MODULE 2.A: The Self From Philosophical Perspective
MODULE 2.A: The Self From Philosophical Perspective
MODULE 2.A: The Self From Philosophical Perspective
I. Introduction/Module Overview
Philosophy ignites the inquisitive mind to discover the ultimate causes, reasons, and
principles of the things around us. It also goes beyond the scientific investigation by exploring all
areas of knowledge like politics, religion, psychology, physics and many more. The word
philosophy means “love of wisdom” which refers to the desire for truth by incorporating never
ending inquiries to provide answers to the questions about the nature of human existence.
Ancient philosophers attempted to explain social and natural phenomena coming up with their
own definitions of how the world works and which factors contribute to such phenomena. Thus,
it was inevitable to come up with various conceptions of what it means to be human. The nature
about the self is one of the most interesting topics among the philosophers.
This module presents the philosophical perspective of the self to help students identify
one’s own self to attain self-knowledge. It further provides different views of the philosophers
about the nature of self.
II. Desired Learning Outcome
At the end of this module, you will be able to:
a. discuss the different representations and conceptualizations of the self from various
disciplinal perspectives;
b. synthesize the different concepts of the self from the philosophical perspective; and
c. demonstrate critical and reflective thought and analyzing the development of one’s self
and identity by developing a theory of the self.
Renaissance Period
The distinguishing mark that separates Renaissance period to that of Medieval period is
the assertion that knowledge is no longer exclusive to Church. There are factors that enabled the
change. It was this time that the printing press was invented, which makes knowledge available
to everyone including the masses. Compared to the other historical periods in Europe, during the
Renaissance, many people can read and write even if they are not priests or royals. This new
status quo ushered many alternative ideas to flourish, aside from those coming from the church’s
authorities.
One of the most distinctive intellectual movements within the Renaissance was
humanism, which was originally called “humanities”, that is, the study of humanity. The main
emphasis of humanism was secular education using Greek and Latin classics, many newly
rediscovered, rather than medieval sources. Scholars during the Middle Ages had also drawn
from classical Greek and Roman sources, but their larger aim was to use these ancient writers to
bolster Christian theology, and they either ignored or criticized classics that were inherently in
conflict with theology. Renaissance thinkers, by contrast, appreciated the full spectrum of
ancient writers in and of themselves, irrespective of their application to theology. There were
five traditional subjects in humanities education, namely, grammar, rhetoric, poetry, history, and
moral philosophy. The most significant impact humanism had on philosophy was the revived
study of ancient Greek philosophical schools, thanks to the publication of new editions and
translations of classical texts. The invention of the printing press during this time made these
books much more available to readers, and the influence of classical philosophy spread like
wildfire. Humanistic philosophers latched onto the earlier schools of Greek philosophy, almost
as though they were pretending that the middle ages never existed. They variously associated
themselves with Platonism, Aristotelianism, Epicureanism, Stoicism, or Skepticism, interpreting
the classical texts and expanding on them. We will look at four representative humanist thinkers
here.
Our discussion highlights three ingenious philosophers of their time - Francis Bacon,
Rene Descartes, and Thomas Hobbes. There are three concepts you need to remember in this
period: (1) Inductive method, (2) doubt, and (3) selfish human nature.
Rene Descartes: The Self is the Thinking Thing
French philosopher Rene Descartes is the father of modern philosophy and has brought a
new perspective to philosophy and the self. He wants to penetrate the nature of reasoning process
and understand its relationship to the human self. The Latin phrase “Cogito ergo sum” which
means “I think therefore I am”, is the main point of Descartes’ concept of the self. He believes
that the self is a thinking entity distinct from the body, a thing that doubts, understands, affirms,
denies, refuses, imagines and perceives.
schools of Mahayana define this state not as nirvana, but rather as “emptiness” (Ho, 1995: 122).
Nirvana, in turn, is a very close state to what is called mystical experience (Dimkov, 2015, 2017,
2019c). Mystical experience is defined as follows (Gellman, 2014, italics P.R.D.; Dimkov, 2017:
315-316):
Hinduism. Hinduism explains the self through a monistic philosophy (metaphysics). Like
Buddhism, Hinduism views the essence of human life as consisting in suffering and asserts that
this is caused by having a fallacious conception of the self: “The true self is permanent and
unchanging, the non-true self is impermanent and changes continually” (Ho, 1995: 124).
Hinduism in the face of Vedanta postulates an essence, which stands after the so-called
transcendental unity of consciousness (Kant) or the “Self-as-Knower”, namely the non-
changeable “Self-as-Witness” (Ho, 1995: 124). This kind of self is the true self, which cannot be
described, but can be experienced (cf. the conception of the “Observing Self” of Deikman
(Deikman, 1982)). The Upanishads discuss a zone of non-thought, in which the Self-as-Knower
and the Self-as-Witness unite and enter into a trans-cognitive state, in which there is no place for
any cognition (Ho, 1995: 125). This state is described also by other authors as e. g. a substantial
matrix of consciousness (Dimkov), a mold of man (Castaneda), a trans-subjective self (Stace)
and a field of consciousness (Formann) (Dimkov, 2015: 110-111; 2017: 317; 2019c: 71).
VI. References
https://iep.utm.edu/socrates/.
https://philonotes.com/index.php/2020/09/04/kants-concept-of-the-self/.
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/self-knowledge/supplement.html.
https://philonotes.com/index.php/2020/09/04/socrates-concept-of-the-self/.
Ho, D. Y. F. (1995). Selfhood and identity in Confucianism, Taoism, Buddhism, and Hinduism:
Contrasts with the West. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 25(2), 115-134.
http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-5914.1995.tb00269.x.
Mosig, Y. D. (2006). Conceptions of the Self in Western and Eastern psychology. Journal of
Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 26(1-2), 39-50. http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0091266.
Deikman, A. (1982). The observing Self: Mysticism and Psychotherapy. Boston: Beacon Press.
Dimkov, P. (2019a). Bipolar affective disorder with respect to the theories of the constitution of
selfhood via narratives. In Annual collection of papers of the Department of Philosophical and
Political Sciences (pp. 115-133). Faculty of Philosophy, South-West University “Neofit Rilski”.