Jean Bodin On Sovereignty
Jean Bodin On Sovereignty
Jean Bodin On Sovereignty
Early
Journal
Content
on
JSTOR,
Free
to
Anyone
in
the
World
This
article
is
one
of
nearly
500,000
scholarly
works
digitized
and
made
freely
available
to
everyone
in
the
world
by
JSTOR.
Known
as
the
Early
Journal
Content,
this
set
of
works
include
research
articles,
news,
letters,
and
other
writings
published
in
more
than
200
of
the
oldest
leading
academic
journals.
The
works
date
from
the
mid-‐seventeenth
to
the
early
twentieth
centuries.
We
encourage
people
to
read
and
share
the
Early
Journal
Content
openly
and
to
tell
others
that
this
resource
exists.
People
may
post
this
content
online
or
redistribute
in
any
way
for
non-‐commercial
purposes.
JSTOR
is
a
digital
library
of
academic
journals,
books,
and
primary
source
objects.
JSTOR
helps
people
discover,
use,
and
build
upon
a
wide
range
of
content
through
a
powerful
research
and
teaching
platform,
and
preserves
this
content
for
future
generations.
JSTOR
is
part
of
ITHAKA,
a
not-‐for-‐profit
organization
that
also
includes
Ithaka
S+R
and
Portico.
For
more
information
about
JSTOR,
please
contact
[email protected].
JEAN BODIN ON SOVEREIGNTY.
THE of EnglandsinceBen-
politicaland legal philosophy
tham has done much for the fame of Thomas Hobbes.
Reverential hands have placed the sage of Malmesburyon a
pinnacle where his peculiar genius may receive its due honor.
It was a characteristicfreakof fate that committedto Austin
and Molesworth and Grote, chiefs of modern radicalism, the
task of securing proper recognition for the most resolute
defenderof absolute monarchy. The work,however,was well
done, and to-day English politics and jurisprudence alike
look to Hobbes as their philosophical progenitor. His devo-
tion to the cause of monarchyis justly regardedas accidental
rather than essential in his general theory. Quite apart
from this incidental feature, the solid and enduring sub-
stance of his system is his doctrine of sovereignty-of the
ultimatenature of political and legal authority. The mathe-
matical precision of his analysis in this field forms a most
striking contrast to the confused thinking of most of his
contemporaries,and the English school of positive law has
done little more than develop the conceptionswhich he clearly
defined.
The veneration of Hobbes by his countrymenis thus jus-
tifiable. But though his work in the developmentof political
science was great and significant,it is quite wrong to suppose
that the historyof the theorywithwhichhis name is associated
begins withhim. ThoughtfulEnglishmennowadayssometimes
concede the insularityof their national character. It is this
quality, probably, that accounts for the common neglect of
Hobbes's continental forerunner. The same tendency is at
work in the common ascription of the theories of the social
contractand of popular sovereigntyto the writersof the Puri-
JEAAT BODIN ON SOVEREIGTY. 83
The dates which mark the limits of Bodin's life, 1530 and
1596, suggest at once the turmoilof his political environment.
It was the period that witnessed the extinctionamid imbecility
and crime of the house of Valois. The forces of feudalism;
revivedunderdecliningroyalauthority, and those ofreligiousani-
mosity,stimulatedby the Reformation,reduced France to anar-
chy. Imminentor actual civil war was forfourdecades the pre-
vailingcondition. It was the timeof the Guises, of Catherinede
No. i.] JEAN BODIN ON SOVEREIGNTY. 85
II.
In laying the foundationsfor his discussion of sovereignty,
Bodin follows pretty closely the lines of Aristotle's Politics.
The social basis and philosophicalend of the state; the analysis
of the family and the distinction between family and state;
the characteristicsof paternal authorityand the institutionof
slavery,-are all treated in a mannerthat stronglysuggests
the Greek precursor. But it cannot be said that Bodin is sub-
servient to the Stagirite in his conclusions. He is too true to
the Aristotelian method to attain Aristotelian results. In
philosophy based on history,the accident of chronologry must
profoundlyaffect differentsystems. The later writer has
necessarilymore historyfromwhich to generalize. Nineteen
centuries separated Bodin from Aristotle- centuries replete
with strikingsocial and political phenomena. That any of the
Greek's principles could be approved by the Frenchman, is
a great tribute to the former's genius ; that so many were
modifiedor rejected, is the surest basis for the renownof the
latter. The influenceswhich are most apparent where Bodin
diverges fromAristotle are those of Roman history and law,
Jewishtraditionand recent European history.
It is not my purpose to dwell on all the interestingfeatures
of the Republic outside of the doctrineof sovereignty. Some
of the more striking may be mentioned in passing. The
author formtulatesat the outset a definitionof the state (res-
pueblica) which suggests the most conspicuous characteristics
of his philosophy. "The state is an aggregationof families
and their commonpossessions, ruled by a sovereignpower and
by reason." I In this is implied,what the later chapters elab-
orate, that the basis of the state,both in historicaland in logical
development,is the family; that a distinction must be drawn
between interests that are common and those that are not;
that a supremepower is essential to the idea of the state; and
that governmentis conditioned by a moral end. By rational
1 " Respublica est familiarum summapotes-
rerumqueinteripsas communium,
tate ac rationemoderatamultitudo." Lib. i, cap. i.
go POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERLY. [VOL. XI.
