Pettit (2013) On The People's Terms - A Republican Theory and Model of Democracy
Pettit (2013) On The People's Terms - A Republican Theory and Model of Democracy
Pettit (2013) On The People's Terms - A Republican Theory and Model of Democracy
org/9781107005112
On the People’s Terms
The John Robert Seeley Lectures have been established by the University
of Cambridge as a biennial lecture series in social and political studies,
sponsored jointly by the Faculty of History and the University Press. The
Seeley Lectures provide a unique forum for distinguished scholars of
international reputation to address, in an accessible manner, themes of
broad and topical interest in social and political studies. Subsequent to their
public delivery in Cambridge the University Press publishes suitably
modified versions of each set of lectures. Professor James Tully delivered the
inaugural series of Seeley Lectures in 1994 on the theme of Constitutionalism
in an Age of Diversity.
PHILIP PETTIT
cambridge university press
Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town,
Singapore, São Paulo, Delhi, Mexico City
Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781107005112
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library
References 311
Name index 329
Subject index 333
ix
Tables
x
Acknowledgements
This book has been long in the making. I decided to give more attention to
the relationship between republican political theory and democratic theory
soon after publishing Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government
in 1997 (Pettit 1997c) and I wrote some papers on the topic in the years
immediately following. I worked at developing an overall view of repub-
licanism and democracy in the Pufendorf Lectures in Philosophy at the
University of Lund in 2005, in the Albertus Magnus Lectures in Philosophy
at the University of Cologne in 2009 and, finally, in the Seeley Lectures in
Political Theory at the University of Cambridge in 2010. I wrote up a final
draft of the book while on a year’s research leave at the Center for Advanced
Study in the Behavioral Sciences at Stanford in 2010–11 and I reworked the
text in the course of a graduate seminar in Philosophy and Politics at
Princeton University in Fall Semester 2011. Late in the piece I presented
related material in the Frankfurt Lectures in Political Theory at the Goethe
University in Frankfurt, and in the Quain Lecture in Jurisprudence at
University College, London, and the intense discussions on each occasion
led to some final alterations. I am grateful to all those institutions for their
support, as well as to the John Guggenheim Foundation for the award of a
fellowship in 2010–11.
In the course of the years working on the text I built up an enormous
number of personal, as well as institutional, debts. Since I cannot hope to
acknowledge all my creditors, I hope just a few words of thanks will suffice. I
am grateful for the valuable contributions of my audiences and hosts at the
institutions where I lectured or gave seminars on the topic, for the contri-
butions of the graduate students with whom I have been fortunate to work
on related topics, and for the wholly invaluable commentary and criticism
that was provided week after week by the students who participated in the
Princeton seminar in 2011. I must also thank those who took the trouble to
read the full text and sent often extremely insightful and helpful comments:
David Plunkett, who used it in a course at UCLA; my colleague, Annie
xi
xii Acknowledgements
Stilz, who was a selfless, illuminating critic; and especially Niko Kolodny,
who wrote as a temporarily anonymous reviewer for Cambridge University
Press and forced me to reconsider a long list of issues.1
Sustained interaction with those Princeton colleagues associated with the
University Center for Human Values has been absolutely crucial in shaping
my views; the relevant players, on any count, have to include Anthony
Appiah, Chuck Beitz, Marc Fleurbaey, Dan Garber, Liz Harman, Nan
Keohane, Melissa Lane, Stephen Macedo, Victoria McGeer, Jan Werner
Mueller, Alan Patten, Gideon Rosen, Kim Scheppele, Peter Singer, Michael
Smith and Jeff Stout. There are many others with whom I have had
exchanges, some of them quite extended, on the topics covered. The list
includes John Braithwaite, Geoffrey Brennan, Annabel Brett, Ian Carter,
John Ferejohn, Rainer Forst, John Gardner, Moira Gatens, Bob Goodin,
Alan Hayek, Kinch Hoekstra, Istvan Hont, Duncan Ivison, Frank Jackson,
Susan James, Matthew Kramer, Martin Krygier, Chandran Kukathas,
Cecile Laborde, Niki Lacey, George Letsas, Christian List, Frank Lovett,
Jenny Mansbridge, Jose Marti, Josh Ober, Michael Otsuka, Paul Patton,
Joseph Raz, Magnus Ryan, Wojciech Sadurski, Tim Scanlon, Amartya Sen,
Ian Shapiro, Quentin Skinner, David Soskice, Nic Southwood, John
Tasioulas, Larry Temkin, Richard Tuck, Laura Valentini, Miguel Vatter,
Jeremy Waldron, Albert Weale, Barry Weingast, Jo Wolff and the late Iris
Marion Young.
The various people listed have each played an important role in pushing
and pulling me around the arena of debates covered in the book. My thanks
to all for their interest and their engagement and my apologies, of course, for
what many of them will take – or, as I would naturally like to think,
mistake – for sheer obstinacy. I owe a special debt to Quentin Skinner,
who is responsible for having introduced me to the potential of republican
ideas. And I owe an extra-special debt to Victoria McGeer, with whom
conversation and life never flag. Finally, I should express my gratitude to
Richard Fisher of Cambridge University Press for the enormous encourage-
ment and support that he offered from the time I was first invited to present
the Seeley Lectures.
1
N. Kolodny, in his unpublished paper, ‘Rule Over None: Social Equality and the Value of Democracy’,
offers an alternative way of developing some of the ideas that are basic to the approach taken in this book
and this was a source of constant challenges as I prepared the final version of my own text.
Introduction. The republic, old and new
the project
Every philosophy of the good society starts with an account of the canonical
complaint that the state should help to put right: the evil that the society
should drive out by means of political organization and initiative. The
complaints targeted for political rectification come in two broad families.
On the one side, personal afflictions like misery or poverty or inequality; on
the other, social failures like division or disorder or perhaps an excess of
customary restriction.
The more personal complaints generate a powerfully motivating agenda,
since most of us would rejoice in a state that silenced them. But these
complaints are liable to seem politically over-demanding. While it would be
good to be rid of misery or poverty or inequality, not everyone will agree
that the state could, or should, be given the job of dealing with them. The
removal of the less personal evils is not politically over-demanding in the
same way, for most people will think that the state is able to remedy such
failures. But these complaints may fail to motivate appropriately: their
rectification falls short of what many of us feel that we in a politically
organized society can and should collectively provide for our members.
Republican philosophy identifies a complaint that is meant to be at once
personally motivating and politically feasible. It indicts the evil of subjection
to another’s will – particularly in important areas of personal choice – as an ill
that we all recognize and recoil from and at the same time as an ill that the
state is well placed to deal with. I shall be arguing in the course of this book
that such subjection can be effectively corralled and reduced, though certainly
not wholly eliminated, by means of political initiative. And yet it takes only a
little imagination to realize just how repellent this subjection can be.
Think, by way of exercising such imagination, of how you would feel as a
student if you depended for not failing a course on the whim of an
instructor. Or as a wife if you had to rely on the mood of your husband
1
2 Introduction. The republic, old and new
for whether you could enjoy an unmolested day. Or as a worker if you hung
on the favour of a manager for whether you retained your job. Or as a debtor
if you were dependent on the goodwill of a creditor for whether you had to
face public ignominy. Or as someone destitute if you had to cast yourself on
the mercy of others just to survive or maintain your family. Or think about
how you would feel as the member of a cultural minority if you had to rely
on the humour of majority groups for whether you escaped humiliation; or
as an elderly person if you depended on escaping the notice of youth gangs
for walking safely home; or as a citizen if you were dependent on winning
the favour of some insider group for whether you or your kind ever caught
the eye of government.
It is a commonplace in most cultures that such involuntary exposure to the
will of others is inherently troubling and objectionable. Even when those
others do not exercise their power in actual interference, the very dependency
involved is something from which we naturally recoil. The possible modes of
subjection are many and diverse, as these examples already testify, but it
should be clear that the state is capable of curtailing them in various ways.
Without assuming the cast of a Leviathan in their lives, it can assure its people
of a level of protection, support and status that frees them from at least the
more egregious forms that such dependency can take.
Already in classical, republican Rome, the evil of subjection to the will of
others, whether or not such subjection led to actual interference, was identi-
fied and indicted as the iconic ill from which political organization should
liberate people, in particular those in the fortunate position of citizens. It was
described as the evil of being subject to a master, or dominus – suffering
dominatio – and was contrasted with the good of libertas, or ‘liberty’. The
accepted wisdom was that people could enjoy liberty, both in relation to one
another and to the collectivity, only by being invested with the power and
status of the civis, or ‘citizen’. Being a free person became synonymous with
being sufficiently empowered to stand on equal terms with others, as a citizen
amongst citizens (Wirszubski 1968: Chapter 1).
The idea that citizens could enjoy this equal standing in their society, and
not have to hang on the benevolence of their betters, became the signature
theme in the long and powerful tradition of republican thought. Familiar
from its instantiation in classical Rome, the idea was reignited in medieval
and Renaissance Italy; spread throughout Europe in the modern era,
sparking the English Civil War and the French Revolution; and inflamed
the passions of England’s American colonists in the late eighteenth century,
leading to the foundation of the world’s first modern democracy. With
citizenship becoming more and more inclusive as a category, the idea was
The project 3
that the state could provide for all citizens in such a measure that they would
each be able to walk tall, live without shame or indignity, and look one
another in the eye without any reason for fear or deference.
The recent revival of republican thought is built on this idea that there is
an ideal for the state to promote – freedom understood as non-domination –
that is both personally motivating and politically implementable. Freedom
in this sense is not meant to be the only value in life, or the only value that
ultimately matters. The claim is merely that it is a gateway good, suited to
guide the governments that people form and sustain. Let government look
after the freedom of citizens in this sense, so the line goes, and it will also
have to look after a plausible range of other goods and do so at a plausible
level of provision. It will have to guard against division and disorder and
intrusive regulation and it will have to provide in a decent measure against
misery and poverty, unfairness and inequality.
This book joins a growing body of contributions in political theory that
are guided by the republican ideal and more generally by the republican
tradition of thought.1 While the volume offers an outline history of the
tradition, an analysis of freedom as non-domination, and an account of
what the ideal requires by way of social justice in people’s relationships with
one another, the main focus is elsewhere. It is on what the ideal demands by
way of political legitimacy in the relationships between citizens and their
state. The book argues that while the state has to guard people against
private domination – that is, the requirement of social justice – it also needs
to guard against itself practising a form of public domination. The require-
ment of guarding against public domination, thereby delivering political
legitimacy, turns out to demand a rich array of popular controls over
government: in effect, a distinctive form of democracy. It enables us to
explain why and how government should be forced, in the title of the
volume, to operate on the people’s terms.
1
The recent movement, as I think of it, began from the historical work of Quentin Skinner (1978) on
the medieval foundations of modern political thought, and from his subsequent articles in the 1980s on
figures like Machiavelli, who wrote within the republican tradition identified by John Pocock (1975).
An up-to-date list of English works in contemporary republican thinking should include these books:
Pettit (1997c); Skinner (1998); Brugger (1999); Honohan (2002); Viroli (2002); Maynor (2003); Lovett
(2010); Marti and Pettit (2010); McGilvray (2011); these collections of papers: Van Gelderen and
Skinner (2002); Weinstock and Nadeau (2004); Honohan and Jennings (2006); Laborde and Maynor
(2007); Besson and Marti (2008); Niederberger and Schink (2012); and a number of studies that
deploy the conception of freedom as non-domination, broadly understood: Braithwaite and Pettit
(1990); Richardson (2002); Slaughter (2005); Bellamy (2007); Bohman (2007); Laborde (2008); White
and Leighton (2008).
4 Introduction. The republic, old and new
This theory of democracy, which takes final shape in Chapter 3, will not
be very persuasive unless we can offer at least a rough model of how it might
be institutionally realized. That is what the final two chapters provide.
While the model developed there may be rejected or amended by many
who still want to stick with the basic republican theory, it should at least
help to show that the theory is not institutionally infeasible.
The model developed in chapters 4 and 5 suggests that democracy operates
at its best in a dual process involving, in the short haul, the exercise of popular
influence over government and, in the long haul, the imposition of a popular
direction on government. As a result of the short-term electoral and contest-
atory influence that democracy can give them, so the idea goes, the people
gain the power to force government over the longer term to conform to widely
accepted norms of policy-making. The combination of these two processes,
each with its own temporal register, can ensure that the demos, or ‘people’,
enjoy a significant degree of kratos, or ‘power’, over the laws that govern and
shape their lives, thereby avoiding public domination. The model offers a
picture of how public institutions might serve to implement the republican
version of the democratic ideal, giving people channels of influence that
conjoin to form a river of popular control. Readers who are interested in
this model, rather than in the republican theory on which it is based, might go
directly to the final two chapters, using the propositional summary offered in
the Conclusion to orientate their reading.
In the remainder of this Introduction, I outline the main ideas in the
historical tradition of republican thought, distinguishing them from liberal
and communitarian ideas, and explaining how I make use of them in the
philosophical argument that follows. That argument begins in Chapter 1 with
an account of the republican ideal of freedom as non-domination, and
continues in the following two chapters with the theory of social justice and
political legitimacy that republicanism would support. As already suggested,
social justice constrains the relations that the members of a society should
have with one another, and political legitimacy the relations that they should
have with their government and, more broadly, their state. The theory of
republican legitimacy turns out to offer a theory of democracy, since it
requires a very specific form of equally shared, popular control over govern-
ment. Having developed that theory in Chapter 3, I then go on in chapters 4
and 5 to outline the dual-aspect model of the sort of democracy required.
Even where it covers ground that I have traversed elsewhere, my pre-
sentation of republican history and theory has shifted somewhat as a result
of the many recent discussions of these topics. The historical outline in this
Introduction coheres with the story of republican development that I have
Three core ideas 5
presented in earlier writings, building on the work of Quentin Skinner, but
it sharpens the contrast between the Italian–Atlantic republicanism with
which I identify and the form of republican thought introduced by
Rousseau. The argument in the first three chapters is broadly faithful to
lines of thinking I have defended in other works but is novel on a number of
counts. It builds the discussion around the distinction between freedom of
choice and freedom of the person. It uses an analysis of the fundamental
liberties, and of their grounding in public norm and law, to articulate the
ideal of freedom as a person and the requirements of republican justice. And
it develops a theory of republican legitimacy at proper length, marking it off
from the theory of republican justice on the one side and non-republican
theories of legitimacy on the other.
2
There are three ways, according to most contemporary normative theories, in which a government and
state might fail to be satisfactory (Fukuyama 2011). It might fail to operate impartially by systematically
favouring members of a particular grouping, like a family or tribe. It might operate impartially but fail
to operate according to established, stable rules in decision-making; that is, it might be ad hoc or
capricious, rather than constitutional. Or it might operate impartially and constitutionally but fail to
be accountable to its subjects. The first danger introduces partial, as distinct from impartial, rule; the
second particularistic rule, as distinct from constitutional rule – the rule of law; and the third
paternalistic rule, rather than accountable rule. We might say that in the republican tradition the
mixture of the mixed constitution is meant to ensure impartial rule, the constitutionalism of the mixed
constitution to ensure constitutional rule, and the contestatory character of the citizenry to ensure
accountable rule.
3
Eric Nelson (2004) has identified a Greek tradition in later republican thought that coexisted with the
neo-Roman tradition in which I am interested. I do not give attention to this tradition here.
4
For a vigorous and impressive argument that Machiavelli gave the contestatory element such emphasis
that he should be seen as a distinctive figure in the tradition – a radical democrat rather than an
aristocratic republican – see McCormick (2011). Chapter 6 of that book takes me to task for not being
more Machiavellian in that sense and I hope that the current work may help to counter its depiction of
the republicanism I espouse as being aristocratic in character.
Three core ideas 7
that emerged in the thought of defenders such as James Harrington, John
Milton and Algernon Sidney became a staple of political thought in
eighteenth-century Britain and America, albeit often adapted to make
room for a constitutional monarchy (Raab 1965). And they were incorpo-
rated deeply, if not always overtly, into the enormously influential work of
the Baron de Montesquieu (1989) on The Spirit of the Laws. However
differently interpreted or applied, the ideas were more or less common
property to the Whig establishment in eighteenth-century Britain; to their
Tory opposition, at least as that was formulated by the 1st Viscount
Bolingbroke (Skinner 1974); to radical Whigs who were a constant sting
in the side of every establishment (Robbins 1959); and, of course, to the
American colonists, and their British apologists, who came to feel that the
Westminster Parliament ruled its colonies in a manner that betrayed
the ‘commonwealthman’ or republican heritage (Bailyn 1967; Reid 1988;
Sellers 1995). Republican ideas provided the framework for the arguments
made in support of the cause of American independence over the 1760s
and 1770s – including arguments made by contemporary English sup-
porters such as Richard Price (1991) and Joseph Priestley (1993) – and for
the arguments put forward in the constitutional debates of the 1780s
between federalists and anti-federalists (Madison, Hamilton and Jay
1987; Ketcham 2003).
Amongst the three ideas associated with the republican tradition, the
conception of freedom as non-domination is the most distinctive. If you are
to enjoy freedom as non-domination in certain choices, so the idea went,
then you must not be subject to the will of others in how you make those
choices; you must not suffer dominatio, in the word established in Roman
republican usage (Lovett 2010: Appendix i). That means that you must not
be exposed to a power of interference on the part of any others, even if they
happen to like you and do not exercise that power against you. The mere
fact that I can interfere at little cost in your choices – the mere fact that I can
track those choices and intervene when I like – means that you depend for
your ability to choose as you wish on my will remaining a goodwill. You are
not sui juris – or not ‘your own person’ – in the expression from Roman law.
You are unfree, as the eighteenth-century republican Richard Price (1991:
26) explained, because your access to the options will depend on an
‘indulgence’ or an ‘accidental mildness’ on my part. To quote from a
seventeenth-century republican, Algernon Sidney (1990: 17, 304), freedom
in this tradition requires ‘independency upon the will of another’ – an
‘exemption from dominion’ in relations with others. In an equivalent slogan
from a popular eighteenth-century tract, ‘Liberty is, to live upon one’s own
8 Introduction. The republic, old and new
terms; slavery is, to live at the mere mercy of another’ (Trenchard and
Gordon 1971: ii, 249–50).
In arguing that the state should be concerned in the first place with the
equal freedom of its citizens, republicans held that citizens should each be
assured of enjoying non-domination in a sphere of choice that came to be
described as that of the fundamental or basic liberties (Libourne 1646; Pettit
2008a). This might be identified, in contemporary terms, with the sphere of
choice required for being able to function in the local society (see Sen 1985;
Nussbaum 2006). They thought that a state organized under a mixed
constitution, and disciplined by a contestatory citizenry, was the best
hope of promoting this ideal.
The citizenry was traditionally restricted to mainstream, usually pro-
pertied, males and, under the republican vision, a citizen would be a liber,
or a ‘free-man’, insofar as he enjoyed sufficient power and protection in
the sphere of the basic liberties to be able to walk tall amongst others and
look any in the eye without reason for fear or deference. John Milton
(1953–82: viii, 424–5) captured the idea nicely in arguing that, in a ‘free
Commonwealth’, ‘they who are greatest . . . are not elevated above their
brethren; live soberly in their families, walk the streets as other men, may
be spoken to freely, familiarly, friendly, without adoration’. In the vision
of contemporary republicans, this ideal ought to be extended to an
inclusive citizenry; freedom as non-domination ought to be secured for
all more or less permanent residents, independently of gender or property
or religion.
6
A further distinction within liberal doctrines in this sense is that between those in which freedom is
taken as a goal – I think, as indicated at the end of Chapter 1, that freedom as non-domination should
be taken in this way (Pettit 1997c: Chapter 3) – and those in which the rights associated with freedom
are taken in non-consequentialist form as side-constraints; the best example of the latter approach is
Nozick (1974). For a discussion of consequentialist and non-consequentialist approaches in political
philosophy, see Pettit (2001d, 2012a).
7
Indeed Paley (2002: 331) himself embraced the ‘combination of the three regular species of govern-
ment’ that he claimed to find in England in the 1780s.
8
There might be some merit, for this reason, in adopting Richard Dagger’s (1997) usage and speaking of
the approach defended here – which resembles Dagger’s own – as republican liberalism or liberal
republicanism.
12 Introduction. The republic, old and new
originates with Jean Jacques Rousseau. I describe this approach as commu-
nitarian, for reasons that will become clear shortly, though it is often described
as republican; it represents a broadly Continental form of republicanism, as
distinct from the Italian–Atlantic tradition that I have been characterizing.9
It is easy to mistake the two versions of republicanism, for as liberalism
came to displace traditional republicanism as the main ideology of the
English-speaking world, the name ‘republicanism’ came to designate the
new Rousseauvian doctrine. It is primarily with the Continental, commu-
nitarian version of the doctrine, rather than the Italian–Atlantic tradition,
that critics of liberalism like Hannah Arendt (1958, 1973) and Michael
Sandel (1996) seem to identify, for example.10 It is this version of repub-
licanism that is rejected, along with liberalism, in the work of Juergen
Habermas (1994, 1995).11 And it is this doctrine that self-described liberals
often focus on in arguing for the merits of their own approach (Brennan and
Lomasky 2006).
Rousseau espoused a version of freedom as non-domination or non-
dependency, giving it pride of place in the concerns of the state. He says that
if people are to be free, each must be ‘perfectly independent of all the others’
(Rousseau 1997: ii.2.2). And he maintains that that ‘which ought to be the
end of every system of legislation is . . . freedom and equality’, where
freedom is understood in the sense of non-dependency and equality is
valued ‘because freedom cannot subsist without it’ (Rousseau 1997:
ii.11.1). But while he remained faithful to Italian–Atlantic republicanism
in this respect, he broke dramatically with it in arguing against the mixed
constitution and the contestatory image of the citizenry.
Rousseau rejects the idea of the mixed constitution under the lead of
absolutists like Jean Bodin (1967) in the sixteenth century, and Thomas
Hobbes (1994a, 1994b, 1998) in the seventeenth.12 He accepted their argu-
ment that every state has to have a single, absolute sovereign, individual or
corporate, and that no such agency can operate, as envisaged in the mixed
9
For a fuller discussion of this communitarian form of republicanism, with reference to Kant as well as
Rousseau, see Pettit (2012b).
10
In discussing this conception of the republic in earlier work, in particular the conception as it appears
in Sandel, I have sometimes described it as neo-Athenian (Pettit 1998). I regret that usage now, since
as a matter of history – if not in later representations, which were deeply influenced by Polybius –
Athens had many of the characteristics of a mixed constitution; it was not a city ruled by an assembly
with Rousseauvian powers. See Hansen (1991), and for a summary account that emphasizes this
mixture see Chapter 2 of Dowlen (2008).
11
For the record, I think that Habermas’s own views come close to republican views, as I conceptualize
and defend them.
12
For a wonderful overview of the French tradition in the background of Rousseau’s thinking see
Keohane (1980).
The communitarian opposition 13
constitution, on the basis of coordination between different, mutually
checking centres of power. Hobbes had argued that the mixed constitution
supports ‘not one independent commonwealth, but three independent
factions; nor one representative person, but three’ (Hobbes 1994b: 29.16.
See too 1998: 7.4, 1994a: 20.15). Rousseau strikes a similar note of derision in
attacking the champions of this centrepiece of republican thought: ‘they
turn the Sovereign into a being that is fantastical and formed of disparate
parts; it is as if they were putting together man out of several bodies one of
which had eyes, another arms, another feet, and nothing else’ (1997: ii.2.2).
Bodin and Hobbes had argued that the sovereign could be a monarch,
which was their own favourite candidate, an aristocratic committee, or a
committee-of-the-whole. But they allowed that such a sovereign might del-
egate much of the work of government to another agency. Rousseau held that
only a unanimously endorsed committee-of-the-whole could serve in the
sovereign role, on the grounds that an aristocracy or a monarchy would
impose an alien will on people (1997: i.4.4). And he argued that while the
members of the sovereign assembly have to rely on majority voting in order to
make their decisions (iv.2.7), they should deliberate and vote, at least in the
ideal, on the basis of the common interest. Only if the members act in that
way, he thought, can the assembly claim to be enacting a general will in which
all figure as equal objects of concern. The members of Rousseau’s assembly are
to think as citizens, focused impartially on their common interest, and they
are to vote for any measure they support, not out of personal or factional
motives, but on the impersonal, deliberative basis that ‘it is advantageous to
the State . . . that this or that opinion pass’ (iv.1.6).13
How is this impartiality likely to be achieved? Rousseau thinks that
insofar as the people in assembly have to decide only on matters of general
law – and not on administrative or adjudicative measures involving indi-
viduals (1997: iii.17.5) – they will operate under a veil of abstraction that
keeps personal or factional concerns out of the picture. They will consider
‘the subjects in a body and their actions in the abstract, never any man as an
individual or a particular action’ (Rousseau 1997: ii.6.6). And so they will
tend to be moved, he hopes, not by particularistic motives, but by an
impartial, egalitarian concern ‘with their common preservation, and the
general welfare’ (Rousseau 1997: iv.1.1). They will form their minds and cast
13
On this reading of Rousseau, the common good is not defined procedurally as whatever good is
supported by suitably motivated majority voting; rather it is the good that suitably motivated majority
voting might be expected to track. See Cohen (2010).
14 Introduction. The republic, old and new
their votes on the basis of open deliberation and debate about the require-
ments of the common good.14
Rousseau betrayed the earlier tradition of republicanism in this concep-
tion of popular sovereignty. In his idealized republic, individuals are con-
fronted by the single powerful presence of ‘the public person’, which
‘formerly assumed the name City and now assumes that of Republic or
body politic’ (1997: i.6.10). While he envisages an ideal under which people
are independent of one another as private persons, in line with the repub-
lican conception of freedom, he thinks that this mutual independence is
attainable only at the cost of a form of submission to the public person –
specifically, to the general or corporate will of the public person – that
would have been wholly at odds with Italian–Atlantic sentiments. While
every citizen should ‘be perfectly independent of all the others’, he says, this
is only going to be possible insofar as each is ‘excessively dependent on the
City’ (Rousseau 1997: ii.12.3). The totally novel, consciously outrageous
assumption Rousseau introduces is that ‘each, by giving himself to all, gives
himself to no one’ (1997: i.6.8).
The rejection of the mixed constitution in favour of a popular, majoritarian
sovereign led Rousseau to reject also the contestatory role that was given to
citizens under traditional republicanism. Following Bodin and Hobbes he
emphasizes that the sovereign assembly of the people has to have absolute
power and not be subject to interrogation by citizens, at least when they speak
outside the assembly on the basis of their rights as individuals. Hobbes (1994b:
18.4) had said if subjects could ‘pretend a breach of the covenant made by the
sovereign . . . there is in this case no judge to decide the controversy’. And in
the same vein, Rousseau claims that ‘if individuals were left some rights . . .
there would be no common power who might adjudicate between them and
the public’ (1997: i.6.7). The idea is that there has to be one, final, spokes-
person on what the law is and that if the people could individually contest the
legislature’s decisions outside the assembly, there would have to be another
body to rule between them. Once the legislative assembly has spoken,
according to this picture, it falls to individuals to comply, not complain.15
Citizens are no longer invigilators of government, alert to any possible
14
Rousseau makes some remarks that seem to cast doubt on the value of public deliberation, but in
general, as Joshua Cohen (2010: 75–7, 171–2) argues, he clearly expects deliberation to have a major
role in the proceedings of the assembly.
15
But how, Rousseau asks, ‘are the opponents both free and subject to laws to which they have not
consented’? His response is ‘that the question is badly framed. The citizen consents to all the laws,
even to those passed in spite of him, and even to those that punish him when he dares to violate any of
them’ (iv.2.8).
The communitarian opposition 15
misdoing and ready to challenge and contest the legislative, executive and
judicial authorities. They are law-makers, not law-checkers, generators of law,
not testers of law. They serve in the production of public decisions, not in
controlling for the quality of decisions proposed or made.
This viewpoint is deeply opposed to accepted republican doctrine and in
adopting it Rousseau is moved by a thought first floated by that great enemy
of the doctrine, Thomas Hobbes (1994b: 18.6). This is the idea that no law
supported by the general impartial will ‘can be unjust, since no man can be
unjust towards himself’ (Rousseau 1997: ii.6.7). Far from every law being a
fair target for civic critique and challenge, each comes draped in an authority
and majesty that brooks no individual opposition. Having been party to the
creation of the popular sovereign no one as an individual retains the right of
contesting the decisions of the collectivity, even if those decisions are ones
that the person argued against in assembly. In an extraordinary reversal of
received ideas, the cause of freedom as non-domination, from which
Rousseau starts, is now linked with a new, communitarian form of the
very absolutism that republican doctrine had always challenged. The people
or community gets to be sacralized, as it assumes the role of the popular,
incontestable sovereign, incapable of doing wrong to its own members.
While Rousseau’s wider theory is deeply at odds with Italian–Atlantic
republicanism, however – and while, as I believe, it is normatively unattrac-
tive – it has one powerfully appealing element. This is his ideal of a deliber-
ative assembly in which everyone is able to speak and vote on an equal basis,
and yet is required to speak and vote on the basis of a concern with the
common good.16 Elaborated influentially in the work of Juergen Habermas
(1984–9, 1994, 1995), the constraint requires participants in a deliberative
assembly to argue for their different proposals on the basis of ‘reasons that
are persuasive to all who are committed to acting on the results of a free and
reasoned assessment of alternatives by equals’ (Cohen 1989: 23). Such consid-
erations will include general reasons to do with what promises more peace or
order or prosperity for the society as a whole. But they can also include reasons
16
While Rousseau does not address the issue of how precisely the parties should deliberate with one
another, his insistence on their abstracting from personal and factional considerations can be taken to
mandate something like this constraint. In any case, the constraint ought to be congenial from a
Rousseauvian point of view. Setting it up as a formal requirement would serve as a defence against the
intrusion of personal and factional concerns in the decisions of the assembly. If the participants are
explicitly required to seek out mutually acceptable reasons in support of their proposals, that in itself
may serve to elicit an attachment to the viewpoint of the public (Elster 1986). And once it is salient to
everyone that everyone is expected to do this, it may become shameful for participants to display
concerns of a more personal or factional character (Brennan and Pettit 2004). The topic is central to
the discussion in Chapter 5.
16 Introduction. The republic, old and new
put forward on behalf of a particular subgroup or individual. The consider-
ation in this case will not be just that the subgroup or individual is unsatisfied,
as if all others should be moved by that thought, but that the group or
individual suffers a disadvantage to which – purportedly by general criteria
that are endorsed across the society – no one should be exposed.
This deliberative constraint will play a role in our later discussions and, to
that extent, the position taken in this book has Rousseauvian linkages. But
the point I want to emphasize here is that the communitarian vision he
sponsored is nonetheless hostile to the central tenets of Italian–Atlantic
republicanism. Rousseau himself remained faithful to that tradition in his
continuing to embrace something like the ideal of equal freedom as non-
domination. But even this connection was broken amongst those who
identified with his vision in later generations. As his ideas washed around
political circles, this last vestige of republican thought was swept away in the
flood. It became natural to think, in a vulgarization of Rousseau’s own
analysis (Spitz 1995), that freedom is nothing more or less than the pos-
session or exercise of the right to participate in popular decision-making.
Benjamin Constant was probably the major figure in accomplishing this
final step, although he did so as a critic, not a defender. Himself attracted to
what was seen as a brand of liberalism – although one that in many respects
kept close to the older republicanism – he gave a famous lecture in 1819 that
described the supposedly ancient way of thinking about politics and free-
dom with which the liberal view has to compete (Constant 1988). According
to this ancient way of thinking, he says, the people in a commonwealth
constitute the sovereign, the role of citizens is to participate as officials or
electors in sovereign decision-making and – this is the alteration from the
strict Rousseauvian picture – freedom consists in nothing more or less than
the right to participate in such communal self-determination: the right to
live under a regime of law that you have a certain participatory or electoral
role in creating.17
With this twist, Rousseau became associated with a set of ideas that
contrasts in every dimension with the Italian–Atlantic tradition. This new
ideology replaced freedom as non-domination with freedom as participa-
tion. It replaced the institutional ideal of the mixed constitution with that of
a popular, absolutely sovereign assembly. And it replaced the ideal of a
contestatory people with that of a participatory legislature against which
17
Yiftah Elazar has persuaded me that while the eighteenth-century thinker, Richard Price (1991),
preserves other aspects of the Italian–Atlantic tradition, he had also begun to emphasize this self-
legislative theme.
The communitarian opposition 17
individuals had no rights in their own name. This broadly communitarian
family of ideas assumed many different forms, for example in Kant’s
political philosophy (Pettit 2012b), as it became associated with the nation-
state rather than a city-state like Rousseau’s Geneva, as the body of citizens
proper was taken to be less inclusive than Rousseau imagined and, in a final
departure, as participation was allowed to become electoral rather than
legislative in character. But no matter what form it assumed, the approach
remained decidedly at odds with the Italian–Atlantic tradition from which
it had sprung.
The contrast between the approaches shows up nicely in their different
images of the free person or citizen. The free-man in the Italian–Atlantic
tradition, the liber of Roman thought, was someone who lived in his own
domain – the masculine form fits with the habits of the time – on terms that
he himself set. Within that domain he lived sui juris, as it was put in Roman
law, ‘under his own jurisdiction’. He did not operate in potestate domini, ‘in
the power of a master’, and he did not have to make his choices cum
permissu, ‘with permission’. He could act without fear or deference, being
protected and empowered in relation to others, and even in relation to the
very law that helped establish his position.18
The tradition emphasized, of course, that no one can expect to enjoy this
status outside a community in which citizens are powerful and vigilant
enough to keep tabs and impose checks on government. It is because they
‘attain unto liberty’ on the basis of such political engagement, as James
Harrington (1992: 75) puts it in the seventeenth century, that free citizens
are ‘able to live of themselves’. But while the status of the free person can exist
only in the presence of such public virtue, it consists, according to this way of
thinking, in the enjoyment of equal freedom as non-domination across a
range of significant, personal choices: the fundamental or basic liberties. These
choices have to be available in common to all citizens, and available on the
common basis of a protective and empowering law and culture.
18
Although self-described liberals do not ordinarily emphasize the need for contestatory virtue, they do
often endorse this ideal of the free person, preserving a deep commonality with Italian–Atlantic
republicanism. Isaiah Berlin (1969: lx) embraces the ideal when he says that freedom requires ‘an
area . . . in which one is one’s own master’; a domain where one ‘is not obliged to account for his
activities to any man so far as this is compatible with the existence of organized society’. This domain
is to constitute ‘a certain minimum area of personal freedom which must on no account be violated’
(Berlin 1969: 123). It is not clear how you can be your own master without enjoying non-domination;
to enjoy non-interference by grace of just the goodwill of another would seem to leave you well short
of the independence required (Pettit 2011b). But putting that problem aside, it is clear that on this
issue republicanism and liberalism may often converge.
18 Introduction. The republic, old and new
The image of the free person assumes a different cast in the Rousseauvian
tradition. According to the new, communitarian, way of thinking, the free
person is the active political figure whose highest fulfilment consists in
participating with others, at whatever level of community, in activities of
shared deliberation and decision-making. In Hannah Arendt’s (1958) favourite
phrase, it is the citizen who embraces the vita activa rather than the vita
contemplativa – the active rather than the contemplative life – and in particular
an active life in the realm of public affairs. This rather romantic picture of the
tirelessly engaged public figure stands in stark opposition to the image of the
free-man in older republican thought, though it may echo the emphasis on
the need for a contestatory citizenry. Whereas Italian–Atlantic thought hails
the enjoyment of a publicly protected freedom in the domain of private life –
a freedom, in the republican picture, that enables you to stand equal with
others, not depending on anyone’s grace or favour – this new vision tends to
downplay private life in favour of public engagement.
20
The closest I have come to doing intellectual history is in my work on Hobbes’s theory of language,
thought and politics (Pettit 2008c). But even there I think of what I do as proposing a reading or
20 Introduction. The republic, old and new
reflective equilibrium
The normative claims defended in the book should not be judged by
historical criteria, therefore, but rather by philosophical. The philosophical
methodology I follow is that which John Rawls (1971) described as reflective
equilibrium. The idea is to set out general principles for the domain
investigated, whether it be justice or legitimacy or sovereignty; to use
empirical assumptions to derive their implications for specific cases; to see
how those implications fit with what we find credible on reflection; and to
go back and forth in the search for adjustments at either end that can
promote overall coherence.
The methodology is even relevant to the interpretation of freedom as
non-domination. I do not suppose that this is the only conception of
freedom in common usage, as Chapter 1 should make clear (on different
conceptions, see Schmidtz and Brennan 2010). My claim rather is that this
way of thinking about freedom has serious payoffs in normative thought. It
enables us to develop theories of social justice, political legitimacy and
international sovereignty that stand up well to the tests that reflective
equilibrium would support.21
This point is worth emphasizing because ordinary talk of freedom offers us a
network of flexible and, it may often seem, wayward idioms. We say that if you
can’t enact a certain option then it’s not a matter of your free choice. And yet
we also say that you may be free to do something – say, go and vote – even
when you are confined to bed and cannot get to the polling station. We say
hypothesis – that Hobbes was the first to think of language as an invention that transformed the nature of
its inventors – that others are better qualified to test. That also is how I think of the idea, as it was
formulated for example in Pettit (1996a, 1997c), that the main figures in the republican tradition
conceptualize freedom as non-domination; that idea was stimulated, of course, by the work of
Quentin Skinner, though it gave a somewhat different twist to what he had been saying (Pettit 2002b).
21
When we follow the method of reflective equilibrium, I assume that we share general ideas about the
nature of values like freedom, justice and legitimacy – the ideas come to us as connotations of the
terms – and that a normative theory should try to respect these in the interpretation of what the values
demand. I also assume that an overall normative theory will force us to weight these values against
each other and to try to reconcile their rival demands. And I assume, finally, that the demands of
values in this or that context – the demands of freedom-in-the-face-of-power, for example, or the
demands of justice-in-the-face-of-reasonable-disagreement – do not have to be derived from the pure
or abstract theory of freedom or justice, whatever that might be. I hope that in good part these
assumptions will be justified, arguendo, by the role they play in my argument. The first two
assumptions put me at loggerheads with the ‘more ambitious and hazardous’ holism that Ronald
Dworkin (2011: 263) supports, under which the demands of all values whatsoever are to be construed,
so that there are ‘no genuine conflicts’ (119) between them. For critical remarks on Dworkin’s
methodology see Pettit (2011a). The third assumption puts me at a distance from G. A. Cohen’s
(2008) foundationalist claim that the demands of justice under a contingent condition like reasonable
disagreement are to be derived from their demands in abstraction from any such contingent fact. For a
critique see Larmore (2012).
The emerging view of democracy 21
that even if something is not permitted, you may still have the freedom to
choose it. And yet we also say that you do not have the freedom to act in a
certain way – say, steal someone’s property – because it is forbidden. We say
that you may do something freely even if other options, unbeknownst to you,
are all closed. And yet we also say that you do not enjoy freedom in a certain
choice if there is only one alternative available: if, in effect, you are forced to
take that particular path. We say that you have a free choice between two
alternatives in a certain domain if those in charge there leave the decision up to
you. And yet we also say that you do not enjoy freedom in a choice if you can
make the decision only because others give you permission.
This variety of usage should not suggest that freedom-related words and
idioms are unconstrained and that like Humpty Dumpty we can make them
mean what we like. Describing a choice or action as free is always meant to
mark a contrast with some other choice or action. But one and the same act
may count as free in relation to one contrast and unfree in relation to another.
And so, as different contexts put different contrasts in play, we may find
ourselves ascribing freedom in the one case, unfreedom in the other. Take the
example where you are confined to bed on election day. By contrast with
another citizen who is not confined in that manner, you are not free to vote.
But by contrast with a non-citizen it remains perfectly sensible to say that you
are indeed free to vote. The predication of freedom is a useful way of marking
a contrast in each case, yet the contrast it marks differs from one case to the
other. And so we find ourselves saying what appear to be contradictory things
when, as a matter of fact, they are perfectly consistent.
These observations about the idioms of freedom mean that if we are to
build a political theory around the idea of freedom, then we have to regiment
things a little and rule on exactly how we are using the term and its cognates.
That is precisely what I do in Chapter 1, setting out the regimented, republican
understanding of freedom with which I shall be working. While the regimen-
tation builds on connotations of freedom that are recognized in ordinary talk –
otherwise it would not count as a theory of freedom – the final case for
preferring it to alternatives shows up in its capacity to underpin an independ-
ently attractive theory of justice, democracy and indeed sovereignty.
22
For other views on which democracy requires a degree of constitutional protection see Cohen (1989);
Habermas (1995); Holmes (1995). For concerns about the extent to which any degree of constitutional
protection can hamper democratic initiative, see Schwartzberg (2007) and Tully (2009). And for an
outright defence of the adequacy of electoral, majoritarian democracy see Waldron (1999a, 1999b).
24 Introduction. The republic, old and new
supports constitutional as well as electoral measures, then there is no reason
why it should support the precise sorts of institutions that characterize
extant regimes. Which precise measures it should support in any area will
be determined by empirical considerations, as well as the more abstract,
philosophical arguments advanced here; that is in the nature of institutional
design. But even the broad-brush strokes offered by way of sketching
possible institutional designs should make it absolutely clear that the agenda
supported by the republican argument is reformist and progressive in its
implications.
23
Michael Walzer’s (1981) complaint about the way in which philosophers ignore democracy, speaking
as if they had the authority of the sage, is fully consistent, I believe, with my viewpoint here. Like him,
I allow that most recommendations in normative political theory – all but the commitment to a fall-
back democracy – are democratically negotiable.
chapter 1
Freedom as non-domination
1
The ability or capacity to perform any option may be represented as coming in degrees, depending on
how easy the choice of the option is. Or it may be taken to have an on–off character, with the degree of
ease being registered at least implicitly in the characterization of the option. On the first approach we
would speak of the ability at a certain level of ease, L, to do X; on the second we would speak of the
ability in an on–off sense to do X-at-level-of-ease-L. While I avoid addressing this issue explicitly in the
current text, I follow broadly the second approach. Thus I argue that imposing an ease-reducing
penalty on doing X involves replacing the original option, X, by a different option, penalized-X. Such a
replacement may be more or less invasive, as I shall put it, depending on how large the penalty is. I am
grateful to Raffi Krut-Landau for a discussion of this point.
26
Freedom as non-domination 27
mail may not reach its destination because of problems at the post office – but
it is enough that as a matter of contingent fact there are no obstacles in the
way. Sending a letter to your correspondent is an option for you just to the
extent that the world happens to be compliant – there are no postal problems –
and success is in your hands.
There is a metaphysical issue about what has to be true of you as an agent in
order for it to be true that a choice is up to you: that you can make it the case
that the world in a moment from now is an X-world or a Y-world or a Z-
world – a world where a letter is on its way to your friend, or a world where it
isn’t. The question in particular is whether you can play this choice-resolving
role and yet be constituted, like every other natural entity, out of physical
constituents that conform to physical laws. This is the issue of whether you
have metaphysical freedom of will and it falls well outside our concerns here.
I shall just assume that you have the power of free will, however that is to be
understood, and ask about what social and other factors can impact on your
exercise of the power in such a way that, intuitively, they reduce your freedom
of choice.2
Almost all schools of thought agree that any factor that can reduce your
freedom of choice in that sense constitutes a hindrance that makes one or
another option unavailable: it removes some of the objective or cognitive
resources required for accessing the option, or it restricts your use of those
resources; it impairs or impedes the capacity that those resources establish.
But there is disagreement on two broad fronts: first, on the issue of what
has to be hindered in order for the freedom of a choice to be reduced; and
second, on what sorts of hindrances can impose a reduction of freedom.
I address the first issue in Section 1 and discuss different aspects of the
second issue in the three sections following.
In Section 1 I argue that your freedom of choice will be reduced by a
hindrance to any one of the options that characterize it, not just by a hindrance
to the option you prefer. In Section 2 I argue that your free choice of an option
may be hindered in either of two significantly different ways: one involves
vitiating factors, as I shall call them, the other factors of an invasive kind. In
the following two sections I then go on to explore the ways in which you may
2
For the record, my own view is that we should identify free will in the metaphysical sense with
conversability: a capacity to register and respond to reasons, as they are presented in interpersonal
conversation (Pettit and Smith 1996; Pettit 2001b, 2005b, 2007a). This, broadly, is the commonality
shared by those who are fit to be negotiated with from within what Peter Strawson (1962) calls the
participant as distinct from the objective stance. ‘Orthonomy’, which I mention later, is the virtue
displayed by someone to the extent that they successfully exercise conversability across the normal
human range. It constitutes free will in the psychological, as distinct from the metaphysical, sense.
28 Freedom as non-domination
suffer a loss of freedom through invasion, as distinct from vitiation. I argue in
Section 3 that domination – exposure to another’s power of uncontrolled
interference – is necessary for invasion: interference in the absence of domi-
nating power is not enough. And I argue in Section 4 that domination is
sufficient for invasion: you can suffer invasion without actually suffering
interference. Section 5 looks in the light of this discussion at what we others
can do to ensure your freedom in any choice, guarding you against vitiation
and invasion.
Assuming that vitiation is not a problem, the lesson of the chapter is that
freedom in a choice requires just the absence of domination; it is equivalent
to the freedom that was hailed as an ideal in the long tradition of republican
thought. While this equation of freedom with non-domination allows us to
say that domination with interference is worse in various ways than dom-
ination without interference, it marks the threshold where freedom begins
to fail at the point where domination, even domination without interfer-
ence, kicks in. With the argument for this understanding of freedom in
place, we can go on in the next chapter to ask after what it would mean to
establish equality for people in the enjoyment of freedom: that is, to ensure
an equal status for them as free citizens. This ideal amounts, as we shall see,
to a republican ideal of social justice.
Hobbes’s position
The best-known defender of the first answer is Thomas Hobbes. His view
of freedom – corporal freedom, to be exact (Pettit 2008c: Chapter 8) – is
3
I ignore a third possible answer, that in order to reduce your freedom every option other than at least
one has to be hindered – that you have to be more or less forced to perform the remaining option. This
answer hardly makes an appearance in the literature.
What has to be hindered to reduce freedom of choice? 29
summed up in his famous, consciously anti-republican definition of a free-
man (Skinner 2008b): ‘a free-man is he that in those things which by his
strength and wit he is able to do is not hindered to do what he has a will to’
(Hobbes 1994b: 21.2). According to this definition, a hindrance takes away
from your freedom in a choice only if it hinders an option that you have ‘a
will to’; only if you prefer the option that is subject to hindrance.
This claim is not just an implication of his definition that may have
escaped Hobbes’s attention. It is a thesis that he explicitly defends in a debate
with Bishop Bramhall about the preconditions for having a free choice
between playing tennis or not. Bramhall suggests that if you are considering
whether or not to play tennis – we assume a willing partner – and you decide
against doing so, then you may still have been wrong to think that you had a
free choice. After all, unbeknownst to you, someone may have shut the door
of the (‘real’) tennis court against you. Hobbes is undaunted by the claim,
asserting that for anyone in your position ‘it is no impediment to him that the
door is shut till he have a will to play’ (Hobbes and Bramhall 1999: 91).
The line that Hobbes takes here is that your freedom in a choice is reduced
only when there is a hindrance that frustrates you in the attempt to satisfy
your final preference between the options. There is no frustration if a
hindrance blocks you taking an option that, as it happens, you do not want
to take anyhow; and so in that case there is no loss of freedom either. We may
all agree that you freely decided against playing tennis and that you might
therefore be held responsible for this decision; after all, you thought you could
act on your preference, whatever that turned out to be, and as a matter of fact
you did act on the preference you formed (Frankfurt 1969).4 But is managing
to choose in accordance with the preference you form, even managing to do so
in the manner illustrated by the tennis example, all that freedom in a choice
requires? I argue not.5
There is a clear contrast between a case like that of the tennis example
and the case where all of the options, and not just the option preferred, are
unhindered. In the tennis-type case we can say that you made a choice
freely, but not that you had a choice between the option preferred and the
alternative, a choice between playing tennis and not playing tennis. In the
contrast case, both things are true: whatever you choose, you choose freely
and, moreover, you have a choice between the given options. The question
to consider is whether in fostering freedom of choice we ought to try to
4
In such a case the action you take is voluntary, in ordinary usage, being taken for reasons other than
that you have no (acceptable) alternative; on this conception of voluntariness see Olsaretti (2004).
5
For a different point of view, in which ‘voluntary’ is equated with ‘willing’, see Otsuka (2003: Chapter 5).
30 Freedom as non-domination
ensure that both things are true or just the one. Ought we to try to give
agents choice over which of the options to realize? Or ought we to try just to
ensure that their preference between the different options is satisfied?
These are distinct ideals and they have different ramifications for policy.
If we seek the richer goal, trying to keep all your options open, we will want
to invest resources in making each available, independently of what you are
likely to prefer. If we seek the more austere goal, trying merely to avoid
preference-frustration, we will want to invest resources in making an option
available only to the extent that it is likely that you will choose that option.
The richer ideal is more expensive in the resources required, the poorer
more economical. Where we do not have the resources to support the first
ideal, of course, it will make sense to focus on the second. But this does not
yet tell us which ideal is the more appealing, nor which answers better to the
ordinary notion of freedom of choice.
Berlin’s critique
Other things being equal, the richer ideal is certainly the more appealing,
since its satisfaction entails the satisfaction of the more austere counterpart:
if you can do whatever you might prefer, you will be able to do what you
happen actually to prefer. More importantly, however, that ideal also
answers better to our shared ideas about freedom of choice. It sustains the
natural assumption that if you enjoy freedom in a choice between certain
options, then it must be up to you whether one or another option is realized.
And it enables us to avoid some counter-intuitive results that plague the
Hobbesian view.
If we say that preference-satisfaction is enough for freedom of choice, as
Hobbes implies, then you may count as free in a choice, even when you are
forced to choose as you do; the force won’t matter so long as the action you
are forced to take is the one you prefer. We might choose to live with that
counter-intuitive result, arguing that other virtues in the Hobbesian approach
outweigh the cost of doing so. But there is still worse in store for us if we
stick with that approach, as Isaiah Berlin (1969: xxxix) has pointed out (Pettit
2011b).6
6
Berlin clearly focuses on this point only in the 1969 Introduction to the collection in which his 1958
lecture on ‘Two Concepts of Liberty’ was published and acknowledges doing so as a result of criticism
by an anonymous reviewer of the 1958 lecture in the Times Literary Supplement. That reviewer, it
appears, was Richard Wollheim. I am grateful to Albert Weale and Jonathan Wolff for throwing light
on this for me.
What has to be hindered to reduce freedom of choice? 31
If we say that preference-satisfaction is enough for freedom of choice, then
we have to acknowledge that there are two distinct ways in which you can
make yourself free in a choice between two options, X and Y, where you want
X and it happens to be obstructed. You may remove the hindrance so that
you can get what you want, i.e. X. Or you may work at changing your
preference, so that you come to want what you can get, i.e. Y. But, as Berlin
(1969: xxxix) argues, it is quite absurd to think that you might make yourself
free in this second manner: ‘to teach a man that, if he cannot get what he
wants, he must learn to want only what he can get may contribute to his
happiness or his security; but it will not increase his civil or political freedom’.
Berlin’s argument is worth setting out in detail.
1. Suppose with Hobbes that you enjoy freedom in a choice between X and
Y just in case you avoid hindrance in the option that you actually choose;
suppose that non-frustration is enough for freedom.
2. By that supposition, you do not enjoy freedom of choice in the case
where I hinder X, not Y, and you choose X.
3. But, by supposition, you would enjoy freedom of choice in that case, if
you were to choose Y.
4. If you know the situation, therefore, it appears that you can give yourself
freedom of choice, without constraining my hindrance, just by adapting
your preferences and choosing Y.
5. But this is absurd. You cannot make yourself free in the choice just by
accommodating yourself to my disposition to hinder your choice.
6. Thus the original supposition that non-frustration is enough for free-
dom of choice must be false.
In order to illustrate the problem, imagine that you are a prisoner who,
being forcibly imprisoned, does not have freedom of choice between staying
behind bars and living in the outside world. Do you lack freedom just because
the option you happen to prefer is living outside prison, as the Hobbesian
approach implies? If so, then you can make yourself free – you can give
yourself freedom in the choice between living in prison or outside – just by
adapting your preferences and coming to want to stay in prison. As Berlin
(1969: 139) expresses the thought, ‘I need only contract or extinguish my
wishes and I am made free.’ But this is patently absurd and argues powerfully
for rejecting the Hobbesian approach. Adaptation to a constraint cannot count
on any plausible way of thinking as a form of liberation from that constraint.7
7
While adaptation cannot plausibly make you free in the sense required, there is an independent sense
in which it may serve freedom: it can expand the range of choices available to you. Suppose you would
like to be able to choose between spending or not spending the odd weekend with me, where you can
32 Freedom as non-domination
Think of each option in a choice as a door, where an option is available
just when the door is open (Berlin 1969: xlviii). The lesson of this argument
is that it is not enough for freedom of choice in the ordinary sense that the
door you actually choose to push on happens to be open. It must also be the
case that any other option in the choice, any door that you might have
pushed on instead, is also open. Suppose we are considering whether you are
free in a choice between two options, X and Y. If you are truly to count as
having a free choice in the actual world, then you must not be hindered in
the actual world where you prefer X but equally you must not be hindered
in the possible world where you prefer Y.8 You must get what you actually
want but it must also be the case that you would have got the other option
had you wanted it instead.9 All doors must be open.
As against this point of view, a partisan of the Hobbesian position might
argue that it would be irrational to care about what happens should you
choose a particular option, say Y, when you think it vanishingly unlikely that
you might choose Y. And, building on that observation, the opponent might
urge that you should care about the hindrance to an option only in a way that
reflects the probability that you assign to choosing it.
This objection is misdirected. When you perform as a deliberative agent,
you think of yourself as someone able to choose between the available options,
someone on whom the choice depends. You conceive of yourself, in other
words, as the arbiter and author of whether the world will be one in which this
option materializes or one in which some alternative materializes. This self-
conception is inconsistent with indifference to the prospect of any option
only spend a weekend with me if you are prepared to go hiking, a prospect that is currently
unattractive. You might provide yourself with such a choice by working on your preferences and
making hiking into a tolerable prospect.
8
Is it enough that you enjoy the absence of hindrance in the actual world where you prefer X and in the
nearest possible world in which you choose the other option, Y? Or is it required that you can get X in
any of a wider range of worlds, including the actual one, in which you prefer X; and can get Y in any of
a wider range of possible worlds, including the nearest possible one, in which you prefer Y? My own
view is that you must escape hindrance for each option in a wider range of worlds; that this range of
worlds is discernible only on an intuitive, context-sensitive basis; and that it does not include all
possible worlds. These issues about the relationship between non-hindrance and freedom – about how
robust non-hindrance must be (Pettit 2001a; List 2004, 2006b) – are parallel to issues in epistemology
about the relation between true belief and knowledge; see for example Williamson (2000). I abstract
from them in the current discussion.
9
Strictly, there is a problem in saying that to be free in the choice of X, it must be the case that you could
have chosen the alternative, Y, had you wanted to – had you preferred that option. This condition
might be incapable of fulfilment because you are the sort of person who would only want to do Y if it
was not an available option; the possibility will be salient from Groucho Marx’s quip that he would
only want to join a club that would not accept him as a member. The problem can be overcome if what
is required is that you could have chosen Y had you tried to do so, where it is not required in that
eventuality that you actually prefer Y. For expressive convenience, I shall ignore this complication in
the text. I am grateful to Lara Buchak for alerting me to the problem.
What has to be hindered to reduce freedom of choice? 33
being hindered, even one you are unlikely to take. Any such hindrance will
compromise your status as an agent, pre-empting the capacity that you take
yourself – we assume, correctly – to possess. And so the prospect of any such
hindrance is bound to be unattractive.
This discussion began with the question as to what has to be hindered in
a given choice in order for the hindrance to reduce the agent’s freedom.
Following Berlin, I propose to understand freedom in such a way that in a
choice between given options, say X, Y and Z, or just X and Y, your freedom
can be reduced by the hindrance of any one of those options, regardless of
which you happen to prefer. Such a hindrance will make one or more of the
options unavailable, undermining your objective or cognitive resources. It
will mean that you are no longer in a position to say or think truly ‘I can
do X, or I can do Y, or I can do Z’. One or another of those disjuncts will be
false as a matter of fact or false as a matter of your perceptions.
11
For reasons familiar from the debate between evidential and causal decision theory, the hypothetical
probabilities P(H if X) and P(H if Y) should be understood, not as conditional probabilities, but in
one of the alternative modes consistent with causal decision theory. See Joyce (1999). Take the
conditional probability P(H/X), the probability of H given X. This might be low, not because X is an
open door, but because those who are capable of hindering you in the choice want you to choose X.
12
Waldron (2007) uses the fact that it may be sensible to invest resources on the basis of probability of
choice to argue, in effect, for linking freedom with the absence of frustration. For a response see Pettit
(2007a). Waldron adopts a position similar to that taken by Goodin and Jackson (2007), which I go
on to discuss in the text.
Vitiating and invasive hindrances 35
15
In earlier work I relied, not on the distinction between invading and vitiating hindrances, but on the
closely connected distinction between hindrances that compromise, and hindrances that condition,
freedom (Pettit 1997c: Chapter 2).
Vitiating and invasive hindrances 39
control of what you do. It may amount to usurping your control over the
choice, taking charge of what you do. Or it may amount to claiming a share
in that control, establishing limits on the extent to which you can select an
option according to your own preference.
This observation shows that subjection to the will of another, be it total
or partial, represents one way in which your choice may be invaded, being
subject to a specific rather than a generic hindrance. But such subjection to
another agent’s or agency’s will also looks to be the only way in which a choice
may be invaded. A hindrance that invades your choice between options has to
be triggered by your seeking to satisfy your will in that choice, rather than
materializing for independent reasons. And while that triggering condition
can be fulfilled in the presence of a will that competes with your own will for
control of what you do, it is hard to see how it could be met otherwise. Your
seeking to satisfy your will in a choice is hardly likely, for example, to trigger
the appearance of a natural obstacle to your getting your way. For these
reasons we may identify invasive hindrances to choice with hindrances that
reflect the will of another as to what you should do.
When we discuss the variety of invasive hindrances in the next section,
we shall see that others may impose their will on you without deliberately
hindering you – without, in that sense, interfering with you. But many
thinkers treat the interference that another inflicts on you as the paradigm of
an invasion of choice. They equate the invasion of choice with an inten-
tional attempt to usurp or claim a share in your control, or perhaps with a
quasi-intentional counterpart of such an attempt: say, the negligent failure
to take an expected level of care not to undermine your control (Miller
1984). Isaiah Berlin (1969: 122) is one of this group, holding that the primary
offence against freedom of choice is ‘the deliberate interference of other
human beings’.
What sorts of factors will count as vitiators rather than invaders of a free
choice? The answer should now be obvious. Any factors that deprive you of
resources required for freedom in that choice, or that limit the use to which
you can put those resources, without imposing the will of another as to what
you should do. Any factors, in other words, that impair or impede your
capacity to use your resources for satisfying your will but without deriving
from the intrusive will of another agent or agency. Thus any lack of personal,
natural or indeed social resources will vitiate your freedom in a choice,
provided it is not a lack deriving from the will of another agent or agency as
to how you in particular, or those in your particular category, should make
that choice. Such failures of resources may derive at any time from your own
illness or disability, from the limits of your natural environment, from the
40 Freedom as non-domination
continuing, damaging results on you or your environment of the invasion of
earlier choices, from the aggregate consequences of independently motivated
actions by others, or from the actions of another agent that are necessitated in
some way and not a matter of voluntary choice (Olsaretti 2004).
The line drawn between invasive and vitiating hindrances runs bright and
clear in most cases, but it is less salient with the hindrances that derive from
the actions that others take. There is a big difference between the case where
you deny me the option of reading the newspaper, as in invasive interference,
and the case where that option ceases to be available because most other
people come to rely on electronic sources of news, put the newspaper out
of business, and thereby vitiate my choice of reading the newspaper. But
what, for example, of the case where there is only one copy of the newspaper
available, you and I both wish to read it and, recognizing the competition
between us, you grab it first, thereby frustrating me? Or what about the case
where the union of workers in the newspaper office calls a strike in order to
punish the management but fully recognize that this will frustrate readers like
me? Does such an act count as invasion or vitiation?
I say in each case that it counts as invasion. You may not wish to impose
your will on me as such, lamenting the fact that we cannot both read the
newspaper, but you impose your will on me – you actively and deliberately
interfere with me – for the instrumental reason that that is the only way in
which you can satisfy your own will. Equally, the union in the newspaper
office may not wish to impose their will on readers like me just for its own sake;
they may only impose their will on us for the instrumental reason that that is
the best way in which they can pressurize management to improve wages or
conditions. We may not take such a contingently motivated invasion to be as
bad as an invasion pursued for its own sake. And, to anticipate the argument of
the next chapter, we may not think that invasions of that type ought always to
be prohibited in a free society. But on the line taken here we clearly have to say
that nonetheless it counts as a straightforward case of invasion.
