EXISTENTIALISM Book NOTES 2017-18
EXISTENTIALISM Book NOTES 2017-18
EXISTENTIALISM Book NOTES 2017-18
Aluva 1, 2017-2018
EXISTENTIALISM
PART ONE
1. General Introduction
Greek and Hebraic tradition of human history unfolds the quest for
human transcendence; for the Greek tradition it was achieved by the
abstraction of reason beyond the temporal particularities of
existence; and for the Hebraic tradition, the experience of
transcendence is understood in terms of faith in an
incomprehensible God. Human existence is frail, finite, naked, and
filled with sin before the unknowable God. The book of Job presents
the plight of human existence and the incomprehensible majesty of
the divine. The idea of the eternal can be revealed in human
passionate commitments that are finite and temporal. The agonies
and cries of the people can in certain sense is taken to the beyond
dimension where transcendence comes to pass in the concrete bare
human existence who inhabits this world.
1.2 History
The back ground and history of existentialism could be seen from the
existential context of the 19th century Europe. Philosophers who
debated the meaning of life in 19th-century Europe were trying to
understand what it meant to have a 'self' and how human beings
could live an ethical existence. While mathematicians and scientists
explored the natural laws of the universe, religious people and
theologians discussed God's expectations for a good life and the
human soul. At the same time, social scientists tried to explain
economic and social phenomena through methods involving logic
and reason. In comparison to the vastness of the universe, it's not
surprising that human experiences and lives often seemed brief and
insignificant. Inevitably, people may have wondered: 'Why do so
many bad things happen to good people?' And if there was an
omnipotent being, why did that being seem indifferent rather than
interested in what happened to us?
1.3Types of Existentialism
In term of the existence and relevance of God, there are three
schools of existentialism thought:
1. Theistic Existentialism ( Kierkegaard, Buber, and Marcel)
2. Atheistic Existentialism ( Sartre, de Beauvoir, and Camus)
3. Agnostic Existentialism (Heidegger)
4. Literary Existentialism (Kafka and Dostoyevsky)
2. GENERAL CHARACTERISTICS
According to existentialists, human beings spend their lives in a void
plagued by angst and despair in a world defined by alienation and
absurdity. Absurdity refers to the persistence of human beings in
living out our lives, despite little evidence that what we do matters in
the greater universe. We create meaning in our lives even when there
is little or no evidence of a natural force or omnipotent being
protecting or guiding us. We simply continue to exist
aimlessly.Existentialists also used words like 'authenticity' and
experience, instead of viewing your experience as defined by outside
forces, such as God, the greater society or the universe.
Jean Paul Sartre likewise speaks of the need for a truly authentic
existence, even though his intellectual climate is that of an avowed
atheist. Sartre’s man, who is “to freedom condemned,” must choose
resolutely, despite the fact that he has absolutely no basis for his
choices. One who refuses to choose is guilty of bad faith, which is
always associated with an inauthentic existence.
7
For the early Camus, the The Myth of Sisyphus, Cross Purpose and
The Stranger, authentic existence is a life amidst the absurd.
Authenticity of existence demands a rejection of both physical and
philosophical suicide. Sisyphus, who defiantly scorns the gods who
have condemned him to roll his stone endlessly, is the
personification of authentic existence. For the later Camus, authentic
existence has moved from an ethics of sheer quantity to an ethics of
quality. A common brotherhood of man, an insistence that there
must be a difference between stoking the Nazi crematory fires and
devoting one’s life to the care of lepers, the emphasis on limits and
on stable essences or natures in the context of early Greek
philosophy—these postures characterize an authenticity of existence
in the later Camus.
2.8 Freedom
For the existentialists, no idea is more central than freedom. As
Kierkegaard puts it, “the most tremanedous thing which has been
granted to man is choice [and] freedom.” A centruaryy later Sartre
will refer to freedom as the defining feature of existentialism. “at the
10
Most pessimistic belief systems find the source of their despair in the
fixed imperfection of human nature or of the human context;
however, the existentialist, denies all absolute principles and holds
that human nature is fixed only in that we have agreed to recognise
certain attributes. It is therefore subject to change by a single
individual if he acts bravely in contradiction to the accepted
principles. Therefore, for the existentialist, the possibilities of
altering human nature and society are unlimited, but at the same
time, individuals can hope for help in making such alterations only
from within themselves.
3. TERMS IN EXISTENTIALISM
3.1 The Absurd: The absurd can occur only when two elements are
present: our desire to explain “reality,” and the recognition that the
world is not thus explicable, but that it exists without apparent
justification, foundation or purpose.
3.2 Nausea: Nausea is the feeling of repulsion that overtakes us
when we become aware of the absurdity of existence, the
“meaninglessness” of life.
3.3 Anguish: Anguish is the normal condition of those who become
aware of their total liberty, and of the fact that there are no universal
values to justify the choices they have made.
3.4 Authentic: Individuals who have grasped and accepted the fact
that they are free, who have realised what their situation is, and who
11
PART TWO
Introduction
Anti-Hegel
Kierkegaard’s basic outlook is the very antithesis of Hegel’s. Whereas
the latter sought to reconcile oppositions and to blend and integrate
opposite ends of the spectrum into one reconciling synthesis, which
would blunt neither extreme, Kierkegaard called for a clear-cut
radical commitment one way or the other. If the Hegelian ideal was
both/and, Kierkegaard upheld a strict either/or. Which, as we know,
is the verytitle of ne of his most well-known works?