III.
of the sover-
Zegzunferendarumwere but the commissioners
eignpopulusRomanus. Regents,viceroysand suchdignitaries
fallintoa like category. Yet Bodin takes care not to carry
the idea of " perpetual" too far. He is not readyto exclude
the conceptionof monarchfromthe scientifictreatmentof
politics. "But if,"he says,"we construeperpetualpoweras
that whichwill neverhave an end, sovereignty will have no
existencesave in the popularand thearistocraticstate; since
the people [only] is immortal,unless,indeed,it be utterly
exterminated."The lifetenureof supremepower,therefore,
constitutessovereignty in an individual. Sovereignty in this
sense may be bestowedby a people on an individual,or be
transferred fromone individualto another,and in eithercase
it is equallyvalid,so longas it is freefromcondition.
Justat thispointthereis obviousone ofthegaps in Bodin's
theory. He is at some pains to establishthe alienability of
sovereignty- that long and hotlycontestedpoint; but he
omits to account philosophically for the possessionof that
which he holds may be transferred.He is verynear to a
realizationand a solutionof the problemwhen he reflects on
the immortality of "the people,"as comparedwithany indi-
vidual. He mighthave distinguishedbetweenthe eternal
principleof orderand authority whichis impliedin the very
conceptionof an immortalpeople, and the power to issue
and enforcespecificcommandswhich is but an outcomeof
that principle. But here, as in so manyother partsof his
work,Bodinis preoccupiedwithhis purposeof justifying abso-
lutemonarchy;and he misses the chance to pass fromlegal
to thebroadergroundsof politicalsovereignty.
The supremacyimpliedin majestasis set forthby Bodin
withan abundanceof analysisand illustration.The essence
ofthe idea is embodiedin thewords" legibusso/uta." Sover-
eigntyhas its chiefand characteristic functionin the making
of laws.' Fromthebindingforceof theselaws,the sovereign
is by the natureof the case free. But notfromall laws. " If
1 Summumjus majestatisin eo potissimumversani,cumnon modo singulissed
etiamuniversisleges danturiisque imperatur.
94 POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERLY. [VOL. XI.
IV.
When we turn from Bodin to Hobbes, we find that the
latter,unlike the former,2leaves no uncertaintyin respect to
the origin of sovereignty. A deliberateact of volitionby each
memberof a communitytransfersall his rightsand powers to
some person or assembly of persons. In this transferis to be
found the originof the body politic,as distinct from a mere
inorganicmass of individuals. In the aggregate of rightsand
powers transferredis the essence of sovereignty. Right and
might are in Hobbes fundamentally identical; therefore,
supremacyof the sovereignover the individualspringsimmedi-
atelyfromsuperiorityof power. But Hobbes is not contentto
start fromthe mere fact of individualconsent as the condition
of political organization. The cause forthis consent is sought,
and is found in the instinct of self-preservation. Without
following the philosopher into his ingenious theory of the
"state of nature" and the "war of all against all," his conclu-
sion is that for self-preservationmen's reason teaches the
necessity of certain rules, conformityto which is indispensable
to social existence. These rules require,among other things,
the abandonmentby the individualof his natural rights,which
1 From as far back as the time of Philip the Fair the lawyersof the rising
French monarchyhad scoffedat the pretensionsof the emperors; and legal
tradition probably aided Bodin in his criticism. Cf. Poole, Illustrations of
MediaevalThought. 2 Ante,p. 93.
IOO POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERLY. [VOL. XI.
V.
From the standpointof pure speculation,it is impossible to
deny that Hobbes's doctrineis more complete and perfectthan
that of Bodin. Where the latter, with the caution of the
philosophicstatesman,hesitated,the former,with the indiffer-
ence of the exact mathematician,followed the path of his
reasoning to the end. The student of historyand law is not
apt to be as confidentas the devotee of the physical sciences,
in regard to the availability of abstract formulasfor solving
political problems. The hostilityaroused by the ethical4 and
1 Leviathan,p. 87.
2 " Where there is no commonwealththereis . . . a perpetual war of every
man against his neighbor; and thereforeeverythingis his that gettethit and
keepethit by force; whichis neitherproprietynor community, but uncertainty."
Leviathan,p. I I6.
3 While Bodin, as stated above, looks upon custom as lacking the character
of law until the sovereign signifiespositivelyhis will in respect to it, Hobbes
regards the silence of the sovereign as expressinghis will. "When long use
obtaineththe authorityof a law, it is not the length of time that maketh the
authority,but the will of the sovereign signifiedby his silence." Leviathan,
p. 124.
4 It must be pointedout, however,that in one importantinstancecriticism of
Hobbes is generallyunfair. He is censuredgreatlyforholdingthat no law,i.e.,ex-
pressionof the will of the sovereign,can be unjust. He does, no doubt,say pre-
ciselythat. But he has so definedjustice as to include underthe termonlypartof
theidea usuallyconnotedthereby. Justice,he says,is onlythekeepingofpromises;
and the originalcontractinvolveda promiseof submissionto thesovereign. Dis-
obedience,therefore, is unjust. But this sense of justice involves onlywhat is
I04 I POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERL Y