Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, and The Reformulation of Social Theory
Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, and The Reformulation of Social Theory
Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, and The Reformulation of Social Theory
0021–8308
No one knows who will live in this cage in the future, or whether at the end of this
tremendous development entirely new prophets will arise, or there will be a great rebirth of
old ideas and ideals. . . . The next task would be . . . to show the significance of ascetic
rationalism . . . for the content of practical social ethics, thus for the types of organization and
the functions of social groups from the conventicle to the State.
Max Weber,
The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism2
The first thing which needs to be said about The History of Sexuality is that it is
neither about history nor sexuality. Foucault never evidences an interest in
history, except in so far as it could be used to clarify the nature of the present,
or problematize certain current ideas or practices. 3 In The History of Sexuality
Foucault is interested in techniques of the self, techniques by which individuals
form themselves and relate to themselves as subjects of certain practices,
discourses, and rationalities, which in The History of Sexuality just happen to
concern sexuality (Foucault, 1983b, p. 229).
If the object of The History of Sexuality is not really sexuality at all, but the
manner in which human beings constitute themselves and relate to themselves
as subjects, about the social constitution of ‘self’ and ‘subjectivity’, and the
socially constituted practices by which individuals come to govern themselves
as ‘selves’ and ‘subjects’, why does Foucault choose to deal almost
exhaustively with sexuality? Why is it that ‘‘the project of a science of the
subject has gravitated, in ever narrowing circles, around the question of sex[?]’’
(Foucault, 1978, p. 70).
As Deleuze argues, Foucault is following his familiar strategy of identifying
the specific means by which the constitution of an object of power/knowledge
© The Executive Management Committee/Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 1999. Published by Blackwell Publishers 108 Cowley
Road, Oxford, OX4 1JF UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.
204 T. J.
Berard
is carried out. The constitution of subjectivity, Foucault suggests, is largely
carried out through a rationality organized around the themes of sex and desire;
‘‘it is in sexuality that [the relation to oneself] is established or carried out’’
(Deleuze, 1986, p. 102). As Foucault states, we have been led ‘‘to direct the
question of what we are, to sex’’, and this discourse of sexuality has brought us
‘‘almost entirely—our bodies, our minds, our individuality, our history—under
the sway of a logic of concupiscence and desire. Whenever it is a question of
knowing who we are, it is this logic that henceforth serves as our master key’’
(1978, p. 78).
But Foucault also offers us a much more substantial illustration of the
centrality of sexuality for larger questions of knowledge, power, and
subjectivity:
[Sex] was at the pivot of the two axes along which developed the entire political
technology of life. On the one hand it was tied to the disciplines of the body: the
harnessing, intensification, and distribution of forces, the adjustment and economy of
energies. On the other hand, it was applied to the regulation of populations. It
fitted in both categories at once, giving rise to infinitesimal surveillances, permanent
controls, extremely meticulous orderings of space, indeterminate medical or psycho-
logical examinations, to an entire micro-power concerned with the body. But it gave
rise as well to comprehensive measures, statistical assessments, and interventions
aimed at the entire social body or at groups taken as a whole. Sex was a means of
access both to the life of the body and the life of the species. It was employed as a
standard for the disciplines and as a basis for regulations. This is why in the nineteenth
century sexuality was sought out in the smallest details of individual existences; it was
tracked down in behavior, pursued in dreams; it was suspected of underlying the least
follies, it was traced back into the earliest years of childhood; it became the stamp of
individuality – at the same time what enabled one to analyze the latter and what made
it possible to master it. But one also sees it becoming the theme of political operations,
economic interventions (through incitements to or curbs on procreation), and
ideological campaigns for raising standards of morality and responsibility: it was put
forward as the index of a society’s strength, revealing both its political energy and its
biological vigor. Spread out from one pole to the other of this technology of sex was a
whole series of different tactics that combined in varying proportions the objective of
disciplining the body and that of regulating populations (Foucault, 1978, p. 146).4
There was the problematization of madness and illness arising out of social and
medical practices, and defining a certain pattern of ‘normalization’; a problematization
of life, language, and labor in discursive practices that conformed to certain
‘epistemic’ rules; and a problematizatin of crime and criminal behavior emerging from
certain punitive practices conforming to a ‘disciplinary’ model. And now I would like
to show how, in classical antiquity, sexual activity and sexual pleasures were
problematized through practices of the self, bringing into play the criteria of
‘aesthetics of existence’ (1985, pp. 10–12; cf. 1988c, p. 257).
At another time, Foucault claims that what interests him is, ‘‘. . . precisely
the forms of rationality applied by the human subject to itself . . . how is
it that the human subject took itself as the object of possible knowledge?