The crowd
Kierkegaard was of the opinion that the journey to selfhood will
succeed to the extent that one rises above the values, goals and
attitudes of the common herd and strives to realize his unique
unrepeatable identity. “a crowd… in its very concept is the untruth,
by reason, of the fact that it renders the individual completely
impenitent and irresponsible, or at least weakens his sense of
responsibility by reducing it to a fraction.” (The point of view) he
completely reject the Hegelian notion of man realizing his true
essence in proportion as he distances himself from what is taken to
be mere particularity and becomes a moment in the life of the
12
PHILOSOPHY OF GOD
God’s Existence
Kierkegaard’s main thesis about the existence of God is that it can
only be known by the leap of faith. It is a question of being willing to
“let the proof go” and make the saltomortale as some have described
it (the mortal leap). In any case, Kierkegaard was reluctant to apply
the term “existence” to God for he understands the word as denoting
our own finite and temporal mode of being. Existence can, however,
be used to high-light the great paradox of the incarnation, whereby
16
The Prophet
A telling extract form Kierkegaard’s journal. 1853, reads, “I have
something upon my conscience as a writer. Let me indicate precisely
how I feel about it. There is something quite definite I have to say,
and I have it so much upon my conscience that (as I feel) I dare not
die without having uttered it. For the instant I die… the question will
be put to me: ‘hast thou uttered the definite message quite
definitely?’ and if I have not done so, what then?” several entries in
the journals and a whole spate of attacks on the contemporary
religious establishment make it clear that Kierkegaard was sincerely
convinced that god has called him, as another Jeremiah, to launch a
scathing attack on the compromising, fawning attitudes of the local
Christian church. As he put it later in the same journal, “let us collect
all the New Testaments we have, let us bring them out to an open
square or up to the summit of a mountain, and, while we all kneel, let
one man speak to god thus: take this book back again; we men, such
as we are, are not fit to go in for this sort of thing, it only makes us
unhappy. ‘This is my proposal, that like those inhabitants in Gesara
we beseech Christ to depart from our borders. This would be an
honest and human way of talking – rather different from the
disgusting hypocritical priestly fudge about life having no value for
us without this priceless blessing which is Christianity.”
Philosophical Anthropology
Martin Buber’s major philosophic works in English are the widely
read I and Thou (1923), a collection of essays from the 1920s and 30s
published as Between Man and Man, a collection of essays from the
1950s published as The Knowledge of Man: Selected
Essays and Good and Evil: Two Interpretations (1952). For many
thinkers Buber is the philosopher of I and Thou and he himself often
suggested one begin with that text. However, his later essays
articulate a complex and worthy philosophical anthropology.
The “I” of man differs in both modes of existence. The “I” may be
taken as the sum of its inherent attributes and acts, or it may be
taken as a unitary, whole, irreducible being. The “I” of the “I-It”
relation is a self-enclosed, solitary individual (der Einzige) that takes
itself as the subject of experience. The “I” of the “I-Thou” relation is a
whole, focused, single person (der Einzelne) that knows itself
as subject. In later writings Buber clarified that inner life is not
exhausted by these two modes of being. However, when man
presents himself to the world he takes up one of them.
profound than it actually is. Buber acknowledges that the text was
written in a state of inspiration. For this reason it is especially
important to also read his later essays, which are more clearly
written and rigorously argued. E. la B. Cherbonnier notes in
“Interrogation of Martin Buber” that every objective criticism of
Buber’s philosophy would belong, by definition, to the realm of “I-It”.
Given the incommensurability of the two modes, this means no
objective criticism of the “I-Thou” mode is possible. In his response
Buber explains that he is concerned to avoid internal contradiction
and welcomes criticism. However, he acknowledges that his
intention was not to create an objective philosophic system but to
communicate an experience.
Only man truly distances, Buber argues, and hence only man has a
“world.” Man is the being through whose existence what “is” becomes
recognized for itself. Animals respond to the other only as embedded
within their own experience, but even when faced with an enemy,
man is capable of seeing his enemy as a being with similar emotions
and motivations. Even if these are unknown , we are able to
recognize that these unknown qualities of the other are “real” while
our fantasies about the other are not. Setting at a distance is hence
not the consequence of a reflective, “It” attitude, but the precondition
for all human encounters with the world, including reflection.
Buber argues that every stage of the spirit, however primal, wishes to
form and express itself. Form assumes communication with an
interlocutor who will recognize and share in the form one has made.
Distance and relation mutually correspond because in order for the
world to be grasped as a whole by a person, it must be distanced and
independent from him and yet also include him, and his attitude,
perception, and relation to it. Consequently, one cannot truly have a
world unless one receives confirmation of one’s own substantial and
independent identity in one’s relations with others.
Buber explains that imagination is the source of both good and evil.
The “evil urge” in the imagination generates endless possibilities.
This is fundamental and necessary, and only becomes “evil” when it
is completely separated from direction. Man’s task is not to eradicate
the evil urge, but to reunite it with the good, and become a whole
being. The first stage of evil is “sin,” occasional directionlessness.
