0% found this document useful (0 votes)
35 views6 pages

Final Assignment

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1/ 6

NORTH SOUTH UNIVERSITY

Department of History and Philosophy

Assignment
Course Code: PHI 104
Section: 14

Name: Md. Ashik Mahmud


Student ID: 1811845043
Kantian Ethics

Immanuel Kant was a German philosopher and one of the central


Enlightenment thinkers. Kant's comprehensive and systematic
works in epistemology, metaphysics, ethics, and aesthetics have
made him one of the most influential figures in modern Western
philosophy.
Kant's theory is an example of a deontological moral theory–
according to these theories, the rightness or wrongness of actions
does not depend on their consequences but on whether they fulfill
our duty. Kant believed that there was a supreme principle of
morality, and he referred to it as The Categorical Imperative. Kant
believed that there was a supreme principle of morality, and he
referred to it as The Categorical Imperative. The Categorical
Imperative determines what our moral duties are. Kant believed that
there was a supreme principle of morality, and he referred to it as
The Categorical Imperative. The Categorical Imperative determines
what our moral duties are. Kant also has something to say about
what makes someone a good person. Keep in mind that Kant
intends this to go along with the rest of his theory, and what one's
duty is would be determined by the categorical imperative.
However, one can treat this as a separate theory to some extent, and
consider that one's duty is determined by some other standard.
Keep in mind that what is said below has to do with how one
evaluates people, not actions. A person's actions are right or wrong,
a person is morally worthy or lacks moral worth. A person's actions
determine her moral worth, but there is more to this than merely
seeing if the actions are right or wrong.
Kant’s most influential positions in moral philosophy are found in
The Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (hereafter,
“Groundwork”) but he developed, enriched, and in some cases
modified those views in later works such as The Critique of Practical
Reason, The Metaphysics of Morals, Anthropology from a
Pragmatic Point of View, Religion within the Boundaries of Mere
Reason as well as his essays on history and related topics. Kant’s
Lectures on Ethics, which were lecture notes taken by three of his
students on the courses he gave in moral philosophy, also include
relevant material for understanding his views. We will mainly focus
on the foundational doctrines of the Groundwork, even though in
recent years some scholars have become dissatisfied with this
standard approach to Kant’s views and have turned their attention
to the later works. We find the standard approach most illuminating,
though we will highlight important positions from the later works
where needed.

1. Aims and Methods of Moral Philosophy


2. Good Will, Moral Worth and Duty
3. Duty and Respect for Moral Law
4. Categorical and Hypothetical Imperatives
5. The Formula of the Universal Law of Nature
6. The Humanity Formula
7. The Autonomy Formula
8. The Kingdom of Ends Formula
9. The Unity of the Formulas
10. Autonomy
11. Virtue and Vice
12. Normative Ethical Theory
13. Teleology or Deontology?
14. Metaethics
The most basic aim of moral philosophy, and so also of the
Groundwork, is, in Kant’s view, to “seek out” the foundational
principle of a “metaphysics of morals,” which Kant understands as
a system of a priori moral principles that apply the CI to human
persons in all times and cultures. Kant pursues this project through
the first two chapters of the Groundwork. Kant’s analysis of
commonsense ideas begins with the thought that the only thing
good without qualification is a “goodwill”. While the phrases “he’s
good hearted”, “she’s good-natured” and “she means well” are
common, “the goodwill” as Kant thinks of it is not the same as any
of these ordinary notions.
According to Kant, what is singular about motivation by duty is that
it consists of bare respect for the moral law. Kant holds that the
fundamental principle of our moral duties is a categorical
imperative. It is imperative because it is a command addressed to
agents who could follow it but might not. Kant’s example of a
perfect duty to others concerns a promise you might consider
making but have no intention of keeping in order to get the needed
money. Naturally, being rational requires not contradicting oneself,
but there is no self-contradiction in the maxim “I will make lying
promises when it achieves something I want.” An immoral action
clearly does not involve self-contradiction in this sense (as would
the maxim of finding a married bachelor). Kant’s position is that it
is irrational to perform an action if that action’s maxim contradicts
itself once made into a universal law of nature. The maxim of lying
whenever it gets you what you want generates a contradiction once
you try to combine it with the universalized version that all rational
agents must, by a law of nature, lie when doing so gets them what
they want.
The Categorical Imperative, in Kant’s view, is an objective,
unconditional and necessary principle of reason that applies to all
rational agents in all circumstances. Although Kant gives several
examples in the Groundwork that illustrate this principle, he goes
on to describe in later writings, especially in The Metaphysics of
Morals, a complicated normative ethical theory for interpreting and
applying the CI to human persons in the natural world. His
framework includes various levels, distinctions and application
procedures.
The received view is that Kant’s moral philosophy is a deontological
normative theory at least to this extent: it denies that right and
wrong are in some way or other functions of goodness or badness.
It denies, in other words, the central claim of teleological moral
views. For instance, act consequentialism is one sort of teleological
theory. It asserts that the right action is that action of all the
alternatives available to the agent that has the best overall outcome.
Here, the goodness of the outcome determines the rightness of an
action.
Metaethics has seemed to a number of Kant’s interpreters that it is
important to determine whether Kant’s moral philosophy was
realist, anti-realist, or something else. This issue is tricky because the
terms “realism,” “anti-realism” and “constructivism” are terms of
art. One might have thought that this question is quite easy to settle.
At the basis of morality, Kant argued, is the Categorical Imperative,
and imperatives are not truth apt. It makes little sense to ask whether
“Leave the gun, take the cannoli.” is true. But, in fact, the question
is not at all easy.
Metaethics has seemed to a number of Kant’s interpreters that it is
important to determine whether Kant’s moral philosophy was
realist, anti-realist, or something else. This issue is tricky because the
terms “realism,” “anti-realism” and “constructivism” are terms of
art. One might have thought that this question is quite easy to settle.
At the basis of morality, Kant argued, is the Categorical Imperative,
and imperatives are not truth apt. It makes little sense to ask whether
“Leave the gun, take the cannoli.” is true. But, in fact, the question
is not at all easy.
According to Kant a good person is someone who always does their
duty because it is their duty. It is fine if they enjoy doing it, but it
must be the case that they would do it even if they did not enjoy it.
The overall theme is that to be a good person you must be good for
goodness sake.

You might also like