Through what forms of rationality and historical conditions? And finally at
what price? This is my question: at what price can subjects speak the truth
about themselves?’’ (1988b, pp. 29–30). Foucault relates this rationalization
of subjectivity to the manner in which relations of power are rationalized
(cf. Foucault, 1988a, p. 84). The ability to speak the truth about one’s
subjectivity thus exacts the high price of subjecting oneself to rationalized
relations of power. Foucault shows us, in effect, ‘‘how self-control is integrated
into the practice of controlling others’’, (Foucault, 1988c, p. 258), bringing
us full circle through Foucault’s works to an obviously Weberian theme.5
One could make a similar case for conceiving ‘the will to knowledge’ as
a recurring theme, one which acknowledges the Nietzschean influence. 6 In
this light, Foucault’s works can be seen as describing the strategies of power
which are immanent in various manifestations or applications of the will to
knowledge, and The History of Sexuality can be seen as attempting the ‘political
economy’ of a will to knowledge about sexuality (see, e.g., Foucault, 1978,
p. 73).
In 1983, Foucault places his works in the context of a continued interest
in a genealogy of ourselves in relation to (1) ‘‘truth through which we
constitute ourselves as subjects of knowledge’’, (2) ‘‘a field of power through
which we constitute ourselves as subjects acting on others’’, and (3) ‘‘ethics
through which we constitute ourselves as moral agents’’ (1983b, p. 237).
In 1984 (the year of his death), he suggests that he has continually ‘‘tried
to locate three major types of problems: the problem of truth, the problem
of power, and the problem of individual conduct’’ (Foucault, 1988a, p. 243).
In another 1984 interview, Foucault emphasizes the theme of subjectivity
and truth, how the subject enters into games of truth (Foucault, 1987, p. 1).
The interest in practices of the self then can be seen as a third way of
facing the problem of the relationship between the subject and games of
truth (Foucault, 1985, p. 2). At other times the theme is simply power, but
power intimately related to knowledge and subjectivity, especially modern
power, or what Halperin has called liberal power (1995, pp. 18–19).
What is worth noticing is that there exists a marked continuity between
all these different statements of continuity; whether Foucault is speaking of a
history of the subject, a history or political economy of the will to truth, a
history of truth, a history of problematizations, the rationalization of power
relations, a re-elaboration of the theory of power, the genealogy of the
present, the genealogy of ethics, or a dozen other projects, he is still referring
to one and the same body of work, one might even call it a research
programme, to which The History of Sexuality clearly belongs, and of which
The History of Sexuality was Foucault’s last contribution.
THE HISTORY OF SEXUALITY AS A BREAK WITH EARLIER WORKS
Foucault has received an enormous amount of critical attention, but the most
prominent and influential of it misses the significance of his final works, the
second and third volumes of The History of Sexuality, and the articles and
interviews concerning this project. Not only does Foucault deserve to be
remembered for his thought at its latest stage of development, but many readers
deserve a more adequate statement of Foucault’s contributions to social theory.
What follows will be structured as a series of responses to some of the most
frequent and famous criticisms of Foucault’s studies, methods, and politics. A
discussion of more worthy but less influential criticisms is beyond the scope of
this project, which aspires merely to defend the sensibility of doing and reading
such work.
In the process of addressing criticisms, I will attempt to delineate an implicit
social theory in Foucault’s works. The task of delineating an implicit social
theory is no less possible, and no less desirable, for all of Foucault’s persistence
in refusing to outline a social theory and refusing to prescribe methods. His
protestations do speak for his intellectual integrity, but they also obscure the
coherence of his works (which has been challenged by, e.g., Taylor [1986, p. 83]
and Jameson [1998, p. 106]) and obscure his reasons for breaking with
established traditions in philosophy and social theory.
What happens is that the more powerful the vision of some increasingly total system
or logic—the Foucault of the prisons book is the most obvious example—the more
powerless the reader comes to feel. Insofar as the theorist wins, therefore, by
constructing an increasingly closed and terrifying machine, to that very degree he
loses, since the critical capacity of his work is thereby paralyzed, and the impulses of
negation and revolt, not to speak of those of social transformation, are increasingly
perceived as vain and trivial. . . (Quoted in Hoy, 1986b, p. 11).
Such criticisms are common, and famous, but miss the mark, and at best
fault Foucault for the way he has been received by some academics, these being
either the critics themselves, or unspecified, perhaps even hypothetical victims
of theoretically induced political paralysis. The failure of these criticisms is
suggested not only by the substance of Foucault’s writings and interviews, but
more importantly, by the fact that his ideas not only allowed for his own
activism and that of others who draw on his work, but demonstrably provide
resources and inspiration for such activism.
Politically, Foucault’s insights did not prevent him from being an activist for,
e.g., mental patients, prisoners, and homosexuals, nor have all social critics and
activists rejected his theories (cf. Halperin, 1995, p. 23). But Foucault’s works
must be seen, not only as compatible with activism, but more positively as
having contributed to significant movements in social criticism, and by
extension political activism, including his own, but also Said’s critique of
orientalism (1978), a variety of intelligent critiques of modern institutions and
discourses (e.g. Caputo & Yount, 1993), including ground-level, practical
critiques of penal and psychiatric institutions, and many works in feminist and
queer theory, including Butler’s (1990; 1993), but also those of, e.g., Aladjem,
Bordo, Flax, Grimshaw, Halperin, Hekman, Jagose, Lloyd, Probyn, Sawicki,
and Soper.