Endless possibility can be overwhelming, leading man to grasp at
anything, distracting and busying himself, in order to not have to
make a real, committed choice. The second stage of evil is
“wickedness,” when caprice is embraced as a deformed substitute for
genuine will and becomes characteristic. If occasional caprice is sin,
27
Buber interprets the claim that in the end the good are rewarded and
the bad punished as the experience the bad have of their own
fragmentation, insubstantiality and “non-existence.” Arguing that
evil can never be done with the whole being, but only out of inner
contradiction, Buber states that the lie or divided spirit is the specific
evil that man has introduced into nature. Here “lie” denotes a self
that evades itself, as manifested not just in a gap between will and
action, but more fundamentally, between will and will. Similarly,
“truth” is not possessed but is rather lived in the person who affirms
his or her particular self by choosing direction. This process, Buber
argues, is guided by the presentiment implanted in each of us of who
we are meant to become.
f. Hindrances to Dialogue
Along with the evasion of responsibility and refusal to direct one’s
possibilities described in Good and Evil: Two
Interpretations (1952), Buber argues in “Elements of the
Interhuman” (1957, in The Knowledge of Man) that the main
obstacle to dialogue is the duality of “being” (Sein) and “seeming”
(Schein). Seeming is the essential cowardice of man, the lying that
frequently occurs in self-presentation when one seeks to
communicate an image and make a certain impression. The fullest
manifestation of this is found in the propagandist, who tries to
impose his own reality upon others. Corresponding to this is the rise
of “existential mistrust” described in Buber’s 1952 address at
Carnegie Hall, “Hope for this Hour” (in Pointing the Way). Mistrust
takes it for granted that the other dissembles, so that rather than
genuine meeting, conversation becomes a game of unmasking and
uncovering unconscious motives. Buber criticizes Marx, Nietzsche
and Freud for meeting the other with suspicion and perceiving the
28
1.3 Mystery
And then, one fine day, the mind comes up against not this or that
aspect of being but being itself- being as being, as Aristotle would
say. The temptation, of course, is to make use of the same technique
of reduction: to envelop being, to surround it, to gaze upon it, to
decompose it into abstractelements and to categorize these according
to various logical heads “valid” for “thought in general”. Putting the
same thing in other words, we could say that
“problematisation”consists of making an irreducible opposition
between subject and object, between “the in me and the before me”,
31
2.2 Inter-subjectivity
However, through my body, I am not open to the physical cosmos
only. As a human person, I am essentially open to the “other”: to
other human persons. But my relation to other persons can be of two
types. First, I can look upon “the other” as a mere object, an
instrument for my self-gratification – such as when, in a “broken
world”, I judge a person in terms of his functions and use him for my
benefit in that regard, nothing more. This happenswhen I treat a bus-
conductor as a bus-conductor and no more, never thinking of him as
person or respecting him so. But I can also view a person as a subject
– not an “it” or a “he” or a “she” (i.e., in effect, as an object) but as a
thou (French, tu, Germen Du). Here we are relating, as subjects: we
are on the plane of intersubjectivity. At this level I experience
disposability (deponibilite, making oneself available, as a person, for
another). At the interpersonal, intersubjective level, participation in
32
man can discover and encounter God. But, one can refuse to, also.
It’s a question of deponibilite: as in any possible intersubjective
relationship, it’s up to me. I can make myself available to “the other”
as a person, or I can prefer to remain within the limits of my egoism
– I can prefer to be un-available.
human thought. Nor is it, under pressure from our scientific age to
be now made a kind of handmaid of science: providing and analyzing
the basic scientific concepts. Nor are we justified by making
philosophy into the study of this or that existent, a being chosen out
of the many. Indeed, this is what often happens. Consciously or
unconsciously, philosophy settles down to be the study of a being.
Either we imagine that we are studying Being while we are treating of
the alleged sum total of existents under that name. But such a totality
is still a being and nothing more.
No “science” of Being
It is an understandable temptation for philosophy to try to prove its
worth by trying to make of itself a “science”. Understandable,
because we live in a technological age in which only that which is
“science” seems to command respect. And once again, there are not
lacking those who try to make philosophy a science among other
sciences, calling it the science of knowledge (epistemology and
nothing more) or the science of correct argumentation (logic) or
whatever. But- and here jaspers show his Kantian roots- philosophy
cannot be a science. And this also because Being cannot be
objectified, as science does to its subject matter. Once we objectify
Being we make it a being. Even the “totality of all that is”- which is
what some people image they study when they make philosophy a
“science”- ends up by reducing this totality to an instance to Being.
In any case such a “totality” is only an imaginary being:” it can never
by the “object” of a “science”. And, as japers never wearies of
reminding us, we never have an experience of pure Being, only of
beings which are, at most, particular manifestation of it.
PHILOSOPHY OF MAN
The “prophetic” philosopher
One of the great formative influence on the mind of jaspers was the
sociologist and economist, Max Weber, whom he hailed as “the last
genuine national German; genuine because he represented… not the
37
will to power for one’s own empire- at any price and above all
others-, but the will to realize a spiritual and moral existence which
he holds its ground by power but also places this power itself under
its own conditions.” (Philosophical autobiography) no doubt Weber
inspired him in his development of the notion of “prophetic
philosophy” which he once briefly (and ambiguously) summed up as
“a substitute for religion.” This was a notion that the grim experience
of Nazi Germany brought out all the more, when youth deserted the
quest for truth to join the bullying gangs of Hitler Youth and
University professors let themselves become mere propaganda tools
for the Reich.
The idea was reaffirmed in the already sixties where the breakdown
of conventional religion left host of young people without religious
guides and prophets in their search for meaning. All these
developments emphasized the need for the philosopher to discharge
his eternal “prophetic” role, filling in the spiritual vacuum which
religion and its ministers could no longer respond to. The
philosopher, like another Max Weber, would have to awaken in man
“philosophical faith” (cf. below) from which spiritual values and
perhaps a new springtime for religion could be born. Above all, the
“prophetic philosopher” had the responsibility of reminding man of
that dimension of transcendence in his life; lead him to recognize its
possibility and, finally, make the leap of “philosophical faith” which it
invited.
