Constructing Measures
Constructing Measures
Constructing measures
So far we have been taking measures for granted; except for a few, almost
trivial examples we have not shown that they exist. In this chapter we shall
develop a powerful technique for constructing measures with the properties
we want, e.g. the Lebesgue measures and the coin tossing measure described
in Section 5.1.
When we construct a measure, we usually start by knowing how we want
it to behave on a family of simple sets: For the Lebesgue measure on R, we
want the intervals (a, b) to have measure b − a, and for the coin tossing
measure we know what we want the measure of a cylinder set to be. The
art is to extend such “pre-measures” to full-blown measures.
We shall use a three step procedure to construct measures. We start
with a collection R of subsets of our space X and a function ρ : R → R+ .
The idea is that the sets R in R are the sets we “know” the size ρ(R) of – if,
e.g., we want to construct the Lebesgue measure, R could be the collection
of all open intervals, and ρ would then be given by ρ((a, b)) = b − a. From
R and ρ, we first construct an “outer measure” µ∗ which assigns a “size”
µ∗ (A) to all subsets A of X. The problem with µ∗ is that it usually fails to
be countably additive; i.e. the crucial equality
[ ∞
X
∗
µ ( An ) = µ∗ (An )
n∈N n=1
doesn’t hold for all disjoint sequences {An } of subsets of X. The second step
in our procedure is therefore to identify a σ-algebra A such that countable
additivity holds when the disjoint sets An belong to A. The restriction of µ∗
to A will then be our desired measure µ. The final step in the procedure is
to check that µ really is an extension of ρ, i.e. that R ⊂ A and µ(R) = ρ(R)
for all R ∈ R. This is not always the case, but requires special properties of
R and ρ.
We begin by constructing outer measures.
1
2 CHAPTER 6. CONSTRUCTING MEASURES
We are now ready to define the outer measure µ∗ generated by R and ρ: For
all B ⊂ X, we set
(i) µ∗ (∅) = 0.
(n)
S {Ck }k,n∈N of all sets in all the coverings is a countable
The collection
covering of ∞ n=1 Bn , and
∞ ∞ ∞ ∞
!
X (n)
X X (n)
X
∗ X ∗
ρ(Ck ) = ρ(Ck ) ≤ µ (Bn ) + n = µ (Bn ) +
2
k,n∈N n=1 k=1 n=1 n=1
(if you feel unsure about these manipulations, take a look at Exercise 5).
This means that
[ ∞
X
µ∗ ( Bn ) ≤ µ∗ (Bn ) +
n∈N n=1
Remark: Note that property (iii) in the proposition above also holds for
finite sums; i.e.
N
[ XN
µ∗ ( Bn ) ≤ µ∗ (Bn )
n=1 n=1
(to see this, just apply (iii) to the sequence B1 , B2 , . . . , BN , ∅, ∅, . . .). In par-
ticular, we always have µ∗ (A ∪ B) ≤ µ∗ (A) + µ∗ (B).
We have now completed the first part of our program: We have con-
structed the outer measure and described its fundamental properties. The
next step is to define the measurable sets, to prove that they form a σ-
algebra, and show that µ∗ is a measure when we restrict it to this σ-algebra.
4. Assume that R is a σ-algebra and that ρ is a measure on R. Let (X, R̄, µ̄)
be the completion of (X, R, µ). Show that µ∗ (A) = µ̄(A) for all A ∈ R̄.
5. Let {an,k }n,k∈N be a collection of nonnegative, real numbers, and let A be
the supremum over all finite sums of distinct elements in this collection, i.e.
I
X
A = sup{ ani ,ki : I ∈ N and all pairs (n1 , k1 ), . . . , (nI , kI ) are different}
i=1
µ∗ (A ∩ E) + µ∗ (A ∩ E c ) = µ∗ (A)
µ∗ (A ∩ E) + µ∗ (A ∩ E c ) ≤ µ∗ (A)
µ∗ (A ∩ E) + µ∗ (A ∩ E c ) = µ∗ (A ∩ E c ) ≤ µ∗ (A)
for all A ⊂ X. 2
Next we have:
(ii) If E ∈ M, then E c ∈ M.
(iii) If E1 , E2 , . . . , En ∈ M, then E1 ∪ E2 ∪ . . . ∪ En ∈ M.
(iv) If E1 , E2 , . . . , En ∈ M, then E1 ∩ E2 ∩ . . . ∩ En ∈ M.