Theoretically, neither Foucault’s theory of power nor his theory of
subjectivity allow for the charges of neo-conservatism and fatalism.
Foucault’s theory of power explicitly rejects the position that ‘you are
always- already trapped’’ (Foucault, 1978, p. 83; cf. 1997, p. 157). Power,
according to Foucault, is never a monolithic entity, wielded by one individual or
group against another. Power, understood as inherently relational, presupposes
‘at least a certain form of liberty’ and the possibility of resistance (see, e.g.,
Foucault, 1978, p. 95; 1987, pp. 11–13). For a power relationship to obtain,
according to Foucault, the victim must be recognized as a person who acts, and
the exercise of power is therefore viewed as ‘‘a total structure of actions
brought to bear upon possible actions . . . always a way of acting upon an
acting subject or acting subjects by
virtue of their acting or being capable of action’’ (Foucault, 1983a, p. 220).
Elsewhere he argues, ‘‘Power is exercised only over free subjects, and only
insofar as they are free’’ (1983a, p. 221). The victim of power, as an actual or
potential actor, always retains the possibility of acting in a manner which resists
the power which victimizes him. Power is therefore understood as a
‘multiplicity of force relations’, which allows for resistance and the occasional
reversal of force relations, both logically, due to its relational nature, and
structurally, in the form of disjunctions and contradictions which provide
spaces or footholds for resistance (see, esp. Foucault, 1978, pp. 92–93). It
follows that, even though ‘‘one can never be ‘outside’ power’’ (1980a, p. 141),
‘‘[this] is not to say either that those [power relations] which are established are
necessary, or, in any case, that power constitutes a fatality at the heart of
societies, such that it cannot be undermined’’ (Foucault, 1983b, pp. 222–223;
cf. 1981, p. 8). Indeed, if power is everywhere, by Foucault’s thinking this
means that the possibility of resistance is everywhere, too (see esp. Foucault,
1978, p. 96).
Foucault’s theory of subjectivity, similarly, does not lend itself to
conservatism or fatalism, when properly understood. According to Foucault, the
subject (or individual, or agent) cannot simply be counterpoised to power.
Subjectivity is no longer thought of as if it might suffer from false
consciousness as if from an operable tumor, or as if society were present as an
occupying force in the commonwealth of the psyche, as with the super-ego.
Subjectivity is seen instead as constituted by social practices, rationalities,
discourses etc., which are positive as well as negative, productive as well as
repressive. Foucault is therefore arguing neither that subjectivity has been
colonized by power, nor that it has been placed on a short leash, both of which
remain caught within a ‘metaphysics of external relations’ (Butler, 1993, p. 34),
but rather that power is a constituent element of subjectivity, that subjectivity
and power cannot be understood as antagonistic forces at all (cf. Butler, 1993,
p. 15; Halperin, 1995, pp. 18–19).
It is true that Foucault forwards a powerful challenge to any belief in the
autonomous individual or the free agent, conceived of as independent from
‘ideology’ and power relations. But he has not denied a degree of voluntarism
or agency (see, esp., Foucault, 1997, pp. 32, 61). As Butler observes, subjects
who are socially constructed are not thereby determined (1990, p. 143; 195a,
p. 46). Rather, Foucault’s analysis centers on what might be called a political
will (see, esp., Foucault, 1997, pp. 32, 61), capable of critically reassessing the
self’s mode of constituting itself as a subject, as subject to subjectivity (cf.
Foucault, 1983b, p. 252). This is not fatalism, but a rejection of the episteme in
which the fate of the subject vis-a`-vis power is an intelligible question (cf. Butler,
1995a, p. 46).
But Foucault’s theories of power and subjectivity are not even political
theories, so much as empirical theories with consequential political
implications. The prominent critics tend to either miss Foucault’s
reconceptualizataion of the relations between subjectivity and power, or fault it
for its political implications.
But they therefore avoid the empirical claim which is the most original and most
provocative thesis of The History of Sexuality. This thesis suggests that the way
we experience and relate to ourselves as subjects, e.g. through the deployment
of sexuality, is the most insidious and entrenched strategy of subjugation in
the modern state, which subjugates us all the more if we rely upon our
subjectivities or sexualities as the foundation of resistance or liberation (cf.
1977a, pp. 102–103). In judging such a claim, critics have routinely neglected a
fundamental consideration; the truth value of empirical claims cannot be deduced
from political commitments, either foundational or strategic. The objection that
the individual is logically distinct from, and can be liberated from, ‘ideology’
and power, for example, is not so much an engagement with Foucault’s claims
as a vehement reiteration of the very presuppositions which Foucault rejects as
both
mistaken and self-defeating (cf. Touey, 1998, p. 96).