Philosophical faith
In jaspers elaboration of “philosophical faith” we can see the
influence of both Kant and Kierkegaard. I encounter transcendence
in the very act of encountering my limitedness. This, for instance, is
felt in moments of great crisis, such as the death of a loved one or in
a moment of failure. But from then on it is only a leap of
“philosophical faith” that can lead me further. The transcendent is to
be apprehended not by any proof, not even by a kind of mystical
experience- both of these would reduce it to a kind of object. This can
only be done by freely deciding to affirm it as my truth, in the
exercise of my liberty. It is called “philosophical” faith to distinguish
39
The famous quotation from Von Der Wahrheit (1947) is well known:
“he (the one god) is the encompassing of all encompassing and (he)
aroused the deepest, absolute trust, he is the power… and the
greatest closeness which has its place within the inwardness of man.
He is providence, not fate; inscrutably he guides in inconceivable
judgment.” But he immediately adds, “But whatever is said about
him, is immediately also false.” This is understandable. For,
according to him, to speak of the transcendent is to objectify it and
this is to falsity it. That is why jaspers prefer to speak of the
“illuminating” function of philosophy, “showing” what cannot really
be “said”.
40
Hannah ardent, for one, dubbed him “the secret king of thought”.
For Coplestion, after wrestling with a particularly knotty issue in his
writings, once asked, “Does ambiguity belong to the essence of
Heidegger’s thought?” hence, we should go into this ticklish issue at
the outset. Why is Heidegger so difficult, so obscure? Is it plain
intellectual cussedness, an unnecessary over-mystification of things?
Or is there some deeper, inner necessity at work? On our response to
that question will depend very much the effort we are prepared to
put into breaking the heideggerian code!
A response
41
Invariably, to maintain the imagery, we should not seek out the big,
well-frequented highways: they tend to circle the forest or take the
quickest route through it. They are not interested in exploring the
forest but merely in moving through it and get on to some pace else
considered more important. What we should look for is the
“woodman’s path” (Holzweg). Such paths are made by men who are
interested in the forest. They invariably lead to the very heart of all,
to a clearing (Lichtung). Thence we can follow up other such paths –
wegmarken (road-markers), Unterwege (approacahes), Feldwege
(paths across the field) – invariably in circular, exploratory
movements. These are paths not familiar to the usual run of travelers
and so will seem unusual and odd. This explains the “oddness” of the
language Heidegger will use. Traditional language and approaches,
according to him, but skirt the issue or hurry through it. They aren’t
geared to exploring, going deeper into.
Let us follow, then, this path, the path suggested by etymologies. This
path ‘summons us back’, ‘reclaims us’, ‘revokes us’ a pilgrimage to
the well-springs of Greek thought. And we begin to recognize that the
Greek language “is no mere language like the European languages
known to us. The Greek language and it alone is logos… in the Greek
language what is said is at the same time, and in an eminent way,
that which it is called (is designated as). If we hear a Greek word with
a Greek ear, we follow its legein(speaking), its direct immediate
presentation of what it says.” And he adds the sentence with which
has concluded the last section, “through the audible Greek word we
are directly in the presence to the thing itself, not first in the
presence of a mere word-sign.” This is what Steiner calls Heidegger’s
“etymological realism”, Heidegger’s conviction that Greek words (at
last once upon a time), since they stood at the origin of western
philosophizing and of many western languages (this applies, really,
44
such a value because that is what “one” in this country or social class
or whatever is expected to do. Instead of living as a man (der mann)
he has settled for being an impersonal, anonymous “One” is
supposed to believe.
thus open to Being. Man is thus one who stands in a special relation
to Being and also one who has some kind of preliminary ideas of
Being. To ask a question, as Heidegger so perceptively remarks,
implies already some vague knowledge of what that thing is. It is the
vagueness of this knowledge that moves us to seek a deeper
understanding or Being. On the other hand, we can only attain this
deeper understanding because we already have some kind of grasp of
it at the start, however hazy. This is Heidegger’s famous
“hermeneutical circle”.
An indifferentist, then?
If Heidegger is not positively an atheist, is he, at least, an
indifferentist? That is, one who couldn’t be bothered whether God
existed or not. The answer is, once again, no. it is just that the
question of the existence of God cannot, according to Heidegger, be
raised on the plane of the existential analysis of Dasein. The God
issue if related to the level of “the essence of the holy”. Modern man,
however, is so preoccupied with the world and his projects that he is
not normally open to this level. But his is not tantamount to
affirming that God is dead for modern man, in the Nietzschean
sense. Heidegger tells us that his philosophy is awaiting a new
manifestation of the divine and, in fact, this is the problem of the
world. Still, poets like Holderlin (Heidegger’s favorite) bear witness,
in some obscure and prophetic way, to the divine.
V FREDERICH NIETZSCHE
Introduction
Two Moralities
It was, again, in Beyond Good and Evil that Nietzsche
expounded his discovery of the tv c types of morality that
divide the human species: “slave morality” and “master
morality”. It effect, “slaves” are those who - for religious or
51
The Superman
The word that Nietzsche coined in this connection,
Uebermensch, literally means Overman and that is how it is
sometimes translated, but it is the more amendable
Superman that seems to have won out. The Superman
stands for the one who surrenders himself fully to the Will
to Power and attains its fullest expression. As such, it is
more a goal to be achieved than an actual person. What
would such a person be like? Nietzsche interestingly
characterizes him as “the Roman Caesar with Christ’s soul”,
a fusion of all that is macho and beautiful with all that i>
constitutive of inner depth and maturity. “Man is a rope
52
Nietzsche on Woman
The Superman is necessarily masculine. Nietzsche, clearly a
misogynist, had no place for ; Superwoman. For him, the
chief - indeed, the only - merit of woman was that she be the
mother of a future manly warrior, a potential Superman.