Proof: We have already proved (i), and (ii) is obvious from the definition
of measurable sets. Since E1 ∪ E2 ∪ . . . ∪ En = (E1c ∩ E2c ∩ . . . ∩ Enc )c by
De Morgan’s laws, (iii) follows from (ii) and (iv). Hence it only remains to
prove (iv).
To prove (iv) is suffices to prove that if E1 , E2 ∈ M, then E1 ∩ E2 ∈ M
as we can then add more sets by induction. If we first use the measurability
of E1 , we see that for any set A ⊂ Rd
µ∗ (A) = µ∗ (A ∩ E1 ) + µ∗ (A ∩ E1c )
and hence
We would like to extend parts (iii) and (iv) in the proposition above to
countable unions and intersection. For this we need the following lemma:
µ∗ (A ∩ (E1 ∪ E2 ∪ . . . ∪ En )) = µ∗ (A ∩ E1 ) + µ∗ (A ∩ E2 ) + . . . + µ∗ (A ∩ En )
Proof: It suffices to prove the lemma for two sets E1 and E2 as we can then
extend it by induction. Using the measurability of E1 , we see that
= µ∗ (A ∩ E1 ) + µ∗ (A ∩ E2 )
2
En = An ∩ (E1 ∪ E2 ∪ . . . ∪ En−1 )c
for n > 1, and note that En ∈ M since M is an algebra. The sets {En } are
same union as {An } (make a drawing!), and hence it
disjoint and have the S
suffices to prove that n∈N En ∈ M, i.e.
∞ ∞
[ [ c
µ∗ (A) ≥ µ∗ A ∩ En + µ∗ A ∩
En
n=1 n=1
6.2. MEASURABLE SETS 7
SN
Since n=1 En ∈ M for all N ∈ N, we have:
N N
∗ ∗
[ ∗
[ c
µ (A) = µ A ∩ En + µ A ∩ En ≥
n=1 n=1
N ∞
X
∗ ∗
[ c
≥ µ (A ∩ En ) + µ A ∩ En
n=1 n=1
∞ ∞
∗ ∗
[ ∗
[ c
µ (A) ≥ µ A ∩ En + µ A ∩ En
n=1 n=1
duce a new symbol for it, but in some situations it is important to be able to distinguish
quickly between µ and µ∗ .
8 CHAPTER 6. CONSTRUCTING MEASURES
To get the opposite inequality, we use Lemma 6.2.4 with A = X to see that
N
X N
[ ∞
[
µ(En ) = µ( En ) ≤ µ( En )
n=1 n=1 n=1
(i) ∅ ∈ R
(ii) If R ∈ R, then Rc ∈ R.
(iii) If R, S ∈ R, then R ∪ S ∈ R
(iv) ρ(∅) = 0
µ∗ (A) ≥ µ∗ (A ∩ R) + µ∗ (A ∩ Rc )
for any setPA ⊂ X. Given > 0, we can find a covering C = {Cn }n∈N of A
such that ∞ ∗ c
n=1 ρ(Cn ) < µ (A) + . Note that {Cn ∩ R} and {Cn ∩ R } are
coverings of A ∩ R and A ∩ Rc , respectively, and hence
∞
X ∞
X
∗
ρ(Cn ∩ R) + ρ(Cn ∩ Rc ) =
µ (A) + > ρ(Cn ) =
n=1 n=1
∞
X ∞
X
= ρ(Cn ∩ R) + ρ(Cn ∩ Rc ) ≥ µ∗ (A ∩ R) + µ(A ∩ Rc )
n=1 n=1
P∞
For any > 0, there is a covering C = {C n }n∈N of R such that n=1 ρ(Cn ) <
µ∗ (R) + . The sets Cn0 = R ∩ (Cn \ n−1
S
k=1 C k ) are disjoint elements of R
whose union is R, and hence by condition (v) in the definition above
∞
X ∞
X
ρ(R) = ρ(Cn0 ) ≤ ρ(Cn ) < µ∗ (R) +
n=1 n=1
Since > 0 is arbitrary, this means that ρ(R) ≤ µ∗ (R), and since we already
have the opposite inequality, we have proved that µ∗ (R) = ρ(R). 2
(i) If R, S ∈ R, then R ∩ S ∈ R.
