0% found this document useful (0 votes)
73 views3 pages

Solutions For Exercise Sheet 1

This document contains solutions to exercises in probability theory. Exercise 1.1 discusses measurable maps between probability spaces. It gives an example of a non-measurable map and calculates the number of measurable maps between two simple probability spaces. Exercise 1.2 examines whether the sum of random variables is itself a random variable, and gives a counterexample. Exercise 1.3 considers the algebra and sigma-algebra generated by finite subsets of the real line. Exercise 1.4 defines the completion of a sigma-algebra and shows it is indeed a sigma-algebra, and extends a measure on the original sigma-algebra to the completion in a consistent way.

Uploaded by

EDU CIPANA
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
73 views3 pages

Solutions For Exercise Sheet 1

This document contains solutions to exercises in probability theory. Exercise 1.1 discusses measurable maps between probability spaces. It gives an example of a non-measurable map and calculates the number of measurable maps between two simple probability spaces. Exercise 1.2 examines whether the sum of random variables is itself a random variable, and gives a counterexample. Exercise 1.3 considers the algebra and sigma-algebra generated by finite subsets of the real line. Exercise 1.4 defines the completion of a sigma-algebra and shows it is indeed a sigma-algebra, and extends a measure on the original sigma-algebra to the completion in a consistent way.

Uploaded by

EDU CIPANA
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 3

TU München Probability Theory

Zentrum Mathematik Summer Term 2013/14


Lehrstuhl für Wahrscheinlichkeitstheorie Berger/Salvi/Miller

Solutions for Exercise sheet 1


σ-Algebras, Measurable Maps and Random Variables
Solution for Exercise 1.1

(i) The identity is measurable.


(ii) Take the map X : Ω1 → Ω2 such that X(1) = 1, X(2) = 1 and X(3) = 2. X is ot
measurable, since the pre-image of the set {1} ∈ F2 is the set {1, 2} 6∈ F1 .
(iii) There are 33 = 27 different maps between Ω1 and Ω2 (for each of the 3 elements in
Ω1 there are 3 possibile images in Ω2 ). Only 15 of them are measurable. Keeping
X(1) = 1, there are five possibilities for the images of 2 and 3:
• 2→1 and 3 → 1;
• 2→2 and 3 → 3;
• 2→3 and 3 → 2;
• 2→2 and 3 → 2;
• 2→3 and 3 → 3.
The same holds when we keep X(1) = 2 or X(1) = 3, for a total of 15 combina-
tions. All the other maps are not measurable (see e.g., part (ii)).

Solution for Exercise 1.2

(i) If X and Y are random variables, then also Z = X + Y is a random variable.


In fact, we only have to verify (see Hint) that {ω ∈ Ω : X(ω) + Y (ω) < q} ∈ F
Q
for all q ∈ . We can rewrite
{X + Y < q} = {X < q − Y }
[ 
= {X < a} ∩ {a < q − Y } .
a∈ Q
Q
Since {X < a} and {a < q − Y } are in F for each a ∈ (by measurability of X
and Y ), also the countable union of the intersection of such events is in F.
(ii) If X + Y is a random variable, X and Y do not have necessarily to be random
variables. As an easy counterexample take Ω = {ω1 , ω2 , ω3 , ω4 } equipped with
the σ-algebra F = {Ω, {ω1 , ω2 }, {ω3 , ω4 }, ∅} and the following random variables:
X : Ω → R such that X(ω1 ) = 1, X(ω2 ) = 2, X(ω3 ) = 1, X(ω4 ) = 2, and
Y : Ω → R such that Y (ω1 ) = −1, Y (ω2 ) = −2, Y (ω3 ) = −1, Y (ω4 ) = −2, .
Then neither X nor Y is a random variable (e.g., X −1 (2) = {ω2 , ω4 } 6∈ F), but
X + Y ≡ 0 is constant, hence measurable.
Solution for Exercise 1.3
The first version of the exercise was misunderstandable, sorry for that. |A| could be
intended as the cardinality of A or as its Lebesgue measure. This does not make a
big difference for the purposes of part (i), but can make things trickyer for part (ii).
Apologies.
(i) F is an algebra:
– Ω= R is in F, since Ωc = ∅ is clearly finite.
– If A, B ∈ F and are finite, then also A ∩ B is finite. If, w.l.o.g., Ac and B are
finite, then A∩B is finite. If both Ac and B c are finite, then (A∩B)c = Ac ∪B c
is also finite.
– If A ∈ F is finite, then (Ac )c is of course finite, so that Ac ∈ F, too. If on the
other hand A ∈ F and Ac is finite, then it is clear that Ac ∈ F.
BUT F is not a σ-algebra! Take for example A1 ,S
A2 , ... such that Ai = {i} for all
N
i ∈ . Then clearly Ai ∈ F for all i´s, but A = ∞i=1 Ai is not: both A = and N
c
R N
A = \ are not finite.
(ii) We have to enlarge F to the smallest σ-algebra containing F. Consider
F̃ = {A ⊂ R : either A is countable or Ac is countable}.
We claim that F̃ = σ(F).
– σ(F) ⊆ F̃ : since clearly F ⊂ F̃ , all we have to do is to show that F̃ is a
σ-algebra.
∗ R ∈ F̃ is again ok.
∗ If A, B ∈ F̃ and are countable, then also A ∩ B is countable. If, w.l.o.g.,
Ac and B are countable, then A ∩ B is countable. If both Ac and B c are
countable, then (A ∩ B)c = Ac ∪ B c is also countable.
∗ If A ∈ F̃ is countable, then (Ac )c is of course countable, so that Ac ∈ F̃ ,
too. If on the other hand A ∈ F̃ and Ac is countable, then it is clear that
Ac ∈ F̃ .
∗ Finally, the countable union of countable sets is again countable.
– F̃ ⊆ σ(F): this is maybe the hardest part. Let A ∈ F̃ be countable (otherwise
we can apply the same way of reasoning to Ac ). Then there exists a bijection b
N
between A and . Let S