“Man shall be trained for war, and woman for the recreation
of the warrior”, he pontificates in Zarathustra, “All else is
folly”. And he concludes the section on Woman in that book
with the telling advice: “Thou goest to women" Remember
thy whip!” in a later section on Friendship he assures us,
“Woman is not yet capable of friendship, she knoweth only
love” (and by that last word he means crude sex). And he
sums it all up bluntly, “Women are yet ever cats and birds.
Or, at best, cows”.
Nietzsche on Christianity
We have already had occasion to recall some of Nietzsche’s
shrill diatribes against Christianity, calling it, among other
things, “the immortal curse of mankind”. Indeed, his
scurrillous attacks on the religion of his childhood are
rivalled only by his harsh words against Judaism, which,
according to him, laid the seeds of that other-worldliness
and negation of the earth that would be carried on in
Christianity. Understandably, priests are seen as the arch-
culprits, the propagators of a mascochistic, world-hating
and pro-slave spirituality. They are “insidious dwarfs”, “a
parasitical human type”, “anointed world traducers”,
“venomous spiders of life”, the “cleverest of conscious
hypocrites” and much else besides. And the most
outstanding examples of such men are the Jesuits!
However, as we shall see in the critical comments, to be fair
to Nietzshce, we must quote other passages where he seems
55
Eternal Recurrence
This doctrine, allegedly glimpsed by Nietzsche in his early
writings and only later spelt out in all clarity and boldness,
came to be presented by him as the touchstone of a genuine
“yes- attitude” to life: only the one who could joyfully accept
this doctrine was saying a yes to the Will to Power. Of
course, the idea of a cyclic return of all persons and events
in the world was nothing new. Nietzsche had come across it
in the Indian and Greek authors he had studied. He sought
to give it some evidential basis in the manifestation of
nature as a closed circle, repeating itself again and again ...
and in the notion of reincarnation. In his late writing, The
56
Sartrean Ontology
Writers are drawing attention, these days, to the new ontology
implicit in all existential works. Though we may not go so far as to
hold with some that existentialism is but a neo-metaphysics, one
cannot deny that, for Sartre, his philosophy of reality is the key to
making sense of his philosophy, including, above all, his views on the
absurdity of things. Key words, here, are being-in-itself, being-for-
itself and nothingness. Sartrean ontology sees reality as basically
comprising subjects and objects. The former are being-for-itself
(pour soi), the latter make up the being-in-itself (ensoi). The ensoi is
primarily the fixed, static world of material objects around us. But it
can also include conscious individual beings – myself or others-
insofar as they are views as an object of introspection or objective
study. The pour soi is that which has awareness– it is not necessary
that this subject be always actually thinking or deliberating.
57
More and more writers, now days, are drawing attention to the new
ontology implicit in existential works. We may not go so far as to
characterize the movement, as some critics do, “a kind of neo-
metaphysics and nothing more.” still, especially for Sartre, a grasp of
a particular existentialist ontology is pre-requisite for understanding
his philosophical outlook. Indeed, Sartre’s “anti-theology” and his
vision of man as a “useless passion”, together with his thesis of the
absurd are all founded on hi ontology. After all, the sub-title of Being
and Nothingness is “a phenomenological essay on ontology”. Key
notions, here, are being-in-itself (ensoi), being –for-itself (pour soi)
and nothingness (neant). Let us take a brief clarificatory look at each.
Being-in-itself (ensoi)
This is the first of the two major categories within which all reality
falls. Being-in –itself can roughly be identified with objects.
However, let us rememb4er that under this heading comes not only
the material things of our daily existence (trees, tables, buildings and
so on), but every conscious beings – myself and other persons,
whenever we contemplate them objectively, either thought detached
introspection or cold observation. The notion of being-in-itself
implies fixity. Mere static being there, no scope for spontaneity,
freedom of development. It is a finished product, inert and passive.
When I treat a conscious being as an object, as explained above, I
reduce it to a defined and rigid thing.
Nothingness
In his imaginary exchange between Heidegger and Sartre, Joseph
Fell has Sartre remarked to Heidegger that they have “nothing” in
common. And this is literally true. The notion of “nothing” (le neant
for Sartre and das Nichts for Heidegger) is made good use of by both
philosophers. In fact, Sartre is indebted to Heidegger for it though, it
must be admitted, in the formers’ hands it has no longer the same
significance. The fact is further complicated by the fact that,
according to me, le neant has two distinct (though not wholly
unrelated) connotations. First, it can be seen as a kind of synonym
for the pour-soi, as being properly identifies the finished product
that is the en-soi. Then – and this is its primary significance in
Sartre – it is a necessary by-product of the work of consciousness (le
pour-soi). For, it its function of observing things, (l’ensoi) it detaches
some objects from others and gives meaning or form to them. In
effect, it is at the same time, by its ignoring or disregarding the rest
of things, it temporarily annihilates them, inasmuch as it leaves them
formless and meaningless. This process, Sartre calls
neant(annihilation).
Surplus
This is how I render the associated word de trop. No sooner does
Sartre realize that the material world is inexplicable – that is,
meaningless- in its particularity, does he recognize, to his horror,
that his existence is equally unaccountable for. He, as much as the
root, is merely “there”; there is no reason why the particular person
he is, or the particular thing anything is, should be there. All are
equally unnecessary, unjustifiable, surplus, de trop “I exited just like
a stone, a plant, a microbe.” Neither I, nor any of these things, have
any right to exist.