In invasions of these kinds, whether inherently or contingently hostile, you
exercise a power of interfering or not interfering with me, depending on your
will. Both forms of interference contrast, however, with the vitiating sort of
constraint you impose on me when you have no choice, by whatever criteria,
but to impose a certain constraint: you intervene in my choice, but out of
necessity, not out of a will – a free will, as we might say – to intervene rather
than not intervene. Thus, if we think that you have no choice but to seek your
own preservation in a certain context, and if your doing so impacts negatively
on me, then the constraint you impose constitutes a vitiating, not an invasive,
hindrance to my choice. You impose more or less involuntarily on me.
Vitiating and invasive hindrances 41
The relevance of vitiating hindrances
Hobbes acknowledges the importance of vitiating hindrances when he says,
as we saw, that a person makes a free choice in virtue of not being hindered
‘in those things which by his strength and wit he is able to do’. He implies
thereby that you can be free to choose an option only if you have the ‘strength
and wit’ – in our terms, the objective and cognitive resources – to be able to
enact it; only if it lies, as we say, within your capacity. And he contrasts
the way in which you can be deprived of your freedom by a vitiating failure
on this front – as, for example, when you are like ‘a man fastened to his bed
by sickness’ – with the invasive way you may be deprived of freedom by
‘external impediments’ (Hobbes 1994b: 21.1). In the latter case you are made
properly unfree, as we might put it; in the former you are made non-free, not
being eligible as a candidate for the enjoyment of freedom (Pettit 2008c:
Chapter 8).
Our distinction between invaders and vitiators of choice diverges from
Hobbes’s in two connected ways. First, it recognizes resources beyond the
internal resources of strength and wit on which he focuses. And second,
it breaks with his approach in associating invading resources only with
will-imposing hindrances and not, as he does, with any external impedi-
ments.16 Still, abstracting from those differences, our claim that there are
two sharply divided kinds of hindrances to freedom is broadly faithful to
the Hobbesian view.
Where the standpoint adopted in the last section put us on Berlin’s side
and against Hobbes, it turns out that the standpoint adopted in this not only
puts us on Hobbes’s side; it also puts us against Berlin. For Berlin (1969: 122)
maintains, quite assertively, that freedom in a choice does not require the
absence of vitiators, only the absence of invaders. ‘Mere incapacity to attain a
goal is not lack of political liberty,’ he says, where he clearly means the sort of
incapacity produced by vitiation. The observation behind his claim is that we
can say that you are free to vote or not to vote, for example, just in case the
government does not deny you the vote and regardless of whether you have
the capacity to get to the polling station: regardless, for example, of whether
you are fastened to your bed by sickness. Berlin generalizes this conception of
liberty, arguing that the freedom to make a choice, even in the ordinary sense
16
Despite these differences, it is not misleading to think of Hobbes as looking for a distinction, similar
to ours, that will mark off inherently inimical from incidentally inimical deprivations of freedom.
Given that he thinks of all resources as internal, and of failures that deprive an agent of those resources
as incidental, he may think of external impediments as targeting the use of those resources – their use,
necessarily, in the external forum – in an attempt to satisfy the agent’s will.
42 Freedom as non-domination
in which we predicate such freedom, does not ever entail the capacity to make
that choice: it does not require the presence of the resources that would make
the choice feasible.
We do often speak of liberty in the sense in which it is enough for freedom
of choice that the choice is not blocked by government or by any other
agency. But, going back to a theme in the Introduction, I think that this usage
is quite special, being useful only in certain contexts. Thus in the context of
marking the person’s citizenship it might serve a useful purpose to ascribe
the freedom to vote to the person who is sick in bed. It would be highly
misleading to say more generally, however, that you can enjoy the freedom to
choose between certain options, even when you lack the capacity to exercise
the choice (Van Parijs 1995). In most contexts to say that you are free to choose
between the options – that in that sense you have freedom of choice – is to
imply that the option to be realized is up to you. And it can be up to you only
if you have the resources and capacity to make such a choice: only if you are
free of vitiation, not just free of invasion.
The connection between freedom and responsibility reinforces this intui-
tive claim (Pettit 2001e). Suppose you believe that you have freedom of choice
between options, X, Y and Z. Under standard assumptions about the con-
nection between freedom and responsibility, you will have to think that you
are fit to be held responsible for whatever you choose: you can be blamed or
praised, as appropriate, depending on the merits of the option selected. But if
you believe that you lacked the objective or cognitive resources needed for
choosing one or another of the options, then you could not think that you are
fit to be held responsible for choosing that option. Hence your belief that you
have freedom of choice between the three options requires you to believe that
you have all the resources required for choosing any of them.17
The difference between the view adopted here and that which Berlin
espouses is of importance to how we keep the books on freedom but it need
not mark a substantial divergence in ultimate commitments. The reason is
that while Berlin thinks that strictly speaking the freedom to choose between
certain options does not require the capacity to do so, he insists that freedom
will be of little value in the absence of such a capacity. ‘What is freedom to
those who cannot make use of it?’ he asks. ‘Without adequate conditions for
the use of freedom, what is the value of freedom?’ (Berlin 1969: 124; see too lii).
Treating freedom as a bundle of legal, not necessarily effective, liberties,
John Rawls (1971) also distinguishes between what freedom requires, strictly
17
I am grateful to Daniel Berntson for discussion on this point.
Vitiating and invasive hindrances 43
speaking, and what it requires if it is to be valuable. We shall see in the next
chapter that this is an important feature of Rawls’s view and that it is relevant
to the comparison between his theory of justice and the theory that a
republican approach would support.
18
The primacy of will-imposed hindrances – usually identified with acts of interference – is denied by
Van Parijs (1995). Others are sympathetic with this viewpoint but concede that will-imposed
hindrances should be given priority on the superficial grounds that they are more salient candidates
for political remedy than other sorts of hindrances (Steiner 1994; Carter 1999; Kramer 2003). On the
relevance of political salience see Carter (2008: 62). Most approaches, like that adopted here, take will-
imposed hindrances to have priority over other hindrances on deeper, less contingent grounds.
19
This comment explains why the theory of freedom developed here is capable of allowing for the
systemic dangers to freedom that Clarissa Hayward (2011) rightly emphasizes. It provides a reason for
recognizing what I later describe as structural domination. My thanks to Maeve Cook for a helpful
exchange on this point.
Vitiating and invasive hindrances 45
certain options and the subjection to another’s will, the invasion by another,
that denies you the chance to make the choice according to your will. The
emerging picture shows that there are two dimensions to freedom of choice:
on the one side, the freedom that goes with the unvitiated range of choices
available; and on the other the freedom that goes with not being invaded by
others in the exercise of those choices. The unvitiated resources at your
disposal define a range of effective opportunities, and to the extent to which
that range is wider, you have greater latitude for choice, greater freedom of
opportunity. Being in a position to use those resources without invasion –
not being subject to the will of another, however partially, on the matter of
how you exercise the capacity they give you – will enable you to exploit
those opportunities more effectively.20 Where the unvitiated resources
ensure your freedom of opportunity, the absence of subjection and invasion
ensures your freedom of exercise or control.21
This observation teaches an important lesson about measuring freedom of
choice. Suppose we want to determine how two people fare in their freedom
of choice. The most obvious way to do this will be to take a range of option-
sets or choices as reference points – the choice between X and Y, the choice
between V and W, and so on – and then to ask how the agents compare in
opportunity-freedom and exercise-freedom, how they compare in latitude
and control, with respect to those choices: how far they avoid vitiation, on the
one side, and invasion on the other.22
Even if we think that comparisons of freedom of choice ought to be made
by reference to the same range of option-sets, however, we may take any of
a number of routes. One approach would be to assume equal unvitiated
capacity across those option-sets – that is, to assume equal freedom of
20
Here I make use of the notion of opportunity and exercise popularized by Charles Taylor (1985a) in
his distinction between opportunity and exercise concepts of freedom.
21
Eric McGilvray (2011) gives an illuminating account of how the traditional republican way of thinking
about liberty came to be ousted by the new commercial or market conception of liberty in the
nineteenth century; he links the latter with the earlier notion of natural liberty that figured prominently
in the juristic tradition. Among the two conceptions he describes we might say that the republican
tended to focus on the absence of servitude, the commercial on the presence of latitude.
22
The most salient alternative to this approach would be to follow Hobbes and argue that how much
freedom two people enjoy depends on how far they each enjoy exercise-freedom in respect of the
different options within their personal, idiosyncratic capacity: how far each is unhindered in ‘the
things which by his wit and power he is able to do’. But this alternative would have the absurd
consequence that the prince who can do lots of things – the prince who has enormous freedom of
opportunity – may count as no more free than the pauper who has few if any opportunities for choice.
The measurement of freedom of choice ought to be option-relative, as Hobbes would agree, but
comparisons of freedom will make best sense if two people are measured against the same range of
option-sets rather than each being measured against a different range: those that happen to lie within
their own capacity and to constitute effective opportunities for choice.
46 Freedom as non-domination
opportunity – and to try to chart variations in the degree to which people are
subject to invasion from others: that is, variations in their freedom of exercise
or control. Another would be to assume equal freedom of exercise and to chart
variations in their freedom of opportunity: variations in their unvitiated
capacity to exercise choice across the different option-sets. And yet another
would be to assume neither sort of freedom and to try to track variations in
both dimensions across the same option-set. This project would require us to
assign relative weights to vitiating and invasive hindrances.
Whichever of these paths we take, the measurement of freedom raises
a daunting challenge. It is deeply unclear how exactly we should weight
vitiating and invasive hindrances against one another, though my earlier
comments argue for giving invasive hindrances some priority. And equally it
is unclear how we should measure and compare different levels of freedom
within the category of exercise on the one side or opportunity on the other.
We shall see in the next two sections that there are different ways in which
your freedom of exercise or control may be hindered: that is, different ways in
which your choices may be invaded. Your freedom to choose between X, Y
and Z, to anticipate that discussion, may be reduced by suffering uncontrolled
interference on the part of another – interference can involve the removal,
replacement or misrepresentation of one or more options – or just by suffer-
ing domination: that is, just by being exposed to a power of uncontrolled
interference on the part of the other. And to add to the complexity that this
distinction introduces, there are different degrees in which a given option may
be removed, replaced or misrepresented; there are different degrees in which
such interference may be uncontrolled by you; and there are different degrees
in which you may be exposed to a power of uncontrolled interference. Since
it is unclear how exactly to measure or commensurate such variations in
degree it is clearly going to be extremely difficult to measure the extent to
which a hindrance may reduce your exercise-freedom in the choice.
There are similar difficulties in store on the issue of how to measure and
compare degrees of opportunity-freedom, despite the fact that the issue has
received a good deal of attention in recent literature (Sugden 1998; Carter
1999; Kramer 2003). Just to illustrate the sort of problems that arise here, take
a set of options X, Y and Z in which you and another have the same freedom
of exercise: there is no one in a position to subject either of you to their will.
And imagine now that you only have the opportunity to choose X or Y and
the other has the opportunity to choose any of the three options. Presumably
that means that you have lesser opportunity-freedom. But what are we to say
about the degree by which your freedom falls short? Do we think that the
shortfall is the same, regardless of how far the new option, Z, is intuitively
Vitiating and invasive hindrances 47
different from X and Y, for example, or regardless of how far it represents an
option that you value or ought to value? If X and Y involve drinking one or
another beer, does it matter that Z is a beer rather than a wine option, or a
beer or wine option that you would particularly like to have?
Should these observations lead us to despair about the prospect of measur-
ing freedom of choice? I think that there is reason not to expect a plausible,
more or less mechanical algorithm for ordering all possible variations in
people’s fortunes on a common scale of freedom. But we need not despair
about being able to establish some accepted standards whereby, for a given
range of choices, we can compare and order the more salient differences found
amongst the citizens of a given society or, perhaps, across two or more distinct
societies.
This issue will be central to the next chapter, when we consider how we
might pursue the goal of securing equal freedom as non-domination for the
members of a society. We shall see in that context that it makes good sense
to identify a range of significant choices or option-sets – the basic liberties,
as I think of them – and to look for a system that safeguards against
shortfalls from a culturally established, common yardstick in the extent to
which people have the opportunity to make those choices and in the extent
to which they avoid subjection to the will of others in how they exploit that
opportunity. I take the relevant yardstick to be set by what I call the eyeball
test. At the level set by this test, the safeguards should enable people, by local
standards, to look one another in the eye without reason for fear or
deference. The achievement of that discernible and applicable ideal would
make, intuitively, for the equality of people in their status as free persons or
citizens: that is, in the free status that has long been an ideal in republican
thinking.
23
Here I follow MacCallum (1967) in assuming, for simplicity, that even the notion of positive liberty
can be cast as requiring the absence of an obstacle. But the notion of positive liberty is often associated
with late nineteenth-century liberalism in Britain – modern liberalism, as it was then called (Gaus
1983) – and in that tradition positive liberty consisted, not in escaping internal obstacles, but in
making positive use of their absence by achieving a form of self-realization (Baldwin 1984). Note that
while I go along with MacCallum’s schema here I break with it in the next chapter when I argue that
the freedom of a person does not just require the absence of certain obstacles but, more specifically, an
absence that is secured by a rule of accepted norm and law.
24
The notion of autonomy or self-governance is employed by another set of thinkers for purposes of
developing, not an ideal of personal life, but an ideal also for politics. See for example Christman (2009).
No invasion without domination 49
There is a perfectly good sense in which freedom of choice requires some
version of autonomy or orthonomy – some kind of psychological freedom,
as it might be put (Pettit 2001e) – but I will be ignoring it in the present
context. Our concern is with your freedom of revealed will, not with
whether the will that you reveal counts as your true or real will. This is
appropriate in a book on political philosophy. All of us face a challenge as to
whether the will we form in one or another domain of choice answers to
standards of autonomy or orthonomy. But that is a psychological or ethical
challenge, not one that can plausibly be laid to the charge of a collective,
coercive agency like the state.
I mentioned early in the chapter that we are not concerned in this book
with what gives you metaphysical free will: that is, with what makes you
into an agent with the capacity, however that is understood, to take one or
another option in a given choice. What we have just seen is that equally we
are not concerned with what gives you psychological free will, enabling
you to form your will autonomously, however autonomy is understood.
Our concern is solely with social free will or, in effect, political freedom: that
is, with what is required for it to be the case that however imperfectly
formed your will may be, you are in a position to make your choice, without
vitiation or invasion, according to that will.
25
Perhaps because of wanting to make it easier to measure and compare the degree of freedom that people
enjoy, some recent thinkers have argued for limiting the interference that can reduce freedom of choice
to the removal of an option in this sense – to what is often described as prevention (Steiner 1994; Carter
1999; Kramer 2003). Representatives of this view of freedom, sometimes described as the pure negative
theory (Carter 2008), have elaborated the most systematic, freedom-based alternative to republican
theory. While I believe that the two theories have to be judged ultimately on the basis of a methodology
of reflective equilibrium, as indicated in the Introduction, I think that this rival theory has to live with
some strikingly counter-intuitive judgements on how freedom may be reduced in a given choice. On
the one side, it would force us to ignore activities whereby I do not remove an option in the choice but I
do replace it; for debate on the claim that still I reduce your ‘overall freedom’ in such a case see Kramer
(2008) and Pettit (2008d). On the other, it would force us to ignore activities in which I do not interfere
with how things are as a matter of actual fact but I do interfere with how they are according to your
perceptions; I impose a cognitive rather than an objective restriction on you. And, on the face of it, those
interventions have a capacity to impose my will on you, as argued in the text.
52 Freedom as non-domination
choice between X, Y and Z-minus. It prevents you from choosing Z, albeit not
in the sense in which the actual removal of that option would do this.
Why say that penalizing an option means replacing it? The question
raises some tricky issues about the individuation of options but, for the
record, my own approach is as follows. I assume that for any agent there are
features or properties such that their presence reliably supports the attrac-
tion or aversion felt for a given prospect or option (Pettit 1991, 2005c). I hold
that a given option ceases to be the same option – it shifts identity – in the
case of any alteration in such a desiderative feature. To impose a penalty or
even the chance of a penalty on one of your options, then, is presumably to
change its desiderative features and to replace it by a different option. But to
impose a change that does not alter the desiderative features is not to replace
the original option; it changes the option but does not replace it.26
Thus, to explain how this stipulation should be understood, I do not
replace the option of your reading, as distinct from not reading, a book just
by moving the book from your left side to your right. This changes the
option but not in a desiderative and relevant fashion. Nor do I replace that
option just by offering you a reward for not reading it. This makes for a
desiderative change but not for a change in the option itself.27 While the
offer raises the opportunity cost of that option, as economists say, this just
means that there is now a more attractive alternative than previously.28
Assuming that desiderative features are not subject to much variation across
people, or at least across people in a given culture, we can take the replace-
ment of an option always to involve a change in any socially recognized
26
On the approach sketched, I can change any of your options by associating it with a property that
matters to you, whether it matters in a personal, self-regarding way or matters in a wholly impartial
manner: it reflects your moral vision of the universe. We might vary the picture by restricting the
relevant properties to ones in the self-regarding category. This would guard against the consequence,
which I am prepared to live with, that I can restrict your freedom by ensuring that should you take a
certain option then some bad consequence will follow for people elsewhere for whom you have a
moral, though not a personal, concern.
27
I rely here on an intuitive sense of the distinction between changes that alter a thing itself and
Cambridge changes, as they are sometimes called: changes such as the change I undergo when
someone emigrates from the country and I become thereby the nth oldest resident. An option
changes when its character or consequences change, as we may put it, but it does not change just
because there is a change somewhere else in the world. In our example it does not change – or, to
anticipate the next footnote, does not necessarily change – because of a change in the alternatives.
28
Although increasing the opportunity cost of an option does not necessarily change the identity of the
option, the nature of alternatives can sometimes affect the identity of an option. Taking an apple and
leaving an orange for your companion is a different option from taking the apple where the alternative
is a smaller apple; in the former case it is a perfectly polite option, but in the latter it is not, and
politeness is a presumptively desiderative feature. See Pettit (1991).
No invasion without domination 53
feature of that kind: in any established desirability characterization, to use a
term of Elisabeth Anscombe’s (1957).29
Although the replacement of an option, Z, makes it strictly impossible
to choose Z, as distinct from Z-minus, it does so in a sense that allows us
to distinguish between many different grades of interference. There are
degrees in how far an option may be removed or replaced, since it may be
removed or replaced across a smaller or larger range of possible scenarios.
But there are also other, more salient differences in the degree to which an
option may be replaced. The penalty attached to Z may be lesser or
greater, to go back to our example, and Z-minus may vary in a lesser or
greater degree from Z. It may even be so small a penalty, as we say, that it
does little or nothing to stop you from ignoring the penalty and still
choosing Z-minus. The removal of the option, Z, would prevent you
across relevant variations of scenario from choosing any Z-like option; the
replacement of the option prevents you from choosing only the narrowly
individuated Z – in effect, Z unpenalized. Your freedom in the choice
will be reduced by any penalty and any replacement – you will strictly
be denied a choice between X, Y and Z – but it may not be reduced,
intuitively, by much. This observation points us to a particularly striking
respect in which the measurement of freedom is bound to be a complex
project.
If a penalty or threat of a penalty can invade your freedom of choice, do we
have to say that a reward or offer of a reward – an ordinary, non-mesmerizing
reward – can have the same effect? Do we have to say that I restrict your
choice by offering you a regular, non-mesmerizing reward for choosing X, for
example, introducing the enhanced option of X-rewarded or X-plus? That
depends on whether the reward is refusable or not. If it is not refusable, so
that your options are now X-plus, Y and Z, then we have to say that I have
replaced one option and restricted your choice between X, Y and Z. But if the
reward is refusable, as rewards generally are, then I will not have had any
restrictive effect. It will still be the case with each of the three original options
that you can choose that option; for all I have done, you will still have all the
objective resources required and, we may assume, all the cognitive resources
too. I will have added a further option, X-plus, to that set of options but I will
29
The assumption entails that we cannot easily change our attachment to one or another feature. And that
is independently important in my perspective. Otherwise, you might be able to make yourself free in
certain choices by adapting so that the options are individuated in a way that removes obstacles:
adaptation might promise liberation. I am grateful to Hrishikesh Joshi for pressing the point.
54 Freedom as non-domination
have left each of the original options, X, Y and Z, in place.30 Thus the offer of
a reward does not serve to restrict your choice.31
We have seen that I may restrict a choice of yours by removing or replacing
one or more of the options you face, changing the set of alternatives that is
objectively available. But I can also restrict your choice by changing how the
alternatives present themselves according to your perceptions: by putting
apparent but merely pretend options on the table, thereby misrepresenting
the actual options in place. An option will be available for your choice just
insofar as you can make use, first, of the objective resources required for taking
it rather than any alternative and, second, the cognitive resources needed to
identify and understand the options on offer, to see that you are in a position
to choose any one of them, and so to decide on what you prefer. Apart from
affecting the use of your objective resources in order to change the choice you
face, I can act to similar effect on the use of your cognitive resources. And that
type of action should count equally as a mode of interfering with you: a
potential way of restricting your exercise of choice.
There are two distinct strategies I might adopt with a view to misrepre-
senting your options, each of which comes, like removal and replacement, in
degrees. One is deception; the other manipulation. If I deceive you about the
options available in a choice, or about the consequences they are likely to
trigger, I can obviously lead you to believe that the options are other than,
as a matter of fact, they are. I can act on you so that the set of options you
confront, according to your perceptions, is not X, Y and Z, but a set in which
one or another option is removed or replaced or a further option is added.
I will do this for example if I misinform you about the options on offer, or
issue a bluff threat to penalize one of them, or even make an insincere offer to
reward its choice. These are all means whereby I can impose cognitive, if not
objective, limits on your exercise of choice.
This observation raises a natural question. It should be clear why I can
restrict your choice by removing or replacing an option according to your
perceptions, since removing or replacing an option as a matter of actual
fact has the same effect; in either case I will deny you access to the option
affected. But I do not restrict your choice by the objective addition of a
30
Adding X-plus will change the opportunity costs of taking any of the other options, in particular,
X. But I am assuming, as mentioned earlier in the text, that a change in the opportunity cost of an
option does not entail a change of identity.
31
What if the offer is exploitative, taking advantage of your lack of acceptable alternatives and offering
an X-plus that is manifestly unfair? Strictly, the offer will not reduce your freedom in that particular
choice, though you may count as taking the offered option involuntarily (Olsaretti 2004). But the
offer may establish a relationship between us, as exploitation is generally taken to do, in which I
dominate you. Similar remarks apply to the offer of the blackmailer.
No invasion without domination 55
further option, as when I make an offer and add X-plus to the set. So why
do I do so when I lead you to believe falsely that another option like X-plus
is available?
When I add an option objectively to your choice, allowing you to see the
actual options available, then it remains up to you whether you choose X or Y
or Z; it’s just that you have the extra possibility of choosing X-plus instead.
Thus I leave you in a position where you can act on your will or preference,
whatever that should turn out to be. When I deceive you about the availability
of an extra option like X-plus, however, the apparent availability of X-plus
affects the presentation of X. It makes the option of choosing X, which is all
that is actually available to you, look like an option that can have the reward
attached. In effect, it replaces the option X, as it is cognitively registered, by a
pair of options: X-and-refuse-the-reward, or X-and-accept-the-reward.
I will not succeed in deceiving you, and so not succeed in restricting your
freedom, if you realize that I am deceptive and ignore what I say. But what of
the case where I do successfully deceive you but do not stop you choosing as
you would have done in my absence? What of the case where I issue a bluff
threat to penalize an option, say Y, and this is not enough to make you change
your mind: you still opt for Y? Can I be said to restrict your choice in this sort
of case? I will have forced you to choose from amongst a set of apparent options
that did not conform to the set actually available. Where the actual choice was
between X, Y and Z, I forced you to choose as if it were a choice between X,
Y-minus and Z. It may be a happy result that having formed a will to take
Y-minus, you actually get something better, plain Y. But nonetheless, I forced
you to form your will in the dark, not on the basis of how things actually were.
Apart from deceiving you, I may deny you the use of your cognitive
resources in making a certain choice by recourse to what I call manipula-
tion. Manipulation denies you the possibility of making a choice on the
basis of a proper understanding of the options on offer. It applies pressures
that affect your exercise of the capacity to think straight about the consid-
erations for and against different choices and so about the nature of the
options on offer. Manipulation may involve hypnotizing you, mesmerizing
you with the prospect of extraordinary rewards, making you feel guilty
about not doing what I wish, snowing you with so much information that
you are putty in my hands, or exposing you, if I am capable of it, to the
undermining power of my rhetoric.
Like successful deception, successful manipulation will affect the exercise
of your cognitive capacity to choose between certain options, even if it
leaves your objective capacity in place. By means of manipulation, I may
succeed in getting you to choose as I wish, but even if I fail in that, I will still
56 Freedom as non-domination
have restricted your choice by getting you to face what seem like different
options from those that were objectively available. I rig things so that your
will between X, Y and Z – the will you would form if you saw those options
for what they truly are – does not dictate the action you take; rather it is
dictated by your will over the distorted versions of those options that
I conjure into existence.32
In summary of what we have argued, then, there are three ways in which
I may interfere with you and restrict your choice: by removing options, by
replacing options or by misrepresenting options. And misrepresentation
can involve removing, replacing or adding an option in your cognitive
perception of things. The different modes of interference are salient in the
questions and answers mapped in the accompanying Table 1.2.
33
I assume in this example, and I make analogous assumptions in the other cases where I apply the
lesson of the example, that the will that you display in giving instructions can be identified as suitably
stable or authoritative in comparison with the will that the instructions require me to frustrate. There
are a number of ways in which this assumption might be vindicated but I do not pursue them here.
58 Freedom as non-domination
example is that there can be no active invasion of choice unless there is
domination. The active, intentional restriction of your choice by any other
agent or agency will be invasive only to the extent that it reflects a will that
you do not control.
The republican lesson about uncontrolled interference has often been
formulated in the claim that, provided it is non-arbitrary, interference does
not subject you to an alien will. Arbitrary interference, on this interpretation, is
interference practised in accordance with the arbitrium, or ‘will’, of another. It
is precisely what I describe here as uncontrolled interference: that is, interfer-
ence that is exercised at the will or discretion of the interferer; interference that
is uncontrolled by the person on the receiving end (Skinner 2008a).
In what follows I shall make little or no use of the term ‘arbitrary’,
preferring to speak of uncontrolled interference. The reason is that while I
believe that in earlier republican usage the word had something close to the
meaning I ascribe, it has other, misleading connotations today. In one usage,
arbitrary interference is interference that is not subject to established rules.
But interference that conforms to rules, and is non-arbitrary in that sense, may
still be uncontrolled by you and can count as arbitrary in our sense. In another
usage, arbitrary interference is interference that is wrong or objectionable,
so that what is arbitrary from one evaluative standpoint may not be arbitrary
from another. But while uncontrolled interference is going to count as
uniformly objectionable in most moral views, even those who adopt a contrary
view – even someone, for example, like Hobbes – ought to be able to agree on
whether, and to what extent, an act of interference counts as uncontrolled
and arbitrary in our usage. On that usage the term has a perfectly descriptive,
determinable meaning and people can agree on when it applies and when it
does not apply, independently of differences in the values they espouse; it is
not a value-dependent or moralized term.34
It may be useful to add one further comment about treating licensed or
controlled interference as non-invasive of free choice. This is that the con-
cession does not allow paternalistic interference. When I am being paternal-
istic I interfere in your choice according to your interests, though not
necessarily according to your wishes. But interests are always open to inter-
pretation, since they consist roughly in the wishes that you would have for
yourself, if you were able to view your predicament accurately and rationally
34
For an understanding of ‘non-arbitrary’ that preserves the rule-conformity connotation, though
without creating a great gulf between us, see Lovett (2010). For an evaluative understanding of the
term, but again one that does not create any substantive divergence of views, see Richardson (2002).
For a critique of my position that turns on related issues see McMahon (2005) – and for related
discussion, Costa (2007) – and for my response to that critique see Pettit (2006a).
No domination without invasion 59
(Geuss 1981; Smith 1994). And to the extent that I impose my own inter-
pretation on your interests, discounting yours as inferior, I act paternalistically
(Shiffrin 2000). Such paternalistic intervention, in the nature of the case,
involves interfering according to my own arbitrium, or ‘will’, not yours, and is
an exemplar of domination. The most that might be allowed on the repub-
lican view is interference according to interests that you are disposed or ready
to avow, where that readiness is easily tested and established; only this could
give you the control required to avoid domination (Pettit 2001e).
35
Note that if we include the non-standard resources activated under your belief that I have a power of
interference, intimidation will count as a form of invigilation; the distinction depends on requiring
invigilation to depend on standard, presupposed resources of interference. Note also that while
intimidation without invigilation depends on your falsely believing that I have a power of interfer-
ence, it is distinct from deception, considered as a particular, intentional act of deceiving you about
the options available in the relevant choice. This is to clarify how I keep the books on these questions,
but not to suggest that it is a uniquely appropriate way of doing so. I am grateful to Dorothea Gadeke
for discussion on this point.
No domination without invasion 63
Can I alienate my power of interference, and suspend the domination
I practise, by persuading myself that it is wrong to interfere in your choice?
Will the moral constraints that I thereby recognize act as checks on my will
and serve to liberate you, whether wholly or in part? I do not think so. Even
if I form the view that it is wrong to interfere with you, it remains the case
that I may prefer to practise interference, whether out of weakness of will,
out of malice, or out of a will for evil; the option continues to lie within my
capacity. My power of interference in your choice, and my domination over
you, can only be contained by external checks that remove or replace the
interference option or put it cognitively off the menu. My believing in the
wrongness of interfering will only introduce an external check to the extent
that I am thereby exposed, as I see things, to the penalty of moral disap-
probation for behaving in that way.
For those who continue to baulk at the idea that domination without
interference constitutes an invasion of your freedom, subjecting you to
my will, there is one last consideration worth introducing. This is that such
subjection is enough in itself to trigger the resentment that, as we saw,
typically characterizes the invasion, as distinct from the vitiation, of choice.
You may not resent me for the power that I am given by social convention or
natural prowess over you, since I am not responsible for having such power.
But it would only be human of you to resent me for acquiescing in the power
and, in particular, to resent the failure of the society not to rectify that
imbalance and affirm your equal standing. You may burn with such resent-
ment, as documented in oral and literary tradition, even as you recognize that
I do not want to have a power of interference and even think it wrong to
exercise that power against you.
These observations are interesting in themselves, but they also suggest that
we should recognize an indirect or structural form of domination as well as the
direct or personal kind, willed or unwilled, that we have been describing
(Hayward 2011). It is usually because of the ways a society is organized,
culturally, economically or legally, that some people have such power in
relation to others that they dominate them directly, and dominate them
without necessarily wishing for domination or even approving of it. Thus it
is usually because of the way that marriage law or workplace law is structured
that husbands or employers have a dominating power over their wives or
workers. These modes of organization may vitiate, but not invade, choice, as
when they emerge for example from customary practice, but they can indi-
rectly facilitate the worst forms of invasion and domination in a society. The
republican theory of justice, which we discuss in the next chapter, is designed
in great part to target such structural domination, looking for measures
64 Freedom as non-domination
whereby people can be assured on a public basis of not being dominated by
others in the broad range of the basic liberties.
36
The point is more easily lost in the ingratiation case, it should be noticed, than in the case of
adaptation. We can readily imagine cases in which one single episode of ingratiation secures access for
you to a range of undominated choices. And in such cases it is easy to forget about the question of
whether the choice in which ingratiation enabled you to get your way was itself free – I say it was not –
and to focus on the fact that in view of the new choices that become available, the ingratiation was
66 Freedom as non-domination
Adaptation may be a rational response to the frustration imposed by
another, since it does indeed give you a second-best: if not freedom to satisfy
your preference, regardless of what you prefer to do, at least the formation of
a preference you can satisfy. And ingratiation may equally be a rational
response to another’s power of interference, since it also gives you a second-
best: if not freedom to satisfy your preference, regardless of what others
prefer that you do, at least enough breathing space to let you act as you will.
It may not give you the benefits of a secure peace in your relations with the
powerful, but it will give you the consolations of a fragile cease-fire.
The gain secured in each case allows us to say, in ordinary usage, that by
contrast with the situation where you do not make such responses you can
win a degree of freedom for yourself by adaptation or ingratiation. This is
because in ordinary usage, as we have seen, talk of freedom is often used to
mark context-sensitive contrasts, so that one and the same choice may be
described as free or unfree, depending on the contexts under comparison.
But no matter what the context of usage, the benefit that you win by
adaptation or ingratiation is not freedom in the regimented sense that we
have been developing; in this sense, freedom of choice requires that every
option be accessible and that your access to any option be independent of
the preference of another as to what you should do.
We can give nice expression to this sense of freedom by elaborating on
Berlin’s open-doors metaphor. Where the anti-adaptation assumption
means that all the options in a free choice have to be open doors, the
anti-ingratiation claim implies that not any mode of openness will do. Are
you free just insofar as both doors are open in the choice between X and Y?
Not necessarily. What freedom ideally requires is not just that the doors
be open but that there be no door-keeper who has the power of closing a
door; there is no door-keeper on whose goodwill you depend for one or
another of the doors remaining open. If I am in the position of such a
door-keeper, therefore, your access to the X and Y options is not sup-
ported in the manner that freedom of choice strictly requires.
As the plausibility of the anti-adaptation assumption argues that all the
doors in a free choice must be open, then, so the plausibility of the anti-
ingratiation assumption argues that there must be no dependence on the
liberating in a distinct sense. Suppose, to go back to our old example, that you ingratiate yourself
sufficiently with the warden or parole board to have a choice between remaining in prison or living
outside. The ingratiation will mean that you did not have a free choice in that instance but it will be
liberating in the distinct sense that it enables you now to enjoy all the undominated choices that
become available in the world outside.
No domination without invasion 67
good graces of a door-keeper. When you ingratiate yourself with me and I
let you go by a door that I would otherwise have closed, you do not cease to
be subject to my will. You have not escaped the constraint that made you
unfree in the first place, nor done anything to reduce the effectiveness of the
constraint. While continuing to operate under the yoke of my will, you have
merely adjusted so as to make your life more comfortable.
37
For a somewhat variant treatment see List (2006b) and the discussion of freedom, which follows this
treatment, in List and Pettit (2011: Chapter 6).
68 Freedom as non-domination
version of the approach, we will want to minimize the sum: P(H if X & F) +
P(H if X & U) + P(H if Y & F) + P(H if Y & U).38
Minimizing this sum will mean maximizing expected non-domination.
It will involve keeping or putting barriers in place against the possible
interference of those who would otherwise have a power of interference in
your relevant choices. And it will mean keeping or putting obstacles in place
against the formation of agents or agencies that could have such power, if
they did come into existence. Thus it might mean taking steps to guard
against the possibility of a loose collection of individuals – say, a belligerent
minority or a potentially oppressive majority – incorporating to form a
dominating presence in the lives of others.
I add one final comment on the relationship between domination,
interference and frustration. We noted earlier that hindrance with frustra-
tion is more harmful than hindrance without and that hindrance without
frustration gets worse – it holds out the prospect of greater harm – as the
probability of frustration increases. Equally, domination with interference is
intuitively more harmful than domination without, so that we can associate
progressively greater levels of harm with the following three conditions:
domination without interference or frustration; domination with interfer-
ence but without frustration; and domination with both interference and
frustration. And correspondingly, we can say that domination without
interference gets worse as interference becomes more probable, and that
interference without frustration gets worse as the probability of frustration
rises. My inclination is to cast the extra harms imposed by interference and
frustration as distinct harms from the loss of freedom but, as I mentioned in
38
In an earlier footnote on freedom as non-interference I suggested that in an X–Y choice it is not
enough for such freedom that you enjoy the absence of hindrance in the actual world where you prefer
X and in the nearest possible world in which you choose the other option, Y; it is required, plausibly,
that you can get X in any of a wider range of worlds, including the actual one, in which you prefer X;
and can get Y in any of a wider range of possible worlds, including the nearest possible one, in which
you prefer Y. I take a similar view of the range of possible worlds in which you must avoid interference
if you are to enjoy non-domination. And here as in the other case, I think that this range of worlds is
discernible only on an intuitive, context-sensitive basis and, of course, that it does not include all
possible worlds. The worlds where non-domination requires that you choose X without interference,
for example, may vary in the precise physical movements whereby your X-ing is realized and in the
degrees of friendliness or hostility that others display. But they do not extend to all possible worlds in
which you choose X. Thus you are not unfree to make the choice between X and Y just because you
would suffer interference with X, should those in whose presence you act not only turn hostile, but
also develop super-human powers. The need to rely on contextual assumptions to determine the
range of relevant possible worlds is regrettable, but from the point of view of formalizing the theory of
freedom it seems inevitable. As mentioned in the earlier footnote, the indeterminacy is akin to that
which arises in epistemology when we ask about the range of possible worlds in which true belief has
to be present – when we ask about the extent to which true belief has to be robust – if there is to be
something deserving of being called knowledge.
How can we ensure your freedom of choice? 69
discussing hindrance and frustration, there is no objection in principle to
seeing them as freedom-related harms.39 We might well think that while
domination is enough for the loss of freedom, interference and frustration
make the loss more severe still.40
41
This line of thought is connected with the old slogan, according to which you are unfree in a choice
when you are exposed to forms of interference, presumptively serious, that others can impose at will
and with impunity. Others will be able to interfere at will insofar as they are not prevented or not
likely to be prevented from interfering. And others will be able to interfere with impunity insofar as
they are not subject to a penalty that inhibits and deters interference, making it effectively ineligible.
We can make you free, so the idea goes, to the extent that we can prevent or inhibit interferers in a
suitable degree: we can deny them interference-at-an-acceptable-cost.
How can we ensure your freedom of choice? 73
(uncontrolled) interference less likely, it also reduces the power of interfer-
ence on the part of the powerful.42
43
As we shall see, I think that the state should pursue people’s enjoyment of freedom as non-
domination under the normative constraint that it treats all its citizens as equal. But this does not
involve giving up on consequentialism. It merely implies that the state’s treating people as equals is a
good in its own right and has to be built into the strategy that the state adopts. Consequentialism does
not put any restriction on the goods that may be given countenance; it merely stipulates that the
strategies it is right for any agent or agency to adopt are a function of the goods that it can thereby
expect to promote.
chapter 2
Social justice
Assuming for the moment that state and government are required in order
to organize life in a society on a coercive basis, there are two large questions
that any political philosophy must address in the context of that society.
First question: what decisions or policies should the state impose in order to
establish social justice in the relationships between its citizens? Second
question: what processes of decision-making should it follow, if it is to
count as a politically legitimate decision-maker for its citizens on questions
of justice, and indeed on related matters too? Both questions might be
treated as questions of justice in an encompassing sense of the term, but
since I think they are importantly distinct, I shall cast the first as a question
of social justice, the second as a question of political legitimacy.
I take citizens in this discussion to comprise, not just citizens in the
official sense, but all the more or less settled residents of a state who, being
adult and able-minded, can play an informed role at any time in conceptu-
alizing shared concerns and in shaping how the state acts in furthering those
concerns (compare Tully 2009: i, 3). Special issues of justice and legitimacy
arise with those who are not adult or not able-minded, with those who are
not permanent residents, and indeed with those who are not yet born, as
related issues arise, of course, with the treatment of other animals. But I
shall almost exclusively concentrate on the general issues that arise for how
the state should treat current citizens in my broad sense.
I shall take the state and the government to be corporate entities related
in such a way that the state acts through government agents or agencies –
legislative, executive or judicial – and whenever those agencies act, the state
acts through them: they act, as it is said, in the state’s name. The issues of
social justice and political legitimacy that I discuss can be equally well cast
either as issues involving the state or as issues involving government and I
shall make use of both formulations. In each formulation, the issues raised
presuppose that the relevant entity, state or government, is an agent. While
it may involve the participation of many different individuals, it is disposed
75
76 Social justice
and expected to form and avow a coherent set of purposes and judgements
and to live up to them in how it behaves; it counts in that sense as a
corporate agent (List and Pettit 2011).
The state or government in every society imposes an order of law,
however we choose to define law, and the questions of social justice and
political legitimacy involve two different aspects of that order. The social
justice question is: does the state treat its citizens well and equally in
selecting the order that it imposes? The political legitimacy question is:
does the state treat its citizens well and equally in the way it imposes that
order? Each question can be taken as the universal form of a question that
every citizen is in a position to raise in his or her own case: does the state
treat me well in the nature of the order imposed and in the manner of its
imposition? The universal form is generated on the assumption that there is
no reason to privilege any one citizen over others and that the particular
question arises with the same force in everyone’s case.
The order of law that a state imposes will generally include substantive
provisions on how citizens should relate to one another and procedural
provisions on how they should relate to the state: provisions, for example,
on the rights of voting and of standing for office that they should have. Such
procedural provisions are relevant, particularly on the approach taken here,
to the issue of political legitimacy. And so, for reasons of convenience, I shall
take the social justice question to bear only on the nature of the order
imposed by the state as the determinant of people’s relationships with one
another, whether as individuals or as members of various groups. In asking
the social justice question as to whether the state imposes a suitable order,
then, the focus will be on how satisfactory the order is as a social order: as an
order that shapes people’s relationships with one another. In asking the
political legitimacy question as to whether the state imposes the order in an
appropriate manner, the focus will be – at least in part – on how satisfactory
the order is as a procedural order: as an order that shapes people’s relation-
ships with the state itself.
The issue of political legitimacy, which will lead us into democratic
theory, I postpone until the next chapter. The issue of social justice I
address in this.1 I have no quarrel with those who see the questions as
each bearing on a different aspect of justice in the more comprehensive,
social-cum-procedural sense – justice, for example, in the sense of John
1
A concern with social justice, as distinct from political legitimacy, is the sort of concern that Madison
had in mind in Federalist Papers, no. 51, when he said that it ‘is of great importance in a republic . . . to
guard one part of the society against the injustice of the other part’ (Madison, Hamilton and Jay 1987).
Social justice and equality 77
Rawls (1971, 1993) – but I shall continue to describe them in separate terms.
As will appear in the next chapter, I believe that treating the questions
together within a theory of comprehensive justice has led to a misconstrual
of the second question.
The position for which I will be arguing in this chapter is, roughly, that
the republican theory of social justice – depending on context, I shall often
say simply, justice – requires that people should enjoy freedom as non-
domination in their relationships with one another, whether as individuals
to individuals, as groups to groups, or as groups to individuals. And the
position for which I will be arguing in the next is that the republican theory
of political legitimacy – again, I shall often say simply, legitimacy – requires
that people should enjoy freedom as non-domination in their relationships
to their state or government. Republican justice is primarily opposed, on
this approach, to private domination; republican legitimacy to public. In
introducing the approach in the present chapter I shall assume, as men-
tioned, that a state is necessary and has a corporate character. I will try to
vindicate those assumptions in the next.
This chapter falls into four sections. In Section 1, I introduce the repub-
lican ideal of justice as the enjoyment of equal freedom as non-domination
amongst citizens, arguing that this can only mean equality in the enjoyment
of certain fundamental choices, the basic liberties, on the basis of a guaran-
tee of public resources and protections. When choices are safeguarded by
public resourcing and protection in this way I will often describe them for
convenience as being secured or safeguarded or entrenched, though
entrenchment in this sense does not necessarily connote constitutional
embedding. In Section 2, I use two plausible constraints to identify the
basic liberties that ought to be publicly entrenched in that sense. In
Section 3, I give an illustrative sketch of the policies that the republican
theory of justice would require; this is to gesture at an institutional model of
republican justice on a par with the institutional model of republican
legitimacy – in effect, republican democracy – that I seek to provide in
the final two chapters. And then in Section 4, I offer some comments on the
distinctive features of the emerging theory.
The connection
Almost everyone will agree that the challenge in a theory of justice, social or
indeed comprehensive, is to identify in any context the ‘proper balance
78 Social justice
between competing claims’ that arise there (Rawls 1971: 9). In the domestic
context of a particular state I take the citizens to be the relevant claimants,
where the citizenry includes all adult, able-minded, more or less permanent
residents. And I take the state or the government – that is, the agency
whereby the state enacts its business – to be the addressee of their claims and
so the entity that has the job of identifying and enforcing the demands of
justice. So what are the claims that citizens have within the state and what
would constitute a proper balance between those claims?
Almost everyone will agree, not just that this is the central question in a
theory of domestic justice, social or comprehensive, but also that any
plausible answer to the question has to satisfy a certain egalitarian con-
straint. In order to establish a proper balance between the claims of its
citizens, the state must treat them as equals in determining that balance: it
must express or manifest an equal degree of concern for each of them
(Dworkin 1978). And so, whatever benefits the state makes available as a
matter of justice to its citizens, it is subject to the constraint of making them
available in an expressively egalitarian way. This constraint does not neces-
sarily argue that the state should adopt a policy that imposes a certain
substantive equality amongst citizens. In itself it requires only that in
selecting policies, the state should recognize that people count equally: it
should act on the principle that ‘all are entitled to respect’ (Raz 1986: 219).
The connection between social justice and expressive equality is scarcely
surprising, for the very paradigm of injustice is the scenario where those of a
certain caste or colour, religion, gender or ethnicity suffer discrimination
under the institutions established by the state. The just system, so the lesson
goes, cannot be a system that discriminates on any such basis between its
members; it is inherently impartial.
My discussion of social justice in this chapter, and my discussion of
political legitimacy in the next – my discussion, in other words, of each
aspect of comprehensive justice – starts from the normative assumption that
the state ought to be expressively egalitarian in this sense. The assumption
that the state ought to treat people as equals, satisfying expressive egalitari-
anism, implies on the side of the citizenry that they ought to be willing to
live in society under an arrangement where they are treated as equals: they
ought to be prepared, as we may put it, to live on equal terms with others
and not claim a special position for themselves. This means that any
complaints about their treatment that citizens can expect to command a
hearing must be consistent with a willingness to live on equal terms with
their fellow citizens: in effect, they must be publicly avowable in the context
of reciprocal exchange.
Social justice and equality 79
Why commit to expressive egalitarianism in this sense? The reason goes
back to a point registered in the introduction to the chapter. Each of us can
reasonably ask about how well the state treats us both in the nature of the
order it imposes and in the mode of its imposition. And the assumption that
we are each in a position to raise those questions with equal validity – an
assumption encoded in our being willing to discuss them with one another –
generates the universal counterparts. Thus a theory of social justice will
address the question as to what order the state must impose if in that respect
it is to treat its citizens well and equally. And a theory of political legitimacy
will address the question of how it must impose that order if in that distinct
respect it is also to treat them well and equally.
The two points of general agreement that we have registered take us only
a limited distance in thinking about the demands of social justice. Particular
theories of justice diverge on the good or goods in respect of which the state
should treat its citizens as equals: that is, on what it is to treat them well.
And they diverge also on what it is for the state to satisfy the equality
constraint in delivering that treatment: that is, on what it is to treat them
equally. They go different ways both on the substantive matter of what
should be pursued in an expressively egalitarian fashion, and on the meth-
odological issue of what expressive equalization entails.
Take the substantive issue, first of all. Libertarian theory holds that
the state ought to treat people as equals in protecting their purportedly
natural rights; depending on how rights are interpreted, this comes in two
versions, respectively right-wing (Nozick 1974) and left-wing (Vallentyne
and Steiner 2000a, 2000b). Luck-egalitarian theory holds that the state
ought to treat people as equals in distributing resources, except when
people can only blame themselves for their misfortune: the inequality
they suffer, as it is sometimes put, is a result of ‘option-luck’ rather than
‘brute luck’ (Dworkin 2000; Fleurbaey 2008). Utilitarian theory holds
that the state ought to treat people as equals in a concern for their utility
or perhaps their opportunity for utility (Arneson 1989; Roemer 1998).
Capability theory maintains that it ought to treat them as equals, rather, in
providing for their basic capacity to function in the local society (Sen 1985;
Nussbaum 2006; Alexander 2008). And mixed theories look for the
treatment of people as equals in respect of different goods in different
spheres (Walzer 1983) or in respect of any of the goods that confer a
presumptive advantage (Cohen 1993).
Rawls’s (1971) theory, to which we will return later, belongs in this mixed
category, for it requires the state to treat its citizens as equals in providing for
each the mix of primary or omni-functional goods – goods that are
80 Social justice
indispensable for people, regardless of their particular goals or wishes – that
are prescribed under his two principles of justice. These goods include
liberty and opportunity, income and wealth and a basis for self-respect.
Rawls formulates the principles of justice that are meant to deliver primary
goods as follows, with the first principle having lexical priority: that is, it
cannot be violated for any gain in the second.
a. Each person has an equal right to a fully adequate scheme of equal basic liberties
which is compatible with a similar scheme of liberties for all.
b. Social and economic inequalities are to satisfy two conditions. First, they must
be attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality
of opportunity; and second, they must be to the greatest benefit of the least
advantaged members of society. (Rawls 1993: 291)
Whatever good or mix of goods they favour, theories of justice differ also
on the methodological issue of what it is for the state to treat people as
equals with respect to that good. In order to understand this point of
divergence it may be useful to think of the different ways in which parents
might think of treating their children as equals in providing from a fixed set
of funds for a good like education. Assuming that none of the children
suffers from cognitive or related problems, parents might follow any of five
salient, though not necessarily exhaustive, strategies.
* Equal investments. The parents might take expressive equality to require
providing exactly the same funds for the education of each child; this
would give the children equal opportunities for success.
* Equal direct returns. They might take it to require providing or refusing
such funds for each as ensure that, regardless of their different capacities,
the children all end up at the same educational level or position; this
would give the children equal educational outcomes.
* Equal derived returns. They might take expressive equality to require
providing funds for each that will enable the children to develop their
educational potential and thereby to achieve the same level of fulfilment
in their work and life; this would give the children equal outcomes in a
different currency.
* Equal rates of return. They might take it to require providing funds in
funds that enable the children each to enjoy a certain threshold benefit,
where this provision may allow some of the children to do better than the
threshold while others barely reach it.
Social justice and equality 81
As the parents in our little example might treat their children as equals
under any of these five strategies, so a theory of justice might require the
state to treat its citizens as equals in any of the corresponding ways. Each
strategy is expressively egalitarian insofar as it can be taken to reflect an equal
concern for members of the relevant constituency, children or citizens. But
only the first three can be cast as strategies that reflect a concern that equality
should prevail amongst those individuals (Temkin 1996). Those three
strategies are substantively as well as expressively egalitarian.2
The substantively inegalitarian character of the fourth, rates-of-return
strategy appears in the fact that the utilitarian project of maximizing overall
happiness in a society, however unequal the distribution amongst individ-
uals, exemplifies this approach. It involves investing resources at any time
wherever the rate of return is highest and doing so to the point where
resources are exhausted and the marginal rate of return from investment in
any one person is the same as the marginal rate of return from investment in
any other. The substantively inegalitarian character of the fifth threshold-
benefits strategy appears in the fact that it would allow some individuals to
do significantly better than others in relevant benefits, provided they all
reach the appropriate level. One example is Harry Frankfurt’s (1987)
sufficientarianism, which argues that all should be provided with what by
suitable standards is a sufficient level of resources for social flourishing. The
capability approach adopted by Amartya Sen (1985) and Martha Nussbaum
(2006) is also sufficientarian, on the face of it, since it argues that all should
be provided only with a basic capability for functioning in the local society.3
These observations give us a useful lead on what form we might expect a
republican theory of justice to assume. On the substantive question, they
suggest that it ought to make some version of freedom as non-domination
into the good with respect to which the state is required in justice to treat its
citizens as equals; otherwise it can hardly count as a distinctively republican
theory. And on the methodological question, they suggest that while the
theory has to be expressively egalitarian, it may take any of a variety of
forms, some of them substantively egalitarian, some of them not. I look now
at how best to interpret the goal of republican justice and then at what this
interpretation implies for the equality strategy that the theory ought to
endorse.
2
Another strategy that might be taken to reflect an equal concern for the children, while not being
substantively egalitarian, is prioritarianism (Parfit 2000). I discuss it briefly later in the text.
3
For discussions on how far the approach is sufficientarian see Part 1 of Kaufman (2006).
82 Social justice
The freedom goal of republican justice
In order to build further on these observations we need to identify in greater
detail the ideal of freedom as non-domination that the state should be
required to foster. In principle, the state ought to promote the enjoyment of
free or undominated choice amongst its citizens, under the expressively
egalitarian constraint of treating those citizens as equals. But what does this
prescription entail in practice?
In seeking a more concrete version of the prescription I propose that we
should take as a guiding heuristic the image of the liber, or ‘free person’, in
the republican tradition. That picture claims to represent a status in which
people can all enjoy freedom of choice fully, and yet also enjoy it equally.
Using this heuristic as a guide to what republican justice would require
presupposes that the circumstances of the society are not so dire, nor the
disparities between people so severe, that it is impossible for people gen-
erally to achieve the status of a free person. This is just to require that the
circumstances of justice obtain, in John Rawls’s (1971: 126–30) phrase: that
is, that the society is operating within a more or less normal range of
material scarcity and individual capacity.
In the received republican image, free persons can walk tall, and look
others in the eye. They do not depend on anyone’s grace or favour for being
able to choose their mode of life. And they relate to one another in a shared,
mutually reinforcing consciousness of enjoying this independence. Thus, in
the established terms of republican denigration, they do not have to bow or
scrape, toady or kowtow, fawn or flatter; they do not have to placate any
others with beguiling smiles or mincing steps. In short, they do not have to
live on their wits, whether out of fear or deference. They are their own men
and women, and however deeply they bind themselves to one another, as in
love or friendship or trust, they do so freely, reaching out to one another
from positions of relatively equal strength.4
There are three important lessons that the traditional image of the free
person teaches us about how we might concretize the ideal of freedom as
non-domination as a target of justice. The first offers direction on the range
of free choices that free persons ought to enjoy, the second provides an
indication of the basis on which those choices ought to be secured or
4
Presented in this way, the image of free persons may seem to be silent on the political front, implying
nothing about people’s political rights or responsibilities. But the presentation is adequate for our
purposes, since we are abstracting in our discussion of justice – that is, social justice – from the relation
between citizens and government. I reintroduce that relation in the following chapters when I go on to
discuss legitimacy and democracy.
Social justice and equality 83
entrenched, and the third gives us guidance on when such entrenchment is
enough to give people the status of free persons.
The first lesson is that free persons are free in virtue of being secured in
the exercise of a specific class of choices, not in making just any old
choices. They are not to be entrenched in acting violently towards others,
for example, in appropriating as much land as they want, or in pursuing
spectacular adventures. They are to enjoy access to needed resources and
protections in a range of choice where all can operate at once – perhaps
with special assistance for some individuals – without getting in one
another’s way. This is the domain of the fundamental liberties, as they
were described by the seventeenth-century radical, John Libourne (1646).
While these liberties were often cast in his time and place as the ancient,
historically sacred rights of Englishmen, they gave institutional expression
for Libourne to ‘the freeman’s freedom’; they reflected the fact that men
and indeed women ‘are, and were by nature all equal and alike in power,
dignity, authority, and majesty – none of them having (by nature) any
authority, dominion or magisterial power, one over or above another’
(Sharp 1998).5
The second lesson of the free-person image is that in order to enjoy
freedom in the exercise of the basic liberties, people should have a publicly
established and acknowledged status in relation to others; only this could
enable them to walk tall and look others in the eye. Within the sphere of
those liberties people should be entrenched on a public basis against the
incursions of others. They ought to enjoy objective safeguards that apply
regardless of the will of others as to how they should choose in that domain.
And it ought to be a matter of shared awareness in the society that they are
so guarded. They should have an undominated status both in the objective
and the subjective or inter-subjective sense of status.
The public safeguards required for the enjoyment of such status are
traditionally taken to include the laws that provide in a saliently equal
manner for the entrenchment of people’s liberties. But given that univer-
sally beneficial laws are likely to be supported by attitudes of approval for
compliance and disapproval for non-compliance, the safeguards are also
bound to include associated norms or morals. Norms in this sense are
regularities of behaviour such that, as a matter of public awareness, most
members conform to them, most expect others to approve of conformity or
5
The abstraction from issues of legitimacy means that the basic liberties envisaged here do not include
the political rights that Rawls counts as basic liberties in his first principle of justice.
84 Social justice
disapprove of non-conformity, and most are policed into conformity by this
expectation about what will attract approval and disapproval.6
Corresponding to the coercive effect of laws against fraud or violence or
murder, we might expect to find norms that occasion a complementary,
approbative effect, deterring potential offenders by holding out the prospect
of communal disapproval. Machiavelli (1965) remarks in Discourses (1.18) on
the importance of having norms available to support the laws in this way:
‘just as good morals, if they are to be maintained, have need of the laws, so
the laws, if they are to be observed, have need of good morals’.7 We shall be
exploring the connection more deeply towards the end of the chapter.
The first lesson that I drew from the free-person heuristic bears on what
should be safeguarded – the fundamental or basic liberties – and the second
on how they should be safeguarded: by reliance on public laws and norms.
The third lesson identifies the criterion for determining what is enough by
way of safeguarding them – what level of support is sufficient to let us think
that for practical purposes people all enjoy freedom as non-domination in
the relevant choices. The lesson suggests that people should securely enjoy
resources and protections to the point where they satisfy what we might call
the eyeball test. They can look others in the eye without reason for the fear
or deference that a power of interference might inspire; they can walk tall
and assume the public status, objective and subjective, of being equal in this
regard with the best. This eyeball test fits with our discussion at the end of
the previous chapter of the level of prevention and inhibition that might
effectively counter domination. The satisfaction of the test would mean for
each person that others were unable, in the received phrase, to interfere at
will and with impunity in their affairs.
The eyeball test does not require that people should be able to look one
another in the eye, regardless of their personal lack of nerve. It requires that
they have this capacity in the absence of what would count, even by the
most demanding standards of their society, as mere timidity or cowardice.
The reference to timidity is essential, since no public safeguards can
6
The definition follows Pettit (1990) and Brennan and Pettit (2004: Part iii) with one amendment: it
says that a norm is a regularity such that almost everyone expects others to approve of conformity
rather than, in the older formulation, that it is a regularity such that almost everyone approves of
conformity. The change allows us to recognize as norms regularities that, unbeknownst to people, do
not actually attract general approval (Prentice and Miller 1993); for a fuller discussion of this possibility
see Pettit (2008e). While I do not offer a defence for defining norms in this way, it should be noted
that it fits extremely well, particularly in the way it connects norms and approval, with the under-
standing of norms in the larger literature (Hart 1961; Winch 1963; Coleman 1990; Sober and Wilson
1998; Elster 1999; Shapiro 2011).
7
See too Tyler (1990).
Social justice and equality 85
compensate for differences between individual personalities and for varia-
tions in people’s capacity to deal with the overbearing assumptions of
others. The reference to the standards of their society is necessary since
there is likely to be cultural variation in what counts as mere timidity rather
than rational fear or deference. People are liable to vary across societies in
the different levels of vulnerability to which they have become inured, in the
probability that they assign to others becoming hostile, and in the levels of
trust that they invest in one another. If there is cultural variation on this
front, then it is clearly local standards that should provide the relevant
benchmark for determining when fear or deference is irrational and when
prudent; there is not going to be any universally valid alternative that might
be invoked in their stead.
The effect of the eyeball test is to require a certain threshold of
resourcing and protection that should be secured for all in the domain
of the basic liberties. We know from the last chapter that other people’s
capacity to interfere may vary in two ways. They may be capable of any
form of interference in a lesser or greater degree, facing lesser or greater
difficulty and lesser or greater danger. And they may be capable in
whatever degree of a more or less serious form of interference: they
may be capable of preventing the choice of an option at one extreme
or, at the other, capable just of imposing a more or less trivial cost. This
variation teaches an important lesson for how the eyeball test should be
understood and applied. Since both dimensions of variation are impor-
tant, the test requires that the level of protection provided in any area of
choice should increase with the seriousness of the interference against
which protection is needed and with the ease of access to that level of
interference.
The third lesson of the free-person heuristic makes the goal of a repub-
lican theory of justice more accessible than it might otherwise be. It means,
as we saw, that you cannot rely on the state to compensate for your timidity
or other failures and that you can enjoy the full benefits of public resourcing
and protection only if you display a certain degree of personal affirmation
and courage. And it also means that having resources and protections
over and beyond what is required to satisfy the eyeball test – say, as a result
of enjoying above-average wealth – is excess to the requirements of your
status as a free citizen. Certain differences of wealth and power may
jeopardize the freedom as non-domination of the less well off, as we shall
see, and be objectionable on that count. But, assuming that they are not
allowed to have this effect, they are consistent with the status of a free citizen
being available to all, richer and poorer alike.
86 Social justice
My characterization of the three lessons of the free-person heuristic
suggests that they apply independently of one another, and for simplicity
of presentation I shall generally continue to write as if they do. But the third
lesson about the eyeball test has an important priority and is bound to
impact on the application of the first two. That test plays a part in
determining, not just the level of resourcing and protection that ought to
be secured for given choices, but also the range of choices that ought to be
entrenched in that way and the nature of the public entrenchment that
ought to be provided.
Take the first lesson, which teaches that free persons should enjoy
resources and protections in an area of choice where all can operate at
once, at least with special assistance for some individuals, without getting in
one another’s way. When is special assistance to be provided for those in
particular need, presumably by the state? Suppose that some people are
impaired or disabled in a way that makes them incapable, without state
assistance, of operating in a certain area of choice; perhaps they need some
prosthetic aid in order to be able to function there and are incapable of
purchasing it for themselves. How are we to determine whether they should
be given that aid and whether the relevant choice should be entrenched as a
basic liberty for all? The answer can only be determined by the eyeball test.
