The Problem of Evil
The Problem of Evil
Definitions[edit]
Evil[edit]
A broad concept of evil defines it as any and all pain and suffering,[10] yet according to John
Kemp, evil cannot be correctly understood on "a simple hedonic scale on which pleasure
appears as a plus, and pain as a minus".[11][10] According to the National Institute of
Medicine, pain is essential for survival: "Without pain, the world would be an impossibly
dangerous place".[12][13] Marcus Singer says that a usable definition of evil must be based on
the knowledge that: "If something is really evil, it can't be necessary, and if it is really
necessary, it can't be evil".[14]:186
While many of the arguments against an omni-God are based on the broadest definition of
evil, "most contemporary philosophers interested in the nature of evil are primarily
concerned with evil in a narrower sense".[15] The narrow concept of evil involves moral
condemnation, and is applicable only to moral agents capable of making independent
decisions, and their actions; it allows for the existence of some pain and suffering without
identifying it as evil.[16]:322 Christianity is based on "the salvific value of suffering".[17]
Philosopher Eve Garrard suggests that the term evil cannot be used to describe ordinary
wrongdoing, because "there is a qualitative and not merely a quantitative difference
between evil acts and other wrongful ones; evil acts are not just very bad or wrongful acts,
but rather ones possessing some specially horrific quality".[16]:321 Calder argues that evil must
involve the attempt or desire to inflict significant harm on the victim without moral
justification.[10]
Evil takes on different meanings when seen from the perspective of different belief
systems, and while evil can be viewed in religious terms, it can also be understood in
natural or secular terms, such as social vice, egoism, criminality, and sociopathology.
[18]
John Kekes writes that an action is evil if "(1) it causes grievous harm to (2) innocent
victims, and it is (3) deliberate, (4) malevolently motivated, and (5) morally unjustifiable".[19]
Omni-qualities[edit]
Omniscience is "maximal knowledge".[20] According to Edward Wierenga, a classics scholar
and doctor of philosophy and religion at the University of Massachusetts, maximal is not
unlimited but limited to "God knowing what is knowable".[21]:25 This is the most widely
accepted view of omniscience among scholars of the twenty-first century, and is
what William Hasker calls freewill theism. Within this view, future events that depend upon
choices made by individuals with freewill are unknowable until they occur.[22]:104; 137[20]:18–20
Omnipotence is maximal power to bring about events within the limits of possibility, but
again maximal is not unlimited.[23] According to the philosophers Hoffman and Rosenkrantz:
"An omnipotent agent is not required to bring about an impossible state of affairs... maximal
power has logical and temporal limitiations, including the limitation that an omnipotent
agent cannot bring about, i.e., cause, another agent's free decision".[23]
Omnibenevolence sees God as all loving. If God is omnibenevolent, he acts according to
what is best, but if there is no best available, God attempts, if possible, to bring about
states of affairs that are creatable and are optimal within the limitations of physical reality.[24]
Secularism[edit]
In emeritus professor of philosophy at Whitworth University Forrest E. Baird's view, one can
have a secular problem of evil whenever humans seek to explain why evil exists and its
relationship to the world.[28] He adds that any experience that "calls into question our basic
trust in the order and structure of our world" can be seen as evil,[28] therefore, according
to Peter L. Berger, humans need explanations of evil "for social structures to stay
themselves against chaotic forces".[29]