Nausea
The profusion of unnecessary and incomprehensible things is enough
to fill sensitive Roguentin with horror … Nausea. They intrude upon
him, as it were, and Sartre never tires to use the crudest images to
represent the “existential panic” their ineluctable abundance can
produce: “Soft monstrous masses, in disorder-naked, with a frightful
and obscene nudity.” In speaking of his own-and man’s –fact of
being de trop, he prefers metaphors borrowed from the most basic
bodily function, as this passage from the words, “breathing,
digesting, defecating with gay abandon, I was living just because I
had started living.” All this fills him with loathing and plunges him
into “a horrible ecstasy.” “Everything is gratuitous, this garden, this
town, and myself- that is nausea.”
Absurdity
The startling revelation that everything which exists has no reason
for existing sparks of, in Roquentin - Sartre, the terrible admission
that the whole world is founded on a frightening but unyielding
absurdity. “The word absurdity springs at the moment from my pen,”
60
confesses the young mean. “I understood that I had found there the
ley of existence, the key to my nausea and of my whole life: the fact
that whatever I could seize upon thereafter leads to this fundamental
absurdity.” And this absurdity traps all things. Even reasonable
beings. “they hadn’t asked to exist, only they couldn’t have prevented
it; that is all.”
PHILOSOPHY OF MAN
The lonely Exile
This is the primary condition of man is a world which is absurd, man,
who has no established system of meanings and motives with which
to explain things. Images of loneliness, of being an exile and of
feeling-apart recur in Sartre’s writings. “We are anxiety itself,” he
writes bluntly in being and nothingness. And Orestes, in the flies
feels his loneliness as a kind of leprosy: “… alone, like a leper. I felt
alone, in the middle of my benign little world, like someone who has
lost his shadow.” “Or, as Mathieu in the reprieve, puts it more
eloquently, “I am nothing, I have nothing. As inseparable from the
world as the light and yet exiled, like light, slipping over the surface
of stones and of water, without anything ever clinging to me or
embracing me. Cast out. Cast out. Cast out of the world. Cast out
from the past. Cast out from my own self.”
Freedom
But suddenly there appears an apparent ray of hope on the gloomy
landscape. True, reality is contingent and absurd. Doubtless neither
man nor things have any essence, which might justify their existence.
All at once man realizes one thing: he, at least, can change. His
power of consciousness invests him with the ability to choose and
create his own essence, a porteriori while conscienceless; inanimate
matter is doomed forever to remain, fixed in its absurd state. Things
are imprisoned in non - meaning: man can create his own meaning.
We can grasp the sense of elation with which Orestes makes this
discovery: “I am free, Electra! Freedom has broken upon me like a
thunderbolt!” it is up to us to make our own standards of Good and
Evil. Nothing of man, the gods can do nothing against such a man!”
thus exclaims Orestes once again. “Justice is man’s affair,” he avers,
“I need no God to teach it to me.”
61
“Condemned to be Free”
“I am my liberty,” writes Sartre in being and nothings. It is more
correct to say that man is freedom than to say that he has freedom.
“Freedom coincides at its roots with the non-being which is at the
heart of man.” (ibid.) however this freedom is not an unmixed
blessing; in fact, it is more of an unalloyed course. “I am condemned
to be free,” we read in an oft-quoted passage from the reprieve. For
freedom lays a heavy obligation on sour shoulders and there is no
release from this terrifying burden. At every moment we are obliged
to invent values, to independently on impulse, as it were- give
meaning to a senseless world. And it is not legitimate to abdicate this
fearsome duty by blindly following the alleged universal or objective
values offered us by society or religion or philosophy or whatever. To
quote Orestes once more, “I am condemned to have no other law but
my own...” we have not chosen to exist; we have not chosen to be
free. But we do exist and we are free. There is nothing we can do
about that. Now this burden of making choices in freedom every
moment, every day is all the more terrifying when we realize that in
each particular choice we make, we are implicating, somehow or the
other, the whole of mankind. For each choice that I make, willy-nilly,
creates a possible standard which others in a similar situation are
tacitly invited to follow
A “useless passion”
The pour-soi longs for the stability and rest of the en-soi. It would
wish to achieve such repose while at the same time retaining its
freedom. In short, it is demanding the impossible – to be, at the
same time, en-soi-pour-soi, which is a contradiction, it is in this
sense that he says that man is a “useless passion”, a longing for what
can never be. And only despair can result from such an unfulfillable
desire. The only “solution” is to accept the despair that cannot but
result from this “useless passion”. Then only can authentic,
constructive, life begin. In Orestes’ words, “human life begins on the
other side of despair.” However, most man find this despairs too
painful and so they take the easiest way out. If they can’t have
stability and freedom, they prefer to sacrifice their freedom for the
sake of stability alone. In other words, they opt to be en-soi, trying to
cover up their mauvaisefoi by various pretences.
PHILOSOPHY OF GOD
The desire to be God
We have seen above that man is basically a useless passion, that is,
he is ever striving to fulfill an impossible dream, a basic
63
Atheism or anti-atheism
Sartre is an atheist, but – at his admission – not one who would
waste time discussing the merits or demerits of the possible existence
of God. He dismisses the deity as but one of the various forms of
mauvasiefoi which people use for abdicating their freedom and not
doing anything. As he points out in clarificatory paragraph from
existentialism and humanism: “existentialism isn’t the type of
atheism as would exhaust itself in demonstrating that God didn’t
exist. It avers rather: even if God existed, that would make no
difference- such is our point of view… man must re-discover himself
and convince himself that he must save himself, even if it were
possible to come up with a valid proof of God’s existence.” Such, at
any rate, is Sartre’s avowal. Just how incidental or irrelevant is the
issue of God’s existence, we shall explore in our critical comments.