That a choice is such that those who lack access to it will not be able to pass
the eyeball test in the local society makes the canonical case for why the state
ought to resource the needy in a special way and ought to entrench the
choice as a basic liberty for all. Thus, to take a salient example, it may argue
for providing wheelchairs for those who cannot afford them and for build-
ing wheelchair ramps in public buildings.
Or consider the second lesson, according to which free persons should be
entrenched on a public basis in the exercise of the basic liberties. What exact
sort of public entrenchment ought to be provided? Take the presumptively
basic liberty of moving wherever you will within a society. Does that require
just the protection of travellers, without any particular resourcing? Or does
it also require the provision of a public network of road or rail or air travel, as
distinct from some privately provided routes? Or the provision of a public
means of travel, as in a publicly subsidized rail or bus or plane network? Or
even the provision of subsidies for those who cannot afford to use a public or
private network? Here, as elsewhere, such questions teem, and the eyeball
test provides the only compelling basis for an answer. Thus when I speak in
what follows of the need to entrench or secure or safeguard various basic
liberties I shall abstract from the question of whether this means just
protecting them, or protecting them and providing general resources that
Social justice and equality 87
everyone needs, or doing those things and, in addition, providing special
resources for some who are particularly needy, whether financially or by
reason of requiring a mechanical aid like a wheelchair. In every case the
question can only be answered on the basis of the eyeball test but I shall not
explore the precise answers that are appropriate in different cases.
In giving a central role to the eyeball test, I follow an approach opened up
by Amartya Sen (1983b) in the development of his criterion of functioning
capability. He suggests that to be poor – to lack a basic functioning capability
in your society – is closely related, as Adam Smith (1976: 351–2) argued, to
being unable to live without shame amongst your fellows: to failing to meet
material standards that others in the society expect all ‘creditable people’ to
attain. Smith’s criterion is less demanding than that employed here but it is in
the same spirit and may even reflect his own allegiance to republican ways of
thinking (Winch 1978). Smith suggests that poverty entails not being able to
look others in the eye without reason for fear or deference: that’s where the
shame lies. The line taken here is that while that is certainly true, satisfying the
test requires full freedom as non-domination and not just the absence of
poverty. Escaping the shame of poverty is only a first step towards the
enjoyment of interpersonal status and the achievement of freedom.
8
I observed in the last chapter that domination with interference and frustration plausibly counts as
worse than domination with interference but without frustration, and that in turn as worse than
domination without interference or frustration. But that observation will not play any role in this
chapter, or indeed in the next. In guarding against unfreedom in the enjoyment of fully resourced
choices, it is essential to guard against domination, since domination is sufficient, as well as necessary,
for unfreedom. And if we eliminate domination then that will be enough to eliminate forms of
interference and frustration that are hostile to freedom. The observation from the last chapter will
88 Social justice
With these observations in place, we can see that what it means for the
state to treat citizens as equals in this way, satisfying the expressively
egalitarian constraint, is to provide them each with a certain threshold
benefit in the currency of free or undominated choice, as required under
the sufficientarian strategy described earlier. It means providing for such a
level and kind of entrenchment, in such a range of choice, that people each
have the status, traditionally understood, of the free person or citizen. The
choices to be entrenched are the basic liberties; the kind of entrenchment to
be provided is the public sort that enlists laws and norms; and the level of
entrenchment to be secured is whatever is necessary for passing the eyeball
test in the local society. That each is required to enjoy this threshold of free
undominated choice is consistent with some people having such private
sources of power and wealth that they enjoy free undominated choice in a
yet greater range and with yet greater security. That is why the approach can
be cast as sufficientarian.
Since the enjoyment of such a sufficiency of free or undominated choice
means enjoying the status of the free person or citizen, however, we can
describe the strategy in other terms too. We can cast it as an approach that
argues for equalizing derived returns, as in the third strategy mentioned
earlier, where free-person status is a return derived from the required pattern
of resourcing and protecting choice. Although it constitutes a sufficientari-
anism in the currency of free or undominated choice, the republican theory
of justice supports a substantive egalitarianism in the currency of free or
undominated status. Depending on what the relevant currency is taken to
be, it assumes one or the other profile.
In the remainder of the book I shall generally speak of the republican
theory of justice as substantively, as well as expressively, egalitarian, taking it
to argue for promoting people’s equality in freedom as non-domination,
where this is now understood as freedom of undominated status, not
freedom of undominated choice. It may have been the substantively egali-
tarian aspect of republicanism that Cicero (1998: 21) had in mind when he
made his much-quoted comment on the nature of the libertas enjoyed by
the liber. ‘Nothing can be sweeter than liberty. Yet if it isn’t equal through-
out, it isn’t liberty at all.’
As a substantively egalitarian theory, the republican approach to justice
may seem to be exposed to the now well-known complaint that like any
such theory it would argue for reducing the level of the better off in order to
assume relevance only in ranking imperfectly just or imperfectly legitimate regimes. Thus it will count
in favour of one imperfect regime over another that the domination it allows, unlike the domination
allowed in the other, does not promise actual interference or frustration.
Social justice and equality 89
achieve equality with the worse off, even when that reduction has no other
beneficial effects; it would support levelling-down (Parfit 2000). This
objection will be irrelevant so long as all actually achieve an undominated
status. While some may have greater wealth or power in such a scenario this
will not give them a greater status freedom, as we saw, and so will not
provide a reason for levelling down. Nor will the objection be relevant
where all can in principle be brought to achieve an undominated status but
not all actually attain it. In such a situation there will be transfers possible
that lift all to that undominated level. But what of the case where it is
impossible for everyone to enjoy an undominated status? What of the case
where some are deprived of status freedom, and deprived in such a way that
their position cannot be remedied by redistribution from the better off?
Would the approach argue that in this scenario the state should worsen the
position of the better off just for the sake of establishing equality: just for the
sake of depriving everyone in the society of an undominated status and
setting up a beggar-thy-neighbour form of equality?
No, it would not. The primary commitment in the republican approach
is to expressive egalitarianism and the first injunction is that the state should
promote people’s enjoyment of undominated choice under the constraint
that it treats them as equals, displaying an equal concern for each. We
argued that this commitment would support an equal free status for all,
invoking the traditional image of the free citizen, on the supposition that
the circumstances of justice prevail and that such a status can in principle be
achieved for all. If that assumption fails, as it is taken to fail here, then the
only commitment remaining in place will be the original, expressive one. It
may be reasonable to assume that short of emergency situations, or grave
disparities in the capacities of different people, there will be an applicable
ideal of free citizenship that all can in principle achieve; this is because the
ideal is differently interpreted in different societies and can allow for
variations in background fortune or misfortune. But if things were so bad
that no such ideal could be satisfied for all, then the only commitment
would be to expressive, not substantive, equalization.
What might expressive equalization in the sphere of free choice support
under such hard circumstances? What might it mean for the state to
promote free or undominated choice amongst its citizens, under the con-
straint of treating all as equals? There are a number of possibilities, one of
which is a version of the prioritarianism that Derek Parfit (2000) supports.
This holds that in the circumstances imagined the state’s equal concern for
each would argue for giving a greater weight – of whatever magnitude – to
bettering the lot of the worse off. The idea is not to prioritize the worse off as
90 Social justice
a way of reducing the relativity between them and others – it is not driven
by a concern with furthering substantive equality – but to prioritize the
worse off because of the poorer absolute level at which they exist and
function. If the state is to care equally for each of its citizens, then such a
weighting of the worse off would make very good sense.
The possibility envisaged in the objection just raised is that the repub-
lican theory of justice might be over-demanding, assuming as it does that
people within a society can all be positioned to achieve the status of the free
person or citizen. But another objection to the theory might be that it is
likely to be intuitively under-demanding, looking for an ideal of equal status
freedom that allows for differences in people’s private wealth and power.
The objection is that the theory may permit such differences in private
resources that it ceases to be intuitively appealing: to recall John Rawls’s
(1971) test, it fails to deliver a reflective equilibrium with our considered
judgements as to how far differences in private resources are allowable.
This objection also misfires. The level of resources and protections
required for undominated status – the threshold of provision necessary –
is determined on a basis that takes into account the resources and protec-
tions available to others. If the state allows excessive disparities between the
endowments of different people, then the less well off are unlikely to be able
to attain that threshold. It is true that equality in status freedom – equality,
as we may say, in freedom as non-domination – is consistent with differ-
ences of private wealth and power and with corresponding differences in
resources and protections. But still the ideal imposes severe constraints on
how large or pervasive those differences can be allowed to be.
The constraining aspect of the ideal comes out in a pair of related effects
that are going to be present in many, although perhaps not all, contexts
(Pettit 1997c; Lovett 2001). Suppose that you have fewer resources and
protections than your neighbour and that we, acting for the state, have a
choice between conferring more on you or conferring more on the neigh-
bour; the choice may arise with providing services, delivering subsidies or
imposing taxes. If we invest in the neighbour rather than investing in you,
then we are likely to do relatively less well in guarding against domination,
since you are in more danger of domination and so more likely to be in a
position to benefit from the extra investment. And if we invest in the
neighbour rather than investing in you, then we are likely to worsen the
danger of domination in absolute terms, since the neighbour is more likely
to be enabled by the extra investment to dominate you or others.
The first of these effects means that investing resources or protections in
the better off has diminishing marginal productivity; as it targets the better
Social justice and equality 91
and better off, it is less and less likely to be productive – that is, less and less
likely to increase non-domination. And the second of the effects means that
such investment also has increasing marginal counter-productivity; as it
targets the better and better off, it is more and more likely to be counter-
productive – that is, more and more likely to reduce non-domination. The
effects combine to give us reason for thinking that if the state seeks to
promote equal freedom as non-domination – that is, to make the status of
free citizenship available to all – then it will be systematically programmed
to reduce material inequalities in people’s resources and protections.
The reason why the ideal of equal status freedom supports an antipathy
to material inequality is that it is essentially social in character. You would
not enjoy freedom as non-domination in a universe where there were no
others, as by traditional accounts you might enjoy freedom as non-
interference. To enjoy this freedom presupposes relationships with others
and consists in relating to them on a pattern that rules out domination. It
requires the absence of domination, not as such, but in the presence of
relationships that make domination saliently possible and non-domination
correspondingly desirable. To enjoy the relevant freedom of non-
domination is to be someone who commands a certain standing amongst
your fellows.
The social nature of the ideal of equal freedom as non-domination means
that it has an interactional character of a kind that some recent theorists of
equality have celebrated (Anderson 1999; Scheffler 2005; O’Neill 2008).
What matters is not that individuals are allotted the same good in a certain
dimension, independently of how this affects their relations with one
another. What matters is that they have the same good in a dimension
that impacts on how they can interact with one another and on what
standing they can command in one another’s eyes. Thus it is entirely
intelligible that how far you enjoy undominated status depends, not just
on the resources and protections at your disposal, but on how they compare
with the resources and protections at the disposal of others. Let them
compare too unfavourably and you are very unlikely to enjoy an undomi-
nated status.9
9
A nice test that emphasizes the importance of interactional equality, built on an idea taken from Derek
Parfit (2000), is this. Imagine a world of mutually insulated societies and suppose we have a choice
between two egalitarian policies, A and B. The policies would produce the same average equality score,
measured by whatever index we favour, but policy A would do so while achieving a high degree of
equality within each society and policy B would leave as much inequality within societies as between
them. From the point of view of equality which policy should we prefer? If we prefer A, which seems
like the obvious choice, then that shows just how far we value equality for its impact on interactions
between people.
92 Social justice
The discussion in this section gives us a good idea of how to go about
elaborating a republican theory of justice and I try to provide a model of its
institutional implications in Section 3 of the chapter. But before coming to
that sketch we need to devote some time to a preliminary task. This is to try
to work out a conception of the fundamental or basic liberties that, as we
have seen, are going to require safeguarding under a republican theory.
Two criteria
One approach to promoting people’s equal freedom as non-domination
might be to look for a system under which people have the same level of
freedom in different sets of choices, where the set of choices available to each
gives no one reason to envy the position of another. I might be free in a
domain of choice where it really matters to me that I have freedom and you
might be free in a distinct domain that answers better to your concerns.10
But even if we could find customized domains of choice that satisfied the
envy test at any moment, they would not continue to satisfy it as the
membership of the society changed or as the preferences of members
altered. And in any case it is extremely hard to see how the system imagined
could be implemented. In seeking to equalize freedom as non-domination,
the only feasible project is to look for a system under which people
approximate the same level of freedom in the same choices.
But what choices should people be put in a position to enjoy equally?
They must be choices that people can each have the wherewithal to make, at
least when some are given special assistance by the state; whether special
assistance is appropriate, as we saw earlier, will be determined by the eyeball
test. And they must be choices, of course, that the state can protect,
shielding people from the domination of others. So what choices should
the state safeguard if it is to provide people with the equal freedom that
justice would seem to require? What are the choices that people ought to be
enabled to make, and to make without the domination of others – without
dependency on their goodwill and forbearance?
10
We might take this to be what Hobbes recommends when, as we saw, he thinks that free-men will
each be unhindered in doing the things that by their strength and wit they are able to do; we might
take him to suggest that native wit and strength determine the choices in which each will want to
avoid hindrance.
The basic liberties 93
The free-person heuristic provides us with useful guidance in dealing
with this question (Pettit 2008a).11 Since freedom on that heuristic is an
ideal that all the citizens in a society ought to be able to enjoy under the law,
the basic liberties ought to be construed so as to make such universal
enjoyment possible. The exercise of the basic liberties ought not to be an
impossible ideal that is accessible to none; an elite ideal that only some can
access; or a competitive ideal such that if some access it, that reduces the
chances of others doing so. John Locke (1960: ii.57), who remained faithful
in this respect to republican thinking, spells out the message clearly.
Arguing that ‘where there is no law, there is no freedom’, he says that
everyone should be provided only with a liberty to act ‘within the allowance
of those laws under which he is, and therein not to be subject to the
arbitrary will of another, but freely follow his own’.
This observation argues in favour of two basic criteria that candidates for
entrenchment as basic liberties ought to meet. First, the choices to be
entrenched ought to be capable of being exercised by each, consistently
with being exercised by all. And second, they ought to be capable of
satisfying or fulfilling each, consistently with satisfying all (see Anderson
1999). I call the first the criterion of co-exercisability and the second the
criterion of co-satisfaction. If co-exercisability were breached, then people
would have to compete for being able to exercise the basic liberties, so that
the status of the free person would not be equally accessible to all. If co-
satisfaction were breached, then the basic liberties would not enable people
to achieve the level of fulfilment we naturally associate with having the
status of a free person.
The basic liberties ought to include only choices that meet these two
criteria. And they ought to include all of the possible choices that do so. Any
shortfall in the choices that the state safeguards would be an unnecessary
restriction on the freedom that can be enjoyed by citizens and would not fit
well with the traditional image of the free person. Thus we may identify the
basic liberties with all, and only, those choices that are co-exercisable and
co-satisfying in a society.12 I now proceed to look in greater detail at the
choices that are likely to qualify for being basic liberties in that sense.
11
While I follow the lines developed in Pettit (2008a), I make some small amendments and abstract
from much detail.
12
The extension of a set of choices in this manner will be uncontentious in the case where there is no
impact on the existing choices by the addition of more. But there will certainly be issues of how to
measure and compare liberties when two or more extended sets differ in the precise choices
entrenched. I ignore those questions here, however, as I think that there is no easy answer in the
abstract, no algorithm for determining the relative merits of contending sets; the comparison between
such sets can only be carried forward in context-bound judgements about their relative attractions.
94 Social justice
The two criteria that I employ in identifying basic liberties, it should be
noted, are not value-laden and should be capable of being applied in
common by thinkers with very different commitments. The assumption
that the basic liberties should be as large a class as possible makes almost all
potentially free choices into candidates for consideration and then the co-
exercisability and co-satisfaction constraints act as filters to narrow down
that class. The approach breaks with two more standard lines. One offers a
few examples and directs us to the class of basic liberties without the help of
any criteria, only a gestural ‘and so on’. The other identifies the basic
liberties by a value-laden criterion: say, as liberties that are essential for
the development of the moral personality (Rawls 1993). Our approach is
more directive in the guidance it provides than the first alternative and it is
less dependent on a particular moral vision than the second.13
Co-exercisable choices
The first criterion holds that any choice that deserves to be safeguarded
should be the sort of choice that all the citizens of a society – roughly, all
adult, able-minded, relatively permanent residents – can exercise, and
exercise at more or less the same time. This criterion can be taken to outlaw
two categories of choice. As a constraint of individual exercisability, it
outlaws choices that are inaccessible to particular people, even with special
state provision. And as a constraint of collective exercisability, it rules out
choices that people cannot exercise together – roughly, at one and the same
time – even with suitable state resourcing.
Taking up the first constraint, it should be clear that there are many
choices that not everyone is able to enact or exercise. Not everyone can decide
what you think or say or wish for; only you can do that. So by this require-
ment there is no possibility of entrenching for all a basic liberty of making up
your mind on such matters. All that might be entrenched is the liberty for
each to make up his or her own mind on the issues: your liberty to make up
your mind, my liberty to make up my mind, and so on. What goes for
making up your mind goes for any action that involves you, or any particular
individual, in the position of agent, and this suggests that the basic liberties
must all have a self-referential or agent-relative character. They must be
restricted to liberties on the part of A to determine how A acts, liberties on
the part of B to determine how B acts, and so on. They cannot extend to
liberties on the part of anyone to determine how others act.
13
My thanks to Annie Stilz for forcing me to see this point.
The basic liberties 95
The individual exercisability constraint imposes this restriction on the
basic liberties as a matter of logical or metaphysical necessity. But it imposes
other restrictions as a result of contingent facts about what most of us can
and cannot do. It is a contingent fact that not everyone can climb Mt
Everest and that not everyone – perhaps not anyone – can jump ten feet.
Since these limitations are not ones that the state could plausibly enable
people to overcome, the basic liberties must operate within the boundaries
of exercisability that they establish. They must be limited to choices that fall
within everyone’s competence, at least when that competence is enhanced
by the state. Everyone might have a basic liberty of movement within the
public territory of the state – and a basic liberty of leaving that territory if
another state allows this – even though such movement might require the
state provision of transport facilities for those who cannot walk or cannot
afford the cost of transport. And while that basic liberty would enable some
individuals to exercise their special capacity to climb mountains, climbing
mountains is still not a basic liberty. At most it is a derived liberty that is
available, in virtue of their having the basic liberty of travel, to those with
mountain-climbing skills.
The individual exercisability constraint does not only restrict basic
liberties to choices we are individually capable of exercising, at least with
public support. It also restricts them to choices in the exercise of which we
do not depend on the voluntary cooperation of others. None of us can be
sure of being able to tango or to sing in a choir or to incorporate with others
in a group agent, since such actions require others to be willing to join with
us in their performance. And so choices involving those activities cannot
count as basic liberties that ought to be secured by state resourcing and
protection. The only choices that might call here for entrenchment as basic
liberties are the choices of tangoing, or associating in other ways, with those
who are willing to tango or associate with you.14
The collective, as distinct from individual, exercisability constraint impo-
ses further restrictions on candidates for the choices that the state ought to
secure.15 Clearly, it would rule out entrenching options that as a matter of
necessity not everyone can adopt at once. Thus no option that requires
achieving a superior position to others could be a basic liberty. You cannot
have a basic liberty to achieve an above-average score in a test, or to win a
14
Nor, it may be added, should the state secure the choices of existing groups, since this would favour
those who already happen to have formed such groups and would fail to treat people equally.
15
This constraint is close to the compossibility constraint that Hillel Steiner (1994) imposes on basic
rights.
96 Social justice
citizen-of-the-year award, though, of course, you may have the liberty to try
to attain such a distinction (O’Neill 1979–80). Apart from ruling out such
positional options, the constraint would also rule out options that are
available only conditionally on others not availing themselves of that
option. As things now stand, you may have a choice between selling your
house at current market value or continuing to own it. But not everyone
who owns a house can exercise that choice at once. Let all house-owners try
to sell their houses at current market value and the inevitable consequence
will be that the market value will fall well below its current level.
The collective exercisability constraint imposes these particular restric-
tions as a matter of logical necessity. But it imposes even more interesting
restrictions on the basis of contingent fact. Thus the fact that many of the
resources required for certain choices are scarce rules out making those
choices into basic liberties. In these cases, as Herbert Hart (1955: 175) puts it,
‘owing to scarcity one man’s satisfaction causes another’s frustration’. The
farmer and the cowboy may be friends if there is country enough for them
each to find land that they can use as they wish; the farmer will fence in one
region, the cowboy let cattle roam in another. But if there is only so much
land to go around, then under that condition of scarcity it will be impossible
for them each to use the land as they wish. Thus the collective exercisability
condition implies that the freedom to use land to your personal taste cannot
be a basic liberty.16
Hart himself invokes the unrestricted use of land to illustrate the fact that
there are some liberties that cannot be simultaneously enjoyed by all; there
would be physically inevitable conflicts amongst people who sought to
exercise that liberty at once (Hart 1973: 546–7). Another example, as he
suggests, would be the action of travelling by one’s preferred mode of
transport, since there would be a similar ‘conflict between pedestrians’
freedom of movement and the rights of automobiles’ (Hart 1973: 546,
n. 49). And another might be the action of withdrawing one’s money
from a bank; let everyone try to do that and the institution will break
down. Further examples can readily be imagined. The principle generating
them is captured nicely in G. A. Cohen’s (1979) observation that while
everyone in a room might be individually able to leave by the doorway, they
need not be able to do so together: the door may be just too narrow.
16
The farmer and the cowboy will be familiar from Rogers and Hammerstein’s musical, Oklahoma, but
the predicament they exemplify was already a matter of human experience in clashes between farming
and foraging peoples, some as early as the fifth millennium bce; see Morris (2010: 112–14, 127–8, 271).
The basic liberties 97
No plausible sort of state resourcing could overcome problems of collec-
tive exercisability that are based in logical necessity.17 But is there anything
that the state might do to overcome the problems raised by contingent facts
of scarcity? Are there any legal or political measures that might enable
people to co-exercise options otherwise precluded by scarcity, or at least
to enable people to co-exercise options that are closely related to the
precluded options? If there is nothing the state can do on these fronts,
then the alternatives are bleak. We will have to give up on the idea of
establishing basic, co-exercisable options in the use of land or transport, for
example. We might then have to acquiesce in an anarchic free-for-all where
the spoils go to the victor. Or we might have to adopt a system of central
rationing under which people live with whatever they are centrally allocated
in the way of permits for land-use or transport. Neither sort of alternative is
appealing.
Fortunately, however, there are measures that the state can take to
resource collectively exercisable choices in such areas. It can introduce
rules of coordination that would eliminate the problem of competition in
the use of land and transport and under those rules it can define or identify
choices that all can exercise at one and the same time. Let the state set up
common rules of ownership, for example, and it will be possible for every-
one at once to own and use land – or any other commodity – according to
those rules. Thus there can be a basic, rule-dependent liberty of owning and
using property. Let the state set up rules of the road and it will be possible
for everyone at once to use his or her preferred mode of transport; drivers
will take one route, pedestrians another. And so, again, there can be a basic,
rule-dependent liberty of travelling under the rules of the road by whatever
means you prefer.
Regulatory or coordinating initiatives of this kind would enable a society
to resource choices in ownership or travel that can then be candidates for
protection as basic liberties. And parallel initiatives could allay a vast array of
similar problems. The rules that govern banking can make it possible for
people to have regulated or coordinated access to their funds. And any rules
that coordinate access to something that cannot be accessed at once by all –
this, on the model of exit from a crowded room – can make it possible for
people to have a basic liberty in the exercise of the corresponding rule-
dependent choice.
17
I ignore rather implausible measures whereby, for example, everyone might have a choice of being top
dog for a day.
98 Social justice
Co-satisfying choices
If certain choices are worthy of being entrenched as basic liberties then not
only should they be individually and collectively exercisable – not only should
they be capable of being exercised by each, consistently with being exercised
by all – they should also meet a further condition. This is that they should be
sufficient to satisfy each consistently with satisfying all. As the criterion of co-
exercisability imposes a constraint of individual exercisability and a constraint
of collective exercisability, so this criterion imposes two constraints also, one
of which requires individual satisfaction, the other collective satisfaction.
The criterion of individual satisfaction argues that the choices we
entrench as basic liberties should be ones that by received social criteria
promote the enjoyment and welfare, over the long term, of those who make
them. In principle this criterion leaves room for denying protection for
certain choices that are judged to be harmful for the individuals exercising
them, even for criminalizing them as victimless offences. In practice, how-
ever, the republican approach is unlikely to argue for establishing such
intrusive criminalization, as we shall see later. Doing so would impose
collective judgement and preference on any individual in choices that are,
by hypothesis, co-exercisable. To treat such choices as victimless crimes, or
just to leave them unprotected, would be to impose society’s interpretation
of their interests on people and would represent a sort of paternalism that is
inconsistent with freedom as non-domination, as we saw in the last chapter
(Shiffrin 2000).
This is a point at which the eyeball test serves an important role, as
foreshadowed earlier, in determining how choices ought to be publicly
entrenched. When choices have the potential for harming the adult, able-
minded agents who exercise them, the eyeball test argues against criminal-
izing them or leaving them unprotected but does not support any more
active provision in their support. Take the choices associated with the use of
recreational drugs or with certain forms of gambling. The eyeball test
suggests that such choices do not call for any active form of resourcing,
and may even deserve to be subjected to heavy taxes.18 But it strongly
supports the view that since any other approach would be paternalistic,
failing to acknowledge the status of the agents, still the choices ought to be
protected. They ought to be given at least that minimal form of
entrenchment.
18
Even John Stuart Mill (1978) argued that such a line would be perfectly defensible, suggesting in some
cases that a society should seek to reduce the attractions of choices that can threaten long-term damage
to the chooser by imposing relatively higher taxes on the resources that they require.
The basic liberties 99
Turning to the other aspect of the co-satisfaction criterion, the constraint
of collective, as distinct from individual, satisfaction implies that in order to
count as entrenchable basic liberties, choices should not be such that if some
or all individuals exercise them then many people, perhaps including those
individuals themselves, will cease to enjoy the choices. Candidates for
entrenchment as basic liberties should be choices of such a kind that even
if everyone takes them, everyone can be more or less fully satisfied. This
constraint rules out choices in three broad categories: counter-productive
choices, over-empowering choices and harmful choices.
Taking harmful choices first, it is worth noting that there are many
choices that include the option of intentionally harming another person
and yet pass the constraint of co-exercisability. There is nothing in the
constraint of co-exercisability to stop people being able to lie and to steal
and even be violent to one another. But clearly establishing the choices of
inflicting such harms as basic liberties would in no way contribute to the
satisfaction of people overall. And so, unsurprisingly, the constraint of
collective satisfaction would argue against giving such choices an
entrenched status. The choices to be established as basic liberties should
all be innocent choices, as we might put it.
Over-empowering choices, to move onto a second category, are choices
whose entrenchment might allow the emergence of serious asymmetries in
the relative balance of resources and power amongst people. We saw earlier
that there is good reason to establish rules governing the use of land and, by
extension, property in general. Such rules would introduce rule-dependent
choices in the domain of ownership, exchange and bequest that people can
each exercise without coming to blows in the manner of the cowboy and the
farmer who struggle for possession of the same land. But it should be clear
that the rules of property may enable some individuals to gain such
economic power that they are bound to dominate others in certain con-
texts – for example, in employment or legal action or competition over
access to health resources. The constraint of collective satisfaction would
argue against introducing a system of choices that is liable to have such an
over-empowering effect. It would support any less dangerous alternative
that may be available.19
19
How might we cope with this problem, giving effect to the requirement of collective satisfaction?
There are a variety of measures that might be explored. Introducing progressive taxation as part of the
property system would be one possibility (Murphy and Nagel 2004). Another might be a system of
support or subsidy, in relevant contexts, for the economically weaker. Or yet another might be a
restriction on the comparative advantages that money can buy.
100 Social justice
The problem illustrated by harmful and over-empowering choices
derives from the fact, as Herbert Hart (1973: 550) observes, that entrenching
a choice as a basic liberty ‘necessarily does two things: first, it confers on
individuals the advantage of that liberty, but secondly, it exposes them to
whatever disadvantages the practice of that liberty by others may entail for
them’ (550). But this observation also explains why choices in a third,
counter-productive, category should be ruled out by the constraint of
collective satisfaction. These are choices whose exercise by a number of
people – at the limit by all – undermines the benefit that gives the choice its
characteristic rationale and appeal for some or for all (see Parfit 1984: Part i).
Hart (1973: 543) illustrates the case where the exercise of a choice by any
number of people undermines the benefit that it promises for each. Let
people all have a choice of addressing a group at will: say, a group compris-
ing their fellow citizens. It will clearly be possible for them each to address
the group and to do so at the same time, so that the earlier constraints raise
no problem here. But still we might pause over thinking that this choice
should be established as a basic liberty. For if a number of members try to
speak to the assembly at one and the same time, no one will be heard. And
so no one will be able to enjoy the characteristic benefit of speaking to the
group. Other examples of this sort of case arise wherever the individual
choice of a certain option promises a certain reward for each but the
aggregate result of a number of people taking that choice is that that reward
is not delivered. People may each wish to own a gun for their own defence
but if everyone owns a gun then, plausibly, no one is defensively better off.
People may each wish to drive into the city centre, but if everyone does so
then the point of driving there may be undermined for all.20
Another sort of case that fits in the counter-productive category arises
with choices that impose external costs on others, often triggering claims in
tort law. Let people have the liberty of making whatever use they wish of a
river that runs through their land and there is bound to be trouble in
prospect. The use which those upstream make of the river may severely
limit the use to which those downstream wish to put it; for example, the
20
In these cases, as in the case of speaking to the group, it is generally true, first, that everyone has a
reason to pursue the activity if no one else does; and second, that everyone prefers that no one pursues
it than that everyone pursues it. But it is worth noting that in some of the cases, unlike the group case,
a third clause is satisfied too: everyone may have a reason – a new reason – to pursue the activity if
others all do so. Setting virtue aside, no one will relish being the only person without a gun in a gun-
toting society. This makes these particular examples into cases of a broadly free-riding character
(Pettit 1986). In these cases, people each have a reason for pursuing the activity even if all others do –
they will not want to be made a sucker, as it is sometimes said – but that reason is not the
consideration that originally gave the choice its appeal.
The basic liberties 101
upstream factory can make it dangerous to allow downstream cattle to drink
the water. If any choice that is to be established as a basic liberty has to be
co-satisfying for all, not just co-exercisable by all, then this sort of choice
cannot be entrenched in that way.
Can the state help to overcome the sort of problem raised in our three
sorts of harmful, over-powering and counter-productive choices? Yes,
clearly it can. As with some of the problems raised by the constraint of
collective exercisability, it can introduce rules under which people are given
options that are close to the original, problematic options but are capable,
unlike them, of meeting the constraint of collective satisfaction. Thus the
problem illustrated by the case of speaking to a large group can be solved
under rules such as Robert’s Rules of Order (Robert 2011). These allow people
to take turns in speaking, dictating a pattern under which they can each
make proposals, suggest amendments to the proposals of others, and debate
and vote on the various issues that arise in their discussion. As such rules
might resolve the debating predicament, similar rules might resolve the
problems illustrated with gun ownership and car use. People can be given
the rule-dependent option of owning guns on condition of passing certain
tests or of using free or cheap parking facilities and taking public transport
into city centres.
The case illustrated with the upstream and downstream use of a river is
typically resolved in a different manner. The law of torts allows plaintiffs to
appeal to the courts for case-by-case judgements on whether someone
should be allowed to exercise such a choice and, if allowed, whether they
should be required to adopt precautions against damage to others. The
Hand test, named after the US Judge, Learned Hand, offers useful guidance
in the area. The idea, roughly, is that if the expected cost of effective
precautions to an agent in the exercise of some choice is less than the
expected cost to others of the harm associated with the choice taken without
precautions, then the choice should only be allowed when relevant precau-
tions are in place. Applied to the river case, it would require those upstream
to make use of the river only under limitations or precautions that involve a
lower expected cost for them than the expected cost to others of the
upstream activity taken in the absence of limitations or precautions.
* The freedom to travel within the society and settle where you will.
Back now to the crucial question. Suppose that the largest possible set of
such basic liberties is secured by public resourcing and protection in a
society. Does the entrenchment of liberties like these suffice on its own
for making a full and meaningful life possible for individuals? Suppose you
have the resources for making such choices and are not dominated in any of
these broad areas: you are able to exercise your own discretion, by intuitive
criteria, without worrying about the goodwill of others. Would the enjoy-
ment of the unvitiated, uninvaded capacity to exercise choice across that
range of opportunities suffice to give you access to the life that we would
expect a free person to be able to achieve?
The enjoyment of such liberty might not suffice for a meaningful life
under a Romantic or post-Romantic image of the fulfilment required – for
example, the Nietzschean image of life as an Übermensch. But the assump-
tion in the republican tradition is that it certainly can. It is possible to be as
free as a full and meaningful life requires, so the idea goes, and yet only to be
as free as other people: only to enjoy the same freedom across the same
choices and on the same public basis. It is possible to be personally fulfilled
without being socially privileged.
I go along, unhesitatingly, with this traditional view. Looking at the list
of entrenched liberties, I am inclined to ask a rhetorical question. If the
availability of these choices is not enough to make a meaningful, independ-
ent life possible, what else is needed? If not this, what? Perhaps the best way
of defending an affirmative attitude, however, is to look at what individuals
104 Social justice
would have to enjoy in the way of resources and protections if they really
had access to a maximal set of entrenched basic liberties. That takes us to the
topic of the next section. I sketch a model there of the institutions and
policies that the republican theory of justice would require – a model of how
we might safeguard the basic liberties equally for all – and suggest that the
model fits well, as reflective equilibrium requires, with our considered
judgements of justice.
Beyond Rawls
How plausible is it to claim that what justice requires amongst citizens is
equal freedom as non-domination, as we have articulated that ideal, and
nothing more? The claim may seem downright incredible in virtue of the
fact that whereas John Rawls’s (1971, 1993, 2001) theory of justice imposes
two principles, one prescribing equal freedom and the other a close cousin
of material equality, this theory imposes the first alone. Rawls’s theory, after
all, is the very paradigm of what we ought to expect of a theory of justice,
and if ours departs significantly from it, then that may seem to raise a
question about its plausibility.
It turns out, however, that the republican account cannot be cast as an
attempt to espouse Rawls’s first principle and to dispense with his second.
There are two reasons for this, even assuming that the same basic liberties
are targeted by each.21 First, unlike the republican approach, Rawls’s first
principle does not require full resourcing for the basic liberties; and, second,
it does not require their protection against domination, only their protec-
tion in a weaker sense.
21
Rawls’s basic liberties are not derived on a systematic basis, unlike those we target. In any case they
include certain liberties associated with political rights, such as the freedom to vote, since Rawls does
not distinguish the issue of legitimacy, as I understand it here, from the issue of justice.
108 Social justice
In Rawls’s usage people are free to do or not do something just insofar as
it is legally permissible for them to do it or not do it: they have a legally
protected right in respect of the choice or, equivalently, ‘government and
other persons . . . have a legal duty not to obstruct’ (1971: 203). ‘Liberty’, as
he says, ‘is a complex of rights and duties defined by institutions’ (Rawls
1971: 230). But the liberty to choose in this sense between two options
is quite consistent with an inability to make the choice: having that ability is
not required for the liberty as such, only for its worth or value (Rawls 1971:
204–5). Thus, for all that Rawls’s first principle requires, the choices that are
established as basic liberties need not be secured for all by public resourcing.
There is a direct contrast with the republican approach.
The second way in which the principle falls short of the republican
requirement is that it does not support an equally high level of protection
for the basic liberties. Rawls assumes, in line with standard practice, that
insofar as others are meant to have a legal duty not to interfere with one of
his basic liberties, they are subject to penalties. But he thinks that such
penalties may be scaled to the probability that others will indeed interfere.
Thus he says that while penalties may always be necessary for purposes of
giving people confidence that others will respect their legal duties, in the
sort of regime where there is general compliance – the regime that he seeks
to characterize in his ‘ideal theory’ – they will not be required for any other
reason: ‘in a well-ordered society sanctions are not severe and may never
need to be imposed’ (Rawls 1971: 240).22
This makes clear that for Rawls domination is not a problem as such. The
society envisaged in his ideal theory may be well ordered just because the
powerful generally display goodwill towards others. And so protecting
people against them only by such penalties as are required to create
confidence that they will not interfere – a confidence that is easily achieved,
given the evidence of goodwill – may leave the powerful effectively
22
Rawls’s views on freedom are quite complex. He begins with the idea that any form of freedom is a
freedom from constraint: ‘this or that person (or persons) is free (or not free) from this or that
constraint (or set of constraints) to do (or not do) so and so’. On this account, ‘many kinds of
conditions’ may serve a constraining role, including ‘duties and prohibitions defined by law’ and
‘coercive influences arising from public opinion and social pressure’, so that freedom presumably
consists in the absence of such constraints (Rawls 1971: 202). But he quickly goes on to give freedom
an institutional cast, as in my presentation here, holding that you are free to do something just insofar
as you have the legal right to do it or, equivalently, just insofar as ‘government and other persons . . .
have a legal duty not to obstruct’ (Rawls 1971: 203). ‘Liberty, as I have said, is a complex of rights and
duties defined by institutions’ (Rawls 1971: 230). On this institutional account to be free to do
something is not necessarily to avoid vitiating factors, for you may not avoid natural limitations,
which are now said just to deprive your liberty of its worth or value (Rawls 1971: 204–5); and
presumably you may not avoid the ‘influences arising from public opinion and social pressure’.
Sketch for a model of justice 109
unbound; it may leave them able to interfere at a relatively low cost. Were
domination taken to be a problem by Rawls, then he could not adopt this
line. He would have to recognize that even in a well-ordered society, it is
essential to have suitably protective blocks and burdens in place in order to
establish that no one depends on the goodwill of others for avoiding
interference.
What would make for a suitable level of protection – and, more generally,
entrenchment – against others? Some protection will come about via the
denial of resources or opportunity to the powerful – this amounts to
disarming those individuals or groups – and some via the defence of
individuals against them, whether at the time of the attempted offence or
by means of later requital. But no matter what form it takes, it is likely to
come in degrees. So what level of protection is going to be adequate to deal
with the danger of domination? The republican answer, of course, is that
protection ought to extend to the baseline dictated by the eyeball test: a
threshold, recognized in public awareness, such that for those at or above it,
a tendency to worry about the power of others – and so a tendency, for
example, to try to keep the powerful sweet – will be taken to express an
unwarranted, perhaps even irrational, degree of timidity or cravenness.
Whatever the level of protection that all should enjoy under such a test, it
is certainly higher than anything envisaged by Rawls in his vision of a society
that satisfies only his first principle of justice.
Because it does not guarantee the resourcing of the relevant choices, or
provide for their protection against domination, Rawls’s first principle
leaves many intuitively unjust inequalities in place. Not guaranteeing
resources required for exercising the relevant basic liberties, it may leave
some people in a position where they are unable to exercise those choices.
And failing to protect the liberties against domination, it may not register
the same degree of vulnerability, or the same need for safeguards, that would
appear in the republican project. It is because of the inequalities that this
principle would leave in place that Rawls introduces the second principle of
justice, seeking a fit – perhaps after some adjustment on the two sides – with
his considered judgements of justice; such a fit would help to establish the
reflective equilibrium with the judgements that his methodology requires.23
I argue that things look very different if we articulate the freedom-centred
concern in the republican way, relying on the eyeball test for interpreting it.
Let the resourcing of basic liberties, not just their protection, be important
23
For an explicit comment on how fulfilment of the second principle is required to provide in this way
for the basic liberties – in Rawls’s terms, to give them value. See Rawls (2001: 177).
110 Social justice
for freedom as non-domination, as the first chapter showed. And let the
protection required be sufficient to guard against domination under the
eyeball test. My claim is that in that case, the cause of entrenching the basic
liberties will come intuitively close to providing for what most of us will be
happy to think of as justice. It will not leave in place the shortfall that
prompts Rawls’s recourse to his second principle.
In order to see that this is so, it will be useful to look briefly at a model of
the policies that the equal entrenchment of the basic liberties is likely to
require. This is a slightly hazardous enterprise, for two reasons. Policies have
to be guided as much by empirical assumptions as by philosophical princi-
ples, so that principles alone will not lead us firmly to policies. And in a real-
world scenario of limited resources any policy programme is going to have
to require a variety of trade-offs, some of which are hard to track in advance.
The following sketch of the sorts of policies that a republican theory of
justice would support is bound, therefore, to have only a tentative and
illustrative status. For reasons of simplicity I set it out without much
argument over detail, though at almost every point I rely on the intuitive
guidance provided by the eyeball test.24
There are three main areas of policy-making that any plausible project of
entrenching the basic liberties would have to address. To describe them
alliteratively, the first of these has to do with public infrastructure, the
second with public insurance and the third with the public insulation of
people against danger from others. Infrastructural programmes would
establish a framework for the enjoyment of freedom as non-domination
amongst all citizens, insurance programmes would guard each against some
of the misfortunes that can undermine the achievement of equal freedom as
non-domination and insulation programmes would provide for their pro-
tection against the dangers that others can represent within specific relation-
ships and on a more general front.
Infrastructural programmes
There are three kinds of infrastructural programmes that will be required in
a republican theory of justice. These are necessary to establish a suitably
24
Notice, however, that republican policies will not have to alter with every change in actual circum-
stances. No matter what the actual circumstances, they are required to promote non-interference
across a range of possible circumstances; they have to make non-interference robustly available over
variations both in people’s own preferences for what they should do and in other people’s preferences
for what they should do. I return to this point in the concluding section of the chapter.
Sketch for a model of justice 111
broad range of choices in which people can hope to enjoy equal freedom as
non-domination in relation to one another.
The first requirement is that children in the society each have access to
the sort of education necessary to provide them with essential skills, to bring
their particular talents to fruition, to give them a full sense of the rights and
responsibilities of citizenship and indeed to let them see how bad it is for
anyone to suffer domination in the sphere of the basic liberties. Let people
be lacking in such developmental ways, and they will be incapable of
asserting themselves with others, or assuming the status of free persons;
indeed they may even be a danger to others, not recognizing the reciprocal,
freedom-based claims that are made upon them.
The second and third programmes required by way of infrastructure are
environmental in character, not developmental. One bears on the institu-
tional environment in which people operate, the other on the physical
environment, natural and constructed, in which they live.
In order for people to be able to enjoy the basic liberties equally, there has
to be a legal dispensation in place that provides a suitable institutional
environment for people’s lives together. That dispensation would establish
the property conventions and other arrangements required for the avail-
ability of certain co-exercisable, co-satisfying choices; provide rules for the
definition and redress of torts or wrongs that people may suffer as a result of
the negligence, if not the intrusive ill will, of others (Goldberg 2005: 6);
enable people to associate and incorporate with one another on a suitable
contractual basis, whether commercially, in employment, or in marriage
(Cohen 1933); and allow them to argue through the courts or other channels
for adjustments to the basic liberties that are protected. Beyond that, it
would enable people to enjoy the extra choices that may be made available
for entrenchment as a result of stable economic and financial institutions
(McGilvray 2011; Tomasi 2012). And at the same time it would establish
restrictions and regulations that guard against financial crisis, economic
recession, uncoordinated competition, commercial monopoly and
uncosted externalities, as well as the inequalities of power and influence
that allow some to lord it over others. All of these ills are likely to limit or
frustrate people’s equal access to basic liberties.
The third domain of policy-making that the state must address, if it is to
promote the widespread enjoyment of freedom as non-domination,
involves the material rather than the institutional environment. There will
be fewer basic liberties available for people, at least in the long run, the less
sustainable the natural environment, the less efficient the energy network,
the less reliable the organization of transport and information, the less
112 Social justice
effective the public health system and, indeed, the less secure the territory of
the state. Thus it will follow under the republican programme, as it will
follow under any plausible agenda for the state, that there have to be policies
in place to promote corresponding, broadly ecological goals.
Catering for the development of citizens, and for the maintenance of a
suitable environment, institutional and material, is one basic part of what is
going to be domestically required of a state if it is to promote equal freedom
as non-domination, establishing a suitably broad range of choices that can
be entrenched as basic liberties. The other two parts require arrangements
for the public insurance of individuals against certain ills, and for their
public insulation against the power and ill will of others.
Insurance programmes
There are a variety of conditions in which people are going to be unable to
exercise some of their basic liberties or are going to be exposed to the
domination of others. People will suffer such vulnerabilities if they do not
have sure access to shelter and nourishment; to treatment for medical need
or support for disability; or to representation in appearing as plaintiffs or
defendants in the courts. It is going to follow straightforwardly, on the
republican approach, that they should therefore be publicly insured – or
publicly required and enabled to have private insurance – against such
possibilities. They should be provided with social security, medical security
and judicial security, whether by means of a system of social insurance,
national health and legal assistance, or by any of a number of alternatives:
say, the provision of a basic income for each citizen (Raventos 2007). They
should be provided in these domains with Sen’s (1985) basic capabilities for
local functioning (Nussbaum 2006).25
Why require insurance against the ills listed rather than just putting
arrangements in place that make it likely that those in need will be helped
out? Why not just provide incentives – for example, tax concessions – that
will motivate the wealthy and powerful to help the needy? Or why not just
rely on people’s natural philanthropy to cater for the needs of others?
Perhaps those in physical need will be better off if they can have recourse
to privately funded kitchens and shelters, and perhaps those in medical and
25
This policy recommendation presupposes certain empirical assumptions, as I said that almost all such
recommendations do: in this case, the assumption that markets will typically leave people in need of
such insurance. For a defence of that assumption, and a critique of the ‘great risk shift’ whereby
markets were supposed to be capable of providing suitably, see Quiggin (2011).
Sketch for a model of justice 113
legal need will be better off if they can enjoy the pro bono services of
philanthropic professionals.
Republican theory is bound to reject the idea of forcing the less well off to
have to rely in this way on voluntary forms of philanthropy. The needy will
depend on the goodwill of voluntary benefactors for not being exposed to
the interference of those who are in a position to interfere in their lives,
which already comes dangerously close to being dependent on their good-
will in a dominating way.26 And once the needy are incorporated into
relations of such dependency, the baseline of expectation is bound to shift
so that any withdrawal of philanthropic assistance will count as the denial of
an established option: that is, as a form of interference. At that point the
needy will be exposed to a salient power of interference on the part of their
benefactors – an unvitiated, uninvaded capacity to interfere – and they will
be straightforwardly dominated. Or at least that will be so in the event,
surely quite likely, that benefactors are not pressurised to provide their
services or there are not so many benefactors lined up to provide help that
the needy depend on the goodwill of none in particular.
Not only should the needy be insured against the sorts of misfortune we
have been considering, they should be publicly insured in this way or, at the
least, publicly required and enabled to have private insurance. The need for
public insurance derives from the republican requirement that people
should be guarded against private domination by their enjoyment of a
public status as citizens who can access needed resources and protections.
If people enjoyed only publicly unmarked safeguards against private dom-
ination then they could not hope to live up to the traditional image of free
persons. Public insurance does not require universal provision for social,
medical and legal security but it does require that if people are unable to
provide for themselves in that manner, the public purse is available for their
support.
Many advanced societies fail to provide properly for the insurance of their
members on the social, medical and legal fronts, but it is worth noting that
almost all admit the desirability of public insurance on other fronts, so that
they can hardly object in principle to the argument here. No advanced
society is ready, for example, to deny help to those in a particular area who
are exposed to a natural catastrophe such as an earthquake, a hurricane or a
26
This goes back to the issue at the end of Chapter 1 as to whether failing to guard against the invasion
of freedom is as bad as invasion and whether the power of so failing is as bad as the power of invading.
I am assuming here that any philanthropic agency is going to be in a position, should it suit its
purposes, to withdraw benefits from a particular individual or at least from a particular area, whether
of geography or activity.
114 Social justice
tsunami. Very few are willing to deny special assistance to those unlucky
enough to be born with certain disabilities, or to develop them in later life.
And few are ready to allow depositors to lose all their savings when a major
bank is in difficulty. Such catastrophes expose people to the possibility of
domination in just the way that more personal crises can do. If it seems
reasonable for government to guard against their effects, then it should seem
equally reasonable for it to guard against the effects of personal crises as well.
But what if the personal crises are self-induced, as we might say? What if
the people who suffer them are to blame for falling on such bad times; they
gambled their money away, they smoked excessively or drove recklessly, or
they engaged in legally risky ventures? What, in short, if their problems are
due to bad option-luck rather than brute, bad luck? Does that imply that
there is no ground for state provision?
This implication is not supported by a republican approach to these
issues. For whatever the origin of the problem in any such case, the crisis still
exposes people to domination and still calls for remedy (Scheffler 2005). But
isn’t there a certain moral hazard in providing the benefits of a public
insurance for the bad results of an event for which a person holds a certain
responsibility? Might it not lead to reckless risk-taking on the part of some?
It might but it probably wouldn’t, for two reasons. First of all, the crises
involved are such that few would willingly run a salient risk of suffering such
a problem. And second, the insurance benefits available are not likely to be
such as to compensate fully for the loss endured in such a crisis. In any case,
it would seem perfectly reasonable for a community or state that is prepared
to insure its citizens in certain ways to take measures that guard against
reckless risk-taking. Such measures might take the form of obliging people
to wear seat belts while driving or of imposing restrictions on their oppor-
tunities to gamble or to incur excessive contractual obligations.
27
The policy likely to be supported would run directly counter to ‘the traditional negative libertarian
“at-will” doctrine that, consistent with contractual obligations, an employer may fire an employee for
“good cause, no cause or even for cause morally wrong”’ (Levin 1984: 97). For historical background
see Cornish and Clark (1989: 294–5).
116 Social justice
parts they play, and act to an aggregate effect that may not be clearly visible
to any one of them (List and Pettit 2011). Consequently, the corporate
agents they bring to life lack the vulnerability and the capacity for empathy
that individuals generally display (Bakan 2004). Compared with individual
human beings, such organizations will generally have an indefinite time-
horizon, a systematic indifference to life’s anxieties, and a more or less
bottomless purse.
Given the rights that they now enjoy in most societies, corporate agents
represent salient sources of domination. Think of how a multinational
corporation can treat its workforce – say, in its determination of working
hours or conditions – when it can move base without excessive cost and the
workforce are heavily dependent on it for employment and welfare. Or think
about how it may treat the local population or the local environment when
the community would be put in serious economic jeopardy by the corpo-
ration’s departure. Or think, finally, about how it may treat those who suffer
as a result of its negligence, whether as individual customers or as the victims
of an explosion or oil-spill, when it has access to better legal counsel, can drag
out court cases for years, and is subject to none of the pressures that shape
individual mentalities, not even the pressure of prospective death.
This rehearsal of problems is confined to the commercial sphere, ignoring
the issues raised when the victims of child abuse try to take on a church, for
example, or disaffected students or their parents attempt to achieve redress
from a school or university, or indeed a small business tries to negotiate terms
with a powerful union. But the problems should be more than enough to
illustrate the difficulties that have to be overcome if domination is to be
reduced within relationships between individuals and corporate bodies.
I do not mention the problems now in order to list some pat solutions.
What I mainly want to do is to stress the depth of specific safeguards that the
republican programme would call for and the challenge that it raises for the
design of suitably protective institutions (Lovett and Pettit 2009). But I
cannot resist making one suggestion. This is that corporate bodies of the
kind reviewed might be subjected in their own right, and on various fronts,
not just to the tort law that is universally allowed, but also to the discipline
of the criminal law that I shall be discussing shortly (Pettit 2007d, 2009a;
List and Pettit 2011).
The criminal law presupposes a capacity for understanding the merits of
the options presented in any choice, in particular the prohibition to which
relevant options are subject, and a capacity to respond appropriately to a
judgement of those merits. But there is every reason to think that a suitably
organized corporate entity will have, or can come to have, such capacities.
Sketch for a model of justice 117
And equally there is every reason to think that it makes sense to hold such an
entity responsible for any acts that it sponsors, organizing things in a way
that allows members to perform the acts in its name. Holding such an entity
responsible in its own right is consistent with holding those members
responsible at the same time for playing the parts required of them.
If we do expose corporate entities to criminal liability, then we can
impose penalties that ought in the longer term to deter offenders. While
the penalties may have to be mainly financial – we can’t put corporate
entities in prison, though we can disband them – they will inevitably carry
associated reputational costs: punishments in the currency of esteem
(Brennan and Pettit 2004). Such costs are bound to be particularly prob-
lematic for any corporate agent. They will affect the capacity of the
commercial corporation to attract or retain customers and the capacity of
non-commercial corporations like a church to attract or retain members.
They can chasten and discipline the most powerful organization and they
direct us to a way of establishing significant political control over corporate
behaviour.
Q. 1. What is criminalization?
To criminalize certain types of act is to introduce a system of law that is
designed to regulate – in particular to minimize – their occurrence by the
imposition of penal costs. Regulation by such penal costs is a distinctive
form of regulation. It contrasts in particular with opportunity-cost regu-
lation, on the one side, and admission-cost regulation on the other.
Opportunity-cost regulation would rely on regulating a particular sort of
action by rewarding the alternatives to such action. Admission-cost
28
I draw freely in the following discussion on Braithwaite and Pettit (1990) and Pettit (1997b). I have
been deeply influenced by Braithwaite’s work in this area.
118 Social justice
regulation would regulate the action by permitting people to perform it, but
only on condition that they pay a certain absolute cost: in effect, it charges
them for the right to perform the action.
By contrast with opportunity-cost regulation, criminalization imposes
absolute rather than relative costs: it makes threats against those who perform
a criminalized act rather than offering rewards for those who avoid it. And by
contrast with admission-cost regulation, it does not exonerate criminal
offenders who are willing to accept the penalties attached to their behaviour
and pay the cost; it continues to condemn the acts performed, communicating
a presumptive disapproval on the part of the community in general of anyone
who would perform them (Duff 2001). In making these points, I draw on what
I consider as a more or less commonly shared understanding of what crimi-
nalization involves. I take myself to be explicating the meaning of criminaliza-
tion rather than prescribing anything about the form that it should assume.
30
Where there is a shortfall from full culpability, different cases may require different departures from
normal procedure. Many forms of shortfall mean that the offence will not involve the first of the three
elements of harm that the text goes on to discuss, or at least not in the full degree; it will not impose
the will of a fully conversable agent. That argues that the departure from normal procedure should be
towards greater leniency. But the case of the highly dangerous, if not fully culpable, offender – say, a
certain sort of psychopath – suggests that this need not always be so. While such an offender ought
not to attract the condemnation attached to the criminal law, it may be necessary to impose severe
restraints for the sake of public protection. There is a difficult issue as to how such offenders ought to
be treated under a republican dispensation but I cannot explore it further here. I am grateful to Ben
Ewing for discussion of these issues.
31
For reasons advanced elsewhere, I believe that corporate bodies may be fit subjects for the criminal law
and that in their case it may make good sense to require, not actual guilt or mens rea – not full
culpability – but the capacity to develop procedures for guarding against the offence in question
(Pettit 2007d, 2009a; List and Pettit 2011).
Sketch for a model of justice 121
abused – there is no parallel argument against giving them a right to exercise
mercy under specified circumstances. Thus if an offender becomes disabled
in the course of committing an offence, there may be no pressing need to
reassure the community, and independent considerations may argue for
clemency. The right to exercise mercy would occasion domination only if it
were used at the unchecked discretion of authorities to treat like cases
differently, or used in such a widespread fashion that offenders can generally
expect to escape the advertised rigours of the law.
Any sentence that incorporates rectificatory features will have a deterrent
quality, since it is bound to impose costs on the offender. These include the
reputational costs of condemnation and the material costs of compensation.
But they include in particular the costs that must be paid for communal
reassurance, since these are determined precisely by the requirements of
effective deterrence. A criminal justice system is designed in the first place to
provide people with a suitable level of public protection against crime, and
hence assurance that they are not likely to be subject to the will of criminal
offenders (Kelly 2009).32 The threatened penalty required by such protec-
tion and assurance is designed to deter potential offenders and it is the
imposition of such a deterrent penalty – the implementation of the threat –
that provides the reassurance that rectification of the crime may require.
Since reassurance will be less readily forthcoming with chronic offenders,
this consideration also allows for the possibility of increasing penalties for
repeat offenders (Braithwaite 2002).
This connection with deterrence does not mean in itself that the
approach taken here has a consequentialist character, since retributivists
can also argue that while penalties should be scaled with offences on
independent, non-consequential grounds, the nature of the penalties
employed at different levels should be determined by deterrent consider-
ations.33 But the approach sketched, like the approach adopted throughout
32
This means that the severity of sanction will often have to be designed to compensate for the difficulty
and unlikelihood of detecting a relevant offence and not just a function of the degree of harm caused
by the offender and their degree of culpability.
33
Retributivism, as I understand it, is defined by commitments like the following.
1. There are certain constraints, which are not fully sensitive to consequences, that apply to criminal
punishment.
2. These include a ceiling constraint and perhaps also a floor constraint; the first argues against
exemplary punishment, the second against mercy.
3. Punishment should involve hard treatment, and not just because hard treatment has a deterrent
effect or is required if criminal penalties are to have a protective purpose.
4. Penalties should be proportional, ordinally or otherwise, to the degree of severity of the harm
combined with the culpability of the act, and not to anything else (with a possible exception if
mercy is allowed; see commitment 2 above).
122 Social justice
this book, is indeed teleological or consequentialist in character. The argu-
ment is that judicial and penal practice in the state ought to be designed on
such a rectificatory pattern that overall it makes for the promotion of equal
freedom as non-domination. This sort of practice-wide consequentialism is
consistent, of course, with requiring individual judges and courts to abide
more or less rigidly by the requirements of the practice, treating those
requirements as unconditionally binding (Rawls 1955). Thus, while the
practice described would allow judges and courts to be merciful in certain
cases, provided they can justify the exercise of such discretion, it would not
allow them ever to impose an exemplary punishment, making a generically
deterrent example of a particular offender.
5. Merely ordinal proportionality would require that penalties and crimes should be ordered from
toughest/worst to least tough/least bad and then paired off appropriately, with the toughest
applied to the worst crime, the next toughest to the next worst, and so on. Non-ordinal
proportionality would require that something more is possible in either or both of the two
scales; the limit case would be a belief in the lex talionis: an eye-for-an-eye, a tooth-for-a-tooth,
and so on.
The character of republican justice 123
The principle of republican justice
The principle or standard that the theory deploys, as we have seen, is simply
that arrangements between citizens should be designed to promote people’s
equal enjoyment of freedom as non-domination: that is, the equal entrench-
ment of their basic liberties on the basis of public laws and norms. This
principle is modest in its suppositions, goal-oriented in form, and general in
scope – in particular, general enough to be able to serve in either ideal or
non-ideal theory. Corresponding points apply to the principle of republican
legitimacy, as that emerges in the next chapter, but it will suffice to show
how they apply in the case of justice.
The republican principle is extremely modest in characterizing justice by
the requirements of equal freedom alone, without reference to any of the
richer and more controversial values invoked in many other theories of
justice; it is minimalist in the terms required to justify the policies supported
(Cohen 2004). What enables it to achieve this modesty is the independently
plausible argument that for relevant, unvitiated choices freedom requires
non-exposure to the interference of others, not just the absence – the
fortuitous absence, as it might be – of that interference. This construal of
freedom is plausible and also, as we saw in the Introduction, one with a long
historical pedigree. It was only in the eighteenth century, in the work of
figures like Jeremy Bentham and William Paley, that freedom came to be
routinely characterized as requiring non-interference rather than non-
domination. Contemporary theories of justice all give importance to free-
dom but take equal freedom to require so little that its requirements have to
be supplemented from other sources – as, for example, Rawls’s second
principle – in order to fix the demands of justice.
The principle of justice deployed in the republican theory, to move to a
second characteristic, offers a goal-oriented or consequentialist criterion of
evaluation. It says that a socio-political arrangement – a basic structure, as
Rawls calls it – will be just to the extent that it promotes free or undomi-
nated choice amongst its citizens, under the expressively egalitarian con-
straint of treating them as equals. More concretely, assuming that the
circumstances of justice obtain, it prescribes the promotion of the substan-
tively egalitarian goal of equal status freedom for all. This does not mean
that agents within the socio-political system are generally licensed to behave
opportunistically or strategically, as already mentioned, adjusting their
responses according to what they happen to think is best for promoting
that goal. It is the structure itself that is designed to promote the goal and it
is only likely to do this if the agents acting under the institutions established,
124 Social justice
be they officials or citizens, are generally required to act in accordance with
the duties and rights that they have under that structure (Rawls 1955).
Not only is it a practice-wide form of consequentialism; it is also a
constitutive, as distinct from a causal, variety of the approach (Pettit
1997c: Chapter 3). The goal of equal freedom as non-domination is modally
demanding, as we saw at the end of the last chapter, requiring a pattern of
non-interference that is robust across scenarios in which there are variations
both in what people prefer to do and in what others prefer that they do. But
people will enjoy the robust non-interference associated with justice – the
status of a free person – as soon as there are institutions of resourcing and
protection in place to safeguard them. The existence of those institutions
will not provide for people’s free status by way of a downstream causal effect
that takes some time to materialize. It will establish them in that status
without waiting on the result of any contingent causal process. The insti-
tutions will relate to the free status they establish in the way that the
antibodies in your bloodstream relate to the immunity against a certain
disease that they constitute. We can understand what such freedom requires
without knowing which institutions are required to support it – thus
freedom is not defined in terms of those institutions – as we can understand
immunity without knowing anything about antibodies. But still the con-
nection between the institutions and the freedom, or the antibodies and the
immunity, is not of a causal character. As the antibodies promote the
immunity by constituting it, so we can say that the institutions promote
freedom and justice in a parallel, constitutive fashion.