X = R ∪ R1 ∪ . . . ∪ Rn
Sn
(i) if a set R ∈ R is a disjoint, finite union R = i=1 Ri of sets in R,
then
Xn
λ(R) = λ(Ri )
i=1
S
(ii) If a set R ∈ R is a disjoint, countable union R = i∈N Ri of sets in
R, then
X∞
λ(R) = λ(Ri )
i=1
Proof: We only prove (ii). The proof of (i) is similar, the only difference be-
ing that we in one place use condition (i) of the theorem instead of condition
(ii).
To prove (ii), observe that since R is a semi-algebra, the intersections
Ri ∩ Sj belong to R, and hence by condition (ii) in the theorem
∞
X
λ(Ri ) = λ(Ri ∩ Sj )
j=1
= m
S
(ρ is well-defined as part (i) of the lemma tells us that if A P j=1 Sj is
n
another
Pm way of writing A as a disjoint union of sets in R, then i=1 λ(Ri ) =
j=1 λ(S j )). To use Carathéodory’s Extension Theorem 6.3.2, we need to
show that ρ is a premeasure, i.e. that
∞
X
ρ(A) = ρ(An )
n=1
and
Nn
[
An = Sn,k
k=1
S S
Since A = n∈N An = n,k Sn,k , part (ii) of the lemma tells us that
M
X X
λ(Rj ) = λ(Sn,k )
j=1 n,k
µ∗ (E) = µ∗ (X) − µ∗ (E c )
d) Show that µ∗ (F \D) < and explain that µ∗ (F \E) < and µ∗ (E\D) <
.
e) Explain that for any set A ⊂ X
µ∗ (A ∩ F ) = µ∗ (A ∩ D) + µ∗ (A ∩ (F \ D)) < µ∗ (A ∩ D) +
and
µ∗ (A ∩ Dc ) = µ∗ (A ∩ F c ) + µ∗ (A ∩ (F \ D)) < µ∗ (A ∩ F c ) +
µ∗ (A) ≥ µ∗ (A ∩ (F c ∪ D)) =
= µ∗ (A ∩ F c ) + µ∗ (A ∩ D) ≥ µ∗ (A ∩ E c ) + µ∗ (A ∩ E) − 2
and use it to show that if E is ∗-measurable, then E is measurable. The
notions of measurable and ∗-measurable hence coincide when µ∗ (X) is
finite.
(ii) All infinite intervals of the form (−∞, b] and (a, ∞) where a, b ∈ R.
16 CHAPTER 6. CONSTRUCTING MEASURES
We have reached our goal: The lemma above tells us that we can apply
Carathéodory’s theorem for semi-algebras to the semi-algebra R and the
function λ. The resulting measure µ is the Lebesgue measure on R. Let us
sum up the essential points.
6.4. LEBESGUE MEASURE ON R 17
The next result tells us that measurable sets can be approximated arbi-
trarily well by open and closed set.
Proof: We begin with the open sets. Assume first that A has finite measure.
Then for every > 0 there is a covering {Cn } of A by half-open rectangles
Cn = (an , bn ] such that
∞
X
|Cn | < µ(A) +
2
n=1
∞ ∞
X X
µ(G) ≤ µ(Bn ) = |Cn | + < µ(A) +
2n+1
n=1 n=1
and hence
µ(G \ A) = µ(G) − µ(A) <
by Lemma 5.1.4c).
If µ(A) is infinite, we slice A into pieces of finite measure An = A ∩
(n, n + 1] for all n ∈ Z, and use what we have already proved to find
S an open
set Gn such that An ⊂ Gn and µ(Gn \ An ) < 2n+2S. Then G = n∈Z Gn is
an open set which contains A, and since G \ A ⊂ n∈Z (Gn \ An ), we get
X X
µ(G \ A) ≤ µ(Gn \ An ) < < ,
2n+2
n∈Z n∈Z
18 CHAPTER 6. CONSTRUCTING MEASURES
E + a = {e + a | e ∈ E}
Proof: We shall leave this to the reader (see Exercise 7). The key observa-
tion is that µ∗ (E + a) = µ∗ (E) holds for outer measure since intervals keep
their length when we translate them. 2
One of the reasons why we had to develop the rather complicated ma-
chinery of σ-algebras, is that we can not in general expect to define a measure
on all subsets of our measure space X — some sets are just so complicated
that they are nonmeasurable. We shall now take a look at such a set. Before
we begin, we need to modify the notion of translation so that it works on
the interval [0, 1). If x, y ∈ [0, 1), we first define
.
x+y if x + y ∈ [0, 1)
x+y=
x + y − 1 otherwise
x ∼ y ⇐⇒ x − y is rational
6.4. LEBESGUE MEASURE ON R 19
and since µ([0, 1)) = 1, this is impossible — a sum of countable many, equal,
nonnegative numbers is either ∞ (if the numbers are positive) or 0 (if the
numbers are 0).