There are some thinkers who are, from the very beginning,
unambiguously identified as philosophers (e.g., Plato). There are
others whose philosophical place is forever contested (e.g.,
Nietzsche); and there are those who have gradually won the right to
be admitted into the philosophical fold. Simone de Beauvoir is one of
these belatedly acknowledged philosophers. Identifying herself as an
author rather than as a philosopher and calling herself the midwife of
Sartre’s existential ethics rather than a thinker in her own right,
Beauvoir’s place in philosophy had to be won against her word. That
place is now uncontested. The international conference celebrating
the centennial of Beauvoir’s birth organized by Julia Kristeva is one
of the more visible signs of Beauvoir’s growing influence and status.
64
Done (1974), she discusses her life from 1962 to 1972. Other well-
known works of hers include the novel She Came to Stay(1943) and
her essay The Ethics of Ambiguity (1947).
A question that naturally comes to mind is why there are so few (any
at all?) women philosophers. It is assuredly not because women have
not the required intellectual ability to philosophize! Other callings
have attracted their attention, apparently, the more practical ones.
Whether this be of their choice or due to social pressures is, of
course, debatable. At any rate, three is barely any philosopher of note
in the thousands of years of recorded history, in the East as much as
in the west. Even Ms. Beauvoir, philosopher though she might be in
her own right, has no particularly unique theory or idea of her own in
philosophy, apart from her studies of feminism and her
documentation of male chauvinism!
FEMINISM
The Second Sex
Most philosophers agree that Beauvoir's greatest contribution to
philosophy is her revolutionary magnum opus, The Second Sex.
Published in two volumes in 1949 (condensed into one text divided
into two "books" in English), this work immediately found both an
eager audience and harsh critics. The Second Sex was so
controversial that the Vatican put it (along with her novel, The
Mandarins) on the Index of prohibited books. At the time The
Second Sex was written, very little serious philosophy on women
from a feminist perspective had been done. With the exception of a
handful of books, systematic treatments of the oppression of women
both historically and in the modern age were almost unheard of.
Striking for the breadth of research and the profundity of its central
insights, The Second Sex remains to this day one of the foundational
texts in philosophy, feminism, and women's studies.
The main thesis of The Second Sex revolves around the idea that
woman has been held in a relationship of long-standing oppression
to man through her relegation to being man's "Other." In agreement
with Hegelian and Sartrean philosophy, Beauvoir finds that the self
needs otherness in order to define itself as a subject; the category of
the otherness, therefore, is necessary in the constitution of the self as
66
The work is divided into two major themes. The first book
investigates the "Facts and Myths" about women from multiple
perspectives including the biological-scientific, psychoanalytic,
materialistic, historical, literary and anthropological. In each of these
treatments, Beauvoir is careful to claim that none of them is
sufficient to explain woman's definition as man's Other or her
consequent oppression. However, each of them contributes to
woman's overall situation as the Other sex. For example, in her
discussion of biology and history, she notes the women experience
certain phenomena such as pregnancy, lactation, and menstruation
that are foreign to men's experience and thus contribute to a marked
difference in women's situation. However, these physiological
occurrences in no way directly cause woman to be man's subordinate
because biology and history are not mere "facts" of an unbiased
observer, but are always incorporated into and interpreted from a
situation. In addition, she acknowledges that psychoanalysis and
historical materialism contribute tremendous insights into the
sexual, familial and material life of woman, but fail to account for the
whole picture. In the case of psychoanalysis, it denies the reality of
choice and in the case of historical materialism, it neglects to take
67
Although we certainly can not claim that woman's role as the Other is
her fault, we also cannot say that she is always entirely innocent in
her subjection. As taken up in the discussion of The Ethics of
Ambiguity, Beauvoir believes that there are many possible attitudes
of bad faith where the existent flees his or her responsibility into
prefabricated values and beliefs. Many women living in a patriarchal
culture are guilty of the same action and thus are in some ways
complicitous in their own subjugation because of the seeming
benefits it can bring as well as the respite from responsibility it
promises. Beauvoir discusses three particular inauthentic attitudes in
which women hide their freedom in: "The Narcissist," "The Woman
in Love," and "The Mystic." In all three of these attitudes, women
deny the original thrust of their freedom by submerging it into the
object; in the case of the first, the object is herself, the second, her
beloved and the third, the absolute or God.
Beauvoir's emphasis on the fact that women need access to the same
kinds of activities and projects as men places her to some extent in
the tradition of liberal, or second-wave feminism. She demands that
women be treated as equal to men and laws, customs and education
must be altered to encourage this. However, The Second Sex always
maintains its fundamental existentialist belief that each individual,
regardless of sex, class or age, should be encouraged to define him or
herself and to take on the individual responsibility that comes with
freedom. This requires not just focusing on universal institutions, but
on the situated individual existent struggling within the ambiguity of
existence.
Alert Camus born in 1913 in Algeria; his father died in a war, when
Albert was only one year old. He experienced extreme poverty in his
childhood. His love for nature is reflected in his writings. Besides
poverty, he experienced illness (tuberculosis) as well. During the II
World War he worked with the resistance group. In 1957 he received
Nobel Prize for literature. In 1960 he died in a car accident. Some of
his works are: The Myth of Sisyphus, The Stranger, The Rebel, The
Plague etc.