We have seen that the principle of republican justice is modest and goal-
oriented. A third feature worth mentioning is that it is available for the
applied exercise of measuring and comparing regimes for how just they are,
not merely for the theoretical exercise of identifying the perfectly just
society. It is a general theory of justice, as we might say, not the sort of
transcendental theory, as Amartya Sen (2009) describes it, which can rule
only on matters of perfect justice. While we can use the principle for
identifying an ideally just society – say, a society that is just enough to
pass the eyeball test – we can also use it to evaluate and rank the rather less
than ideal systems with which the real world presents us and to track
piecemeal progress within them (Marti and Pettit 2010: Chapter 5).
There are two reasons why the theory can serve us in the exercise of
measuring and comparing actual, imperfect regimes for how just they are.
The first is that it is a consequentialist theory that associates justice with
approximation to a certain goal. And the second is that it does not – or does
not necessarily – make any idealizing assumptions about human nature or
The character of republican justice 125
compliance with the law that would render it difficult to apply in the
ordinary world. These two features combine to ensure that in principle
we can measure and compare actual regimes for how just they are by seeing
how close they get to the relevant goal. In both respects the approach
contrasts with Rawls’s theory of justice. This insists in a non-
consequentialist spirit that justice is associated with instantiating a certain
pattern – the two principles – not with promoting it. And, perhaps even
more restrictively, it operates with the idealizing assumption that in ranking
regimes by reference to this pattern, we should assume that there is full
compliance in each with whatever laws are established there.34
But to say that the republican theory of justice allows for the applied
exercise of measuring and comparing justice in actual regimes is not to say
that our discussion has done enough to equip it for such application. There
are different dimensions on which a society’s degree of approximation to
establishing equal freedom as non-domination might be charted and a fully
applicable theory would have to provide weightings for these. As between
two different societies, for example, people might differ in enjoying freedom
in different sets of choices or in enjoying it with different degrees of
entrenchment. And where they enjoyed the same low degree of entrench-
ment for the same choices, they might differ in the likelihood of achieving
preference-satisfaction: they might differ in enjoying entrenchment, here
for exercising options they are likely to prefer, there for exercising options
they are unlikely to prefer. The republican theory can be used in practice for
measuring and comparing justice only under stipulations as to the relative
importance of these and other dimensions of variation in the measurement
of freedom and other values. And if no plausible stipulations are available on
the relative importance of two dimensions, that will mean that societies that
differ insofar as one does better in the one dimension, the second in the
other, may have to count – perhaps quite intuitively – as displaying justice
in the same degree.35
34
Rawls (1971: Part iii) argues that his two principles will tend to be internalized by those living under
them and to constitute a stable structure. But it would seem to be more satisfactory to consider
different principles, without assuming universal compliance, and then to rank them by reference,
among other standards, to how far they are likely to attract general compliance and display stability.
35
A full and applicable political theory would not only have to allow for variations in different
dimensions of social justice but also for variations in the relative degree of political legitimacy or
international sovereignty that societies enjoy. While there are reasons for giving political legitimacy a
basic importance, as mentioned briefly in the Introduction, the issue of weighting between these
different aspects of performance is too complex to be addressed fully here.
126 Social justice
The demands of republican justice
The republican theory of justice displays characteristic features, not just in
the principle that it deploys, but also in the demands that it supports. The
demands of the theory are quite substantive, despite the modesty of the
principle from which they are derived, as our institutional model of
republican justice indicates. They are designed to put resourcing and
protective measures in place that guard against personal domination in
the sphere of the basic liberties to the extent of enabling people to pass the
eyeball test. They are meant to reduce the incidence of domination
between people and to nullify the institutional or structural factors that
facilitate it (Hayward 2011).
The demands made by republican theory are certainly not as extensive as
those of egalitarian theories that seek the elimination, for example, of all the
effects of brute luck on people’s fortunes.36 Nor are they even as extensive as
Rawls’s requirements. His second principle of justice would look for mate-
rial equality, after all, except when the second principle of justice moderates
it, allowing a degree of relative inequality on condition that it improves the
absolute returns to the worst-off position. But those theories often seem like
moral fantasies: manuals for how God ought to have ordained the order of
things – or manuals for how we ought to rectify God’s failures – rather than
real-world manifestos for what the state should do in regulating the affairs of
its citizens.37
Such comparators aside, the republican theory of justice would still look
for quite extensive, even radical measures; while minimalist in its justifica-
tory base, it is not minimalist in substance (Cohen 2004). Beyond the
infrastructural requirements on which all sensible theories ought to con-
verge, as we have seen, it would seek a high level of social insurance, a firm
basis for the insulation of people in vulnerable relationships and a suitable
basis for the general insulation provided by the criminal justice system. It
would provide for the basic functioning capabilities of all citizens, as Sen
(1985) and Nussbaum (2006) describe them, and would enable people to
look others in the eye, without reason for fear or deference – or at least
without any reason related to the danger of interference.
36
For a recent interpretation and defence of luck egalitarianism see Tan (2008) and for a response that I
find congenial see Sanyal (forthcoming).
37
Hegel (1991: 80) has a salutary remark on the topic: ‘One cannot speak of the injustice of nature in the
unequal distribution of possessions and resources, for nature is not free and is therefore neither just
nor unjust.’
The character of republican justice 127
In arguing that the just state ought to promote equal freedom as non-
domination amongst its citizens, the republican theory of justice does not
suggest that freedom as non-domination is the only value that matters, as a
utilitarian theory might argue that utility is the only relevant value. What it
holds, however, is that if we look after the requirements of equal freedom as
non-domination, then we will have looked after the requirements of many
other values as well: for example, the value of enjoying functioning capa-
bilities. Look after equal freedom as non-domination in the relations
between citizens and you will have looked after an intuitive, left-of-centre,
account of the demands of justice. And, to anticipate the argument of the
next chapter, look after equal freedom as non-domination in the relations
between citizens and state and you will have looked after an intuitive,
democratic account of the demands of legitimacy. Freedom as non-
domination is not the only value in politics but in the account defended
here it serves a gateway role: if we pay the price of securing freedom as non-
domination in a suitable measure, we will have paid enough to secure social
justice and political legitimacy (Pettit 2005a; for a dissenting view see
Markell 2008).
Political legitimacy
In the last chapter we focused on issues of social justice: that is, justice in the
relations between people within a state, including relations mediated by
their belonging to groups and bodies of various kinds. According to the
theory developed, justice requires the state to promote the freedom as non-
domination of all its citizens – broadly, all adult, able-minded and more or
less permanent residents – safeguarding their fundamental liberties on the
basis of public laws and norms. This focus on relations amongst citizens
leaves out of consideration the relations between citizens as a whole and the
state itself. It ignores the question of whether the state operates with
political legitimacy in imposing a social order, however just that order
might turn out to be. It is one thing to argue that the social order imposed
by a state is just, it is quite another to argue that the political imposition of
that order is legitimate.
Social justice does not entail political legitimacy, by this account, nor
does political legitimacy entail social justice. Thus, to take the second
dissociation first, a state might be fully legitimate, by whatever criterion,
and yet not succeed in furthering the cause of social justice very well; it
might support misconceived, if not ill-willed, policies. It is a failure of this
kind that Rousseau had in mind when he acknowledged the possibility that
the perfectly legitimate regime – in his terms, the regime that seeks to enact
the general will – may still go astray: ‘By itself, the people always wills the
good, but by itself it does not always see it’ (1997: ii.6.10).
Turning now to the other dissociation, it also seems that the just society
might fall well short of being fully legitimate. The traditional paradigm of
the illegitimate regime is that which is controlled by a despot or by a foreign
power. But we can imagine a benevolent despotism, or an enlightened
colonialism, under which people’s relations with one another are ordered
in a socially just manner. That order might not have the robust entrench-
ment that we would associate with justice, especially from a republican
viewpoint. The will at its source might not have the reliability – the
130
Political legitimacy 131
resistance to despotic or colonial discretion – that the Roman Digest of law
requires when, quoting Ulpian, it says that ‘Justice is the steady and
enduring will to render unto everyone his right’ (Watson 1985: Book i,
Part 1, para. 10).1 But in other respects, it could be beyond reproach.
These remarks are meant to underline the conceptual divergence
between the demands of social justice and the demands of political legiti-
macy, not to suggest that in practice they can come apart very deeply. It is
unlikely that people who fared badly in justice terms could do much about
constraining the state to satisfy legitimacy. And it is unlikely that the
unconstrained state would do much to establish justice amongst its citi-
zenry. But the fact that political legitimacy can come apart in any measure
from social justice means that it makes a distinct demand and that we have
to begin afresh in thinking about what it requires.
Not only does political legitimacy make a distinct demand, it makes a
demand that we cannot ignore. In any society there are going to be different
views as to what social justice requires in the organization of people’s
relationships. Thus there is going to be a question as to whether it is
appropriate for people, recognizing their differences with one another, to
accept the decisions of the state as binding on them all and to submit to the
coercive application of those decisions by the state. And it will be appro-
priate for them to do this, presumably, only insofar as there is something
about the standing of the state in relation to them as a whole – something
about the relations between the state and its citizens – that makes it into the
legitimate arbiter and decider in their lives. The question for a theory of
legitimacy is to identify the factor that can give such a standing to the state
(Nagel 1987).
My discussion in this chapter falls into five sections. In Section 1, I look at
the legitimacy issue itself, asking after the precise source and nature of the
problem, and seeking to combat the tendency to let it drop from sight. In
Section 2, I argue for a tight linkage between legitimacy and freedom and
show that under freedom as non-domination legitimacy has a straight-
forward requirement: a form of popular or civic control over the state. In
Section 3, as in an intermission, I analyse the notion of control in general,
contrasting it with consent. In Section 4, I argue that if it is to support
1
The Latin is: Justitia est constans et perpetua voluntas ius suum cuique tribuendi. The view that justice
does not require such constancy of will is expressed in Leo Strauss’s (2000: 75) reading of the Greek
tradition, which he may or may not endorse himself (see Vatter 2011): ‘The just man does not hurt
anyone, but helps everyone who has dealings with him. To be just, in other words, simply means to be
beneficent. If justice is then essentially translegal, rule without laws may very well be just: beneficent
absolute rule is just.’
132 Political legitimacy
legitimacy, then popular control must be individualized, unconditioned
and efficacious in character, satisfying a rich version of the democratic ideal.
And then in a short Section 5, I make some observations on the desirability
of such a democratically controlled state, drawing attention to differences
between the perspective adopted here and other approaches.
The chapter provides a theory of democracy, arguing that the job of
democratic institutions is to ensure the form of popular control required for
political legitimacy. But the discussion does nothing to identify the sorts of
institutions that might actually do this job. That task is taken up in chapters
4 and 5, which provide an institutional model of democracy that is meant to
illustrate what the republican theory requires.
We argued in the last chapter about the requirements of republican
justice, starting from the expressively egalitarian assumption that the state
ought to treat its citizens as equals. As explained in that earlier argument, the
same egalitarian assumption will direct the argument in this chapter, when
we look for what is required by republican legitimacy. The normative
assumption is, on the one side, that the state ought to treat its citizens as
equals and, on the other, that citizens ought to be willing to accept this and
to live on equal terms with one another. This assumption is intuitively
compelling and is not specific to the republican approach; it is endorsed in
every plausible political philosophy.2
3
The ideal of a rule of impersonal, will-independent norms may have had a certain presence in the
history of republican thought. It often seems to lurk in the background when writers emphasize that
the great protection against the tyrannical and, more generally, the illegitimate regime is an ‘empire of
laws and not of men’, as James Harrington (1992: 8) described it, invoking Aristotle and Livy in his
support. The tradition led John Adams (1776) to write that ‘the very definition of a republic is “an
empire of laws, and not of men”’. This line of thought is also present in many authors who enthuse
about the common law, on the grounds that it emerges without a concerted, potentially dominating
will from decisions over particular cases. See for example Hayek (1988), who may have been influenced
by Kant’s (1996: 294) belief that ‘the sovereign, which gives laws, is, as it were invisible; it is the
personified law itself, not its agent’. For a commentary on the Kantian influence on Hayek, see
The legitimacy question 135
But however attractive the idea of an impersonal, will-independent
regime of protection, there is little hope that it could operate effectively in
the absence of a state. There are three salient problems that it would
confront. A first is that spontaneous norms would be unlikely to identify
basic liberties of an appropriate kind, particularly in view of the differences
between people on relevant matters and the difficulties of sorting out a
suitable set of liberties. As we saw in the last chapter, a variety of more or less
conventional rules, and provisions for the continuing adjustment of those
rules, are required in order to define suitably co-exercisable and co-satisfying
liberties.
A second problem with the proposal is that even if spontaneous norms
were satisfactory in other respects, they would be unlikely to mandate and
support full resourcing of basic liberties, especially when such resourcing
requires a degree of redistribution. Unregulated by the agency of a state,
wealth and power tend to accumulate in fewer and fewer hands. As by an
‘iron law’, to quote a recent history of political order, ‘the rich tend to get
richer, in the absence of state intervention’ (Fukuyama 2011: 368). It is
extremely unlikely that any spontaneous norms could resist the effects of
growing economic accumulation and ensure the resourcing of basic liberties
for the poor as well as the rich.
An order of spontaneous norms would be unlikely, then, either to
identify or to resource a suitable set of basic liberties. A third problem is
that it would also be unlikely to provide suitable protection for all.
Communal norms may assume any of a variety of objectionable profiles,
as they reflect divisions within society and impose patterns that are highly
injurious to those on the weaker side of gender or religious or ethnic or other
divides. It was for this reason that John Stuart Mill (1978) railed against the
despotism of custom. Norms of the kind envisaged may not impose the will
of a potentially dominating agency; after all, they are sourced and supported
by non-intentional attitudes. But they will almost certainly fail to protect
the members of certain groups against the most rampant domination on the
part of others.4
Kukathas (1989). A more plausible view of the laws is found in Demosthenes (1939: Section 224) in
Against Meidias: ‘And what is the strength of the laws? If one of you is wronged and cries aloud, will the
laws run up and be at his side to assist him? No; they are only written texts and incapable of such
action. Wherein then resides their power? In yourselves, if only you support them and make them all-
powerful to help him who needs them. So the laws are strong through you and you through the laws.’
4
See Fukuyama (2011: Chapter 17) for a related, salutary discussion of how the emergence of the rule of
law typically depends on the support of a state; it does not appear as by an invisible, non-intentional
hand.
136 Political legitimacy
I conclude that the cause of social justice requires the corporate agency
of a coercive state and that no apolitical order could serve in that role. To
assume that the state is essential for the promotion of social justice, of
course, is not to assume that any particular sort of state is essential, and
certainly not to assume that the existing pattern of states is ideal. But the
assumption that any sort of state is necessary generates the problem that
is now at the centre of our concern. Given that a state is necessary for
justice, there is an issue about how it ought to relate to its citizens, as
distinct from the issue of how the citizens ought to relate to one another.
And that, as I conceive of it, is the issue of legitimacy. Where the issue
of social justice is a matter of the horizontal relations of citizens to one
another, political legitimacy is a matter of their vertical relations to the
state that rules over them.
5
That the reasons are pro tanto in character means that they can be overridden by countervailing
considerations, as when the red lights go on. But consistently with having this pro tanto status, the
reasons might function under normal conditions – that is, in the absence of red lights – in an
exclusionary manner that precludes exercises in the weighing of pros and cons (Raz 1986). I am
grateful to Caleb Yong for a discussion on related matters.
The legitimacy question 137
Suppose that the social order imposed by a state is just and that the state
itself, by whatever criteria, is legitimate. In that case we will naturally say
that in view of its legitimacy people are morally obliged to accept the
regime, in some sense of acceptance, and that in view of its justice they
are obliged to endorse and comply with the laws. But what does it mean to
accept a regime? And how does such acceptance come apart, if at all, from
endorsing and complying with its laws?
The answer appears once we consider a case where the regime continues
to count as legitimate but certain of its laws are unjust. The injustice of
those laws will mean that people are not subject to the same content-
dependent obligation to endorse and comply with them, although they
will certainly be subject to a fall-back, pro tanto obligation that applies in all
half-reasonable systems of laws, just and unjust. This is the content-
independent obligation to comply that derives from the fact that once social
regularities are established by law people generally coordinate their activities
around the expectation of mutual compliance (Raz 1986). But the injustice
of certain laws will also mean, plausibly, that people are morally permitted,
perhaps even obliged, to try to change those laws. That raises the question as
to what is allowed to people in their attempts to change unjust laws. And it
is here that legitimacy, and the acceptance that I have associated with
legitimacy, are relevant.
The acceptance of the regime means, I propose, that attempts to change
unjust laws should be restricted to measures that are consistent with the
regime’s remaining in place. It requires you to acknowledge the state as the
appropriate arbiter and decider of legal issues, rather than taking the law
into your own hands, and to campaign for change on the assumption that
the state is to retain that role. Legitimacy imposes a pro tanto moral
obligation, then, if you oppose certain laws or measures – and given differ-
ent conceptions of justice, everyone will be disposed to challenge some – to
oppose them in ways allowed by the system: to stop short of revolution or
rebellion or, in an older word, resistance. It makes it permissible, invoking
justice or some other virtue, to oppose certain laws within the system: in a
word, to contest them. But it makes it impermissible to reject or resist the
regime itself.
Most regimes will offer some ways of opposing its laws that are clearly
within the system: appealing to the legislature, taking the government to
court, speaking out in the media, demonstrating in the streets and, of
course, challenging the governing party at election time. But the act of
breaking the law – notwithstanding coordination-based reasons to comply –
may also count as a mode of contestation, a way of opposing laws within
138 Political legitimacy
the system.6 This is exemplified in campaigns of civil disobedience where,
for example, campaigners break the laws – perhaps the laws they oppose,
perhaps other laws – in order to display opposition. When brought before
the courts, campaigners typically acknowledge the authority of the courts to
penalize them, thereby displaying their acceptance of the regime itself and
disavowing revolution or resistance. They invoke their willingness to accept
the authorized penalty for whatever abuse they have committed to draw
attention to the injustice of those laws.7
The legitimacy of a social order is often thought to correlate with the
political obligation of citizens. Such political obligation, on the proposal I
am making, is not the pro tanto obligation to obey the laws but the pro tanto
conditional obligation, if you oppose the laws, to oppose them within the
system.8 This conception of political obligation is independently plausible,
since political obligation is traditionally taken to bind people insofar as they
are citizens proper, not merely temporary or transient inhabitants. Even
those passing through a society have a pro tanto obligation to obey the law;
like others, they will have a content-dependent obligation to obey just laws,
and may have a content-independent obligation to obey any law, just or
unjust. But only citizens are likely to have substantive rights to oppose the
law within the system and only they can be meaningfully bound to limit
their opposition to intra-systemic contestation.
This comment squares with the broad conception of citizenship with
which I have been working. All adult, able-minded, more or less permanent
residents count as citizens, on this conception, not just those with the right
to vote and stand for office. While not all citizens in my broad sense will
have electoral rights, they will all have formal and informal rights to oppose
the law of a kind not readily given to those merely passing through. And in
effect most will have the right to seek electoral rights – and to expect to gain
them – by applying for formal citizenship. They will be in a position akin to
those enfranchised citizens who choose not to enrol on the voting lists, or
not to take part in voting, and who thereby deny themselves the oppor-
tunity to exercise their electoral rights.
6
The fewer the means of opposing a regime within the system, of course, the less likely it is that the
regime will count as legitimate: that is, the more likely it is that there are going to be some unjust
laws such that the available ways of opposing them within the system are so few that people are no
longer obliged to confine themselves to such opposition. But the availability of civil disobedience
means, at least in theory, that there is always at least one way in which a regime can be opposed
within the system.
7
For a broadly congenial – purportedly ‘republican’ – account of the sort of civil disobedience that
might be warranted see Markovits (2005).
8
For an intriguing but rather different view of political obligation, see Gilbert (2006).
The legitimacy question 139
The discussion so far speaks as if it is only the state, or the social order
it imposes, that counts as illegitimate. But this is for convenience only.
When a state or regime is illegitimate then the laws it upholds are
individually illegitimate and the branches of government that run the
state are illegitimate too: they are tainted by the illegitimate routines of
appointment employed. But there is also room for claiming in the same
sense of the term that while a regime is generally legitimate, certain laws
or appointments – including the appointment of an executive or other
branch – are illegitimate: they happen to breach conditions of legitimacy
that the regime generally respects. While I shall continue to concentrate
on the legitimacy or illegitimacy of regimes, I do not mean to deny that
there is room for invoking the concept in more local complaints as well.
And of course I allow that illegitimate laws, being objectionable like
unjust laws, may be suitable targets for contestation within a legitimate
regime.
Is it appropriate, however, to treat the legitimacy of a regime as an on–
off matter, as in effect I have been doing? I believe that the factors that
make for political legitimacy, like the factors that make for social justice,
come in different degrees. But as I am happy to treat social justice as an
on–off matter, given the eyeball test for determining where the justice
threshold lies, so for similar reasons I am happy to treat political legitimacy
as an on–off matter. As we shall see, there is an intuitive tough-luck test for
determining in a parallel way where the legitimacy threshold falls.
I said earlier that while the justice of the laws gives people a content-
dependent if pro tanto reason to conform, there will almost always be a
content-independent reason to conform to any reasonable system of laws,
just or unjust, viz., that they serve as coordinating devices around which
people build mutual expectations. Given that the laws of a legitimate
regime may not themselves be legitimate, and given in particular that the
regime itself may fall short of legitimacy, it is natural to ask whether there
is any corresponding fall-back reason why people should still not resist
the regime: any reason why they should restrict themselves to opposing it
within the system.
The issue is not central to our concerns but, for the record, I think that
there may be a very good reason – and not just a reason of personal
prudence – to stop short of resistance to a certain sort of illegitimate regime.
This is that however illegitimate it may be, the regime is still capable of
being made legitimate by being treated as if it were legitimate: that is, by
being opposed only within the system. Without being fully legitimate, the
system may in that sense be legitimizable. And my proposal is that
140 Political legitimacy
legitimizability can plausibly count as a fall-back reason to avoid outright
resistance and oppose a state only from within the system.9
The virtue of patriotism, traditionally associated with taking sides with
your existing state in international conflicts, might be taken in the domestic
context to argue for this sort of fidelity to an existing state and constitution,
even in the face of the state’s failure to be legitimate (Mueller 2007). I shall
not have much to say about legitimizability or patriotism in the remainder
of this book. But it should be clear that the issue is of immense importance
when it comes to drawing practical implications for how far people are
politically obligated to the states they live under. Few actual states may
count as legitimate, even by the realistic, tough-luck test of legitimacy
introduced later, but many are likely to count as at least legitimizable.
We have seen that according to any theory, the legitimate and just order
imposes a moral obligation to accept the regime and to comply with the law –
as always, in a pro tanto sense – and that the legitimate but unjust order
imposes an obligation to accept the regime, opposing unjust laws – and, of
course, illegitimate laws – only within the system: that is, contesting those
laws but not resisting the regime. The illegitimate and unjust order will not
require acceptance or compliance on the same basis; putting aside fall-back
reasons, it will permit citizens to resist the regime and, using whatever means
are available within, or presumably without, the system, to try to alter the law.
What of the fourth, unlikely case, where there is an illegitimate, yet just order?
That will allow resistance to the regime but offer reasons of both a content-
dependent and content-independent kind for compliance with the law; it will
authorize a mix of challenging the authority of the state to impose the laws
combined with recognizing that the laws imposed are themselves unobjec-
tionable. The possibilities are charted, however roughly, in Table 3.1.
Legitimate social order Should accept, should comply Should accept, may contest
Illegitimate social order May resist, should comply May resist, may contest
9
As legitimizability offers a reason for treating a state as if it were legitimate, so I have argued elsewhere
that a corresponding form of responsibilizability offers a reason for treating someone as if they were
responsible: that is, for holding them responsible. See Pettit (2001e, 2007d). The responsibilizable
agent will be capable of being made responsible – fit to be held responsible – by being treated as if they
were responsible – that is, by being held responsible. The legitimizable state will be capable of being
made legitimate – fit to be opposed only within the system – by being treated as if it were legitimate –
that is, by being opposed only within the system.
The legitimacy question 141
Legitimacy in its heyday
One reason for speaking of political legitimacy and social justice, rather than
of justice in a comprehensive sense, is that it may help to guard against the
danger of not recognizing how distinct these questions are.10 The social
justice question bears, as we know, on the character of the rules that
determine the claims that citizens have, relative to one another, within
the state. The legitimacy question bears on the way in which that set of
rules – and any other associated rules – is imposed on citizens. It concerns
the actual world and the contingent relationship between the people in a
regime and the social order that obtains amongst them; in particular, the
relationship whereby that order is sustained under the regime. By all
accounts the social order will be legitimate insofar as it is sustained in an
appropriate way, illegitimate insofar as it is sustained inappropriately: say, to
invoke paradigm cases, sustained independently of what citizens think, by
the will of a local despot or a foreign power.
Theories of the requirements of legitimacy assumed a remarkably
strong form in seventeenth- and eighteenth-century political thought,
though always against a background assumption that limited the people
or citizenry to mainstream, usually propertied males. The theory of the
divine right of kings had suggested that only the actual, if presumptive,
blessing of God could establish the legitimacy of a sovereign and of the
order that that sovereign chose to impose. Thomas Hobbes (1994b)
directly challenged that theory in arguing that it was the implicit, con-
tinuing consent of subjects – albeit a form of consent that could be
extracted under fear or pressure – that made the rule of a particular
sovereign legitimate; postulating the harsh alternative of a lawless state
of nature, he thought that rationality required individuals to give their
consent to whatever individual or body had the power to keep the peace.
John Locke (1960) argued that two conditions gave legitimacy to a
commonwealth: first, the unanimous, historical consent of individuals,
guided by a desire to establish a fair arbiter of disputes, to exit the state of
nature and set up a state; and two, the support of the existing government
by majority will, as evident in the failure of a majority to be moved to
rebellion by any alleged abuses of the arbiter role. Finally, Jean-Jacques
Rousseau (1997) held that legitimacy required that the majority voice of
the assembled citizens should rule on issues of general law, where once
10
The person who has done most to underline the distinctness of these questions in the recent literature
is A. J. Simmons (1976, 1979, 1999).
142 Political legitimacy
again such majoritarian decision-making had been unanimously and
freely accepted, in exiting the state of nature and forming a state.
Thinkers like Hobbes, Locke and Rousseau certainly had ideas about the
social order that they thought government should establish, but their works
were primarily addressed to the issue of legitimacy, which they made vivid
with the theatrics of an imagined state of nature. Each was intent on
identifying those conditions under which they thought people were obliged
to accept a regime and conditions under which they were entitled to rebel:
that is, to reject the state or sovereign whereby the existing order is
sustained. The Hobbesian and even Lockean theories offered very limited
grounds for rebellion, although it is worth recalling that Bishop Bramhall
(1658: 515), his opponent in debates about freedom, thought that Hobbes’s
Leviathan was ‘a rebel’s catechism’. Rousseau’s Social Contract was more
radical in intent, suggesting that many existing states were not involved in a
legitimate exercise but merely in ‘subjugating a multitude’ (Rousseau 1997:
i.5.1). It is no wonder that he attracted the hostile attention of the French
and other authorities, although he was prudent enough not to call explicitly
for rebellion against their regimes.
11
The approach that he exemplifies in this later turn is shared loosely among a large range of
contemporary political and moral thinkers, including Charles Beitz (1989), Thomas Pogge (1990),
Thomas Nagel (1991), Brian Barry (1995), T. M. Scanlon (1998) and Rainer Forst (2002). For a radical
critique see Simmons (1999) and for a critique more closely related to the Rawlsian starting point see
Reidy (2007). Anna Stilz (2009) represents a rather different approach that also starts with Kant – in
particular, with his observation that the right to external freedom presupposes membership in a
144 Political legitimacy
justifiability in this sense is a concern that that order should have a certain
intrinsic character – in particular that it should be comprehensively just –
and is distinct from the concern for whether it is appropriately supported
that we find in Hobbes, Locke and Rousseau (Simmons 1979, 1999).
The elision of the problem of legitimacy under the contractualist way of
thinking may be due to a confusion that is easily made. Legitimacy is the
ideal, under a natural formulation, of having a social order that is imposed
only insofar as it satisfies terms that people actually endorse. Under this
ideal people effectively dictate the terms on which a social order will be
accepted and, on any interpretation of that claim, they can be said to
support the order imposed. Justice, in the new contractualist formulation,
is easily confounded with this. It is the ideal of having a social order that is
imposed only insofar as it satisfies terms that people could have rationally
endorsed, even if they didn’t: in Rawls’s (1995: 148) way of thinking, ‘terms
that all reasonable parties may reasonably be expected to endorse’. The
difference in formulation is subtle but it may mark a deep divide. Even an
order that is not suitably supported by its people, as they are actually
disposed, might satisfy terms that they would endorse if they were properly
rational or reasonable.
As I mentioned, contractualist theory focuses not only on social justice
but on comprehensive or social-cum-procedural justice, so that Rawls (1971:
2003) includes procedural or political rights amongst the basic liberties
required by justice. Does the wider focus of contractualist and similar
theories mean that the criticism offered here is unfair? I do not think it
does mean this, but postpone an account of why not until the end of this
chapter. At that point we will be in a better position to see both the strength
and the weakness of the approach that contractualism typifies.12
I have been arguing that perhaps the two major strands of political
thinking, respectively utilitarian and contractualist, tend to neglect the
issue of legitimacy, ignoring the importance of how people actually relate
political society: this, because there can be no property, for example, without a coercive state (Kant
1996: 409). She argues that given our joint engagement in creating our local political society, it will
have a distinctive claim on us – in our terms, a claim of legitimacy – and we will have a correlative
obligation of loyalty to it; or at least this will be so insofar as the society does actually provide for our
enjoyment of external freedom.
12
If the procedural rights that count for Rawls among the basic liberties were required to ensure people’s
control over the social order, then on the view to be defended here, Rawlsian justice – that is, his two
principles – would require legitimacy in our sense. But as a matter of fact Rawls (1971: 233) himself
downplays the political liberties, as we shall see, casting them as ‘subordinate to the other freedoms’,
and does not suggest that they ought to ensure control in that sense. His focus on justice is mainly a
focus on social justice, as we have been describing it, and it does not bring issues of legitimacy into
prominence.
The legitimacy question 145
to the regime under which they live. But the oversight is not confined to
these two approaches. Egalitarians of various stripes also tend to ignore the
question, concentrating on the extent to which a social and perhaps proce-
dural order displays the particular sort of equality they favour, be that
equality in resources, utility, capability, or whatever. Other very different
writers like David Gauthier (1986) and Robert Nozick (1974) also overlook
legitimacy in favour of something else. Gauthier looks for an order that self-
interested subjects would have rationally agreed on, starting from a bargain-
ing standpoint that it would have been rational to accept. And Nozick looks
in a legal order for the satisfaction of a parallel counterfactual: if people were
situated in a morally acceptable world – as he thinks of it, a Lockean state of
nature – then they could plausibly have generated that order as the bypro-
duct of morally acceptable, self-interested adjustments.
But there are some contemporary figures who may be keyed, however
implicitly, to the legitimacy problem. They generally start with democratic
decision-making, however understood, and argue for the importance of
having a social order that is sustained by suitable democratic mechanisms.
This group will include deliberative democrats who insist on the impor-
tance of having an order that is actually sustained by processes of democratic
deliberation; it will not include those, however, who insist merely on the
importance of having an order that could have been sustained in that way.13
More generally, the group will include those who see importance as such in
the fact that a social order is grounded in a pattern of democratic decision-
making, whether canonically deliberative or not.14 The republican theory of
legitimacy, as we shall see in later chapters, connects with these democratic
traditions of thought.
A question of freedom
What might make it the case that the state that imposes a social order on its
citizens does so legitimately? What might ensure that while citizens may not
all approve of what the state actually does in establishing laws, imposing
15
Despite his opposition to contractualism, Bernard Williams (2005: 4) adopts a usage that is very close
to this when he says that the ‘basic legitimation demand’ requires the state to ‘offer a justification of its
power to each subject’. Since the justification need not be accepted by each subject, this conception of
legitimacy is also distinct from that invoked here.
Legitimacy as popular control 147
policies or levying taxes, still they do not have good grounds for complaint
about its presumption in taking those actions? They remain obliged to
accept the state as the relevant arbiter and decider of legal issues, restricting
themselves to opposing laws only within the system set up by the state.
The primary reason that the state raises a question of legitimacy of this
kind is that in pursuing its distinctive tasks, it assumes and exercises a
presumptively unchallenged right to coercion: it brooks no opposition.
People are not given an individual choice on whether or not they will
have to follow the laws imposed, fall in line with the policies pursued, or
pay the taxes that are levied on them. They are required by the state to do so,
on pain of enduring the rigours of punishment. The problem of legitimacy
is how to reconcile such political submission with personal freedom, identi-
fying a sort of regime that can coerce citizens without depriving them of
their freedom. The question, in Rousseau’s (1997: iv.2.7) words, is how ‘a
man can be both free and forced to conform to wills which are not his own’.
Or in a contemporary variant, ‘How might a person be self-governing
through institutional enactment of a law to which he is opposed?’
(Michelman 1999: 23).
On this freedom-centred interpretation of legitimacy, the question in
republican terms is whether a state can impose coercively on citizens with-
out dominating them. We saw that in order to promote social justice the
state must treat citizens well and equally in ordering their relations with one
another; in republican terms it has to provide for their equal undominated
status in those relations. What we now have to see is whether in a corre-
sponding sense it can treat citizens well and equally in ordering their
relations with the coercive state itself; whether it can provide for their
equal undominated status in those relations.
It is worth noticing that, phrased in this way, the problem of legitimacy
can be detached from ideas of the state of nature that provided a stage-
setting in the heyday of the problem. Once it is granted that freedom can be
compromised, not just by the social order imposed by the state, but also by
the mode in which the state imposes it, the problem becomes inescapable.
And the problem remains inescapable even if we reject the idea that in order
to solve it we have to show how it could have been rational for people to
opt for political organization from within an imagined scenario of a pre-
political, natural kind. Arguably, the legitimacy problem was at the centre of
concern from well before the advent of state-of-nature thinking; it assumed
that place in the Roman origins of republican thought and remained at the
centre throughout the period of Renaissance and modern republicanism.
Roman republicanism was grounded in the claim that people’s freedom
148 Political legitimacy
would be compromised under any form of monarchy and that it was only
citizenship in a suitable republic that could ensure freedom. This same
thesis is present in Machiavelli’s Discourses and in the literature of the
seventeenth- and eighteenth-century tradition, inspiring a search for repub-
lican devices whereby a state might impose on people without compromis-
ing their freedom (see Richardson 2002).
There may be grounds for arguing that despite taking away people’s
freedom, a state can claim the authority that goes with legitimacy on distinct
grounds and that legitimacy does not have to be interpreted in freedom-
centred terms. Perhaps the state is successful in epistemic terms, letting
people reliably identify the requirements of justice without subjecting them
to the rule of others (Estlund 2007).16 Or perhaps it enables them to live
together without civil war, as a pragmatic justification might suggest
(Williams 2005). Perhaps it is the only sort of state that coheres well with
an assertion of the fundamental equality of human beings (Buchanan 2002).
Perhaps, to invoke a broadly Confucian approach, it puts people of virtue
and talent in power; it is distinctively meritocratic (Bell 2010). Or perhaps,
as Ronald Dworkin (2011: 321–2) has recently argued, it manifestly strives to
promote social and procedural justice, ‘recognizing that the fate of each
citizen is of equal importance and that each has a responsibility to create his
own life’.
Such theories of legitimacy will only have plausibility, however, on the
assumption that no effective state can preserve people’s freedom. It would
hardly make sense to invoke an epistemic, pragmatic, egalitarian or meri-
tocratic feature – or the goodwill that Dworkin invokes – in arguing for the
legitimacy of a freedom-denying regime, if there were an alternative regime
available that could claim to preserve people’s freedom. Why should people
accept a freedom-denying state, whatever its other merits, when there is an
alternative available that can play the role of common arbiter and decider
without compromising their freedom? It is only if we have to despair about
assessing legitimacy in terms of freedom that we will be required to explore
alternative approaches. Thus we are returned to the freedom-centred
version of the legitimacy issue. How can the citizens of a state be free and
yet subject to state coercion?
This question, as might be expected, is going to assume a different
form, depending on how freedom is understood. I look in this section
at the way it will present itself, first, under the conception of freedom as
16
For another broadly epistemic approach, although one inspired by a pragmatist perspective see Talisse
(2007).
Legitimacy as popular control 149
non-interference, and then under the conception of freedom as non-
domination. I shall argue that while freedom as non-interference cannot
support any plausible conception of legitimacy, republican theory can;
and that under a republican conception, what legitimacy requires is
shared, popular control of the state.
17
It is worth noting that unlike Bentham, Paley (2002: 312) argued that no coercive laws that promoted
the common good should be regarded as reducing the freedom of subjects.
18
As I argue in Pettit (1997c: Chapter 1), a friend of Bentham’s, John Lind, used these ideas to
propagandize on behalf of the British government against the American colonists in the 1770s.
Drawing on Bentham, he argues against the republican Richard Price, that liberty is ‘nothing more
or less than the absence of coercion’ and therefore that law inevitably takes away liberty since ‘all laws
are coercive’. And then, with those claims in the background, he asks why the rule of the British
government in America is problematic, given that it imposes laws at home as well as in the colonies.
The idea is that the Americans have no particular complaint since the law-making power is ‘exercised
by the same persons over all the subjects who reside in all the other parts of this same empire’ (Lind
1776: 16, 24, 114).
Legitimacy as popular control 151
century (Atiyah 1979).19 The idea is that if someone consents to an arrange-
ment with another under which they suffer the other’s intervention, then
such an invited form of intervention does not count as interference and does
not take away from freedom. In a legal, Latin tag that was often invoked in
this connection, injuria non fit volenti: ‘no injury, and no interference, in
the presence of consent’ (Hobbes 1994a: 21.3, 1998: 3.7).
This response need not imagine a population-wide agreement to esta-
blish a political regime of the kind invoked in the state-of-nature tradition.
What it says is that the state will not count as interfering with its citizens,
even as it imposes coercively upon them, so long as the interference
practised attracts the consent of each individual subject. The consent
postulated may be prior consent or consent of a continuing character. But
in neither case can the postulate serve the purpose for which it is designed.
The consent you may have given to the state’s coercion in the past is quite
consistent with that coercion’s being unwelcome and frustrating at later
times in the characteristic manner of interference. So there is no hope on
that front. The continuing consent you may be thought to give to the state’s
coercion offers a more promising ground for claiming that the coercion does
not constitute interference. But this possibility also turns out to be a dead
end. The problem is that it is utterly implausible to postulate continuing
consent on the part of citizens generally, however implicit or tacit the
consent may be, to the coercion of their state. People may welcome the
regime they live under but, as David Hume (1994) had already argued in
the eighteenth century, they will not consent to it in the sense of adopting it
voluntarily: that is, adopting it in preference to an otherwise acceptable
alternative (Olsaretti 2004). And it is only consent that is voluntary in that
way – and not just voluntary in the Hobbesian sense in which submission
out of fear counts as voluntary – that can make the coercion of the state
count as something less than interference.
If these observations are sound, then the conception of freedom as non-
interference raises a dilemma for understanding legitimacy in a freedom-
centred way. Either, to take the first response, legitimacy in that sense ceases
to count as an ideal that a state or social order ought to satisfy, which is
problematic. Or, to take the second, it becomes an ideal that no actual state
19
I bracket the role of the monarchomach (or king-killing) tradition of thought as that is represented,
for example, in the late-sixteenth-century tract, Vindiciae Contra Tyrannos (Languet 1994). Adherents
of this tradition, which became an established school of thought in many European countries, argued
against absolutists that any people that is ruled by a monarch must be supposed, as a collectivity, to
have made a contract with their ruler under provisos that would allow them to dismiss that ruler –
literally or figuratively to kill the king – in the event of certain forms of injustice or tyranny.
152 Political legitimacy
or social order is capable of satisfying, which is equally problematic. Either
the ideal is irrelevant, in effect, or it is infeasible. Things look very different,
however, from a republican perspective in which freedom is cast as non-
domination.
21
John Rawls (1993: 222) appears to envisage this form of current consent when, having dismissed the
possibility of past consent, he writes: ‘we may over the course of life come freely to accept, as the
outcome of reflective thought and reasoned judgement, the ideals, principles, and standards that
specify our basic rights and liberties, and effectively guide and moderate the political power to which
we are subject. This is the outer limit of our freedom.’ For a defence of the view that such acceptance
can count as voluntary, see Otsuka (2003: Chapter 5).
22
If you bind yourself only conditionally, retaining the ability to call off the arrangement in the event of
the other person breaching some conditions, you will retain a degree of control and may not be
subject in a relevant sense to the domination of the other.
The nature of control 159
freedom as non-interference make use of the idea of controlled interference,
joining republicans in the claim that a suitably controlled but in no way
consensual government – this is the possibility explored in the next section –
might be a legitimate, freedom-compatible agency?
Might they argue that controlled intervention is not really interference,
to take a first possibility, as they seek to argue that consensual intervention is
not really interference? No. Controlled but non-consensual intervention
must count as a form of interference, since it may also be characteristically
frustrating. Moreover, unlike consensual intervention, there is no sense in
which it will count as invited or condoned. Thus, even if the intervention of
the state in people’s lives takes place under their control, there is very little
plausibility in saying that it does not really count as interference. It may be
extremely frustrating and in general there is no sense in which citizens need
invite or condone it.23
Might those who cast freedom as non-interference accept this but still
argue, to take a second possibility, that controlled interference does not take
away freedom in the same way as uncontrolled? Again, no. Under the
conception of freedom as non-interference, you are going to have freedom
of choice in relation to me just insofar as I do not interfere with you: I do not
intentionally remove, replace or misrepresent any option. You will suffer a
loss of freedom as a result of any such interference on my part and you will
suffer a loss of freedom only as a result of such interference. On this
approach, then, the issue of whether I have a power of uncontrolled
interference in your choice is irrelevant to whether I take away from your
freedom. And equally, the issue of whether the state has a power of
uncontrolled interference in the choices of citizens is irrelevant to whether
it takes away from their freedom. Freedom just is non-interference, on this
approach, and the issue of whether the interference is controlled or not is
simply beside the point.
There may be a powerful intuition, as I think there is, that the interfer-
ence you control – the interference exemplified in the alcohol example –
does not take away from your freedom of choice. But in order to give
countenance to that intuition, members of the opposed school of thought
would have to give up on their central commitment to the idea that
interference and interference alone reduces freedom. They would have to
endorse the republican idea that it is domination that really matters in the
23
The only plausible case in which we might want to deny the name of interference to a form of
intrusive intervention is where the intervention is both consensual and controlled. It genuinely
attracts the voluntary, continuing consent of the subject of the intervention.
160 Political legitimacy
freedom stakes. Thus the idea that a suitably controlled government might
be a freedom-consistent agency is simply unavailable under the identifica-
tion of freedom with non-interference. It is exclusive to the republican way
of thinking about freedom.
24
Nor of course can you escape the deeper necessity of living in community with other people. For an
extended argument that this should be regarded as a matter of more than causal necessity see Pettit
(1993).
25
I ignore the question of whether this would hold even if the very survival of the state depended on
keeping you, and others like you, within its boundaries.
162 Political legitimacy
not discriminatory and dominating from the point of view of anyone. The
policy will mean that it does not have a choice, as such, between admitting
you and not admitting you, depending on its will. And if under that policy it
refuses you admission, then this should not count as fully voluntary
interference. It will be a by-product of an independently necessitated,
otherwise unobjectionable policy: a restriction on your freedom of move-
ment, to be sure, but one that vitiates that freedom rather than invades it.26
These observations indicate that you need not think of yourself as
unfree – unfree in the sense of being dominated by an alien will – just
because you have to live under a state and perhaps in this state rather than
any other. That you have to live under these constraints is determined by
historical and political necessity. Like having to live in the presence of
gravity, it is a product of the existing world order, not the result of a
dominating presence in your life. The existing world order may be highly
undesirable, of course, and in principle there might be ways of reorganizing
it – for example, ways of incorporating states into a single agent like a world
state or confederation – in which there is less domination overall. But given
the world order we have, it is not due to the dominating power of any state,
and certainly not of your own state, that you have to live in some political
society or other. And it need not be due to the dominating power of any
state, and certainly not your own state, that you have to live in this political
society in particular. These circumstances may be exasperating but they do
not testify to the presence of a dominating will in your life.
An analogy may help to illuminate the role of historical and political
necessities under these arguments. Suppose that you live in a world, how-
ever fanciful, where as a result of past adjustments the space of economic
activity is entirely taken up by corporations. You could not complain of
being dominated in such a world by the fact that you have to work in an
incorporated company, not for yourself or for a private employer, though
you might bemoan the absence of such possibilities. And you could not
complain of suffering interference and domination just because you cannot
change place of employment to another company; no company can afford
to take on all those employees who wish to work for it. There might be
reasons for the government to try to change employment practices in certain
ways, and reforms might hold out the prospect of more freedom as non-
domination overall. But it remains the case that in the world imagined the
restrictions associated with having to work in some company, and not
necessarily in the company of your first choice, do not in themselves
26
There are difficult issues here that I cannot explore fully. See Abizadeh (2008).
The requirements on popular control 163
constitute domination. The analogy is imperfect but may help to explain
why you and your fellow citizens are not dominated by the historical and
political necessities to which you are subject.
Back to our main theme. As historical and political necessities mean
that the state is not in a position to allow you to live in a natural, rather
than a political, condition, or in any other state you might prefer, so a
functional necessity means that it is not in a position to grant you the
privilege, no matter how virtuous you may be, of obeying the law on a
non-coercive basis: that is, without fear of penalty. This is a third area
where state restriction is independently necessitated and does not entail
state domination.
Assume, in line with common wisdom, that in every society it is neces-
sary to employ coercion against at least some potentially recalcitrant mem-
bers. Coercion may be necessary to get those individuals to comply – lesser
obstacles of shame or whatever might not work – and/or it may be necessary
to provide assurance for the community that they will indeed comply – they
will not free-ride on the efforts of others. But if the state imposes on some in
this way, then assuming as we do that it has to satisfy the egalitarian
constraint, it has no choice but to impose on all in similar manner; doing
so will be a functional necessity. If the state did not impose equally on all
then, by any yardstick, it would offend against that constraint, not treating
citizens as equals. And if you or anyone else looked for the privilege of not
being exposed to the coercive imposition of the law – if you argued for being
allowed to display your virtue in voluntarily obeying the law – then you
would also be in breach of that constraint: you would show yourself unwill-
ing to live on equal terms with others. The normative constraint of expres-
sive egalitarianism is fundamental to the approach adopted here, and to any
half-plausible alternative. Accept that constraint and you cannot think that
it is within the state’s discretion to give you the privilege of not being
coerced to obey the law.27
The three constraints reviewed mean that you cannot regard your state as
dominating you just because you have to live in political society, you have to
live in this state rather than any other, and you have to live under coercive
regulation. It is true, of course, that if your state dissolved itself, then it
would not impose such constraints. But its continuing to exist is neces-
sitated by its role in protecting against foreign domination and does not
represent a power of imposing on you or not imposing on you, depending
27
To put the point in Kant’s (1996: 393) words, each of you has a claim only to a freedom in relation to
the state that ‘can coexist with the freedom of every other in accordance with a universal law’.
164 Political legitimacy
on its will. Thus you scarcely have a reasonable complaint against your
actual state. On the contrary, as we suggested, the fact that other states are
poised to assume control of the territory in which you live, and therefore
represent possible sources of domination, means that you would have a
reasonable complaint if your state did dissolve itself. Let the state remain in
place and you can avoid foreign domination: that is, a form of rule which,
by definition – that is, in virtue of what it means to be foreign – is going to
be uncontrolled by you and your fellow citizens, as you actually are. Let it
dissolve itself and foreign domination is unavoidable.28
The background picture to the argument in this section is a bleak but
realistic image of the world of states. Charles Tilly (1975: 42) claims that in
Europe, ‘War made the state and the state made war.’ The idea, which
applies elsewhere as well (Fukuyama 2011: 110–11), is that in a world of
potential conflict, different communities are likely to find political organ-
ization attractive and that the more organization there is in other commu-
nities, the more attractive it becomes in each. States call one another into
existence, in other words, as by an iron law of community competition.
Short of a world-changing, game-changing challenge, I suspect that this law
will continue to dictate the need for political organization, making the state
into a domestically indispensable and internationally resilient institution.
Not only is it necessary for the promotion of any plausible conception of
justice, as we argued earlier; it is necessary on empirical grounds as well.
The world in which states protect their citizens from the threat of other
states may be considerably less attractive than a world in which there are no
states or – more plausibly, in view of our argument that the state is required
for justice – a world in which there is only one state or federation (but see
Pinker [2011]). But in any case, this world represents an equilibrium
scenario where a state will not do better by its citizens, and will almost
certainly do worse, by unilateral dissolution. The state-bound world might
be represented, in a pessimistic analogy, on the model of a racing circuit
where the cars are spread out all around the track and each is travelling at a
highly dangerous speed.29 It would be better if all the cars travelled at a more
moderate pace, as it might be better if all existing states dissolved them-
selves. But each would do worse for itself by slowing down, as each state
would do worse for its citizens by dissolving itself, since that would almost
certainly cause a major pile-up.
28
I am grateful to Niko Kolodny for pressing me on this issue.
29
This is developed from an analogy presented for other purposes in Jackson (1987).
The requirements on popular control 165
The lesson of this discussion is that while the legitimate state is
required under republican theory to be controlled by its citizens, the
domain of control cannot extend to the point where people are able to
decide whether to live in or out of political society, whether to live in this
state or another, and whether to live under coercive or voluntary fidelity
to the law. No state – or at least no expressively egalitarian state – has a
choice between giving or refusing its citizens control on such issues, and
what legitimacy requires is that it give them control only on the range of
issues where it itself has such discretion. This is the range of decision-
making in which historical, political and functional necessities allow it
to choose between interfering and not interfering and, where it does
actually interfere, to choose between interfering in this or in that manner,
to this or to that effect. Let citizens have control over this restricted
domain and they will have all the control required for avoiding state
domination.
On the account of domination offered in the first chapter, there are
two forms of intervention in your choices that are not going to be
dominating; however, they may cramp your decision-making. One is
the intervention of constraints that do not reflect the will of another
towards you and the other is the intervention of intentional agents who
act under your control. The lesson of this discussion has two parts,
corresponding to these two forms of undominating intervention. The
first is that being required to live with others in a particular, coercively
regulated state is the product of will-independent constraint and not a
dominating imposition. And the second is that the threat of domination
arises only in the area of discretion that the state enjoys – that is, in
choosing to interfere with its citizens on one pattern or another – and that
it is here that you and your fellows have to be able to exercise suitable
control if you are to escape domination.
In the example with the alcohol cupboard that I used to introduce the
idea of a controlled and undominating state, there are two ways in which
you control me. First, you can suspend the arrangement under which I am
required to return the key at your request although only on twenty-four
hours’ notice. And second, you can shape and reshape that arrangement as
you will. We can see now that there is only a partial analogy between this
case and the case with the state. For in the case of the state, the arrangement
under which you and your fellows are subject to state coercion is not of your
devising and is not subject to your suspension; it is imposed under will-
independent necessity. You can only have control in the matter of how the
state operates under that arrangement.
166 Political legitimacy
But the disanalogy between the cases is not a problem. For your free-
dom as non-domination does not require you and your fellows to be able
to suspend the arrangement under which you live on a state-bound planet,
you are confined to living under the state into which you are born, and
you are required to live under a coercively imposed regime of law. Those
constraints may be mediated in the actions of states, showing up in the fact
that states claim a monopoly on territory and don’t allow outsiders to
enter at will and impose their laws coercively on all their subjects. But they
derive from necessities that leave states, and your state in particular, no
choice in such matters. Being required by independent necessity to
impose the relevant constraints, the state does not impose them out of a
will to restrict you and your fellows; necessity sidelines any will or
preference it might have in the matter.30
30
We saw earlier that an approach centred on the conception of freedom as non-interference cannot
take the existence of a system of control to ensure that state interference does not count as
interference. But it is worth noting, as implied in our discussion, that the approach does not have
to treat the actions of the state that are necessitated in the manner described in this section –
necessitated historically, politically or functionally – as instances of interference. The actions may
restrict people’s choices, but since they are not actions in which the state has any choice, they cannot
be taken as acts of voluntary restriction – acts that are chosen over acts that would count as acceptable
alternatives (Olsaretti 2004).
The requirements on popular control 167
Any system of control, as we have seen, is going to be a system of directed
influence: that is, influence exercised to a certain purpose or direction. This
system of control will have to guard against the domination of individual
citizens, not just the domination of the collective citizenry. But popular
control of government will not ensure someone against public domination,
if they have little or no part in the exercise of that control: the interference of
government will continue in that case to be imposed on them by an alien
will. Thus the first requirement on popular control is that it should be
individualized appropriately, giving each an equal share in the control of
government.
But there are two other requirements that popular control of government
must also satisfy if it is to guard against the domination of the state. Not
only must it be an individualized form of control, it must also count as
unconditioned and efficacious in character. It must be unconditioned in the
sense of being robust over changes in the will of the controlled government,
or indeed of any party other than the controlling people, and it must be
efficacious in the sense of being intuitively sufficient to guard those people
against having to see the coercion of the state as the work of an alien will.
The individualized system of control must ensure a suitable resilience and
level of impact to guard people against state domination.
If a system of popular control meets these three requirements – I discuss
them in greater detail shortly – then it ought to satisfy citizens that they are
not dominated by the imposition of certain laws or by the way those laws are
implemented by the executive or applied by the judiciary. It is true that
citizens will not be able to think of themselves as exercising personal control
over the state. But that they cannot exercise personal control is a by-product
of the historical necessity of living in political society. And that they cannot
demand a form of personal, as distinct from equally shared, control is an
implication of the normative necessity of living on equal terms with their
fellow citizens. No complaint about having to share control equally with
others will be consistent with a claim to be willing to live on equal terms
with their fellow citizens.
The requirement of sharing control equally with others might be
described as a one-for-all constraint, since it means that citizens each have
to accept that they do not have unilateral control over government. But the
constraint is balanced by what we might call an all-for-one compensation.
Under a system of equally shared control, the controlling collectivity is
bound to be much more effective than any single actor could hope to be.
And that agency may be expected to achieve for each whatever it achieves for
any; otherwise the equality constraint would be in jeopardy.
168 Political legitimacy
An individualized system of popular control
A system of control will be individualized insofar as it gives a comparable
role to each of the individuals involved in the exercise of control. Strictly,
the system might take either of two forms. It might enable people each to
exercise control in their own right, where their personal level of control is
equal. Or it might enable them to exercise a form of joint control, where
their share in that joint control is equal. But I see no plausibility in the first
scenario. The salient way to realize it would be by giving everyone an
individual veto over the doings of government – by requiring continuing,
universal consent – or perhaps by giving each an equal right of exit (Warren
2011). But establishing a general right of veto or exit would be inconsistent
with the state’s continued existence as a corporate agent that can reliably
generate and implement law, since it would put it at the mercy of individual
whim.31 Hence the only way in which the state can operate effectively and
yet satisfy the demands of republican legitimacy is by giving each of its
citizens an equal share in a system of joint control.
This observation will rule out a unanimity voting system, amounting as
it does to a regime that gives each a veto, but all other systems of shared
control will remain on the table, at least to the extent that they allow equal
sharing. These candidates will include other systems of voting, whether
majoritarian or super-majoritarian. But they will also include systems in
which voting plays only a subsidiary part, or perhaps no part at all. We
have seen that control may be exercised on the basis of active, virtual or
reserve influence, for example, and that if the influence is active, it need
not even have an intentional character; it may be like the influence of the
comatose patient.
Popular control, by the lesson of our earlier discussion, has to involve
popular influence and popular direction. Thus the requirement of equally
31
There is also a normative argument against a universal veto. If people each had a veto over how the
laws are made, implemented or adjudicated, that would enable a single recalcitrant individual to undo
the social order, create a stateless zone and, to continue with an earlier assumption, make invasion by
other states more or less inevitable. I assume that the obligation of a legitimate state to give citizens
equal control over its doings would put that requirement – that normative necessity – in the way of
this option. If the state has a duty to give its citizens equal control over how it performs, then to allow
any individual the power of exposing their fellows to the jeopardy of foreign intervention would be
quite inconsistent with that obligation. Notice that despite the opposition he would certainly want to
mount against a universal veto, Kant (1996: 393–4) could not rule it out on the basis of his requirement
of ‘innate right’ – the basic right in his political philosophy (Ripstein 2009) – that one be independent
from ‘being bound by others to more than one can in turn bind them’. Notice, too, that this argument
against a universal veto does not carry over to a majority veto, at least not if the majority is not an
incorporated agent with a will of its own (List and Pettit 2011).
The requirements on popular control 169
shared control entails, on the face of it, that people should share equally
both in exercising influence over government and in determining what
direction that influence is to impose. This entailment has not always been
endorsed within historical tradition. There was an extended debate in the
eighteenth century, for example, as to whether equal liberty requires that all
citizens – in effect, all mainstream men – should each be fully enfranchised,
thereby having an equal influence, or whether equal liberty can be achieved,
and so a suitable direction imposed on government, via the well-disciplined
influence of the few (Reid 1988).
It should be clear, however, and it should have been clear in the eight-
eenth century, that there cannot be equally shared control without equally
shared influence. If some people are to depend on the good offices of an elite
party in order to force government in a direction they all care about – and
not in a direction particularly favourable to the more powerful – then they
are dependent on the goodwill of that party for their very freedom. And
that, in republican logic, is anathema. Richard Price (1991: 80) spoke for the
right side – and he suggested, the traditional side – when he claimed that
‘every independent agent in a free state ought to have a share in the
government of it, either by himself personally, or by a body of representa-
tives in chusing whom he has a free vote’.
What, however, does equality in the exercise of influence require? It
cannot require that everyone should participate equally in the system of
popular influence, since some individuals may choose not to play their part
in the system, whether generally or on specific occasions; they may be happy
to go along with what others decide. Even under a system of compulsory
voting, such as that in Australia, people may spoil their vote and are in no
sense compelled to have a normal electoral input.32 What equally shared
influence requires, therefore, can only be equal access to the system of
popular influence: an opportunity for participation in that system that is
available with equal ease to each citizen.33
32
But it is worth noticing that even when people do not vote – or do not contest government decisions
in any active way – still they exercise some influence: they reduce the majority of the winning party or
they allow government not to have to deal with their contestation. On such matters see Guerrero
(2010).
33
Richard Tuck (2008) makes an intriguing case for thinking that preferring to have a group achieve a
certain effect makes it rational to prefer to play a part – even a palpably redundant part – in bringing
about that effect; see too Goldman (1999). I think that the preference to play a part may be
intelligible – there may be good reasons why you might want to do so – but I do not agree that the
preference over the outcome rationally requires the preference for playing a part. It may be otherwise
objectionable to let others bring about a result that you cherish, even when you know that your help is
unnecessary, but it is surely not irrational. For a similar critique, see Brennan (2011).
170 Political legitimacy
What might make for equality, not in the exercise of influence, but in
determining the direction that the influence imposes? Each citizen will
share equally in determining the direction their influence imposes if that
direction is required to be one that each is ready to accept; that each is
disposed to find acceptable.34 This requirement may not be satisfiable
amongst fanatics or zealots who insist on special treatment: say, the pri-
vileging of their religion or ethnicity. But it will be enough by our normative
standards if it is satisfied amongst those, as we put it earlier, who are willing
to live on equal terms with others: amongst those who accept that the state
should treat its citizens as equals.
To sum up the two lessons of individualization in a slogan, then, the
citizens of a legitimate state have to enjoy equal access to a system of popular
influence and that system of influence has to give the state an equally
acceptable direction – that is, a direction that they are all actually disposed
to accept. We will be looking at what might promote equally accessible
influence in the next chapter and at what might promote an equally accept-
able direction in the chapter after that.
34
Saying that something is acceptable often has a normative significance among contractualists,
implying that it is such that people ought to accept it. Here and throughout this book, the word
has a non-normative sense, implying that the object or policy or whatever is such that people are
disposed to accept it; they find it acceptable, as we say.
The requirements on popular control 171
will count as controlling another only insofar as the influence exercised leads
to the required result independently of the will of the controlled agent, or
indeed of any third party. Inter-agential control will count as control proper
only to the extent that it is unconditioned on any will other than that of
the controller.35
Suppose that you, A, are said to control what another person, B, does
because B obeys your instructions or, to take a case where your control is not
intentional, because B anticipates and acts on your wishes without your
even being aware of this. Imagine now that the correlation between your
instructions or wishes and B’s actions – the inputs on your part, the outputs
on B’s – is contingent on B’s wanting to humour you, or on my requiring B
to humour you. In that case you can scarcely be held to control what B does;
more colloquially, you cannot be said to have power over B. If the corre-
lation depends entirely on B’s will, no one has power over B; and if it
depends on my will, then it is I who has power over B, not you. The
correlation may depend on any of a variety of contingent circumstances:
that B is in thrall to your charms, for example, or that you have greater
physical strength or cultural clout. But it cannot depend on B’s willingness
to play the part, or on the willingness of any third party to make B do so.