But on a more substantive note, the implication of Foucault’s claim is not
that resistance is futile, or that no freedoms can be gained. The implication is
that, in the development of critical instruments, one should be ‘‘suspicious of
one’s own inscription within the power/knowledge apparatus’’ and be aware of
the limitations of one’s critical instruments (Bove´, 1986, pp. xxvii-xviii; cf.
Bordo, 1993, p. 167; 1989, p. 15; Butler, 1995a).
That such reflexive, critical attention to strategies of resistance need not lead
to fatalism or conservatism is perhaps best illustrated by recent feminist
appropriations of Foucault. Most commonly, feminists appreciate Foucault for
providing critical methods which denaturalize and de-reify subjugating
institutions and modes of thought (Probyn, 1993) and disrupt and erode
discourses that legitimate patterns of liberal domination (Flax, 1990a, p. 39).
Somewhat more positively, feminists have used Foucault’s insights to expose
and reject presuppositions about the body and subjectivity which undermine or
betray feminist goals (Bordo, 1989; Butler, 1990, p. 93; 1995a, pp. 48, 54), and
also to expose and reject authoritative or representational claims which
marginalize, exclude or suppress others (Flax, 1990b, pp. 48–49; 1990a, p. 183;
Butler, 1995a,
p. 50; 1990, p. 4). Most positively, Butler’s Foucauldian reconceptualization of
identity as socially produced ‘‘opens up possibilities of ‘agency’ that are
insidiously foreclosed by [foundational] positions’’ (1990, p. 147; cf. 1995a, p.
50).
But Foucault’s theory does more than argue for the logical possibility of
resistance, and the obsolescence of any subject/power antagonism. Even though
Foucault was very guarded in forwarding positive suggestions, let alone an
agenda, there are several points at which Foucault identifies what might be
fruitful directions for liberatory struggles. One passage from the first volume of
The History of Sexuality which clearly suggests a basis and direction for
liberatory struggles is the following:
It is the agency of sex that we must break away from, if we aim—through a tactical
reversal of the various mechanisms of sexuality—to counter the grips of power with
the claims of bodies, pleasures, and knowledges, in their multiplicity and their
possibility of resistance. The rallying point for the counterattack against the
deployment of sexuality ought not to be sex-desire, but bodies and pleasures
(Foucault, 1978, p. 157).
This reliance on bodies and pleasures can best be understood, I think, as trying
to establish a basis for resistance which is universal and pre-discursive and
therefore doubly innocent. Admittedly, this is not a well-developed strategy for
resistance or liberation, and it is not much of a political platform; it refuses to
put faith in a singular source of resistance or a singular counter-knowledge, and
it seems to reject discursively constituted phenomena (e.g. sex, desire) as an
adequate basis for resistance, in favor of bodies and pleasures, which are not
only individual but which are given to the individual (logically and historically)
prior to subjectivity.7
But there are also more positive, perhaps more viable, suggestions for
liberatory movements, which are forwarded after the first volume. These
involve not the rejection of subjectivity in favor of bodies and pleasures, nor the
rejection of subjectivity in favor of a willed ignorance (de-problematization) of
the self, but the creation or fostering of new forms of subjectivity (see, e.g.,
Foucault, 1983a.
p. 216; Halperin, 1995. pp. 67–73, 109–112), especially through the
development of a new ethics (Foucault, 1983b, p. 231; cf. Dreyfus and
Rabinow, 1986, p. 121; Sawicki, 1996, pp. 174–175).
Despite Foucault’s vehement objections to some aspects of Greek ethics,
especially their presupposition and perpetuation of social inequalities, Foucault
took from Greek ethics, or ‘aesthetics of existence’, the idea that subjectivity
was not inherently subjugating. In volume II he writes, ‘‘in classical Greek
thought, the ‘ascetics’ that enabled one to make oneself into an ethical subject
was an integral part—down to its very form—of the practice of a virtuous life,
wich was also the life of a ‘free’ man in the full, positive and political sense of
the word’’ (1985, p. 77). In volume III he observes ‘‘the subject is constituted
through practices of subjection, or, in a more autonomous way, through
practices of liberation, of liberty, as in Antiquity’’ (1988a, p. 51). Elsewhere
Foucault speaks of the attractions and potential of a creative and aesthetically
based ethics, instead of an ethics based on codes and prohibitions (Christian or
juridico-discursive ethics) or upon the notion of a true self (Sartrean
authenticity) (Foucault, 1983b, pp. 236–237, 231; 1991a, p. 49; Kritzman, 1988,
pp. xxiv-xxv; cf. Berard, 1999; Bernauer & Mahon, 1994, p. 155). Such forms
of subjectivity would still be socially constituted, of course (Foucault, 1988a, p.
51), but they would be less subjugating and more autonomous (Foucault, 1987;
1988a, p. 51; cf. Deleuze, 1986, p. 101).
