuality there is karma and rebirth. [34]
[Just as a mirage looks like water, but is neither water nor really anything, so the
components look like a persisting self but they are not really a self. [54]]
When one understands the relation of cause and effect in this way, one realises
that the world as a whole cannot be considered as an entity that might or might
not exist. [38]
(If the notion of causation belongs to the sphere of our experience in that it is
to be understood in terms of relations between finite things, how can we apply
62 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
it to the cosmos as a whole and argued that it must come from someone or
something?)
Followers of the Upanis.adic tradition do not worry when they say that familiar
worldly life will not exist in the state of liberation. So why are they afraid when we
say that there are no absolutely real entities here either? [40]
In the state of release (moks.a) there are neither individual identities nor the five
components. But if such a state is dear to you, why do you resist the elimination
of the self and the components in this life? [41]
It is not the case that nirvān.a is non-existent. But what could constitute it as an
entity? Nirvān.a is beyond the concepts of being and non-being. [42]
In brief, the nihilist theory denies that actions have consequences. This false view
is immoral and leads to hell. [43]
In brief, the true view is that actions have consequences. This correct view brings
merit and rebirth in good states. [44]
When thanks to insight one has ceased to think in terms of what is and what is
not, one no longer thinks in terms of merit and demerit. The good say that this is
freedom (moks.a) that is beyond good and bad births. [45]
***
If a cause is produced before its effect or simultaneously with it, in reality it is not
a cause. The concept of origination is incoherent, either from the absolute or the
conventional point of view. [47]
Causal relations may be expressed like this: when A is present, B arises. For
instance when we have the idea of long, that of short arises. When something is
Nāgārjuna and Madhyamaka Buddhism 63
produced there is production of something else – such as radiance after the
production of a lamp. [48]
When one understands causality like this, it does not lead to nihilism. [50]
The world does not come into existence. It does not go out of existence. It does
not remain static even for an instant. How can we say that the world as a whole,
to which the categories of past, present and future do not apply, is real? [63]
In truth, since the temporal framework does not apply to either the world or to
nirvān.a, how can we specify a real difference between the two? [64]
Given that there is no duration, there is neither origination nor cessation. So how
can the world be produced, endure, and cease. [65]
Just as the concept of production cannot apply to the cosmos taken as a whole,
nor can that of time, and the correlative notions of origination, endurance
and cessation. The cosmos cannot have a starting point in time, if time is a
measure of change and times are relations between things in the cosmos.
Next we see a characteristic example of Nāgārjuna’s arguments against the
Abhidharma:
How can existence be non-temporal if things are always changing? If it is not the
case that things are always changing, how can we account for their variability? [66]
If everything is momentary, how do things get older? But if things are not
momentary, in the sense that they remain the same, how do they get older? [68]
Beginnings, middles and ends must be considered like the instant (i.e. similarly
reducible, so there is an infinite regress). The condition of being a beginning, a
middle and an end does not exist from itself or from something else. [70]
No atom is simple since it has many sides. No atom lacks sides (if it did it could
not be connected with others). The ideas of unity and plurality are mutually
dependent, as are those of existence and non-existence. [71]
Chapter II
As the Kadalı̄ tree and all its parts when split down the middle is not anything,
likewise with the person when it is analysed into components. [1]
Hence the enlightened ones have said that all dharmas lack intrinsic natures. They
have ascertained the real nature of the components and seen that they are not
substantial. [2]
The Buddha has stated that what is observed and what is stated in scriptures is
neither true nor false. When there is an argument, there is a counter-argument
and neither is absolutely true. [4]
The universe is really beyond the categories of truth and falsity. In truth, we
cannot say ‘it is’ or ‘it is not’. [5]
How could the omniscient Buddha affirm of the universe, about which no true
statement is possible, that it has an end, or that it is infinite, or that it is really
plural or that it is non-differentiated? [6]
People ask how many Buddhas have been, will come and are here now. But the
notion of a limit on the number of beings presupposes the three-fold temporal
framework. [7]
There is no cause of the growth of the world. Decay is relative to the three-fold
temporal framework. [8]
In this consists the depth of the teaching that is a secret from ordinary people:
that the world is like a magical illusion is the essence of the teaching of the
Buddha. [9]
Nāgārjuna and Madhyamaka Buddhism 65
An elephant conjured up by magic may appear and it may seem to have a
beginning and end. But really it has no beginning and end. [10]
Likewise we see apparent beginnings and ends of things in the world. But in
reality there are neither fixed beginnings nor ends. [11]
As a magic elephant comes from nowhere and goes nowhere, being due to a
conjuror’s pretence, it does not last as a reality. [12]
Likewise the world is like an illusion that comes from nowhere and goes to
nowhere. It does not last as a reality since it is only mental delusion. [13]
What then is the meaning of this world organised by the three times? It cannot
be said to be nor not to be, except from the conventional standpoint. [14]
Therefore the Buddha did not say whether it is finite or infinite, plural or single. [15]
Refutation of Objections
Nāgārjuna wrote an important work called ‘The Refutation of Objections’
(Vigraha-vyāvartanī) in response to criticism levelled at his method by
followers of the Nyāya school. He envisages an opponent who says that
the proposition that all entities lack intrinsic natures itself lacks one and thus
cannot deny anything. If he admits that the proposition has an intrinsic nature,
he is contradicting himself [VV 1–2].
What does it mean to say that a statement lacks an intrinsic nature? When
a statement is true, it is an example of language operating as an instrument of
knowledge (pramān.a). Nāgārjuna is supposing that the opponent holds that
the essence of a pramān.a consists in its power (śakti) to be an instrumental
cause that establishes the truth about things. So the point is that if a pramān.a
lacks intrinsic nature, it also lacks that capacity.
Nāgārjuna replies that the opponent has not understood the meaning
of emptiness. Entities that are interdependently originated are empty of
intrinsic natures because they are dependent upon causes and conditions. His
proposition is indeed empty in this sense. But everyday objects, albeit empty,
perform their functions successfully. The same applies to his proposition.
Essence is not a precondition of functioning in an ever-changing world. The
statement has a therapeutic value for people who take it for granted that things
have essences.
There is also the objection from the Nyāya school that Nāgārjuna cannot
show that all things are empty, since such a demonstration requires that
there are valid means of knowing (pramān.as: i.e. perception, inference and
66 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
testimony). The objects of the pramān.as must exist too, because one cannot
negate what does not exist. The opponent says:
You deny the reality of things after you have apprehended them by perception,
but you also say that the perception by which entities are cognised is not a
reality. [VV 5]
Nāgārjuna replies:
If you hold that objects are established by means of knowing (pramān.a), tell me
how you establish those means of knowing. [VV 31]
If you think that pramān.as are established without pramān.as, you have
abandoned your own doctrine. [VV 33]
If you think that the means of knowing are established independently of the
objects known, then those means of knowing are not means of knowing about
anything. [VV 41]
If the pramān.as are established only in relation to the objects known, the objects
known are not established by the pramān.as. [VV 43]
If you hold that the objects of knowing are established by the means of knowing
and that the means of knowing are established by the objects of knowing, you
cannot establish either. [VV 46]
If the pramān.as are established by the objects known, and if those objects have to
be established by pramān.as, then, because the pramān.as have not been estab-
lished, the objects have not been established either. So how will the objects known
establish the means of knowing?’ [VV 48]
Nāgārjuna and Madhyamaka Buddhism 67
Further reading
David Burton’s Emptiness Appraised is the best starting point. Chapter III of Paul Williams’s Mahāyāna
Buddhism is helpful. His Altruism and Reality is mostly about the Bodhicaryāvatāra. See especially
Chapter V.
The Bodhicaryāvatāra is lucidly translated in Crosby and Skilton (1996).
Bhattacharya (1998) translates the Vigrahavyāvartanī. Lindtner (1982) contains much helpful
explanatory material, as well as texts and some translations. The most readable translations of the
Madhyamakakārikās are those by Jay Garfield (1995) and Frederick Streng (1967). Chapters VI–IX
of Mark Siderits, Personal Identity (2003), sees emptiness as a global form of anti-realism and offers
much food for thought.
Hahn (1982) has the text of the Ratnāvalī.
For engagement with Nyāya over the question of the pramān.as see especially Uddyotakara’s
commentary on Nyāya-Sūtra 2.1.8–19. This is translated in Jha (1984), p. 606ff.
Bimal Matilal’s ‘Logical Illumination of Indian Mysticism’ (Matilal, 2002) is stimulating.
Chapter Outline
Extracts from Vasubandhu’s ‘Twenty Verses Proving that only
Mental Phenomena are Real’ (Vijñapti-mātratā-siddhi) 72
Thirty verses on consciousness 74
Vasubandhu and Sthiramati on ‘The Construction of Phenomena’ 76
Illustrative extracts from Sthiramati’s Madhyāntavibhāgat.ı¯kā 76
Further reading 81
Questions for discussion and investigation 81
Some Buddhists espouse an idealist form of philosophy in that they deny that
there are any material or physical realities existing independently of minds.
There are neither selves nor an external world but only constructs of selfhood,
agency and objectivity arising from the flux of momentary self-aware thoughts
and feelings. We must bear in mind here that the philosophers were also
monks, practising profound meditation every day. The point is reflected in the
designation of this tradition as ‘Yogācāra’, which means, ‘the practice of yoga’.
(Other names include ‘Citta-mātra’, which means ‘mind-only’ and ‘Vijñāna-
vāda’ or ‘consciousness theory’.) Meditation often involves experiencing what
are purely thought-forms as if about external realities. It is not surprising
that such people should be especially open to the possibility that what we
ordinarily take to be external realities are but projections of consciousness.
The Buddhist idealists have a strong sense that the ways in which we experi-
ence what we unenlightened beings call the external world is conditioned by
personal and subjective factors. Our mind-set or world-view determines how we
see the world. What makes one person’s perception of a state of affairs different
‘Mind-Only’ Yogācāra Buddhism 69
from that of another is the moods, emotions and memories that one brings to
bear in the circumstances. This is illustrated by the point that when hungry
ghosts see a body of water, they see a mass of pus. Humans see it as a crystal
stream and drink from it. Such observations about the subjective constitution of
experience do not in themselves license any conclusions about the ontological
status of the physical world. But we shall see that these Buddhists present argu-
ments against the intelligibility of the concept of material substance.
The central figure here is Vasubandhu who lived during the period c. 350–
400 A.D. Trained in Sarvāstivāda methods of analysis and meditation, he
wrote a work called the Abhidharmakośabhās.ya which is a critical survey from
a Sautrāntika point of view of Buddhist realist schools. Another work is the
Karmasiddhiprakaran.a, which is a Sautrāntika critique of realist notions
of how karma operates, and an attempt to reconcile atomistic impersonality
with moral responsibility and consequentiality. It appears that he moved
from a representationalist to an idealist philosophical position and wrote the
Madhyāntavibhāgaśāstra, the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa, the Vim.śatikā and the Trim.śikā
from that point of view. His commentator Sthiramati lived around 550 A.D.
The Sautrāntika representationalists think that it makes sense to suppose
that most of our perceptions have external causes. Mental contents are
representations (ākāra) caused by a world outside the mind to which they
bear some relation. That relation is not one of mirroring or picturing since
they hold that the external world really consists of a flux of unique momentary
particulars (svalaks.an.a) and does not feature as such in the content of
awareness. They posit an external world on the basis of the inference that
there has to be something that causes those experiences over whose occur-
rence we have no control (bāhyārtha-anumeya), not as a result of direct
acquaintance (bāhyārtha-pratyaks.a). We can see how easily this may encourage
an idealist outlook. The gulf between what is supposedly given in experience
and its interpretation in concepts, thinking and judging (an interpretation that
conceals rather than discloses) is just too wide. If we are not directly acquainted
with objects in the world, and if conceptual and descriptive thinking does
not reach out to the world, and if the existence of that world can only be
certified by inference (itself a mental activity), why suppose that there is an
extra-mental physical dimension to reality? If the manifest content of experi-
ence is determined by our thoughts rather than by objects in the world, we
might wonder what sense can be given to the notion of a mind-independent
reality. Surely it is falling out of the picture. If experience of a hypothetical
given – the amorphous flux of ineffable particulars – does not express that
70 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
given as such but is posited as something that has a purely instrumental causal
role in the genesis of discursive thinking, actually concealing the true nature of
things, it is not obvious that experiences of such a given need be postulated at
all. Considerations like these (whose influence is apparent in Dignāga’s
Ālambana-Parīks.ā) seem to be the impetus behind Vasubandhu’s move
towards idealism or the view that only the mental factors of existence
(vijñaptis) are real. Vasubandhu came to reject the Sautrāntika view that we
can validly infer that there is an extra-mental reality as the cause of our percep-
tual sensations. We do not need to posit a material dimension of reality in
order to explain the character of experiences, whose occurrence can be
explainedby the revival of traces of prior experiences (vāsanā or sam.skāra)
within a stream. There is an argument from economy: it is always better to
assume one thing than to assume many. It is better to postulate potent mental
traces of experiences than to posit external objects. (Perhaps he thought that
the maxim that ‘when something is seen, there is no need to postulate the
unseen’ begs the question.) He argued against the very coherence of the notion
of material substance. He rejected the Vaibhās.hika view that we are directly
aware of objects made up of real physical atoms. Atoms are partless and indi-
visible. As such they cannot join together. But if we insist that atoms come
together, they must have parts. If they coalesce, there will be no increase in
extent: if they have no dimension, they cannot combine to form larger objects.
If they have dimension, they will be divisible and this undermines atomism. If
there are no atoms there cannot be any wholes distinct from their parts. The
Vaibhās.ika realists hold that all mental acts have existent objects external to
the mind. They say that to be is to cause an awareness: anything that is the
referent of an awareness exists. Vasubandhu argues that dreams and hallucina-
tions show that this is not true. Perceptions do not necessarily depend upon
mind-independent realities.
We might suppose that as well as objects outside the mind, there is also spatio-
temporal determination. Vasubandhu replies that experience of such determina-
tion also occurs in dreams. In response to the argument that it appears that
there are many minds experiencing the same objective environment, Vasub-
andhu appeals to the Buddhist notions of hells, which are shared hallucinations.
Vasubandhu thinks that individual events in a mental series are aware
of themselves. An awareness is simultaneously and in virtue of the same act
self-cognized, just as a lamp illuminates itself while illuminating an object.
This tenet of the reflexivity of mental events is central to the idealist outlook:
It shows that an idea can be the object of another idea and that there is no need
to posit physical objects as the causes of our thoughts. Moreover, the reflexivity
‘Mind-Only’ Yogācāra Buddhism 71
of each individual mental event dispenses with the need for an independent
consciousness, an observer-principle with a perspective on mental states.
Like all Buddhists, Vasubandhu believes that it is the intentional actions
of sentient beings that are responsible for the diversity and organization of
the cosmos, which exists to be the environment in which the consequences
of actions are to be experienced. The Abhidharma thinkers understand this
realm to be basically constituted by the material and mental elements of
existence. The idealists reject the category of material elements and hold
that think that the elements of existence are only the mental ones. Lives are
streams of ideas (vijñapti) ever emerging from a mental storehouse of vestiges
(ālaya-vijñāna) impressed by previous actions. These self-conscious ideas may
mistakenly conceive themselves as individual subjectivities, viewing ideas as
other than themselves and as constituting other streams.
Vasubandhu’s view is that unenlightened people lead an enchanted life con-
taminated by selfish attachments, aversions and delusions. Enlightened people
who are detached from the objects of sense realize that what we call the world is
a fabric of appearances. They are free from desires, aversions and delusions; in
particular the delusion that one is fundamentally an enduring, substantial soul,
a ‘further fact’ over and above the stream of one’s psycho-physical continuity.
Awareness of a mind-independent physical world is the product of habitual con-
struction by ideas projecting themselves as if external. People are individualized
not through relations to external circumstances but by a ‘mind-set’ consisting of
their inherited traits, attitudes, moods, emotions and memories. Deconstruction
of such factors encourages detachment from everyday experience.
Our everyday environment and ways of life are considered a mirage conceal-
ing authentic reality. That reality is consciousness from which arises phenomenal
reality, the environments experienced by sentient beings. For the first moment
of consciousness he adopts the tradition’s expression ‘the construction of phe-
nomena’ (abhūta-parikalpa), which means the dichotomization of conscious-
ness into subjects and objects of awareness (grāhya-grāhaka-vikalpa).
The unenlightened mind is veiled by moral, emotional and intellectual
defects (kleśa), foremost among which are cravings, antagonisms and failures
in understanding. Defects spring from seeds embedded in streams of con-
sciousness. They suppress the pure factors that are conducive to salvation
and whose cultivation promotes a transformation of mind and conduct. The
Buddhist path, understanding, meditation and morality, is intended to
counteract the impure factors. The aspirant to enlightenment must focus
attention upon eliminating impurities. Internalization of the teaching that the
elements lack fixed and enduring identities (dharma-nairātmya) produces
72 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
2. If ideas are not caused by external objects, they would not be determined by
time and place, there would be no shared experiences, and they would not
have effects.
And why is it produced in the streams of experience of all who are present
at that time and place and not just in one, just as the illusory appearances
occur in the stream of the visually impaired and not in others?
And why are the hairs and bees seen by the visually impaired are not causally effect-
ive? Things seen in dreams do not perform the functions of their counterparts in the
waking state. Fictional cities don’t do anything because they do not exist.
In dreams, things are seen at specific places and times. So spatio-temporal deter-
mination is established without external objects. Beings in hell, who are there
because of similar maturation of karma, all see a river of pus. Thus is there shared
experience although the objects of awareness are not externally existing.
In erotic dreams there is emission of semen without intercourse. All the denizens
of hell suffer, although the guards be unreal, as a consequence of the maturation
of parallel karma.
74 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
6. If you allow that the experiences of individuals in hell are the products of
purely mental karmic traces, why not admit that this applies to all
experiences?
10. The truth is that persons lack permanent identity. Put another way, the teach-
ing that everything is ideas leads to internalization of the truth that there are
no dharmas with permanent identities.
11. The object in awareness is a not a single whole. It is not a multiple composed
of many atoms. Nor is it a conglomeration of atoms. This is because the
atoms do not exist.
12. Given its simultaneous connection with six other atoms, the atom would
have six parts. If the six occupy the same place, they would have the same
mass as one.
The first is the fruition (vipāka) of ‘seeds’ of experiences, deposited in the store-
consciousness or receptive mind (ālaya-vijñānam) by previous actions occurring in
a stream. This is called the store-consciousness. It contains experiences in the form of
implicit ideas. The receptive mind is always associated with mental phenomena
(caitta) including sensations, perceptions, attentiveness, feelings, and intentions.
Enlightenment is a transformation of the receptive mind. [3–5a]
Mental construction is produced by causes and conditions and hence its nature is
dependent or conditioned (paratantra). But in its original, pristine self-sufficient
state, mind is not conditioned by causes. This unconditioned mode is called its
perfection (nis.panna). [21]
What are called the three natures are not intrinsically determined. [23]
The permanent and true nature of the elements is purely mental. [25]
As long as one does not realize that only the mental elements of existence are
real, the subject-object mentality persists. [26]
Just confronting an object and thinking ‘this is merely an idea’ is not to experience
the mind-only state. [27]
When thought does not apprehend any objective support (ālambana), then it is
established in the mind-only state. In the absence of objects of thought, there is
no grasping. [28]
This is supernatural direct intuition, beyond the mind (citta), beyond thinking.
This is the transformation of the receptive mind, immune from afflictions and
obscurations. [29]
76 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
Sthiramati begins by saying that the stanza is directed against the view of the
Mādhyamikas that none of the elements of existence (dharma) are realities.
In order to repudiate this universal denial it is said that ‘the construction of
phenomena’ exists.
– But does not this contradict the Buddhist scriptures to the effect that all the
elements of existence are empty?
There is no contradiction because it says that ‘duality is not found there’. This
means that the construction of phenomena is empty of the distinction between
knowing subjects and objects known. It does not mean that the Absolute is void
of intrinsic nature.
– But if duality is never real, like the hare’s horn, the constructor of phenomena
will be the only true reality. This entails that the Unconditioned is not a reality.
No, because the scripture says ‘Emptiness is real’. Emptiness here means
the absence of the opposition between subject and object in the constructor of
phenomena, not the non-existence of the Unconditioned Reality. [page 10]
Sthiramati now turns his attention to the Sarvāstivādin view that in addition to
minds and mental acts, material objects are also objective realities. The statement
that the construction of phenomena really exists is intended to refute this. There
is no matter that is independent of this process. This is why the text says, ‘there is
no duality there’ meaning that the construction of phenomena is neither the
apprehender of anything, nor is it apprehended by anyone. Moreover, it is simple
reality, void of subjects and objects.
If there are no objects, there are no subjects. There are no objects subsisting
independently of the construction of phenomena.
This is why the text says, ‘the Unconditioned exists’. The Unconditioned is the
transcendental reality. It is free from the subject-object duality. It is the foundation
of the construction of phenomena. So liberation is possible.
78 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
– But if the Absolute is the basis of the construction of phenomena, why it is not
apprehended?
The assertion that the construction of phenomena exists can be taken as meaning
that the elements of existence are modifications of consciousness.
The denial of duality can be directed against the Sarvāstivādin view that objects
both appear and exist in their own right independently of the construction of
phenomena. [page 11]
Some think that the denial of duality is just nonsense. Others think that the empti-
ness of the elements means just that there is no controlling inner soul.
To counter the denial that there is an ultimate reality, the scripture states that the
Unconditioned exists.
– But if the subject-object duality is unreal, why does the deluded world think that
it exists?
In general terms, it is mind and the whole range of mental acts in the three
spheres of existence, past, present and future, the complex of causes and effects
constituting beginningless sam . sāra and lasting until nirvān.a [page 12]. Specifically,
it is the subject-object polarity (grāhya-grāhaka-vikalpa). The object-pole is con-
sciousness representing things and people. The subject-pole is representations in
consciousness of a self and its perceptions. An example of an object apprehended
would be something with colour, shape and size. An example of a subject would
be a visual perception. The subject-object polarity is not intrinsic to the construc-
tion of phenomena. Unenlightened people do not understand the nature of the
Unconditioned Reality because it is concealed from us. But the enlightened being
(Bodhisattva) correctly discerns that the construction of phenomena is empty of
‘Mind-Only’ Yogācāra Buddhism 79
the subject-object polarity. After the experience of duality has been superseded,
the unconditioned reality and the construction of phenomena remain. The
Bodhisattva intuits them as they are without any mistaken superimposition.
Vasubandhu: The projection of objects means colours and shapes etc. The projec-
tion of living beings means the sense faculties in one’s own and other experi-
ential streams. The projection of self means the corrupt mind that posits a
permanent self. The projection of perceptions means the six modes of sense-
based awareness. The unreality of objects means that they do not exist inde-
pendently of consciousness. In this sense the ideas of them are false.
Sthiramati: It has been taught that the construction of phenomena that is empty
of subject and object is real. The verse explains how the sense-faculties, objects
and perceptions are related to it.
[page 15] By statements that the construction exists, we learn that it is a reality
but nothing about its nature. We do not understand the reason for our instinctive
adherence to the subject-object polarity despite the unreality of duality. That is
why the verse indicates that the intrinsic nature of the construction of phenomena
is consciousness. The basis of our instinctive adherence to the subject-object men-
tality is the projection of objects and living beings etc. Ideas of inanimate objects,
living beings, polluted minds and sense-based perceptions are maturations of
seeds, vestiges of prior intentional actions, in the storehouse consciousness (ālaya-
vijñāna). These specific transformations of karmic potencies create the different
modes of phenomenal existence.