Note that this argument works not only for the Lebesgue measure, but
for any (non-zero) translation invariant measure on R. This means that it is
impossible to find a translation invariant measure on R that makes all sets
measurable. ♣
rA = {ra | a ∈ A}
Ca = {ω ∈ Ω | ω1 = a1 , ω2 = a2 , . . . , ωn = an }
and call it the cylinder set generated by a. We call n the length of Ca . Let
R be the collection of all cylinder sets (of all possible lengths).
Proof: The intersection of two cylinder sets Ca and Cb is either equal to one
of them (if one of the sequences a, b is an extension of the other) or empty.
The complement of a cylinder set is the union of all other cylinder sets of
the same length. 2
The next lemma tells us that this condition is trivially satisfied because
the situation never occurs – a cylinder set is never a disjoint, countable
union of infinitely many cylinder sets! As this is the difficult part of the
construction, I spell out the details. The argument is actually a compactness
argument in disguise, and corresponds to Lemma 6.4.3 in the construction
of the Lebesgue measure.
Before we begin, we need some notation and terminology. For each
k ∈ N, we write ω ∼k ω̂ if ωi = ω̂i for i = 1, 2, . . . , k, i.e., if the first k coin
tosses in the sequences ω and ω̂ are equal. We say that a subset A of Ω is
determined at k ∈ N if whenever ω ∼k ω̂ then either both ω and ω̂ belong to
A or none of them do (intuitively, this means that you can decide whether ω
belongs to A by looking at the k first coin tosses). A cylinder set of length k
is obviously determined at time k. We say that a set A is finally determined
if it is determined at some k ∈ N.
Proof: The three lemmas above give us exactly what we need to apply
Carathéodory’s theorem for semi-algebras. The uniqueness follows from
Proposition 6.3.3. The details are left to the reader. 2
7. (You should do Exercise 6 before you attempt this one.) Assume that I is a
nonempty subset of N. Define an equivalence relation ∼I on Ω by
AI = {A ∈ A | A is I-determined}
There is a similar result in measure theory that we are now going to look
at. Starting with two measure spaces (X, A, µ) and (Y, B, ν), we shall first
construct a product measure space (X × Y, A ⊗ B, µ × ν) and then prove
that
Z Z Z Z Z
f d(µ × ν) = f (x, y) dµ(x) dν(y) = f (x, y) dν(y) dµ(x)
µ × ν(A × B) = µ(A)ν(B)
for all A ∈ A and all B ∈ B (think of the formula for the area of an ordinary
rectangle).
As usual, we shall apply Carathéodory’s theorem for semi-algebras. If
we define measurable rectangles to be subsets of X × Y the form R = A × B,
where A ∈ A and B ∈ B, we first observe that the class of all such sets form
a semi-algebra.
λ(A × B) = µ(A)ν(B)
6.6. PRODUCT MEASURES 25
N Z Z
X
= lim 1Cn ×Dn (x, y)dµ(x) dν(x)
N →∞
n=1
N
Z "Z X #
= lim 1Cn ×Dn (x, y)dµ(x) dν(x)
N →∞
n=1
Z " N
Z X #
= lim 1Cn ×Dn (x, y)dµ(x) dν(x)
N →∞
n=1
Z "Z N
#
X
= lim 1Cn ×Dn (x, y)dµ(x) dν(x)
N →∞
n=1
∞
Z "Z X #
= 1Cn ×Dn (x, y)dµ(x) dν(x)
n=1
Z Z
= 1C×D (x, y)dµ(x) dν(x) = µ(C)ν(D)
Theorem 6.6.2 Assume that (X, A, µ) and (Y, B, ν) are two measure spaces
and let A ⊗ B be the σ-algebra generated by the measurable rectangles A × B,
A ∈ A, B ∈ B. Then there exists a measure µ × ν on A ⊗ B such that
µ × ν(A × B) = µ(A)ν(B) for all A ∈ A, B ∈ B
If µ and ν are σ-finite, this measure is unique and is called the product
measure of µ and ν.