Think of the example in which you give me the key to the alcohol
cabinet, instructing me to hand it over only at twenty-four hours’ notice.
Suppose I go along with your instructions, but merely with a view to giving
you the pleasant illusion of control; suppose that I am about to exit our
relationship and think of this as a parting, somewhat sardonic gift. In that
case you do not have the control you imagine; without realizing it, you are
in my hands, at my mercy. So why is there control in the normal case? Why
is the correlation between your instructions and my responses stable in a
way that is independent of my will? Presumably because, by implicit
assumption, the relationship matters to me, whether for intrinsic or instru-
mental reasons, and there are heavy costs associated with refusing to go
along: say, with just giving up the key in blatant disregard of the arrange-
ment, or with refusing to part with it at all.
For a further illustration of why inter-agential control has to be uncon-
ditioned, think of the case of the comatose patient, in Amartya Sen’s
example, whose wishes over hospital treatment are empowered by the fact
that his family or friends force the doctors to abide by them. Although we
did not make the point earlier, we can now register that if it is up to the
35
For a congenial interpretation of related themes see N. Southwood’s unpublished paper, ‘Democracy
as a Modally Demanding Value’.
172 Political legitimacy
discretion of a single person amongst the family or friends, or up to their
jointly exercised discretion, to determine whether the patient’s wishes
should prevail, then those individuals are going to be in control, not the
patient. In order for the patient to have control, it will have to be the case
that the responsiveness of the doctors is not conditioned on the willingness
of any single agent to speak for the patient. This requirement might be
fulfilled if there were some pressure on family or friends to intervene in the
patient’s name – if it was not just a matter of their discretion – or if there was
a queue of individuals lined up to play the role, so that the intervention did
not depend on their individual or joint discretion.
We saw in the first chapter that you are not free in a choice between X, Y
and Z if you can act according to your will – if you can control your
actions – only insofar as I allow it. What we are now discussing is a parallel
observation that bears, not on your control of your own actions, but on your
control of the actions of another party. You control your own actions only
insofar as you do not depend on the will of another for being able to satisfy
yourself; you can satisfy yourself over changes in what any other wants you
to do. You control the actions of another agent only insofar as you do not
depend on the will of another – that same agent or a third party – for being
able to get the other to satisfy you, acting on your instructions or wishes;
you can get the agent to satisfy you over changes in what the person wants to
do and over changes in what anyone else wants the person to do. As the
failure of the first condition means that you do not enjoy freedom – power
or control over yourself – so the failure of the second means that you do not
enjoy power or control over the other. Freedom requires a robust capacity to
satisfy yourself; power over another requires a robust capacity to get that
other to satisfy you.
The observation made in these examples applies to the control of any
agent or agency over another and so to the popular control that we want
citizens to exercise over the state. The implication of the requirement in the
political case is that the equally accessible popular influence that is required
to impose an equally acceptable direction on government has to meet a
further demanding constraint. It has to produce that effect independently of
the willingness of government to go along and independently of the will-
ingness of any other agency to have the government go along.36
36
The other agency envisaged here might be an effectively independent army, a group of moneyed
supporters or even a foreign power. The army possibility led most traditional republicans to oppose
the idea of a professional or standing army; many saw the development of such an army – indeed such
armies – as the factor that brought down republican Rome.
The requirements on popular control 173
In every regime, the government, or at least the executive arm of govern-
ment, is likely to be enormously more powerful than any other individuals
or bodies, having special access to the means of universal coercion. But if the
government is the powerful party in the relationship between people and
government, then how can we expect the people to be able to exercise the
independent or unconditioned form of influence that is required? It may
seem that the people can hope to enjoy only the appearance of a controlling
influence, not the real thing: only the trappings of power that are available
when an indulgent state is willing to humour its citizenry.
The difficulty posed by this observation is real but not overwhelming.37
For the experience of societies over the past couple of centuries, even
perhaps before, shows that the control of the people over the state can be
grounded in a disposition of people to rise up in the face of a government
abuse of legitimacy and a disposition of government to back down in
response to the fact or prospect of such opposition. This is the trump
card that the people are always in a position to play, relying on any of the
various measures, violent and non-violent, direct and indirect, individual
and collective, that can be used to resist a regime. To the extent that the
possibility of popular, successful resistance is on the cards – to the extent
even that it is on the cards as a matter of common belief – the influence of
the people over government can be established on a robust basis and can
constitute a real form of power.
The observation that popular control of government is grounded in the
actual or perceived potential for widespread resistance – people’s presump-
tive power of rebellion – is not new. John Locke embraced the importance
of the possibility in arguing for the right of people to rise up against the
government, should it not be fulfilling its allotted role: as he saw it, the role
of being an impartial arbiter of disputes. In his view, as on the view to which
our considerations lead us, the legitimacy of a government ultimately turns
on whether ‘the community may be said in this respect to be always the
supreme power’ (Locke 1960: ii.149). The people will have to be the
supreme power in any polity that has a claim to legitimacy.
Adam Ferguson, a Scottish adherent of the eighteenth-century republican
creed, gave the idea memorable expression in describing the requirements
37
It is taken to be overwhelming by those like Georgio Agamben (2005) who follow Carl Schmitt in
arguing that even democratic governments fail the requirement. Their argument is that even such
governments freely decide – that is, decide independently of any external pressure such as that which I
go on to identify – that a given case is a non-exceptional one where the rule of law applies or is an
exceptional or emergency case where the rule of law is suspended. In Schmitt’s (2005: 5) words,
‘Sovereign is he who decides on the exception.’
174 Political legitimacy
of liberty.38 The liberty of the British people, he suggests, may be manifest
in the fact that laws are formulated under widely accessible influence and
given a widely acceptable direction. But its grounding goes much deeper: ‘it
requires a fabric no less than the whole political constitution of Great
Britain, a spirit no less than the refractory and turbulent zeal of this
fortunate people, to secure it’ (Ferguson 1767: 167). This characteristically
republican theme has a long history. It appears most dramatically in the idea
championed in Machiavelli’s (1965) Discourses that what enabled the citi-
zenry of republican Rome to enjoy their freedom vis-à-vis the state was
something that might appear at first sight to be a source of instability: the
willingness of the plebeian poor to rise up against even the suspicion of an
abuse or usurpation of power by the nobles. The price of liberty, in the
hallowed republican slogan, is eternal vigilance.
It goes without saying that societies differ greatly in the extent to which
this support for popular influence and control over government is avail-
able. It will be available in a measure that reflects the extent to which two
factors are in place and/or are taken as a matter of common belief to be in
place: on the one side, the disposition of the people to resist perceived
abuses of power by the government; and on the other, the disposition of
those in government to be inhibited by the fact or the prospect of such
resistance. These two factors determine how resistive a society is: how far,
in reality and/or perception, the citizens are resistance-prone and the
government resistance-averse.39
We saw earlier that in order to be individualized, popular control must
be grounded in an equally accessible system of influence that operates
in an equally acceptable direction. But we now see that the system of
directive influence to which citizens are given equal access has to be a
system of unconditioned or independent or resilient influence. It must
enable people to enjoy a directive influence over government that is based
on the resistive character of the society, not on the goodwill of government
or of any other agency.
38
As a matter of passing interest, Ferguson opposed Richard Price on the issue just mentioned as to
whether equal control requires equal influence: in effect, the universal franchise. See Price (1991: 80).
39
A society might be resistive in this sense and yet not be very regularly subject to popular disturbance;
the important thing is that resistance should remain a permanent possibility. John Locke may mean
just to register this – and not to strike what may seem like a complacently conservative note – when he
argues that since resistance is difficult to organize, and dangerous if it fails to attract majority support,
it won’t materialize except in the event of extreme abuse: ‘such revolutions happen not upon every
little mismanagement in public affairs’; they are likely to be triggered only by ‘a long train of abuses,
prevarications and artifices’ (Locke 1960: ii.225).
The requirements on popular control 175
An efficacious system of popular control
But popular control of government does not only require that people should
enjoy equal access to a popular system of unconditioned influence and that
this system of influence should push government in an equally acceptable
direction. If the popular system of unconditioned influence is to ensure the
popular control required for legitimacy, then it must also satisfy a further
condition. It must be effective or efficacious enough to impose a popular
direction on government that nullifies the intrusion of alien will. It may not
reach the upper limit at which it would be as effective as possible, consis-
tently with the equal sharing of that control. But whether it reaches or falls
below that limit, it must be intuitively satisfactory.
This third condition takes us back to the requirement that the state
should treat its citizens well and equally in the manner in which it imposes a
social order, as well as in the character of the order imposed. The state would
treat its citizens as equals if it gave them the same equal share in a system of
unconditioned control. But it would not treat them well if that system of
control were unnecessarily limited. In order to ensure social justice, the state
must secure people’s equal, undominated status vis-à-vis one another to a
suitably high level or degree, as we saw in Chapter 2. And in order to achieve
political legitimacy it must secure their equal, undominated status vis-à-vis
the state to a similarly high level. That is the requirement registered in the
demand that the system of control in which people equally share should be
efficacious.
In theory, the constraints imposed under a suitable system of equally
shared control might bear only on the policies and related decisions imple-
mented by government, reducing the options in each area just to one. Such
policy-centred limitations would clearly deny those in power the opportu-
nity to evade popular control in the decisions they take. But in practice, any
plausible constraints are likely in each area to leave a number of policy-
options in place, not to reduce the options to just one. And so the
constraints imposed on government must also include many that bear on
the processes whereby ties are broken and decisions taken in each domain of
policy-making.
Such constraints, too, can serve the purpose of stopping those in power
from operating outside the boundaries of popular control. They might
require, depending on the issue, that decisions are taken by reference to
expert or impartial or judicial bodies, by a majority vote in the legislature or
in a referendum, or even by some kind of lottery. The assumption is that
while such process constraints will leave the final determination of policy in
176 Political legitimacy
any area to the luck of the draw – including, for example, the draw that gives
one or another side a majority in a legislature or referendum – that mode of
determination can be consistent in the relevant area with popular control. If
it allows the wills of some to rule on certain matters, as in giving the majority
party control of various issues, it does so only because such restricted
empowerment is consistent with all that popular direction and control
requires; like the power that I enjoy when you give me the key to the
alcohol cupboard, the power given to the majority party can only be
exercised within accepted bounds and need not count as dominating.
The fact that in practice many decisions will have to be left to govern-
ment under the best imaginable regime of popular control raises the spectre
of abuse in this range of discretion. Abuse might consist in the authorities
smuggling some self-serving candidates into the set of policies between
which a decision has to be made in any area, or indeed keeping some
popularly acceptable candidates out of that set. Or it might involve the
authorities taking advantage of loopholes in the processes available to
resolve policy disputes in any area for their own special benefit or the benefit
of cronies.
These possibilities sharpen the question as to how much popular
control – in particular, how much popular influence – will count as
enough to banish the spectre of uncontrolled or arbitrary government.
How efficacious ought the people’s influence over government to be?
How far ought it to be able to impose a popular direction on government,
removing opportunities for the intrusion of private interest and private
will? The question is akin to the issue, addressed in the preceding chapter,
as to how far people need to be guarded against domination from one
another for the enjoyment of freedom. Here the issue is how far people
ought to be able to control those in power on an equally shared basis, if
they are to enjoy freedom in relation to government. Where the earlier
question asked after the degree of entrenchment required for private non-
domination, this question asks after the degree of empowerment required
for public non-domination.
In answer to the earlier question, I suggested that the best we can say is
that entrenchment is adequate in a given society to the extent that by local
standards people would display excessive timidity if they could not pass the
eyeball test there – if they could not look one another in the eye without
being prompted to fear or deference by the possibility of another’s interfer-
ence. Where the eyeball test is a good index of whether the guards against
private domination are adequate, a parallel tough-luck test is a good index of
whether the guards against public domination are efficacious.
The requirements on popular control 177
Imagine that the party or personnel in government do not meet with
your approval. What are you to think if they are manifestly appointed under
a suitably efficacious form of popular influence and direction, in which you
have an equal share? You can only think that it was just tough luck that
those appointed are not to your taste; it was not the work of a dominating
will, as it would be, for example, under a colonial administration. Or
imagine that the government passes legislation of which you disapprove:
say, legislation requiring the construction of new prisons. What are you to
think if it does so, again manifestly, under the equally shared, suitably
efficacious control of the people? You can only think that it was just tough
luck for you that the decision went that way; it was not the result of a will at
work in the public sphere that operates beyond the equally shared control of
you and your fellows. Or imagine, finally, that in implementing the
legislation, the government decides to your dismay that one of the prisons
should be located in your neighbourhood – in your back yard. What are you
to think if it manifestly makes this decision under a suitably efficacious form
of control in which you and those in your area equally share? Again you can
only think that it was just tough luck that the decision went against you; it
was not due to the special influence of those who are richer or electorally
better placed or closer to the corridors of power.40
The point of legitimacy is to ensure that you and your fellow citizens are
not subject to an alien, controlling will, despite that fact that there may be a
good deal of discretion exercised by those in power. Such legitimacy will be
adequately ensured, so these observations suggest, to the extent that you and
your fellows have good grounds to think that any unwelcome results of
public decision-making are just tough luck. By local standards of when trust
is well placed and those in government inhibited from exploiting loopholes
in the constraints imposed, you need not view unwelcome results as the sign
of a malign will at work against you or your kind; or at least you need not do
so, assuming you are not subject to excessive anxiety or distrust. You may be
exasperated by what transpires in the formation of government, or in the
creation or administration or adjudication of the law, but if you really share
in equal, suitably efficacious control of government, which is what repub-
lican legitimacy requires, then you will not have a reason to feel resentment
at how the state performs.
You may feel resentment, of course, at how your fellow citizens behave in
private or public roles, even when there is no question of popular control
40
My thanks to Ben Ewing for discussion of the points in this paragraph.
178 Political legitimacy
being undermined; you may be indignant about the culpable ignorance or
indifference, for example, that their refusal to support a certain policy seems
to display. Such resentment at individuals is quite consistent with allowing
that the state itself, since it enacts a will over which you enjoy shared,
suitably efficacious control, is not deserving of resentment. That the state
enacts an unjust policy, by your lights, will be a result of the bad luck of your
having many culpably ignorant or indifferent compatriots, not a result of its
harbouring an alien will. Insofar as the tough-luck test is satisfied, the will
displayed by the state is under an efficacious form of control that you share
equally with others in imposing. If that will fails to track the good, then you
and your fellows have only yourselves to blame. And if you don’t blame
yourself, you can only blame your fellows.
A variant of the tough-luck test of efficacy applies, not just in the sorts
of example given, but also in a case where you are charged with a crime,
found guilty and sentenced to some punishment: perhaps a period in
prison. If you are innocent of the crime, there will still be a great difference
between the case where it really is just tough luck that all the evidence
pointed against you, and that the institutions in place were incapable of
registering your innocence, and the case where the system allowed some-
one the power of acting against you: say, a police officer or public
prosecutor who was hostile to you personally, or to those in a particular
subgroup to which you belong. But what if you are guilty of the crime? In
that case, a legitimate system will enable you to think, not that it was
tough luck that you were sentenced to prison, but something related: that
you have only yourself to blame. Knowing the rules under which you live,
and knowing that you share equally in control of them, you cannot
complain about what is imposed under those rules as a penalty for your
breaking them.41
The tough-luck test offers an intuitive way of gauging how far the efficacy
of democratic control over government is satisfactory. It should be noted,
however, that it is only available as a plausible criterion of performance, on
the republican assumption that legitimacy requires people to exercise con-
trol over the will of government, not control over everything that happens.
Thus it is no problem for republican theory that in any area of policy brute
41
There are difficult issues, however, that I am ignoring here. Some arise as a result of moral differences;
for an excellent discussion of such cases see Talisse (2009). Other difficult issues are multi-cultural
questions of the kind that Will Kymlicka (1995) in particular has put on the table; for a broadly
republican approach see Nathan (2010) and for an incisive discussion of one particular issue see
Laborde (2008).
The democratic state 179
chance ultimately determines what exact policy or decision the government
selects under the terms imposed on it by the people.42
The lesson of the two previous requirements on the popular control of
government that legitimacy requires was that people should have equal
access to a popular system of unconditioned or independent influence that
pushes government in an equally acceptable direction. Adding in the third
requirement, the lesson is that popular, legitimating control of government
requires equal access to a popular system of unconditioned and efficacious
influence – specifically, one that imposes an equally acceptable direction on
government. Putting the implications of legitimacy in a slogan, we may say
that people have to enjoy an equally accessible form of influence that
imposes an equally acceptable direction on the state. But it should always
be understood that the directive influence to which people are given access
has to be not only equal or individualized, but also unconditioned and
efficacious.
A theory of democracy
Starting from the requirements of legitimacy, understood on republican
lines, we have argued that they can be fulfilled only insofar as citizens enjoy a
suitable range, kind and degree of control over government. There are no
other salient conditions that we might require a legitimate state to fulfil.
And so we may conclude that a state will be legitimate just to the extent that
in a suitable domain people enjoy equal control over government: equally
accessible influence – unconditioned and efficacious influence, as I shall
assume – that pushes government in an equally acceptable direction.
Any system that satisfies such conditions deserves to be described as a
democracy, since it gives the demos, or ‘people’, an equally shared,
42
In this as in other respects, republican theory enables us to support judgements that are independ-
ently plausible: it satisfies the test of reflective equilibrium with such judgements. This is particularly
striking in the present instance, since the plausibility of the tough-luck test is not so readily
established on other accounts of the role of democracy. On many other accounts the people would
only enjoy control to the extent – an impossible ideal – that they controlled everything that transpires
at the hands of government agencies: only to the extent that they determined the content of every law
and policy, every decree and judgement. On the present account they will enjoy control to the extent
that they control the will at the origin of what transpires. And they can achieve this insofar as they can
impose terms that leave little or no room for the intrusion of alien will on the part of government
agencies, even if they leave matters of detail to the luck of the draw. We will be looking in later
chapters at examples of how such control can work.
180 Political legitimacy
independently supported and intuitively efficacious degree of kratos, or
‘control’, over the state.43 And so what we have developed can count as a
republican theory of democracy. There is no one proprietary meaning of the
term ‘democracy’, as it is used in ordinary or philosophical or scientific
language; people often divide on what exactly the notion of democracy
connotes (Connolly 1993). Thus the theory according to which democracy
requires a popular system of individualized, unconditioned and efficacious
control does not count as analytical in character; it does not offer an analysis
of the term ‘democracy’ as a theory of causation might offer us an analysis of
the term ‘cause’. What it offers, rather, is an ideal that democracy, at its best,
might be required to achieve or approximate.44
Put in other terms, what the theory offers is an account of what demo-
cratic institutions ought to do: a job specification that they ought to be
designed to implement. But such a job specification naturally raises a
question about its capacity to be implemented. The question is whether
the ideal of a regime in which people share equally in control of government
is institutionally feasible or just a utopian pipedream.
The only way to answer this question is to develop a model of how certain
realizable institutions might bring the ideal into existence, or close to
existence. Having sketched the requirements of republican justice in sec-
tions 1 and 2 of Chapter 2 – having described the job specification under
which a just social order requires the publicly entrenched enjoyment of
basic liberties – we went on in Section 3 to indicate the sorts of institutions
that might realize that ideal. We need to do the same thing for the ideal of
legitimacy or democracy, offering a model of democratic institutions in
which it might be brought to life.
I take up this task in the two chapters following. In Chapter 4, I look at
the civic or popular influence that democracy in a republican sense would
require and in Chapter 5 at the civic or popular direction that that influence
ought to impose on government. The model that emerges in those chapters
need not persuade everyone who accepts the republican theory of demo-
cracy. For all I know, there may be a better, perhaps even radically different,
alternative available. My commitment to the model goes less deep,
43
For a popular but very useful introduction to the origin of the notion of democracy see Dunn
(2005).
44
The conception is close to what Ronald Dworkin (2006: 131) describes as a ‘partnership view of
democracy’ under which ‘democracy means that the people govern themselves each as a full partner in
a collective political enterprise so that a majority’s decisions are democratic only when certain further
conditions are met that protect the status and interests of each citizen as a full partner in that
enterprise’. See too Dworkin (2011: Chapter 18). For a somewhat different account of the linkage
between democracy in this sense and the absence of domination see Lovett (2010: 210–20).
The democratic state 181
therefore, than my commitment to the theory. I offer it in the spirit of a
realistic proposal, as I take it to be, which shows that the republican ideal of
legitimacy and democracy is not other-worldly; it is an ideal that can inform
politically serious contemporary debate.45
45
The republican model of democracy emerging from this account might figure among the models in
David Held’s (2006) standard account, but it does not coincide with the model that he describes as
republican.
182 Political legitimacy
status freedom, at least not with the robustness that a just and democratic
state might underwrite.
The kingdom of ends is a stateless dispensation in which members may
differ in their levels of wealth and power but are each morally committed at
the highest possible level. They are committed, first, to showing respect for
others and second, perhaps going beyond Kant, to showing concern, as well.
Their commitment to respect obliges members of the kingdom of ends to
renounce interference in one another’s basic liberties, so I shall assume, and
their commitment to concern obliges them to provide any resources that
others may require.
Would the introduction of a just and democratic state improve the lives
of the moral paragons who inhabit the kingdom of ends? I believe it would.
In all likelihood, it would provide a much more effective means of identify-
ing the basic liberties that people are to enjoy. But, much more importantly,
it would also provide in a novel way for the entrenchment of those liberties.
Were people moral in the degree imagined, then the more wealthy and
powerful would be disposed not to interfere with others and not to allow
others to go without needed resources. But their acting on that disposition
would depend on their continuing to embrace and abide by the require-
ments of the assumed morality. It would depend, to recall a point from the
first chapter, on their displaying a good will rather than a weak will or a will
to evil. In such a world, therefore, some members would have to depend on
the goodwill of others for enjoying the basic liberties. And so the coercive
laws of a just and democratic state would play a crucial, beneficial role,
establishing external checks and supports to guard each member against
dependency on the will of the more powerful. They would be a means of
providing for people’s enjoyment of status freedom.46
Would this freedom really be a benefit, however, given that the members
of the kingdom of ends are vanishingly unlikely to turn ill-willed? Yes, for
reasons rehearsed already. Seeing and treating one another as agents, not as
pre-set, probabilistic devices, even the members of the kingdom of ends
would have to recognize that whether another relatively powerful member
chooses to interfere with them, or chooses not to help out in the absence of
46
One qualification. In the kingdom of ends, social norms of a particularly respectful, and indeed
benevolent, kind might be expected to emerge and, having emerged, might put suitable checks on
interference with others or even on indifference to their needs; any such failure might trigger costs in
the economy of esteem (Brennan and Pettit 2004). I ignore this here, since my only point is that the
kingdom of ends as traditionally conceived would deliver more benefits if it were complemented by a
democratic state. For a useful discussion of Kant’s kingdom of ends that is in some ways congenial
and in others uncongenial, see Van der Rijt (2012: Chapter 5).
The democratic state 183
resources, will often be up to that person. And so they would have to
recognize that on one or another front they depend on the person’s good-
will. Thus, as we imagine the perspective of weaker parties, we see that they
would be inevitably and manifestly indebted to the powerful amongst them
for non-interference or for the resources they enjoy. They would be in the
position of dependants, not equals, in relation to those parties.
The failure of the kingdom of ends to provide for the status freedom of its
members highlights the importance of what the just and democratic state
can provide. Introduced to the kingdom of ends, it would give each member
protection against the accessible, if highly improbable, interference or
indifference of the stronger. And in providing that benefit, it would confer
a free status that would previously have been unavailable. The actual
behaviour of people after the introduction of such a regime of law and
coercion might not differ very much from their behaviour beforehand. The
role of coercive law in providing a second line of defence against weakness or
illness of will on the part of the powerful would not be visible in anything
that anyone did – at least not if we assume that prior to the appearance of a
state the powerful didn’t ever display any weak or ill will. But the role of
coercive law would still be of the utmost importance. It would mean that
the non-interference and resources that the weaker enjoy come to them, not
in the guise of a gift for which they should be grateful, but rather in the guise
of an institutionally guaranteed claim.
As mentioned earlier, the coercive state is certainly needed to promote
compliance and to assure compliers that others are complying too. But we
can now see that it is needed on a third count, too. For the just and
democratic state relies on coercion – the coercion involved in protecting
against interference and in redistributing to those with insufficient
resources – to ensure that people’s enjoyment of the basic liberties is
publicly entrenched. This coercive entrenchment provides people with a
freedom as non-domination that is independent of the will of others as to
how they should choose, including the will of government itself. And that
is not something that mere morality can provide.
G. A. Cohen (2008: 148) expresses the orthodox view on the coercive
state, however just and however democratic it may be, when he says that
there are only two functions that it can play: ‘coercion is necessary only for
deviance or assurance reasons’. But this is wrong, according to the picture
emerging here. Provided it is just and democratic, under the republican
specification of those virtues, the coercive state can generate a good for all of
us – the good of status freedom – that we cannot provide for one another on
the basis of our own goodwill. We cannot provide this for one another as we
184 Political legitimacy
actually are. And we could not provide it for one another, even if we were as
angelic as the members of the kingdom of ends.
Economists characterize benefits that the private market is incapable of
producing, and that appear to require collective organization, as public
goods. These are goods like defence, criminal justice and public health
that for reasons of psychology or organization – say, the disposition to
free-ride – we would be unlikely to generate in the absence of centralized
coercion. The upshot of the discussion is that the free status that repub-
licans envisage is also a public good. Freedom requires independency on
the will of others, even the goodwill of others. And for that deep and
inescapable reason, free status is something that we can make available to
one another as individuals only by collectively organizing ourselves in a
state – strictly speaking, a just and democratic state.47
Back to Rawls
In introducing the model of social justice that republican theory would
support, I argued that in important respects it would break with Rawls,
replacing his two principles with a single principle that calls for giving
people status freedom in relation to one another. While the republican
theory would undoubtedly overlap with Rawls’s in many of the policies
supported, it would provide support on a different basis. It may be useful in
concluding this discussion of the republican theory of legitimacy and
democracy to sketch a parallel comparison with the approach that
Rawlsian and related theory would adopt.
As we saw earlier, Rawls and others focus on comprehensive, social-cum-
procedural justice in evaluating a legal order – a basic structure, in his
sense – rather than breaking that evaluative task, as we have done, into the
distinct issues of social justice and political legitimacy. Rawls explores the
comprehensively just order by asking which basic structure or structures
would satisfy his contractual eligibility or his civic justifiability test. And in
answering that question he requires, unsurprisingly, that the just structure
should give people certain basic political liberties and rights. The issue for
47
At this point we have reason to think that it is not only good, assuming there are people around, that
no one should dominate others, and that no one should vitiate anyone’s undominated capacity; it is
good that there should be people around who can enjoy mutual undominated relationships. This
good is close to that which is celebrated by recognition theorists (Honneth 1996) and others who are
influenced by Hegel’s account of the status associated with freedom (Patten 2002). Adopting this
view would help republican theory to deal with some of the complex issues raised in population
theory as a result of the non-identity problem (Parfit 1984: Chapter 16). I am grateful to Jake Nebel for
exchanges on this topic.
The democratic state 185
us, then, is whether the political rights he envisages might be sufficient to
satisfy the demands of political legitimacy or republican democracy:
whether they might be enough to give people an equal share in a public
system of individualized, unconditioned and efficacious control.
The political rights to which Rawls (1971, 1993) directs us include all the
procedural liberties associated with electoral democracy – for example, the
freedom to vote or to stand for office – as well as the rights of free speech,
association and movement that they presuppose. But he does not lay much
emphasis on the procedural liberties, casting them at one point as ‘sub-
ordinate to the other freedoms’ (Rawls 1971: 233). What is important in his
perspective is that if we consider impartially what society ought to provide
for individuals – if we consider this, for example, from the point of view of
the original position, in which none of us know how we will fare under the
basic structure adopted – we must conclude that it ought to furnish them
with procedural as well as more substantive liberties and rights. Those
requirements are benefits that each should fully and equally enjoy, within
a suitable mix of substantive and procedural rights, on pain of suffering
unfairness. But they do not have a special status and may even be sub-
ordinate to their substantive counterparts.
On the republican view, things look quite different. Republican theory
casts the procedural rights that people are to enjoy – together, as we shall
see, with other, less formal, rights – as powers that they must each fully and
equally exercise if they are not to suffer subjection and domination by an
uncontrolled state. It invests the state with heavy responsibilities in the
sphere of social justice, as Rawls does. But it emphasizes that nonetheless the
coercive state is a real danger – a danger to the very freedom that social
justice is meant to promote – and that citizens must share equally in control
of political coercion if they are to enjoy the status of free persons. The
spectre of the despotic and illegitimate state – even the benevolently
despotic state – haunts the approach as thoroughly as the spectre of the
socially unjust regime. And it inevitably gives prominence to the demand
for a regime of shared, popular control.
This may explain why Rawls and others do not actually give the same
standing to the requirements of legitimacy and democracy as republicans.
But are they actually prevented from doing so by their focus on compre-
hensive, social-cum-procedural justice? Could they maintain that focus and
yet be persuaded by the case for republican freedom to give a greater
importance to democracy?
In principle, yes. The tests of contractual eligibility and civic justifiability
on which Rawls relies can be seen as ways of operationalizing the normative
186 Political legitimacy
demand for the state to treat its citizens as equals (Dworkin 1978). Accepting
such a test, we can still go along with republican thought and take freedom
as non-domination, understood in a status sense, as the good with reference
to which the test ought to be applied. And if we do this, then no basic
structure will appeal unless it gives citizens a suitable level of equally shared
control over how it is likely to evolve at the hands of government. Let it fail
to give citizens such control and their freedom is going to be jeopardized at a
very deep level. They may seem to enjoy social justice under the envisaged
structure but they will enjoy it only as the result of an indulgence on the part
of those in power. The freedom that social justice purports to give them will
not really be freedom, since it will be tainted by their dependency on the
goodwill of government.
The upshot is that while the Rawlsian approach of articulating the
demands of social and procedural justice in a comprehensive package may
actually lead to a downgrading of legitimacy and democracy, this is not an
inevitable result. It would be avoidable, at least in principle, under the
assumption about the importance of freedom as non-domination that
republicans make. It is certainly useful to guard against the possibility of a
downgrade by distinguishing between the demands of social justice and
political legitimacy, as we have done here. But that way of presenting things
merely facilitates an insight into the importance of democracy that is already
guaranteed by embracing the core republican ideal.
chapter 4
Democratic influence
The idea in this chapter and the next is to explore the institutional
possibility that the people in a polity might have such control over those
who run the state that they are not individually dominated by the interfer-
ence that the state practises in taxation, coercion and punishment. To the
extent that they have a control that makes such interference non-
dominating, the citizens will not lose out in freedom just by the fact of
living within that state and, by republican criteria, the state will count as
politically legitimate. A state that is legitimate in that sense may not achieve
a great deal in guarding against private domination and achieving social
justice, though it probably has to achieve some minimum threshold if
citizens are going to be capable of exercising control over its doings.
Control, as we saw, depends on two distinct elements, influence and
direction. Thus the people will achieve control over the state insofar as they
attain influence, on the one side, and succeed on the other in using that
influence to impose a suitable direction on government. Such popular
control will be suited to republican purposes, guarding against domination,
to the extent that it gives each citizen an equal share in the control,
particularly an equal share in a form of control that is suitably uncondi-
tioned and efficacious. People must enjoy an equally accessible form of
unconditioned and efficacious influence that imposes an equally acceptable
direction on the state. In this chapter I look at how people might enjoy the
required influence and I turn in the next chapter to how this influence
might impose the required direction. In this chapter’s discussion of the
institutional means whereby people might come to enjoy the required
influence I shall anticipate the discussion in the next and assume that the
influence they enjoy can support a popular direction and not merely be
wayward in character.
How to approach the discussion of the influence that the people might
have in a polity? Should I look at utopian, perhaps fanciful ideals of how
popular influence might materialize? Or should I start from democratic
187
188 Democratic influence
institutions with which we are all familiar and begin to chart the influence
that they make possible? It’s a hard choice. If I go the first way, I may be
accused of dabbling in ‘models of speculative perfection’, in William Paley’s
(2002: 319) words, and risking irrelevance in the discussion of obtainable
reforms. If I go the second way, I may be charged with lowering my sights
and paying undue obeisance to the status quo.
I propose to approach the challenge as follows. I begin with a model in
which the citizens gather periodically in a plenary assembly, a committee-
of-the-whole, to determine the laws of the community. This model, which
is reminiscent of Rousseau’s assembly, offers a plausible, initial interpreta-
tion of what it might be for the people to enjoy equally accessible influence
over government. Whatever its other faults, however, I argue that the model
is quite infeasible, even in an electronic age in which people might assemble
virtually. Having identified the problems of feasibility that a plenary assem-
bly would confront, I go on in Section 2 to discuss the rival merits of two
quite different forms of non-plenary assembly, one indicatively representa-
tive and the other responsively representative. And having argued in favour
of the responsive form, I then argue over sections 3, 4 and 5 that in order to
serve the cause of republican legitimacy, this assembly has to be subjected to
a series of important amendments. The model to which these amendments
lead promises to deliver a form of popular influence that is appropriately
individualized, unconditioned and efficacious, as our ideal of legitimacy
requires.
This final model does not conform to the status quo in existing systems of
representative democracy but it is close enough to warrant a claim to
institutional feasibility: it represents a regime we can see how to establish
and stabilize. And yet the model is far enough away from the status quo to
direct us to reforms that are required if our institutions are to support a form
of popular influence that is individualized, unconditioned and efficacious.
The model incorporates versions of the mixed constitution and the contest-
atory citizenry that bulk large, as we saw, in Italian–Atlantic republicanism.
1
The procedure under which this was possible was known as the graphe paranomon: it allowed for the
indictment of those proposing measures contrary to the laws (Hansen 1991; Ober 1996).
2
For an exchange on Hobbes on democracy see Tuck (2006) and Hoekstra (2006).
190 Democratic influence
democracy, in which the laws are imposed by a sovereign committee of the
many. Unlike Aristotle, Bodin and Hobbes ridiculed the idea of a state that
would operate under a mixed constitution. While taking different argu-
mentative routes to the conclusion, they each maintained that because such
a constitution would not identify and establish a single commander or law-
giver, it would undermine the capacity of the state to serve its purpose,
ensuring order and peace in the land; it would be a recipe for civil strife and
political disaster.
But if Bodin and Hobbes were the first to enunciate clearly the image of
government by a plenary, legislative assembly, it was Jean Jacques Rousseau
who offered the first, full-scale defence of the model. Working with the
categories inherited from such absolutist predecessors, as we saw in the
Introduction, Rousseau (1997: ii.2.2) rejected the idea of the mixed con-
stitution: it would turn the sovereign, he says, ‘into a being that is fantastical
and formed of disparate pieces’. But he could not accept the idea of a
monarchical or an aristocratic state, given his attachment to the broadly
republican ideal that no one should have to live in subjection to another.
And so he had little option but to argue in support of what Bodin and
Hobbes would have called a democracy. He held that the people should
gather periodically in a sovereign assembly to deliberate and decide upon
the laws and that they should then give the job of implementing and
adjudicating those laws to appointed magistrates. He himself thought of
this design as republican but not democratic, since he used the term
‘democracy’ in a somewhat idiosyncratic manner to describe an arrange-
ment in which the assembly would implement, as well as make, the laws
(Rousseau 1997: iii.17.5).
Following Hobbes, Rousseau holds that while there has to be unanimity
in the contract to enter political society – ‘the act by which a people is a
people’ (1997: i.5.2) – that contract makes it alright for further decisions to
be taken by majority vote: ‘the vote of the majority always obligates all the
rest; this is a consequence of the contract itself’ (iv.2.7).3 But he breaks with
Hobbes in hailing a deliberative ideal, according to which the members of
his assembly should vote on the basis of the common good. They should
each think as citizens, focused impartially on their common interest, and
they should vote for any measure they support, whatever their personal or
factional interests, on the grounds that ‘it is advantageous to the State’
3
He recommends that on some important matters, it may be useful to require a super-majoritarian
approval: this could be introduced, presumably, by a prior majority agreement. See Rousseau (1997:
iv.2.11).
The plenary assembly 191
(Rousseau 1997: iv.1.6); this is required if the majority vote they cast is to
reflect the general will of the community, as he calls it. We shall return to a
consideration of the deliberative constraint in the next chapter, when we ask
how popular influence might be directed in a manner acceptable to all. In
this chapter, our focus is on the prior question of how to organize a system
of popular influence so that everyone has an equal share. And in discussing
that question we can abstract from whether or not people should be
required to exercise their collective influence under a deliberative constraint.
I, A, vote Yes No No
You, B, vote Yes Yes Yes
C votes No Yes No
We vote Yes Yes No
4
The discursive dilemma is a generalization of the doctrinal paradox that arises for collegial courts; this
was first properly identified and analysed by Lewis Kornhauser and Larry Sager (1992a, 1992b, 1993).
The plenary assembly 193
The problem, as a number of results have shown, is not specific to
majority voting. It is liable to arise under a variety of interpretations of
the constraints of individual responsiveness and collective rationality.5 But
it is sufficiently well illustrated for our purposes by the infeasibility of
majoritarian decision-making.
The problem means that it is not going to be enough for a group,
however deliberative it may be, just to rely on majority voting – or on any
of a variety of such bottom-up voting procedures – to aggregate its views.6
The group must keep track of where the accumulating commitments
generated by individual rounds of voting are leading it – its members
must gather feedback on whether the commitments are generating incon-
sistency – and it must be able to respond appropriately to that information.7
One strategy it might adopt is the straw-vote procedure. Under this proce-
dure, a majority vote in support of some judgement will be treated as a straw
vote until the result is tested and shown to be consistent with judgements
supported previously; if it fails that test then either it or some prior vote is
rejected (List and Pettit 2011: Part i). The lesson is that in order to guard
against inconsistency in its group views, the group has to be able to access
and process feedback on where the votes of members are leading it and,
when those votes lead to inconsistency, it has to make revisions that restore
consistency – or at least insulate any inconsistencies that prove recalcitrant.
A group might conduct this reflexive exercise in a mechanical way,
establishing a routine whereby any later vote that proves inconsistent with
earlier commitments is nullified: this would force our A–B–C group to reject
the negative vote and endorse ‘p-and-q’, for example. But that would scarcely
be satisfactory, since the recognition that prior votes require accepting a result
such as the combined package might be thought by members to provide
reason, not for revising the negative vote on the combined package, but
for rejecting the prior, positive vote on one of the elements in the package.
A satisfactory, decision-making body would have to be able to conduct
5
For an initial result see List and Pettit (2002) and for a survey of later results see List and Polak (2010)
and List and Pettit (2011).
6
Some authors like to contrast aggregative and deliberative processes, as if deliberation meant that
aggregation was unnecessary or unproblematic. But it is agreed on all sides among deliberative
democrats that deliberation will not generally lead to consensus and that the differences which
deliberation still leaves in place have to be resolved by a voting process. The discursive dilemma
shows that when the issues to be voted on are logically connected, as they generally will be over any
stretch of time, then there may still be a serious problem of aggregation.
7
Those members, as Niklas Luhmann (1990: Chapter 9) argues, have to keep track in an exercise of self-
reference on how under a common name – in his argument, that of the state – they are getting to be
committed.
194 Democratic influence
second-stage, post-feedback deliberation – for short, reflexive deliberation –
as well as the basic deliberation conducted prior to first-stage voting (Pettit
2007a, 2007b). This is the sort of deliberation required under the straw-vote
procedure. The group votes that p, votes that q, and, on finding that it also
votes against p-and-q, deliberates about which vote to reverse.8
This takes us to the denouement (Pettit 2003b). No plenary assembly
could be expected to be able to conduct this reflexive form of deliberation,
assuming that its numbers are large. It may be possible to get members to
deliberate in a basic way about a single issue – say, whether to increase
defence spending or to increase education spending – and then to resolve
remaining differences by voting. But what can they do to deliberate in the
wake of feedback on the inconsistency of the various measures they have
supported – this might be made salient by a suitable feedback committee –
and on the comparative merits of resolving it in one or another manner? It is
unlikely in the extreme that any large body could discharge this reflexive
task satisfactorily. The consideration argues powerfully against the feasibil-
ity of the plenary assembly model and, more broadly, against any wholesale
reliance on popular referenda for determining the conduct of government.9
One response to this critique might be to suggest that apart from the
plenary assembly, there should be a body that is charged with restoring
consistency whenever plenary voting generates a problem. But this body
would have enormous discretion and power, since the resolution of an
inconsistency could take any of a number of directions: the most recent vote
might be nullified or, alternatively, any of the previous votes that are relevant
to the inconsistency might be set aside. To empower such a body in this
measure would undermine the rationale for the plenary assembly; it would
make a mockery of the claim that the assembly gives power to the people.10
8
Might it help if the group voted only on logically independent propositions that are fit to count as
premises, allowing judgements on other propositions to be determined by the votes on the premises?
No, because there is no prospect of agreement on which propositions are fit for the role of premises,
and which not. See Harman (1986).
9
Why do I concentrate on the problem of aggregating judgements, illustrated by the discursive
dilemma, rather than on the problem of aggregating preference orderings, illustrated by the
Condorcet paradox, that Kenneth Arrow (1963) made famous and by related results (Riker 1982)?
Three reasons. One, it is easier to appreciate the problem illustrated by the discursive dilemma. Two,
the Arrow impossibility can be presented as a special case of the impossibility illustrated in the results
on judgement aggregation; see List and Pettit (2004) and Dietrich and List (2007). And three, the
possibility of reflective deliberation, unavailable in a plenary assembly, also offers the only half-
satisfactory response to the Arrovian problem. For a debunking account, however, of the Arrovian
challenge see Mackie (2003).
10
This critique of the plenary assembly depends on the assumption that the members of such an
assembly are going to have to make their decisions by casting on–off votes in expression of their
The responsively representative assembly 195
judgements on particular issues. But that assumption is realistic (List and Pettit 2011: Part 1). It is not
going to be possible to pre-package all the issues to be decided, only allowing consistent packages to
come up for assembly vote, since new issues are bound to arise all the time. And when it comes to
endorsing a response to any issue, members are going to have no option but to record a positive or a
negative vote on each possible response. There is no feasible way, for example, in which they could
record a probabilistic degree of credence in each response and then look for some method whereby
their different probability distributions might be aggregated into a group distribution. There may be
abstract theories in which such aggregation can be modelled but it is entirely unclear how it might be
achieved in actual institutions.
11
For a more developed account of the responsive-indicative distinction on which the following
discussion draws see Pettit (2009b, 2010b). Jane Mansbridge (2009) documents the history of a
closely related distinction between a sanction and a selection model of representation and establishes a
range of points bearing on how the selection model may be developed. That article is broadly
congenial to the viewpoint I defend here, though it is more sanguine about the possibility of
combining responsive and indicative representation. For a different way of generalizing the concept
of representation beyond responsive representation see Rehfield (2006) and for a very useful dis-
cussion of the history and concept of representation, see Vieira and Runciman (2008).
196 Democratic influence
together about it. The body is meant to be a microcosm of the society both
in the way it is composed and in the way it operates.
In order to be a compositional microcosm this assembly will have to be
statistically representative of the community as a whole, with the main
communal categories being represented proportionally within it. And in
order to be an operational microcosm its members will have to guard against
any pressures that would lead members to behave out of character: that is,
on the basis of anything other than the dispositions that make them typical
of their category. Those requirements suggest that the assembly envisaged
should comprise a random sample of the population that is small enough to
make deliberation possible and that it should be given authority for a period
that is short enough not to expose members to the warping incentives and
pressures of office. It might comprise five hundred or fewer members,
selected on the basis of chance, and it might hold power for at most a
year or two. Given the information and leisure required for public decision-
making, the resolutions of such an assembly could reasonably be expected to
be indicative of the decisions that the people as a whole would support, were
they able to assemble and deliberate appropriately.
The idea of an indicative assembly of citizens has good historical creden-
tials. It was this sort of assembly that traditional institutions like the lottery
were designed, wittingly or not, to establish.12 While the ecclesia of Athens
in the fifth and fourth centuries bce was open to all citizens, the member-
ship of equally crucial bodies was determined by lottery. Thus the judicial
panel of about six thousand citizens was fixed on an annual basis by lot and
the case-by-case membership of the courts and other smaller bodies –
including the ‘nomothetai’, who came to have responsibility for recom-
mending on any proposed change in the law – was fixed by a second, ad hoc
lottery amongst the members of the panel (Hansen 1991; Ober 1996).
A similar lottery system played a part in the constitutions of many medieval
Italian city-states, where appointments to law-making and related bodies
were often made by lot (Waley 1988; Dowlen 2008). And the lottery idea
also had an implicit presence in the medieval development of the jury
system: to be subjected to the judgement of your peers, whether in deter-
mining that there is a legal case to answer, or that you are legally liable, was
12
It is unlikely that the design was witting. There were other purposes that might have been more
prominent in the minds of traditional communities: for example, that lottery ensured against the
excessive influence of any particular clique or faction. See Dowlen (2008). My thanks to Matteo Faini
for discussion on this point.
The responsively representative assembly 197
to be exposed to a body that was meant to be indicative of the citizenry as a
whole (Abramson 1994).
There are also contemporary cases of indicative bodies being put to work
in place of the population as a whole. The British Columbia Citizens’
Assembly is a good example, though only one of many (Sintomer 2007).
A body of 160 citizens, selected on a statistically representative basis, it was
entrusted by the government of British Columbia in 2004 with producing a
recommendation on the voting system to be used in the province (Warren
and Pearse 2008). Another example is provided by the deliberative opinion
polls championed by James Fishkin (1991, 1997). These comprise fewer
numbers and meet over rather shorter periods, but are also designed to make
recommendations on public issues that reflect what the community as a
whole would recommend, were it possible for the whole population to
assemble and deliberate.
14
My discussion is simplified insofar as I do not look at responsive and indicative relationships in which
there is a correlation not only between the dispositions that are present in people and representatives –
for example, their beliefs in a certain domain – but also between the dispositions that are absent on the
two sides: for example, their failures to believe certain things in that domain. For a treatment in which
this simplification is lifted, and probabilities of correlation are introduced, see List and Pettit (2011:
Chapter 4).
15
The difference between the two modes of political representation corresponds to a distinction drawn
in epistemology between two modes of epistemic representation, sensitive and safe (Sosa 2007). A
responsive body will offer a sensitive representation of popular dispositions: as those dispositions
change under certain inputs, so its dispositions will tend to change too in sensitive response. An
indicative body will offer a safe representation of popular dispositions: as its dispositions change under
The responsively representative assembly 199
An indicative-cum-responsive assembly
Although supporters of the French Revolution often invoked Rousseau’s
name as a source of inspiration, they uniformly went along with the idea
that any governing assembly would have to be elected. But the general
assumption was that such an electoral body would also have an indicative
status, as a microcosm or model of the whole population. Thus, in an
address to the French Constituent Assembly, Honoré Mirabeau main-
tained: ‘the representative body should at all times present a reduced picture
of the people – their opinions, aspirations, and wishes, and that presentation
should bear the relative proportion to the original precisely as a map brings
before us mountains and dales, rivers and lakes, forests and plains, cities and
towns’ (Pitkin 1969: 77). This opinion was widely shared amongst enthu-
siasts for assemblies of elected representatives. About that same time, the
American anti-federalist, Melanchton Smith, could write: ‘The idea that
naturally suggests itself to our minds, when we speak of representatives is,
that they resemble those they represent; they should be a true picture of the
people’ (Ketcham 2003: 342).
But the shift from a statistical to an electoral selection system inevitably
makes for the diminution, even the elimination, of the indicative status of a
governing assembly. The assembly that is elected may be compositionally
indicative of the population as a whole, at least if the electoral system is
designed, as John Stuart Mill (1964) thought it should be, to ensure a high
degree of proportionality. But there is every reason to think that the
assembly will fall short of being operationally indicative in any significant
measure. It is unlikely to be a body such that if it votes for a certain measure,
that is a sure sign that the population as a whole, were it able to assemble and
deliberate, would vote for that measure.
certain inputs, that is a fairly safe sign that under those inputs the dispositions of the people would
change too. Responsive representatives are reliable trackers of popular dispositions, so we might say,
where indicative representatives are reliable mirrors of popular dispositions.
200 Democratic influence
The assembly could make a good claim to be an operationally indicative
status if the interests on which its members acted combined in aggregate to
model the interests distributed across the population as a whole. But unlike
statistically selected members, those who are elected are extremely unlikely
to meet this modelling requirement. The condition on which they can be
expected to be responsive representatives, as we saw, is that they will
generally want to be re-elected, or to satisfy other electoral pressures, and
will therefore seek to provide what their constituents and supporters are
disposed to welcome. But to the extent that they pursue this goal, it is
unlikely that they will mirror in aggregate the interests distributed across the
population.
Seeking re-election as they do, they will each favour measures that appeal
especially to more pivotal or marginal voters in their constituency or to
the supporters on whom they particularly depend. And equally they will
tend to strike idealistic postures that cast them in a good light as individuals –
say, moralistic postures on prostitution or taxation or crime or indeed
capitalism – rather than endorsing the compromise solutions that they
might be otherwise disposed to support (Brennan and Lomasky 1993).
A body of such electorally interested representatives is not going to act like
a faithful microcosm of the society as a whole. The point was made by
Benjamin Constant (2003: 387) in 1810. ‘You choose a man to represent you
because he has the same interests as you. By the very fact of your choosing
him, however, your choice of placing him in a different situation from yours
gives him a different interest from the one he is charged with representing.’
It is important to register that any representative body will tend to be less
indicative of the population as a whole, the more its members are electorally
responsive. But the observation does not mean that there is no point in
trying to combine indicative and responsive elements in the representative
status given to any body or indeed, as we shall see, any public office. Thus an
indicative body might be usefully forced to be responsive by being exposed
to review or challenge, if not to election; the British Columbia Citizens’
Assembly was exposed, perhaps for this reason, to a referendum on its
recommendation.16 And an electorally responsive body might be more
acceptable to a population to the extent that it satisfies a degree of propor-
tionality and can claim in some respects to be indicative.17
16
For the record, its recommendation for a change in the voting system in British Columbia received a
little short of the 60 per cent support that it was required by government decree to receive.
17
The very common practice of dividing a country into distinct districts might be taken to promote
proportionality in a geographical dimension. Is a wish for a certain proportionality behind this
practice? It is hard to believe that it did not play some role in justifying that practice but the evidence,
The responsively representative assembly 201
In favour of the responsive assembly
There is surely a useful role that indicative bodies such as the British
Columbia Citizens’ Assembly can fulfil in a contemporary democracy.
But if we are looking for a permanent assembly to govern a society, then
the electoral, responsive assembly scores decisively above it. A fairly obvious
consideration in its favour is that it allows for the same members to be
returned to office, thereby making for a continuity of experience and
expertise across different assemblies. The indicative assembly does not
promise such continuity, at least short of radical amendment, and it is
hard to see how government could operate effectively if a completely new
legislative body had to take over every year or so. But apart from this
consideration, there are three other reasons why the electoral model ought
to have much greater appeal.
The first is much cited in the literature on representative – that is,
electorally and responsively representative – democracy, including in
authors as different as John Hart Ely (1981), Joseph Schumpeter (1984),
Juergen Habermas (1995), Stephen Holmes (1995) and Ian Shapiro (2003).
A system of open, competitive, periodic election would require the satis-
faction and reinforcement of a number of basic liberties, depending for its
very operation on their successful exercise. But a system that was designed to
facilitate indicative rather than responsive representation – or, for that
matter, a plenary assembly system – would not be likely to have the same
salutary impact.
The liberties I have in mind are the freedom of speech, association and
travel that are required if people are to be able to stand for office, combine in
parties, promote their policies and expose other parties, including the
governing party, to criticism between and at the time of elections. It is
only in a society where individuals have these freedoms – and, I would say,
have them in the rich republican sense of escaping domination – that they
can hope to continue to share equally in a system of independent influence
over government. Let any of the freedoms be curtailed and the prospects for
equally accessible or individualized influence are in immediate danger.
Those who are exposed to any possibility of check or coercion in response
to speech may not speak their piece in criticism of this or that proposal, for
example. And their failure to speak will not provide default support for the
proposal, as it might have done in various contexts. No matter what the
according to Rehfield (2005), is against this hypothesis. Still, districting does induce a similarity in one
dimension – if, nowadays, a fairly unimportant one – between the population as a whole and the
legislature that represents it.
202 Democratic influence
context, people’s silence will communicate nothing, since it can always be
taken to reflect their lack of freedom (Pettit 1994).18
Let any of these freedoms be curtailed and not only does the prospect of
equal, individualized access to influence decrease; so does the prospect for an
unconditioned sort of influence. We saw in the last chapter that the people’s
influence will be unconditioned, and not granted as an indulgence of the
government or the army or whatever, to the extent that the society is resistive:
as a matter of actual fact and/or as a matter of common perception, people are
disposed to resist any governmental abuse of power and government is
disposed to respond to such resistance. It is only in a society where people
actively exercise freedom of speech, association and travel – and are allowed to
do so by government authorities – that these dispositions can assume the
status of unchallenged facts, registered in the shared consciousness of the
population. And so it is only in such a society that people can have influence
over government, regardless of whether those in government – or those in any
other agency – are happy to give them influence.
Where an electoral, responsive regime would require – and as it continues
in existence, reinforce – a culture of freedom in the domain of speech,
association and travel, the statistical, indicative regime would run the risk of
failing to nurture such a culture. It might be introduced in the context of
such freedoms, but its operation would not require their continuing exer-
cise, at least outside the assembly itself. With any such freedom, it is at least
likely that if you fail to use it, you lose it: your successful exercise of the
freedom plays a crucial role in checking and confirming the absence of a
power of interference on the part of others. Thus the statistical, indicative
regime would expose a community to a very great danger that the electoral,
responsive regime would actively serve to combat.
Apart from this consideration – and the consideration of continuity in
office that we mentioned earlier – there is a second reason for preferring the
electoral, responsive regime to the statistical, indicative one. I assume, on
the basis of the argument in the last chapter, that a deliberative, democratic
assembly, be it indicative or responsive, should mediate the influence of
individuals in a particular direction or to a particular purpose; we postpone
discussion of the required direction to the next chapter. The second con-
sideration in favour of the responsively representative system is that it is
more likely than the alternative to make it possible for people to impose a
direction on government.
18
For an exchange on this issue see Langton (1997) and Pettit (2007a).
The responsively representative assembly 203
A system of influence that is required to further a given purpose may fail
in either of two ways. One involves false negatives, as they are called; the
other false positives. False negatives consist in oversights: failures to propose
or generate all the candidate policies that might promote the direction or
purpose sought. False positives consist in mistakes: failures to test and filter
out proposals that do not promote that direction or purpose, perhaps
serving an inimical end instead. This double possibility of failure suggests
that the ideal channel for popular influence will involve, first, an initial
process that guards against oversights, generating an ample supply of
candidates for consideration; second, a process that guards against mistakes,
testing the candidates with a view to filtering out those that prove unsat-
isfactory; and third, a repeating sequence in which these interact in the
identification of a final set of successful candidates. It will involve a complex
process of a familiar generate-and-test character.
In a generate-and-test process, every element generated is tested before
being allowed into the evolving product; it is incorporated in that product if
and only if it passes the test (Dennett 1996). The procedure will be familiar
from a variety of contexts. At one end of the spectrum of possible examples,
it is illustrated by the process in which authors generate texts and editors test
and filter them, so that what gets published is the joint product of both
processes. At the other end it is illustrated by the process in which random
mutation generates variations in existing genomes and natural selection tests
the variations for whether they are adaptive – whether they increase the
inclusive fitness of organisms – letting them survive only if they are.
Returning now to our two representative assemblies, it should be clear
that the electoral, responsive assembly does considerably better on this
count. The elected legislators have every incentive to search out policies
that are likely to go down well with voters, competing as they do for voter
support, so that they may be expected to generate a rich supply of candi-
dates. And when they go to the electoral polls – and when they record voting
intentions in opinion polls – the electing voters will have every incentive to
scour both the policies proposed and the policies implemented to see how
far they measure up to whatever metric they impose. Assuming that there is
a suitable metric in operation – this, in effect, is the topic of the next
chapter – the process has both of the elements required in a generate-and-
test procedure.
Things are bound to be very different, however, with the statistical,
indicative assembly – and indeed also with the plenary assembly. Such an
assembly would not offer separate locations at which policies can be
generated and tested and it would not provide actors with distinct
204 Democratic influence
incentives, on the one side, to generate an ample supply of candidate
policies and, on the other, to test those candidates for how well they
measure up to relevant desiderata. It promises a calm, smooth process of
legislation, in which impartiality ought to prevail quite easily. But that
promise is much less likely to deliver people from the false negatives and
positives that threaten them than the two-dimensional, back-and-forth
dynamic that we should expect to find in the presence of electoral
competition.
The problem is made vivid in reflection on how we in a general pop-
ulation might feel about being governed by an indicative assembly. How
would we be likely to react to being governed, this year by one contingently
selected group of fellow citizens, the next year by another? We would surely
want each group to be held to account for the policies it introduces in its
period in office. It would seem utterly complacent to let an indicative
assembly act as seems best without having to face any challenge from
outside. True, the members would have to live under whatever laws they
introduced and that has always been taken as an important check in
republican thinking.19 But is it check enough? Does it provide against the
possibility of the group’s being somewhat unimaginative or somewhat
thoughtless, for example, in the decisions it makes? The answer, plausibly,
is that it does not. The absence of a group of electors to whom they are
answerable means that the members of an indicative assembly will not be
kept on their toes in the same manner as the members of a responsive
body.20
The two considerations just put forward for preferring the responsive to
the indicative assembly will carry weight, quite independently of republican
commitments. But there is a third consideration that carries particular
weight from within our republican perspective.21 This is that an indicative
body, unlike a responsive, is necessarily linked with the spectre of a certain
sort of domination. If such a body is given charge of the full range of
legislative issues, then it will have a power to determine both the issues it
considers and the resolutions that they are given. Operating as a corporate
19
Algernon Sidney (1990: 571) endorses this constraint in the seventeenth century when he writes of
members of Parliament: ‘They may make prejudicial wars, ignominious treaties, and unjust laws. Yet
when the session is ended, they must bear the burden as much as others.’ Joseph Priestley (1993: 140)
endorses it a century later when he raises and answers a question about the American colonists: ‘Q.
What is the great grievance that those people complain of? A. It is their being taxed by the parliament
of Great Britain, the members of which are so far from taxing themselves, that they ease themselves at
the same time.’ See too Locke (1960: Section 138).
20
This consideration is also relevant in assessing the use of lotteries defended in Burnheim (1985).
21
I am grateful for observations on this issue to Niko Kolodny and Jake Zuehl.
The responsively representative assembly 205
agent, it will have to form a will of its own and exercise that will under few, if
any, constraints. Not being subject to electoral challenges, however – or
perhaps to the challenges that presuppose a vibrant, electorally nurtured
culture of freedom – the assembly’s will may be difficult for the people to
control and render undominating. The assembly may have been chosen for
the prospect of forming an indicatively representative and congenial will – a
will that the population as a whole might well have formed in their place –
but it will not be forced in any way to remain congenial; it will have the
standing of a benevolent despot.
The lesson of this observation is that while we may rely on indicatively
representative bodies to make decisions on particular issues, or particular
ranges of issues, it would not be a good idea to give such an electorally
uncontrolled body the open-ended authority of a legislative assembly.
There may be no objection on republican grounds to a statistically repre-
sentative body like the British Columbia Citizens’ Assembly, which was
charged with making a judgement and recommendation on the best voting
system for their Province and on nothing more. But there would certainly
be grounds for objecting to a statistically representative body that would
have the open-ended discretion of legislature.22
23
In his famous account of how he thought democracy ought to work, Edmund Burke (1999) derided
this sort of assembly as a ‘congress of ambassadors’.
24
It is important that the system I have in mind here is not only parliamentary in character, with the
legislature electing the administration, but also that it is non-proportional. Where many parties have
to combine to form government, as is typical of highly proportional systems, then the system will be
more like Washington than Westminster. Thus, to anticipate the text, so many parties will be needed
to form government that policy is mainly going to be determined post-election in inter-party deals.
The responsively representative assembly 207
unresponsive to the country-wide demands of the electorate. While both
count as deputies, the members of the representative assembly are likely to
behave as trustees, to invoke our earlier distinction, and the members of the
assembly of representatives to behave as delegates (Pitkin 1972).
This is not the place to make a judgement on the merits of these two very
different systems of responsive representation, though the Westminster
system seems likely to serve republican goals more reliably. In any full-
scale assessment of democratic designs it would be essential to take account
of the differences between the systems and to judge on their specific
advantages and disadvantages, but this book does not attempt that sort of
detailed assessment. Abstracting from detailed institutional recommenda-
tions, the aim is to explore how far any democracy that is organized to broad
republican specifications can ensure the legitimacy of the state.