– But why does mind represent things as if they were external to it? We would
never mistake a post for a man if there were no men.
80 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
Coloured things with size and shape, sounds, smells, flavours and textures are
really just internal to the mind. Likewise with our ideas of sentient beings and the
thinking self.
[page 16] Perceptions appear to grasp external objects but the truth is that there
are no external objects corresponding to them.
– But common sense says that the objects of perception and the sense faculties
are mind-independent realities. Why should we reject this in favour of idealism?
There are many cases of awareness in the absence of real external objects, for
example, dreams, hallucinations, projections in meditation. If the production of
awareness were causally dependent upon external objects, ideas could not occur
in the absence of the latter and their content could not be different from the
things that have produced them [so we would see water-atoms and light waves,
not rainbows].
Hence, we say that every perception representing things and living beings arises
without any external objects. If there are no real objects, the ideas of the self and
its perceptions are not genuine either, since the two are co-dependent. Although
the subject-object polarity is unreal, the consciousness that posits it is real.
***
The construction of phenomena can be understood under three descriptions:
It is called the Constructed nature when there are objects, the Dependent nature
because of the construction of phenomena, and the Perfected nature when there
is no duality. (1. Verse 6. Page 18)
The subject-object polarity does not really belong to the construction of phenomena,
which is called the dependent nature when it is subject to causes and conditions. It
is called constructed when it appears under the form of subject and object which
do not really exist there. It is perfected when those conditions do not obtain. In
this way, three natures are attributed to the construction of phenomena.
Moreover, they themselves say that compounds or wholes are purely nominal
or conceptual existents (prajñapti-sat). How then can they be the causes of
perceptions if they are themselves constructs out of experiences of the given?
Further reading
Text and translation of the ‘Twenty Verses’ in Tola and Dragonetti (2004) and Wood (1991). For the
‘Thirty Verses’ see Wood. For Sthiramati’s Madhyāntavibhāgat.īkā, I have used Pandeya (1989). The
first book is interpreted with informative notes in Stcherbatsky (1970).
Chapter IV of Paul Williams, Mahāyāna Buddhism (1989) is enlightening.
Chapter Outline
The Sām
. khya vision 82
Causal processes 84
The human condition: bondage to natural causality 86
The Yoga vision 87
Further reading 89
Questions for discussion and investigation 89
The Sām
. khya vision
Sām.khya is one of the six orthodox Brahminical Hindu systems of salvation
or ‘visions’ (darśana), and it is closely associated with the Yoga system of
spiritual development. Although this tradition is ancient, its basic text is
the Sām.khya-Kārikās of Īśvarakr.s.n.a (c. 400–500 A.D.) upon which there are
commentaries including the Yuktidīpikā (c. 650 A.D.) and the Tattvakaumudi
by Vācaspati Miśra (c. 841 or 976 A.D.). Sām.khya is basically a non-theistic,
world-renunciatory and gnostic outlook, rather than a religion for the person
immersed in daily life and ritual religion. Its goal is the elimination of
suffering by the eradication of its ultimate cause. Religious practices, such
as rituals and austerities, can only afford a temporary relief from suffering.
What is required is discriminative understanding of the difference between
the conscious subject, and material nature and its manifestations. In other
words, we need to understand that the active embodied person is alienated
from its true identity, which is but reflexive static conscious subjectivity. The
goal is ‘isolation’ or freedom from determination by natural causal processes.
Sām
. khya and Yoga 83
Sām.khya posits a dualism of souls and matter. There is an infinity of souls
(purus.a), which are self-contained and inactive self-aware conscious monads
whose true mode of existence is beyond space, time and matter. Souls are
merely disinterested observers, and most definitely not active participants
in the sphere of becoming. Somehow, some of these souls have become
entangled in the material environment, including individual personality and
the body. Sām.khya and Yoga aim to free the soul from this imprisonment
by matter and rebirth.
Souls have become confused with limited and basically material forms.
When there is an association between what is merely a static conscious monad
and the material mind (buddhi), the latter is illuminated, irradiated by the
light of consciousness and becomes as-if conscious [SK 20]. The confusion is
compounded when the activity of the buddhi is mistakenly attributed to the
inactive soul. Thus we have the origins of the individual person and the series
of births marked by suffering. But the souls are really always purely passive
spectators of human experiences, abiding in splendid isolation, each illumi-
nated only by its own consciousness. It is, however, a basic tenet of Sām.khya
that the experiences deriving from involvement with matter which bind the
soul also operates for the sake of its release (SK 21).
The other pole of the dualism is Primal Matter (pradhāna or mūla prakr.ti).
It is beginningless and ever-changing. The latter spontaneously transforms
itself (parin.āma) into the real cosmos of material and psychological phenom-
ena. The best we can say is that this just happens. There is no divinity initiating
or superintending the process.
Prime Matter is said to consist of three strands (gun.a): sattva (goodness and
light), rajas (dynamic energy) and tamas (heavy and dark). (The Yuktidīpikā
interprets the triad as standing for happiness, distress and delusion.) Before
the manifestation of the cosmos, they are in a state of equilibrium, cancelling
out one another’s properties. Their ‘mere existence’ is said to prompt the
transformation of material nature. Matter (prakr.ti) transforms for the sake of
the human souls so that they have experiences that lead them to realize the
difference between soul and matter. Opponents ask how an unconscious
cause can act for the sake of anything, let alone produce specific and organized
realities. The Sām.khya position, however, is that the existence of the cosmos
call for explanation. The world consists of active and complex realities made
of parts. Each has its own purpose and we should assume a purpose for the
totality. They espouse a principle that composite entities exist for the sake of
something else (parārtha) that is different in nature from them. So it is
84 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
concluded that physical entities exist for the sake of conscious souls.
Just as the unconscious milk functions for the nourishment of the calf, so matter
functions for the sake of the liberation of the soul (purus.a). [SK 57]
Through repeated meditation on the nature of the manifest world, there arises
the intuitive insight that the purus.a is not the individual personality and whatever
it identifies with. [SK 64]
Primal Matter evolves to produce the basic material and psychological realities
tattva – i.e. buddhi (mind/intellect); aham.kara (one’s sense of personality;
manas (the co-ordinator of the separate sense-faculties and their deliverances);
the five sense-faculties (indriya); physical organs; the essences of sounds,
touch, colours, tastes and smells; and the gross elements – space, air, fire, water
and earth which make up physical objects). These products contain the gun.as
in differing proportions and compose the world we inhabit.
Individual objects are collections of qualities (gun.a-sam.drava) such as
colours, shapes, textures, tastes and smells. The Sām.khyas reject the Nyāya
view that there is a separate property-possessor (dharmin) that is distinct from
the conglomeration of properties. They think that once we have listed, as it
were, all the properties of an entity, there is no extra factor called the substrate.
Such would be what is sometimes called a ‘bare particular’ or an entity without
properties, and that makes no sense. It has indeed been observed that the notion
that the ultimate subject of predication should be something without properties
is an idea so absurd that only philosophers could have come up with it.
All that is required for the substantial unity of entities over time is that
they be integrated in a suitable way. As the Yuktidīpikā puts it, ‘When an entity
without departing from its nature loses an earlier property and receives a
new one, that is called modification (parin.āma)’ (YD pp. 111 and 163]. This
is true to experience. People and things change all the time and still remain
identifiably the same. There can only be change, rather than replacement, if
something stays the same.
Causal processes
Sam.khya propounds a theory of causation termed satkārya-vāda which
says that future products pre-exist in a potential state in their underlying,
Sām
. khya and Yoga 85
substrative causes (upādāna-kāran.a) prior to their actualization or manifesta-
tion (abhivyakti) as entities identifiable by their specific names and forms.
Milk transforms into yoghurt. Milk is the underlying cause or substrate and
yoghurt emerges as a product (kārya) from it. Pots are transformations of
the clay that is their substrative cause and which their individual forms
have implicitly pre-existed. Here the causal process involves a modification
(parin.āma) of a stable underlying reality and not the generation of a totally
novel product. Hence there is a strong ontological link between the emergent
effect and its causal substrate. We shall see the importance of this emanative
model of cosmic causality for those forms of Vedānta that see the cosmos of
souls and matter as real transformations of the divine being.
The Sām.khya theory of causation develops in opposition to that of the
Nyāya-Vaiśes.ikas. That position is called asatkārya-vāda or ‘the production of
something new’. This says that prior to origination, the effect did not exist in
its underlying cause but is a totally new product, different from the already
existent basic elements out of which it is made. They reject the category of
potentiality, holding that only what is actual and concrete is real and can cause
something else. Causation is not the actualization of what was potential but
the generation, through re-arrangement, of new entities out of already existent
factors. A cause is defined as a necessary prior condition of an effect. There are
three factors in a causal complex such as the manufacture of a cloth by a weaver
out of threads: the substrative or underlying cause (samavāyi-kāran.a) which is
always a type of substance (dravya) – e.g. the threads comprising the cloth
(the new whole – avayavin); the non-inherent cause (asamavāyin) which is
always a quality (gun.a) or activity (karma) – e.g. the weaving and colour of
the threads; the efficient or instrumental cause (nimitta) – e.g. the shuttle
and other instruments. The weaver is the agent cause. The products of causal
processes are integrated wholes (avayavin). The whole is a new creation with
its own identity, over and above the sum of the parts in which it inheres. The
whole entity cannot exist without the parts, but the parts can exist without the
whole. It is distinct from the parts since it manifests a single specific universal.
An individual object must be the substrate of a universal; such as cowness
or potness – a collection of different parts will not suffice. That the whole is
not reducible to its parts is crucial to the Nyāya-Vaiśes.ika resistance to
the Buddhist reduction of objects to constituents and phases because they
explain endurance through space and time in terms of integrated natures
that are held together by the relation of inherence (samavāya). The Nyāya-
Vaiśes.ikas adduce a number of reasons for their view that prior to origination,
86 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
the effect does not exist in its underlying cause. Some of them are:
modifications – that is to say, all forms of thought and feeling, whose forms
the soul has assumed. The goal is a disengagement from the life of action in
which the soul recovers its true nature. This is achieved by constant contem-
plative practice and detachment, presupposing mental and moral cultivation.
Detachment is said to be self-mastery on the part of one who no longer
thirsts for perceptible objects or any of the transitory goals promised by the
Scriptures. Active yoga consists in austerities, the recitation of mantras and
the study of scriptures bearing on freedom from rebirth, and the direction
of the mind to Īśvara – an exemplary soul (purus.a) who has transcended the
mutually dependent factors of karma and what are collectively termed ‘the
afflictions’. The latter are ignorance (a failure to discriminate what matters
from what does not, the morally valuable from the corrupt, and what is one’s
true identity from one’s personality and everyday identifications), selfishness,
desires, animosity and attachments. The discriminating person has realized
that everything is unsatisfactory because pleasures turn into frustrations,
because of the weight of dispositions inherited from previous lives over which
we have no control, and because our minds are always restless and at war
within themselves.
The soul in its pure form is mere non-intentional awareness. When
implicated in the conditions of space and time, it has an observer’s perspective
on of the thoughts and feelings that are functions of the embodied mind with
which it is associated.
The eight stages of the physical, moral and mental discipline of classical
Yoga are:
Self-restraint; non-violence, honesty in thought, word and deed, sexual restraint and
lack of greed.
Discipline: interiorization, tranquillity, asceticism, mantra recitation, the study of texts
on liberation and attention to God.
Physical postures; exercising control over the psychosomatic complex.
Breath-control: regulation and reduction of the processes of inhalation and exhalation
that increase psychophysical control.
Withdrawal of the senses from their objects and direction of attention to the inner
self.
Attention: focusing the mind on a single point (i.e. an object of meditation).
Meditation: the uninterrupted continuity of awareness of the object of meditation.
Profound contemplative introversion in which there is no self-awareness.
Further reading
For the Sām.khya-kārikas see Larson (1979).
Larson and Bhattacharya (1987) has a useful introduction and summaries of works, including the
important Yuktidīpikā, which is edited in Wezler and Motegi (1998).
For the Yoga-Sūtras and commentaries see Woods (1927) and Whicher (1998).
Chapter 11 of Halbfass (1992) is valuable for Sām.khya.
Chapter Outline
Nyāya 92
Vaiśes.ika 92
Metaphysics: the system of categories (padārtha) 93
Substances: the category dravya 93
The category Gun.a (quality) 98
The category Karman (motion) 100
The category general property (Sāmānya) 100
The category Viśes.a (ultimate particularity) 103
Samavāya (the inherence relation) 104
The category Abhāva (absences) 105
Epistemology: the Pramān.as 105
Knowledge by perception (pratyaks.a) 109
Anumāna: knowledge by reasoning or inference 111
Śabda: testimony and the transmission of true information 113
Words and sentences 114
Further reading 115
Questions for discussion and investigation 116
describe. By the time of Udayana (c. 1050–1100 A.D.) they had coalesced
and what follows is a synthetic overview of some of their concepts and
categories. Any attempt to delineate our world-view in a categorial scheme
will run into problems. Inconsistencies are bound to arise. The Navya-
Nyāya thinkers, the most influential of whom are Gangeśa and Raghunātha,
attempt resolutions of some of the problems and introduce clarifications
and innovations. Their writings are very difficult and I have not attempted
to say much here.
Some people and their works:
Nyāya
Gautama Aks.apāda (c. 150 A.D.), the author of the fundamental Nyāya-Sūtra.
Vātsyāyana (350–400 A.D.) author of the Nyāya-Bhās.ya on the Nyāya-Sūtra.
Uddyotakara (550–600 A.D.) author of the Nyāyavārttika.
Jayanta Bhat.t.a (850–900 A.D.) author of the Nyāyamañjarī.
Vācaspati Miśra (A.D. 950–1000) author of the Nyāyavārttika-tātparyat.īkā.
Bhāsarvajña (900–950 A.D.) author of the Nyāyasāra and Nyāyabhūs.an.a.
Udayana (c. 1050–1100 A.D.) author of the Laks.an.āvalī, Ātmatattvaviveka, Nyāyakusumañjali and
Kiran.āvalī.
Gaṅgeśa (c. 1300 A.D.), author of the Tattvacintāman.i.
Raghunātha (1475–1550 A.D.), author of the Padārthatattvanirūpan.a and Dīdhiti on the
Tattvacintāman.I.
Vaiśes. ika
Kan.āda, Vaiśes.ika-sūtras (first century A.D.?)
Praśastapāda (c. 500 A.D.), author of the Padārthadharmasam.graha.
Śrīdhara (fl.991 A.D.), author of the Nyāyakandali on the preceding.
Early Nyāya says that we reach the Highest Good by understanding the truth
about the reliable methods of knowing (pramān.a), the knowable objects
(prameya) and the various forms of argument and debate. In other words, the
truth (pramā) will set us free. Freedom here results from the elimination of
misconceptions, activities, rebirth and suffering.
We will begin by looking at the knowable objects and their organization in
a system of categories (padārtha) and then move on to a consideration of the
methods of knowing.
Nyāya and Vaiśes.ika 93
The above three are all categories of particulars that fall under the universal
properties inhering them.
mental synthesis holds merely between the cognitions, they would become
assimilated to each other and we would no longer have a series of discrete
individual factors constituting the stream of experiences. In a case like this
we need some further factor that explains unification across sensory faculties,
the connection through time between my present sight of the orange and
my recognition of the orange as similar to one previously tasted, and the con-
nection between the earlier experience, the present desire and the anticipation
of the experience of eating the orange. It is significant that we do not have
to connect these experiences with a single subject. The ‘I’ is given as implicit
in them. To turn Hume against himself, ‘I can never catch myself at any time
without a perception’.
The Buddhist may say that cases of mental synthesis arise in virtue of the
cause-effect relation between momentary cognitions in a single series and so
there is no need to posit a single cognizer. The response is that even if there
can be a cause-effect relation between different momentary mental events,
this would not explain the phenomenon of memory. For a mental event to
be experienced as a memory, there has to be an enduring subject. A prior
experience of pleasure in a stream would be precisely that. It would not
be remembered from the present perspective as what had been a pleasant
experience. Just as one person does not remember what was experienced by
another, so one discrete cognition cannot remember the content of another.
The Buddhist attempt to explain all of the above phenomena in terms of a
stream of experiences impersonally related as cause and effect is not really
satisfactory. There has to be something that holds the stream together, some-
thing that, as it were, underpins the causality. It is not clear that the Buddhist
account can explain synthetic experiences (pratisam.dhāna) if they understand
one mental event in a series as the cause of the next only in the sense that one
precedes the other. But such a relationship can occur between events occur-
ring in different series. Something stronger than causality is required – namely,
the mental events are all related to something else.
There has to be something in relation to which an experience is identified
as past, another present and another anticipated as future. Something has to
unify the manifold of current experiences. Experience flows: we are always
aware of it changing through time. But change is only possible if there is
some stable factor that undergoes it. The Buddhist is actually talking about
successive replacements rather than change. An enduring principle of
identity, the subject of experiences, is the most economical explanation of
the phenomena.
Nyāya and Vaiśes.ika 97
The reductionist theory that psychological continuity is nothing but a basic-
ally impersonal continuum of causes and effects has a persistent allure, despite
its physicalist and functionalist animus. But there are some considerations that
should make us think twice about the explanatory sufficiency of causality here.
It is uncontroversial that causal relations sometimes hold between experiences.
I burn my hand on a hot pan lid, cry out and my wife is alarmed (perhaps . . .).
But the experiences here do not belong to a single person. It may perhaps be
the case that a causal account can be given of the formation of personality
or character when this is regarded as in some sense an achievement. But a
problem is that a lot of fragmentation or disintegration of experiences over
time is consistent with their still being a single person. (Less dramatically, as
the reader knows, my mind flits from one thing to another quite at random.)
As Bishop Butler said to Locke, a person is more than what they remember.
It might be possible to give an objectifying purely causal description of the
psychological processes of an animal that is not a person – one that cannot
use the pronoun ‘I’. In the case of a personal individual stream of experiences,
it is plausible to say that sometimes a present experience (causally) elicits
a memory. But the reductionist account says that the relations between
experiences within a single stream (‘series person’) are all causal ones. This
is questionable. It is not clear that in every case of experience B following
experience A, the relation is causal. But the basic being of the subject (that
which is meant by ātman) is a given. It is not a product or an achievement.
This basic subject is expressed in first personal ‘I-thoughts’ and the relevant
connections here are not causal ones. The first-personal, autobiographical
continuity of human persons is not given in causal terms. If I think, ‘I was born
in Heswall’ and ‘I now live in Liverpool’, I can truly conclude, ‘I was born
in Heswall and now live in Liverpool’. That conclusion has nothing to do with
causation, but is a matter of inferential entailment. The inference is valid
because the two features are states of the same person. So it is not obvious that
the unity of a person’s mental life is to be explained in causal terms. Causal
connections between experiences are insufficient to constitute or produce a
continuum. The connections hold because of the character of the relation
between thoughts, and that relation derives from their being states of the
same person. The reductionist view is that personal identity is an illusion
that is constructed out of experiences. We then mistakenly invest this illusory
identity with an enduring character. The basic objection is this: how can
construction, mistaken or otherwise, happen if there is nothing capable of
doing the constructing in the first place?
98 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
That is to say, information may be received from the environment via the
senses, processed by the mind (manas) and stored in the memory without
being consciously registered. The introspective elevation to explicit awareness
of an item of informational input is termed anuvyavasāya. This happens when
one cognitive state becomes ‘telescoped’ by another. They do not accept that
cognitions about the environment are intrinsically reflexive or self-illuminating.
An objection to this is that if the elevation to consciousness of an informa-
tional state requires another psychological state, an infinite regress results.
A cognitive episode qualifies as a piece of knowledge rather than an infor-
mational state or mere true belief when it is produced by one of the reliable
methods of knowing (pramān.a). Present experience (anubhava) may be true
or misleading. Perceptual knowledge is direct contact with an object or
state of affairs. A true cognition is one in which the attribute that is possessed
by the external object is a feature of the content of the cognition. A false aware-
ness is a situation which the actually present external object does not have the
attribute that is a feature of the content of cognition, as when we think, ‘This is
silver’ in relation to a piece of shell. The awareness refers to real silver existing
elsewhere and not to a mental entity such as an hallucination or to a ‘mere
appearance’. Falsehood is exposed in practical failure. The tradition develops a
sophisticated form of a direct realist epistemology holding that there is a
structural isomorphism between the complex content of a true cognition and
an objective state of affairs.
Universals explain our use of general terms, of which they furnish the stable
grounds for the repeated applications. The meanings of words are complex: a
word such as ‘cow’ signifies the concept cowness, it produces an image of the
form typical of cows, and it can denote an individual cow. Universals explain
why we understand entities as belonging to kinds. We can only identify
an entity as being similar to another entity if there is some objective basis
for that similarity. If everything were utterly unique, we could not relate the
contents of our cognitions to each other. It is an illusion to suppose that
we could re-identify anything if particulars did not manifest shared features.
Re-identification of a particular as belonging to a kind to which others
also belong presupposes that kinds are given and not merely conceptually
fabricated in accordance with human interests. The success of most of our
activities shows that the concepts and categories included in the padārtha
scheme are not more or less arbitrary inventions. There have to be universal
principles running through reality. It is not enough to say that we recognize
similarity of the basis of clusters of similar observable features. Particulars
differ and observable features are promiscuously distributed. An albino tiger
is still a tiger. Something else that combines the clustered features must be
posited and that extra factor is the unitary universal. Many universals are
manifested in concrete shapes (ākr.ti) that are specific and regular arrangements
of parts characteristic of a kind. When we see an individual cow that is a mani-
festation (vyakti) of the universal cowness we also see the universal by virtue
of the shape. The perceptible shape cannot be identical with the universal
because it is a collection of features that are integrated by the universal.
Not every characteristic that we understand as common to a group of
individuals is a genuine universal (jāti). We can divide the world up in all
sorts of ways, generating as many properties as suit us. We can speak of ‘the
community of cooks’, but ‘being a cook’ is not a jāti but an imputed property
(upādhi). ‘Being able to swim’ is an ability possessed by some in varying degrees
so it cannot be a unitary single property. Another example is ‘being a beast’,
which covers many different animals. This is a compound imputed property
that is a synthesis of a number of features in this case being hairy, having a
tail and having four legs. It is artificial in that it cuts across natural kinds and
violates the natural order of classification.
The genuine properties are objective and natural. They are intrinsic
features of the instances where they occur. They carve nature at the joints.
They are discovered, neither manufactured nor invented nor conceptually
constructed. The classes of their instances are not miscellanies. Some of our
Nyāya and Vaiśes.ika 103
concepts, such as ‘horse’ and ‘blue’ coincide with the genuine properties and
qualities immanent in the cosmos and regulative of its actual conditions. But
the imputed properties are just useful concepts.
Udayana formulated six impediments that prevented an upādhi from being
a jāti:
Anumāna: knowledge by
reasoning or inference
While perception is an instrument for the acquisition of knowledge about
what is present to the mind and senses, inference (anumāna) is a means of
acquiring knowledge about matters that are beyond the range of direct
acquaintance. The outlook is empiricist (although we must remember that
sensory experience is not restricted to particulars but includes universal
properties and relations): inference depends upon information supplied by
perception.
According to Nyāya, inference begins with a doubt, such as whether there is
a fire on a remote mountain. The relevant observation is that we can see smoke.
In this case, fire is termed the sādhya – that which is to be established. The
mountain is called the subject (paks.a) and the smoke is called the reason (hetu)
in the inferential process. We already know that there is no smoke without
fire (this invariable association is called vyāpti) and are familiar with other
instances where they co-occur, such as the kitchen. By way of corroboration,
we also know the truth of the contraposed version of the generalization: ‘no
fire, no smoke’ from cases like the lake. This negative example is intended to
show that we have investigated the matter thoroughly and have not confused
smoke with mist seen rising from a lake early in the morning. We apply know-
ledge of the general principle to the case in question and can safely conclude
that there is indeed fire on the mountain although we do not see the fire.