Even if such suggestions do not form an agenda, and even if they are rather
abstract, it should be clear that Foucault did not advocate fatalistic or
conservative theories of the subject and power, but was interested in replacing
the conventional modes of resistance by more viable ones (see, e.g., Foucault,
1991a, p. 173), with the
clear goal of fostering some form of freedom (cf. Flax, 1990a, p. 209; Sawicki,
1996, pp. 170, 174).
The fact that Foucault and many others have found his theories to be
compatible with, useful for, or inspiring of political activism should tell us that
paralysis or fatalism is only one possible response to Foucault’s writing. The
question now becomes: what accounts for the difference in reception? Foucault
suggests that the suspicion of fatalism follows from the very presuppositions
about power which he calls into question (Foucault, 1983a, pp. 216–217). It is
also worth pointing out that Foucault wrote primarily for people, like himself,
who did not feel free, with the aim of showing people that ‘‘they are freer than
they feel’’ (Martin, Gutman & Hutton, 1988, pp. 10–11). Perhaps those critics
who only feel trapped after reading Foucault might profit from a second
reading, now that they have fallen into the intended audience.
Whatever the case, there is a sharp distinction to be drawn between a neo-
conservative or fatalist and an author who, through misunderstanding or
divergent interpretations, has a neo-conservative effect on a subset of his
readers, especially if this subset turns out to be a rhetorical artifice.
NOTES
1
The History of Sexuality comprises three volumes: The History of Sexuality, The Use
of Pleasure, and The Care of the Self, in that order. To avoid confusion, ‘The History of
Sexuality’ will refer to the three-volume series, not the first volume.
2
Weber (1958, pp. 182–183). Cf. Foucault (1997, p. 43).
3
See, e.g., Foucault (1977a, p. 31). More accurately, Foucault was interested in
archaeology and genealogy, both distinct from intellectual history. Briefly, and roughly,
archaeology studies the implicit, underlying rules, shared by disparate bodies of
knowledge in a certain historical period, which inform the definition of the objects of
study, the formation of concepts and the manner of theory-building, and not what was
said, who said what, and in what order. See, e.g., Foucault (1970, p. xi; 1988b, p. 31).
Genealogy can be likened to a historical knowledge of struggles which is tactically
useful for contemporary struggles. See Foucault (1980b, p. 83).
4
Cf. the discussion of docile bodies in Foucault (1977a, pp. 136–139).
5
There is much to be gained by the comparison of Foucault’s studies to Weber’s
Protestant Ethic: both studied the secularization of ascetic practices and the increasing
rationalization of modern life, and both were critical of the fact that what at first were
the elective virtues and spiritually meaningful practices of an elite became inescapable
and onerous burdens for everyone.
6
See, esp., Foucault (1988b, pp. 31–33, 8). The History of Sexuality can be seen as an
elaboration and substantiation of Nietzsche’s theory of ‘pastoral power’ (1967).
7
Butler, in an intelligent treatment of supposedly prediscursive phenomena, rejects
even this slender and elusive grounding as romanticism and sentimental indulgence, and
yet still demonstrates that Foucault is an invaluable resource for feminist/queer critiques
(1990, pp. 96–98; 1993; cf. Foucault, 1980c).
8
Here Foucault means by ‘game’, ‘an ensemble of rules for the production of truth’.
REFERENCES
ALADJEM, T.K. (1996). The Philosopher’s Prism: Foucault, Feminism, and Critique. In
S. Hekman (ed.), Feminist Interpretations of Michel Foucault. University Park, PA:
Pennsylvania State University Press, pp. 283–298.
BENHABIBS., BUTLER, J., CORNELL, D. & FRASER, N. (1995). Feminist Contentions: A
Philosophical Exchange. New York: Routledge.
BERARD, T.J. (1999). Dada Between Nietzsche’s Birth of Tragedy and Bourdieu’s Distinction:
Existenz and Conflict in Cultural Analysis. Theory, Culture and Society, 16, 141–165.
BERNAUER, J.W. & MAHON, M. (eds.) (1994). The ethics of Michel Foucault. In G. Gutting
(ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Foucault. New York: Cambridge University
Press, pp. 141–158.
BERNAUER, J. & RASMUSSEN, D. (eds.) (1987). The Final Foucault. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
BORDO, S. (1993). Unbearable Weight: Feminism, Western Culture, and the Body. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
BORDO, S. (1990). Feminism, Postmodernism, and Gender-Scepticism. In L.J. Nicholson
(ed.), Feminism/Postmodernism. New York: Routledge, pp. 133–156.
BORDO, S. (1989). The Body and the Reproduction of Feminity: A Feminist Appropriation
of Foucault. In A.M. Jaggar & S.R. Bordo (eds.), Gender/Body/Knowledge: Feminist
Reconstructions of Being and Knowing. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press,
pp. 13–31.
BOURDIEU, P. (1984). Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste. Translator
R. Nice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
BOVE´ , P. (1986). The Foucault Phenomenon: the Problematics of Style. In G. Deleuze,
Foucault. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. vii–xl.