25
Notwithstanding other differences on issues of constitutional design, I hope that these remarks will
signal a deep level of agreement with Richard Bellamy (2007), who also works within the republican
research programme.
208 Democratic influence
Electoral institutions are necessary in practice, if not in strict logic, for
giving influence and control to the people. They force people to exercise
their freedoms in political action, whether as candidates or supporters,
critics or activists, and they thereby reinforce the enjoyment of those
very freedoms. They push political parties into exploring the space of
possible policies and they require ordinary citizens to form and express
their views in response. They constitute the catalyst that triggers and
sustains the process whereby people may hope to gain influence over
government.
But, however essential in practice, electoral institutions do not suffice
on their own to maintain a suitable system of popular influence. There are
serious problems that need to be addressed if an electoral system is to
provide the form of popular influence that is required for democratic
control in the republican sense. It is only if we can identify institutional
means for remedying such electoral shortfalls, therefore, that we can hope
to achieve democracy under the republican specification of what it
requires.
The main requirement on a system of popular influence, as we saw in the
last chapter, is that it must be equally accessible to all citizens. This parallels
the requirement, to be explored in the next chapter, that the direction it
imposes should be equally acceptable to all. But not only should the system
of influence be individualized in this sense; it should also be unconditioned,
as we put it, and efficacious. Assuming that it imposes a popular direction,
as it must do in order to constitute control, its operating to a directive effect
should not be conditioned on the willingness of the government, or any
other party, to go along; and it should not allow for the influence of private
will in public decision-making beyond what the tough-luck test would
allow.
An electoral system of popular influence raises problems on all three
fronts, since it might fail to be individualized, unconditioned or effica-
cious. I shall review these over the final three sections, making sugges-
tions about the institutional measures that might provide remedies. My
institutional suggestions are meant to be illustrative of the initiatives
that might be taken and should not be treated as definitive recommen-
dations for action; such recommendations would have to be guided, not
just by philosophical analysis, but also by empirical observation and
modelling. What the suggestions show, I hope, is that there is no reason
to despair about the possibility of setting up a suitably democratic
system of influence. All that is needed is imaginative institutional
design.
An individualized system of influence 209
26
Examples of such exclusion occur in many parts of the United States, where the papers that voters
have to produce in proof of their identity at the polls are not always in the possession of the poorer; or
where those who are convicted felons lose their right to vote, even when they have completed their
prison sentences. Such abuses argue strongly in favour of the compulsory system of voting employed,
for example, in Australia. This system imposes a small fine on those who do not register at the polls,
and have no independent excuse to offer, but it ensures a voter turn-out well above 95 per cent; more
important, again, it ensures that those who do not turn up at the polls are a more or less random
group, not a specific class. See Hill (2000) and A. Fowler’s unpublished paper, ‘Turnout Matters:
Evidence from Compulsory Voting in Australia’, for relevant background on the effects of compul-
sory voting. Under non-compulsory systems it is always possible, perhaps even likely, that the poorer
and underprivileged will be systematically ignored in political circles; see Bartels (2008).
27
Many systems give rise to this last difficulty when there is a second house, such as the Australian or the
US Senate, to which states of different sizes elect members in equal numbers. This might not be a
problem, if the second house had a distinct function from the lower house in those countries, but
other things being equal it is a problem as things actually stand and it does call for reform. Other
things may not be equal, as suggested in the next chapter, to the extent that apart from a norm of
equal influence, people in a society like Australia or the United States also endorse a norm – perhaps
for contingent historical reasons – to the effect that states should have equal senatorial representation.
An individualized system of influence 211
any issue, whether moved in the immediate fashion of a referendum or in a
manner mediated by the decisions of elected representatives.28
The discontinuous nature of electoral influence raises a serious problem
for how we might individualize the influence mediated under an electoral
system, letting it resemble the influence achieved under a continuous
system where, as the example with the ball shows, individuals can share
equally in determining the impact of their joint influence. Individuals will
not share equally in determining the impact of any particular electoral
exercise and so it may seem that they cannot be provided with individu-
alized influence of the kind we are seeking.
But while this is a serious problem, there is a more or less salient solution on
offer. Although individuals cannot share equally in determining the impact of
any particular electoral exercise, it might be that with each of the issues
resolved in such an exercise, they have an equal chance of sharing equally in
the determination of the impact – an equal chance of being on the winning
side.29 And if they had an equal chance of winning, then we could scarcely
hold that the system of influence was not appropriately individualized.
Things might be arranged, following this proposal, so that there is no ex
ante reason to think that for any randomly chosen pair of individuals, there
will be a difference between their chances of being on the winning side on any
randomly chosen issue. This condition will be satisfied under a system where
each person has the same vote, and each vote has the same value just so long as
one further proviso is fulfilled. This is that the issues over which they vote are
ones where there is no ex ante reason to think – no reason grounded in their
identity or character, as that is determined independently of their disposition
to vote – that some are bound to vote for a particular side. But this proviso,
alas, is not always going to be satisfied. It will flounder on a problem that has
become famous as the problem of an ‘elective despotism’ or a ‘tyranny of the
majority’ (Madison, Hamilton and Jay 1987: no. 10).
30
There is a scope ambiguity, as logicians describe it, between the characterization of the case where
there is a sticky-divide problem and the characterization of the case where there isn’t. In the former
case we say that there are individuals such that there are issues on which those individuals are in a
minority; in the latter we say that there are issues such that there are individuals who are in a minority
on those issues.
31
Electoral challenge can be seen, of course, as a form of collective contestation; on this point see
McCormick (2011: 152).
214 Democratic influence
the prospect of an impartial judgement on the question and, if the judge-
ment goes in favour of the challenges, the prospect of an adjustment that
satisfies them.
Under plausible assumptions about our little group of five, the members
will be easily granted such individualized, potentially effective contestation.
The vegetarians will be free to point out the effect of majority voting and to
argue on grounds of equal access to influence for an adjustment to the
pattern. Here there is an obvious alternative: to let the members take turns
in dictating where they are to eat (Risse 2004). The ethos of any plausible
group is likely to support the egalitarian objection, and to prompt the
adoption of the alternative mode of decision-making.
As with the vegetarians in this example, people whose religious or cultural
identity pre-commits them to taking a particular side on certain issues can
enjoy equal influence over government only insofar as they are able to
contest the appropriateness of majority voting in a referendum or via a
legislature for determining such issues. They have to be able to make the
case for why majority voting on those issues ensures that they do not share
equally with others in controlling for the direction taken by government.
And they have to be able to expect that the case they make in contesting the
law or proposal receives an impartial hearing and is dealt with appropriately.
Allowing for the contestation of the results of a majoritarian voting
system – or of any comparable system of individual inputs to aggregative
decision-making – certainly makes things messy. But it is hard to see how
anyone who is concerned with giving people equal access to influence over
government could disallow it. Jeremy Waldron (1999a, 1999b) offers power-
ful support for majority voting on the grounds that it does better than
alternatives in the promotion of equal influence. But how could we invoke
the value of such equality in the exogenous design of a voting system
without allowing that if there is ground to argue that the system is not
actually delivering equality, then voters should be able to argue for one or
another amendment to the system (Beitz 1989)? To deny voters the right to
invoke the value of equality in critique of a system that is chosen for its
promise of delivering equality would be to fail to honour that very value.32
32
Waldron (2006: 1364) takes a more congenial line in arguing that although the members of a
democratic society, on his assumptions, ‘believe in majority rule as a rough general principle for
politics, they accept that individuals have certain interests and are entitled to certain liberties that
should not be denied simply because it would be more convenient for most people to deny them.
They believe that minorities are entitled to a degree of support, recognition, and insulation that is not
necessarily guaranteed by their numbers or by their political weight.’ I am grateful to Caleb Yong for
drawing this to my attention.
An individualized system of influence 215
When a system of influence allows individuals to invoke in criticism of its
operations the very equality of influence it is designed to promote, then it
counts in an established term as a recursive procedure (Benhabib 1996). It
exemplifies a system that may be put into operation, not just in shaping
distinct, external issues, but in shaping the very form that it assumes itself.
To canonize majority rule – to give it sacred and unquestionable status –
would be to deny the possibility of recursion and, inevitably, the possibility
of reforming the system itself. To allow majority rule to be subject to
contestation and amendment, and to keep the possibility of continued
contestation and amendment alive, is to keep future developments open.
Institutional implications
In analysing how a representative assembly might operate – a responsively
rather than an indicatively representative body – I abstracted from the
precise details of the electoral system that ought to be introduced. This
argument for allowing the individualized contestability of the assembly has
been put forward under a similar abstraction from institutional detail. But it
should be clear, in broad outline, what sorts of measures are likely to be
required. A system that allows potentially effective, individualized contest-
ability will have to provide, not just for contestability proper but,
pre-contestation, for transparency in the decisions contested and, post-
contestation, for impartiality in resolving the charges raised. The require-
ments are as follows.
* Transparency: the capacity of members of the society to know what
33
I assume that a system of rights can be made to work productively, without cramping democratic
initiative (for such concerns see Schwartzberg 2007; Tully 2009).
34
The fact that I avoid making any detailed institutional proposals may suggest that in the perspective
adopted here, the status quo in most democracies is pretty well OK. I do not support that suggestion.
I believe that there is much work to be done in theoretically elaborating and empirically testing the
institutional requirements of republican ideals and that this work may support quite radical measures,
including measures of which we may currently have no inkling. Take a proposal, then, like that which
John McCormick (2011) makes for a people’s lottery-selected tribunate. It would be a serious mistake
to think that because I do not endorse it here, there is a deep rift between the radical republican
democracy for which he looks and the image of republican democracy developed in this book. There
is no necessary divergence between us, at least not on this ground; I am conducting an argument at a
level of abstraction that makes it impossible to explore such proposals.
218 Democratic influence
the individualized testing of any policies generated and of any processes
used in the generation of policies. It requires giving people an editorial, as
well as an authorial, role – a role in testing as well as generating policies –
and, in particular, an editorial role that has an individualized and not just a
collective dimension.35
The desideratum
We assume that the influence people have under an electorally centred
system is supposed to impose a certain direction on government; this
assumption will be at the centre of concern in the next chapter. It is
important to recognize that people might be able to use their electoral
and contestatory influence to elicit such a direction on the part of those in
authority, without this system of influence being unconditioned or inde-
pendent. They might be able to prescribe for such a direction only because
those in power, wanting perhaps to think of themselves as democrats, like to
let their policies correspond to popular demands. Or they might be able to
prescribe for the direction only because some background power such as a
military service or a moneyed elite or an imperial overseer happens to favour
government policies that are popularly satisfying.
If the people had a directive influence over government only by this sort
of courtesy or connivance, then that influence would not give them control
or power over government. Control requires that the correlation between
popular demand and government supply should be robust across variations
in the will of government or in the will of any third party. Let the correlation
be contingent or conditioned in this way, and it will be the agency on which
the correlation depends that enjoys power or control, not the people whom
that agency chooses to benefit.
One of the main concerns that recurs in the history of Italian–Atlantic
republicanism is the fear that the independence of the people as a source of
directive influence on government is going to be very difficult to maintain.
That independence will be jeopardized under two conditions, so Richard
Price (1991: 78–9) argued. One is when a foreign state allows a people to
govern itself but reserves the right to suspend the arrangement so that it is
‘liable to be altered, suspended or over-ruled at the discretion of the state
35
For earlier treatments in which these two dimensions of democracy are emphasized see Pettit (1999,
2000a, 2000b).
An unconditioned system of influence 219
which possesses the sovereignty’. And the other is when the representatives
of the people operate under a ‘higher will which directs their resolutions,
and on which they are dependent’. In this condition, as in the first, govern-
ment acts under the influence of the people but because that influence is
conditional on the acquiescence of a higher will, the government is subject
to ‘no controul from the people’.36
What measures would be likely to give an independent, unconditioned
character to the system of popular influence available under an electoral and
contestatory regime? I ignore the problem on the international front, since it
would take us into the domain of international relations. The question we
confront is, what measures might guard the system against exhibiting a
domestically conditioned variety of popular influence: a sort of influence
that remains in place only to the extent that government, or some collateral
power, is content for it to remain in place?
In discussing this issue in the last chapter we saw that the only assured
safeguard is a resistive community: that is, a community in which, as a
matter of fact and/or common belief, people are disposed to resist govern-
ment, should it ignore popular influence, and government is disposed to
avoid triggering resistance. Just the presence of an electoral system, even one
that is adjusted in a contestatory way so as to ensure individualized influ-
ence, is obviously not enough to guarantee such a resistive culture. So what
initiatives might we take to promote this desideratum?
36
The concern with being subject to foreign control was central to the complaints of the American
colonists after the repeal of the Stamp Act in 1766. While the repeal seemed to recognize the right of
colonial subjects – or at least propertied, mainstream males – to govern themselves on a more or less
popular basis, it came with a sting in the tail. The Westminster Parliament did indeed withdraw an act
that had seemed to violate that right but it insisted at the same time, in the so-called Declaratory Act,
that it did so as matter of grace, not because of any obligation. Parliament, so it was declared, ‘had,
hath, and of right ought to have, full power and authority to make laws and statutes of sufficient force
and validity to bind the colonies and people of America, subjects of the crown of Great Britain, in all
cases whatsoever’. See the unpublished paper by J. Rakove, A. R. Rutten and B. R. Weingast, ‘Ideas,
Interests, and Credible Commitments in the American Revolution’, and, for theoretical background
to that paper, Weingast (1997).
This sort of concern was widespread in that period. Thus in 1782 the Westminster Parliament was
pressed into repealing a law of 1720 under which the Dublin Parliament – not, of course, a very
representative body – could have its resolutions nullified in London; this law had been designed, in its
own words, ‘for the better securing the dependency of the kingdom of Ireland on the crown of Great
Britain’ (Stewart 1993: 26). But critics protested that repeal was not enough, since it did not entail a
renunciation of Westminster’s right to overrule them. And then, perhaps because of the lesson
learned in America, Westminster responded by passing such a renunciation in 1783. See Stewart (1993:
Chapter 4). Perhaps it was for that reason that in seeking to end home rule in 1800, London did not
suppress the Dublin Parliament but induced its members, largely on the basis of bribes, to dissolve the
body.
220 Democratic influence
I propose that two absolutely crucial measures for promoting it correspond
to the two institutional elements that characterize Italian–Atlantic republican-
ism: on the one side, the mixed constitution and, on the other, the contestatory
citizenry. If the constitution is mixed, then government is likely to be resistance-
averse, and if the citizenry has a contestatory character, then the people are
likely to be resistance-prone. The society, in short, is likely to be resistive.
The individualization of popular influence already argues for a degree of
mixture in the constitution, for example in the separation of adjudicative
power from other forms of power. And the individualization of popular
influence requires people to be contestatory in the assertion of their individual
and minority claims against majoritarian neglect. The best hope for making
popular influence unconditioned or independent is to push for further devel-
opments on these fronts. In outlining the developments needed, as I now go on
to do, I shall assume that the requirements for an electoral system in which
influence is individualized are already in place. The need for transparency,
contestability and impartiality has already been institutionally satisfied.
37
One way of marking their position is to say that they were positivists about sovereignty. Just as
positivists about law argue that even bad law – even law that breaches natural law – should still count
as law, they argue that even the bad sovereign – even, for example, the tyrannical sovereign – should
An unconditioned system of influence 221
Bodin and Hobbes adopted an antagonistic stance towards the mixed
constitution, because they saw quite clearly what that arrangement, as it was
characterized and celebrated by Polybius (1954), Cicero (1998) and
Machiavelli (1965), was designed to do. It was meant to ensure that the
state could not have the sort of power that would allow authorities to
impose their own, arbitrary will on the people they govern. And so it was
straightforwardly inconsistent, as Bodin and Hobbes saw it, with the sort of
role that they envisaged for sovereign and state.
While traditional defenders of the mixed constitution present it in
received terms as a mixture of the three pure constitutional types, mon-
archy, aristocracy and democracy, this rhetorical trope serves to encode
straightforward institutional constraints. They divide into constraints asso-
ciated with any constitutional order, on the one side, and constraints
associated with the mixing of powers on the other. The constitutional
constraints require that government should operate in accordance with
due process, not ruling by ad hoc decree but via public, general and
prospective regulations (Fuller 1971; O’Donnell 2004). They impose what
has come to be known as a rule of law under which, as Cicero (1998: 151)
expressed the ideal, ‘a magistrate is speaking law, and law a silent magis-
trate’. The mixture constraints require something designed to be supportive
of such a rule of law: that different governmental powers be held in different
hands; that those different powers should be shared out amongst different,
mutually checking agents or agencies; and that the centres of power should
be designed to give all sectors of the people a fair presence or representation
in the exercise of power. To put the lesson in a slogan, the mixture of the
mixed constitution requires a separation of powers, a sharing of powers and
a balancing of powers.
What are the powers of government that should be separated under the
mixed constitution (Gwyn 1965; Vile 1967)? The answer that became
standard under the influence of the Baron de Montesquieu (1989) is, the
powers of legislation, administration and adjudication. But that may be
over-inclusive in one way, under-inclusive in another. It may be over-
inclusive in calling for the separation of legislation and administration,
since the experience of Westminster systems of government is that there
is no real danger – and there may be some real benefit – in not separating
still count as sovereign. And just as positivists take law to count as law in virtue of serving a certain
function – for example, that identified in Hart (1961) – so they take the sovereign to count as
sovereign in virtue of serving the function they identify as crucial: that of establishing peace and order
in the society. For some cautionary remarks about the interpretation of Hobbes on this point, see
Hoekstra (2001).
222 Democratic influence
those branches. And it may be under-inclusive in failing to call for the
separation of different branches of the armed and police forces, the separa-
tion of secular from religious authorities, and indeed, the separation of
centres of political power from those in control of commerce and business.
Such divisions are liable to be just as important as more formal devices in
guarding against the abuse of public power.38
How should any power be shared under the mixed constitution?
Bodin’s early critics pointed out that there were many ways in which
law-making might be shared amongst different individuals or bodies, or
divided out amongst them (Besold 1618: 279–80; Cabot 1751; Franklin
1991). The same remains true today. Thus the legislative power might be
dispersed by giving the right to propose laws to one body or official, the
right to decide on the proposal to another; by having two or more
legislative houses, as in standard bicameral systems; by exposing the
power of those houses to the constraint of the courts, as the individual-
ization of influence requires; and/or by giving a formal or effective veto
to the administration over what laws are to stand or be enforced.39 This is
not the place, however, to discuss the relative merits of such arrange-
ments or the virtues of combining them in different ways.
The balancing of powers complemented the required separation and
sharing of powers in the traditional image of the mixed constitution
(Richter 1977). The constitution was to combine the inputs of nobility
and commons, as in the traditional picture, and thereby ensure that no one
was excluded from influence. This requirement was interpreted in a
demanding, democratic spirit by writers like Machiavelli (1965) in the
sixteenth century – see McCormick (2011) – and by radical commonwealth
writers in eighteenth-century England (Lieberman 2006). That interpreta-
tion emphasizes that popular acquiescence in how a regime operates is the
ultimate guarantor of a constitution and that this gives the citizenry as a
whole a special role in the maintenance of the regime.
38
For an original and congenial development of this encompassing view of the separation – and also the
sharing and balancing – of powers, see Braithwaite (1997). And for a consciously republican
application of the view in the analysis of policy-making in an emerging democracy, see
Braithwaite, Charlesworth and Soares (2012).
39
Thus it might be worth noting that Athens shared out legislative power between the ecclesia, the
courts and the law-amending body, the nomothetai (Hansen 1991; Ober 1996) and that among other
measures Rome had distinct law-making bodies such as the tribal and centuriate assemblies (Millar
1998). This particular Roman arrangement creates different possible sources of law where most
arrangements create different possible veto points. For a nice discussion of the futility of looking
for which institution was really the sovereign in ancient Athens, see Ober (1996: 120–1).
An unconditioned system of influence 223
Bodin and Hobbes and like-minded opponents of the mixed consti-
tution would not have objected greatly to the separation of powers as
such, since they were happy to allow the administration of government
to be delegated to other hands. And neither would they have railed
against the balancing of powers, even interpreted radically, since they
allowed that an inclusive, majoritarian democracy was a legitimate, if not
a desirable, regime. Their real opposition would have been to the sharing
of legislative power, since it appeared, particularly in combination with a
sharing of administrative and judicial powers, to ensure that government
would be unable to close ranks and assert its authority in unruly and
divisive times.
From our point of view, of course, it is good that government should be
unable to close ranks in this way. To the extent that the agencies of
government are unable to make common cause against popular pressure,
they will be more disposed to try to avoid triggering popular resistance. Any
one governing agent or agency may be tempted to challenge popular feeling
and to face down popular resistance. But the very fact that the state acts only
when its component bodies all come into alignment – and that it is forced to
act under the constraints of a rule of law – means that the government as a
whole is less likely to be disposed to display such bravado. That government
will not be as ready as any individual part might be to ignore or push back
against popular resistance.
In concluding this discussion of the mixed constitution, it may be useful
to point out that apart from being institutionally worrisome, the absolutist
critique launched by Bodin and Hobbes – and supported in different ways
by Rousseau and Kant (Pettit 2012b) – is philosophically misconceived.
Bodin and Hobbes assume that in order to be a source of coherent law the
state has to perform as an agent or agency with a single mind – a person,
they often say – and that in order to be a source of effective sanction it has to
have absolute power. The first claim is the most relevant in the argument
against the mixed constitution. Building on the assumed need for an agent
or agency with a single mind, they each maintain that this would be
unavailable if the constitution allowed for independent centres of power,
however coordinated. ‘It is impossible that the commonwealth, which is
one body, should have many heads,’ Bodin (1967: vi.4.198) writes. If it were
organized in that way, Hobbes maintains, then we would have ‘not one
independent commonwealth, but three independent factions; nor
one representative person, but three’ (Hobbes 1994b: 29.16). And, as we
saw in the Introduction, Rousseau (1997: ii.2.2) takes up the theme with
224 Democratic influence
relish, arguing that under the mixed constitution the sovereign is turned
into ‘a being that is fantastical and formed of disparate parts’.40
We can agree for reasons already rehearsed that it is essential, as all
thinkers assume, that the state or commonwealth should operate like a
single agent or person in delivering and applying law. To be an agent in the
appropriate sense is to be an individual or body that can recognize demands
like those of consistency and prove responsive to them. It is to be susceptible
to the constraints and challenges of reason in the adoption of ends and in
the formation of judgements as to how best to promote those ends. These
critics argue against the mixed constitution because they assume that in
order for a state to assume such an agential or personal status, there has to be
a spokesperson available to speak for it. This spokesperson may be a king or
queen, they say, or an aristocratic or democratic assembly that operates
under majority rule. More generally, it has to be a spatio-temporally
concrete entity, not an entity that exists on the basis of how different
individuals or bodies operate and coordinate. But this is sheer dogma.
There is absolutely no reason why the state should not be a distributed
agency that is answerable to the demands of reason, like any agent, but
answerable in virtue of the rules of coordination under which distinct
component parts cooperate (List and Pettit 2011).
We saw earlier that as a matter of fact an assembly that operates blindly
under majority rule won’t be able to live up to the demands of reason and
agency and that for every candidate, law or policy generated there should be
a test to determine if it is likely to induce inconsistency. This testing might
clearly be done under a system of mutual checking between different houses
in a legislature and under a constraint of engagement between those houses
and a constitutional court. Such an arrangement, representing a simple
form of mixed constitution, would give a voice to the people, as Bodin and
Hobbes require. But that voice would emerge from the interaction between
different bodies in the complex whole; it would not be the voice of a single
body, authorized to act as spokesperson for the whole.
Why did Bodin, Hobbes and Rousseau overlook this possibility? Apart
from the fact that it suited their political purposes to neglect it, they may
well have been moved by what A. N. Whitehead (1997: 51) calls the fallacy of
misplaced concreteness. This fallacy might have led them to think that if
40
The theme routinely appears also in the long tradition on which Rousseau had a shaping influence.
See for example Hegel’s (1991: 308) critique of the idea that the different powers in the state should be
independent: ‘it is plain to see that two self-sufficient entities cannot constitute a unity, but must
certainly give rise to a conflict whereby either the whole is destroyed or unity is restored by force’.
An unconditioned system of influence 225
there is a mind in the commonwealth then this corporate mind must be
located in a single place within the commonwealth: in the head of the
monarch, quite literally, or in the forum where the assembly meets. But the
purposes and judgements on which the state acts – the mind that informs its
behaviour towards citizens and towards other individuals and bodies – may
emerge from the interaction of distinct, separated parts within the state.
They do not have to be located in any one of these concrete parts.
Gilbert Ryle (1949) tells a story about the visitor to Oxford who is taken
around the colleges and, thinking that it is something equally concrete, asks
also to see the University. What the visitor fails to register is that the
University exists and performs as a unified agency in virtue of the way
that the colleges interact; it exists in and through them, emerging as a
superordinate entity, rather than consisting in something coordinate and
additional. What is true of the University in relation to the colleges can be
equally true of the state in relation to its constituent parts. In order to have a
state that speaks with one voice and displays one mind, it is not necessary
that one of those parts should be sovereign. The state may be a super-
ordinate entity that exists on the basis of a sustained, disciplined form of
interaction between the parts. That is the possibility that critics of the mixed
constitution wittingly or unwittingly neglected.41
41
In contemporary philosophy of mind, the critique of the Cartesian idea that the mind or soul of the
human being condenses in a particular entity – the res cogitans or ‘thinking thing’ – indicts Descartes,
so we might say, for having fallen also into the fallacy of misplaced concreteness (Dennett 1992; Clark
1997). There is a nice parallel between concretist assumptions about the mind of the individual
subject and concretist assumptions about the sovereign in the state.
226 Democratic influence
Taking up the need for a contestatory citizenry, we should note that the
individualization of power already requires people to be disposed to contest
laws and policies that seem to undermine their equality of influence. But the
need to ensure that popular influence is not conditioned on the goodwill of
government, or that of any third party, supports the requirement independ-
ently. People must be on the watch for proposals or measures that are not
suitably supported – more on this in the next chapter – and they must be
ready to organize in opposition to such policies. It is only in the presence of
concerted, sustained oversight of government activity – only in the presence
of civic vigilance, in the old term – that we can have any assurance that
government will be forced to remain responsive to popular inputs.
But what is required to ensure an appropriate form of vigilance? The
freedoms of speech, association and travel that any effective electoral system
presupposes must be registered in common consciousness. And citizens
must regularly exercise and put those freedoms to the test in an active,
engaged style of politics. While not everyone need be an activist, vigilance
requires a high aggregate level of civic engagement. Numbers of people
must be there to manifest an interest in every initiative of government and
numbers must be there to insist on the government’s justifying the initia-
tives it takes. Democratic life, as it is sometimes put, has to have an
agonistic – better perhaps, an antagonistic – character.
Is this ideal romantic rather than realistic? It would be romantic if it
required political activists and public-interest groups to keep individual tabs
on everything, as in some traditional images of civic virtue (Montesquieu
1989). But contemporary states are too complex to allow such panoramic
scrutiny and interrogation. What is needed, obviously, is specialization and
organization: in short, a division of labour in the exercise of civic vigilance.
And that ideal is scarcely unrealistic, since contemporary democracies natu-
rally give life to watchdog, activist bodies – non-governmental organizations –
that operate locally, nationally and internationally across the various
domains of political life. These include bodies that specialize, for example,
in consumer issues, people’s working conditions, women’s rights, environ-
mental sustainability, racial equality, opportunities for the disabled, the
conditions of prisoners, gay and lesbian rights, health provision and public
education.
The specialization in civic vigilance and contestation that public-interest
bodies make possible is desirable on two fronts. It does not only make it
possible to have government more effectively invigilated by the citizenry
than would be feasible under a regime of panoramic monitoring. It also
makes it possible to recruit people to the exercise of civic vigilance on the
An unconditioned system of influence 227
basis of their particular concerns and passions; recruitment does not have to
appeal merely to the abstract call of virtue. There will be no problem with a
civic vigilance that is exercised on the basis of such particularistic enthusi-
asm and attachment, provided that it appeals to a public standard like the
ideal of equal influence and that appeal is made in a public forum. It can be
sourced in the divisions and resentments emphasized in the long republican
tradition by Machiavelli and by contemporary writers who identify with his
themes (McCormick 2011). It can be nourished just by what Adam
Ferguson (1767: 167) described as the ‘refractory and turbulent zeal’ of
ordinary people.
Not only does the activism envisaged here reject the romantic idea of
each citizen’s exercising a panoramic, altruistic form of oversight; it also
rejects the equally romantic idea of a participatory, Rousseauvian engage-
ment. The participatory approach is so other-worldly that it is likely to
demoralize activists, not inspire them: its ‘insistence on the identity of the
ruler and the ruled has the effect’, as one author puts it, ‘of removing
democracy from the pages of history and of restricting it to an ideal that
has never before been realized, not even in ancient Athens’ (Green 2004:
748). The engagement that is required to make popular influence robust is
rather the activity of the radical social movements that offer an account of
common concerns, articulate a suite of popular demands, and challenge
government for its failures to recognize or reflect those demands in its
policies (Young 1990; Honig 2001). While it gives people an active part in
the political system, it does not pretend that politics is a matter of the people
coming together in a grand, will-forming, law-making exercise.
But if the contestatory model of the democratic people is not romantic in
character, neither does it have the cynical cast assumed by political realists.
Thus it contrasts just as sharply with views according to which democracy
requires the stabilizing effect of widespread apathy and, as by a happy fault,
actually generates such apathy (Lipset 1960). If democracy is taken to consist
in nothing more than the electoral assignment of governmental responsibility
to a particular party or group, then it may operate best if there is little
turbulence amongst the population. But if it consists in the individualized
and unconditioned control of government by the people, then it must wither
away in the presence of popular apathy. Let people allow themselves to
become apathetic and the business of government is bound to be consigned
to hands on which they have no influence and can impose no direction.
Calling for contestatory vigilance is not redundant, then, any more than
it is romantic. People do have to make an effort to overcome political
apathy, so that the habit of making such an effort deserves the name of
228 Democratic influence
virtue. It constitutes a motivated variety of virtue – a sort of virtue that is
independently reinforced by personal interest and spontaneous invest-
ment – as distinct from virtue of a pure, moralistic kind. However demand-
ing, such motivated virtue is certainly within people’s reach. And so people
may be held responsible for failing to exemplify vigilance and contestation.
Let them fail to display it and ‘they may thank themselves’, as James
Harrington (1992: 20) put it in the 1650s; the failure will stem from a
weakness of will for which they only have themselves to blame.
These observations show that the contestatory spirit required under a
republican regime counts as a form of civic virtue, albeit virtue in a sense in
which it ought to be readily achievable. But there is one other aspect of this
virtue that we ought also to stress. This is that, while it consists in a willingness
to challenge public proposals and policies, alleging that they are not supported
by the people, or not supported in a manner that treats all members as equals,
it presupposes a commitment to living under an arrangement where all
members of the community can share in a system of equal popular influence.
Contestatory virtue is not the sort of contrarian or sectarian disposition that
opposes compromise and accommodation. It is the virtue of citizens who
embrace the ideal of a republic in the community in which they happen to
live – they are in that sense patriots (Viroli 1995) – and who are willing to do
all that is required for realizing the ideal. Not only are they patriots in
supporting their country internationally, to invoke the usual application of
the idea. More relevantly for our concerns, they are also patriots at home.
They are committed to establishing an undominating government in their
country, just as it is, and rather than yearning or working for a land governed
by their particular tribe or creed or colour, they accept that this will require
accommodation on all sides, their own included.
The ideal of the contestatory citizenry that we have been describing is
intimately connected with the ideal of the mixed constitution. Given that the
voice of the people is meant to emerge from a process of interaction between
different bodies, there is every reason to think that individuals operating in
contestatory, as well as electoral, guise should constitute one of those parts. But
whereas the idea of a contestatory citizenry coheres in this way with the mixed
constitution, it is utterly at odds with the Rousseauvian image of a law-making
assembly that speaks with the voice of a uniquely authorized spokesperson for
the people. If the law-making assembly is the spokesperson that speaks with
unique authority for the public or the people, as in the image that Rousseau
inherited from Hobbes, then individuals cannot be allowed in their private
capacity as subjects to contest that voice. Were they given rights to question
the dictates of the sovereign assembly, then that assembly could not speak with
An efficacious system of influence 229
the requisite authority. Thus, as we saw in the Introduction, Hobbes (1994b:
18.4) says that if subjects could ‘pretend a breach of the covenant made by the
sovereign . . . there is in this case no judge to decide the controversy’. And
Rousseau faithfully echoes that thought when he maintains that ‘if individuals
were left some rights . . . there would be no common power who might
adjudicate between them and the public’ (Rousseau 1997: i.6.7).42
42
Kant follows Rousseau in this image of a uniquely authorized spokesperson and elaborates a similar
thought when he asks who is to decide the sort of issue that might arise between subject and sovereign
under a contestatory arrangement. Envisaging an individual rather than a collective sovereign, he
gives the following answer. ‘Only he who possesses the supreme administration of public right can do
so, and that is precisely the head of state; and no one within a commonwealth can, accordingly, have a
right to contest his possession of it’ (Kant 1996: 299; see too 463). It is this consideration that leads
Kant to the view, mentioned in the earlier discussion of contractualism, that even should the
sovereign ‘proceed quite violently (tyrannically), a subject is still not permitted any resistance by
way of counteracting force’ (Kant 1996: 298). For an argument that still Kant could have found
grounds for condemning the Nazi state see Ripstein (2009: 341–2).
230 Democratic influence
policy in one or another direction. Where that policy goes will depend on
how we cast our votes and on what we choose to contest as individuals or
subgroups, whether via the legislature, in the courts, through ombudsman
or related channels, or, of course, in the media and on the streets. The
system will be set up in such a way that the actions we take individually and
in aggregate ought to be capable of making a huge impact. There will be
nothing to inhibit us from seeking such an impact, as we operate in a space
of free speech and association and are in no way dependent on the acqui-
escence of a higher will. And the system will be designed under such
constraints – under such checks and balances – that the inputs we deliver
are transmitted smoothly, perhaps even with some amplification, to the
points where they can have an effect on policy.
But these comments address only active efforts at influence and miss out on
influence of other kinds. For if we, the people, have the power of exercising
such active influence, whether electorally or otherwise, then we can practise a
corresponding form of virtual influence on how government behaves. Without
intervening when we are happy with government performance, we can remain
poised to intervene should things not transpire to our satisfaction. We can ride
herd on government, to return to the cowboy metaphor, wittingly or unwit-
tingly ensuring that it does not take a policy-making direction to which we
object. Without actually doing anything active, we can stop government going
against our dispositions, as the cowboy who rides herd on his cattle stops them
from going against wishes he has actually formed.
Apart from active and virtual influence, an electoral-cum-contestatory
system will also allow us to practise reserve influence. We exercise this form
of influence when we do not have formed dispositions in regard to the
direction government should take on a certain issue of policy, but we
remain disposed to intervene should such a disposition materialize. If we
form a disposition that rules against a certain policy, then if the policy has
actually been adopted we will use our active influence to combat that policy,
and if it remains a merely possible option, we will rely on our virtual
influence to keep it from being adopted.
Where we can command a virtual or reserve form of influence over
government, it is very likely that those in power will become aware of the
fact. And if government is aware of our power in this regard, then it is likely
to be suitably inhibited.43 Conscious that we would oppose the adoption of
43
To be aware of the virtual interference of another agent is to be exposed to coercion; to be aware of the
reserve interference of another agent – to be aware of the invigilation practised by that agent – is to be
exposed to intimidation.
An efficacious system of influence 231
a certain policy, it is likely on that account to be slow to pursue it. And
conscious that we might turn against a certain policy that we do not
currently oppose, say as a result of seeing how it works in practice, govern-
ment is likely on that account to be hesitant to introduce it. Thus we can
enjoy influence over government just by being saliently disposed in this or
that direction. Without raising a hand or uttering a word, we can put
government in a position where it will do our work for us in acting
according to our actual or likely dispositions.
These comments should make clear that under the system described so
far the river of popular influence can run wide and deep. It can flow into
every corner and cranny of government decision-making, imposing con-
straints on what decisions the different agencies reach and on how they
reach them. The influence may emanate not just from how we act in general
elections and in individualized contestations but, as in the virtual and
reserve cases, from how we are just disposed to act on those fronts. It can
enfranchise our dispositions, as well as our deeds.
Given the multi-dimensional manner in which our dispositions can
impinge on government performance, there is every hope that the influence
we exercise can constrain government to the point where private will is only
allowed an impact that is consistent with the direction the influence is
designed to impose. Assuming that there is an equally acceptable direction
in which this popular influence can push government – that is the topic of
the next chapter – the influence ought to be efficacious enough, other things
being equal, to ensure the satisfaction of the tough-luck test.
But are other things going to be equal? Is the river of popular influence
going to be allowed to flow wide and deep? Or will it be excessively diverted or
diluted by the other streams of influence that can inundate the public world? I
discuss that possibility in this final section, addressing three dangers in partic-
ular and arguing that none is inescapable. The first is the danger of elected
politicians usurping the influence of the people under motives of self-interest.
The second is the danger of private lobbies usurping that influence out of a
desire to push government in a direction that does not necessarily have popular
support. And the third is the danger that unelected authorities, including
authorities established to counter the earlier dangers, might gain a hold over
government policy that is not sensitive to popular demands.44
44
Many of the points made in the following discussion draw on earlier arguments in Pettit (2002a,
2004b). Where I wrote there of the need to depoliticize democracy, however, I now tend to avoid this
talk. It has helped to bolster the criticism that republicanism, as I interpret it, does not give people a
proper, democratic role. See McCormick (2011: 155–7).
232 Democratic influence
The danger from elected politicians
Benjamin Constant (2003: 387) identifies the first danger crisply when, as
we saw, he observes that if you elect someone to a representative office then
you thereby give ‘him a different interest from the one he is charged with
representing’. By electing representatives, at least in the normal run of
things, we give them a special interest in being re-elected and a powerful
concern to take steps that will facilitate re-election and to avoid steps that
will stand in the way. This observation points us immediately to areas of
policy-making in which elected politicians would have to be saintly not to
be moved by their own interests, regardless of what popular influence
supports – or indeed of what the preconditions for popular influence
require.
The prospects of re-election are going to depend for many politicians on
the voting and districting system under which they operate. A first lesson,
then, is that they should not be given management of such electoral issues.
But the prospects of re-election are also going to depend on how informa-
tion on government performance is shaped and communicated. So a second
lesson is that elected politicians should not be given command over the
release of social and economic data and statistics. Again, to go to a more
general matter, the prospects of re-election are going to depend most
saliently on the experience of voters in the present, so that there is going
to be a powerful incentive for politicians to make that experience sweet and
to downplay future costs, where these are costs that electors may be
presumed to care about, but to be easily led into ignoring. This last
consideration argues for a number of lessons: for example, that government
policies on interest rates, on energy and environmental issues, and perhaps
on criminal sentencing ought not to be left entirely in the hands of the
elected. Politicians, being focused on the electoral short term, are always
likely to favour lower interest rates, easier energy and environmental
demands, and tougher, retributively satisfying sentences. And however
attractive in the short term, such policies can be very destructive and costly
over the longer haul.
How to cope with such dangers? The most obvious response, and one
taken in many democracies, is to put these areas of policy-making at arm’s
length from elected politicians. This response would argue for establishing
an independent electoral commission with responsibility on districting and
other electoral decisions; for introducing a body like the British Columbia
Citizens’ Assembly to make recommendations on some particular issues; for
setting up independent, reputable authorities to gather, analyse and release
An efficacious system of influence 233
publicly important data and statistics; for investing an economically
informed central bank with responsibility for interest rates and related
issues; and for having similar bodies make recommendations, and effec-
tively constrain policy, on issues of energy and the environment and on
matters of criminal sentencing.45
These comments are made on the assumption that the self-interest of
politicians will be exclusively electoral in character. But we should also
recognize the danger that once they occupy positions of power, politicians
will be exposed to a special temptation to accept hidden payments for the
favours they can do for certain individuals, corporations and other bodies.
This danger argues too for the introduction and empowerment of certain
unelected authorities, with a power of auditing the public books and, where
required, sponsoring charges of corruption.
In dealing with the requirements for individualizing popular influence I
argued that there would have to be channels of challenge, and tribunals of
adjudication, that are independent of government. This requirement was
further supported by our discussion of how to make popular influence
unconditioned. For all we said in those discussions, however, judicial and
cognate authorities might be elected in their own right or appointed with a
certain arm’s-length independence from government. The pressures
reviewed in this section argue against election. And so they point us to
yet another area – the conduct of the courts and other tribunals – where
the regulation of public life should be assigned to appointed, independent
authorities, not to figures who are required to keep an eye on the electoral
significance of their various decisions. But does the investment of such
unelected authorities itself raise a problem for the influence of the people?
I turn to that question after discussing the problem raised by private
lobbies.
46
One of the first policy changes introduced by President Zapatero of Spain, as he sought to follow a
republican agenda, was to put the national broadcaster at arm’s length from the control of the
government. See Marti and Pettit (2010).
An efficacious system of influence 235
there is no governing party or coalition whose members have to close ranks on
pain of allowing the administration to fall (Lessig 2011). In such systems,
legislators can vote independently of party and, while that sounds attractive, it
means that they can be exposed to enormous financial pressure to vote in this
or that manner on particular issues. Limiting private campaign finance,
providing public funds to match private campaigning funds, and restricting
the use of expensive advertisements on the electronic media are all possible
modes of dealing with the problem. But unfortunately such steps are some-
times not possible under received and difficult-to-amend constitutions. Thus
they would be very hard to implement in the US, since the courts treat money
spent on elections as protected political speech, arguing that the more speech
there is, the better; and put few restrictions even on essentially self-interested
bodies like commercial corporations (Bakan 2004).
It is generally easier to deal with this particular problem in parliamentary
democracies. Not only do most parliamentary regimes allow the use of
independent regulators to impose restrictions on campaign finance; when
they are not so proportionally elected as to put very loose coalitions in
power, these regimes offer an inbuilt, though only partial, safeguard against
the influence of private lobbies that seek to buy favours. The members of
the majority party in the legislature have to vote together on major issues,
since the administration is liable to fall if they do not close ranks in this way.
And that means that in order to influence what happens in government,
private lobbies have to buy over the whole party or couple of parties in
power; they cannot concentrate, as in the US system, on buying off
individual, more or less pivotal figures.
47
Pierre Rosanvallon (2006: 240) treats the Interstate Commerce Commission, established in the
United States in 1887, as one of the first examples of an ‘independent institution’, ‘shielded from the
direct authority of executive power’.
236 Democratic influence
adjudicative roles, they have a distinctive independence in common. They
are appointed to their offices by elected officials rather than being elected
themselves but they do not serve as functionaries of those officials; they are
appointed to serve for fixed or open terms, not at the pleasure of those who
appoint them.
The last question we need to confront is whether such unelected author-
ities constitute a source of influence that is independent from the influence
of the people, undermining the regime of popular influence for which we
are looking. The existence of these authorities may cause less of a problem
for a system of popular influence than the dangers they are designed to
combat. But the question is whether nevertheless they are a problem:
whether they represent a current of influence that dilutes the stream that
originates with the people.
The question is easily answered in the case of the statistically or indica-
tively representative assembly that is charged, like the British Columbia
Citizens’ Assembly, with giving advice on the decision to be taken on a
particular policy or set of policies. Such a body does not adopt initiatives in
causal response to the dispositions of people in the manner of electoral,
responsive representation. But that it takes one or another initiative is good
evidence that the people as a whole would adopt that sort of initiative, under
suitable information and deliberation. The intentional empowerment of
such an indicatively representative body, then, can be seen as a way of giving
influence to the dispositions of people in the domain where it operates.
Certainly it can be seen in this way, if there is a safeguard against the body
assuming a dominating role in its own right; this will be in place, for
example, when its recommendations are subject to independent review –
for example, by a referendum of the kind required in the British Columbia
case. The existence of such an advisory body is not an obstacle to the
influence of the people, but rather a means of channelling that influence.
I suggest that if other independent, unelected officials and bodies are
appointed under suitable conditions, and are forced to operate under suitable
constraints, then they too may have a claim to serve the people in the same
indicative way. Suppose that a judge or court, an electoral commissioner or
commission, a central banker or a central bank are selected on the publicly
contestable grounds of scoring well on experience, expertise and impartiality.
Suppose, second, that they are exposed to incentives of professional esteem to
show themselves to be experienced, expert and impartial in the way that they
resolve different issues (Brennan and Pettit 2004). Suppose, third, that they
are given a brief that has presumptive popular support: a brief to interpret and
apply the law impartially, to set up district boundaries and voting rules that
An efficacious system of influence 237
maximize electoral competition, to establish interest rates that guard against
inflation or unemployment. And suppose, finally, that they can be forced to
operate under conditions of such publicity, and such exposure to criticism
and challenge, review and censure – in brief such contestation – that they face
serious costs if they fail to live up to their brief. In that case, the decisions they
make are likely to be ones that the people, individually or collectively, would
make or approve if they had all the relevant information and expertise. And
this is not just a happy result of how they are independently disposed: it is a
pattern that is more or less imposed on them by the contestatory pressures to
which they are subject.
In our earlier picture, electorally responsive officials and bodies are
representative of the people in virtue of being responsive and are forced to
perform appropriately by the individualized contestation to which they are
exposed. In the picture I am sketching here, unelected authorities have a
complementary profile. They are indicative officials and bodies as a result of
the basis on which they are selected, the incentives to which they are
exposed, and the briefs they are given. And like elected authorities they
are forced to perform appropriately by the individualized contestation to
which they are exposed. They are proxies for the people who serve a crucial
representative role in complementing and containing the people’s elected
deputies.
The unelected authorities to which this analysis applies are not limited to
those in official roles of the kind illustrated. Any system of individualized
contestation requires particular individuals or groups to be ready to bring
charges against those in government, elected or unelected, whether in the
courts, in the press, or on the streets. What gives such contesting parties –
such private attorneys general, as they are sometimes known – the right to
speak, as they generally claim to do, in the name of the people? I think we
can cast them as indicative representatives who are subject to such con-
straint and contestation that they are bound to enact a brief, as we might
think of it, that they are given by the people. The brief is provided implicitly
in the fact that a popularly approved constitution allows private attorneys
general to mount arguments in the courts or other forums against new laws
and other decrees. The rationale behind the brief is to ensure that those in
any potentially disadvantaged sector of society can be represented by one of
their kind, or someone sympathetic, in challenging and testing the measures
at issue. And those private attorneys are more or less bound to enact their
brief, and honour its rationale, by being required to follow established
channels, arguing their case in a publicly accessible forum on publicly
available and contestable grounds.
238 Democratic influence
To gesture at the possibility of making unelected authorities into indi-
cative, suitably controlled representatives of the people is not to design the
incentives and briefs, the appointment procedures and operating con-
straints that might promote that ideal. Here, as in the other cases reviewed
in this chapter, we have to be content with being able to see in the abstract
how the people might enjoy a system of equally accessible influence that
meets republican constraints. I think that the considerations offered do
support the claim that this is a feasible possibility in the current case – and in
the other cases rehearsed – even if the rehearsal of such considerations falls
well short of the hard work required in institutional design.
The picture emerging from the discussion requires an electoral and
contestatory democracy that is established on a constitutional basis,
written or unwritten. The system envisaged is a form of constitutional
democracy insofar as it combines familiar democratic devices with more
or less familiar constitutional elements. But it is not a system in which
these devices and elements are just added together as independent com-
ponents. And it is not a system in which the constitutional elements are
fixtures that resist democratic control. The constitution is there to facil-
itate democratic influence – that is, an equally accessible form of uncon-
ditioned and efficacious influence – not just to complement it as an
independent factor. And the constitution is going to remain there only
to the extent that the democratic influence it facilitates is not exercised for
purposes of revising it. In view of these features, the picture we have been
led to adopt might be cast in James Tully’s (2009: i, 4) phrase, as
democratic constitutionalism: an approach in which ‘the constitution
and the democratic negotiation of it are conceived as equally basic’ (see
too Mueller 2007; Espejo 2011).
I said at the beginning of the chapter that our discussion would lead us to
a model of equally accessible popular influence that is far enough away from
the status quo to direct us towards reforms, yet near enough to assure us of
its feasibility. I hope that this promise seems to have been borne out in the
picture that has emerged from our critique of the plenary assembly, our
endorsement of an electoral assembly, and our introduction of amendments
to ensure that the popular influence it mediates is suitably individualized,
unconditioned and efficacious. With that picture in place, we turn in the
next chapter to ask how such a system of equally accessible influence –
equally accessible, unconditioned and efficacious influence – might push
government in an equally acceptable direction and establish the popular
control that republican democracy requires.
chapter 5
Democratic control
1
For an overview of various attempts to define democracy with a view to characterizing actual regimes
see Tilly (2007: Chapter 1). Given the account in this book of the institutions required for a republican
democracy, it ought to be possible to adapt one of these approaches in developing an audit of
democracy. The Economist Intelligence Unit offers a congenial index of democracy at www.eiu.
com/public/democracy_index.aspx.
Two familiar models of directed influence 243
with the standard approaches associated with them. That will lay the
ground for introducing a third, more promising candidate that I go on
to explore in Section 2.
2
Under the policy-first version, deputies are cast as delegates, in Hannah Pitkin’s (1972) phrase; under
the deputy-first they are cast as trustees. As we saw in the last chapter, deputies of either sort are
responsive representatives and should be distinguished from proxies, or indicative representatives. The
view of the American founders was clearly that elections would serve in the first place to select out
suitable deputies (see too Madison, Hamilton and Jay 1987: no. 57; Herreros 2006).
Two familiar models of directed influence 245
freedom of religion to anyone, which would unnecessarily restrict the range
of basic liberties. And it will be better than privileging one religion, since
this would reject people’s claim to equality; as we saw in the last chapter, it
would effectively ensure that people did not have an equal share in the
electoral system of popular influence.
What obtains in the religious domain holds also in a range of other
domains. As we have a shared individual interest in freedom of religion, so
we will have such a shared interest in having a regime that allows you to
hunt and me to farm, you to have clean water and me to build a factory, and
so on. The public interest, conceived in this way, is composed of those
goods that anyone who accepts the necessity of living on equal terms with
others is likely to want to have collectively guaranteed or promoted. It
consists in the interests that people are going to share insofar as they have
equal status as members of a polity (see Goodin 1996; Pettit 2004a).
While this account distinguishes the public interest from the intersection
of private interests, it also makes it distinct from what might be described as
the good of the nation or people, considered as a corporate entity. Considered
in a corporate role, a nation survives over many generations and its good may
have little to do with the good of the individuals who make it up at any time.
The nation or people may prosper in terms of international power relations,
for example, without that prosperity making for an aggregate gain amongst
members; maintaining the hegemony may be extremely costly and provide
most members with only the dubious benefit of being able to take pride in
their state. To identify the goal that the people might intentionally impose on
a state as the maintenance of such a corporate performance would be counter-
intuitive, though a certain sort of nationalism might support the line. It would
be to reject Aristotle’s (1996: 2.5) common sense when he argues in The Politics
that while a set of odd numbers may add up to an even sum, a population of
unhappy people cannot add up to a happy polis: ‘the whole cannot be happy
unless most, or all, or some of its parts enjoy happiness’.
If these observations are sound, then the most plausible version of this
first account of popular direction would say that the people exercise popular
control insofar as they intentionally use their influence to force government
to pursue public-interest policies, where the public interest is understood in
a post-social but non-corporate manner. The people may be held to do this
either in a policy-first or deputy-first manner: either by first identifying
suitable policies and then selecting representatives who support those
policies; or by first identifying suitable representatives and then relying on
them to formulate public-interest policies. But in either version, as we shall
see, the theory is less than satisfactory.
246 Democratic control
The elected representatives in each version may deliberate with one
another before casting their votes on the policies to be put in place. But
despite each endorsing a consistent set of policy judgements, the effect of
aggregating their votes may be to support an inconsistent package; that is
the lesson of the discursive dilemma, as we saw in the last chapter. This
means that the body of elected representatives will have a good deal of
discretion in deciding on their policies, whether they decide on them one by
one, as under the Washington system of deal-making, or in the overall
programme that parties typically present to the electorate in the
Westminster alternative.
The availability of such discretion accentuates a deep difficulty for the
intentional-direction approach. The politicians in the system – and to some
extent the people too – must be virtuous enough to make impartial judge-
ments on what is in the public interest and then to introduce policies that
promote that interest. In particular, they must be virtuous enough to do
this, even when electoral or other private interests – and no system of
popular influence can completely silence these – argue strongly for warping
the judgements or the policies in another direction and, of course, for
representing that redirection as itself required by the public interest.
Indeed, they must be virtuous enough to do this, even when all we know
of cognitive frailty suggests that private interest can delude them into seeing
the redirection as a requirement of public interest; it can enable them to
hide their misrepresentation from themselves (Gilovich, Griffin and
Kahneman 2002; McGeer and Pettit 2009).
The virtue required of people and representatives under the intentional-
direction story, unlike the virtue we ascribed to those who identify with
certain watchdog groups and social movements, is likely to be unmotivated.
There need not be any elements of personal interest or spontaneous
commitment to support it, so that the virtuous performance required may
only be forthcoming in the presence of something close to moral perfection.
That is a problem, for two reasons. One, such virtue is not an assured
commodity and a system that requires it is not guaranteed to be sustainable.
And two, even if people and politicians were generally disposed to be
virtuous, they might not be confident about one another’s virtue, and,
lacking assurance on the point, might fail to display virtue themselves; they
might each look after their own interests, fearing the prospect of being made
a sucker by others.
We can be concerned about this problem, I should mention, without
going to the extreme of adopting the so-called knave’s principle. We need
not assume, in Bernard Mandeville’s (1731: 332) words, that the best sort
Two familiar models of directed influence 247
of constitution is the one which ‘remains unshaken though most men
should prove knaves’. We can reject the principle, in David Hume’s
words (1875: 117–18), that in ‘fixing the several checks and controls of
the constitution, every man ought to be supposed a knave, and to have no
other end in all his actions than private interest’. The knave’s principle
may be counter-productive, as some empirical evidence suggests; it may
argue for institutions that crowd out whatever virtue is available, say by
triggering resentment and defiance (Pettit 1996b; Brennan and Pettit
2004: Chapter 14). Without embracing any such dubious principle,
however, we can still see good reason to reject any design that would
make unmotivated virtue into a prerequisite for the proper performance
of an institution; we can see good reason to economize on virtue
(Brennan and Hamlin 1995).
The intentional-direction model fails on precisely this count. It requires
politicians to put aside their private concerns – including their characteristic
concern with re-election – in formulating the policies that promise to
promote the public interest. And it requires ordinary electors to be disposed
to demand and respond to policies that succeed in doing this. Politicians
and electors must each form judgements about what the public interest
requires. They must do so in full sensitivity to the range of relevant
concerns, however altruistic. They must use their discretion in aggregating
those judgements without letting private interest or other pressures warp
the exercise. And they must then live up to those judgements – if you like,
those public-spirited preferences – in their performance on different fronts:
at the polls, in the party room, and in Parliament or Congress. O brave new
world that hath such people in it.
If this response seems somewhat cynical, I might add in conclusion that it
is fully in line with the long tradition of republican thought. Amongst
republican thinkers across different periods, it has been a constant refrain
that human beings are universally corruptible if often – thanks perhaps to
supportive institutions – actually uncorrupt (Pettit 1997c: Chapter 7).
Public office is a particular source of corruption, according to the tradition,
since it gives bearers a special opportunity to benefit from evil-doing and
often a special capacity to avoid being caught. It enables them, like the ring
of Gyges, to further their self-interest without having to run the usual risks
of detection and punishment. Thus, as Richard Price (1991: 30) puts the
recurrent theme, ‘There is nothing that requires more to be watched than
power.’ To entrust politicians with the articulation and advancement of the
public interest, regardless of their private concerns, would fly in the face of
this caution.
248 Democratic control
The non-intentional direction of government
We saw in Chapter 3 that it is possible for a person to control a process
without exercising control intentionally. The example we gave, drawn
from Amartya Sen, was that of a patient in a coma whose wishes dictate
the treatment provided, thanks to the intentional efforts of family and
friends. The wish of the patient has an influence on the treatment
adopted by the hospital, due to the influence of family and friends; it
controls for the treatment that the patient receives. And the connection
between influence and effect, input and output, is suitably robust or
unconditioned: while it depends on one of the family or friends coming
forward, for example, any of a number are willing to do so. Thus if the
wish had been absent, then the hospital would not in all likelihood have
provided that treatment; and if a different wish had been in its place, to
mark a richer possibility, then the hospital would have provided that
alternative instead.
In this example, the purpose effected by the system of influence and
direction is truly a goal or desideratum of the agent: it corresponds, after all,
to a wish. It is because of the influence of that wish that the treatment
assumes a certain form. But the causal mechanism whereby the wish
generates the treatment involves, not the intentions and efforts of the
agent, but rather those of family and friends. The lesson of the example,
then, is that direction and control may be non-intentional as well as inten-
tional. That lesson applies in collective, as well as individual, cases, as we
shall now see, and directs us to a second way in which popular influence
might be recruited to serve a popular purpose.
Consider the invisible hand whereby, under standard economic assump-
tions, the behaviour of consumers in an open market ensures the satisfaction
of the wish on the part of each to be able to buy goods and services at the
lowest feasible price. Consumers are each disposed to buy something of a
given quality as cheaply as possible, thereby displaying that wish, and to
shop around in order to achieve this. Producers of the commodity or service
are disposed to undercut one another’s prices in order to maximize revenue;
if they are not, then others will have an incentive to enter the market and
challenge them. And the effect of the interaction between the dispositions of
the two groups is to push producers to sell at the competitive price: that is, at
the lowest price that is consistent with their remaining in business.
Consumers do not cooperate on the basis of a shared intention or wish to
establish competitive pricing – certainly they need not do so. But they do
each wish to be able to buy what they want at competitive prices – although
Two familiar models of directed influence 249
not perhaps under that description – and the effect of their each acting on
those wishes is that, as by an invisible hand, the wishes are satisfied.
The notion of an invisible-hand mechanism became widely known and
celebrated in the wake of Adam Smith’s economic theories, as presented in
The Wealth of Nations in 1767 (1976). Unsurprisingly, it was soon adapted
for use in political theory. A compatriot of Smith’s, James Mill, argued in
1819, in a small treatise entitled An Essay on Government, that if we only
design the electoral system appropriately, then we can rely on an invisible
hand to promote the public interest (Lively and Rees 1978). Mill had rallied
behind Jeremy Bentham’s new philosophy and he argued that in a suitable
electoral system we can rely on an invisible hand to promote a utilitarian
version of the public interest: in the popular slogan of the time, the greatest
happiness of the greatest number.
Mill begins from an assumption that all human beings pursue their own
interest-satisfaction, where this is understood as the satisfaction of their
selfish preferences – in brief, their own happiness (Lively and Rees 1978: 5).
This gives him a utilitarian conception of the public interest; it consists in
‘that distribution of the scanty material of happiness, which would insure
the greatest sum of it in the members of the community, taken together’
(Lively and Rees 1978: 5). How then is a community of such individuals to
rely on government – government by a small number of their members, as
he assumes it has to be – to promote the public interest? ‘The community
itself must check these individuals, or else they will follow their interest’
(Lively and Rees 1978: 22) – their ‘sinister interest’, as he also describes it
(25). And how is the community to do this? By relying on ‘that grand
invention of modern times, the system of representation’ (Lively and Rees
1978: 21). Specifically, by relying on a system under which, first, electors are
inclusive enough to exemplify the range of interests in the community as a
whole (Lively and Rees 1978: 22) – Mill thinks that all older males will be
enough (27); and second, the period between elections is as short as
possible, consistently with allowing representatives to get on with their
job (25).3 The idea is that this system will force representatives to reflect
the interests of constituents in their voting, and that with such ‘an identity
of interest’ (Lively and Rees 1978: 34) between electors and elected, the
decisions reached will reflect a compromise that is going to promote the
greatest aggregate satisfaction of essentially self-interested agents. This
satisfaction is what he takes to constitute the public interest.
3
I am ignoring the fact that for Mill that job was mainly to keep an eye on the government exercised by
the King and his ministers.
250 Democratic control
If Mill’s picture is sound, then those in government will promote the
public interest of the community, in the utilitarian sense in which he
understands the public interest, and do so under the popular influence of
voters. That popular influence will generate the public interest, however,
not via an intention on the part of electors as a whole to let the public
interest have a dictating role, but rather via a mechanism that operates
behind their backs. With electors each voting for policies or deputies that
promise to satisfy their own self-regarding preferences, and with deputies
seeking to track the preferences of their constituents, the aggregate, unin-
tended effect is supposed to be that the interests of electors are maximally
satisfied overall.
Not many contemporary thinkers embrace Mill’s account of the popular,
invisible-hand direction of government that can be achieved under a
responsively representative picture. Whether interpreted on a basis that
gives priority to policies or deputies, it is open to the obvious objection
that for all that he says, electors and elected may form coalitions to impose
particular sectional interests in a way that is unresponsive to minority
interests within the society. Forming on the basis of common ethnic or
religious, commercial or regional priorities, such interest-groups could
systematically warp the laws and policies of government in their own favour.