A demonstrative inference (prayoga) used to persuade someone else
(parārtha-anumāna) would be formulated by the Nyaya-Vaiśes.ikas as:
Statement of the position or uncertainty (pratijñā): ‘There is fire (sādhya) on the moun-
tain (paks.a).’
Logical reason (hetu): Because there is smoke on the mountain.
General principle (vyāpti): ‘Wherever there is smoke, there is fire’ that is supported by
examples (dr.s.t.ānta) – like a kitchen (sapaks.a); unlike a lake (vipaks.a).
Application: ‘There is smoke on the mountain’, which states that the subject under
consideration has the logical reason that is always associated with (pervaded by or
included in – vyāpta) the property to be proved.
Conclusion: Therefore, there is fire.
(a) the reason occurs in cases where what is to be proved is absent (i.e. it occurs in
vipaks.as).
Example: The village is holy, because it is close to the Ganges. But there are
unholy things close to the Ganges (called sādhāran.a-hetu).
(b) Where the logical reason only applies to the subject of the inference (asādhāran.a-
hetu). Example: ‘Sounds are impermanent, because they are audible.’ It is a
condition of an inference’s validity that we should be able to cite an instance
other than the subject of the inference were both the logical reason and the
property to be proved always occur together. But this is impossible here because
nothing other than sounds have the property of audibility.
Nyāya and Vaiśes.ika 113
(c) Where the subject of the inference is universal. For example ‘Everything is
nameable, because it is knowable’. The invariable association is, ‘Whatever is
knowable is nameable’. Distinct from the universal subject, there can be neither
a sapaks.a nor a vipaks.a, showing the invariable association between the logical
reason and what is to be proved. Since the inference begins from a question
about whether nameability applies to the subject, the invariant association,
‘whatever is knowable is nameable’ is itself doubtful.
inference and not a method of knowing in its own right. Nyāya, and virtually
everyone else, treat testimony as an independent pramān.a, largely because of
the problems attaching to assimilating it to either perception or inference.
At the same time, they are aware that of the things that we know, many are
known on the basis of testimony and not perception or inference. They say
that testimony is information supplied by someone who knows the truth and
wants to tell it. Speech often misleads but it is a method of knowing in so far
as the speaker is well-informed and sincere. As well as reliable information
about matters belonging to our world, testimony also includes the Scriptures
composed by the ‘Seers’ who originally heard the sound-units comprising the
Vedas. Later writers hold that the Scriptures are reliable because a benevolent
and omniscient deity is their author.
It is assumed that the normal situation is that what the speaker states when
he utters an assertoric sentence and what the hearer understands directly is a
piece of verbal knowledge (śābda-bodha) about a state of affairs in the world.
Let us bear in mind that it is possible to understand a proposition without
believing it to be true and that it is possible to assent to a false proposition.
So neither understanding not assent is sufficient for knowledge. The Nyāya
account of testimony establishes the conditions under which the hearer under-
stands a proposition, assents to it and obtains a piece of knowledge.
One knows a proposition expressed by a sentence (i.e. there is śābda-bodha)
when:
The hearer acquires a true belief about the world from hearing the sentence.
The speaker knows the truth and is reliable, sincere and competent.
The sentence expressing the proposition has these features:
Further reading
An enjoyable starting-point is Jayanta’s play, Much Ado about Religion (Dezső, 2005) Act Three of
which sees a confrontation between Nyāya and Buddhist ideas.
Another way into the original material is Annambhat.t.a’s Tarka-sam.graha (Athalye 2003).
The Nyāya-Sūtras and the commentaries by Vātsyāyana and Uddyotakara are translated in Jha (1984).
There are summaries of works and a helpful introduction in Karl Potter (1977), which deals with
Nyāya-Vaiśes.ika up to Gaṅgeśa, and in Potter and Bhattacharya (1993) for the later period.
Bimal Matilal, Perception, treats extensively of Nyāya debates with the Buddhists. Despite the title, its
scope is wider than epistemology.
116 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
Chapters VI–XII of Matilal (2002) discuss the Nyāya realism in the light of some contemporary
philosophical interests.
Jonardon Ganeri, Indian Logic, is a useful collection. The same author’s Semantic Powers concerns
Navya-Nyāya philosophy of language, but says illuminating things about the earlier tradition.
Ingalls (1951) is a lucid guide to key Navya-Nyāya concepts.
Kishor Chakrabarti (1999), Classical Indian Philosophy of Mind, also deals with questions about the self
and the existence of God.
Scharf, Denotation (1996) has a section on Nyāya theories about linguistic meaning and reference and
translates Nyāya-Sūtra, 2.2.58–69.
Halbfass, On Being and What There Is (1992) and Tachikawa, The Structure of the World (1981) focus
on Vaiśes.ika.
The best, if not the only, work on the materialist tradition is Franco (1994), Perception, Knowledge and
Disbelief.
The central concept here is that of dharma, which comprises the notions of
natural law, right order and social and religious duty. Dharma is revealed by
the authorless, eternal and infallible Vedas. We act in accordance with dharma
when we obey the Vedic injunctions. What is to be done is dictated by scrip-
ture, not determined by human intellect and will. Such a mode of living relates
us to the highest good.
It is the dharma of grass to grow and of the sun to shine. It is the dharma of
members of the Brahmin caste to study and teach the Veda and the dharma of
Vaiśyas to engage in agriculture or commerce. Dharma would be unknown
were it not taught by the Vedas, which are explicated in texts called the
Dharma-Śāstras. As an ethical outlook, the concept of dharma is thoroughly
deontological. Consequentialist standards such as welfare, pleasure and pain,
the biddings of conscience, divine command or the cultivation of virtuous
character are all irrelevant to the determination of what is right and wrong.
Values are exclusively defined by Vedic injunctions and prohibitions, and are
manifested in the ‘conduct of the virtuous’ that derives from strict observance
of the Vedic rules separating the pure from the pollutant. Dharma is not a
‘universal’ ethic in that its demands vary according to one’s caste and stage
of life. One and the same type of action might be right for one person
(sva-dharma = ‘own dharma’) and wrong for another. There was a widespread
recognition of the principle that it is better to perform one’s own dharma
badly than that of another well.
It appears that originally the observance of dharma meant the performance
and patronage of elaborate and expensive sacrificial rituals generating
prosperity (bhoga) and temporary enjoyments in paradise (svarga). Its neglect
has all sorts of negative consequences ranging from personal misfortunes to
the collapse of the universe into chaos.
For the later Mīmām.saka theorists of ritual and social duty, the correct
performance of both the public sacrificial rituals by Brahmin priests and the
domestic rituals by householders of the highest three castes, in addition to
observance of the obligations appropriate to one’s caste and stage of life (varn.a-
āśrama-dharma) controls, maintains and perpetuates order and stability in the
universe. A properly performed rite automatically produces its result. It does
not depend upon any divine action. The gods exist only in name, that is to say,
only in so far as their names are mentioned in the course of rituals. There is no
belief in an absolute divinity unsurpassably great being. In that sense, the
Mīmām.sakas are atheists.
The Mı̄mām
. sā Vision 119
Mīmām.sā is primarily the hermeneutics and defence of those parts of
the Vedas that prescribe the performance of rituals and describe their results.
The primary concern is the correct performance of the rituals, including
the question of who is entitled to perform them and reap their benefits.
Mīmām.sakas are also concerned with questions about how language operates,
whether it is primarily referential and fact-asserting, or primarily action-
guiding, the nature and relationship of words and sentences and whether
words primarily signify individuals or express universal concepts. They debate
with the Buddhists over the question of the eternity of the phonemes (varn.a)
comprising the Vedas. They are also concerned with the question of what must
be true of the nature of individual sacrificial performers if they are to receive
the benefits of the rituals in the future.
Infallible Scripture (śruti) is classified in three ways:
by a god’) and temporary applications to the men who are its bearers. But
in the cases of sortal and mass-terms such as ‘cow’ and ‘gold’, capacity and
application always coincide.
A given word stands for a limitless number of its objects: ‘We say, “The
single word ‘cow’ is uttered eight times and not that there are eight words
‘cow’ ” ’ The word-object connection (śabda-artha-sam.bandha) cannot be a
human creation. It cannot be established every time we use a particular word.
But we have no traditional recollection of anyone originally fixing the
references of words.
Each word expresses its own meaning and an uttered combination of word-
meanings is understood as a sentence. Sentences are not units of meaning over
and above the words comprising them. This is the mainstream view espoused
by Śabara and Kumārila and it is called ‘abhihita-anvaya’ or ‘the connection
of meanings that have been expressed’. (There is another view propounded
by Kumarila’s contemporary Prabhākara that is called ‘anvita-abhidhāna’
(‘expressing inter-related meanings’).) Prabhākara thinks that word meanings
are primarily understood when used to prescribe actions and to bring things
about rather than as referring to already existent objects. So the fabric of
linguistic understanding consists of sentences that include a verbal meaning.
Words have meaning only in the context of sentences. All meanings are
relative to particular situations. They argue that a child does not learn indi-
vidual words on their own but learns language through the insertion and
removal of words in sentences. She hears, ‘bring a cow’ and sees someone do
that. Then she hears, ‘bring a horse’. By the removal and insertion of words in
sentences, she learns the meanings of individual words. The theory of ‘the
expression of inter-related meanings’ may also be interpreted as the view that
it is only in the context of a sentence that a word has meaning: when we want
to know the meaning of a word, we should look at its use in context and not
scrutinize it in isolation.
Let us now return now to Kumārila’s view that the real relation between a
Sanskrit word and its extra-linguistic signification is inseparable and eternal.
If the word-meaning relation is to be permanent and unbreakable, words must
be primarily expressive of general concepts and the objects falling under
them. They do designate particulars when used in sentences in specific
circumstances, but this is not their primary signification. The word-meaning
relation obtains between a word and a natural or artificial kind (ākr.ti or jāti).
Words mean the underlying structures (ākr.ti) common to natural and artificial
kinds of things. The relation is fixed (niyama) and natural (autpattika). The
The Mı̄mām
. sā Vision 123
permanence of the word-object relation is of course consonant with the notion
of the intrinsic validity of the Vedas. If the Vedic words were like names and
primarily signified individuals, the word-meaning relation would be continu-
ally broken and reconstituted. But the form common to all cows is a structure
comprising the essential properties that make something a cow. It is basic to
the cosmos and is endlessly manifested as individual (vyakti) cows. The ākr.ti
is not just the visible appearance of cows. Cows come in all sorts of shapes,
sizes and colours. But each and every one shares the same internal biological
structure that we may call ‘cowness’ or ‘bovinity’. It is that to which we refer
when we speak of ‘The Cow’, meaning the species. The generic form of gold
(what we would call its atomic number or molecular structure) is likewise
common to all artefacts made of gold.
As Kumārila puts it, ‘the kind (jāti) is called the physical structure (ākr.ti)
because it is that by which the individual (vyakti) is formed. The generic
property (sāmānya) is the basis of a single concept under which individuals
fall’ [ŚV Ākr.tivāda 3]. The form is a generic property of many things. It is
not a configuration of parts (sam.sthāna) because there is no configuration of
parts in the case of actions, qualities and substances like the self. Because a
configuration perishes and differs for each individual, if that were the form, it
could not be the generic property expressed by a word. The generic property,
kind or form is a property constitutive of individuals and it is the object of a
simple cognition.
It is the form that is the primary signification of the word ‘cow’. That is why
it can apply to many. In everyday life and in Vedic usage, it designates an
individual in the context of a sentence. Kumārila says that in the case of
singular reference several factors are present: the kind (jāti construed as ākr.ti),
its individual manifestation (vyakti), their relation, the combination of
˘
those three, gender and causal role in an event (kāraka). In the expression
‘a white cow’, the quality-word (gun.a-śabda) ‘white’ behaves similarly. In
isolation it expresses a quality. In context it designates a particular instance
that is a part (am.śa) of an individual substance. A verbal root expresses
an action-type. In context, a finite verbal form specifies an activity.
The idea is that any perception that is about some object (in contradistinction
to a sensory impression that is of an object in the sense that it is caused by it)
must be to some extent informed by conceptual thought. That Kumārila
recognizes the non-cognitive character of sensation is apparent from verses
121–122 where he says that the sense-faculties are an instrumental cause
of cognition but they are not cognitive.
[112] In the first place here is cognition (jñāna) that is just seeing (ālocanā) and it
is free from concepts (nirvikalpaka). It is produced from the pure entity and is like
the cognitions of infants and the mute.
[113] Neither general (sāmānya) nor specific features (viśes.a) figure explicitly in the
content of awareness, but the individual that is their substrate is grasped.
126 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
The next three verses refer to an Advaita-Vedānta view that will appear in the
writings of Man.d.ana Miśra (c.700 A.D.) who says that, ‘Initially there is non-
conceptual perception relating to the bare reality of an entity (vastu-mātra).
The ensuing conceptual cognitions comprehend its peculiarities’ (Brahma-
Siddhi p. 71.1–2).
[114] Others say that there is an ultimate universal called ‘Substance’ or ‘Reality’
that is the sole object of perception.
[117] That is false because we apprehend a distinct form in the case of each
individual entity. It is not the case that no differences are grasped just because we
cannot apply a word to the object.
[119] The entity is not identified in its uniqueness because it is not distinguished
from others. A generic feature is not grasped because we do not notice any
similarity with other entities.
state, but one that does not involve any specific thoughts about what is in the
field of vision. Its content is non-conceptual. But I may shift the focus of my
attention and register that the expanse is green and undulating. On closer
inspection, I come to understand that I am seeing a golf course. I am now in
an informational state whose content is conceptual. An animal or infant could
be seeing the same area, but could not believe that it is a golf course.
The problem with Dignaga’s position is that it cannot accommodate the
following distinctions:
true. Errors and hallucinations sometimes occur, but they can be explained
as arising from identifiable defects in the perceptual apparatus, or from the
indistinctness of objects. Cognitions can be trusted as valid if they are not
contradicted by a subsequent perception. In short, there is no need to check
everything. Reliability may be safely assumed.
For a realist like Kumārila, the variety of experience depends upon differ-
ences between the objects grasped. The metaphor of ‘grasping’ is instructive,
conveying that objects already exist, independently of any thinker. They are
not created or produced by knowledge. There is no veil of representations
intervening between the knowing subject, the agent of the act of knowing
and the given. Consciousness is not a repository of forms or concepts, but is
more like a capacity for activity. When a cognition brings about the property
known-ness in an object, that property is accidental: its loss or gain makes no
real difference to the object.
We have said that intrinsically valid cognitions are true just in virtue of
their occurrence. The Vedic sounds are heard to command the rituals and
tell of the supernatural benefits accruing to their performers. (If what is
promised is something concrete and it does not happen, this can be blamed
on a mistake in the performance of the ritual.) In the cognition of the Vedic
mandates, there is no scope for falsehood, no possible standpoint from which
they might be criticized and countermanded, and no room for scepticism
about their authority.
Thinkers in the early Mīmām.sā tradition such as Śabara thought of dharma
as the same as the performance of prescribed actions. But this makes dharma
as transitory as those actions, with the consequence that we cannot credibly
establish a connection between an action and its consequences. The earlier
thinkers thought of the rituals as generating an unseen factor called apūrva
(‘something new’) or adr.s.t.a (something unseen) that transmitted the ritual’s
effect to the future. But its status and location were vague. Later writers favour
the view that Dharma is an eternal reality that is manifested in the rituals
and their consequences. The concept of manifestation is invoked in various
contexts to explain occasions where something eternal becomes perceptible in
certain conditions. For example, timeless phonemes are manifested in audible
sounds. A universal property (jāti or sāmānya) such as cowness is manifested
in individual cows (vyakti). Apūrva is treated by Kumārila as a power (śakti)
belonging to dharma that belongs to the sacrifices and to the identity of the
sacrificers. It activates the fruits of the rituals.
The Mı̄mām
. sā Vision 133
We began by mentioning that ritualism is sometime called the ‘earlier
Mīmām.sā’ by the Vedāntins who consider themselves in different ways to have
superseded the performance of rituals as leading the way to the highest good.
They maintain that at best it can only deliver a temporary state of well-being
in paradise, followed by a return to lesser incarnations. It is to the Vedāntins
that we turn in the next chapter.
Further reading
For the view that meaningful language is essentially prescriptive rather than fact-asserting (and the
Vedāntic response), see Lipner (1986), Chapter 1.
Chapters III, IV and IX of Halbfass (1991) are about Vedic orthodoxy, and ritualism and sacrificial
causality.
Olivelle (1999) and (2005) translate the texts that concern the practical applications of Dharma.
Act Four of Jayanta’s Much Ado about Religion (Dezső, 2005) sees a debate about the authority of the
Vedas.
Matilal (1990) Chapter X (‘Words and Sentences’) expounds abhihitānvaya versus anvitābhidhāna.
Scharf (1996) has a long section on words and meanings, accompanied by translations of typical
Mīmām.saka argumentation.
Eltschinger (2007) is a mine of information about Kumārila. For the latter’s epistemology, Taber (2005)
is invaluable and contains a richly annotated translation of the chapter on perception in Kumārila’s
Ślokavārttika.
nexus or parallelism of being (an analogia entis) between the world and the
Brahman that is its cause. Madhva is an exception here in that he denies that
there is a real continuity of being between God and the world. He maintains
(like the Śaiva Siddhāntins by whose outlook the Dvaita tradition is influ-
enced) that God produces the cosmos out of eternally real prime matter that is
distinct from him.
Bhāskara and his followers say on the basis of the scriptures expressing unity
that the Brahman although having every excellent quality such as freedom from
evil is conditioned by a limiting condition (upādhi) and is bound and released, and
is the substrate of transformations (parin.āma) that are various imperfections.
[Vedārthasam . graha para. 8]
Because Bhāskara and his followers do not accept any realities other than the
Brahman and the limiting conditions, given the association between the Brahman
and the limiting conditions all the defects proper to the latter will apply to the
Brahman itself. [Ibid. para. 54]
Yādavaprakāśa and his followers, explaining the exact meaning of the scriptures
about unity say that the Brahman, an ocean of unsurpassable and immeasurable
noble qualities proper to its nature, is by nature both distinct and not distinct from
Vedānta 137
sentient beings, and the abode of many kinds of impure transformations.
[Ibid. para. 9]
Given their assumption that the individual self and the Brahman are both different
and non-different, it follows that if the Brahman is essentially the same as the
individual souls all the defects belonging to them will belong to it also. If God is
essentially constitutive of all the different creatures then he is the identity of each
and every one. Such being the case, all their pleasures and pains will belong to
him. [Ibid. para. 58]
Further reading
Nakamura (1990), History of Vedānta is comprehensive.
For the Paramārthasāra see the text, translation and generous annotation in Danielson (1980).
11 Advaita-Vedānta
Chapter Outline
Śam
. kara 140
Authentic Being 144
The inexpressibility of the Brahman 149
Bhagavad Gı̄tā-Bhās.ya 13.12b 149
The path of active religious practices is insufficient for
enlightenment 150
Śam
. kara and the Buddhists 156
Man.d.ana Miśra 162
The development of the tradition 166
Further reading 166
Questions for discussion and investigation 167
Discursive thought carries the mind here and there. Attention, extroverted or
introverted, is restless. Feelings and moods come and go. Most of life is
pervaded by the dualities of means-end rationality, the seeker and the goal,
actions and their results. But the meditator absorbed in profound contempla-
tion has neither thoughts nor feelings, nor experience of a world external to
consciousness. There is just motionless undifferentiated awareness that does
not seek to accomplish any purposes. This state is what Advaita calls ‘pure
consciousness’. Tranquil consciousness knows no fluctuations. It is not directed
towards nor about objects. It is not about anything. It has no specific content.
It is said to be blissful, for it nothing lacks. There is no sense of selfhood or
individuality. There is merely: being conscious.
Advaita-Vedānta 139
The Advaita tradition is inspired by certain Upanis.adic passages suggestive
of the identity of the soul and the Absolute Reality such as:
In the beginning, all this was just Being, one only without a second. (Chāngogya
Upanis.ad 6.2.1)
But many of the scriptures have a dualistic sense, some clearly suggesting a
difference between the Brahman and the individual souls and the cosmos,
others talking in terms of distinct agents, instruments and goals that are
aspects of external religious practices, and others obviously supposing that
the Supreme Principle is a being with glorious characteristics. Advaita-Vedānta
draws a distinction between the ultimate authority of texts teaching non-
difference and those that cannot possibly be construed in a non-dualistic
fashion. While this may appear controversial, it is not unprecedented for as
we saw above, the Mīmām.sakas had already distinguished between those texts
that prescribe actions (vidhi) and those that merely describe how and why to
do things (arthavāda).
Advaitins say that the essential teaching of the Upanis.ads is that what we
experience as the differentiated world of interrelated conscious and non-
conscious individual entities is really a complex, proliferated misunderstand-
ing superimposed upon the undifferentiated and inactive Brahman or Pure
Being. That foundational reality is nothing other than the coincidence of Being
and static consciousness. Liberation is just the cessation of the ignorance
or misconception (avidyā) that is responsible for our experiencing reality as
fragmented and our misunderstanding ourselves as individual experiencers
and agents. While religious activities, ritual and meditative may point one in
the right direction by purifying the mind and distracting us from immediate
selfish pursuits, they cannot produce enlightenment of liberation from rebirth
directly.
This is the tradition of those who deny that extroverted religious activity
can of itself deliver liberation from rebirth. Enlightenment arises from intuitive
insight unmediated by thoughts and words, into the identity of the ‘inner self ’
(pratyag-ātman) and the Brahman. This is the mystical realization of the
equation of Being and Consciousness. It is the manifestation of what one
always and already is. While insight obliterates all experience of differentiation
and individuality, vestiges of such experience persist in the life of the enlightened
one, who is ‘liberated while alive’ until his release at death. A possible response
140 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
on the part of the one who has seen the light is the renunciation of all ritual
acts as well as all everyday responsibilities and obligations. Śam.kara’s radical
vision is that of the world renouncer (sam.nyāsin). Man.d.ana Miśra is more
concerned with integrating liberating gnosis into the everyday life of the
householder. He recognizes that renouncing social ties and the shared religion
is not an easy option. He says that the Vedic rituals purify the mind and prepare
the way for realization of one’s true identity as the Brahman. Understanding of
that identity, conveyed by scripture, is intensified by ritual and contemplation
that counteract the still forceful traces of the pluralistic mentality. He recom-
mended the repetitive type of meditation called prasam.khyāna as a means of
removing moral defects and hindrances (kleśa) and as a way of internalizing
the Upanis.adic statements conveying non-duality. We shall see Śam.kara
rejecting this version of the view that liberation is the fruit of a combination
of works and gnosis.
Śam
. kara
Śam.kara, one of the founders of the tradition holding that differences are
unreal, probably lived around 700 A.D. His major work is a commentary on
the Brahma-Sūtras. He also wrote commentaries on the Bhagavad Gītā and on
individual Upanis.ads. Among the many other works attributed to him by
the Advaita tradition, the ‘Thousand Teachings’ or Upadeśa-Sāhasrī stands
out. His vision is that of the radical renouncer, which ultimately calls into
question the values of mainstream orthodoxy by denying that there are any
real individual thinkers, agents and acts.