BURCHELL, G., GORDON, C. & MILLER, P. (eds) (1991). The Foucault Effect: Studies in
Governmentality. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
BUTLER, J. (1990). Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. New York: Routledge.
BUTLER, J. (1993). Bodies That Matter: On the Discursive Limits of ‘Sex’. New York:
Routledge. BUTLER, J. (1995a). Contingent Foundations. In S. Benhabib, J. Butler, D.
Cornell & N.
Fraser, Feminist Contentions: A Philosophical Exchange. New York: Routledge, pp. 35–57.
BUTLER, J. (1995b). For A Careful Reading. In S. Benhabib, J. Butler, D. Cornell & N.
Fraser, Feminist Contentions: A Philosophical Exchange. New York: Routledge, pp. 127–
143. CAPUTO, J. & YOUNT, M. (eds.) (1993). Foucault and the Critique of Institutions.
University
Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.
DELEUZE, G. (1986). Foucault. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
DAVIDSON, A.I. (1994). Ethics as ascetics: Foucault, the history of ethics, and ancient
thought. In G. Gutting (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Foucault. New York:
Cambridge University Press, pp. 115–140.
DAVIDSON, A.I. (1986). Archaeology, Genealogy, Ethics. In D. Hoy (ed.), Foucault: A
Critical Reader. Basil Blackwell, pp. 221–233.
DREYFUS, H. & RABINOW, P. (1986). What is Maturity?: Habermas and Foucault on ‘What
is Enlightenment?’ in D. Hoy (ed.), Foucault: A Critical Reader, Cambridge, MA:
Blackwell, pp. 109–121.
DREYFUS, H. & RABINOW, P. (1983). Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics,
2nd Ed. University of Chicago Press.
FLAX, J. (1990a) Thinking Fragments: Psychoanalysis, Feminism, and Postmodernism in the
Contemporary West. Berkeley: University of California Press.
FLAX, J. (1990b). Postmodernism and Gender Relations in Feminist Theory. In L.J.
Nicholson (ed.), Feminism/Postmodernism. New York: Routledge, pp. 39–62.
FOUCAULT, M. (1965). Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason.
Translator R. Howard. New York: Vintage Books.
FOUCAULT, M. (1970). The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences. New
York: Vintage Books.
FOUCAULT, M. (1972). The Archaeology of Knowledge and the Discourse on Language.
Translator
A. Smith. New York: Pantheon Books.
FOUCAULT, M. (1977a). Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. Translator A.
Sheridan.
New York: Vintage Books.
FOUCAULT, M. (1977b). language, counter-memory, practice: selected essays and interviews by
Michel Foucault. Editor D. Bouchard. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
FOUCAULT, M. (1977c). Intellectuals and Power. In D. Bouchard (ed.), language, counter-
memory, practice: selected essays and interviews by Michel Foucault. Ithaca, N.Y.:
Cornell University Press, pp. 205–217.
FOUCAULT, M. (1977d). Revolutionary Action: ‘Until Now’. In D. Bouchard (ed.),
language, counter-memory, practice: selected essays and interviews by Michel Foucault. Ithaca,
N.Y.: Cornell University Press, pp. 218–233.
FOUCAULT, M. (1978). The History of Sexuality: Volume I: An Introduction. Translator R.
Hurley. New York: Vintage Books.
FOUCAULT, M. (1980a). Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972–1977.
Editor C. Gordon. New York: Pantheon Books.
FOUCAULT, M. (1980b). Two Lectures. In M. Foucault, Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews
and Other Writings, 1972–1977. Editor C. Gordon. New York: Pantheon Books, pp.
78–108.
FOUCAULT, M. (1980c). Introduction. In M. Foucault (ed.), Herculine Barbin: Being the
Recently Discovered Memoirs of a Nineteenth-Century French Hermaphrodite. New York: Pantheon
Books, pp. vii–xvii.
FOUCAULT, M. (1981). Spring. is it useless to revolt? Philosophy and Social Criticism, 8,
2–9. FOUCAULT, M. (1982). Spring. is it really important to think? Philosophy and Social
Criticism,
9, 30–40.
FOUCAULT, M. (1983a). Afterward: The Subject and Power. In H. Dreyfus and P. Rabinow
(eds.), Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, 2nd Ed. University of
Chicago Press, pp. 208–226.
FOUCAULT, M. (1983b). On the Genealogy of Ethics: An Overview of Work in Progress. In
H. Dreyfus and P. Rabinow (eds.), Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics,
2nd Ed. University of Chicago Press, pp. 229–252.
FOUCAULT, M. (1984a). The Foucault Reader. Editor P. Rabinow. New York: Pantheon
Books. FOUCAULT, M. (1984b). Nietzsche, Genealogy, History. In M. Foucault, The
Foucault
Reader. Editor P. Rabinow. New York: Pantheon Books, pp. 76–100.