But though Mill’s specific proposal no longer attracts many supporters,
there are loose relatives of the proposal that have been given some support in
more recent times. One is interest-group pluralism. It would suggest that
while interest-groups would certainly upset Mill’s individualist scheme,
they themselves might compete for influence over government in such a
way that the authorities can be expected, on pain of not being re-elected, to
look for the highest possible aggregate satisfaction of those competing
interests. According to this view, as one commentator puts it, ‘influence
over political decisions is diffused over a host of organized groups – trade
unions, business organizations, churches, societies for the promotion of this
or the protection of that – which express a variety of views and interests’
(Lively 1975: 58). And the idea, at least in some interpretations, is that if
people are generally represented in such interest-groups, then the influence
of those groups over government, proportional as it is likely to be to their
numbers, can be expected to be utilitarian in its overall effect: that is, to lead
to something like maximal preference-satisfaction overall.
This alternative, invisible-hand account of how the people might direct
government is open to even more salient objections than James Mill’s own.
For as many commentators have argued, there is absolutely no reason to
think that the influence of the different groups will be proportional to their
Two familiar models of directed influence 251
numbers (Connolly 1969). It is much more likely to be proportional to their
power over government, where that power is going to reflect a range of
possible factors: their level of organization and their financial resources,
their potential for campaigning against government or disrupting govern-
ment performance, and their usefulness at election time.
Starting afresh
The discussion of existing proposals for the popular direction of govern-
ment, whether intentional or non-intentional, seems to give credibility to
Schumpeter’s scepticism. There may be ways of establishing popular influ-
ence, even ways of making it into a very rich and penetrating form of
influence, as we saw in the last chapter. But going on the official record,
there appears to be very little prospect of using that popular influence to
impose a suitably popular direction on government.
The first of the two broad approaches sketched would organize govern-
ment around people’s public-interest judgements: their impartial preferen-
ces over what happens to the society as a whole. The second would organize
it under a mechanism designed to make government responsive to more
particular attitudes: people’s partial preferences over what happens to them
and theirs. But there seems to be little chance of arranging things so that
either socially oriented or self-oriented preferences can rule appropriately in
the corridors of power. The view that socially oriented preferences might
rule requires a dubious faith in the reliability of people’s virtue. The view
that self-oriented preferences might rule – that is, rule in a more or less
inclusive and fair fashion – requires an equally dubious faith in the capacity
of society to guard against the effects of unequal power.
Notwithstanding these criticisms, however, each of the approaches dis-
cussed has an appealing aspect. The first is attractive in focusing us on a
plausible goal for popular direction: that of the public interest, understood
in a post-social, non-corporate manner. The second is attractive in directing
us to a plausible means for popular direction: an invisible-hand mechanism
that does not require people to maintain monitoring and control of govern-
ment on an intentional basis. This raises the question as to whether there
might not be a third arrangement with both appealing aspects: a way of
directing government towards something like the public interest, as that is
understood in the first approach, that is implemented by something like an
invisible-hand process, as that is exemplified in the second.
As it happens, I think that this scenario is a real institutional possibility. It
will materialize, so I argue, insofar as two conditions are fulfilled. First,
252 Democratic control
people come to support certain norms of public policy-making, whether or
not this is something they intend, in virtue of pursuing popular influence
over government. And, second, these norms come to direct public decision-
making, whether or not this is something that people intend, thereby
establishing a popular purpose that government serves.
I look at how these two conditions can be fulfilled in Section 2 and at the
merits of the system of popular direction that this would install. And then in
Section 3 I explore the implications of the system for political ontology – for
our view of the nature and the relationships between people, constitution
and state – arguing that it allows us to think that in a distinctive sense
government satisfies Lincoln’s three demands: it is of the people, by the
people and for the people.
I describe the picture emerging from our considerations as a dual-aspect
model of how popular influence can impose a popular direction. This is
because democratic politics works in two timescales, according to that picture.
In day-by-day policy-making, the people exercise an equally accessible form of
electoral and contestatory influence over public decision-making. And by
means of doing this in the short haul, they manage over the long haul to
impose an equally acceptable direction on the performance of government.
4
My use of the model of the condominium for thinking about republican political theory, which I
pursue here and later in the text, is mirrored in an intriguing way by a recent set of studies that look at
how far condominiums and related organizations live up to republican expectations in post-Soviet
Russia. See Kharkhordin and Alipuro (2011).
A dual-aspect model of democracy 253
In an acceptance game, the parties each seek to influence others in favour of
this or that policy by announcing the minimal concession that they are willing
to make, by revising their offers or bids in face of a failure to secure con-
vergence, and by going through successive rounds or revisions until conver-
gence is achieved. The drive in this exercise is to identify an arrangement that
each is willing to accept – in that sense, it is an acceptance game – assuming
that they each wish to grant the smallest concession that they can get away
with; they each want to make the smallest sacrifice possible to the interests or
indeed the opinions that they stand for. This exercise might be conducted
without any discussion in a round of bids akin to the bids made in opening a
game of bridge. But if discussion is allowed, then it will consist in self-serving
arguments by the different parties. Those on lower, less expensive floors might
argue, for example, that they are unable to concede further in view of their
relative poverty, that their interest in securing convergence is less than the
interest they are being asked to sacrifice – for example, unlike those on higher
floors, they can live without an elevator service – or that the remaining
concession required from the better off is really quite trivial.
In the acceptability game, things are done in quite a different fashion.
The parties are required to propose the policy that they favour in the
domain of group choice – or perhaps to suggest a novel candidate – and
to present considerations to one another that should count as relevant by
the lights of all. The idea is that any considerations adduced should help to
make the policy acceptable to everyone, given shared assumptions about the
dispositions of each; they should engage with those dispositions and help to
make the policy congenial to each. The exercise is much more demanding
than one in which they each just announce what they are prepared to
accept. And equally it is more demanding than one in which each puts
forward considerations that, as they claim, others morally ought to accept:
considerations that they ought to accept, for example, assuming that they
ought to share the speaker’s religious faith or ethical vision. The consid-
erations adduced should count as relevant according to everyone’s views but
according to everyone’s views as they actually are or can be brought to be,
not according to everyone’s views as in some sense they ought ideally to be.
The participants in the acceptability game, being required to treat others
as equals, will debate with one another on broadly the sort of model
envisaged by deliberative democrats.5 They cannot present considerations
that some subset of the group are bound to regard as irrelevant from their
5
The thinker who has done most to emphasize the potential of the acceptability game, though not in
that phrase, is Juergen Habermas (1984–9). Jon Elster (1986) gives an insightful presentation of the
254 Democratic control
point of view; certainly they cannot do so and expect to carry others with
them. Willingly or unwillingly, they are required to obey the old principle
of law and rhetoric (Skinner 1996: Part i): audi alteram partem, ‘hear the
other side’.6 The only considerations they can invoke are ones that argue on
all sides – though perhaps with a varying force or weight – for accepting the
policy supported; they must count with everyone as grounds that it is at least
relevant or pertinent to adduce in arguing for or against a policy. Being
presented as considerations that everyone licenses in this way, or can at least
be expected to license, the rival parties offer them as reasons for why
everyone ought to be ready to accept the policy proposed.
The acceptability game is governed, in the nature of the case, by a norm
to the effect that participants should only offer considerations for or against
a policy that all can regard as relevant. On the account adopted earlier, a
norm is a regularity of behaviour amongst the members of a group such
that, as a matter of shared awareness, almost everyone complies with it,
almost everyone expects others to approve of compliance and/or disapprove
of non-compliance, and this expectation helps to keep the regularity in
place. Under the pressures of the acceptability game, it is inevitable that
participants will generally comply with the regularity of seeking out con-
siderations that all others, no matter what their interests or opinions, can
treat as relevant in collective decision-making; else they will have little
impact. And it is equally inevitable that participants will register this fact
in common awareness as well as registering at the same time that any failure
of compliance will attract the inhibiting derision or disapproval of others.
Those who present considerations that can only carry weight with a partic-
ular subgroup will be laughed out of court.
approach that distinguishes it usefully from alternatives. Although the participants in an acceptability
game are required to be willing to operate on equal terms with others – that is built into the game – the
considerations that are likely to be valorized there should be distinguished from the ‘public reasons’
that John Rawls (1999) associates with ‘reasonable political conceptions of justice’ (133). Unlike Rawls’s
public reasons, the considerations endorsed may be context-bound in three distinct senses. They may
pass muster only because of the history of the group: an example, used later in the text, might be the
consideration, licensed in a history of federation, that argues for the equal representation of states with
different population levels. Unlike Rawls’s reasons, they may be required to pass muster at any time
with current members, not to be such that they would pass muster under any feasible change in or of
the membership; this limitation is not objectionable insofar as a change of that type, for example a
change in degree of religious uniformity, would generate a revision of accepted considerations under
the discipline of an acceptability game. And unlike Rawls’s reasons, they may be specifically tied to
particular issues about whether to adopt this or that policy or to endorse this or that process of
decision-making; they may not generalize into any easily formulated principles. For a good account of
Rawls on public reason see Larmore (2003).
6
For a recent psychological argument that this is an important and productive discipline on human
reasoning see Mercier and Sperber (2011).
A dual-aspect model of democracy 255
This general, guiding norm – this norm of norms – does not require that
participants only offer considerations that have already been tried and
tested. It will prime them to search out considerations in any domain of
policy-making that people can be brought to endorse, given their existing
commitments. Suppose people are committed to the high-level principle of
equality in all possible domains. Or suppose, more plausibly, that they are
committed to equality in an area that is distinct from the domain under
discussion. On the basis of such prior commitments, the supporters of a
certain sort of policy in that domain may invoke the consideration of
equality, arguing for its relevance on the basis of the general commitment
to equality or the commitment to equality in a distinct but purportedly
parallel domain. They may or may not be successful in gaining such
acceptance for the relevance of the equality consideration in the domain
addressed, certainly not on the first round. But if the consideration really
does cohere well with the existing commitments of participants, then sooner
or later it is very likely to win acceptance as a relevant coin in the currency of
acceptability debates.
If people abide by the norm of norms in debates with one another – if
they invoke only considerations that may be expected to count as relevant
by all lights – then this should ensure the emergence of more specific norms
amongst them. Let participants be successful in getting the pertinence of
certain considerations accepted by all. That means that there will be
evidence to hand that makes it manifest to all that everyone accepts their
pertinence; manifest to all that this is manifest to all; and so on in the usual
hierarchy associated with common or mutual belief (Lewis 1969). Over
time, then, the considerations will come to constitute points of reference
that are manifestly pertinent or relevant, by everyone’s lights, to issues of
public policy.7 For any accepted consideration, C, it will be true, and true as
7
Does the dichotomy of acceptance and acceptability game neglect a third alternative in which it is
required that people all be able to see proposals as acceptable but not necessarily on the same grounds,
only on their own personal grounds? For a sophisticated development of such an approach see Gaus
(2011), and for a related approach that privileges religiously motivated, doctrinally specific reasons see
Stout (2004). My own view, which I cannot fully defend here, is that no such approach can point us to
a genuine alternative, in view of the following dilemma. If people do not have to defend the personal
grounds on which they require public policies to be acceptable – if, in a term introduced later in the
text, those personal grounds do not have to answer to concordant interests – then the proposal is likely
at best to support a version of the acceptance game, as participants seek to make compromises with one
another and avoid a destructive stalemate. If people do have to defend those grounds at a higher level,
however, on the basis of concordant interests – for example in the way that people might appeal to
religious freedom in defence of their own sectarian right of practice – then the proposal amounts to a
version of the acceptability game. For an illuminating discussion of this and related positions see the
unpublished paper by S. Macedo, ‘Why Public Reason?’
256 Democratic control
a matter of common awareness, that almost everyone treats it as a relevant
factor in political argument, almost everyone expects others to approve of
this treatment and to disapprove of a refusal to grant such treatment, and
almost everyone is motivated by this expectation to grant it this treatment
themselves.
Specific norms of argument and deliberation will emerge, on this
account, as an inevitable by-product of the successful, continuing use of
the acceptability game: that is, by robust adherence to the norm of norms
associated with the game. Participants will learn that as a matter of common
awareness this or that consideration is going to count as relevant – to pass
muster – in arguing for or against a policy. And with the approval or lack of
disapproval attending such a practice, they will learn as a matter of common
awareness that to reject the relevance of the consideration will earn the
inhibiting disapproval of others. Thus the consideration will be reinforced
by its own specific norm, coming to wear the tag: deny my relevance –
however you weight me – at your peril!
The considerations that an acceptability game is likely to valorize in this
way fall into two broad categories: considerations of convergent, and
concordant, interests. Convergent considerations will point participants
to universal benefits that all take to be relevant, or can be brought to see as
relevant, in matters of shared decision-making. Examples in the political
world would certainly include the benefit of equality or cohesion, pros-
perity or peace and, of course, the corresponding harms of inequality or
divisiveness, poverty or conflict. If you can show that only one of a
number of competing policies in any area promises to provide such a
benefit or avoid such a harm, then you will have registered something that
ought to carry weight on all sides, though perhaps heavier weight on some
sides than on others.
Concordant, as distinct from convergent, considerations point the
participants in an acceptability game to benefits that accrue only to this
or that individual or subgroup. Despite the partiality of their relevance to
people’s fortunes, these considerations will command a following on all
sides to the extent that everyone accepts that it is a matter of convergent
interest that the group as a whole should confer that benefit on the sort of
individual or subgroup favoured. No group can accept that the interest of
each in securing a certain advantage, regardless of the cost to others,
provides a relevant consideration in joint policy-making. But a group
may well accept, for example, that none of its members should have to
suffer the sort of inequality that majority voting would impose on the
vegetarian members in the dining-club example of the last chapter. More
A dual-aspect model of democracy 257
generally, the group may accept that members have a concordant interest
in being protected against any such inequality, or against any of a variety
of misfortunes. Thus a likely harm to one or another member on this front
may pass as a relevant consideration in joint policy-making. And some-
thing similar may hold with a suitable benefit. For example, the fact that a
benefit would help some while not doing any harm to others – the fact that
it would represent a Paretian improvement – may argue on all sides for a
policy that promises that benefit.8
Whether they reflect convergent or concordant interests, the more
specific norms of policy-making will direct participants in any acceptability
game to an evolving body of arguments that they can safely draw upon in
supporting this or that proposal. But they will also provide resources that
participants can exploit in supporting this or that process or procedure for
resolving the differences that remain in place after deliberation. Differences
will almost always remain in place, since the considerations presented on
different sides of a policy debate will rarely underpin unanimous agreement;
they will only reduce the number of candidates on the table. And so it will
be necessary at some point to bring the deliberative exercise to an end and
achieve resolution by recourse to some independent procedure: say, by
voting amongst the remaining alternatives, by selecting between them on
a lottery basis, or by referring the issue to an agreed umpire. Thus, as specific
norms of policy-making will bear on different policies, so they will also bear
on the suitability in a given case of resorting to one or another process of
final resolution.
The specific norms that emerge in any group will never constitute a
closed set, fixed once and for all (Young 1990, 2000; Honig 2001). They will
be subject to constant development, as deliberative innovators manage to
gain acceptance for novel sorts of argument, perhaps by extending the reach
of recognized arguments to new domains, perhaps by coming up with new
arguments that gain acceptance by others. Such innovations are likely to be
triggered by changes in the dispositions of the existing membership and, of
course, by changes of membership that occur at any time and across differ-
ent times. As new norms evolve in this way, others may decay and lose
potential, say because they are not acceptable to some members in the
changed society. But in general we would expect the norms that are given
8
Notice the difference between the following claims. One, the subgroup should not be expected to bear
a certain cost by criteria that no one in the society who is willing to live on equal terms with others
would reject. Two, the subgroup should not be expected to bear the cost by criteria that no one could
reasonably reject: by criteria that no one could reject while counting by some independent standards as
a reasonable person. It is the first claim that is relevant in this discussion, not the second.
258 Democratic control
countenance to increase in number and application, being laid down like a
sediment deposited by the flow of debate and exchange.
Returning to our earlier example, imagine the policy-making norms that
are likely to gain hold amongst the owners in a condominium of apart-
ments. Some of those norms will be established in advance under contracts
of purchase, but even if they are not pre-established, we can easily imagine
them emerging and multiplying as members of the condominium come
together to work out the terms on which they are to live together. As owners
talk, try out proposals and then vote on remaining candidates, they will
inevitably establish norms that rule their communal life together. These will
determine:
* The reasons why they should collectively organize the servicing of
11
For an illustration of such a breakdown in a small corporate body, amounting to what I describe as
collective akrasia, see Pettit (2003a).
12
As noted earlier, however, recent changes in broadcasting create a danger that those in different
political parties will only listen in on news and debates in their particular niche (Sunstein 2009).
A dual-aspect model of democracy 263
dramatically in the United States with the rejection of the idea that races
could be separate but equal. And that shift of interpretation released a cascade
of changes in the way things were done in public life.
As there are likely to be various norms of equality under the system of
influence described in the last chapter, so there are likely to be various norms
of freedom. The idea of having a system of popular influence that is indivi-
dualized, unconditioned and efficacious goes naturally with recognizing the
need for each to have a sphere of personal choice and with an interpretation of
the freedom that people should have in that sphere. As with equality, the
demands of freedom may be differently interpreted in different polities and
different periods, but they are likely in any society to enforce some boundary
between the domain where people ought to be able to make their own
decisions and the domain where government or other authorities can rule;
to establish some sense of what is required for people to be able to make their
own decisions in this way, enjoying a relative independence from others; and
to license this or that level of government resourcing and protection as a
means of establishing such independence for all.
A dispensation for ensuring a suitable degree of popular influence has to
assume institutional form at some point, with the introduction of measures
that provide for election, challenge and interrogation; that limit the author-
ity of elected officials and regulate the activities of private lobbies; and that
delineate possibilities of legitimate opposition and contestation. And as the
institutions required emerge and stabilize, they are bound to gain accep-
tance and to license associated norms of argument. Those norms will
support appeals to the principles and precautions that the institutions
embody, such as importance of the separation of powers, the independence
of the judiciary, the transparency of government decisions, and so on. The
precise institutions introduced in any society may vary from the institutions
introduced in others, of course, and as they vary, the corresponding
institution-specific norms will vary too.
Apart from the equality-based, freedom-based and institution-specific
examples just canvassed, a host of independent norms are going to emerge
in any society with growing convergence on the question of what the state
ought to do and with institutions that implement such convergence. The
business that government is charged with taking up will certainly include
the defence of the country, the identification of the basic liberties, the
enforcement of law and order, and the facilitation of industry, commerce
and employment. But in most societies it will also extend, under this or that
interpretation, to the provision of education for the young, the regulation of
various markets, the insurance of communities against catastrophe, and the
264 Democratic control
insurance of individuals against urgent or pressing need, medical, legal or
economic. The list is more or less open-ended.
I have been speaking about the variety of norms that we might expect to
develop in any society, particularly in any society with a system of popular
influence that is designed to be individualized, unconditioned and effica-
cious. There is a common character that we might expect such democratic
norms to display, as I have stressed, but the precise content they assume will
always depend on contingencies of local culture and development. But I
should not suggest that democracy will be free of faults and fetters. The
norms that emerge in any society, reflecting some perhaps questionable
beliefs and values, may often be deficient, judged from the point of view of
this or that conception of justice or legitimacy.
While the history of a democratic society will typically offer a rich and
appealing set of norms to invoke in public life, it can also saddle those who
live in the society with unwholesome constraints and unwelcome fetters.
Every developed democracy will have evolved along a certain trajectory,
being built upon a tradition of letting government take charge of such and
such matters and being associated with more or less settled institutions and
arrangements. This can put a society in a bind, locking members out of the
possibility of arguing for what by most of their shared norms of argument
would constitute an improvement. Thus, to give a simple example, it was
essential in the founding of the United States, and at the time of Australian
federation, that large and small states were given equal representation in the
Senate; this is unsurprising, since they were the parties responsible for
creating the new political order. This pattern of representation would be
unlikely to command much support in either country today, if the con-
stitution were being redrafted from scratch. The citizens of distinct states
within both the United States and Australia are geographically mobile and
probably do not identify as strongly with their local states as their prede-
cessors would have done. But nonetheless, there is no immediate prospect
of an alteration in either regime. The norm of equal state representation has
a pedigree that puts it beyond effective interrogation.
13
The role that norms play in democratic control, in the story developed here, overlaps in part, but only
in part, with the role given to people’s values in other theories. See Brettschneider (2007) for one such
approach and Eisgruber (2001, 2002) for another.
14
We saw earlier that in any domain of decision-making a system of popular influence will require the
generation of proposals on the one side and the testing of the proposals generated on the other; the
generation would guard against false negatives or shortfalls and the testing against false positives or
errors. The policy-condition and the process-condition required for giving norms a directive power,
promoting the goal of policy-making norm-compliance, both bear on the testing rather than the
generation required under such a generate-and-test programme. They would be satisfied by virtue of a
filtering or editorial procedure in which norm-incompatible policies and processes are taken out of
play and only norm-compatible candidates are allowed to survive.
266 Democratic control
influence of those members – and, as we may assume, their individualized,
unconditioned and efficacious influence – and that influence will have the
effect of imposing compliance with the norms that they endorse. The
members will disagree strongly on particular issues, of course, perhaps
dividing into bitterly opposed factions. But to the extent that their differ-
ences continue to be debated and resolved without offending against any
of the norms they hold in common, the members will have succeeded in
establishing a common norm-based order.
Suppose that one party wants to allow some of the apartments in the
building to be rented out to a nearby hotel and the other party is strongly
opposed to this development. And imagine that they make the decision in a
way that conforms to shared norms. Whichever party wins in that case, the
members of the condominium will have achieved an important goal
together: the compliance of their policies and policy-making with norms
that are shared amongst them. They may not come to a common mind on
the particular issue on hand but that will not be a problem so long as the
final decision is made on the basis of norm-compatible process. Suppose
that the numbers for and against the hotel proposal break even and the
decision is made on the basis of a coin-toss, where this process of decision-
making is itself consistent with the accepted norms. The result of such a
chance device will not undermine the common achievement of norm-
compliance. And neither would the victory of one or the other side under
any other accepted process – say, voting on the committee, or in a refer-
endum. One party will prevail on the issue, and perhaps on a range of
related issues, but at a deeper level it is the members of the condominium as
a whole that rule. Their common norms, not the norms of any particular
faction, shape the direction in which the organization moves.
As the norms emerging amongst the members of a condominium can
shape the policies and processes that prevail there, forcing whatever deci-
sions are made to conform to a template they impose, so we might expect
the norms of a political community to have the same directive impact on the
operation of government. The decisions taken by government may vary
enormously, depending on what particular norms have been endorsed, on
who happens to occupy elected or unelected office, and on what those
officials come to decide on specific issues. But if the emergent norms are
truly effective, as they ought to be in the presence of a suitable constitution
and citizenry, then they should put a directive and controlling stamp on
what is collectively done in the community. They should filter out offend-
ing policies and processes, making room only for modes of decision-
making, and actual decisions, that fit with accepted standards.
A dual-aspect model of democracy 267
The regulation its members impose on their condominium, or its citizens
on their government, can be described as deliberative regulation, since the
norms that they deploy all emerge as the by-product of deliberation within
the organization. But the deliberative regulation of the condominium or
government is not likely to come about as a result of every decision being
taken on an explicitly deliberative basis. Since the presence of public
deliberation on a number of occasions at a number of sites is enough to
generate the required norms, that is all it presupposes. And since it will
equally be enough that the norms have been generated and have come to be
generally accepted, even such episodic deliberation will be less and less
required as the condominium or society develops. The regulation will
operate, not on the basis of continuing, ubiquitous deliberation, but rather
as the product of institutional constraints that reflect deliberative norms.
The decisions the body eventually reaches will have to flow along so many
channels, skirt so many potential checks and obstacles, and avoid flounder-
ing on so many contestatory hazards that they are more or less bound to
satisfy the requirements of deliberatively generated norms.
How distinct is this ideal of deliberative regulation from that of deliberative
democracy? It is built out of the same observation, familiar in particular from
the work of Juergen Habermas (1984, 1989), that when people debate with
one another about what they should combine to do, then they have little
option but to seek out considerations that all can see as relevant to a joint
enterprise (Elster 1986). As we know, these may be convergent considerations
identifying benefits they can all share in, such as safety or prosperity or
cohesion. Or they may be concordant considerations licensing the provision
of benefits for a subgroup in a recognized sort of predicament, as when its
members suffer a deprivation that is seen as problematic on all sides, or are in a
position to improve their lot without doing any harm to others.
But while the approach taken here is deeply continuous with the spirit of
deliberative democracy, there is a break at two distinct levels. At a founda-
tional level, the approach is inspired by the republican insight that people
must share equally in their control of government if they are to avoid
domination, and not by a foundational commitment to the value of
deliberation as such (Cohen 1989).15 At the operational level, it is organized
around the idea that it is the deliberative regulation of public business – that
15
Jake Zuehl has persuaded me that in the later papers in Cohen (2009), the foundational commitment
to the value of actual deliberation gets to be qualified in a contractualist way, as the reasons that are
taken to count get to be indistinguishable from the Rawlsian public reasons mentioned in an earlier
footnote.
268 Democratic control
is, regulation by deliberatively tested norms – that is essential, not the
deliberative conduct of decision-making at every site and on every occasion.
The difference of perspective and practice between the two approaches
shows up in the fact that whereas dissensus always represents a second-best
for deliberative democrats, it is entirely acceptable, even desirable, within
the present approach. It is the experience of dissensus, after all, that drives
the different sides to identify common policy-making norms, as they try to
make sense of their respective views to one another. And it is those norms
that constrain the policies that they are willing to entertain and the processes
of decision-making they are ready to employ.
The fact that the deliberative regulation of collective decision-making
does not entail a great deal of deliberative conduct also has a further
implication. It means that the members of a deliberatively regulated
group, unlike the members of a group that conducts all its business in
explicit exercises of deliberation, may not always be conscious of the
deliberative regulation under which they operate. The impact of deliber-
ative norms may be elusive, indeed almost invisible, if the system is working
well. Assuming that it is working at its best, the institutions established will
not be called into question; the arguments put forward at various sites will
be weighed differently but admitted as relevant on all sides; the proposals
made by one or another side will be opposed by others but not condemned
as normatively objectionable; and the final resolution of differences will be
achieved under undisputed processes of decision-making. In short, the
conduct of public business will run along straight and even tracks without
any evidence of being directed onto those paths by a body of popular norms.
The direction of public business by popular norms will become salient
only when things do not go so well in one or another forum and participants
launch norm-based objections to the content of a policy or to the process by
which a policy is determined. But since participants will presumably want to
avoid such objections, they have an incentive to stay within limits that keep
them safe from such retort. And when they do genuinely stay within such
boundaries, the system will be working fairly well; it will be displaying a
high level of compliance with policy-making norms.
Although popular norms may not have a salient presence in a system that
is working well, however, this is not to say that they do not have an impact
there. The impact that they will have under such an ideal scenario, to return
to an idea already introduced in other contexts, will have a virtual or even
reserve character. To take the virtual case, it will be like the impact of the
cowboy who rides herd on his cattle. The cowboy may do little or nothing
by way of guiding the cattle; he lets them have their head, given that they are
A dual-aspect model of democracy 269
on the right path. But he clearly has a determining influence on the path
they take because he is ready to intervene effectively if any of them should
wander off the track. The same is going to be true of the influence that
policy-making norms have in the scenario presented. As policies are pro-
posed, defended and challenged, and as they are finally selected under one
or another process, there will be players within the system who are ready to
cry foul if a policy or process looks to be in breach of accepted norms. And
so even when those norms do not play an active role in the shaping of what
transpires, they can still have a powerful effect. They can ride herd, as it
were, on the process of policy-formation.
Consider the condominium example again. As insiders or outsiders
contemplate what happens in the day-to-day working of the organization,
the salient features will be the routines that are more or less unthinkingly
followed, the ways in which members come to differ on various aspects of
policy, the arguments that they each invoke in support of their views, and
the mechanical resolution to which most of their differences are eventually
subjected. Nowhere in this manifold of observations will there be positive
evidence of the role of the norms to which members subscribe. And yet
those norms will be in place to outlaw any norm-incompatible routines, and
to rule out any arguments – and any proposals based on arguments – that do
not satisfy the norms. The eye-catching exchanges will all take place within
a field of interaction that is shaped by the norms, but the impact of the
norms themselves may be close to invisible. Even when the waters of politics
run at their most turbulent within the condominium, the turbulence will be
consistent with the existence, beneath the surface, of a common stream of
influence and direction.
Dual-aspect democracy
We have argued that any regime of suitable popular influence will give a
powerful role to acceptability games; that such games will give rise to
widespread adherence to policy-making norms; that those norms will
tend to shape policy-making by putting norm-incompatible policies and
processes off the table; that they may operate to this effect without a great
deal of explicit deliberation taking place within the system; and that when
they operate well in achieving the effect, their impact will often be hard to
discern: the influence they support may often have a virtual or reserve
character.
The lesson of these observations is that a regime that is deliberatively
regulated is likely to operate in two time-scales, whether it materializes in a
270 Democratic control
private association like the condominium or in the political community at
large. It will require the short-haul, highly charged process of campaign
and election, proposal and counter-proposal, debate, division and contest-
ation. But it will achieve its signature impact in the long-haul process, as
silently as gravity, whereby participants are wittingly or unwittingly led to
establish only such policies and processes as conform to the norms of
argument and association that prevail amongst them. Over this long haul,
a deliberatively regulated politics will generate and regenerate a supply of
publicly valorized considerations. These will serve at any particular time to
keep an indefinite number of policies and processes off the table, render-
ing them unthinkable and invisible. And they will combine from time to
time to make certain existing policies or processes suddenly seem intoler-
able and in urgent need of repair.
This image of a deliberatively regulated regime constitutes what I
describe as a dual-aspect model of democracy. Apart from the fast democ-
racy of election and contestation that commands most attention amongst
political participants, observers and theorists, it directs us to a slow demo-
cracy that works under suitable forms of popular influence to impose a
distinctive stamp on what government, over the long haul, effects.
In the nature of the case, evidence that a political regime conforms to the
dual-aspect model, constituting a deliberatively regulated democracy, is
going to be hard to identify. The claim that the regime imposes deliberative
norms on government is going to be particularly difficult to establish, given
that such regulation will only be evident over the long haul. In order to
overcome this problem, and illustrate the operation of something like the
dual-aspect model, I must resort to history, in particular the sort of history
that looks at the longue durée.
I think the reality of slow democracy, and the viability of the dual-aspect
model, is well supported in the work of Oliver MacDonagh (1958, 1961,
1977) on the massive shifts in the activities of British government over the
half century or so after the debates about the Great Reform Bill of 1832. I
pick this example for two reasons. One, it is distant enough in time and
culture to allow us to get a clear view of what transpired. And two, it was a
period in which the rise of democracy meant that there was much to
achieve – not just, as is now often the case, much to maintain or recover –
in order to keep the government in line with popular norms. While the
franchise was not greatly extended in 1832, electoral democracy became
more and more established as a guiding ideal in nineteenth-century Britain
and later extensions of the franchise were heralded by an enormous rise in
public petitions and public demonstrations (Knights 2005).
A dual-aspect model of democracy 271
The nineteenth-century transformation took England, and Britain more
generally, from a state that had become minimal by any standards to a
regime in which government assumed responsibility for regulating a great
swathe of social behaviour, establishing offices that imposed strict inspec-
tion and control over such matters as the employment of children, the
treatment of women, the preparation of food and drugs, the operation of
the civil service and, relatedly, the conduct of affairs in mines, mills,
factories, ships, railways and public offices. I do not argue here that this
growth in the administrative responsibility of the state was desirable, though
to my eye much of it clearly was. Drawing on MacDonagh’s work, my only
aim is to use this shift to illustrate the depth at which policy-making norms
can operate in a broadly democratic context to impose a slow, long-haul
direction on government – and often, as in this case, on a deeply resistant,
even resentful administration.
The early nineteenth century in England was a period of enormous social
problems. These were occasioned by a number of connected factors: the
introduction of steam-based industrialization, the vast increase in popula-
tion, the capacity of people to move into new areas, even across oceans, and
the ensuing concentrations in industrial cities and towns; in the first quarter
of the nineteenth century, many towns in Yorkshire and Lancashire grew by
a factor of three or four. With these developments, a more or less pater-
nalistic tradition of management in agriculture and village industry gave
way to the ruthless discipline of Blake’s dark satanic mills. As Sir Walter
Scott wrote in 1820: ‘the manufacturers are transferred to great towns, where
a man may assemble five hundred workmen one week and dismiss them the
next, without having any further connexion with them than to receive a
week’s work for a week’s wages, nor any further solicitude about their future
fate than if they were so many old shuttles’.16
While the problems that arose in the new industrial world were daunting
and varied, the doctrine of laissez-faire individualism that prevailed in
official circles might well have left them unaddressed. As democratization
increased, however, the pressures brought to bear on government pushed it
slowly and reluctantly into becoming something unimagined at the begin-
ning. In MacDonagh’s (1958: 57) words, they occasioned a ‘transformation,
scarcely glimpsed till it was well secured, of the operations and functions of
government’.
The transformation was effected now in the mines, now in the factories,
now in ocean-going ships, having an impact that affected the lives of men,
16
Quoted by MacDonagh (1977: 2).
272 Democratic control
women and children across the society. In each case, the transformation was
prompted by the same factors and developed along the same lines.
The factors that drove the changes, according to MacDonagh (1958: 57–8),
were ‘the increasing sensitivity of politics to public pressures’ that we
would expect with growing democratization and ‘the widespread and ever-
growing influence of humanitarian sentiment and of stricter views of
sexual morality’. The humanitarianism was particularly important, bub-
bling up in ‘the raw and immediate reactions of a variety of ordinary and
thoroughly representative people’, for it managed to overcome the resis-
tance of laissez-faire doctrine and commercial self-interest: ‘the general
level of compassion in contemporary England overswept policy and
commerce’ (MacDonagh 1961: 330). This was not just a dumb, pre-
conceptual sort of compassion; it was organized around concepts and
norms that had deep roots in the political culture. Many of the abuses
condemned were cast as abuses against freedom, for example, and as
analogues of enslavement. In a famous newspaper letter of 1830, a
reformer, Richard Oastler, could write: ‘Thousands of our fellow-
creatures and fellow-subjects, both male and female, the miserable inhabi-
tants of a Yorkshire town . . . are this very moment existing in a state of
slavery, more horrid than are the victims of that hellish system colonial
slavery. These innocent creatures drawl out, unpitied, their short but
miserable existence.’17
The different changes that occurred in nineteenth-century England
were generally prompted, then, by a democratically empowered humani-
tarianism. But not only did the changes have a common source, according
to MacDonagh, they also evolved under a similar dynamic and in parallel
stages.
In each case the change began with the revelation by newspapers or
reform organizations of just how scandalous conditions were in this or that
domain; in each case this scandal led to a degree of public outrage amongst
the population at large; and in each case that outrage prompted a reaction
from government, in particular an initiative designed to put things right.
‘Once it was publicized sufficiently that, say, women on their hands and
knees dragged trucks of coal through subterranean tunnels, or that emi-
grants had starved to death at sea or that children had been mutilated by
unfenced machinery, these evils became “intolerable”; and throughout and
even before the Victorian years “intolerability” was the master card’
(MacDonagh 1958: 58).
17
The letter is to the Leeds Mercury, 16 October 1830; see www.makingthemodernworld.org.uk.
A dual-aspect model of democracy 273
The dynamic that called for such reform never played itself out in a single
round. Almost invariably it transpired some years after the first initiative
that the law had been ineffective and that the scandal remained. And with
that second revelation the dynamic ran its course again, leading to the
appointment of executive inspectors and officers who were charged with
putting the law into effect. Nor was that all. The reports of these admin-
istrators fuelled yet further developments, as it became clear that problems
were proving recalcitrant, and this third iteration of the dynamic generated
a progressively more professional and better-organized public service. The
culmination of such transformations across a variety of domains was the
slow emergence of a new and characteristically modern sort of state.
The impact that popular pressure can give to policy-making norms is well
illustrated, I believe, in this narrative. The norms had a background
presence in people’s attitudes, which survived ideological and party differ-
ences. And they had a slow, relentless effect on how government operated,
pushing it inexorably towards a certain destination. The direction in which
a gradually democratizing government was pushed in Victorian England is
particularly salient to us, given the contrast, at least in the developed world,
between those times and ours. But I believe that it illustrates the sort of
purpose that democracy can serve everywhere in imposing accepted norms
on government. It shows that the dual-aspect model described here is not
necessarily a pipedream.
No illustration of the model is going to be ideal, of course, and there are a
number of particularities about this example that we should note. One is
that while it exemplifies the role of accepted norms in putting certain issues
on the agenda of government and in prompting improvements to a clearly
imperfect practice in that domain, it does not illustrate the less salient role
of norms – so important in any advanced democracy – in maintaining
improvements already in place. A second is that while it exemplifies the role
of accepted norms in putting certain policies off the table – those, for
example, that would allow for the employment of children in mines – it
does not illustrate their equally important role in putting certain processes
or procedures of decision-making off the table. And a third is that it does
not make clear that the satisfaction of humanitarian norms achieved in the
long-haul development described was a by-product of debates that were
focused on rather more specific, short-haul policies. Those norms had a
slowly mounting impact, not because humanitarian norm-compliance was
a target at which anyone aimed, but because it was a common, barely
recognized constraint on the concessions and adjustments that politicians
were forced to make under the pressures of day-to-day politics.
274 Democratic control
Notwithstanding these features, the MacDonagh studies serve us well in
illustrating how popular pressures can empower norms, impose them on
government and make them into a more or less fixed feature of how things
get to be done. They display the workings of a more or less deliberatively
regulated democracy, as the various individuals and bodies involved in its
short-haul operations are pushed under the pressure of popular influence to
adopt a discernible, long-haul direction.
The sort of thesis that MacDonagh defends is borne out in other
contexts too. Thus, to mention one important example, William
Eskridge and John Ferejohn (2010) argue in a detailed examination of
cases that popular pressure in the United States has led to the statutory
implementation and effective entrenchment of norms of equal citizenship,
market openness and personal security. In an uncanny parallel to
MacDonagh’s narrative, they describe a process in which a social move-
ment or other pressure creates a demand for state action; publicly sup-
ported legislation generates a statute embodying a new norm; the statute is
administered and expanded with feedback and pushback from various
sectors of the community; the norm is revisited and reaffirmed by the
legislature in face of opposition; and this is followed by further admini-
strative elaboration, further feedback and pushback, and further legislative
revision (Eskridge and Ferejohn 2010: 19–20). Like MacDonagh, they
illustrate the slow emergence and impact of popular norms that I see as
evidence for what democracy is capable of achieving over the long haul in
imposing a direction on government.
Our discussion points us towards a popular purpose or direction that
might be imposed on government under the system of popular influence
described in the last chapter. That purpose is compliance with policy-
making norms, whether they be norms that put policies or processes off
the table, norms that are associated with the agenda of government, the
status of citizens or the conduct of government, or norms that are encoded
in particular institutions and in laws or conventions that have a less formal
existence amongst members of the community. That purpose can be
systematically promoted, so it appears, as the long-term effect of short-
term attempts to exercise influence within the constraints imposed by an
acceptability game.
With this image of dual-aspect democracy in place, we can turn
finally to considering its attractions. I promised at the end of
Section 1 that the dual-aspect model would combine the appeal of
each of the existing models of popular control: in the first of these,
government is under the intentional control of the people and in the
A dual-aspect model of democracy 275
other under their non-intentional control. It is time now to make good
on that commitment.
water;
* that they each want the group to adopt that strategy and achieve that
result;
* that they are each disposed to play their part so long as others join them;
and
* that others are going to join anyone who takes the initiative.
unilaterally, and if anyone does, then the pattern is likely to be quickly restored. The same is true, I
believe, of the pattern of norm-satisfaction that a deliberatively regulated, dual-aspect democracy
would generate. No one would have an incentive to depart from it unilaterally, at least given the
repercussions that this is likely to have on others. And in the event of a departure, those repercussions
would be likely to restore the pattern.
19
There is a large literature on what it is for people to cooperate in forming such a joint intention and
pursuing such a joint action. See for example Bratman (1987); Searle (1995); Tuomela (1995); Gilbert
(2001). My own preference follows broadly the lines taken by Bratman; see also Pettit and Schweikard
(2006); List and Pettit (2011).
20
For a paper that outlines the form that such a model might take see Bratman (2004).
278 Democratic control
so. They generate the effect by each looking after their own efforts: they
each seek to support their own arguments in accepted terms, and they each
require others to do the same. And they each have a reason to welcome that
effect, given the desire at the origin of those efforts. But the effect itself
eventuates by a hand that is likely to be hidden from them; it materializes
behind their backs.
The critique of the intentional-control model combines with the defence
of the dual-aspect model to suggest that the promotion of policy-making
norm-satisfaction may be possible only on the basis of the invisible-hand
mechanism described. In Jon Elster’s (1979, 1983) phrase, such norm-
satisfaction may constitute an essential by-product. It may be a result that
can be reliably secured only as a side-effect of people’s pursuing some other
aim. Let people explicitly try to agree in identifying and implementing
common norms and they are likely to recognize the costs that the satisfac-
tion of appropriate norms can impose on them and theirs. And as they
recognize those costs, high virtue is liable to fail them and leave them at
irreconcilable loggerheads with one another.21 The only dependable path to
establishing a regime of norm-satisfaction may be the one charted in the
dual-aspect model.
In the account emerging from these observations, the participants in a
dual-aspect democracy will struggle with one another, and perhaps divide
quite antagonistically, over particular matters of policy. But however adver-
sarial their struggle, they will honour the demands of the acceptability game,
and generate norms that have a double effect of cutting down the policies
treated as potential candidates for implementation and of cutting down the
processes to be employed for resolving disputes over candidate policies. This
double impact means that the policies generated ought to make a plausible
claim to be in the common or public interest, where that interest is under-
stood in a post-social, non-corporate manner. Plausibly, indeed, the policies
might even begin to answer to the demands of justice, as those are under-
stood under republican or related conceptions. Being policies supported by
considerations acceptable on all sides – supported in their own right and via
the support given to the processes under which they are selected – they
promise not to be too far out of kilter with what might be expected to
promote justice.
21
There is every reason to think, of course, that as people pursue this norm-identifying exercise under an
acceptability regime, they will establish higher-order norms amongst themselves. The lesson follows
by an argument that parallels Lewis Carroll’s argument in his classic paper on Achilles and the
Tortoise (1895).
A dual-aspect model of democracy 279
The citizens who play their part under the dual-aspect model will each
have their own particular conceptions of justice, of course, differing on at
least some of the policies that they think justice requires. And so in making
proposals, offering objections and generally contesting how things are
evolving under government, they will be guided by those conceptions,
looking for commonly acceptable considerations by which they can hope
to draw others to their side. While no side can expect a full victory in a
society where plurality rules – the republican side included – they may each
still expect that the policies and processes that get established are not going
to offend too radically against their more central principles. And they may
each even hope that as debates and decisions evolve, the most compelling
conception of justice – their own, as they will each take it to be – will come
eventually to prevail.
This is an optimistic vision of how things can transpire under a dual-
aspect democracy and I hasten to add that it will only materialize under
quite demanding conditions. It is a commonplace in economics that few
markets live up to the demanding conditions laid out in textbooks: most are
affected by a variety of economic distortions, ranging from restrictions on
entry to natural monopolies to collusion amongst producers. And it is
equally a commonplace that competitive pricing will not generally materi-
alize in the presence of such distortions. It is important to recognize that a
parallel observation holds in the democratic case. The dual-aspect model of
democracy is only going to work when there is a properly individualized,
unconditioned and efficacious system of popular influence, and when the
rules of the acceptability game have a sufficient presence to ensure the
deliberative regulation of public business. To the extent that distortions
warp the system of popular influence and exchange, there will be a shortfall
from the ideal we have been describing. And the greater the distortions,
plausibly, the larger that shortfall will be.
This observation serves to underline the critical edge of the model
developed here. The dual-aspect model offers us a picture of a system in
which the demos, or ‘people’, enjoy kratos, or ‘control’, over government.
But the model is only going to materialize under the sorts of conditions at
which we have been gesturing in this chapter and the last. Let those
conditions fail and there will be democratic distortions that parallel the
market distortions of which economists speak. While the conditions will
often fail to be satisfied, however – while they will call for revision to existing
practices – the prospect of their fulfilment is not a utopian pipedream. The
dual-aspect model supports a programme of reform and renovation that is
well within the bounds of feasible achievement.
280 Democratic control
24
For an account of the emergence of the idea of the state, in an early version of our current conception,
see Brett (2011). On the development of the idea of the state see Skinner (2009).
288 Democratic control
Holy Roman Emperor; the assumption had been that the Emperor’s writ
did not run within cities that were governed by princes (Canning 1983; see
too Ryan 1999). In the city republic, Bartolus said, the people is a
corporate entity, a legal person, and for all practical purposes a prince;
the people, in his memorable phrase, is sibi princeps, ‘a prince unto itself’
(Woolf 1913: 155–60).25 But who exactly does the word ‘people’ or populus
refer to? Bartolus’s answer is, the civitas. In giving this answer, he gave life
to the ambiguity that haunts us still. For the term civitas may refer either
to the constituting or to the constituted people. It may direct us to the
citizenry that rule in a popular regime – in a regime where, in Bartolus’s
phrase, things are done secundum vices et secundum circulum: ‘by repre-
sentation and rotation’ (Woolf 1913: 180). Or it may refer us to the state
that the incorporating citizenry establish when they operate in that
manner. The civitas as citizenry is the ‘constituting people’; the civitas as
state is the ‘constituted people’.
26
The discussion that follows is germane to many debates. It is relevant, for example, to the debate
between the view, associated with Hans Kelsen, that prioritizes constituted power in conceptualizing
the state and the view, associated with Hannah Arendt, that puts much greater emphasis on the
constituting power of the people. Hans Lindahl (2007: Section 1) offers a very illuminating account of
the divergence on this issue. It should be clear that my sympathies lie broadly on the side that he
associated with Arendt.
27
This represents a perhaps surprising point of continuity with Negri (1999), Hardt and Negri (2000)
and Kalyvas (2005). For an interesting, broadly congenial view of the people as a constitutionally
shaped process see Espejo (2011).
290 Democratic control
views and its own resources. But will it be a sovereign on the internal or
domestic front, vis-à-vis its own citizens? Yes, in the sense that it can be
identified as the source of the laws imposed, to invoke Bodin’s founding
conception of a sovereign, and indeed as an entity that is not itself subject to
the laws. No, in any sense that might reduce the importance of the
constituting or civic people.28 In the dual-aspect model, the corporate or
constituted people is an agent that emerges under the norm-imposing
control of its constituting members, not an entity that can push back against
those very individuals; it is dependent on them for its continued existence
and for the manner of its operation. Again, this observation marks a contrast
with Rousseau, for whom the constituted people – in his story, the popular
assembly – has absolute power over the individual citizens, considered as a
plurality. Each citizen may be independent of others in the Rousseauvian
theory, but they are all required to be ‘excessively dependent on the City’,
where the City is just the people in assembly, the people qua incorporated
(Rousseau 1997: ii.12.3).29
28
The ambiguity was used by many, of course, to identify the sovereignty of the people with the
sovereignty of the state, thereby depriving the idea of popular sovereignty of any bite it might have
had. Thus Hegel (1991: 318) writes that ‘sovereignty lies with the people, but only if we are speaking of
the whole’ – that is, as he goes on to clarify, only if we are speaking of the sovereignty that ‘belongs to
the state’. In tones that hark back to Hobbes, he says that apart from the state ‘the people is a formless
mass’ (Hegel 1991: 319).
29
My view is consistent, however, with that which Nadia Urbinati (2006: 223) expresses as follows:
‘Popular sovereignty, understood as an as if regulating principle guiding citizens’ political judge-
ment and action, is a central motor for democratizing representation.’
The people, the state and the constitution 291
is supposed to be a will that is present in each of the members. It is meant
to be non-dominating, not because it is controlled by suitable norms, but
because it is part of the person’s own will.
30
Akhil Amar (1988) argues that the current US Constitution might be constitutionally amended – say,
by a straight majoritarian vote – and yet not in accordance with Article 5; his surprising claim is that
that article does not identify the only constitutional ways of changing the Constitution. The
motivation for his argument is removed in the viewpoint adopted here, for it would not have to
represent a major democratic crisis for the constituting people of the country to decide unconstitu-
tionally against sticking with the existing Constitution. Rejecting the Constitution in that way would
change the identity of the constituted people, but not the identity of the constituting people. And so
there is no logical difficulty in imagining that one and the same people – one and the same
constituting people – might reconstitute themselves under a new arrangement.
31
In Locke’s view, however, the people – in our sense, the constituting people – play just a remote
standby role, as noted earlier, being ready to intervene only at the extreme where things go quite bad.
The interventions he envisages ‘happen not upon every little mismanagement in public affairs’, he
says; they are likely to be triggered only by ‘a long train of abuses, prevarications and artifices’ (Locke
1960: ii.225).
Conclusion. The argument, in summary
The argument of this book has taken us over a wide terrain, introducing the
republican perspective, traditional and contemporary; presenting the ideal
of freedom that lies at its core; sketching a theory and model of the social
justice that this ideal would support; defending a matching, republican
theory of political legitimacy; and then outlining a model of the democratic
institutions that might be thought to satisfy that theory. In conclusion,
I think the best thing I can do is to provide a summary of the claims
maintained in the development of the argument. While the summary is
inevitably sketchy and inexact, I hope that it will help to facilitate readers in
finding their way through a book that I wanted to make shorter and simpler
than it has turned out to be.
311
312 References
Bell, D. (2010). China’s New Confucianism: Politics and Everyday Life in a Changing
Society. Princeton University Press.
Bellamy, R. (1999). Liberalism and Pluralism: Towards a Politics of Compromise.
London, Routledge.
(2007). Political Constitutionalism: A Republican Defense of the Constitutionality
of Democracy. Cambridge University Press.
Benhabib, S. (1996). ‘Towards a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy’ in
Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, ed.
S. Benhabib. Princeton University Press.
Bentham, J. (1843). ‘Anarchical Fallacies’ in The Works of Jeremy Bentham, ed.
J. Bowring. Edinburgh, W. Tait, vol. ii.
Berlin, I. (1969). Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford University Press.
Besold, C. (1618). Politicorum Libri duo. Frankfurt, J. A. Cellii.
Besson, S. and J. L. Marti (2008). Law and Republicanism. Oxford University
Press.
Bodin, J. (1967). Six Books of the Commonwealth, ed. M. J. Tooley. Oxford, Blackwell.
Bohman, J. (2007). Democracy Across Borders: From Demos to Demoi. Cambridge,
MA, MIT Press.
Braithwaite, J. (1997). ‘On Speaking Softly and Carrying Big Sticks: Neglected
Dimensions of a Republican Separation of Powers’. University of Toronto Law
Journal 47: 305–61.
(2002). Restorative Justice and Responsive Regulation. New York, Oxford University
Press.
Braithwaite, J., H. Charlesworth and A. Soares (2012). Networked Governance of
Freedom and Tyranny: Peace in East Timor. Canberra, ANU Press.
Braithwaite, J. and P. Pettit (1990). Not Just Deserts: A Republican Theory of
Criminal Justice. Oxford University Press.
Bramhall, J. (1658). ‘The Catching of Leviathan or the Great Whale’ in Castigations
of Mr Hobbes . . . Concerning Liberty and Universal Necessity, J. Bramhall.
London, John Crooke.
Bratman, M. (1987). Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason. Cambridge, MA, Harvard
University Press.
(2004). ‘Shared Valuing and Frameworks for Practical Reasoning’ in Reason and
Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz, ed. J. Wallace, P. Pettit,
S. Scheffler and M. Smith. Oxford University Press, pp. 1–27.
(2007). Structures of Agency. New York, Oxford University Press.
Brennan, G. and A. Hamlin (1995). ‘Economizing on Virtue’. Constitutional
Political Economy 6: 35–6.
Brennan, G. and L. Lomasky (1993). Democracy and Decision: The Pure Theory of
Electoral Preference. Oxford University Press.
(2006). ‘Against Reviving Republicanism’. Politics, Philosophy and Economics 5:
221–52.
Brennan, G. and P. Pettit (2004). The Economy of Esteem: An Essay on Civil and
Political Society. Oxford University Press.
Brennan, J. (2011). The Ethics of Voting. Princeton University Press.
References 313
Brett, A. S. (2011). Changes of State: Nature and the Limits of the City in Early
Modern Natural Law. Princeton University Press.
Brettschneider, C. (2007). Democratic Rights: The Substance of Self-Government.
Princeton University Press.
Brugger, W. (1999). Republican Theory in Political Thought: Virtuous or Virtual?
New York, Macmillan.
Buchanan, A. (2002). ‘Political Legitimacy and Democracy’. Ethics 112: 689–719.
(2004). Justice, Legitimacy and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for
International Law. Oxford University Press.
Burke, E. (1999). ‘Speech to the Electors of Bristol’ in Select Works of Edmund
Burke. Indianapolis, Liberty Fund.
Burnheim, J. (1985). Is Democracy Possible? Cambridge, Polity Press.
Cabot, V. (1751). ‘Quod Non Omnis Status Reipublicae Simplex Est’ in Novus
Thesaurus Juirs Civilis et Canonici. G. Meerman. Amsterdam, Pieter de Hondt.
2: 622–3.
Canning, J. P. (1983). ‘Ideas of the State in Thirteenth and Fourteenth Century
Commentators on the Roman Law’. Transactions of the Royal Historical Society
33: 1–27.
Carroll, L. (1895). ‘What the Tortoise said to Achilles’. Mind 4: 278–80.
Carter, I. (1999). A Measure of Freedom. Oxford University Press.
(2008). ‘How are Power and Unfreedom Related?’ in Republicanism and Political
Theory, ed. C. Laborde and J. Maynor. Oxford, Blackwell.
Christiano, T. (2008). The Constitution of Equality: Democratic Authority and its
Limits. Oxford University Press.
Christman, J. (2009). The Politics of Persons: Individual Autonomy and Socio-
historical Selves. Cambridge University Press.
Cicero, M. T. (1998). The Republic and the Laws. Oxford University Press.
Clark, A. (1997). Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World Together Again.
Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.
Cohen, G. A. (1979). ‘Capitalism, Freedom and the Proletariat’ in The Idea of
Freedom, ed. A. Ryan. Oxford University Press.
(1993). ‘Equality of What? On Welfare, Goods, and Capabilities’ in The Quality
of Life, ed. M. C. Nussbaum and A. Sen. Oxford University Press, pp. 9–29.
(2008). Rescuing Justice and Equality. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
Cohen, J. (1989). ‘Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy’ in The Good Polity, ed.
A. Hamlin and P. Pettit. Oxford, Blackwell, pp. 17–34.
(2004). ‘Minimalism About Human Rights: The Most We Can Hope For’.
Journal of Political Philosophy 12: 190–213.
(2009). Philosophy, Politics, Democracy. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
(2010). Rousseau: A Free Community of Equals. Oxford University Press.
Cohen, M. (1933). ‘The Basis of Contract’. Harvard Law Review 4: 553–92.
Coleman, J. (1974). Power and the Structure of Society. New York, Norton.
(1990). ‘The Emergence of Norms’ in Social Institutions: Their Emergence,
Maintenance, and Effects, ed. M. Hechter, K.-D. Opp and R. Wippler,
Berlin, de Gruyter, pp. 35–59.
314 References
Connolly, W. E. (1969). The Bias of Pluralism. New York, Atherton.
(1993). The Terms of Political Discourse. Oxford, Blackwell.
Constant, B. (1988). Constant: Political Writings. Cambridge University Press.
(2003). Principles of Politics Applicable to All Governments. Indianapolis, Liberty
Fund.
Cornish, W. R. and G. d. N. Clark (1989). Law and Society in England 1750–1950.
London, Sweet and Maxwell.
Costa, M. V. (2007). ‘Freedom as Non-Domination, Normativity and
Indeterminacy’. Journal of Value Inquiry 41: 291–307.
Dagger, R. (1997). Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liberalism.
Oxford University Press.
Demosthenes (1939). Against Meidias, trans. A. T. Murray. London, Heinemann.
Dennett, D. C. (1992). Consciousness Explained. New York, Penguin.
(1996). Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life. New York,
Simon and Schuster.
Dietrich, F. and C. List (2007). ‘Arrow’s Theorem in Judgment Aggregation’.
Social Choice and Welfare 29: 19–33.
(2008). ‘A Liberal Paradox for Judgment Aggregation’. Social Choice and Welfare
31: 59–78.
Dowlen, O. (2008). The Political Potential of Sortition. Exeter, Imprint Academic.
Dryzek, J. (2003). Deliberative Democracy and Beyond: Liberals, Critics, Contestations.
Oxford University Press.
Duff, R. A. (2001). Punishment, Communication, and Community. Oxford University
Press.
Dunn, J. (2005). Democracy: A History. New York, Atlantic Monthly Press.
Dworkin, G. (1988). The Theory and Practice of Autonomy. Cambridge University
Press.
Dworkin, R. (1978). Taking Rights Seriously. London, Duckworth.
(1986). Law’s Empire. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
(2000). Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality. Cambridge, MA,
Harvard University Press.
(2006). Is Democracy Possible Here? Principles for a New Political Debate.
Princeton University Press.
(2011). Justice for Hedgehogs. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
Eisgruber, C. L. (2001). Constitutional Self-Government. Cambridge, MA, Harvard
University Press.
(2002). ‘Constitutional Self-Government and Judicial Review: A Reply to Five
Critics’. University of San Francisco Law Review 37: 115–90.
Elster, J. (1979). Ulysses and the Sirens. Cambridge University Press.
(1983). Sour Grapes. Cambridge University Press.
(1986). ‘The Market and the Forum: Three Varieties of Political Theory’ in
Foundations of Social Choice Theory, ed. J. Elser and A. Hillard. Cambridge
University Press.
(1999). Alchemies of the Mind: Rationality and the Emotions. Cambridge University
Press.
References 315
Ely, J. H. (1981). Democracy and Distrust: A Theory of Judicial Review. Cambridge,
MA, Harvard University Press.
Eskridge, W. N., Jr and J. Ferejohn (2010). A Republic of Statutes: The New
American Constitution. New Haven, CT, Yale University Press.
Espejo, P. O. (2011). The Time of Popular Sovereignty: Process and the Democratic
State. University Park, Pennsylvania State University Press.
Estlund, D. (2007). Democratic Authority: A Philosophical Framework. Princeton
University Press.
Ferguson, A. (1767). An Essay on the History of Civil Society. Edinburgh, Millar and
Caddel (reprinted New York, Garland, 1971).
Fishkin, J. (1991). Democracy and Deliberation: New Directions for Democratic
Reform. New Haven, CT, Yale University Press.
(1997). The Voice of the People: Public Opinion and Democracy. New Haven, CT,
Yale University Press.
Fleurbaey, M. (2008). Fairness, Responsibility and Welfare. Oxford University Press.
Forst, R. (2002). Contexts of Justice: Political Philosophy beyond Liberalism and
Communitarianism. Berkeley, University of California Press.
Frankfurt, H. (1969). ‘Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility’. Journal of
Philosophy 66: 829–39.
(1987). ‘Equality as a Moral Ideal’. Ethics 98: 21–43.
(1988). The Importance of What We Care About. Cambridge University Press.
Franklin, J. (1991). ‘Sovereignty and the Mixed Constitution: Bodin and his Critics’
in The Cambridge History of Political Thought 1450–1700, ed. J. H. Burns and
M. Goldie. Cambridge University Press.
Fukuyama, F. (2011). The Origins of Political Order: From Prehuman Times to the
French Revolution. New York, Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
Fuller, L. L. (1971). The Morality of Law. New Haven, CT, Yale University Press.
Garsten, B. (2006). Saving Persuasion: A Defense of Rhetoric and Judgment.
Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
Gaus, G. (1983). The Modern Liberal Theory of Man. London, Croom Helm.
(2011). The Order of Public Reason: A Theory of Freedom and Morality in a Diverse
and Bounded World. Cambridge University Press.
Gauthier, D. (1986). Morals by Agreement. Oxford University Press.
Geuss, R. (1981). The Idea of Critical Theory. Cambridge University Press.
Gilbert, M. (2001). ‘Collective Preferences, Obligations, and Rational Choice’.
Economics and Philosophy 17: 109–20.
(2006). A Theory of Political Obligation. Oxford University Press.
Gilovich, T., D. Griffin and D. Kahneman, eds. (2002). Heuristics and Biases: The
Psychology of Intuitive Judgment. Cambridge University Press.
Goldberg, J. (2005–6). ‘The Constitutional Status of Tort Law: Due Process
and the Right to a Law for the Redress of Wrongs’. Yale Law Journal 115:
524–627.
Goldman, A. (1999). ‘Why Citizens Should Vote: A Causal Responsibility
Approach’. Social Philosophy and Policy 16: 201–17.
Goldsworthy, J. (1999). The Sovereignty of Parliament. Oxford University Press.
316 References
Goodin, R. E. (1996). ‘Institutionalizing the Public Interest: The Defense of
Deadlock and Beyond’. American Political Science Review 90: 331–43.
Goodin, R. E. and F. Jackson (2007). ‘Freedom from Fear’. Philosophy and Public
Affairs 35: 249–65.
Green, J. E. (2004). ‘Apathy: The Democratic Disease’. Philosophy and Social Criticism
30: 745–68.