There is no question that Śam.kara was an original genius, but it should
be mentioned that the Advaitic tradition traces itself back to Gaud.apāda
who probably lived around 450–500 A.D. and wrote the Āgama-śāstra about
the Mān.dūkya Upanis.ad. He likened the phenomenology of normal experi-
ence to that of dreaming and claimed that in both cases it is only the fact of
consciousness that remains constant. Individual entities (bhāva) are mental
constructs (kalpanā). The one supreme soul, the waveless absolute, imagines
itself as conscious individuals.
Gaud.apāda’s contemporary, the grammarian Bhartr.hari taught the ‘non-
dualism of meaning’ (śabda-advaita). The idea is that the diversified phenom-
enal cosmos (‘the proliferation of names and forms’) is the emanation from a
unitary sonic Absolute not of things but of meanings. It is the appearance
of the transcendent ‘meaning-reality’ (śabda-tattva), otherwise known as the
Advaita-Vedānta 141
Brahman. The Absolute appears to transform itself through its innate powers
into meanings, words and sentences. Words and what they mean are identical.
The differentiated world of our experience is a product of diversification by
language. Reality is a matrix of differentiated meanings rather than things or
objects. Ignorance (avidyā), our default position as it were, is a function of
linguistic proliferation into individual words and propositions. It consists
in understanding the world in term of the individual entities that are the
referents of words and resting content at that level. Bhartr.hari’s linguistic
idealism exercised a considerable influence on Man.d.ana Miśra as well as on
the monistic Śaiva traditions.
In common with many classical Indian philosophers, Śam.kara’s soterio-
logical goal is the freedom of the authentic self (ātman) from rebirth. The
ātman cannot be captured by concepts and words. It will only reveal itself, and
that is something over which we have no control and upon which our activities
have no effect. Ātman here means something like ‘true nature’ or fundamental
identity. It is different from embodied individual personality, from caste-based
˘
social role, and from the psychological functions of thinking and feeling, as
well as the sense of being an agent interacting with the external world. All
of those involve a misidentification of what one really is with some aspect of
objectivity. Nothing that one can objectify, including thoughts and feelings,
can be the true self. We are approaching the notion of the ‘transcendental
subject’, the pre-condition of having any sort of coherent experience. The
notion of subjectivity here is neither individual nor personal. It is not a
particular perspective. We must remember that the state of release involves
no experiences of which anything might be the subject.
The word ātman is usually translated as ‘self ’ and sometimes as ‘soul’. But
the semantic range is broader. It is perfectly normal to speak of the ‘ātman’ of
an entity such as a pot (ghat.a). The compound ‘Ghat.a-ātmā’ does not mean
‘the self of a pot’, let alone its soul, but the nature or identity of pots. The
original meaning was something like ‘vital breath’. The word then came
to mean the spirit that is the essence of a sentient being. Thence developed the
meaning ‘the self ’ and ‘the soul’. Often the masculine singular forms operate
as reflexive pronouns such as ‘oneself ’, ‘herself ’ ‘itself ’ ‘themselves’. As such
it is synonymous with ‘sva’ (one’s/its own). With the rise of theistic forms of
Vedānta, a theological concept of self as The Soul, expressing the individual
as related to divinity, became prominent. But this concept is foreign to the
gnostic traditions, such as Advaita.
Śam.kara thinks that the ātman is revealed when what had thought of itself
as individual manifests its nature as one and the same as the Brahman, the
142 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
BSB 1 1.1
Given that it is impossible that there should be any real relation between Subject
and Object, whose spheres are the concepts of the first person and the third
person, whose natures are opposed like light and darkness, and that all the more
impossible is any real relation between their properties, then it is logical to hold
that it is mistaken to superimpose (adhyāsa) what is objective and its properties on
the first personal subject that is consciousness, and conversely to superimpose
subjectivity and its properties on the third personal objective order of things.
But all the accounts agree that superimposition is the appearance to consciousness
of the features of one thing in something else. Such is the everyday experience of
mother of pearl’s looking like silver and the moon’s appearing double.
But how can there be superimposition of objects and their properties on the
Inner Self, the transcendental subject, that is never an object? One superimposes an
Advaita-Vedānta 143
object on another object that is present, and you say that the inner self is never an
object.
We reply that the denial that the Inner Self is an object requires some qualification
because it may be intimated by the concept ‘I’ and because it is familiar in virtue of
its immediacy. It is not a rule that people only superimpose an object on another one
that is present: people superimpose colour on the sky. So there is no contradiction
in the superimposition of what is not self on the Inner Self. Superimposition as
defined above the learned consider as ignorance (avidyā). They say that knowledge
is the ascertainment of the true nature of an entity by means of discrimination.
But how can the scriptures and means of knowledge relate to what is infected by
ignorance?
We reply that the means of knowing cannot function unless there is an individual
knowing subject that has misidentified itself as ‘I’ and ‘mine’ in relation to the body,
mind and sense-faculties. There can be no perception without sense-faculties and no
operation of the sense-faculties without a body. And no one acts unless the body has
been superimposed upon the soul. In the absence of the two-way superimposition
of soul and not-soul, the Inner Self would not misconceive itself as an individual
agent of knowing. And without the agent of knowing, the means of knowing can-
not operate. In this way, the scriptures and means of knowing relate to what is
infected by ignorance.
Where scripturally ordained religious activities are concerned, the suitably quali-
fied individual is aware that he is related to higher worlds. But that qualification
for religious practice does not derive from a Vedānta-based understanding of the
Inner Self’s not being involved in rebirth and its exemption from caste-status. Prior
to knowledge of the true nature of the transcendental subject, scripture continues
to operate with regard to matters infected by ignorance. Scriptures such as, ‘A
Brahmin must sacrifice’ function only if there is superimposition on the transcend-
ental subject of such specifics as caste, stage of life, age and circumstances.
One superimposes external features on the Inner Self when one thinks, ‘I am doing
well’ or ‘Things are going badly’ with respect to factors such as one’s family. One
superimposes physical features when one thinks, ‘I am fat’ or ‘I am walking’. One
superimposes properties of the mind such as desires, intentions and judgments.
In these ways, the ego is superimposed upon the transcendental subject that is
really the passive witness of experiences. Conversely, the conscious nature of the
subject is superimposed on the mind and so forth.
Authentic Being
For Śam.kara, the fact that awareness occurs as the same in all cognitions shows
that it is the basic reality. In his commentary on Bhagavad Gītā 2.16. (‘Of the
non-existent, there is no coming into being: there is no ceasing to be of
the existent. The difference between the two is seen by those who understand
the truth.’) Śam.kara formulates a substantial conception of ‘Being’ as the
changeless basis of all finite and transitory beings. ‘Being’ thus understood
is not involved in causal relations and is outside space and time. In the
background here is a reaction to Dharmakīrti’s espousal of dynamic causal
efficacy as criterial of reality, with its entailment that anything permanent,
in so far as it is static, would be unreal.
Unconditioned being is the foundational cause of the cosmos. Its genuine
features (jātīyaka-dharma), as opposed to those conditions (upādhi) that we,
or some scriptures, might superimpose upon it are universal presence, etern-
ity, omniscience, omnipotence and its being the true identity of everyone.
Nothing finite and nothing whose existence depends upon its relation to other
things can be truly real. The same applies to anything that is a product.
Products are transformations (vikāra) and a transformation (being a deriva-
tion) lacks a nature of its own. Thought expresses something truly real when it
is constant and unvarying, and when a thought expresses something that
comes and goes, then it concerns what is other than Being.
Bhagavad Gītā 2.17: Asks the question, ‘What is “Being” that exists
timelessly?’ Śam.kara replies that it is the condition of the possibility of
anything: Everything is pervaded by the Brahman, called Being. This Reality
never deviates from the nature that is its own because it has no parts. It cannot
suffer loss because it has no properties. It is the true identity (ātman) of every-
one. Commenting on Gītā 2.18, he says that this timeless, changeless and
indestructible identity cannot be determined by any of the means of knowing
(pramān.a). Dismissing the suggestion that it is determined by scripture and by
perception, he responds that transcendental subjectivity establishes its own
existence (svatah. siddha). It is only if such subjectivity, qua knowing subject,
is already a given that inquiry using pramān.as by one who seeks to know is
possible. We could not act with a view to understanding knowable objects
unless we had already understood ourselves as subjects. The transcendental
subject is a given, a presupposition of the sort of experience that we have.
Scripture is the ultimate pramān.a in the sense that it has its epistemic authority
about the transcendental subject only by stripping away properties that have
Advaita-Vedānta 145
been mistakenly superimposed upon that identity, and not by providing new
information to us about something previously unknown.
From Śam.kara’s Upadeśa Sāhasrī (p.68):
Permanently unchanging consciousness, whose nature is self-luminosity, establishes
its own existence since it does not need a means of knowing for itself. [Everything in
the world requires consciousness to reveal or establish its existence. But conscious-
ness is unique in not needing anything external to establish it: it is self-revealing.]
Anything other [than consciousness] that is insentient exists for the sake of some-
thing else, since it functions in complexes. And in so far as that which exists for the
sake of the something else produces experiences of pleasure, pain and delusion, it
follows that it is what is not the self. Hence its existence (astitva) is not authentically
real (parama¯rtha). Just as the contents of illusions have no real existence apart from
consciousness, so everyday experience of differentiation has no real existence apart
from consciousness. And the permanently unchanging nature of the light of con-
sciousness, the authentic reality, follows from its uninterrupted presence. It is the state
of non-differentiation because it is unvarying in the midst of all the different ideas
presented to consciousness, while the different ideas come and go. Just as the differ-
ent ideas that come and go in dreams are said not to exist in reality, so the different
ideas inconstantly presented to waking consciousness must be unreal too. Because
there is no perspective on consciousness other than that of consciousness itself, it is
not the sort of thing that can be accepted or rejected, and there is nothing else.
Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya 1.1.31
Scriptures such as ‘tat tvam asi’ (‘You are that’) and ‘aham . brahma asmi’ (‘I am the
Brahman’) show that what is called the ‘individual self’ is not ultimately distinct from
the Brahman. It is the Brahman that is called ‘individual person’ the agent and the
experiencer when it is regarded as diversified a result of properties (upādhi) super-
imposed upon it, such as body mind and sense-faculties. Some passages reveal the
true nature of Pure Being by negating differentia resulting from the superimposition
of features. They focus attention on one’s inner identity (pratyag-ātman).
The plural world consisting of entities that are modifications (vikāra) is character-
ised by separations between entities, but what is not a product (avikr.tam) is not
found to be divided. The atmosphere is understood as differentiated from the
earth and so on. Hence it must be an effect. It follows that space, time, the mind
and the atoms are effects.
– But surely the Soul (ātman) is also divided from the atmosphere etc, so must it
not also be an effect?
The Soul is not a modification of anything because that would mean that it is an
effect.
146 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
We cannot deny the reality of the Soul, because of its very nature. The Self is not
a contingent property of anything else since it establishes its own existence and
that existence is not established by any of the means of knowing (pramān.a). One
uses the means of knowing to establish previously unknown objects of know-
ledge. But the Self, because it is the basis of the exercise of the means of knowing,
is established prior to their functioning. The rejection of a reality of that sort is
impossible. A person may deny the existence of some entity or another, but he
cannot deny the subject doing the rejecting.
The point here is that although one’s worldly experiences occur in temporal
sequence, it is a datum of consciousness that one’s core identity is not extended
in time: it is not constituted by temporal parts or phases.
Most followers of the Nyāya-Vaiśes.ika tradition hold that while we have
or are persisting identities, those identities are not intrinsically conscious.
They say that cognitions (and feelings, desires and intentions) are contingent
properties that occur when the embodied ātman is connected with a mind
(manas), the material faculty that co-ordinates sensory data. Śam.kara addresses
this view under Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya 2.3.18:
Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya 2.3.30
As long as one’s identity is that of a transmigrator, as long as the sam . sāric state
has not been terminated by realisation of one’s true identity, association of the
soul with some mind and personality continues. And while there is a relation
to the superimposed property (upādhi) that is the mind then there is individual
personality and the series of births. But in reality there is no individual person apart
Advaita-Vedānta 147
from the nature that is fabricated by relation to the superimposed property that is
the mind. This relation of the superimposed property that is the mind to one’s real
identity presupposes misconception (mithyājñāna) and misconception continues
until knowledge arises. So as long as there is no comprehension of Pure Being,
connection with the superimposed property that is the mind obtains.
Agency does not belong to one’s true identity because it would follow that there
could be no liberation from rebirth. Were agency an essential feature of identity,
it could never be separated from it, just as heat is inseparable from fire. The
ultimate human good cannot happen unless one is free from agency because
agency always involves suffering . . . Agency is not essential because it is one of
the properties superimposed upon the fundamental identity.
The enlightened realise that there is no individual person; no agent and no enjoyer
of experiences, all of which are concepts superimposed upon the true self.
But surely if there are no real personal agents distinct from body, mind and sense-
faculties and distinct from the higher self, then it must be the higher self that is
the transmigrator, the agent and the enjoyer.
We respond that scriptural injunctions teach that certain things are to be done and
thus presuppose an appropriate sort of agency. But it is not the case that this agency
is essential to the soul, because the scriptures teach that one is identical with uncon-
ditioned being. The scriptural injunctions presuppose the type of agency that is fab-
ricated by ignorance. Passages such as, ‘the agent, the person whose nature is
understanding’ (Praśna Up. 4.9) refer to the agency fabricated by ignorance.
Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya 2.3.46
The painful experience of the individual person is not something truly real but is
occasioned by a mistaken failure to discriminate between one’s true identity and
the superimposed properties (mind, body and sense-faculties) that are fabricated
by ignorance.
It is a cardinal Advaitin tenet that the notion of difference does not apply to the
Brahman or ‘pure being’. There is nothing else from which it could differ, and
it has no intrinsic complexity. It is just undifferentiated static consciousness.
148 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya 3.2.11
Some scriptural passages refer to the Brahman as possessing differentia (sa-
viśes.am) while other say that it lacks differentia (nirviśes.am). Does this mean that
the Brahman has both a conditioned and an unconditioned nature?
Śam
. kara responds that the unconditioned reality cannot intrinsically possess
two natures because it is illogical that one and the same reality should both
intrinsically have and lack characteristics such as colour and shape. Relation to
superimposed properties (upādhi) does not involve a change in the real nature
of an entity. A brilliant crystal does not become dim by being related to a
projected red feature. And the superimposed properties in relation to the
Brahman are projected by avidyā. We must understand that of the two sorts
of characteristics, the one of the Brahman as void of every differentia and
beyond discursive thought is the true one.
Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya 3.2.14–15
The Brahman has no forms (ākāra) such as colour and shape. As scripture says,
‘The Brahman is without before and after. There is nothing inside or outside
of it. The Brahman is the identity that experiences everything’ (Br.hadāran.yaka
Upanis.ad 2.5.19.) These passages refer to the transcendent (nis.prapañca) nature
of pure being, so it must be understood that it is formless.
Other scriptural passages that refer to the Brahman as having form are not primar-
ily about the Brahman, but are instructions to contemplate the supreme reality in
certain ways.
There is no problem about the fact that some texts teach meditation on the Brah-
man as having some specific forms. This sort of attribution of characteristics does
not compromise our view that the Brahman does not have a twofold nature
although properties are superimposed upon it. When something is due to a
superimposed property (upādhi), it cannot be a genuine property of an entity. And
the superimposed properties are fabricated due to ignorance. We have already
explained that primal ignorance is the precondition of all religious and secular
dealings.
Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya 3.2.18
Because the nature of unconditioned pure being is consciousness, void of
differentia, beyond mind and language and conveyed by the negation of all
finite characteristics, the scriptures teaching freedom from rebirth use the simile
of the sun reflected in water, meaning that the Brahman’s having different
features is not the real truth because those features are properties that have
been superimposed.
Advaita-Vedānta 149
Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya 3.2.21
Being and consciousness coincide in the Brahman. They are not distinct properties.
The supposition that the Brahman has a mode of being that excludes conscious-
ness and another mode that has the form of consciousness that is other than
being implies that it is internally complex. Being is just consciousness and
consciousness is just being. They are not mutually exclusive, so conceptual analysis
(vikalpa) about whether the Brahman is either Being or consciousness or both is
groundless. Scriptural texts that speak of the Brahman under certain forms have
their own positive purpose: they do not merely have the significance of denying
that finite features of the cosmos pertain to the Brahman. When features of the
cosmos are mentioned in passages enjoining meditation – such as, ‘It is made of
mind: the vital breaths are its body; its appearance is light’ the text does not have
the purpose of suppressing plurality but that of enjoining meditation.
(analogia entis) between the Brahman and anything belonging to the cosmos.
The formula ‘Inexpressible as being or non-being’ was also applied to avidyā
and its works. What Śam.kara actually says here is that it means that the
Absolute is not the sort of empirical thing that either could or could not exist.
It is not knowable by conventional means adapted to our world, but only by
Scripture. He also says:
That which is totally other than the cosmos is explained by the provisional attribu-
tion of features to it followed by a demonstration that they are inappropriate.
‘In the beginning, this cosmos was being alone, one without anything else’ and
‘In the beginning, this cosmos was the one ātman.’ Once it has been understood
that the words in such passages cohere with each other in bearing upon the real
nature of the Brahman, it would be mistaken to assume another meaning, for
that would involve imagining what is not scriptural teaching and abandoning the
scriptural teaching. It is not the case that such fact-asserting passages are to be
understood as expounding the natures of agents [involved in ritual performances]
because there are scriptural texts that repudiate the fruits of ritual activities, such
as ‘Whom might one see and by what means?’
The Brahman, although it is a fully accomplished reality, does not fall within the
province of means of knowing such as perception and inference, because the
identity of the Brahman as one’s true self can only be known from the scripture,
‘That thou art’.
As for the view that the Vedāntic teaching is meaningless in that it is not
concerned with matters to be actively pursued or avoided – this is not a problem
for us who say that the ultimate good is achieved, after the destruction of all
afflictions, merely by knowledge of one’s identity as the Brahman, which is
not something to be pursued or avoided. It is true that there are subordinate
152 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
While some Vedic passages have authority by being injunctive, one cannot impugn
the authority of those scriptures that have knowledge of the self as their result.
The epistemic authority of scripture cannot be known by inference, because there
are no analogous instances that could be cited as part of the argument. Thus it is
settled that scripture is the means of knowing the Brahman.
***
An opposing view, from someone like Man.d.ana Miśra who thinks that liberation
is the fruit of meditation, rather than just knowledge:
The purport of scripture is not mere understanding but religious activity, in this
case meditation or contemplation.
Reply: Although scripture is the means of knowing about the Brahman, still
scripture teaches that the Brahman is something that should be meditated upon
(pratipatti-vidhi-vis.ayatā), in the way in which certain factors (e.g. the sacrificial
post) are taught as subordinate aspects of ritual activities. This is because scripture
is concerned with ritual actions and abstentions. Scripture is meaningful by
moving people to action or by restraining them. Anything else is relevant in so
far as it is supplementary to action-injunctions.
In the same way, the Upanis.adic statements are meaningful. Given that scripture
is injunctive, just rituals such as the Agnihotra are enjoined for the person who is
intent on paradise, so knowledge of the Brahman is enjoined as an activity for the
one intent upon immortality.
Preliminary reply: There is a radical distinction between two kinds of inquiry: in the
ritual portions of scripture, the ritual duty that one wants to know is something
that is to be brought into being, but our quest is for the Brahman that is always
and already fully accomplished. The fruit of knowledge of the Brahman must be
distinct from the fruit of the knowledge of ritual duty that depends upon
performances.
Response from the opponent: No, there is no difference because the Brahman is
taught as connected with injunctions to perform actions by texts such as ‘the Self
is to be visualised’ and ‘Everyone should meditate upon the Self’. The injunctions
stimulate the desire to know the natures the Self and the Brahman and the
Advaita-Vedānta 153
Upanis.ads apply by teaching its proper form as eternally omniscient, all-pervasive,
pure knowledge, liberated, consciousness and bliss. By meditating on that proper
form there arises freedom from rebirth, unknown by ordinary means but known
from scripture. If the Upanis.ads taught established facts without reference to
injunctions to perform ritual actions, they would be meaningless because not
connected with things to be pursued or avoided.
A query: But a fact-assertive statement such as, ‘this is a rope, not a snake’ is seen
to be meaningful by removing fear produced by a misperception. Likewise, the
Upanis.ads are meaningful by removing the misconception about transmigration
when they teach the reality of the non-transmigrating Self.
Reply: this would be the case if the misconception about transmigration were
removed merely by hearing about the proper form of the Brahman, just as the
mistake about the snake is removed just by hearing about the rope. But it does
not cease. Although the Brahman has been heard about, features of transmigrat-
ory life are seen to continue as before. This is why there are injunctions that one
should meditate, after hearing about the Brahman.
Śam. kara now replies: The above view is mistaken because of the radical difference
between the results of the knowledge of the Brahman and knowledge about rit-
ual actions. Actions called duty (dharma) are known from the scriptures. This is the
province of the Mı̄mām . sā Sūtras, which also tell us what to do and what not. The
consequences of right and wrong acts, success and failure, produced by contact
with the objects of the senses, are perceptible pleasures and pains experienced
physically and are known to apply to all creatures from the creator deity Brahma
down to inanimate things. Scripture teaches that there is a hierarchy of pleasures
amongst living beings and from these a hierarchy of dharmas is inferred. From the
hierarchy of dharmas there is a hierarchy of qualified practitioners. The latter
accords with what people aim at and their ability to pay. Those who perform sac-
rifices for the public good follow the higher path because of their special know-
ledge. The southern path is followed by those who perform rituals for themselves.
That there are gradations (tāratmya) in enjoyments in those superior realms is
known from the scripture, ‘dwelling there until merit is used up’. Likewise we
know that degrees of enjoyments amongst terrestrial beings (and below) are con-
sequences of dharmas indicated by Vedic mandates. The gradation in embodied
pleasures and pains, occasioned by the hierarchy of dharma and adharma, on the
part of those subject to defects such as ignorance is known from scripture and
reasoning to be the nature of transmigratory existence. ‘There is no end to pleas-
ure and pain for the embodied one’ refers to the nature of transmigration as just
portrayed. ‘Pleasure and pain do not touch the disembodied’ teaches that the
disembodied state called liberation (moks.a) is not the product of the right actions
specified by Vedic mandates. Liberation cannot be the product of the performance
154 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
of ritual duty, since liberation is the natural state of the soul. Scripture teaches that
the eternally disembodied state called liberation is utterly different from the fruits
of prescribed actions.
Some permanent things, such as earth and the qualities posited by the Sām . khyas,
may change and still retain their identity. But the permanence we are talking
about is absolute, all pervading like the atmosphere, free from every sort of
modification, self-sufficient, impartite and self-illuminating. Where merit, demerit,
their results and the passage of time do not apply, that is the disembodied reality
called liberation. It is the same as the Brahman. Were that being taught as
something subordinate to the performance of actions, and if liberation were to
be accomplished by prescribed actions, it would be impermanent. In fact, it would
be at the top of the hierarchy of impermanent states that are the fruits of action.
But everyone agrees that liberation is permanent. Thus it is illogical that the
Brahman is taught as subordinate to prescribed actions.
Many scriptures such as ‘He who knows the Brahman becomes that Brahman’
teach that liberation is the immediate consequence of knowledge of the Brahman
and rule out any action intervening. No prescribed action intervenes between
the vision of the Brahman and the realisation of pure consciousness as the nature
of everything. Other passages reveal that the sole result of knowledge of the
self’s identity with the Brahman is just the removal of obstacles to liberation. The
Nyāya-Sūtras say the same: release occurs immediately after the destruction of
misconceptions. . . .’ There is removal of misconception as a result of knowledge
of the identity of the self and the Brahman. . . . Knowledge of the Brahman does
not depend upon human activity. Rather, it depends upon reality, like knowledge
of mind-independent entities that are objects of pramān.as such as perception.