FOUCAULT, M. (1985). The Use of Pleasure, Vol. II of The History of Sexuality. Translator
R. Hurley. New York: Vintage Books.
FOUCAULT, M. (1986). The Care of the Self, Vol. III of The History of Sexuality. Translator
R. Hurley. New York: Vintage Books.
FOUCAULT, M. (1987). the ethic of care for the self as a practice of freedom. In J. Bernauer
& D. Rasmussen (eds.), The Final Foucault. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 1–20.
FOUCAULT, M. (1988a). Politics, philosophy, culture: interviews and other writings of Michel
Foucault, 1977–1984. Editor L. Kritzman. New York: Routledge.
FOUCAULT, M. (1988b). Critical Theory/Intellectual History. In M. Foucault, Politics,
philosophy, culture: interviews and other writings of Michel Foucault, 1977–1984. Editor
L. Kritzman. New York: Routledge, pp. 17–46.
FOUCAULT, M. (1988c). The Concern for Truth. In M. Foucault, Politics, philosophy,
culture: interviews and other writings of Michel Foucault, 1977–1984. Editor L.
Kritzman. New York: Routledge, pp. 255–267.
FOUCAULT, M. (1988d). Technologies of the Self. In L.H. Martin, H. Gutman & P.H.
Hutton (eds.), Technologies of the Self: A Seminar with Michel Foucault. Amherst,
MA. University of Massachusetts Press, pp. 16–49.
FOUCAULT, M. (1988e). The Political Technology of Individuals. In L.H. Martin,
H. Gutman & P.H. Hutton (eds.), Technologies of the Self: A Seminar with Michel
Foucault. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press, pp. 145–162.
FOUCAULT, M. (1991a). Remarks on Marx: Conversations with Duccio Trombadori. Translator
R. Goldstein & J. Cascaito. Semiotext(e).
FOUCAULT, M. (1991b). Questions of method. In G. Burchell, C. Gordon & P. Miller (eds.),
The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality. University of Chicago Press, pp. 73–86.
FOUCAULT, M. (1997). The Politics of Truth. Editors S. Lotringer and L. Hochroth. New
York: Semiotext(e).
FRASER, N. (1995). Pragmatism, Feminism, and the Linguistic Turn. In S. Benhabib,
J. Butler, D. Cornell & N. Fraser, Feminist Contentions: A Philosophical Exchange. New
York: Routledge, pp. 157–171.
GIDDENS, A. (1987). Structuralism, Post-structuralism and the Production of Culture. In
A. Giddens & J. Turner (eds.), Social Theory Today. Stanford: Stanford University
Press, pp. 195–223.
GIDDENS, A. (1983). From Marx to Nietzsche?: Neo-Conservatism, Foucault, and
Problems in Contemporary Political Theory. In A. Giddens, Profiles and Critiques in
Social Theory. Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 215–230.
GRIMSHAW, J. (1993). Practices of Freedom. In C. Ramazanoglu (ed.), Up Against
Foucault: Explorations of some Tensions Between Foucault and Feminism. New York:
Routledge, pp. 51–72.
GROSZ, E. (1994). Volatile Bodies: Toward a Corporeal Feminism. Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University Press.
GUTTING, G. (ed.) (1994). The Cambridge Companion to Foucault. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
HABERMAS, J. (1983). Modernity—An Incomplete Project. In H. Foster (ed.) The Anti-
Aesthetic: Essays on Postmodern Culture. Port Townsend, WA: Bay Press, pp. 3–15.
HABERMAS, J. (1986). Taking Aim at the Heart of the Present. In D. Hoy (ed.), Foucault: A
Critical Reader. Basil Blackwell.
HALPERIN, D. (1995). Saint Foucault: Towards a Gay Hagiography. New York: Oxford
University Press.
HARTSOCK, N. (1996). Postmodernism and Political Change: Issues for Feminist Theory. In
S.J. Hekman (ed.), Feminist Interpretations of Michel Foucault. University Park, PA: The
Pennsylvania State University Press, pp. 39–55.
HARTSOCK, N. (1990). Foucault on Power: A Theory for Women? In L.J. Nicholson (ed.),
Feminism/Postmodernism. New York: Routledge, pp. 157–175.
HEKMAN, S., (ed.) (1996). Feminist Interpreteations of Michel Foucault. University Park, PA:
Pennsylvania State University Press.
HOY, D. (ed.) (1986a). Foucault: A Critical Reader. Basil Blackwell.
HOY, D. (1986b). Introduction. In D. Hoy (ed.), Foucault: A Critical Reader. Basil
Blackwell, pp. 1–25.
HOY, D. (1986c). Power, Repression, Progress: Foucault, Lukes, and the Frankfurt School.
In D. Hoy (ed.), Foucault: A Critical Reader. Basil Blackwell, pp. 123–147.
HUTTON, P. (1988). Foucault, Freud, and the Technologies of the Self. In L.H. Martin,
H. Gutman & P.H. Hutton (eds.), Technologies of the Self: A Seminar with Michel
Foucault. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press, pp. 121–144.