A. His Philosophy
His north-African background must have had a role to play in his
neo-paganism and love for nature. There is in every Algerian an
earthly innocence by which he lives the present life to the full. Camus
is critical of the European approach and attitude that is more
70
1. Absurdity
The theme of absurdity is as old as the book of Ecclesiastes; but
Camus has expressed it very accurately as the mood of his time. The
setting was ideal, and he epitomized the prevalent climate of France
under German occupation.
a. Contributing factors
There are many factors that have contributed towards absurdity
being experienced. The human seeks reasons and explanations, but
he is frustrated as no explanation is forthcoming. The contributing
factors are the following. Science: despite its dogmatic claims,
science ends in hypothesis, and thus inadequate. Instead of
understanding, what we find in the world of science is opacity and
irrationality. The powerlessness of the powerful science and reason!
Monotony of Life: life goes on in an orderly and systematic way:
daily, weekly, monthly and yearly time-table and schedule in an
uninterrupted way. We become conscious of the monotony of it,
when we are awakened in thought. Time: man becomes suddenly
aware that time is his worst enemy. We are being carried by time,
and suddenly it destroys us as it takes us to the no-further. This too
begets absurdity. World: the denseness, opacity and hostility of the
world, that have been remaining dormant, suddenly show themselves
violently, and we are thrown into absurdity as there is no why for it.
Inhumanity in the humans: humans have turned out to be inhuman
in their words and actions. The rational beings are engaged in
irrational violence. Death: the inevitability of death puts an end to all
his plans and ambitions. The futility of human life comes to the force.
c. Response to Absurdity
One of the commonest responses to absurdity is escaping from it
either by physical or philosophical suicide. Physical suicide is the
voluntary termination of life. Philosophical suicide is a taking refuge
in faith and religion in order to escape the absurd. According to
Camus, neither physical suicide nor philosophical suicide (hope) is
the authentic response to absurdity. Suicide is a cowardly act, by
which absurdity is apparently destroyed. It is a facile solution in the
face of absurdity. Such a response lacks a fundamental honesty, since
it represents a refusal to face the situation of absurdity. It a cowardly
compromise.
Few of Kafka's works were published during his lifetime: the story
collections Betrachtung (Contemplation) and Ein Landarzt (A
Country Doctor), and individual stories (such as "Die Verwandlung")
were published in literary magazines but received little public
attention. Kafka's unfinished works, including his novels Der
Process, Das Schloss and Amerika (also known as Der
Verschollene, The Man Who Disappeared), were ordered by Kafka to
be destroyed by his friend Max Brod, who nonetheless ignored his
friend's direction and published them after Kafka's death. His work
went on to influence a vast range of writers, critics, artists, and
philosophers during the 20th century.
The characters in his novels usually have no name and are referred to
as K. They are invariably people deprived of spiritual security and
tortured by anxiety and loneliness. They are generally people
frustrated in their attempts to realize their goals, such as knowledge,
social acceptance and salvation. Their lives alternate from hope to
despair, from attempt to failure. They experience painful alienation
from a vague divine authority. This alienation is experienced as being
rooted in some obscure personal guilt and seems to be a sort of
inescapable destiny. The strong existentialist flavour of all these
themes should be evident, especially the angst, the ennui and the
absurd.
His writings are a weird mixture of the realistic and the grotesque,
blending detailed descriptions with an overall atmosphere of fantasy
and nightmare. Events and objects are portrayed with apparent
75
His first story, Poor Folk (1846) won the enthusiastic praise of critics
because it injected something new into Russian literature of the time:
a study of poor, unhappy people. His memories from the House of
the Dead (1861-62) tells in realistic details of prison life, drawing
from his four year prison experience in Siberia for sedition.
Memories from the Underground (1864) is a remarkable
psychological study of an intellectual and spiritual misfit. Crime and
Punishment (1866) catapulted him once more to the fame that had
been eluding him, telling the story of the young student Rokolnikov
who brutally murders an aged female pawnbroker for reasons that
are as unusual as they are unclear. The Idiot (1868) and The
Possessed (1871-72) are two other, less well-known books of his,
written while travelling on the Continent. He returned to Russia to
write his last and finest work, The Brothers Karamazov (1879-
1880), which tells of the murder of the veil Fyodr Karamazov and its
effect on his four sons – Dmitri, a soldier; Ivan, an intellectual and a
sceptic; Aloysha, a religious mystic who enters a religious order, and
Smerdyakov, the murderer.
PART THREE
9. GENERAL CONCLUSION
It is not easy to make an overall or common judgment about a
philosophy that comprises so many different attitudes, from the
atheism of Sartre to the faith of Kierkegaard or Jaspers, from the
courageous despair of Camus to the pathways into Being of
Heidegger. Nor can we deny that existentialism has become for many
shallow people a kind of posture or pose- a convenient excuse for
long hair, drop outs and drugs!
The moral scene in India has long been one in which despair and
frustration are fife. Unfortunately, it has been mainly the nihilistic
and destructive existentialism of Sartre that has been devoured,
digested and dealt out by our intellectuals, our “modern” playwrights
and men of letters, in general. It is a pity that few Indians know of
Camus and Heidegger and Jaspers – fewer, at any rate, than can tell
of hell being the other. Much of this is, no doubt, due to the fact that
the average Indians has known quite a bit of the abuse of authority-
by parents, priests and politicians, hence, Sartrean views on freedom
can easily sound like a rallying cry for rebellious youngsters (and
oldsters) are smarting over domestic dictators, invariably, this but
creates a shallow and transient misfit or dropout who, after some
radical noises, eventually throws in his/her lot with the rat race. This
is sterile and ineffectual revolutionism.
Existentialism, like many of the finest and best things in life, can all
too easily be misuse or abused. It presupposes not a little maturity of
mind in its adherents. But few will deny that it is “the most
stimulating and disturbing, the most bewildering and illuminating
though in a good many generations” (Roger L. Shinn).
BEST WISHES!
80