[‘knowledge of an entity as it is in itself does not depend upon human ideas
but only on the reality itself . . . knowledge of established entities depends upon
reality.’ Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya.1.1.2]. We cannot rationally suppose that such an
Unconditioned Reality, or knowledge of it, has any connection with things to be
brought about. The Brahman cannot be something to be brought about as if it
were the object of the action of knowing. Scriptures declare that the Brahman is
not within the scope of knowing or contemplation.
But if the Brahman is not an object, how can scripture be the source of knowledge
about it?
Freedom from rebirth does not depend upon action as if it were something to be
accomplished. It is not something to be accomplished because it is the already and
always real nature of one’s identity. Even if the Brahman were different from one’s
true identity, it would not be something to be attained because it is all pervading
and always present to everyone.
Release is not the product of ritual purification, which would make it depend upon
human activity. Such purification comes about by the removal of defects or the
acquisition of virtues. The latter cannot pertain to liberation since it is the nature of
the Brahman to which no perfection need be supplied, and there are no defects to
be removed. If you say that release is a hidden feature of one’s self that is mani-
fested when the self purifies itself by action, we deny this since the self cannot be
the substrate of actions. Actions do not exist without modifying their substrates. If
the self were changed by action inhering in it, impermanence of the self would
result. Hence actions cannot inhere in the true self. The inner self cannot be puri-
fied by an action belonging to something external, because it is never an object.
The embodied self may be purified by actions but that which is purified is a self
that has been possessed by ignorance and confused with the body. It is this
personality that considers itself purified by ritual acts. All actions are performed by
the personality that understands itself as an individual centre of consciousness and
which enjoys the fruits of actions.
Release is not the product of ritual purification because it is just being the
Brahman. It has no connection with actions and is the fruit of knowledge alone.
But what is the meaning of passages that look like mandates, such as, ‘The Self is
to be seen, to be heard about’?
We reply that they have the force of diverting attention from natural everyday
activities. A person preoccupied with externals, pursuing the objects of desires,
does not achieve the ultimate human good. Passages such as ‘the self is to be
seen’ actuate a person who seeks the ultimate good to direct his mind towards
the inner self, distracting his attention from mundane activities.
Śam
. kara and the Buddhists
Śam.kara is accused by some opponents of being a ‘closet Buddhist’. Buddhists
and Advaitins agree that the notion of selfhood is illusory because constructed
out of the interactions between our modes of consciousness and the world.
Moreover, like the Buddhists Śam.kara envisages the evaporation of personal
individuality once enlightenment dawns, and blames suffering on ignorance.
But the accusation is far from the truth. Śam.kara’s metaphysic is totally differ-
ent from the Buddhist temporalism that rejects the very notion of enduring
identities in favour of successions of phases. Śam.kara believes that ‘behind’ the
array of changing phenomena there is a single unconditioned reality: the static
co-incidence of pure being and consciousness. Relative to Unconditioned
Being, the world that we experience is less than fully real, not the genuine art-
icle, but there is an ultimate reality enjoyed by depersonalized consciousness.
In other words, the cosmos has a real cause (sat-kāran.a-vāda), even if we must
be agnostic about the ontological status of entities that ‘cannot be determined
as either real or unreal’. This is because every phenomenon is ultimately unreal
when considered as individual, but real in so far as it participates in the general
reality or the Brahman.
Let us see what he says about various Buddhist schools:
Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya 2.2.18
There are three traditions of Buddhist thought:
Those who say that both material and mental phenomena are real.
Those who say that only mental phenomena are real.
Those who say that there are no intrinsic natures.
To begin with, we refute those who admit the reality of all mental and physical
factors. By physical they mean both the four elements and the sense faculties and
their respective objects. They say that earth, water, air and fire are combinations of
Advaita-Vedānta 157
four different kinds of atoms. The five constituents (skandha) that make up human
lives (body, perceptions, feelings, conceptual thoughts and inherited dispositions)
are internal and in combination form the basis of all interpersonal dealings.
Here we object that there are two different kinds of combinations: but the
reality of these sorts of combinations is unintelligible. This is because the atomic
components of the material combinations are non-conscious and the emergence
of sentience depends upon the prior existence of some compound. They do not
accept any other persisting conscious subject or director who could combine the
basic factors. It cannot be the case that the atoms and skandhas function sponta-
neously because that would entail that they would never cease from activity.
We see here the basis of one of the most significant objections to the Buddhist
reductionist analysis. It may appear economical, plausible and attractive but it
is hard to see how after completing the reduction of entities into their elements
there is any way back. It is easy to smash a glass, but impossible to put the
pieces back together again. It is not clear that Buddhism can account for the
emergence of entities, including the person, from the elements.
Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya 2.2.19
The Buddhist says that although there is no persisting subject of experience
or director who combines the basic factors, the world process is sustained by
the interactive causality of dependently originating factors such as ignorance
etc. Ignorance, habits, perceptions, name and form, the six types of sensation,
touch, feeling, grasping, birth, old age and death, sadness, pain, frustration and
discontent form a self-perpetuating circle of causes and effects. The reality of
those facts of life is accepted by everyone. The cycle of factors, each conditioning
the other as effect and cause, presupposes that there are real combinations [such
as bodies and minds].
Śam
. kara replies:
You are only talking about the originating causes of the elements in the series
and overlooking the sort of organisational causality that would account for the
formation of combinations. The latter is impossible if there are only momentary
atoms and no subjects of experience. Perhaps the factors beginning with ignor-
ance are the causes of the formation of aggregates. But how can they cause that
which is the necessary condition of their existence?
Moreover, you do not think that the combinations are formed in the interests of
enduring conscious subjects so that they might experience the fruits of their
karma (bhogārtham). Hence, experience is just for the sake of experience and is
not sought by anything or anyone else. So freedom from rebirth (moks.a) is just
for the sake of itself and there is no one by whom it is sought. A being with an
158 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
interest in both experiencing the fruits of action and gaining freedom from rebirth
would have to exist contemporaneously with those processes and such persist-
ence would conflict with your belief in the instantaneity of beings (ks.an.ikatva).
Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya 2.2.20
The theory that realities are instantaneous implies that when the later moment
originates, the earlier one no longer exists. So it is not possible to establish the
relation of cause and effect between the two occasions. The claim that once
the prior moment is fully actualised it becomes the cause of the later one is
not intelligible because the hypothesis that a fully actualised entity has a causal
function (vyāpāra) means that it is connected to another moment [so it is not
strictly an instantaneous occurrence but an extended one].
Nor does it make sense to say that the causal function simply is the existence of the
prior entity. This is because origin of an effect that is not tinged by the own-nature
(svabhāva) of its cause is impossible. If one accepts that the effect is tinged by the
own-nature of its cause, the nature of the cause continues in the effect and that
entails the abandonment of the hypothesis of instantaneity. Nor can it be argued
that there could be a cause-effect relation without the nature of the cause affect-
ing the effect because if that were applied in all cases there would be chaos.
If origin and cessation are quite other than the entity, it would follow that the
entity is everlasting.
Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya 2.2.25
Moreover the nihilist (Vaināśika – literally the believer in the spontaneous
destructibility of all entities) accepting the instantaneity of everything must
apply instantaneity to the subject of experiences. But that is not possible because
of the phenomenon first personal memory [of the form, ‘I remember that I
did that’]. Such memory is produced by the reoccurrence of an experiential
awareness and it is only possible if the one who remembers is the same as
the original subject. One man does not remember the awareness of another.
How could there be the experience of the awareness, ‘I saw that and am seeing it
now’ if there were no single subject seeing the earlier and the later? We all know
that the experience of recognition occurs only when there is a single subject of
both seeing and remembering. . . . The nihilist knows himself to be the one
subject of seeing and remembering whenever he thinks, ‘I saw that’. He does not
deny that the past perception belongs to him any more than he denies that fire is
hot and light.
Since one and the same agent is connected with the two moments of seeing
and remembering, the nihilist must give up his acceptance of the essential
temporality of beings.
If he recognises that all his past and future experiences belong to one and the
same subject, and accepts that there is sometimes synthetic awareness of both
successive and simultaneous cognitions, how can the nihilist who asserts universal
instantaneity maintain his position?
The Buddhist may say that recognition and synthetic awareness derive from the
similarity of the momentary cognitions [and this generates the misapprehension
that there are persisting object and the illusion that there is an enduring self]. But
similarity is a relation between two different things. Someone who says that
although there is no single perceiver of two similar things, synthetic awareness is
based on similarity is talking nonsense. If he admits that there is a single perceiver
of the similarity between the earlier and later moments, he thereby grants that
there is one thing enduring through two moments and this contradicts the
hypothesis of instantaneity.
or something similar to it. But there is no room for doubt about whether the
perceiving subject is identical to itself or just something similar.
Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya 2.2.28:
The Buddhist pūrva-paks.in: the Enlightened One taught the theory that the
external world really exists in consideration of those followers who were convinced
about the reality of things external to minds. But this was not his own belief,
which was that amongst the five constituents of personal existence (skandhas),
only perceptions were real. According to the ‘vijñāna-vāda’, we can make sense
of everything to do with means of, objects and results of knowing if they are
purely internal to minds. Even if there were external objects, the process of know-
ing would not get under way without mind. But how is it known that this entire
process is internal and that there are no objects independent of perceptions?
Because there cannot be external objects. If external objects are accepted, they
would be atoms or combinations of atoms, such as pillars. But atoms are not
discerned in our awareness of pillars etc because they cannot be represented in
consciousness. External objects cannot be combinations of atoms because we
cannot determine whether they are the same as or different from the atoms.
Moreover, although cognitions share the same nature in that they are just con-
sciousness, they may express different objects. This would not happen unless the
differentia were internal to awareness, so it must be accepted that a cognition has
the same form as its object (vis.aya-sārūpya). Once this is granted, given that the
representation of the object is determined by cognition (and not the other way
round), the postulation of external objects is superfluous. Moreover, given that
the object and the awareness of it always occur simultaneously (sahopalambha-
niyamād), it follows that there is no difference between a cognition and its object.
It is not that the case that where the cognition and its object are concerned, there
is apprehension of the one when there is non-apprehension of the other. This
would not make sense if the two were different in nature – in which case there
would be nothing to stop the one occurring without the other. Hence there are no
objects external to the mind.
Śam
. kara now replies:
The Buddhist may claim, ‘I do not say that I am not aware of objects. What I do
say is that I am not aware of any object apart from perception.’ But objects
independent of perception must be accepted simply because of the nature
of perception itself. No one perceiving a pillar or a wall is just conscious of his
perception. But everyone perceives pillars and walls precisely in so far as they are
the objects of perceptions. Even those who deny the reality of external things
implicitly grant their existence when they say that representations internal to
consciousness (antar-jñeya-rūpam) appear as if external. If we accept that reality
is as it is given in direct experience, it is logical to accept that it is precisely the
external that is manifested in consciousness, but not what is like the external.
The Buddhist argues that the ‘external-like’ is what is manifest because of the
impossibility of external objects. This can’t be right because what is possible and
what is impossible is ascertained by the means of knowing (pramān.a) and the means
of knowing do not depend upon independently arrived at ideas of what we might
imagine to be possible and impossible. What is possible and what not is understood
by the use of some means of knowing. External objects are apprehended as they are
in themselves by all the means of knowing. How can it be said that they are not
possible on the basis of specious argumentation, given that they are perceived. And
it is not the case that there are no external objects because of the conformity
between cognitions and objects. If there were no objects, conformity between
the representation of the object in awareness and the external object would be
impossible. And the object is represented as external. That is why the co-occurrence
of thought and object (sahopalambha-niyama) is due to the fact that a relation of
mode of presentation and object – presented obtains between thought and object.
It does not derive from the identity of thoughts and objects.
white cow. The individuals differ in respect of their colours but the generic prop-
erty cowness is constant and immutable. The distinct identity of the one constant
factor is established in comparison with the two and the distinct identities of the
two are established in comparison with the single factor. Hence, thought and
objects are distinct.
Moreover, two successive but discrete thoughts with a thinker, self-contained and
confined to their own instantaneous occurrences, cannot be related as the appre-
hending factor and the apprehended. It follows that all the Buddhist teachings are
lost because they involve inter-related ideas.
Man.d.ana Miśra
Śam.kara’s contemporary Man.d.ana Miśra is the other founding father of the
monistic Vedanta vision. His Brahma-Siddhi was as influential as Śam.kara’s
commentaries. Vacaspati Miśra attempted to reconcile the outlooks of the two
thinkers in his Bhamatī commentary on Śam.kara’s Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya.
Man.d.ana differs from Śam.kara in seeing positive value in religious
practices. He thinks that Vedic rituals are purificatory and predispose one
to the realization of one’s true identity. He has no quarrel with the path of
world-renunciation (sam.nyāsa) but observes that it is difficult. He thinks
that the enlightenment received from scriptural statements about the truth
of non-duality must be intensified by ritual and contemplation in order to
counteract still forceful residual traces of ignorance.
Śam.kara’s inspiration is selfless contemplative experience, which shows that
tranquil consciousness is the self-revealing and self-establishing true nature of
reality. For Śam.kara, the fact that awareness occurs as the same in all cognitions
shows that it is the basic reality. In pure consciousness there is neither differ-
entiation nor individuality. This is called the Brahman, where consciousness
and Being coincide. Experience of differences between knowers, thoughts
and objectivity are fabricated through misunderstanding. Man.d.ana’s position
is somewhat different. It is what Paul Hacker called a ‘radical ontologism’. Put
simply, Man.d.ana does not put so much weight on considerations about the
nature of consciousness as Śam.kara. If we say that Śam.kara’s vision arose from
looking within, then we may say that Man.d.ana’s began from looking outside.
There is something there, whatever it may be. The foundational scriptural text
here is the Chāndogya Upanis.ad’s ‘In the beginning this world was just being,
one without a second’ (Ch.Up.6.2.1). Being (sattā) presents itself universally.
Being is present everywhere. Not being something, just being. Being is not dif-
ferentiated. Primary awareness, non-discursive and pre-reflective, reveals this
Advaita-Vedānta 163
non-predicative being. Being is apprehended prior to the identification
of objects in respect of their general and specific features. Being is the core
identity of entities when we abstract away their properties and relations.
Everything is experienced as sharing the undifferentiated form of Being that
is always the same everywhere. Hence we have a monism of Being, rather than
one of consciousness. The Brahman is already known in immediate experience,
even though we inhabit the sphere of avidyā (misunderstanding), having lost
sight of the true nature of Reality.
It is difficult to capture exactly what ‘Being’ means other than to say that
it is the foundational reality of beings. It is that which is the unconditioned
condition of there being anything at all. Man.d.ana also says what it is not.
For example, it is more than actual and concrete entities that exercise causal
efficacy, which Dharmakīrti treats as the criterion of reality. Moreover, it is not
the susceptibility for being connected with some means of knowing or mode
of evidence (pramān.a). Such an epistemic account of being would restrict what
is to what can in principle be known or identified. Man.d.ana’s view is that Being
transcends knowability. The conception is richer than that expressed by the
existential ‘is’ that we use to assert that some entity is numbered among the
objects that furnish our world (‘There is a table here’). It is certainly stronger
than Frege’s suggestion that affirmations of existence are just denials that the
number zero applies to some concept. It is also more than is captured by the ‘is’
of predication, which we use to say that something is such and such (‘The table
is black’). Finally, Being is not an entity because it does not belong to a kind.
The Being of beings is the Brahman, that which is unconditioned by
particular features. It is known as such from the advaita-śrutis, which also
teach the unreality of diversity. But if scripture is a means of knowing a
non-dual reality, it is in conflict with everyday perception that apprehends
differentiated entities. Man.d.ana denies that there is a conflict: perception
apprehends pure being. The rationale for the denial that difference and
individuality are basic realities and for the claim that perception does not
grasp difference is extensively elaborated in arguments that will be developed
by later Advaitins, especially Vimuktātman [fl. 950 A.D.] and Śrī Hars.a
[fl.1150 A.D.]. We shall briefly mention a few points here.
Perception identifies the proper form of an entity: it refers to the thing
just as it is in itself. Separating it from other things comes next. We cannot
differentiate unless we have identified something in the first place. If differen-
tiation or exclusion (apoha) were the nature and function of perception when
we discern a particular entity, we would perceive the difference of the object
164 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
from everything else whether or not present in space and time. This is
manifestly impossible and contrary to experience. Difference from other
things cannot be the very nature (svabhāva) of an entity. Difference is
relational. If it is constitutive of the nature of an entity, it follows that the
entity is the same as that from which it differs. But if difference is not of
the nature of entities, they are not essentially different.
Another consideration is that if difference is the very nature of entities,
given that it is a form of mutual absence or non-existence (anyonya-abhāva –
one thing’s not being another – a reciprocal absence of natures), it follows that
entities do not exist.
It is objected that Man.d.ana is treating difference as a real feature of entities,
when it is a best a boundary. Difference is not a thing in its own right; it is not
a mode of being of an entity but is only falsely presented by constructive
cognitions (vikalpa). There is no property ‘being different’ that belongs to
entities because difference does not really exist – an imagined nature does not
really belong to an entity. Man.d.ana responds that this is exactly what he is
saying: difference does not really exist but is projected by beginningless avidyā.
He also considers the alternative that difference means the interdependence
of entities and not their natures. A proper form is unitary but entities differ
with respect to each other. Man.d.ana denies that interdependence is a genuine
property of entities (i.e. a property whose loss or gain means a real change in a
thing) by which they are constituted. It is illogical to hold that the continuing
existence of entities depends on other entities when their natures are consti-
tuted by their own specific causes. Interdependence is a human concept and
not something that belongs to things as they are in themselves.
After Dignāga, it became a standard view among Brahminical philosophers
that there are two varieties of perception: non-conceptual and conceptual. The
former is reception of whatever is given: the latter is the explicit identification
of features, both general and specific. As Kumārila put it:
In the first place here is cognition (jñāna) that is just seeing (ālocanā) and it is
free from concepts (nirvikalpaka). It is produced from the pure entity and is like
the cognitions of infants and the mute. Neither general (sāmānya) nor specific
features (viśes.a) figure explicitly in the content of awareness, but the individual
that is their substrate is grasped . . . A subsequent cognition by which an entity
is grasped in terms of its properties such as its universal and its qualities is also
considered a form of perception.
Advaita-Vedānta 165
Man.d.ana denies that there can be two varieties of perception. Perception is a
means of knowing that just refers to Being. Every perception reveals the
general form of being that is the Brahman.
His position is:
What Man.d.ana means is simply that in the first instance we just register the
presence of something really there. (If reality is basically simple, features of
entities such as universal property, qualities and the relations between them
are just products of conceptual superimposition.) Judgements that involve
conceptual or constructive cognition come next. But that is not perception as
a means of knowing. Indeed it is not knowing at all.
The rationale is: perception is a means of knowing. What are called
non-conceptual and conceptual perception are different functions with com-
pletely different kinds of objects. The one refers to undifferentiated pure
being, the other to particularities. He has shown that differentiation is not
genuinely real, so cognitions of particularities must be false. They are cases
of avidyā. Avidyā here means error or misconception (vibhrama). Error must
be about something. There can be no apprehension of the non-existent. So
constructive cognitions must be misunderstandings about pure Being.
Avidyā is not genuinely real – if it were it could never be eliminated – but it
is not totally unreal in that it is a familiar phenomenon. That is why it is
called ‘illusion’.
We beings are alienated from Being. This is avidyā. Avidyā is responsible for
all plurality of individual selves, cognitions and objects, and the concomitant
process of rebirth. It is also connected with sorrow, delusion and passions.
It conceals one’s true nature; instead creating the illusion that one is an indi-
vidual agent subject to ritual and social duties and transmigration. While later
Advaitins will distinguish between subjective avidyā that affects individuals
and avidyā as a positive cosmic force that projects diversity and conceals the
true nature of the Brahman, Man.d.ana, like Śam.kara makes more modest
claims. He says that avidyā belongs to individual selves. This is one of the
reasons why the subsequent tradition will posit a causative avidyā. Something
has to constitute the individual as an individual in the first place if it is to be
the substrate of avidyā.
166 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
Further reading
Śam.kara’s Brahma-Sūtra-Bhās.ya is translated in Thibaut (1904). Mayeda (1979) translates the
Upadeśa-Sāhasrī and has a useful introduction.
Suthren Hirst (2005) is highly recommended for Śam.kara.
Potter (1981) has an introduction and summaries of works by Śam.kara, as well as Man.d.ana’s
Brahma-Siddhi by Allen Thrasher. The latter’s Advaita of Vedānta of Brahma-Siddhi is stimulating,
as are Ram-Prasad (2001 and 2002).
Halbfass (1995) collects important articles by Paul Hacker.
Suryanarayana Sastri (1971) translates a classic of Advaita epistemology and metaphysics. It is a pity
that he repeatedly translates ‘vr.tti’ (mental function) as ‘psychosis’.
Some aspects of the debates between the Advaitins and theists about scriptural exegesis are described
in Bartley, Theology of Rāmānuja (2002).
The Summary of the Text in Acharya (2006) is useful for later Advaita.
Advaita-Vedānta 167
See Granoff (1978) for Śrī Hars.a.
For Bhartr.hari, see John Brough’s classic essays on ‘Theories of General Linguistics in the Sanskrit
Grammarians’ and ‘Some Indian Theories of Meaning’ in Hara and Wright (1996). Also Matilal
(1991).
For Gaud.apāda, there is a text and translation in Karmarkar (1953). See King (1995), for connections
with Buddhism.
devotees equally as servants of God. They model the soul’s relationship with
God upon that between human lovers, and sing of the agony of separation and
the bliss of reunion. The theologians, at least in their prose works in which they
were concerned to demonstrate the concordance of their beliefs and practices
with the normative religion of social and religious duty (varn.āśramadharma)
that respects distinctions of caste, tended to suppress the ecstatic emotional-
ism and incipient social inclusivism of the Ālvār tradition. Nevertheless, they
belonged to a monotheistic devotional milieu in which one is encouraged to
delight in the awareness that one exists to be a servant of the divinity Vis.n.u-
Nārāyan.a. God is a person, a being with will, agency and purposes, upon
whom one is radically dependent and in whom one may take refuge. God is a
compassionate personal being who deserves praise and love. This entirely self-
sufficient deity creates and sustains the cosmos for no purpose other than his
own delight (līlā). He is immanent both as the inner guide, the innermost
constitutive element in people, (antar-yāmin) and as present in the consecrated
temple icon. The reconciliation of mainstream orthodoxy and devotionalism
is seen in the soteriologies of Yāmuna and Rāmānuja when they say that
performance of the duties appropriate to one’s caste and stage of life informed
by understanding of the natures of the individual and highest selves combined
with ritual worship and devotion invites the grace of the supreme person
[Vedārthasam.graha 3]. In the first verse of his Summary of the Meaning of the
Gītā (q.v. van Buitenen (1953), Yāmuna says that Nārāyan.a who is the supreme
Brahman is only accessible by devotion (bhakti) accomplishable by the observ-
ance of one’s social and religious duty, knowledge and dispassion. Bhakti is not
just a matter of feeling. It accords with the belief that if God is the foundational
cause of everything, everything one does is also an action of God. This does
not mean that one’s free actions do not flow from the will. It means that it is
thanks to God that the dependent soul is an entity in the first place.
A further factor constitutive of the Śrī Vais.n.ava tradition is the non-Vedic
or Tantric Pañcarātra system of theology and ritual informing the liturgies
enacted in South Indian Śrī Vais.n.ava temples. This tradition is probably as
old as the Christian era, but it is unlikely that any of the surviving texts were
composed before c. 850 A.D.