JAGOSE, A. (1996). Queer Theory: An Introduction. New York: New York University Press.
JAMESON, F. (1998). The Cultural Turn: Selected Writings on the Postmodern, 1983–1998. New
York: Verso.
KRITZMAN, L. (1988). Foucault and the Politics of Experience. In M. Foucault, Politics,
Philosophy, Culture: Interviews and other Writings 1977–1984. Editor L. Kritzman. New
York: Routledge, pp. ix–xxv.
LLOYD, M. (1996). A Feminist Mapping of Foucauldian Politics. In S.J. Hekman (ed.),
Feminist Interpretations of Michel Foucault. University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State
University Press, pp. 241–264.
MARTIN, L.H., GUTMAN, H. & HUTTON, P.H. (eds.) (1988). Technologies of the Self: A
Seminar with Michel Foucault. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press.
MARTIN, R. (1988). Truth, Power, Self: An Interview with Michel Foucault. In L.H.
Martin, H. Gutman & P.H. Hutton (eds.), Technologies of the Self: A Seminar with
Michel Foucault. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press, pp. 9–15.
MAHON, M. (1992). Foucault’s Nietzschean Genealogy: Truth, Power, and the Subject. State
University of New York Press.
NICHOLSON, L.J. (ed.) (1990). Feminism/Postmodernism. New York: Routledge.
NIETZSCHE, F. (1967). On the Genealogy of Morals and Ecce Homo. Editor W. Kaufmann.
New York: Random House.
NIETZSCHE, F. (1983). Untimely Meditations. Translator R.J. Hollingdale. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
OWEN, D. (1994). Maturity and Modernity: Nietzsche, Weber, Foucault and the ambivalence of
reason. New York: Routledge.
PHILP, M. (1985). Michel Foucault. In Q. Skinner (ed.) The Return of Grand Theory in the
Human Sciences. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 65–81.
POSTER, M. (1986). Foucault and the Tyranny of Greece. In D. Hoy (ed.), Foucault: A
Critical Reader. Basil Blackwell, pp. 205–220.
PROBYN, E. (1993). Sexing the Self: Gendered Positions in Cultural Studies. New York:
Routledge. RABINOW, P. (ed.) (1984). The Foucault Reader. New York: Pantheon Books.
RACEVSKIS, K. (1987). michel foucault, rameau’s nephew, and the question of identity. In
J. Bernauer and D. Rasmussen (eds.), The Final Foucault, Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press, pp. 21–33.
RAMAZANOGLU, C. (ed.) (1993). Up Against Foucault: Explorations of some tensions
between Foucault and Feminism. New York: Routledge.
RORTY, R. (1998). Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought in Twentieth Century America.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
RORTY, R. (1989). Contingency, irony, and solidarity. New York: Cambridge University Press.
RORTY, R. (1986). Foucault and Epistemology. In D. Hoy (ed.), Foucault: A Critical
Reader.
Basil Blackwell, pp. 41–49.
SAID, E.W. (1978). Orientalism. New York: Random House.
SAWICKI, J. (1994). Foucault, feminism and questions of identity. In G. Gutting (ed.), The
Cambridge Companion to Foucault. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 286–313.
SAWICKI, J. (1996). Feminism, Foucault, and ‘Subjects’ of Power and Freedom. In S.
Hekman (ed.), Feminist Interpretations of Michel Foucault. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania
State University Press, pp. 159–178.
SMART, B. (1986). The Politics of Truth and the Problem of Hegemony. In D. Hoy (ed.),
Foucault: A Critical Reader. Basil Blackwell, pp. 157–173.
SOPER, K. (1993). Productive contradictions. In C. Ramazanoglu (ed.), Up Against
Foucault: Explorations of some Tensions Between Foucault and Feminism. New York:
Routledge, pp. 29–50.
TAYLOR, C. (1986). Foucault on Freedom and Truth. In D. Hoy (ed.), Foucault: A Critical
Reader. Basil Blackwell, pp. 69–102.
TOUEY, D. (1998). Foucault’s Apology. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 28, 83–
106. WALZER, M. (1986). The Politics of Michel Foucault. In D. Hoy (ed.), Foucault: A
Critical
Reader. Basil Blackwell, pp. 51–68.
WEBER, M. (1946a) Politics as a Vocation. In H.H. Gerth & C.W. Mills (eds), From Max
Weber: Essays in Sociology. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 77–128.
WEBER, M. (1946b). Science as a Vocation. In H.H. Gerth & C.W. Mills (eds), From Max
Weber: Essays in Sociology. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 129–156.
WEBER, M. (1949). The Methodology of the Social Sciences. Translators and Editors E.
Shils and H. Finch. Glencoe, Illinois: Free Press.
WEBER, M. (1958). The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Translator T. Parsons.
New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.
YEATMAN, A. (1990). A Feminist Theory of Social Differentiation. In L.J. Nicholson (ed.)
Feminism/Postmodernism. New York: Routledge, pp. 281–299.