Guerrero, A. (2010). ‘The Paradox of Voting and the Ethics of Political
Representation’. Philosophy & Public Affairs 38: 272–306.
Guinier, L. (1994). Tyranny of the Majority: Fundamental Fairness in Representative
Democracy. New York, The Free Press.
Gutmann, A. and D. Thompson (1996). Democracy and Disagreement. Cambridge,
MA, Harvard University Press.
Gwyn, W. B. (1965). The Meaning of the Separation of Powers. Nijhoff, The Hague.
Habermas, J. (1984–9). A Theory of Communicative Action. Cambridge, Polity
Press, vols. i and ii.
(1994). ‘Three Normative Models of Democracy’. Constellations 1: 1–10.
(1995). Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and
Democracy. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.
Hansen, M. H. (1991). The Athenian Democracy in the Age of Demosthenes. Oxford,
Blackwell.
Hardt, M. and A. Negri (2000). Empire. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
Harman, G. (1986). Change in View. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.
Harrington, J. (1992). The Commonwealth of Oceana and a System of Politics.
Cambridge University Press.
Hart, H. L. A. (1955). ‘Are There Any Natural Rights?’ Philosophical Review 64: 175–91.
(1961). The Concept of Law. Oxford University Press.
(1973). ‘Rawls on Liberty and its Priority’. University of Chicago Law Review 40:
534–55.
Hayek, F. A. (1988). The Fatal Conceit: The Errors of Socialism. University of
Chicago Press.
Hayward, C. (2011). ‘What Can Political Freedom Mean in a Multicultural
Democracy? On Deliberation, Difference and Democratic Government’.
Political Theory 39: 468–97.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1991). Elements of the Philosophy of Right, ed. A. W. Wood.
Cambridge University Press.
Held, D. (2006). Models of Democracy, 3rd edn. Cambridge, Polity.
Herreros, F. (2006). ‘Screening Before Sanctioning: Elections and the Republican
Tradition’. European Journal of Political Theory 5: 415–35.
Hill, L. (2000). ‘Compulsory Voting, Political Shyness and Welfare Outcomes’.
Journal of Sociology 36: 30–49.
Hobbes, T. (1994a). Human Nature and De Corpore Politico: The Elements of Law,
Natural and Politic. Oxford University Press.
(1994b). Leviathan, ed. E. Curley. Indianapolis, Hackett.
(1998). On the Citizen, ed. and trans. R. Tuck and M. Silverthorne. Cambridge
University Press.
References 317
Hobbes, T. and J. Bramhall (1999). Hobbes and Bramhall on Freedom and Necessity,
ed. Vere Chappell. Cambridge University Press.
Hoekstra, K. (2001). ‘Tyrannus Rex vs. Leviathan’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 82:
420–46.
(2006). ‘A Lion in the House: Hobbes and Democracy’ in Rethinking the
Foundations of Modern Political Thought, ed. A. S. Brett and J. Tully.
Cambridge University Press.
Holmes, S. (1995). Passions and Constraint: On the Theory of Liberal Democracy.
University of Chicago Press.
Honig, B. (2001). Democracy and the Foreigner. Princeton University Press.
Honneth, A. (1996). The Struggle for Recognition. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.
Honohan, I. (2002). Civic Republicanism. London, Routledge.
Honohan, I. and J. Jennings, eds. (2006). Republicanism in Theory and Practice.
London, Routledge.
Hont, I. (1995). ‘The Permanent Crisis of a Divided Mankind: “Contemporary
Crisis of the National State” in Historical Perspective’ in The Contemporary
Crisis of the Nation State?, ed. J. Dunn. Oxford, Blackwell, pp. 166–231.
Hume, D. (1875). Of the Independence of Parliament. Hume’s Philosophical Works,
ed. T. H. Green and T. H. Grose. London, vol. iii.
(1994). Political Essays. Cambridge University Press.
Husak, D. (2008). Overcriminalization. Oxford University Press.
Jackson, F. (1987). ‘Group Morality’ in Metaphysics and Morality: Essays in Honour
of J. J. C. Smart, ed. P. Pettit, R. Sylvan and J. Norman. Oxford, Blackwell,
pp. 91–110.
James, S. (1997). Passion and Action: The Emotions in Seventeenth-Century
Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
Joyce, J. M. (1999). The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory. Cambridge
University Press.
Kalyvas, A. (2005). ‘Popular Sovereignty, Democracy and the Constituent Power’.
Constellations 12: 223–44.
Kalyvas, A. and I. Katznelson (2008). Liberal Beginnings: Making a Republic for the
Moderns. Cambridge University Press.
Kant, I. (1996). Practical Philosophy, trans. M. J. Gregor. Cambridge University Press.
(2005). Notes and Fragments, ed. Paul Guyer. Cambridge University Press.
Kaufman, A. (2006). Capabilities Equality: Basic Issues and Problems. London,
Routledge.
Kelly, E. (2009). ‘Criminal Justice without Retribution’. Journal of Philosophy 106:
440–62.
Kelsen, H. (1961). General Theory of Law and State. New York, Russell and Russell.
(1970). The Pure Theory of Law. Berkeley, CA, University of California Press.
Keohane, N. O. (1980). Philosophy and the State in France: The Renaissance to the
Enlightenment. Princeton University Press.
Ketcham, R., ed. (2003). The Anti-Federalist Papers. New York, Signet Classic.
Kharkhordin, O. and R. Alipuro, eds. (2011). Political Theory and Community
Building in Post-Soviet Russia. London, Routledge.
318 References
Knights, M. (2005). Representation and Misrepresentation in Later Stuart Britain:
Partisanship and Political Culture. Oxford University Press.
Kornhauser, L. A. (1992a). ‘Modelling Collegial Courts. I. Path-Dependence’.
International Review of Law and Economics 12: 169–85.
(1992b). ‘Modelling Collegial Courts. ii. Legal Doctrine’. Journal of Law,
Economics and Organization 8: 441–70.
Kornhauser, L. A. and L. G. Sager (1993). ‘The One and the Many: Adjudication in
Collegial Courts’. California Law Review 81: 1–59.
Kramer, M. (2003). The Quality of Freedom. Oxford University Press.
(2008). ‘Liberty and Domination’ in Republicanism and Political Theory, ed.
C. Laborde and J. Maynor. Oxford, Blackwell, pp. 31–57.
Kukathas, C. (1989). Hayek and Modern Liberalism. Oxford University Press.
Kymlicka, W. (1995). Multicultural Citizenship. Oxford University Press.
Laborde, C. (2008). Critical Republicanism: The Hijab Controversy and Political
Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
Laborde, C. and J. Maynor, eds. (2007). Republicanism and Political Theory.
Oxford, Blackwell.
Langton, R. (1997). ‘Disenfranchised Silence’ in Common Minds: Themes from the
Philosophy of Philip Pettit, ed. H. G. Brennan, R. E. Goodin, F. C. Jackson
and M. Smith. Oxford University Press.
Languet, H. (1994). Vindiciae, Contra Tyrannos. Cambridge University Press.
Larmore, C. (2003). ‘Public Reason’ in The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, ed.
S. Freeman. Cambridge University Press, pp. 368–93.
(2012). ‘What is Political Philosophy?’ Journal of Moral Philosophy 9.
Lessig, L. (2011). Republic, Lost: How Monday Corrupts Congress – And a Plan to Stop
it. New York, Hachette.
Levin, M. (1984). ‘Negative Liberty’. Social Philosophy and Policy 2: 84–100.
Lewis, D. (1969). Convention. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
Libourne, J. (1646). The Legal Fundamental Liberties of the People of England,
Asserted, Revived, and Vindicated. London.
Lieberman, D. (2006). ‘The Mixed Constitution and the Common Law’ in The
Cambridge History of Eighteenth-Century Political Thought, ed. M. Goldie and
R. Wokler. Cambridge University Press, pp. 317–46.
Lind, J. (1776). Three Letters to Dr Price. London, T. Payne.
Lindahl, H. (2007). ‘The Paradox of Constituent Power: The Ambiguous Self-
Constitution of the European Union’. Ratio Juris 20: 485–505.
Lipset, S. M. (1960). Political Man: The Social Bases of Politics. New York,
Doubleday.
List, C. (2004). ‘The Impossibility of a Paretian Republican? Some Comments on
Pettit and Sen’. Economics and Philosophy 20: 1–23.
(2006a). ‘The Discursive Dilemma and Public Reason’. Ethics 116: 362–402.
(2006b). ‘Republican Freedom and the Rule of Law’. Politics, Philosophy and
Economics 5: 201–20.
List, C. and P. Pettit (2002). ‘Aggregating Sets of Judgments: An Impossibility
Result’. Economics and Philosophy 18: 89–110.
References 319
(2004). ‘Aggregating Sets of Judgments: Two Impossibility Results Compared’.
Synthese 140: 207–35.
(2011). Group Agency: The Possibility, Design and Status of Corporate Agents.
Oxford University Press.
List, C. and B. Polak (2010). ‘Symposium on Judgment Aggregation’. Journal of
Economic Theory 145 (2): 441–66.
Lively, J. (1975). Democracy. Oxford, Blackwell.
Lively, J. and J. Rees, eds. (1978). Utilitarian Logic and Politics: James Mill’s ‘Essay on
Government’, Macaulay’s Critique, and the Ensuing Debate. Oxford University
Press.
Locke, J. (1960). Two Treatises of Government. Cambridge University Press.
Long, D. C. (1977). Bentham on Liberty. University of Toronto Press.
Lovett, F. (2001). ‘Domination: A Preliminary Analysis’. Monist 84: 98–112.
(2010). Justice as Non-domination. Oxford University Press.
Lovett, F. and P. Pettit (2009). ‘Neo-Republicanism: A Normative and
Institutional Research Program’. Annual Review of Political Science 12: 18–29.
Luhmann, N. (1990). Essays on Self-Reference. New York, Columbia University Press.
MacCallum, G. C. (1967). ‘Negative and Positive Freedom’. Philosophical Review
74: 312–34.
McCormick, J. P. (2011). Machiavellian Democracy. Cambridge University Press.
MacDonagh, O. (1958). ‘The 19th Century Revolution in Government: A
Reappraisal’. Historical Journal 1: 52–67.
(1961). A Pattern of Government Growth 1800–60. London, MacGibbon and Kee.
(1977). Early Victorian Government. London, Weidenfeld and Nicolson.
McGeer, V. and P. Pettit (2009). ‘Sticky Judgment and the Role of Rhetoric’ in
Political Judgment: Essays in Honour of John Dunn, ed. R. Bourke and
R. Geuss. Cambridge University Press, pp. 48–73.
McGilvray, E. (2011). The Invention of Market Freedom. Cambridge University
Press.
Machiavelli, N. (1965). The Complete Works and Others. Durham, NC, Duke
University Press.
Mackie, G. (2003). Democracy Defended. Cambridge University Press.
McLean, J. (2004). ‘Government to State: Globalization, Regulation, and
Governments as Legal Persons’. Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 10:
173–97.
McMahon, C. (2005). ‘The Indeterminacy of Republican Policy’. Philosophy and
Public Affairs 33: 67–93.
Madison, J., A. Hamilton and J. Jay (1987). The Federalist Papers. Harmondsworth,
Penguin.
Mandeville, B. (1731). Free Thoughts on Religion, the Church and National
Happiness. London.
Manin, B. (1997). The Principles of Representative Government. Cambridge
University Press.
Mansbridge, J. (2009). ‘A “Selection Model” of Political Representation’. Journal of
Political Philosophy 17: 369–98.
320 References
Margalit, A. (2010). On Compromise and Rotten Compromises. Princeton University
Press.
Markell, P. (2008). ‘The Insufficiency of Non-Domination’. Political Theory 36: 19–36.
Markovits, D. (2005). ‘Democratic Disobedience’. Yale Law Journal 114: 1897–952.
Marti, J. L. and P. Pettit (2010). A Political Philosophy in Public Life: Civic
Republicanism in Zapatero’s Spain. Princeton University Press.
Maynor, J. (2003). Republicanism in the Modern World. Cambridge, Polity Press.
Mercier, H. and D. Sperber (2011). ‘Why Do Humans Reason? Arguments for an
Argumentative Theory’. Brain and Behavioral Sciences 34: 57–111.
Michelman, F. I. (1999). Brennan on Democracy. Princeton University Press.
Mill, J. S. (1964). Considerations on Representative Government. London, Everyman
Books.
(1978). On Liberty. Indianapolis, Hackett.
Millar, F. (1998). The Crowd in Rome in the Late Republic. Ann Arbor, University of
Michigan Press.
Miller, D. (1984). ‘Constraints on Freedom’. Ethics 94: 66–86.
Milton, J. (1953–82). Complete Prose Works of John Milton. New Haven, CT, Yale
University Press, vols. i–viii.
Montesquieu, C. d. S. (1989). The Spirit of the Laws. Cambridge University Press.
Morris, I. (2010). Why the West Rules – For Now: The Patterns of History, and What
they Reveal about the Future. New York, Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
Mueller, J. W. (2007). Constitutional Patriotism. Princeton University Press.
Murphy, L. and T. Nagel (2004). The Myth of Ownership. New York, Oxford
University Press.
Nagel, T. (1987). ‘Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy’. Philosophy and Public
Affairs 16: 215–40.
(1991). Equality and Partiality. Oxford University Press.
Nathan, G. (2010). Social Freedom in a Multicultural State: Towards a Theory for
Intercultural Justice. New York, Palgrave Macmillan.
Negri, A. (1999). Insurgencies: Constituent Power and the Modern State. Minneapolis,
MN, University of Minnesota Press.
Nelson, E. (2004). The Greek Tradition in Republican Thought. Cambridge University
Press.
Niederberger, A. and P. Schink, eds. (2012). Republican Democracy: Liberty, Law
and Politics. Edinburgh University Press.
Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Oxford, Blackwell.
Nussbaum, M. (1992). ‘Human Functioning and Social Justice’. Political Theory
20: 202–46.
(2006). Frontiers of Justice. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
O’Donnell, G. (2004). ‘Why the Rule of Law Matters’. Journal of Democracy 15:
32–46.
O’Neill, M. (2008). ‘What Should Egalitarians Believe?’ Philosophy and Public
Affairs 36: 119–56.
O’Neill, O. (1979–80). ‘The Most Extensive Liberty’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society 80: 45–59.
References 321
Ober, J. (1996). The Athenian Revolution. Princeton University Press.
Olsaretti, S. (2004). Liberty, Desert and the Market. Cambridge University Press.
Otsuka, M. (2003). Libertarianism without Inequality. Oxford University Press.
Paley, W. (2002). The Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy. Indianapolis,
Liberty Fund.
Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and Persons. Oxford University Press.
(2000). ‘Equality or Priority?’ in The Ideal of Equality, ed. M. Clayton and
A. Williams. New York, St Martin’s Press, pp. 81–125.
Patten, A. (2002). Hegel’s Idea of Freedom. Oxford University Press.
Pettit, P. (1986). ‘Free Riding and Foul Dealing’. Journal of Philosophy 83: 361–79.
(1990). ‘Virtus Normativa: A Rational Choice Perspective’. Ethics 100: 725–55;
reprinted in P. Pettit (2002) Rules, Reasons, and Norms. Oxford University Press.
(1991). ‘Decision Theory and Folk Psychology’ in Essays in the Foundations of
Decision Theory, ed. M. Bacharach and S. Hurley. Oxford, Blackwell; reprin-
ted in P. Pettit (2002) Rules, Reasons, and Norms. Oxford University Press.
(1993). The Common Mind: An Essay on Psychology, Society and Politics, paperback
edition 1996. New York, Oxford University Press.
(1994). ‘Enfranchising Silence: An Argument for Freedom of Speech’ in Freedom
of Communication, ed. T. Campbell and W. Sadurksi. Aldershot, Dartmouth,
pp. 45–56.
(1996a). ‘Freedom and Antipower’. Ethics 106: 576–604.
(1996b). ‘Institutional Design and Rational Choice’ in The Theory of Institutional
Design, ed. R. E. Goodin. Cambridge University Press.
(1997a). ‘A Consequentialist Perspective on Ethics’ in Three Methods of Ethics:
A Debate. M. Baron, M. Slote and P. Pettit. Oxford, Blackwell.
(1997b). ‘Republican Theory and Criminal Punishment’. Utilitas 9: 59–79.
(1997c). Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government. Oxford University
Press.
(1998). ‘Reworking Sandel’s Republicanism’. Journal of Philosophy 95: 73–96.
(1999). ‘Republican Liberty, Contestatory Democracy’ in Democracy’s Value, ed.
C. Hacker-Cordon and I. Shapiro. Cambridge University Press.
(2000a). ‘Democracy, Electoral and Contestatory’. Nomos 42: 105–44.
(2000b). ‘Minority Claims under Two Conceptions of Democracy’ in Political
Theory and the Rights of Indigenous Peoples, ed. D. Ivison, P. Patton and
W. Sanders. Cambridge University Press, pp. 199–215.
(2001a). ‘Capability and Freedom: A Defence of Sen’, Economics and Philosophy
17: 1–20.
(2001b). ‘The Capacity to Have Done Otherwise’ in Relating to Responsibility:
Essays in Honour of Tony Honore on his 80th Birthday, ed. P. Cane and
J. Gardner. Oxford, Hart, pp. 21–35; reprinted in P. Pettit (2002) Rules,
Reasons, and Norms. Oxford University Press.
(2001c). ‘Deliberative Democracy and the Discursive Dilemma’. Philosophical
Issues (supp. to Nous) 11: 268–99.
(2001d). ‘Non-Consequentialism and Political Philosophy’ in Robert Nozick,
ed. D. Schidmtz. Cambridge University Press.
322 References
(2001e). A Theory of Freedom: From the Psychology to the Politics of Agency.
Cambridge and New York, Polity and Oxford University Press.
(2002a). ‘Is Criminal Justice Politically Feasible?’ Buffalo Criminal Law Review,
Special Issue ed. Pablo de Greiff, 5(2): 427–50.
(2002b). ‘Keeping Republican Freedom Simple: On a Difference with Quentin
Skinner’. Political Theory 30: 339–56.
(2003a). ‘Akrasia, Collective and Individual’ in Weakness of Will and Practical
Irrationality, ed. S. Stroud and C. Tappolet. Oxford University Press.
(2003b). ‘Deliberative Democracy, the Discursive Dilemma, and Republican
Theory’ in Philosophy, Politics and Society Vol. 7: Debating Deliberative
Democracy, ed. J. Fishkin and P. Laslett. Cambridge University Press, pp. 138–62.
(2004a). ‘The Common Good’ in Justice and Democracy: Essays for Brian Barry,
ed. K. Dowding, R. E. Goodin and C. Pateman. Cambridge University Press,
pp. 150–69.
(2004b). ‘Depoliticizing Democracy’. Ratio Juris 17: 52–65.
(2005a). ‘The Domination Complaint’. Nomos 86: 87–117.
(2005b). ‘The Elements of Responsibility’. Philosophical Books 46: 210–19.
(2005c). ‘On Rule-Following, Folk Psychology, and the Economy of Esteem:
Reply to Boghossian, Dreier and Smith’: contribution to Symposium on
P. Pettit’s Rules, Reasons, and Norms. Philosophical Studies 124: 233–59.
(2006a). ‘The Determinacy of Republican Policy’. Philosophy and Public Affairs
34: 275–83.
(2006b). ‘Rawls’s Peoples’ in Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia, ed.
R. Martin and D. Reidy. Oxford, Blackwell.
(2007a). ‘Joining the Dots’ in Common Minds: Themes from the Philosophy of
Philip Pettit, ed. H. G. Brennan, R. E. Goodin, F. C. Jackson and M. Smith.
Oxford University Press, pp. 215–344.
(2007b). ‘Rationality, Reasoning and Group Agency’. Dialectica 61: 495–519.
(2007c). ‘Resilience as an Explanandum of Social Theory’ in Contingency, ed.
I. Shapiro and S. Bedi. New York University Press.
(2007d). ‘Responsibility Incorporated’. Ethics 117: 171–201.
(2007e). ‘Free Persons and Free Choices’. History of Political Thought, Special
Issue on ‘Liberty and Sovereignty’, 28: 709–18.
(2008a). ‘The Basic Liberties’ in Essays on H. L. A. Hart, ed. M. Kramer. Oxford
University Press, pp. 201–24.
(2008b). ‘Freedom and Probability: A Comment on Goodin and Jackson’.
Philosophy and Public Affairs 36: 206–20.
(2008c). Made with Words: Hobbes on Language, Mind and Politics. Princeton
University Press.
(2008d). ‘Republican Liberty: Three Axioms, Four Theorems’ in Republicanism
and Political Theory, ed. C. Laborde and J. Manor. Oxford, Blackwell.
(2008e). ‘Value-mistaken and Virtue-mistaken Norms’ in Political Legitimization
without Morality?, ed. J. Kuehnelt. New York, Springer, pp. 139–56.
(2009a). ‘Corporate Responsibility Revisited’. Rechtsfilosofie & Rechtstheorie, Special
Issue on ‘Philip Pettit and the Incorporation of Responsibility’, 38: 159–76.
References 323
(2009b). ‘Varieties of Public Representation’ in Representation and Popular Rule,
ed. I. Shapiro, S. Stokes and E. J. Wood. Cambridge University Press.
(2010a). ‘Legitimate International Institutions: A Neorepublican Perspective’ in
The Philosophy of International Law, ed. J. Tasioulas and S. Besson. Oxford
University Press.
(2010b). ‘Representation, Responsive and Indicative’. Constellations 3: 426–34.
(2010c). ‘A Republican Law of Peoples’. European Journal of Political Theory,
Special Issue on ‘Republicanism and International Relations’, 9: 70–94.
(2011a). ‘The Hedgehog’s Fantasies’: review of Ronald Dworkin, ‘Justice for
Hedgehogs’. Times Literary Supplement. London, News International.
(2011b). ‘The Instability of Freedom as Non-Interference: The Case of Isaiah
Berlin’. Ethics 121: 693–716.
(2012a). ‘The Inescapability of Consequentialism’ in Luck, Value and
Commitment: Themes from the Ethics of Bernard Williams, ed. U. Heuer and
G. Lang. Oxford University Press.
(2012b). ‘Two Republican Traditions’ in Republican Democracy: Liberty, Law
and Politics, ed. A. Niederberger and P. Schink. Edinburgh University Press.
(in press). Just Freedom. New York, W.W. Norton and Co.
Pettit, P. and D. Schweikard (2006). ‘Joint Action and Group Agency’. Philosophy
of the Social Sciences 36: 18–39.
Pettit, P. and M. Smith (1996). ‘Freedom in Belief and Desire’. Journal of
Philosophy 93: 429–49; reprinted in F. Jackson, P. Pettit and M. Smith
(2004) Mind, Morality and Explanation. Oxford University Press.
Pinker, S. (2011). The Better Angels of our Nature: Why Violence has Declined. New
York, Viking Penguin.
Pitkin, H. (1972). The Concept of Representation. Berkeley, University of California
Press.
Pitkin, H. F., ed. (1969). Representation. New York, Atherton Press.
Pocock, J. (1975). The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Theory and the
Atlantic Republican Tradition. Princeton University Press.
Pogge, T. (1990). Realizing Rawls. Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press.
Polybius (1954). The Histories. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
Prentice, D. A. and D. T. Miller (1993). ‘Pluralistic Ignorance and Alcohol Use on
Campus’. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 64: 243–56.
Price, R. (1991). Political Writings. Cambridge University Press.
Priestley, J. (1993). Political Writings. Cambridge University Press.
Przeworksi, A. (1999). ‘A Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defense’ in
Democracy’s Value, ed. C. Hacker-Cordon and I. Shapiro. Cambridge
University Press.
Quiggin, J. (2011). Zombie Economics: How Dead Ideas Still Walk Among Us.
Princeton University Press.
Raab, F. (1965). The English Face of Machiavelli: A Changing Interpretation
1500–1700. London, Routledge.
Raventos, D. (2007). Basic Income: The Material Conditions of Freedom. London,
Pluto Press.
324 References
Rawls, J. (1955). ‘Two Concepts of Rules’. Philosophical Review 64: 3–32.
(1971). A Theory of Justice. Oxford University Press.
(1993). Political Liberalism. New York, Columbia University Press.
(1995). ‘Political Liberalism: Reply to Habermas’. Journal of Philosophy 92:
132–80.
(1999). The Law of Peoples. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
(2001). Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University
Press.
Raz, J. (1986). The Morality of Freedom. Oxford University Press.
Rehfield, A. (2005). The Concept of Constituency: Political Representation,
Democratic Legitimacy, and Institutional Design. Cambridge University Press.
(2006). ‘Towards a General Theory of Political Representation’. Journal of
Politics 68: 1–21.
Reid, J. P. (1988). The Concept of Liberty in the Age of the American Revolution.
Chicago University Press.
Reidy, D. (2007). ‘Reciprocity and Reasonable Disagreement: From Liberal to
Democratic Legitimacy’. Philosophical Studies 132: 243–91.
Richardson, H. (2002). Democratic Autonomy. New York, Oxford University Press.
Richter, M. (1977). The Political Theory of Montesquieu. Cambridge University Press.
Riker, W. (1982). Liberalism against Populism. San Francisco, W. H. Freeman and Co.
Ripstein, A. (2009). Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal and Political Philosophy.
Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
Risse, M. (2004). ‘Arguing for Majority Rule’. Journal of Political Philosophy 12:
41–64.
Robbins, C. (1959). The Eighteenth Century Commonwealthman. Cambridge, MA,
Harvard University Press.
Robert, H. M., H. M. Robert, III, D. H. Honemann, T. J. Balch, D. E. Seabold and
S. Gerber (2011). Robert’s Rules of Order Newly Revised, 11th edn. Cambridge,
MA, Da Capo Press.
Roemer, J. (1998). Equality of Opportunity. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University
Press.
Rosanvallon, P. (2006). Democracy, Past and Future. New York, Columbia
University Press.
Rousseau, J. J. (1997). Rousseau: ‘The Social Contract’ and Other Later Political
Writings, trans. Victor Gourevitch. Cambridge University Press.
Rubenfeld, J. (2001). Freedom and Time: A Theory of Constitutional Self-
Government. New Haven, CT, Yale University Press.
Ryan, M. (1999). ‘Bartolus of Sassoferrato and Free Cities’. Transactions of the Royal
Historical Society 6: 65–89.
Ryle, G. (1949). The Concept of Mind. University of Chicago Press.
Sandel, M. (1996). Democracy’s Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy.
Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
Sanyal, S. (forthcoming). ‘A Defence of Democratic Egalitarianism’.
Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA, Harvard
University Press.
References 325
Scheffler, S. (2005). ‘Choice, Circumstance and the Value of Equality’, Politics,
Philosophy and Economics 4: 5–28.
Schmidtz, D. and J. Brennan (2010). A Brief History of Liberty. Oxford, Wiley-
Blackwell.
Schmitt, C. (2005). Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty.
Chicago University Press.
Schumpeter, J. A. (1984). Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy. New York, Harper
Torchbooks.
Schwartzberg, M. (2007). Democracy and Legal Change. Cambridge University
Press.
Searle, J. (1995). The Construction of Social Reality. New York, Free Press.
Sellers, M. N. S. (1995). American Republicanism: Roman Ideology in the United
States Constitution. New York University Press.
Sen, A. (1970). ‘The Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal’. Journal of Political
Economy 78: 152–7.
(1983a). ‘Liberty and Social Choice’. Journal of Philosophy 80: 18–20.
(1983b). ‘Poor, Relatively Speaking’. Oxford Economic Papers 35: 153–68.
(1985). Commodities and Capabilities. Amsterdam, North-Holland.
(2002). Rationality and Freedom. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
(2009). The Idea of Justice. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
Shapiro, I. (2003). The State of Democratic Theory. Princeton University Press.
Shapiro, S. (2011). Legality. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
Sharp, A., ed. (1998). The English Levellers. Cambridge University Press.
Shiffrin, S. (2000). ‘Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and
Accommodation’. Philosophy and Public Affairs 29: 205–50.
Sidney, A. (1990). Discourses Concerning Government. Indianapolis, Liberty Classics.
Sieyes, E. J. (2003). Political Writings. Indianapolis, Hackett.
Simmons, A. J. (1976). ‘Tacit Consent and Political Obligation’. Philosophy and
Public Affairs 5(3): 274–91.
(1979). Moral Principles and Political Obligations. Princeton University Press.
(1999). ‘Justification and Legitimacy’. Ethics 109: 739–71.
Sintomer, Y. (2007). Le Pouvoir au Peuple: Jurys citoyens, tirage au sort et democratie
participative. Paris, Edition la Decouverte.
Skinner, Q. (1974). ‘The Principles and Practice of Opposition: The Case of
Bolingbroke versus Walpole’ in Historical Perspectives: Studies in English
Thought and Society in Honour of J.H. Plumb, ed. N. McKendrick. London,
Europa Publications.
(1978). The Foundations of Modern Political Thought. Cambridge University Press.
(1996). Reason and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes. Cambridge University
Press.
(1998). Liberty Before Liberalism. Cambridge University Press.
(2005). ‘Hobbes on Representation’. European Journal of Philosophy 13: 155–84.
(2008a). ‘Freedom as the Absence of Arbitrary Power’ in Republicanism and
Political Theory, ed. J. Maynor and C. Laborde. Oxford, Blackwell.
(2008b). Hobbes and Republican Liberty. Cambridge University Press.
326 References
(2009). ‘A Genealogy of the Modern State’. Proceedings of the British Academy
162: 325–70.
Slaughter, S. (2005). Liberty beyond Neo-Liberalism: A Republican Critique of
Liberal Government in a Globalising Age. London, Macmillan Palgrave.
Smith, A. (1976). An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations.
Oxford University Press.
(1982). The Theory of the Moral Sentiments. Indianapolis, Liberty Classics.
Smith, M. (1994). The Moral Problem. Oxford, Blackwell.
Sober, E. and D. S. Wilson (1998). Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of
Unselfish Behavior. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
Sosa, E. (2007). A Virtue Epistemology. Oxford University Press.
Spitz, J.-F. (1995). La Liberte Politique. Paris, Presses Universitaires de France.
Steiner, H. (1994). An Essay on Rights. Oxford, Blackwell.
Stewart, A. T. Q. (1993). A Deeper Silence: The Hidden Roots of the United Irish
Movement. London, Faber.
Stilz, A. (2009). Liberal Loyalty: Freedom, Obligation, and the State. Princeton
University Press.
Stout, J. (2004). Democracy and Tradition. Princeton University Press.
Strauss, L. (2000). On Tyranny. Chicago University Press.
Strawson, P. (1962). Freedom and Resentment and Other Essays. London, Methuen.
Sugden, R. (1998). ‘The Metric of Opportunity’. Economics and Philosophy 14:
307–37.
Sunstein, C. R. (2009). Republic.com 2.0. Princeton University Press.
Talisse, R. B. (2007). A Pragmatist Philosophy of Democracy. London, Routledge.
(2009). Democracy and Moral Conflict. Princeton University Press.
Tan, K.-C. (2008). ‘A Defense of Luck Egalitarianism’. Journal of Philosophy 105:
665–90.
Taylor, C. (1985a). Philosophy and the Human Sciences. Cambridge University Press.
(1985b). Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2. Cambridge
University Press.
Temkin, L. (1996). Inequality. Oxford University Press.
Thaler, R. and C. Sunstein (2008). Nudge: Improving Decisions about Health,
Wealth and Happiness. London, Penguin Books.
Tilly, C. (1975). ‘Reflections on the History of European State-Making’ in The
Formation of National States in Western Europe, ed. C. Tilly. Princeton
University Press.
(2007). Democracy. Cambridge University Press.
Tomasi, J. (2012). Free Market Fairness. Princeton University Press.
Trenchard, J. and T. Gordon (1971). Cato’s Letters. New York, Da Capo.
Tuck, R. (2006). ‘Hobbes and Democracy’ in Rethinking the Foundations of
Modern Political Thought, ed. A. S. Brett and J. Tully. Cambridge University
Press.
(2008). Free Riding. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.
Tully, J. (2009). Public Philosophy in a New Key. Cambridge University Press, vols.
i and ii.
References 327
Tuomela, R. (1995). The Importance of Us. Stanford University Press.
Tyler, T. R. (1990). Why People Obey the Law. New Haven, Yale University Press.
Urbinati, N. (2006). Representative Democracy: Principles and Genealogy. University
of Chicago Press.
Vallentyne, P. and H. Steiner, eds. (2000a). Left-Libertarianism and its Critics. New
York, Palgrave.
(2000b). The Origins of Left-Libertarianism. New York, Palgrave.
Van der Rijt, J.-W. (2012). The Importance of Assent: A Theory of Coercion and
Dignity. New York, Springer.
Van Gelderen, M. and Q. Skinner (2002). Republicanism: A Shared European
Heritage, 2 vols., Cambridge University Press.
Van Parijs, P. (1995). Real Freedom for All. Oxford University Press.
Vatter, M. (2011). ‘Natural Right and States of Exception in Leo Strauss’ in
Crediting God: Sovereignty and Religion in the Age of Global Capitalism, ed.
M. Vatter. New York, Fordham University Press.
Vieira, M. B. and D. Runciman (2008). Representation. Cambridge, Polity Press.
Vile, M. J. C. (1967). Constitutionalism and the Separation of Powers. Oxford
University Press.
Viroli, M. (1995). For Love of Country. Oxford University Press.
(2002). Republicanism. New York, Hill and Wang.
Waldron, J. (1999a). The Dignity of Legislation. Cambridge University Press.
(1999b). Law and Disagreement. Oxford University Press.
(2006). ‘The Core of the Case Against Judicial Review’. Yale Law Journal 115:
1346–1406.
(2007). ‘Pettit’s Molecule’ in Common Minds: Themes from the Philosophy of
Philip Pettit, ed. G. Brennan, R. E. Goodin, F. Jackson and M. Smith. Oxford
University Press, pp. 143–60.
Waley, D. (1988). The Italian City-Republics, 3rd edn. London, Longman.
Walzer, M. (1981). ‘Philosophy and Democracy’. Political Theory 9: 379–99.
(1983). Spheres of Justice. Oxford, Martin Robertson.
Warren, M. E. (2011). ‘Voting with Your Feet: Exit-based Empowerment in
Democratic Theory’. American Political Science Review 105: 683–701.
Warren, M. E. and H. Pearse, eds. (2008). Designing Deliberative Democracy.
Cambridge University Press.
Watson, A. (1985). The Digest of Justinian, Four Volumes. Philadelphia, University
of Pennsylvania Press.
Watson, G. (2003). ‘Free Agency’ in Free Will, 2nd edn, ed. G. Watson. Oxford
University Press.
(2005). Agency and Answerability: Selected Essays. Oxford University Press.
Weber, M. (1947). The Theory of Social and Economic Organization. London,
William Hodge.
Weingast, B. (1997). ‘The Political Foundations of Democracy and the Rule of
Law’. American Political Science Review 91: 245–63.
Weinstock, D. and C. Nadeau, eds. (2004). Republicanism: History, Theory and
Practice. London, Frank Cass.
328 References
White, S. and D. Leighton, eds. (2008). Building a Citizen Society: The Emerging
Politics of Republican Democracy. London, Lawrence and Wishart.
Whitehead, A. N. (1997). Science and the Modern World. New York, Simon and
Schuster.
Williams, B. (2005). In the Beginning was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in
Political Argument. Princeton University Press.
Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its Limits. Oxford University Press.
Winch, D. (1978). Adam Smith’s Politics: An Essay in Historiographic Revision.
Cambridge University Press.
Winch, P. (1963). The Idea of a Social Science and Its Relation to Philosophy. London,
Routledge.
Wirszubski, C. (1968). Libertas as a Political Ideal at Rome. Oxford University Press.
Wolf, S. (2010). Meaning in Life and Why it Matters. Princeton University Press.
Woolf, C. N. S. (1913). Bartolus of Sassoferrato. Cambridge University Press.
Young, I. (1990). Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton University Press.
(2000). Inclusion and Democracy. Oxford University Press.
Zucca, L. (2007). Constitutional Dilemmas: Conflicts of Fundamental Legal Rights in
Europe and the USA. Oxford University Press.
Name index
Abizadeh, A. 162 Brennan, Geoffrey xii, 12, 15, 20, 117, 121, 128, 169,
Abramson, J. 197 182, 200, 236, 247
Ackerman, B. 285 Brett, A. S. xii, 287
Adams, John 134 Brettschneider, C. 265
Agamben, Georgio 173 Brugger, W. 3
Alexander, J. M. 79 Buchak, Lara 32
Alipuro, R. 252 Buchanan, A. 146, 148, 151
Amar, Akhil 292 Burke, Edmund 206
Anderson, E. 91, 93 Burnheim, J. 204
Anscombe, G. E. M. 53
Appiah, K. A. xii, 128 Cabot, V. 222
Arendt, Hannah 12, 18, 289 Canning, J. P. 288
Aristotle 6, 189–90, 291 Carroll, Lewis 278
Arneson, R. 79 Carter, Ian xii, 44, 46, 51
Arrow, Kenneth 194 Charlesworth, H. 222
Atiyah, P. S. 151 Christiano, Thomas 145
Christman, J. 48
Bailyn, B. 6–7 Churchill, Winston 242
Bakan, J. 116, 235 Cicero, M. T. 6, 88, 221
Baldwin, T. 48 Clark, A. 115, 225
Barry, Brian 143 Cohen, G. A. 20, 79, 96, 183–4
Bartels, L. M. 210 Cohen, Joshua 13, 14, 15, 23–5, 79, 123, 126,
Bartolus of Sassoferrato 287–8 144–5, 267
Beitz, Charles xii, 143, 146, 214, 262 Cohen, M. 111
Bell, D. 148, 151 Coleman, J. 84, 115
Bellamy, Richard 3, 207, 216 Connolly, W. 180, 251
Benhabib, S. 215 Constant, Benjamin 16, 200, 232–3
Bentham, Jeremy 8, 9, 10, 123, 149, Cook, Maeve 44
249, 293 Cornish, W. R. 115
Berlin, Isaiah 9, 17, 22, 29, 30–5, 39, 41–3, 48, Costa, M. V. 58
64–7, 149, 150, 294, 295
Berntson, Daniel 42 Dagger, Richard 11
Besold, C. 222 Demosthenes 135
Besson, S. 3 Dennett, D. C. 203, 225
Bodin, Jean 12–13, 14–15, 189–90, 220–1, 223–5, Dietrich, F. 106, 194
290, 293–4, 303 Dowlen, O. 12, 196
Bohman, J. 3, 128 Dryzek, John 145
Bolingbroke, Viscount 6–7 Duff, R. A. 118
Braithwaite, John xii, 3, 117, 119, 121, 222 Dunn, J. 180
Bramhall, Bishop J. 29, 142 Dworkin, Ronald 11, 20, 48, 78, 79, 148,
Bratman, M. 48, 277 180, 186
329
330 Name index
Eisgruber, C. L. 265 Hayward, Clarissa 44, 63, 126
Elazar, Yiftah 16 Hegel, G. W. F. 126, 222, 224, 290
Elster, Jon 15, 84, 253, 267, 278 Held, David 181
Ely, John Hart 201, 217 Herreros, F. 244
Eskridge, William 257 Hill, L. 210
Espejo, P. O. 238, 289 Hobbes, Thomas 9, 12–13, 14–15, 28–31, 33–5,
Estlund, David 144–5, 148 41–3, 61, 64–7, 141, 142, 151, 189–90, 220–1,
Ewing, Ben 120, 174 223–5, 228, 229, 289, 293–4, 295, 303, 305
Hoekstra, Kinch xii, 221, 189
Faini, Matteo 196 Holmes, Stephen 23–5, 201
Ferejohn, John xii, 274 Honig, B. 227, 274
Ferguson, Adam 173–4, 227 Honneth, A. 184
Fisher, Richard xii Honohan, I. 3
Fishkin, James 197 Hont, Istvan xii, 286
Fleurbaey, Marc xii, 79 Hume, David 151, 246–7
Forst, Rainer xii, 143 Husak, D. 119
Fowler, A. 210
Frankfurt, H. 29, 48, 51, 81 Ivison, Duncan xii
Franklin, J. 222
Fukuyama, F. 6, 135, 164 Jackson, Frank xii, 34, 35, 164
Fuller, L. L. 221 James, Susan xii, 48
Jay, J. 6–7, 76, 211, 244
Gadeke, Dorothy 62 Jennings, J. 3
Garber, Dan xii Joshi, Hrishikesh 53
Gardner, John xii Joyce, J. M. 34
Garsten, B. 259
Gatens, Moira xii Kahneman, D. 246
Gaus, G. 48, 255, 261 Kalyvas, A. 8, 289, 292
Gauthier, David 145 Kant, Immanuel 12, 17, 44, 134, 142–3, 144, 164,
Geuss, R. 59 191, 223–4, 229, 302
Gilbert, M. 138, 277 Katznelson, I. 8
Gilovich, T. 246 Kaufman, A. 81
Goldberg, J. 111 Kelly, E. 121
Goldman, A. 169 Kelsen, H. 287
Goldsworthy, J. 278 Keohane, Nan xii, 12
Goodin, R. E. xii, 34, 35, 245 Ketcham, R. 6–7, 199
Gordon, T. 7–8 Kharkhordin, O. 252
Green, J. E. 227 Knights, M. 270
Griffin, D. 246 Kolodny, Niko xi, 23–5, 204, 211
Guerrero, A. 169, 211 Kornhauser, Lewis 192
Gutmann, Amy 144–5 Kramer, Matthew xii, 44, 46, 51
Gwyn, W. B. 221 Krygier, Martin xii
Kukathas, Chandran xii, 135
Habermas, Juergen 12, 15–16, 23–5, 144–5, 201, Kymlicka, Will 178
253, 267
Hamilton, A. 6–7, 76, 211, 244 Laborde, Cecile xii, 3, 178
Hamlin, A. 247 Lacey, Niki xii
Hand, Learned 101 Lane, Melissa xii
Hansen, M. H. 12, 189, 196, 222 Langton, R. 202
Hardt, M. 289 Languet, H. 150
Harman, G. 194 Larmore, C. 20, 254
Harman, Liz xii Leighton, D. 3
Harrington, James 6–7, 17, 134, 228 Lessig, L. 235
Hart, Herbert 84, 96, 100, 221 Letsas, George xii
Hayek, F. A. xii, 134 Levin, M. 115
Name index 331
Lewis, D. 255 Nozick, Robert 11, 79, 145
Libourne, J. 8, 83 Nussbaum, M. 8, 79, 81, 83, 104–5, 112, 126
Lieberman, D. 222
Lind, John 150–8 Oastler, Richard 272
Lindahl, Hans 289, 292 Ober, Josh xii, 188–9, 196, 222
Lipset, S. M. 227 O’Donnell, G. 221
List, Christian xii, 32, 49, 67, 76, 106, 116, 120, 133, Olsaretti, S. 29, 40, 54, 72, 148, 151, 166
168, 192, 193, 194, 195, 198, 206, 223, 277, 283, 289 O’Neill, M. 91
Lively, J. 191, 249, 251 Otsuka, Michael xii, 29, 158
Livy 6
Locke, John 93, 141, 173, 204, 292 Paley, William 8, 9, 10, 11, 22, 123, 150, 188–94
Lomasky, L. 12, 200 Parfit, Derek 81, 89, 91, 100, 184
Long, D. C. 9 Patten, Alan xii, 184
Lovett, Frank xii, 3, 7, 18, 58, 90, 116, 180 Patton, Paul xii
Luhmann, Niklas 193, 284 Pearse, H. 197
Pettit, P. 3, 8, 9, 11, 12, 15, 17–20, 26, 27, 28–9, 30, 32,
MacCallum, G. C. 48 34, 38, 41, 42, 48, 49, 51, 52, 58, 59, 60, 64, 67, 74,
McCormick, J. P. 6, 213, 217, 222, 227, 231 76, 84, 90, 93, 100, 116, 117, 119, 120, 121, 124, 127,
MacDonagh, Oliver 270–2, 274, 308 128, 129, 133, 140, 150, 157, 161, 168, 182, 189, 192,
Macedo, Stephen xii, 255 193, 194, 195, 198, 202, 204, 206, 218, 221, 223, 231,
McGeer, Victoria xii, 246, 259 234, 236, 245, 246, 247, 259, 262, 277, 281, 284,
McGilvray, Eric 3, 45, 111 287, 289
Machiavelli, Nicolo 6, 84, 174, 221, 222, 227 Pitkin, Hannah 198, 199, 207, 244
Mackie, G. 194 Plato 6
McLean, J. 133 Plunkett, David xi
McMahon, C. 58 Pocock, John 3, 8
Madison, J. 6–7, 76, 211, 244 Pogge, Thomas 143
Mandeville, Bernard 246–7 Polak, B. 193
Manin, B. 195 Polybius 6, 12, 188–9, 221
Mansbridge, J. xii, 195, 195 Prentice, D. A. 84
Margalit, A. 216 Price, Richard 6–8, 16, 169, 173, 218, 247
Markell, P. 127 Priestley, Joseph 6–7, 204
Markovits, D. 138 Przeworksi, A. 241
Marti, Jose xii, 3, 124, 234
Maynor, J. 3 Quiggin, J. 112
Mercier, H. 254
Michelman, F. I. 147 Raab, F. 6–7
Mill, James 191, 249–51, 307 Rakove, J. 219
Mill, John Stuart 98, 119, 135, 199, 210 Raventos, D. 112
Millar, F. 222 Rawls, John 11, 20, 41–3, 76, 78, 79–80, 82, 90, 94,
Miller, D. 39, 49, 84 107–10, 122, 123, 124, 125, 143, 144–5, 146, 150–8,
Milton, John 6–8, 158 184–6, 254, 287, 294, 299
Mirabeau, Honoré 199 Raz, Joseph xii, 78, 136, 137
Montesquieu, Baron de 6–7, 221, 226, 243 Rees, J. 191, 249
Morris, I. 96 Rehfield, A. 195, 201
Mueller, J. W. xii, 140, 238 Reid, J. P. 6–7, 168–9
Murphy, L. 99 Reidy, D. 143
Richardson, H. 3, 58, 128
Nadeau, C. 3 Richter, M. 222
Nagel, Thomas 99, 143 Riker, William 23, 194, 294
Nathan, G. 178 Ripstein, A. 168, 229
Nebel, Jake 184 Risse, M. 214
Negri, A. 289 Robbins, C. 6–7
Nelson, Eric 6 Roemer, J. 79
Niederberger, A. 3 Rosanvallon, Pierre 235
332 Name index
Rosen, Gideon xii Sugden, R. 46
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques 5, 12–18, 130, 141, 142, Sunstein, C. R. 56, 234, 262
147, 189, 191, 223–5, 228, 229, 243, 289, 293–4, 305
Rubenfeld, J. 291 Talisse, R. B. 148, 178
Runciman, D. 195 Tan, K. C. 126
Rutten, A. R. 219 Tasioulas, John xii
Ryan, Magnus xii, 288 Taylor, Charles 45, 146
Ryle, Gilbert 225 Temkin, L. xii, 81
Thaler, R. 56
Sadurski, Wojciech xii Thompson, Dennis 144–5
Sager, Larry 192 Tilly, C. 164, 242
Sandel, Michael 12 Tomasi, J. 111
Sanyal, S. 126, 132 Trenchard, J. 7–8
Scanlon, T. M. xii, 143 Tuck, R. xii, 169, 189
Scheffler, S. 91, 114 Tully, J. 23–5, 75, 217, 238
Scheppele, Kim xii Tuomela, R. 277
Schink, P. 3 Tyler, T. R. 84, 118
Schmidtz, D. 20
Schmitt, Carl 173 Urbinati, Nadia 195, 290
Schumpeter, Joseph 22–3, 201, 241–2, 243, 294
Valentini, Laura xii
Schwartzberg, M. 23–5, 217
Vallentyne, P. 79
Schweikard, D. 277
Van Gelderen, M. 3
Scott, Sir Walter 271
Van Parijs, P. 42
Searle, J. 277
Vatter, M. xii, 131
Sellers, M. N. S. 6–7
Vieira, M. B. 195
Sen, Amartya xii, 8, 69, 79, 81, 83, 87, 104–5, 106,
Vile, M. J. C. 221
112, 124, 126, 145, 155, 158, 171, 248
Viroli, M. 3, 228
Shapiro, Ian xii, 201
Shapiro, S. 84, 292 Waldron, J. xii, 23–5, 34, 79, 145, 213, 214
Sharp, A. 81, 83 Waley, D. 196
Shiffrin, S. 59, 98 Walzer, Michael 23–5, 79
Sidney, Algernon 6–8, 204 Warren, M. E. 168, 197
Sieyes, E. J. 285, 286 Watson, A. 131
Simmons, A. J. 141, 144, 146 Watson, G. 48
Singer, Peter xii Weale, Albert xii, 30
Sintomer, Y. 197 Weber, Max 145–6
Skinner, Quentin xii, 3, 5, 6–7, 9, 17–20, 26, 28–9, Weingast, Barry xii, 219
58, 195, 254, 259, 287 Weinstock, D. 3
Slaughter, S. 3 White, S. 3
Smith, Adam 87, 104–5, 128, 249 Whitehead, A. N. 224–5
Smith, Melanchton 199 Williams, B. 145, 148
Smith, Michael xii, 27, 48, 59, 60, 281 Williamson, T. 32
Soares, A. 222 Wilson, D. S. 84
Sober, E. 84 Winch, P. 84, 87
Sosa, E. 198 Wirszubski, C. 2
Soskice, David xii Wolf, S. 102
Southwood, N. xii, 171 Wolff, Jonathan xii, 30
Sperber, D. 254 Wollheim, Richard 30
Spitz, J. F. 16 Woolf, C. N. S. 189, 190, 288
Steiner, H. 44, 51, 79, 95
Stewart, A. T. Q. 219 Yong, Caleb 136, 214
Stilz, A. xi, 94, 143 Young, I. xii, 227, 257
Stout, J. xii, 227
Strauss, Leo 131 Zucca, L. 106
Strawson, Peter 27, 43, 60 Zuehl, Jake 267
Subject index
333
334 Subject index
control mixed constitution in 283–4
and consent 157–60, 301 role of the people 285–8, 292
idea of 153–6 role of the state 282–5
and influence, see influence see also democracy, Washington system of;
intentional 243–7 democracy, Westminster system of
inter-agential 171
nature of 153–60 egalitarianism, expressive 78–9, 89
non-intentional 248–51 elected politicians, see politicians
popular, see popular control electoral commissions, independent 232–3
unintentional 248–51 electoral influence 209–11, 237, 305–6
courts, in democracy 285 electoral institutions 207–8
criminalization 117–22, 299 enfranchisement of citizens 168–9
English republic 6–7
decision-making, collective 258 equality
deliberative regulation 264–9 commitment to 255
democracy of influence 262
Athenian model 188–9 material 125, 126
Churchill on 242 and social justice 77–92
and constitutionalism 23 in society 2–3, 169
contestatory 227–8, 238 equalization, expressive 79, 89–90
deliberative 267–8, 269–74 An Essay on Government 249–51
dual-aspect model of 252–79, 308–10 exercisability, individual 94–7
electoral 238 eyeball test 84–5, 86–7, 98, 105, 124, 176
emerging view of 21–4
and freedom 22 fallacy of misplaced concreteness 224–5
and justice 24–5 federalist/anti-federalist debate 6–7
model of 4 Florence 6
non-directive influence 22–3 free choice, resources required 36–7
and non-interference 150 free-man 17–18
Schumpeter on 241–2, 306 free-person heuristic 82–7, 93
slow 270–2 freedom
theory of 4, 179–81, 302 in accord with common discourse 9
Washington system of 206–7, 246, 284–5, 304 of association 201–2
Westminster system of 206–7, 246, 284–5, 304 basic 92–107, 201–2, 297–8, 299
democratic control, see control identifying 106
democratic state 179–86 variations in 104–7
appeal of 181–4 of choice 69–74, 83, 103, 295–6
dependent sovereignty of constituted people co-exercisable 93, 94–7, 105, 106, 299–300
289–90 co-satisfying 93, 94–7, 98–101, 299–300
derived returns, equal 80–1 of contract 150
despotism, of custom 135 coordination rules 97
direct returns, equal 80–1 criteria for 92–4, 173–4
Discourses on Livy 6 culturally variable rules 105, 106
discrimination 78 dependency on goodwill 169
domination and exercisability 94–7
by corporate bodies 115–17 and general protection insulation programmes
by employers 115 117–22
and interference 50, 165, 296 hindrance probability 33–5, 295
and invasion 28, 50, 295–6 individual satisfaction 98
necessity for 163, 165 institutional environments for 111
protection against 109–10 and insurance programmes 112–14
types of 63 and law 93
see also control as legal liberties 42
dual process 23 and material environment 110–12
dual-aspect model of democracy 252–79, 280–1 measurement of 44–7
Subject index 335
minority groups 211–13 incorporated people 289
and moral personality 94 independence of the people 218–19
as non-domination 4, 5, 6, 7–8, 9, 18, 22, 25, indeterminacy 282
67–9, 82–7, 88–92, 123, 126–7, 152–3, 166, individual rights 217
183, 293, 294, 296, 297, 301 individual satisfaction 98
factors reducing 27–8 individualized contestability 213–14, 215–18, 304
hindrances to, see hindrances industrialization, of nineteenth-century England
summary 294–7 270–2
as non-frustration 64–9, 296 influence
as non-interference 9–10, 64–9, 123, 149–52, accessibility to 187, 303, 304
293, 301 campaign supporters 234–5
opportunity-freedom 46–7 directed 167, 187, 240–52
physical restrictions on 96 electoral 209–11, 229–31
and political legitimacy 146–9 equally accessible 187, 213–15, 262
procedural 185 failure of 203
and public entrenchment 86–8, 93 individualized 209–18, 262
rule-dependent 97 media 234, 235
and self-determination 16 minority groups 211–13
and special protection insulation programmes plenary assembly 188–94
114–17 popular 168–70, 229–31, 242, 260, 280, 301, 306
of speech 201–2 private lobbies 231, 233–5
and status 83–4, 90–2, 181, 298 reserve 230–1
three theories of 64–7 unconditioned system of 218–29
to interfere 71 unelected authorities 231, 235–8
of travel 201–2 varieties of 156–7
see also choice; liberty virtual 230
freedom-related words 20–1 without control 240–3
French Constituent Assembly 199 see also control
ingratiation 64–7, 72
general protection insulation programmes 117–22 insulation programmes
generic hindrances 37–40 general protection 117–22
global sovereignty 18–19 special protection 114–17
government insurance programmes 112–14
intentional direction of 243–7 intentional-control model 275–7, 306–7
non-intentional direction of 248–51 intentional-direction model 247
oversight of 226 interest-group pluralism 250
and public interest promotion 249–51 interference
Great Reform Bill (1832) 270 arbitrary 58–9
with choice 49, 69–74, 165
Hand test 101 controlled 153
harmful choice 100–1 and eyeball test 84–5, 86–7, 98, 105, 124, 176
hindrances impacts of 229
generic 37–40 and legitimacy 149–52
invasive 35–49, 69, 295 modes of 56
probability of 33–5, 295 moral constraints on 63
resources for free choice 36–7 nature of 50–6
specific 37–40 non-arbitrary 152
to freedom of choice 27–35 paternalistic 58–9
variations in 35 and subjection 56–9
vitiating 35–49, 295 uncontrolled 58–9
will-imposed 44 intimidation 60–4
humanitarianism 271–2, 273 intolerability, of employment conditions 272
invasion, and domination 28, 50, 295–6
impartiality 13–14, 215 invasive hindrances 35–49, 69, 295
impersonal norm 134 investments, equal 80–1
336 Subject index
invigilation 60–4 non-domination 4, 5, 6, 7–8, 9, 18, 22, 25, 67–9,
invisible-hand mechanism 248–9, 250, 307 82–7, 88–92, 123, 126–7, 152–3, 166, 183,
Italian–Atlantic republicanism 5, 8, 12, 14, 15, 293, 294, 296, 297, 301
16–18, 218–19, 220, 293–4 non-intentional model 306, 307
Italy non-interference 9–10, 64–9, 123, 149–52, 293,
medieval 2–3, 6 301
Renaissance 2–3, 6 norms 84, 128, 134, 135, 255–6, 257, 258, 261–9,
275–7
jointly intentional action 277 policy-relevant 261–9, 276, 307–8
justice
and coercion 136 ombudsmen 216
criminalization 117–22 opportunity-cost regulation 117–18
implementation by state 133–4, 299–300 opportunity-freedom 46–7
infrastructural programmes 110–12 option-luck 79
and material equality 125, 126 options
model of 107–22 and distality of choice 102–3
and non-interference 124 removal of 50–6
procedural provisions 76 orthonomy 27, 48, 281–2
Rawls’s theory of 107–10 over-empowering choices 99
and social order 76
see also republican justice; social justice participatory engagement 227
paternalistic interference 58–9
kingdom of ends 181–2, 183 patriotism 140, 261–2
knave’s principle 246–7 people, in dual-aspect democracy 285–8, 289
philanthropy 113
laissez-faire doctrine 271–2 plenary assembly 188–94, 303
law policy-condition 265
coercive 84, see also coercion political campaign supporters 234–5
and liberties 106 political corruption 247
legitimacy political legitimacy 3, 4, 18–19, 20, 76, 77, 294
alternative uses of terminology 145–6 acceptance of regime 137, 300
and civic justifiability 146 and civil disobedience 138
and control 177, 301 content-independent conformity to law 139
international 146 as distinct from social justice 130–1
political, see political legitimacy eclipsed in later political thought 142–5
levelling-down 88, 298 and freedom 146–9
Leviathan 142 in freedom-denying regime 148
liberalism 10–11 illegitimate institutions 139
liberty, see freedom illegitimate laws 139
lobbies, private 231, 233–5 imposition of rules 141
lottery-based system, of assembly membership just illegitimacy 140
196–7, 198 and justice system 133–4
luck-egalitarian theory 79 lawful opposition to 137–8, 139–40
legitimacy threshold 139
manipulation 55–6 as non-domination 152–3
material equality 125, 126 as non-interference 149–52
media influence 234, 235 and norms 134, 135
minority/majority divides 211–13 as on–off 139
mixed theories 79 and patriotism 140
morals 84 political obligation of citizens 138, 300
multinationals, and domination 115–17 as popular control 146–53
summary 299–303
natural resources for free choice 36 traditional 141–2
need, and eyeball test 86 and utilitarianism 142–5
non-directive influence 22–3 political liberty 41–2
Subject index 337
political lobbies 231, 233–5 republicanism
political ontology, principles of 288–92 and communitarian doctrine 11–18
political party policy 285 and liberalism 10–11
politicians, elected and political legitimacy 147–8, 294
dependence on private lobbies 234 resistance (civil disobedience) 138, 173, 219
electoral influence 209–11, 237 resourcing choice 69–74
self-interest of 231, 232–3 responsive assemblies 197–8, 201–5
popular control 160–79 restraint, absence of 9
domain of 160–6 retributivism 121–2
efficacious system of 167, 175–9 return, equal rates of 80–1
individualized system of 168–70, 302 revealed will 47–9
and influence 240–3 rewards 55
nature of 166–7 Robert’s Rules of Order 101, 298
unconditioned system of 170–4 Rome
veto over government 168 institutions 6
see also control subjection in 2
popular direction 245 rule-dependent choices 99
poverty 104–5 rule-dependent liberty 97
power rules, culturally variable 105, 106
asymmetrical 62
individualization of 226 Social Contract 142
reputation of 61–2 social justice 4, 18–19, 20
power sharing 222–3 and basic liberties 77
powers, separation of 143, 221–3 and coercion 136
preference-satisfaction 30–1, 34 and democracy 24–5, 303
priority of constituting people 289 and equality 77–92, 297
private interest 244–5 connection between 77–81
procedural liberties 185 republican justice equality strategy
process-condition 265 87–92
proportionality, in electoral system 199 republican justice freedom goal 82–7
protection and freedom 77
against domination 109–10 parental strategy analogy 80–1
of choice 69–74 and political legitimacy, see political legitimacy
public debate 215 principles (Rawls) 79
public interest 244–5 republican theory of 77, 88–92
public person 14 summary 297–9
see also justice
re-election, of politicians 232, 241, 247 social legitimacy, see political legitimacy
real will 47–9 social resources for free choice 36–7
reciprocal exchange 78 sovereignty
reflective equilibrium 20–1, 294 of constituted people 289–90, 293–4, 305
regularities of behaviour 128 international 18–19, 20
replaceability of constituted people 291–2 special insulation protection 114–17
representation, mechanisms of 199 specific hindrances 37–40
republican justice The Spirit of the Laws 6–7
character of 122–9 spontaneous norms 135
and criminalization 117–22 state
demands of 126–7 as agency 133, 300
equality strategy 87–92 and criminalization 117–22
freedom goal 82–7 and dual-aspect democracy 282–5
minimalism of 123, 126 and justice implementation 133–4
principle of 123–5 types of 189–90
role of law and norm in 127–9 state egalitarianism 78–81
see also justice; social justice status, and freedom 83–4, 90–2, 181, 298
republican rhetoric 254 straw voting 193, 284
338 Subject index
subjection unfree 162
evil of 1–2 utilitarianism 10, 142–5
and interference 56–9
supervision, by public 5 Venice 6
vitiation 28
threshold benefits, equal 80–1 of choice 63, 295
tough-luck test 177–9, 229 vitiating hindrances 35–49, 295
transparency, in decisions 215 voting 168, 192–4, 209–15, 216–17, 260, 283