Pañcarātra sees the world as a real creation by a personally conceived
divinity. It emphasizes divine immanence and accessibility in the temple icon.
It understands people as individual souls. In his Āgama Prāmān.yam, Yāmuna
defends against attacks from Smārtas the orthodoxy of Bhāgavata Brahmins or
Sātvatas who perform Pāñcarātra temple rituals. Some of these who belong to
Viśis.t.ādvaita-Vedānta 171
the Vājasaneyaśākhā of the white Yajur Veda are of unimpeachable Brahmin
status. There are others, who claim adherence to the Ekāyanasākhā and
identify the Pāñcarātra tantras as the fifth Veda (the Vedas are held to be
infinite in extent), but Yāmuna sees their activities as on a par with those of
Smārtas. Suffice it to say that Rāmānuja accepts the epistemic authority
(prāmān.ya) of the Pāñcarātra-Bhāgavata teaching, rejecting the claim that it
is opposed to śruti in that those tantras teach that the individual self has a
beginning. He denies that the system teaches this. Rāmānuja interprets the
Paus.kara Sam.hitā as teaching that the Supreme Brahman, called Vāsudeva, out
of kindness to his devotees continuously wills to exist in modes such as the
temple-icons so as to make himself accessible to those resorting to him. The
Pāñcarātra teaching was composed by God and conforms to that of the Vedas,
understanding of which it facilitates. The system teaches the nature of Nārāyan.a
and the proper way of worshipping him.
Finally, there is a lineage of learned Vais.n.ava teachers (ācārya) specializing
in Upanis.adic exegesis and adept in sophisticated śāstric traditions, Smārta
Brahmins who take refuge in Vis.n.u as their patron deity (is.t.a-devatā).
Nāthamuni, Yāmuna, Rāmānuja and their successors belong to this tradition
of realistic and pluralistic interpretations of the Scriptures instead of the
monism found there by the mystic renouncers of the Advaita tradition.
Viśis.t.ādvaita Vedānta represents a renewal of an ancient tradition of
realistic exegesis of the Upanis.ads. Rāmānuja’s sophisticated theological
formulation of the bhakti religion in opposition to the world-renunciatory
Advaitic gnostic tradition was not new. He cites [Vedārthasam.graha 92–93] a
long list of earlier teachers belonging to the Vedāntic tradition of Upanis.adic
exegesis who taught that bhakti alone, expressed in action and involving
profound understanding, is the path to god.
But Advaitic monism flourished after the seminal works of Man.d.ana Miśra
and Śam.kara (fl.c. 700 A.D.). They hold that ordinary experience articulating
a plurality of individual conscious and non-conscious entities is a beginning-
less global misconception (anādi-avidyā) superimposed upon an inactive and
undifferentiated Brahman characterized as non-intentional pure consciousness.
On this view, the liberation of the soul from rebirth is simply the cessation of
ignorance about the true nature of reality. It is the intuitive realization that
one’s true identity (ātman) is non-intentional awareness (jñapti-mātra) and
that one is not an individual agent subject to ritual duties and transmigration.
This outlook is obviously at odds with the Bhedābheda tradition of Upanis.adic
exegesis, which sees the real cosmos as an emanation (parin.āma) of the
172 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
Absolute and as the real self-differentiation of the Supreme Soul – the substra-
tive cause of all existents. The basic Viśis.t.ādvaitin doctrine that the actual, real
world of conscious and unconscious entities is an organic complex that is both
essentially dependent upon God, and intrinsically distinct from him belongs
to this realistic tradition of thought.
Opposition to Advaita
The Advaitic concepts of the Absolute as impersonal, static, consciousness
and of the non-individual soul (identical with that Absolute principle) as
utterly transcendental and detached from personal individuality are the
fruits of the mystic renouncer’s contemplative experience in whose light the
everyday world appears as less than fully real. But these visionary insights
are problematic when it comes to explaining the genesis of the finite universe
and its relation to the unconditioned reality that has nothing in common
with the world. The developed Advaita tradition attributes the plural universe
and our experience thereof to the operation of a positive force (bhāva-rūpa)
called Avidyā (as the substrative cause of the cosmos, it is obviously different
from everyday notions of ignorance and misconception) which projects
diversity and conceals pure being. The undifferentiated pure conscious real-
ity falsely appears as the plural world when it is obscured by avidyā. Avidyā
explains why we unenlightened beings mistakenly but inevitably think in
terms of different individual entities. Causative avidyā, and its product, the
cosmos, are indeterminable or inexpressible (anirvacanīya) as either real or
unreal. The Viśis.t.ādvaita tradition rejects the latter claim as incoherent: if
something is not real, it is unreal. If it is not unreal, it is real. If it is neither
real nor unreal, it is both real and unreal. If avidyā is different from the
Brahman, monism is compromised. If it is the same as the Brahman then it
exists either absolutely or never. They insist that ignorance cannot be a
subsistent entity with causal efficacy. It is just the absence of knowledge.
Moreover, the putative causal ignorance must have a substrate. It cannot
be the Brahman, which is pure knowledge. Nor can it be the individual self
which, according to Advaita, is itself the product of ignorance. Also, since the
scriptures, in common with all the pramān.as, belong to the sphere of avidyā,
their capacity to reveal the truth is undermined.
174 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
‘Since everything forms the body of the Supreme Person, he is directly signi-
fied by every word.’ Rāmānuja has a semantic principle that the signification of
essentially dependent modal entities (e.g. bodies) extends to the mode possessor.
Whenever something is essentially in an attributive relation to something else
(this includes the relations between qualities, generic properties (sāmānya,
ākr.ti) and the individual substances (dravya) to which they belong as well as
that between souls and bodies), the terms for the attributes may also signify
the possessor. God has created the expressive power (vācaka-śakti) of words
together with the entities which they signify. Any self is a mode of the Brahman
since it is included in the Brahman’s body. Human bodies are modes of their
souls. Words for bodies signify in their primary senses both the conscious
entities ensouling them and God qua the inner controller and guide (antar-
yāmin) of the self. Thus God’s immanence as the soul of each embodied soul is
the basis of the literal reference of scriptural language to Him.
As we saw above (Chapter 10) thinkers of the Bhedābhedavāda tradition
such as Bhāskara and Yādava Prakāśa (1050–1125: originally an Advaitin, then
Rāmānuja’s teacher) formulated versions of pantheism according to which the
cosmos of souls and matter emanates from God. This was repugnant to
Rāmānuja’s tradition. According to the Bhedābhedavāda, the Brahman is the
all-encompassing category of being of which all entities are instances – the
emanations are actually instantiations of God. Their Absolute is originally
undifferentiated being, void of qualities, actions, kinds and individualities, but
becomes threefold as subjects of experience, objects and the controller. The
cosmos is its substrative cause in conditioned form. Effects are not really
different from their material causes and the world is non-different from the
Brahman. The individual self is but the Brahman affected by ignorance
(avidyā), karma and desires (kāma). Rāmānuja’s objection is that this view
converts the Unconditioned into finite reality, subject to transmigration,
imperfection and suffering. One reason for developing the ‘three-level ontol-
ogy’ in which the Brahman, souls and matter are essentially distinct is to avoid
the undesirable consequence that the Absolute is implicated in the vicissitudes
of finite existence. Thus he replaced the Brahma-parin.āma theory with the
idea that real transformation occurs only in the sphere of the entities that
constitute Brahman’s body (brahma-śarīra-parin.āma). He goes beyond an
emanative model of cosmic production by distinguishing between divine pri-
mary causality in constituting the cosmos of souls and matter, and the operation
of secondary causes in the created realms. The Brahman is essentially distinct
from its dependent modes: its essential being or proper form abides intact.
Viśis.t.ādvaita-Vedānta 181
It is in the field of scriptural exegesis that the soul-body model comes into
its own. The interpretation of co-referential (samānādhikaran.a) statements
such as ‘Tat tvam asi’ (‘That thou art’ expressing a relation between the self and
the Brahman) and ‘Satyam. jñānam anantam. Brahma’ (‘The Brahman is real-
ity, consciousness, infinite’: Taittirīya Upanis.ad 2.1.1) is central to Vedāntic
theology. Samānādhikaran.a means the co-occurrence of two or more items,
for example an individual substance and its property, in the same locus or
substrate. In grammatical usage, it is ‘the reference to a single object by several
terms having different grounds for their application’. Such constructions
appear in scriptures expressing the relationship between God and the world,
God and the self or, in the case of ‘Satyam. jñānam anantam. Brahma’ as saying
something about the divine nature.
Vedāntins believe that the language of revealed śruti is our only means of
knowledge (pramān.a) about transcendent reality. We have no cognitive access
to God independently of the infallible and authorless scriptural authorities.
Rāmānuja is a realist holding that there is an isomorphism between knowledge
and the known. There is also a structural isomorphism between scriptural
statements and the reality of which they speak. It is not just the meanings of
words that are informative. Grammatical constructions reflect the nature of
reality. There is a sense in which a thinker’s theory of meaning determines
their metaphysics. Advaitins emphasize the singularity of reference and
construe co-referential constructions as identity-statements conveying an
impartite essence (akhan.d.ārtha). This usually involves attributing non-literal
senses (laks.an.ā-artha) to the co-ordinated words, and this is recognized as
an exegetical weakness. Rāmānuja’s tradition maintains that the grounds for
the application are differences belonging to what is signified. Co-referentiality
is thus the reference to a complex reality by words expressing its different
features. Rāmānuja says that it expresses a single entity qualified by its essen-
tially dependent modes. He interprets co-referential statements about God
and features of creation as expressive of the soul-body relation. In the case of
‘Tat tvam asi’ (‘That thou art’) the Advaitins attribute an extraordinary sense
to each term: ‘that’ stands for the impersonal Absolute, and ‘thou’, has to be
purged of its everyday connotations of individual personality so that it may
signify the Inner Self that is identical with the Brahman. The statement
expresses the identity of the two. But according to the Viśis.t.ādvaita exegesis,
the ‘that’ stands for the creator God, the inner guide of the soul, of whom all
entities are modes since they form his body. ‘Thou’ stands for an individual
self, an essentially dependent mode of God. ‘Tat’ denotes the Highest Self,
182 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
Because the body is a mode of the embodied entity and because the meanings of
words for modes extends to the mode-possessor, there is the principle that the
meanings of words signifying bodies extend to what is embodied. Whenever we
think, ‘This is such and such’, the mode is understood as the aspect that is ‘such
and such’. It is logical that the mode culminates in the mode-possessor since it
depends upon that entity and its being apprehended depends upon that entity.
Thus a word signifying a mode extends to the possessor. (śrı¯ Bhās.ya 1.1.13)
Because all conscious and non-conscious entities are modes of the Supreme Soul
in that they are his body, all words for such beings apply in their primary senses to
the Supreme Soul. (Vedārthasam . graha 75)
People unlearned in Vedānta do not see that all objects and all individual souls
participate in the nature of the Brahman. They think that the referential scope of
all words is restricted to the entities that they usually signify that are in fact only
part of their meanings. Once they have learned about the Vedānta passages, they
understand that all words signify the Brahman who constitutes his various modes
since everything participates in the Brahman in so far as he is the Inner Controller
and that everything is created by him. (ibid. 21)
The body may be thought of in co-ordination with the Self in that it is the essential
nature of bodies to exist in an attributive relation with selves since they would not
exist independently of them. This is comparable to the relation between generic
properties such as cowness and their individual instances. (Gı¯tā Bhās.ya 13.1)
Further reading
The Śrī Bhās.ya is translated in Thibaut (1904), the Vedārthasam.graha in van Buitenen (1956) and the
commentary on the Gītā has an English précis in van Buitenen (1953).
Svāmī Ādidevānanda’s edition and translation of the Yatīndramatadīpikā is useful primary source.
There is a classic monograph by Carman (1974), which can be supplemented by Lipner (1986). Bartley
(2002) sees the soul-body model as an exegetical device and dwells on controversies with Advaitin
interpretations.
For God as the ‘inner-controller’ see Oberhammer (1998).
For the devotional religious context see Hardy (1983).
For Pañcarātra, Schrader (1973) is still the standard work. There is interesting material in Sanderson
(2001). See also Sanjukta Gupta (2000), Laks.mī Tantra.
If we say that there is no text without an author (apaurus.eya) the notions of right
(dharma) and wrong and the other matters of which the scriptures speak that are
accepted by all philosophical traditions lack any foundation. Someone who denies
right and wrong does not help the world and only encourages violence. There is
no point in his trying to serve mankind since he admits no supernatural reality.
Right and wrong cannot be established by human opinions because people are
liable to ignorance and dishonesty.
That the Vedas are not human compositions is self-evident because there is no
tradition testifying to their authorship. Positing an author when one is not known
is an uneconomical hypothesis.
The Vedas are eternal and subsist in the mind of Vis.n.u. They are manifested, but
not originated, when uttered by God.
The Vedas are fact-asserting. They speak of already existing things as well as things
to be done. In ordinary language, meanings are primarily grasped in respect of
things that already exist. Language is primarily informative and descriptive. It is only
once one has understood that something is a means to an end that one acts
accordingly.
The overall purport of scripture is not the identity of the individual soul and God.
Passages stating that they are different are not uninformative repetitions of what
is already known by some other means because the existence of God is not estab-
lished without scripture.
God’s existence cannot be proved by inference because inference can also prove
the opposite.
The argument, ‘The world must have a creator because it is an effect, like a jar’ is
countered by ‘The world has no creator because it is not a single whole object’.
Self-evident experience establishes the difference between the individual soul and
God. Everyone knows that they cannot do everything. Scripture is not an authority
if it contradicts this sort of self-evidence.
The goals of human life such as dharma have results that are ultimately transitory
and mixed with unhappiness (since one knows that they won’t last for ever). Only
freedom from rebirth (moks.a) is the supreme felicity to be sought by those
wandering in sam. sāra.
Freedom is not attained without the grace of God. God feels affection for those
who recognise his superior virtues but not for those who insist on their identity
with him.
Difference
The logical arguments against the reality of difference advanced by Advaitin think-
ers are unsound because difference is the proper form or essential nature (svarūpa)
of an entity.
There is proof of difference by the existence of the relation between attribute and
substrate or quality and qualified. But relation between attribute and substrate
depends upon difference.
These arguments are circular and lead us to conclude that we since cannot
properly formulate an understanding of difference it does not exist.
Madhva replies: But just because difference implies that there are counterparts to
the subject, it does not follow that it is not the proper form of the subject. That
number one is not the number two does not compromise its identity.
The hypothesis that individual entities cognised by the means of knowing are
unreal (mithyā) is an obfuscation since it contradicts the means of knowing.
Reasoning (tarka) on its own cannot refute what has been established by the
means of knowing. What is directly perceived cannot be dismissed as error just by
reasoning.
We move on to the rejection of the Advaitin theory that just as illusions and
mistakes cannot be categorised as real (because subsequently corrected) or
unreal (because they have real effects) neither can the plural cosmos be real or
unreal because it is a product of avidyā.
[143] There is no means of knowing something that is neither real nor unreal.
When someone says, ‘We cannot be aware of what does not exist’ is he thinking
about non-existence or not? If he is not thinking about non-existence, he cannot
deny that non-existence was a real content of thought. If he is thinking about
non-existence, the same applies.
In illusions there is a thought of something real that was not present in a certain
set of circumstances.
We do not need to claim that the content of illusions is neither real nor unreal.
Introducing that category introduces more problems than it solves. For instance, it
is real or not? The idea flies in the face of experience. Everyone thinks in terms of
things either existing or not existing.
190 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
The theory that something that is directly seen as real, is in fact unreal, needs the
support of stronger evidence than observation. But if there is no such evidence,
there is no need to suspect observation. What is known by perception cannot be
refuted by reasoning alone without other more authoritative perceptions. We
know on the basis of perception and reasoning that large objects appear small in
the distance. This is not a perceptual error. We can understand that this is the way
things appear to us. We can use perception to establish the scope of perception,
but there could be no way of establishing that all our perceptions are false.
***
The view of Man.d.ana Miśra and Vācaspati Miśra that avidyā belongs not to
the Brahman but to the individual self can quickly be dismissed because the
very concept of individuality is fabricated by misconception in the first place.
Moreover, if the soul that has avidyā is really identical with the Brahman, then
avidyā belongs to the Brahman too. Some Advaitins argue that the apparent
difference between the soul and the Brahman derives from some sort of
imagined feature or unreal qualification (upādhi) that becomes superimposed
upon the Brahman. But this is unconvincing. If the upādhi is constructed
(kalpita), this act presupposes ignorance in the first place, and the argument
becomes circular: avidyā produces the upādhi, and the upādhi is responsible
for ignorance. If the upādhi is not constructed and is a beginninglessly real
feature of the individual soul, it follows that there is something that originally
differentiates the individual soul from the Brahman. If the qualification really
belonged to the Brahman, it would compromise its perfect simplicity.
The idea that the Brahman is the substrate of ignorance was intended to
avoid these problems. But if this is true, the released soul will be subject to
ignorance too since the Advaitins suppose it to be the same as the Brahman. If
ignorance is somehow implicated in the very being of the Brahman, it must be
real. If such ignorance is responsible for plurality, then plurality is real and it
would be impossible to escape from ignorance-based sam.sāra.
Further reading
Sarma (2003) is a good start. It needs to be supplemented by Mesquita (2000). Gerow (1990) translates
a text from the subsequent tradition and is excellent on the details of the controversies with Advaita.
The Vis.n.u-Tattva-Vinirn.aya is in Raghavachar (1959) with a translation.
Between 700 and 1100 A.D. Kashmir was home to an extraordinarily rich
and sophisticated religious and intellectual culture. Informed by their own
scriptures (called Tantras or Āgamas), monistic and dualistic schools of
Śaivism (the worship of forms of the deity Śiva, sometimes accompanied by
his female partner or Śakti), and to a lesser extent some Vais.n.avas (votaries of
the deity Vis.n.u), competed with Buddhism for the patronage of rulers and the
adherence of the populace. We shall look at the ritualistic monotheism called
Śaiva Siddhānta that understands the world as a real creation for the sake
of individual conscious souls, and also at some of the monistic Śākta cults
194 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
worshipping forms of the Goddess and the fearsome god Bhairava. The
latter follow scriptures that are quite separate from those of the Vedic
tradition, and involve practices involving the violation of taboos as means
of acquiring extraordinary powers, the expansion of consciousness beyond
conventional inhibitions and the propitiation of antinomian deities. They
think that freedom from rebirth is the recognition of one’s true identity
as nothing other than the dynamically conscious source of everything. Both
Śaivas and Śāktas accept the authority of a corpus of twenty-eight divinely
revealed scriptures called Āgamas or Tantras, but the Śāktas expanded the
canon significantly and of course claim finality for their own scriptures.
Most Śaivas accept that the religious observances, gnostic and ritualistic,
sanctioned by mainstream orthodox Brahminism can lead souls to contexts of
experience in higher levels of the cosmos. Indeed, it is of those traditions that
they claim to be superior versions. But they denied that orthodoxy was the
path to the highest attainable good beyond the cosmos of worlds. The ultimate
state is achievable only through the religious disciplines of the Śaiva cults.
Śaiva Siddhānta
This is a Tantric (i.e. non-Vedic) ritual cult teaching that there are three
permanently distinct eternal categories of reality: the godhead named Śiva,
individual conscious souls, and material and psychological realities. Its
scriptural authorities are 28 texts called Tantras or Āgamas that are believed
to be the word of God. It flourished in Kashmir between the eighth and
the eleventh centuries A.D. Important thinkers belonging to this tradition
include Sadyojyotis (c. 700 A.D.), Nārāyanakan.t.ha (925–975 A.D.), his son
Rāmakan.t.ha (950–1000 A.D.) and Aghoraśiva (c. 1150 A.D.). Sadyojyotis
wrote a work called ‘The Examination of God and the Soul’ (expounded by
Rāmakan.t.ha as the Nareśvara-parīks.ā-prakāśa [NIPP]), a commentary on the
Svayam.bhūva-āgama, as well as a number of shorter works. Nārāyanakan.t.ha
wrote a commentary on the Mr.gendra Āgama. Rāmakan.t.ha’s most significant
works, in addition to that just mentioned, include commentaries on the
Mataṅgapārameśvara Āgama [MPAV] and the Kiran.a Tantra.
Śaiva Siddhāntins believe that ritual worship of Śiva, consequent upon
initiation into the religion (dīks.ā) through the imposition of mantras by one
who has undergone a higher consecration (ācārya) and is held to be a human
expression of the deity, is the only means to the human soul’s liberation from
rebirth at death. Initiation and liberation are entirely thanks to the descent of
Śaiva Philosophies of Kashmir 195
Śiva’s grace (anugraha-śakti-pāta). Only Śiva saves. Initiation removes some of
the restrictions on the soul’s potentially infinite innate powers of knowledge
and agency. These, however, cannot be fully manifested in the context of
human life. So initiation does not wholly destroy all the limiting factors proper
to the human condition. The portion that remains is gradually eliminated
over the course of one’s life by the prescribed daily ritual and meditative
observances. Following the prescribed religious path for its own sake prevents
the production of personalizing karma that binds one to rebirth. The latent
accumulated karma that would otherwise have generated further finite
existences is wiped out in the initiation ritual.
The innate capacities for universal knowledge and agency of some souls
have been suppressed by an innate defect called ‘mala’. Mala is also responsible
for those souls’ subjection to bondage by karma and rebirth. The concept
of mala as a substantial and irreducible entity in its own right (vastu) is of
cardinal importance for the Śaiva Siddhāntins because it explains why the
souls undergo subjection to bondage or karmically bound experiences in
the sphere of materiality in the first place. There has to be such a primal and
irreducible defect obscuring the soul’s dual faculty (śakti) of knowledge and
action, because there is no other satisfactory explanation for the process of
transmigration. Originally pure souls would not become involved in rebirth.
(Rāmakan.t.ha discusses this in the sixth chapter of his commentary on the
Mataṅgapārameśvara-āgama [MPAV p. 208 ff.] and in the second chapter of
Kiran.atantra-vr.tti.) This original stain, the root cause of bondage to rebirth,
is categorized as a material substance (dravya) that attaches itself to souls.
Knowledge would be sufficient for liberation if bondage to rebirth were just a
misconception. Indeed, the monistic Śaivas identify it with ignorance and thus
say that it can be removed by knowledge. But knowledge of the presence and
nature of a material substance is insufficient for its removal. Such a substance
can only be removed by action – specifically, the Śaiva Siddhānta initiation
ritual (dīks.ā). Mala is like an ocular cataract, awareness of which does not
prevent its efficacy. Its removal requires the action of the surgeon’s instrument.
When Śiva decides that a human soul, who longs for liberation from rebirth and
accepts the Śaiva teachings, is morally fit for liberation, he induces that soul to
approach an ācārya and solicit initiation. That ritual weakens mala and enables
participation in Śaiva ritual life. The real nature of Śiva is revealed to the initiate
for the sake of the manifestation of his power of cognition. Thus illuminated, he
appears like Śiva and he becomes a Śiva at the death of the body.
Initiation leaves caste, understood as a physical property, intact. The Śaiva
Siddhāntin is thus able to fulfil his Brahminical social and ritual duties.
196 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
His exacting life of Śaiva ritual duty is thus compatible with the observance of
mainstream orthodox Brahminical duty and caste purity (varn.a-āśrama-
dharma). The tradition holds that the daily and occasional obligatory rites
must still be performed because there is still a danger of reverting to sam.sāra
if they are omitted. Indeed, one should not transgress the practices of one’s
caste and station in life. (Some of the monistic Śaiva traditions say that
there votaries are in everyday life Vedically orthodox (i.e. observant of varn.a-
āśrama-dharma), in religion a Śaiva (i.e. a Śaiva-Siddhāntin), but in secret a
Kaula (i.e. an initiate into an ecstatic visionary cult whose practices transgress
the boundaries of conventional orthopraxy).)