N
Ak := b−1 ({1, 2, ..., k}) for all k ∈ . Note
S∞ that each Ak
is in F and that A = i=1 Ai . Since, by definition of σ(F), i=1 Ai ∈ σ(F),
we have that also A ∈ σ(F).

Solution for Exercise 1.4

(i) Clearly A ⊆ Aµ , since every element of A is also in Aµ (take E = F = A in the


definition of Aµ ).
We have to prove the four σ-algebra properties:
(i) Ω ∈ Aµ is clear (take E = F = Ω in the definition of Aµ ).
(ii) Take A1 and A2 in Aµ . We have to prove that A1 ∩ A2 ∈ Aµ .
We know that there exist E1 , E2 , F1 , F2 ∈ A such that: Ei ⊆ Ai ⊆ Fi and
µ(Fi \ Ei ) = 0 for i = 1, 2. First observe that E1 ∩ E2 ∈ A and F1 ∩ F2 ∈ A.
Also, by De Morgan laws, (F1 ∩ F2 ) \ (E1 ∩ E2 ) ⊆ (F1 \ E1 ) ∪ (F2 \ E2 ) so that
the l.h.s. has zero µ measure, being a subset of the union of two zero-measure
sets. Now, it easy to see that E1 ∩ E2 ⊆ A1 ∩ A2 ⊆ F1 ∩ F2 , so we are done.
(iii) If A ∈ Aµ , with E and F as before, A 3 F c ⊆ Ac ⊆ E c ∈ A and µ(E c \ F c ) =
0 (if this was not the case, than there would exist C ⊆ E c \F c with µ(C) > 0,
and we would arrive to the contradiction µ(F \ E) ≥ µ(C) > 0).
(iv) For proving the property for infite intersections, just repeat the argument of
part (ii) for infitely many Ai ´s.

(ii) µ̄(A) = µ(A) for A ∈ A is clearly true by the definition of µ̄. We are left to show
that µ̄ is indeed a measure on Aµ .

• µ̄(∅) = 0 is again clear;


• Now take A1 , A2 , ... ∈ Aµ disjoint sets. Let E1 , E2 , ... ∈ A and F1 , F2 , ... ∈ A
be such that Ei ⊆ Ai ⊆ Fi and µ(Fi \ Ei ) = 0 (i.e., µ(Ei ) = µ(Fi )). Then it
follows that µ(Ei ) = µ̄(Ei ) ≤ µ̄(Ai ) ≤ µ̄(Fi ) = µ(Fi ). At this point it easy to
see that, since also the Ei ´s have to be disjoint,

X ∞
X ∞
[  ∞
[ 
µ̄(Ai ) = µ̄(Ei ) = µ̄ Ei = µ̄ Ai .
i=1 i=1 i=1 i=1

You might also like