Proof: The existence follows from Theorem 6.3.6 as formula (6.6.2) guaran-
tees that conditions (i) and (ii) hold (as ∅ = ∅ × ∅ ∈ R, we need not treat
finite and countable sums separately in this case). The uniqueness follows
from Proposition 6.3.3 (see also Exercise 6.3.1c)). 2
Lemma 6.7.1 Assume that (X, A, µ) and (Y, B, ν) are two measure spaces,
and let A ⊗ B be the product σ-algebra.
(i) For any E ∈ A ⊗ B, we have E y ∈ A and Ex ∈ B for all y ∈ Y and
x ∈ X.
(ii) For any A ⊗ B-measurable f : X × Y → R, the sections f y and fx are
A- and B-measurable, respectively, for all y ∈ Y and x ∈ X.
Proof: I only prove the lemma for the y-sections, and leave the x-sections
to the readers.
(i) Since A ⊗ B is the smallest σ-algebra containing the measurable rect-
angles, it clearly suffices to show that
C = {E ⊂ X × Y | E y ∈ A}
is a σ-algebra containing the measurable rectangles. That the measurable
rectangles are in C, follows from the observation
A if y ∈ B
(A × B)y =
∅ if y ∈/B
28 CHAPTER 6. CONSTRUCTING MEASURES
(check this!) 2
and Z Z
x 7→ f (x, y) dν(y) = fx (y) dν(y)
All σ-algebras are monotone classes, but a monotone class need not be a σ-
algebra. If R is a collection of subsets of Z, there is (by the usual argument)
a smallest monotone class containing R. It is called the monotone class
generated by R.
S S
n∈N En n∈N Fn ∈ M since M is closed under increasing countable
=
unions.
To prove that M is an algebra, we use a trick. For each M ∈ M define
M(M ) = {F ∈ M | F \ M, F \ M, F ∩ M ∈ M}
Lemma 6.7.3 Let (X, A, µ) and (Y, B, ν) be two σ-finite measure spaces,
and assume that E ⊂ X × Y is A ⊗ B-measurable. Then the functions
x 7→ ν(Ex ) and y 7→ µ(E y ) are A- and B-measurable, respectively, and
Z Z
ν(Ex ) dµ(x) = µ(E y ) dν(y) = µ × ν(E)
Proof: We shall prove the part about the x-sections Ex and leave the (sim-
ilar) proof for y-sections to the readers. We shall first carry out the proof
for finite measure spaces, i.e. we assume that µ(X), ν(Y ) < ∞.
Let
R
C = {E ⊂ X×Y | x 7→ ν(Ex ) is A-measurable and ν(Ex ) dµ(x) = µ × ν(E)}
and hence E ∈ C.
Since this shows that C is a monotone class and hence a σ-algebra con-
taining A×B, we have proved the lemma for finite measure spaces. To extend
it to σ-finite spaces, let {Xn } and {Yn } be increasing
S sequence ofSsubsets
of X and Y of finite measure such that X = n∈N Xn and Y = n∈N Yn .
If E is a A ⊗ B-measurable subset of X × Y , it follows from what we have
already proved that x 7→ ν((E ∩ (Xn × Yn )x ) is measurable and
Z
ν((E ∩ (Xn × Yn )x ) dµ(x) = µ × ν(E ∩ (Xn × Yn ))
6.7. FUBINI’S THEOREM 31
The lemma for σ-finite spaces now follows from the Monotone Convergence
Theorem and continuity of measures. 2
Remark: The proof above illustrates a useful technique. To prove that all
sets in the σ-algebra F generated by a family R satisfies a certain property
P , we prove
(i) All sets in R has property P .
(ii) The sets with property P form a σ-algebra G.
Then F ⊂ G (since F is the smallest σ-algebra containing R), and hence all
sets in F has property P .
Proof: We prove the first equality and leave the second to the reader. Notice
first that if f = 1E is an indicator function, then by the lemma
Z Z Z Z
1E d(µ × ν) = µ × ν(E) = ν(Ex ) dµ(x) = 1E (x, y) dν(y) dµ(x)
which proves the theorem for indicator functions. By linearity, it also holds
for nonnegative, simple functions.
For the general case, let {fn } be an increasing sequence ofR nonnegative
simple functions converging
R pointwise to f . The functions x 7→ fn (x, y) dν(y)
increase to x 7→ f (x, y) dν(y) by the Monotone Convergence Theorem.