So the Śaiva Siddhānta is primarily a religion of ritual from initiation until
death. Mala obfuscates awareness that Śiva and the soul are equals (not, for
example, master and servant). Initiation enables the realization of this truth.
But it does not destroy every imperfection. Some karma (were it totally
obliterated, the initiand would die) remains and one is still embodied and
enmeshed in the impure cosmos. Post-initiation performance of ritual
eliminates the residual imperfections. Such observances are not mindless and
mechanical but an enlightened path of active gnosis or understanding-in-
action. Knowledge is only effective when acted upon, and action presupposes
understanding. Daily worship is preceded by a rite in which the practitioner
imagines himself as Śiva, sanctifying himself by the imposition of mantras
on his body and faculties, in accordance with the principle that only Śiva
can worship Śiva. Initiation marks the start of a new way of life and the
transformation of one’s being. Liberation, occurring at death, is understood
as equality with Śiva – meaning a state of qualitative identity in which the
soul’s innate capacities for knowledge and action are fully realized. (In order to
avoid a clash of purposes, the released selves choose not to exercise their
omnipotence.) In should be noted that the tenet that the capacity for agency is
an essential property of the selves in all their conditions is one of the factors
that demarcates the Tantric from those mainstream orthodox traditions that
treat agency as ultimately either illusory or a function of embodiment.
be self-created but must have a maker with the knowledge and power appropri-
ate to its complexity. Thus we establish the existence of God.
There is a specific challenge at this point from the Buddhist Dharmakīrti
(600–660 A.D.) who argues that while we can infer in respect of specific cases
of composition that each has a controlling agent, we cannot infer that all effects
have a single maker. In other words, from the proposition, ‘every effect has a
cause’ we cannot infer ‘there is one cause of every effect’. Pots and mountains
are both effects, but they are effects of different kinds. Rāmakan.t.ha thinks that
this is a quibble that undermines inference: it is established that every sort of
effect is invariably concomitant with some kind of maker ([Kiran.atantra
(Goodall) p. 72]).
But perhaps the world just emerges from the material elements. So why try
to prove another cause called God that is absolutely unseen? Rāmakan.t.ha’s reply
is that a non-intelligent cause could not generate the regular and structured
diversity that the world displays. Without super-natural governance the
emergence of entities from matter would be chaotic. It is true that the world is
organized in accordance with the good and bad karma of sentient beings. But
karma is non-conscious, so such organization requires superintendence by a
single deity with the requisite understanding of the diverse karma of beings.
Paśu
Bound souls that are individual centres of reflexive awareness and agency
potentially capable of existing beyond space, time and the physical. Each
has the essential properties of being a knower and being an agent. While
potentially omniscient and omnipotent, some of them have become enmeshed
in inferior physical and mental existences in the realm of māyā where their
deliberate and intentional actions generate residues which personalize and
remain with the agent until circumstances appropriate for their fruition occur
(karma). Human souls are subject to mala, māyā and karma. Such souls are
equipped with five derivatives from māyā that are called kañcukas:
1. A limited capacity for agency (kalā-tattva) bestowed upon souls who would
otherwise be paralysed by mala.
2. A limited capacity for sensory perception and other intellectual acts (vidyā-tattva).
Aghoraśiva says that ‘vidyā is the means by which one knows the intellect (buddhi)
in its various aspects such as judgment, memory, imagination and concepts’
(Tattvasam. grahat.ika, verse 13).
Śaiva Philosophies of Kashmir 199
3. A principle of causal regularity (niyati-tattva) ensuring that the results of actions
(karma-phala) accrue to the agent.
4. An interest in the objects of experience on the part of the otherwise apathetic
mala-afflicted selves (rāga-tattva).
5. Our experience of time and its successiveness (kāla-tattva). Time is a created reality
and plays no part in the lives of śiva and released souls.
Pāśa or bonds including māyā, karma, mala and Śiva’s power of concealment.
In addition to the five kañcukas, the products of māyā are prime matter
(prakr.ti-tattva) consisting of the three gun.as (sattva, rajas and tamas), intellect
(buddhi), mind (manas), the sense of ego (aham.kāra), the five sense-faculties
and the subtle forms of their objects, the organs of speech and movement, and
earth, water, air, fire and space. The mental apparatus, being inert and material
is not intrinsically conscious, but it may assume the form of awareness. Mental
faculties are purely instrumental, helping bound souls to find their way around
the world. Rāmakan.t.ha says that the instrument of knowing may be said to be
conscious only metaphorically.
Hence whatever we understand the world to be, that will have to become the
object of some means of knowing (pramān.a). There will thus be some sort of
relation between the means of knowing and the objects known. That relation
presupposes that there exists at least one kind of duality. Without a means of
knowing he cannot establish emptiness. The world is objectified (vis.ayīkr.ta)
whenever someone seeks to establish (vyavasthāpāyitum – identifying the
nature of something and discriminating it from others) anything by a means
of knowing. It is impossible to establish anything about that which has not
been made an object. Because of the reality of the process of objectification,
the world cannot be empty in the Madhyamaka Buddhist’s sense. That is to say,
there really are objective standards by which truths can be known.
Rāmakan.t.ha rejects the Buddhist idealist claim that there is non-apprehension
(anupalambha) of the difference between the forms of objects and our cognitions
of them. He says that this is contradicted by the fact that we recognize the
difference between establisher and established. Were it otherwise, we could
not establish anything. The Buddhist agrees that there are methods of estab-
lishing the nature of reality. But such methods cannot just be operating on
themselves because there is a contradiction in something’s performing its
proper function on itself. Hence if there are such methods, they must have
objects external to themselves [MPAV 154–155].
Let us remind ourselves at this point of the difference between the
Buddhist idealists (vijñaptimātra-vādins) and the Buddhist representation-
alists (Sautrāntikas). The latter hold that there is a significant difference
between the way things are and the ways our minds work. They say that
we have to infer (anumeya) the real mind-independent domain (bāhyārtha)
as the ultimate cause of the sorts of experiences that we have. But those
experiences are always interpreted in our ideas. While there is an external
domain consisting of instantaneous unique particulars (svalaks.an.a), it does
not figure as such in the contents of our thoughts. By contrast, the idealist
theory denies that there is a real domain independent of perceptions. Mental
variety derives from the accumulation of mental traces laid down by prior
perceptions. When Dharmakīrti says that there is no difference between the
colour blue and the cognition of blue because they always co-occur, he did
not intend the denial of the mind-independent domain. The argument
recommends agnosticism about its nature: an agnosticism that should wean
us away from our conventional mentality structured by the subject-object
dichotomy. The point was, however, taken by Buddhists and non-Buddhists
alike to be an idealist thesis.
Śaiva Philosophies of Kashmir 201
Dharmakīrti had said that, ‘Although awareness is undifferentiated, it is
considered by the misguided to be differentiated into objects, perceivers
and thoughts.’ This can be interpreted in two ways. If it means that in reality
everything is internal to awareness, it is consistent with the idealist outlook.
But it is also consistent with the Sautrāntika representationalist’s anti-realism
if it is taken as meaning that we naturally understand the world in terms of
subjects, objects and experiences, although those categories do not mirror
reality as it is in itself. Rāmakan.t.ha follows the idealist reading. The idealist
will say that an experience of a pot is precisely that: just an experience. Believ-
ing in a world of mind-independent material objects is just such a matter
of experience. But there is a problem here. Rāmakan.t.ha observes that two
sorts of consciousness are pre-reflectively given in everyone’s experience
(anubhava-siddham): there is the awareness of oneself as the perceiving sub-
ject (grāhaka) and there is awareness of objects apprehended (grāhya). Also,
from the phenomenological point of view, we do experience a difference
between the sorts of awareness that we have of our cognitions on the one hand
and of objects on the other. Moreover, the subject is given in its internality as
the constant and uniform perceiver, but the contents of its awareness of objects
known are always changing. So Dharmakīrti’s claim that consciousness is uni-
form fails. Dharmakīrti thought that the notion of a constant subject was an
illusion, a product of mental construction. But Rāmakan.t.ha points out that
while all sorts of imagination and mental fabrications are possible, the basic
identity of the subject cannot be a construct because it cannot exercise the
process of conceptualization (vikalpa) on itself. The constructor can’t originate
itself as a result of its own constructive activity. It has to be there in the first
place. Rāmakan.t.ha argues that the Buddhists cannot make sense of the notion
of constructive superimposition (vikalpa) if everything is instantaneous. A
momentary awareness is no sooner come than gone. If there is no temporal
duration, there can be no mental synthesis of earlier and later. It follows that
recognition, memory and conceptual construction, all of which require both
duration and a single subject capable of uniting separate cognitions, are impos-
sible [MPAV 159–160].
Rāmakan.t.ha argues for a conception of the self as an enduring principle of
identity, whose essential properties are reflexively known consciousness and
agency. The self is that which always reveals objects. It is established by its own
self-awareness as the stable and continuous illuminator of objects. Embodied
human souls inhabit a structured environment consisting of kinds of persisting
objects that exist independently of minds. The world really is as it appears to
202 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
The Vaibhās.ikas and the Sautrāntikas who accept the existence of entities external
to the mind (bāhyārthavāda); the Mādhyamaka relativists who say that the
constituents of reality postulated by the bāhyārthavādins lack intrinsic identities
(svabhāva-śūnyatā); and the Yogācārins who hold that everything is dependent
upon minds.
They all agree that there is no entity called ‘soul’ which is distinct from transient
cognitions, because we have no knowledge of it.
Śaiva Philosophies of Kashmir 203
The argument from non-cognition (anupalabdhi), characteristic of Dharmakīrti,
is that when an object or state of affairs satisfies the conditions for knowability
or perceptibility, its not being cognized allows us to conclude that it does
not exist. Dharmakīrti maintains that the soul is the sort of thing that would
be knowable by us (upalabdhi-laks.an.a-prāpta) as separate from essentially
temporal episodes of awareness. But it is not thus known and so we may con-
clude that it does not exist.
Rāmakan.t.ha attributes to his Buddhist opponents the view that personal
identity is just an essential temporal stream of experiences, continuously
subject to destruction:
The Buddhist says that we see consciousness appearing in many forms such
as joy and despondency and concludes that we are a stream of impermanent
cognitions. He further argues that where the knowing subject is permanent, it
would be invariant and could not shift the focus of its attention from object to
object. As Dharmakīrti (to whom Rāmakan.t.ha refers frequently) puts it:
The soul is defined as that which is established by its own reflexive awareness
(svasam . vedana-siddha) as a stable continuant (sthiratayā) in as much as it is always
the illuminator of objects.
The self, which is the ever-uniform stable conscious perceiver, is not a conceptual
construct in that it is reflexively given to each person as the observer of all objects.
[NIPP 166 and MPAV 158]
Given that perception proves the nature of the subject as the conscious agent of
the direct perception of all objects, it is not possible to establish the non-existence
of the self since it is self-evident. Being the subject of karmic experience means
being a cognizer. That is the true form of the soul and it is self-evident to every-
one. [NIPP p. 13]
That whose nature is to have knowing as its essential property is the soul that is
the subject of experiences. The soul is proved to exist for everyone because it is
manifest in one’s own direct experience. [Kiran.a p. 53]
This atemporal soul is constantly manifest as the same in all mental acts.
The individual consciousness that is an essential property of everyone is self-
manifesting or reflexive. The reflexivity of consciousness means that when
a subject is aware of some object or fact, simultaneously and in virtue of the
same act, he is aware of himself as the subject or possessor of the experience.
It is important to remember that in this sort of ‘self-consciousness’ the self
does not appear as an object. As Rāmakan.t.ha puts it: ‘It is not the case that
there are two cognitions: one of the object and another of the self. Rather,
when an awareness of an object is also aware of itself, the nature of the self is
given as that reflexivity’ [MPAV p. 157].
Rāmakan.t.ha has to reconcile the diverse and flowing character of our
mental life with the continuous integrity of the soul that is its subject. The
self is not reducible to the states that are its stream of consciousness. The self
cannot be the same as the states because it is the very condition of those states
occurring as a unified stream. The Buddhist takes the opposite position when
he argues that consciousness is always changing: we only find awareness
appearing in various modes such as joy and despondency but never encounter
a separate entity called self [MPAV p. 150]. He concedes that even if the cognit-
ive capacity of the perceiver is not momentary, it definitely is not permanent
because it comes and goes as expressed in experiences like, ‘I have a headache’,
Śaiva Philosophies of Kashmir 205
‘this feels nice’, ‘my sorrow has gone away or it will pass’ [MPAV p. 172]. Given
that we experience cognitions as transitory, it follows that personality is in a
state of constant flux, and a bundle of perceptions is all we are.
Rāmakan.t.ha responds by distinguishing two modes of awareness: the
cognitive discrimination (adhyavasāya) and the permanent background
consciousness. The former is variable because it is a property of the essentially
material and mutable mind (buddhi-dharma). The latter is the awareness
that is a constitutive feature of the human condition (paurus.am). Its absence
is never experienced as it is always encountered as uniform subjectivity
[Kiran.atantra (Goodall) p. 54]. The distinction enables him to say that thoughts
and feelings may come and go, the succession of experiential states may indeed
be variable, but the enduring subject of experiences remains constant, always
revealing itself as the same.
It is undeniable that we experience a stream of consciousness, but this is
different from saying that we are only that stream. Consciousness is a unity
with a perspective upon its different states. The unity of consciousness means
that at any given moment I may be looking at something, feeling something,
thinking about something else, wanting something and deciding to do
something without falling in to schizophrenic morass. The different conscious
acts do not mean that my consciousness is fragmented. My awareness of
the different objects and contents of those states is unified. Consciousness
encompasses the range of mental operations.
Rāmakan.t.ha’s response to the Buddhist account of experience appeals to
two types of argument: one from the phenomenology of consciousness, and a
hypothetical inference (arthāpatti) from the intelligibility of activity that has
future goals:
Indeed, belief in the soul derives from beginningless ignorance (anādi-avidyā) and
since it causes rebirth should be rejected by seekers after liberation who should
practice repeated contemplation of the non-existence of soul. [MPAV 151]
Rāmakan.t.ha replies that this cannot be right because we are aware of the inner
self as something different in kind from objects. If it were the product of
superimposition, it would appear like an object and as different from whatever
was performing the superimposition. But our experience is not like that.
Rather, given that the self is the illuminator of objects, its nature is that of the
internal perceiver. Any superimposer would have to be a stable subject of
awareness. Were it manifest as purely momentary, superimposition would
be impossible because that requires an enduring consciousness capable of a
synthetic cognitive grasp of earlier and later [NIPP p. 15].
According to Buddhists of Dharmakīrti’s school, an instant has no before or
after. A momentary thought is no sooner come than gone. Its origin coincides
with its destruction. If there is no endurance, how would memory and concep-
tual thought be possible since the agent of the synthesis of thoughts is the
consciousness that is proper to the self? Memory and the synthesis of experi-
ences involve conceptualization (vikalpa) which requires the mental synthesis
Śaiva Philosophies of Kashmir 207
of earlier and later by a constant background awareness. But momentary cog-
nitions cannot perform those functions [MPAV p. 159]. Moreover, how can an
instantaneous perceiver objectify itself in such a way that it can mistakenly
impute permanence to itself?
Finally, Rāmakan.t.ha of course rejects the Nyāya-Vaiśes.ika view that the
existence of what for them is a non-experiential principle of identity has to
be inferred since it obviously cannot reveal itself. They posit the self as the
single principle that is necessary for the unification of diverse sensory expe-
riences, for example, touching, tasting and seeing the same thing. It also
explains the possibility of the synthesis of earlier and later experiences over
time. Because cognitions, volitions, pleasures, pains, efforts, merit, demerit
and inherited tendencies are qualities (gun.a) they need a substrate (āśraya)
that is a substance (dravya) and that substance is the self. Rāmakan.t.ha
simply does not accept the Nyāya-Vaiśes.ika ontology about the relationship
between qualities and their possessors. His view is that a substance or
basic particular (dravya) is a confluence of properties (gun.asam.drava or
gun.asamudāya). This is not the same as the Buddhist reductionist view
because substance here means a persisting substrate, an object that is an
integration of properties, where the whole is not a separate entity from its
properties or parts. Rāmakan.t.ha concludes that because cognition, feelings
and intentions are not separable qualities in their own right, we must estab-
lish on the basis of self-evidence, and not inference, that the capacity for
knowing belongs to the nature of the self as its essential property [NIPP
10–11; K53; MPAV153].
Personal agency
The self is not just a stable cognizer or detached observer (as the Sām.khyas
think), it is also a centre of free agency with causal powers (kriyā-śakti).
But the Buddhist cannot make sense of the phenomenon of action since if
the subject of experience were essentially temporal, it could not perform
actions. When something is done by a single instantaneous cognition, its
fruition would be another instant of cognition that would not occur in a later
life of the instigator. Since the instants differ, the experiencer of the fruits of
action will differ from the instigator. The experiencer of the fruit would be a
different entity. The enjoyer of the fruit would be other than the conscious
subject who was the agent of action [MPAV 165–166].
208 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
The Buddhist denies that when one person has done something, its fruits
are experienced elsewhere on the grounds that actions and their consequences
constitute different streams of experiences. Rāmakan.t.ha replies that the
question, ‘which stream is which?’ has no determinate answer if the streams
just consist of momentary entities where an earlier moment is followed by a
later one. That would not be sufficient to yield real distinctions such that we
could identify separate streams. In short, there would not be any individual
streams. The Buddhist claims that a relation of similarity between moments
individuates them into streams consisting of the five skandhas (the body,
feelings, sensory perceptions, habits and conceptual thoughts). Rāmakan.t.ha
says that there would have to be some sort of intimate connection between
the moments. It cannot be produced by space or time since the Buddhist
does not accept that they are realities in their own right. Nor can it derive
from the essential natures of entities. There are two points here. Buddhists
reject essences or unchanging natures. But in so far as anything may be
conventionally treated as having a nature, such a nature derives from its place
in a system of relations. So the notion cannot be appealed to as an explanation
of the generation of those systems. Rāmakan.t.ha concludes that here is no
proof of the existence of integrated streams of experiences because discrete
instants cannot produce individual identities [MPAV p. 166].
The Buddhist doctrine of the essentially temporal nature of all entities
involves a rejection of the theory upheld by mainstream Brahminical ortho-
doxy that actions are to be analysed in terms of specific factors (kāraka-vāda)
such as a fixed starting point, the autonomous agent, the recipient, the object
desired and means. They espouse a theory of causation according to which
there are just processes or sequences of events (kāran.a-vāda) in which
individuals, whether agents or patients, are just aspects of a causal event,
enjoying no special significance. The Brahminical view, according priority
to substances and agents as causal factors, is succinctly expressed in the verse,
‘The master of the factors in relation to action and inaction, whether it is
currently active or not, is the factor called the agent.’
It is soteriologically crucial for Rāmakan.t.ha that the persisting self-
conscious individual substances, embodied and enduring intact through time,
are autonomous ritual and moral agents spontaneously capable of initiating
novel sequences of events that follow from their decisions and that are
not wholly produced by antecedent causal conditions. That is to say, souls are
individual substances possessing innate causal powers that are dispositions
to act in certain ways in appropriate circumstances. Where events involving
Śaiva Philosophies of Kashmir 209
human actions are concerned, souls are, as it were, the glue that holds the
members of a sequence of ephemeral events together as a causal process
and thus account for its continuity. As we have seen, the stable and enduring
ātman, the transcendental enabling condition of experience, which is given in
experience but not produced by it, is exempt from determination by time. Its
agency is not determined by sequences of events.
Personal agency, as opposed to behaviour which may be merely reactive,
instinctive and non-conscious, is necessarily connected with consciousness
and is introspectively manifest to oneself as the reason for one’s physical exer-
tions and movements. In the case of other people, it is analogously inferred
from their bodily actions. Personal agency, which has the nature of autonomy
(svātantrya) in that it is the rational basis for the function or non-function of
all the factors involved in events (kāraka), is directly experienced as being
responsible for effort and physical movements, the performing of religious
and everyday actions having seen or unseen results. It cannot be denied
because, like the state of being a cognizer, it is directly known to each as a form
of internality in that one is the inner instigator of the factors implicit in events
[NIPP pp. 95–96].
He claims that the Buddhist theory implies that it does not matter whether
Devadatta provides services for monks or kills them. Since service and killing
are equally treated as contributory causal aspects of an event, the merit and
demerit proper to each would accrue indiscriminately to Devadatta and to the
mendicants. Where could the difference lie if everything is just an aspect of a
causal process that is a sequence of events? The Buddhist reply that the causal
process is differentiated into streams that are the individual Devadatta as
the instigator, service as the intended purpose and the mendicants as the
beneficiaries then this amounts to acceptance of the kāraka-vāda which
involves the categories of agent, object and instrument and not the process
theory of causation (kāran.a-vāda). And if the kāraka theory is established, so
is the agency of the self [MPAV 171].
Some rituals confer specific benefits and powers. But ritual practice may also
help to consolidate belief, deepen commitment and keep alive an original
inspirational insight by preserving a sense of enlightened deliverance from
the frustrations, changes and chances of daily life. Enlightenment is under-
stood as recovery of one’s true identity as the deity. Salvific realization may be
achieved by ritual informed by gnosis, or by gnosis alone, or it may simply
happen unexpectedly thanks to a purely fortuitous descent of divine grace.
While enlightenment and liberation, understood as the salvific expansion of
consciousness bestowed in initiation, are possible in the course of one’s life
(jīvan-mukti), most initiates have to wait for death, which is coterminous with
the exhaustion of the residual karma appropriate to this life, to experience it
fully. The life of ritual practice confirms and intensifies the original liberating
experience, purifying it of conceptual elements. Thus enlightened, one sees the
world in a new light.
Absolute Idealism
The philosophical articulation of the Śākta cults is a form of Absolute Ideal-
ism: the view that everything is a manifestation of a single trans-individual
214 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
consciousness, which is the only reality that has independent existence. (Since
there has been some controversy about whether some of the Indian thinkers
who have traditionally been characterized as idealists really are idealists,
I should say that I take idealism to mean the rejection of the possibility
of material substance that exists independently of some consciousness. On
this interpretation, Vasubandhu and his followers in the Vijñānavāda tradi-
tion, as well as Utpaladeva, Abhinavagupta and Ks.emarāja are idealists.) This
sort of idealism is not philosophical scepticism about the existence of the
external world. It is the affirmation of the real world as a partial expression of
the divine nature. The world really is independent of human minds. It is not
fabricated by individual perceivers. It is not surprising that people who devote
much time to mental purification by profound meditative exercises, in which
‘thought-forms’ sometimes appear to the practitioner as external, should
incline towards an idealist mentality.
For these ecstatic idealists the world exists only as its representation in
consciousness: it is not the case that there are two types of substance, the
mental and the physical. The theorists of these cults understand the sole
conscious reality as dynamic, projecting both finite centres of awareness
and the experiences of the kinds of objects that they enjoy.
In his Śivasūtra-vimarśinī, Abhinavagupta’s successor Ks.emarāja expresses
the idealist mentality like this:
Consciousness manifests itself both internally [as thoughts and feelings] and
externally [as things and events] in a variety of forms. Because objects only exist in
relation to consciousness, the world has the nature of consciousness. For entities
cannot be known without consciousness. So it is concluded that consciousness
has assumed the forms of entities. By contemplating entities, we can rationally
understand that knowable phenomena are conscious by nature. Consciousness
and its objects have a single nature because they are experienced simultaneously.
[ad Sūtra 30]
Regarding the modes of thinking, ‘I know’, ‘I knew’, ‘I shall know’ which are
founded upon reflexive subjectivity, what else is there to know? If these did
not shine, the cosmos would be dense darkness, or rather it would not even be
that. ‘How does the knower know itself?’ If one denies the conscious subject,
what question and what answer would there be? [IPV p. 71]
own existence. It knows its own nature simply by being what it is. It does not
need anything outside itself to do it for it. In this sense, it is consciousness, not
matter, which is basic.
Śiva’s tranquil state is the highest form of self-awareness. But there is an even
higher state that is ever so slightly distinct, and that is the abode of the Goddess.
The whole of reality comes from the creative light of consciousness (prakāśa), itself
deriving from the sheer delight that lacks nothing and which itself finds its rest
in the uncreated light wherein there are no traces of awareness of differences. The
Goddess is the unsurpassable tranquil state that has consumed the traces of
awareness of existences that had remained in the uncreated light. Śiva’s nature
is the tranquil state that devours time. The Goddess is the perfection of that
tranquillity. (Mahānayaprakāśa 3.104–11. Text cited in Sanderson (2007), p. 309)
Krama practice
The Worship of the Kālīs is a meditative sequence of twelve phases (each sym-
bolized by one of the twelve Kālīs) that effects an expansion of consciousness
from the confines of limited personhood to an enlightened form of awareness in
whose light the everyday world becomes transfigured. In other words, what had
been experienced as the merely mundane is recognized as the self-expression
of the Divinity. In the course of this worship, consciousness transforms itself
as it ‘devours’ both its own contents and its awareness of itself as individual.
One contemplates the emanation (sr.s.t.i) of the cosmos from its transcendent
source, its conservation in being or stasis (sthiti), and its withdrawal (sam.hāra)
into that source, followed by its repeated emanation and so forth. That
process of cosmic emanation is mirrored on the microcosmic level in the
sequential structure of normal cognition that reaches out to objects, focuses
attention upon them and absorbs them into itself. A clue to the nature of the
divine activity is found in such modalities of human consciousness, which
mirror creation, conservation and withdrawal. Our states may be more or less
self-aware. Sometimes we are in an extroverted state, totally absorbed in some-
thing and not really self-aware. But self-awareness brings consciousness to
life. The interplay of extroversion and introversion in our own minds is held
to be a microcosmic imitation of the divine nature. In the Krama ritual one
symbolically contemplates the cyclical process of cosmic emanation, stasis and
222 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
If there were not one conscious Divinity who contains the infinite universe within
himself and who has the powers of knowledge, memory and differentiation,
the harmonious functioning (sthiti) of the human world, which stems from the
synthesis by consciousness (anusamdhāna) of different and separate thoughts,
would cease’.
IPK 1.5.1
The manifestation as external to consciousness of entities that are manifested in
present experience is possible only if they are internal to consciousness.
IPK 1.5.2
If the object were not of the nature of the light of consciousness (prakāśa),
it would remain unilluminated as it was before it was known. The light of
consciousness is not different from the object. The light of consciousness is the
nature of the object.
IPK 1.5.3
If the light (prakāśa) were intrinsically undifferentiated and different from objects,
objective reality would be confused. The object that is illuminated must itself be
of the nature of the light of consciousness because that which does not have that
nature cannot be established.
Utpaladeva and Abhinavagupta hold that we can explain mental variety and
complexity only if it derives from a single conscious source. It is the Sautrāntikas
who think that the mind-independent realm of unique particulars must be
inferred as the cause of such variety, and to a statement of their outlook we
now turn:
IPK 1.5.4
If the light of consciousness is undifferentiated, it cannot cause a diverse and
complex manifestation. Because such a manifestation is inexplicable in these
terms, we must infer external objects as its cause.
IPK 1.5.5
[An argument against a Vijñana-vada Buddhist idealist]
A diverse revival of karmic residues cannot be the cause [of experiential variety]. In
that case there would be the question of what causes the variety in such revival.
IPK 1.5.6
That may be the case. But why posit the external on the grounds that we cannot
explain things otherwise, when all everyday activities can be explained if all things
are manifestations of the single divine consciousness?
IPK 1.5.7
Like a Yogin, just by the power of will, the Divinity whose nature is consciousness,
manifests all phenomena lying within him as external without needing any
independent substrative cause.
IPK 1.5.8–9
We an only use inference if what is to be established has been perceived somewhere
before. The sensory faculties are only inferred in very general terms as causes.
Objects that are totally external to consciousness are never manifested to con-
sciousness at all. Thus their existence cannot be established through inference.
Śaiva Philosophies of Kashmir 229
We can infer the presence of fire from the presence of smoke because we are
familiar with smoke, fire and their relationship. But inference cannot operate
when one of its terms is totally unknown (especially in this case where that
which is to be established is by definition noumenal and outside the range of
our cognitive capacities). This is not inference but pure speculation. It looks
like Utpaladeva may be going too far here. We can infer the existence of the
sensory-faculties from the occurrence of perceptions, although, ex hypothesis,
we never perceive those faculties. What he is in fact saying is that we do
not infer the actual natures of the sense-faculties but only their generic
characteristic of being something that has a causal function. So we are not
inferring and understanding concrete realities but only the abstract concept of
causal efficacy. Thus we have not left the sphere of thinking and entered the
territory of external reality as understood by the Representationalist.
IPK 1.5.10
It is true that there is manifestation of beings that already exist within the Lord.
Otherwise the act of reflexive awareness (āmarśa) that is deliberate willing (icchā)
would not occur [they would not appear unless the Divinity knew them and
desired that they be manifest].
IPK 1.5.11
Reflexive awareness (vimarśa) is the essence of manifestation by consciousness.
Otherwise the light of consciousness (prakāśa) although tinged by the objects
would be lifeless like a crystal.
IPK 1.5.12
That is why one’s real identity is consciousness, meaning the acts of awareness
and the state of being the agent of conscious acts. By that one is distinguished
from the insentient.
IPK 1.5.13
The act of awareness is reflexive, the repository of all meanings, and spontaneously
arising. This is real freedom, the sovereignty of one’s ultimate identity.
230 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
IPK 1.5.14
It is this that is the vibrancy of consciousness, unconditioned Being unlimited by
place or time. This reality is expressed as the essence and the heart of the
Divinity.
IPK 1.5.15
By virtue of this he makes himself the objects of awareness. But the field of cogni-
tion does not subsist independently of him. If he depended on knowable objects
independent of himself, his freedom would cease.
IPK 1.6.1
The reflexive awareness ‘I’, whose nature is the light of consciousness, although
expressed by a word is not a concept (vikalpa) because a concept is an act
of mental discrimination that presupposes the possibility of affirmation and
exclusion, and this awareness has no opposites.
IPK 1.8.1–2
Sometime the Ideas (ābhāsa) are grasped in present sensory experience but
at other times they do not depend upon present experience, as in the cases
of a blind person or in darkness. But there is no difference in the reality of
the Ideas of objects featuring in thoughts, whether they concern past, present
or future.
IPK 1.8.3–4
Even when feelings like pleasure and their occasions are real, and their manifesta-
tions are real conscious states, if they belong to the past their external conditions
are not given. Still, if feelings are intensely reproduced by imagination then they
are felt by the subject as if the past object were present since he experiences the
feeling so vividly.
Śaiva Philosophies of Kashmir 231
IPK 1.8.5
Externality is not a genuine property of the Ideas about realities and non-beings.
Being experienced as external is not the essence of the Ideas. The Ideas, which are
internal, always exist [whether some finite subject thinks them or not].
IPK 1.8.7
The Ideas, in so far as they are of the nature of consciousness, always exist within
[the trans-individual consciousness]. Given that their manifestations as external
are due to the power of māyā, they are experienced as external.
IPK 1.8.9
Owing to the will of the Lord, mental representations and feelings of pleasure are
manifested as if relating to what is external to consciousness.
IPK 1.8.10
Without the unification of cognitions, there would be no worldly life. The unification
of cognitions is based on the unity of trans-individual consciousness. There is one
knowing subject common to all [called the Supreme Self].
IPK 1.8.11
It is he only that is the Divinity by virtue of his constant self-awareness and
representation of things to himself. Reflexivity (vimarśa) is the pure knowledge
and action of the deity.
IPK 2.2.1
The concepts (‘buddhayah.’, which is glossed as ‘satya-ābhāsās’) of action,
relation, universal property, individual substance, space and time which apply
in the sphere of unity and multiplicity, are considered true because of their
permanence and utility.
The theory of Ideas recognizes the categories and the pramān.a framework
that are recognized by the realist Nyāya-Vaiśes.ika school. Utpaladeva and
Abhinavagupta accept the validity of their conceptual scheme, as long as it is
232 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
That single principle which is both within and external, whose form is radiance
unlimited in light and darkness, that is the Divinity that is the essence of all beings.
Its sovereign śakti produces entities. [1–2]
The śakti does not desire to be different from its possessor. The shared nature of
the two is permanent, like that of fire and burning. [3]
This is the deity Bhairava who sustains the cosmos because by his śakti he has
made everything appear as reflected in his own mirror. [4]
The śakti is the transcendent Goddess who delights in contemplating his essence.
Her perfect state neither increases nor diminishes in relation to finite beings. [5]
The Divine Omnipotence eternally delighting in play with the Goddess simultane-
ously dispenses the emanations and reabsorptions of the worlds. [6]
The emanations and reabsorptions of the worlds are established as fissions of the
autonomous innate śakti. [9]
In them there is infinite variety of spheres of experience and their regions, as well
as pleasant and unpleasant experiences. [10]
Śaiva Philosophies of Kashmir 233
When the unconditioned divine freedom is not understood, there is cycle of birth
and death that terrifies the unenlightened. This too is his power. [11]
Divine grace is accessible for one who has gone to a teacher or from scripture.
[12]
God-given understanding of the truth is freedom from birth and death, and it is
perfection for the enlightened ones. This is known as being liberated while still
alive. [13]
Both bondage and freedom proceed from God. They are neither really different
from each other, nor different from God. [14]
In this way Bhairava exercising his three-fold śakti of will, action and knowing is
the true nature of all beings. [15]
Further reading
For the Siddhānta see Sanderson (1992).
Filliozat (1994) translates Sadyojyoti’s commentary on the Svayambhuvāgama.
For the context of Rāmakan.t.ha’s thought about the self, Watson (2006) is valuable.
Goodall (1998) provides a text and lucid translation of the first six chapters of Rāmakan.t.ha’s Kiran.a
Tantra commentary. The Mataṅga commentary is in Bhatt (1977). It has not been translated. Nor
has Rāmakan.t.ha’s Nareśvaraparīks.ā-prakāśa. A (rather doubtful) text is Shastri 1926. Watson
(2006) presents a critical version of much of Book 1.
Elaborate arguments for the existence of God were also formulated by Naiyāyikas beginning with
Jayanta (850–900 A.D.) They are mentioned in ‘Much Ado about Religion’ (Dezső (2005)). By
Jayanta’s time, personalist theism had long surpassed automatic ritualism as the dominant type
of religiosity in many parts of the sub-continent. A useful source here is Krasser (2002) that
discusses both Buddhist and Nyāya thought stemming from Dharmakīrti’s arguments against
an omnipotent and omniscient creator. Also very interesting is Frank Clooney Hindu God,
Christian God.
For the traditions that we have labelled Śākta, see Sanderson (1985 and 1992) to begin with and move
on to Sanderson (1990 and 1995 ‘Meaning in Tantric Ritual’). Professor Sanderson’s preeminence
in this field is evident from his ‘The Śaiva Exegesis of Kashmir’ (2007).
Ks.emarāja’s Pratyabhijñāhr.dayam is in Singh (1982) and his Śiva Sūtra-vimars.inī in Singh (1991).
For Utpaladeva’s Īśvarapratyabhijñākārikā with the author’s own commentary, see the text and
translation in Torella (2002). Abhinavagupta’ s Vimarśinī commentary is in Subramania Iyer
and Pandey (1986).
The Bodhapañcadaśika is in Shastri (1947).
Chapter III of Kahrs (1998) deals with Kashmiri scriptural exegesis. Padoux (1990) is a classic study of
the powers attributed to words in the Hindu traditions.
234 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy
Padoux, A. (1990), Vāc: The Concept of the Word in Selected Hindu Tantras, Translated by Jacques
Gontier, Albany: SUNY Press.
Pandey, K. C. (trans.) (1986), Īśvara-pratyabhijñā-vimarśin.ī of Abhinavagupta: Doctrine of Divine
Recognition, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Pandeya, R. (ed.) (1989), The Pramān.avārttikam of Ācārya Dharmakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Pandeya, R. (ed.) (1999), Madhyānta-Vibhāga-śāstra, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Potter, K. H. (ed.) (1977), Encyclopedia Of Indian Philosophies: Vol. II, Indian Metaphysics and Episte-
mology: The Tradition of Nyaya-Vaisheshika up to Gangesha, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Potter, K. H. (ed.) (1981), Encyclopedia Of Indian Philosophies: Vol. III, Advaita Vedanta up to Śaṅkara
and His Pupils, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Potter, K. H. (1996), Encyclopedia Of Indian Philosophies: Vol. VII, Abhidharma Buddhism to 150 A.D.,
Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Potter, K. H. and Bhattacharya, S. (eds) (1993), Encyclopedia Of Indian Philosophies: Vol. VI, Indian
Philosophical Analysis; Nyāya Vaiśes.ika from Gangeśa to Raghunātha Śiroman.i, Delhi: Motilal
Banarsidass.
Pradhan, P. (1967), Abhidharmakośabhas.yam of Vasubandhu, Patna: K.P. Jayaswal Research Institute.
Pruden, L. (trans.) (1988), Abhidharmakośabhas.yam, Berkeley: Asian Humanities Press.
Raghavachar, S. S. (ed. and trans.) (1959), Śrīmad-Vis.n.u-Tattva-Vinirn.aya of Śrī Madhvācārya,
Mangalore: Sri Ramakishna Ashrama.
Rahula, W. (1969), What the Buddha Taught, London: Gordon Fraser.
Ram-Prasad, C. (2002), Advaita Epistemology and Metaphysics, London: RoutledgeCurzon.
Rocher, L. (ed.) (1988), Studies in Indian Literature and Philosophy: Collected Articles of J. A. B. van
Buitenen, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Sadhale, G. S. (ed.) (2000), The Bhagavad Gītā with Eleven Commentaries, Delhi: Parimal Publications.
Sanderson, Alexis (1985), ‘Purity and Power among the Brahmins of Kashmir’, in M.Carrithers et al.
(eds), The Category of the Person, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 190–216.
Sanderson, Alexis (1990), ‘Śaivism and the Tantric Traditions’, in F. Hardy (ed.), The World’s Religions:
The Religions of Asia, London: Routledge, pp. 128–172.
Sanderson, Alexis (1992), ‘The Doctrine of the Mālinīvijayottaratantra’, in T. Goudriaan (ed.), Ritual
and Speculation in Early Tantra: Studies in Honor of André Padoux, Albany: SUNY Press,
pp. 281–312.
Sanderson, Alexis (1995), ‘Meaning in Tantric Ritual’, in Essais sur le rituel III, Louvain, Paris: Peeters,
pp. 15–95.
Sanderson, Alexis (1995), ‘The Sarvāstivāda and its Critics’, in Buddhism in the Year 2000: International
Conference Proceedings, Bangkok and Los Angeles: Dhammakāya Foundation, pp. 37–49.
Sanderson, Alexis (2001), ‘History through Textual Criticism’, in François Grimal (ed.), Les sources et le
Temps. Sources and Time. A Colloquium, Pondichéry: Institut Français de Pondichéry & École
Française d’Extrême-Orient, pp. 1–47.
Sanderson, Alexis (2007), ‘The Śaiva Exegesis of Kashmir’, in D. Goodall and André Padoux (eds),
Mélanges Tantriques à la mémoire d’Hélène Brunner, Pondichéry: Institut Français de Pondichéry &
École Française d’Extrême-Orient, pp. 231–442.
Bibliography 239
Sarma, D. (2003), An Introduction to Mādhva Vedānta, Aldershot: Ashgate.
Scharf, P. (1996), The Denotation of Generic Terms in Ancient Indian Philosophy: Grammar, Nyāya, and
Mīmām.sā, Philadelphia: American Philosophical Society.
Schrader, F. Otto (1916), Introduction to the Pāñcarātra and the Ahirbudhnya Sam.hitā, Madras, Adyar
Library.
Shastri, J. L. (ed.) (1980), Brahmasūtra- Śaṅkarabhās.yam, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Shastri, J. Z. (1947), Bodhapañcadaśika of Abhinavagupta, Srinagar: Kashmir Series of Texts and
Studies.
Shastri, M. K. (ed.) (1926), The Nareshvarapariksha of Sajyojyoti with the Commentary by Ramakantha,
Srinagar, Kashmir Series of Texts and Studies.
Siderits, M. (1991), Indian Philosophy of Language: Selected Issues, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Siderits, M. (2003), Personal Identity and Buddhist Philosophy: Empty Persons, Aldershot: Ashgate.
Singh, J. (1982), Pratyabhijñāhr.dayam, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Singh, J. (1991), Śiva Sūtras, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Stcherbatsky, Th. (1970), Madhyānta-Vibhanga, Osnabruck: Biblio Verlag.
Streng, F. J. (1967), Emptiness: A Study in Religious Meaning, New York: Abingdon Press.
Subramania Iyer, K. A. (ed.) (1964), Vākyapadīya of Bhartr.hari (Kān.da I), Poona: Deccan College.
Subramania Iyer, K. A. and Pandey, K. C. (eds) (1986), Īśvarapratyabhijñā-vimarśinī of Abhinavagupta,
3 Vols, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Suryanarayana Sastri, S. S. (ed. and trans.) (1971), Vedāntaparibhās.a of Dharmarāja Adhvarin, Madras:
The Adyar Library and Research Centre.
Suryanarayana Sastri, S. S. and Barnett, L. D. (ed. and trans.) (2003), The Paramārthasāra of Ādi Śes.a
and the Paramārthasāra of Abhinavagupta, Fremont: Asian Humanities Press.
Suthren Hirst, J. G. (2005), Śam.kara’s Advaita Vedānta, Abingdon: RoutledgeCurzon.
Svāmī Ādidevānanda, (ed. and trans.) (1949) Yatīndramatadīpikā, Mylapore: Sri Ramakrishna Math.
Svami Dvarikadasa Shastri, (ed.) (1994), Nyāyabinduprakaran.am, Varanasi: Bauddha Bharati.
Swāmi Jagadānanda (1941), Upadeśa SāhasrI of Śrī Śam.karācārya, Mylapore: Sri Ramakrishna Math.
Taber, J. (2005), A Hindu Critique of Buddhist Epistemology: Kumārila on Perception: The ‘Determination
of Perception’ Chapter of Kumārila Bhat.t.a’s Ślokavārttika Commentary, London: RoutledgeCurzon.
Tachikawa, M. (1981), The Structure of the World in Udayana’s Realism, Dordrecht: Reidel.
Thibaut, G. (trans.) (1904), The Vedanta-Sutras with the Commentary of Ramanuja, Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Thibaut, G. (trans.) (1904), The Vedanta-Sutras with the Commentary of Shankaracarya, 2 Vols, Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Thrasher, A. W. (1993), The Advaita Vedanta of Brahma-siddhi, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Tillemans, T. J. F. (1999), Scripture, Logic and Language, Boston: Wisdom Publications.
Tola, F. and Dragonetti, C. (2004) Being as Consciousness, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Torella, R. (ed. and trans.) (2002), The Īśvarapratyabhijñākārikā of Utpaladeva, Delhi: Motilal
Banarsidass.
Watson, Alex (2006), The Self ’s Awareness of Itself: Bhat.t.a Rāmakan.t.ha’s Arguments against the Buddhist
Doctrine of No-Self, Wien: Publications of the De Nobili Research Library.
240 Bibliography
Whicher, I. (1998), The Integrity of the Yoga Darśana, Albany: SUNY Press.
Williams, P. (1989), Mahayana Buddhism, London: Routledge.
Williams, P. (1998), Altruism and Reality, London: Curzon Press.
Wood, T. E. (1991), Mind Only: A Philosophical and Doctrinal Analysis of the Vijñānavāda, Honolulu:
University of Hawaii Press.
Woods, J. H. (1927), The Yoga Sūtras, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Wynne, A. (trans.) (2009), Mahābhārata Book Twelve. Peace. Volume Three. The Book of Liberation,
New York: New York University Press.
Index
buddhi (faculty) 4, 83, 84, 86, 87, 205 endurance vs perdurance 202
‘bundle of perceptions’ 22, 95, 130, 205 essential temporality 1, 13, 14, 158–9, 202,
203, 207, 208
caitta 28 ethics (Buddhist) 17–19, 33, 39
caste 2, 3, 5, 13, 18, 118, 143, 170, 195, 196, ‘event ontology’ 1, 91, 202, 208–9
210, 212, 218 ‘externalism’ 91, 99
causal efficacy see arthakriyā extrinsic validity of knowledge 108
cetanā (intention) 17, 18, 32
citta-viprayukta-dharma 28, 36, 37 ‘fivefold difference’ 185
cognitive errors 49, 73, 77, 80, 106–7, 174 flux, universal 28
consciousness 131, 138, 145, 162, 176–7, of sensation 39
201, 204–5, 214–16, 224 Four Noble Truths 16–17
psychological vs phenomenal 216–17 Frauwallner, E. 26
unity of 205, 231 freedom from natural causality 4, 87
‘Consciousness-only’ (Buddhist freedom from rebirth see moks.a
tradition) Ch. 6, 160–2, 200, 202, 211,
224, 227 Gaud.apāda 140
constituent of personality see skandha gnosis, liberation through 82, 87, 139, 210
‘construction of the unreal’ God
see abhūta-parikalpa inferential proof 113, 172–3, 197–8
linguistic reference to 180
devotional religion 168–9 revealed by scripture 134–5, 172, 181, 184b
dharma (natural right and order) 3–4, 8, grace, divine 168, 170, 186, 188, 195, 197,
118–20, 128, 132, 170, 196 210, 233
Dharmakīrti 38, 46–55, 144, 198, 200, grāhya-grāhaka-vibhāga see subject-object
201, 203 dichotomy
dharmas (basic elements) 14, 26, 27, 28, gun.a (constituent of prakr.ti) 83, 199
29, 30, 32, 33, 40, 57, 58, 59, 64, 75, 77 gun.a (quality) 39, 91, 98–9, 104, 207
Abhidharma classification 28, 36 gun.a-sam.drava 84, 207
differentiation (and individuality)
see bheda hallucinations see cognitive errors
Dignāga 38–45, 46, 47, 49, 50, 52, 54, 124, hetu 40, 52, 53
126, 127
dīks.ā 195, 196, 197, 210, 210 idealism 43, 49, 68, 69, 76–81, 107,
‘direct realism’ 31, 37, 90, 91, 100, 105, 213–14, 224, 227
106, 107, 109, 123–8, 131, 161, 169, absolute 210, 213, 220, 226, 232
174, 181, 185–6, 191 theistic 214
‘disjunctivism’ 107 inferential reasoning see anumāna
dravya 39, 85, 91, 93–8, 104, 175, 177, 179, initiation see dīks.ā
180, 207 intention see cetanā
dravya-sat 28, 59 interdependent origination
dr.śya-anupalabdhi 53 see pratītya-samutpāda
duh.kha 16, 22 intrinsic nature see svabhāva