Hence the latter function is measurable (as the limit of a sequence of mea-
surable functions), and using the Monotone Convergence Theorem again,
we get Z Z
f (x, y) d(µ × ν) = lim fn (x, y) d(µ × ν) =
n→∞
Z Z Z Z
= lim fn (x, y) dν(y) dµ(x) = lim fn (x, y) dν(y) dµ(x) =
n→∞ n→∞
Z Z Z Z
= lim fn (x, y) dν(y) dµ(x) = f (x, y) dν(y) dµ(x)
n→∞
2
Z
= |f | d(µ × ν) < ∞
and
Z Z Z Z Z
f− d(µ × ν) = f− (x, y) dν(y) dµ(x) = f− (x, y) dµ(x) dν(y)
and subtracting the second from the first, we get Fubini’s Theorem. 2
Even when the original measures µ and ν are complete, the product
measure µ × ν rarely is. A natural response is to take it’s completion µ × ν
(as we did with higher dimensional Lebesgue measures), but the question
is if Fubini’s theorem still holds. This is not obvious since there are more
µ × ν-measurable functions than µ × ν-measurable ones, but fortunately the
answer is yes. I just state the result without proof (see Excercise 11).
6.7. FUBINI’S THEOREM 33
Theorem 6.7.6 Let (X, A, µ) and (Y, B, ν) be two complete, σ-finite mea-
sure spaces, and assume that f : X × Y → R is µ × ν-measurable, where
µ × ν is the completion of the product measure. Then the functions fx
and fRy are measurable for almost
R all x and y, and the integrated functions
x 7→ f (x, y) dν(y) and y 7→ f (x, y)dµ(x) are measurable as well. More-
over
(i) (Tonelli’s Theorem for Completed Measures) If f is nonnega-
tive,
Z Z Z Z Z
f dµ × ν = f (x, y) dν(y) dµ(x) = f (x, y) dµ(x) dν(y)
f :R×N→R
be given by
1
f (x, n) =
1 + (2n x)2
1
R R
Compute f dλ. Remember that 1+u2 du = arctan u + C.
x−y
7. Let f : [0, 1] × [0, 1] → R be defined by f (x, y) = (x+y) 3 (the expression
doesn’t make sense for x = y = 0, and you may give the function whatever
value you want at that point). Show by computing the integrals that
Z 1 Z 1
1
f (x, y) dx dy = −
0 0 2
34 CHAPTER 6. CONSTRUCTING MEASURES
and Z 1 Z 1
1
f (x, y) dy dx =
0 0 2
1 2y
(you may want to use that f (x, y) = x2 +y 2 − (x+y)3 in the first integral and
R ∞ R ∞ R 2
∞ 2
f (x, y) dy dx = 0 e−u du .
and show that 0 0
R∞ √
−u2 π
d) Conclude that 0
e du = 2 .
9. Let X = Y = [0, 1], let µ be the Lebesgue measure on X (this is just the
restriction of the Lebesgue measure on R to [0, 1]) and let ν be
R the counting
measure. Let E = {(x, y) ∈ X × Y |x = y}, and show that ν(Ex ) dµ(x),
µ(E y ) dν(y), and µ × ν(E) are all different (compare lemma 6.7.3).
R
R R R
ShowR that
R f dµ×ν = ∞, but that the iterated integrals f (x, y) dµ(x) dν(u)
and f (x, y) dν(y) dµ(x) are both finite, but unequal.
11. In this exercise, we shall sketch the proof of Theorem 6.7.6, and we assume
that (X, A, µ) and (Y, B, ν) are as in that theorem.
a) Assume that E ∈ A ⊗ B and that µ × ν(E) = 0. Show that µ(E y ) = 0
for ν-almost all y and that ν(Ex ) = 0 for µ-almost all x.
b) Assume that N is an µ × ν-null set, i.e. there is an E ∈ A ⊗ B such
that N ⊂ E and µ × ν(E) = 0. Show that for ν-almost all y, N y is
µ-measurable and µ(N y ) = 0. Show also that for µ-almost all x, Nx is
ν-measurable and ν(Nx ) = 0. (Here you need to use that the original
measure spaces are complete).
6.7. FUBINI’S THEOREM 35
e) Prove Theorem 6.7.6 (this is just checking that the arguments that got
us from Lemma 6.7.3 to Theorems 6.7.4 and 6.7.5, still works in the
new setting).