Thomas Pink
Thomas Pink
Thomas Pink
Núcleos do
Integralismo Inglês.
III. Thomas Pink.
Jacques Maritain and the problem of Church and State1
Over two decades, up to the publication in 1951 of his Man and the
State, Jacques Maritain sought to develop a new theory of the
relation between Church and state. He was aware of previous
Church magisterial teaching and canonical regulation that taught or
assumed the model of soul-body union – the Leonine model as I
shall term it, since it was formally endorsed in recent times by Leo
XIII, though it had been proposed for a very long time in theology
approved by the papacy and had been assumed by general councils
and in ecclesial policy:
1
My thanks for comments to the faculty and students of Mundelein Seminary, where an initial
version of this paper was given at an October 2013 joint lecture on ‘Dignitatis Humanae at 50:
The Future of Religious Freedom’, to my fellow lecturer Fr Thomas Joseph White OP, and to
Professor Matthew Levering, who organized the event. My thanks also to referees for The
Thomist for their comments.
but higher than that served by the state, the state, when Christian
and ruled by the baptized, must be prepared to support the Church
in spiritual matters, lending its coercive power to the Church,
acting as the Church’s agent and on her authority – just as in
deliberate human actions that serve the intellectual purposes of the
soul, the body operates at the direction of the soul.
Leo XIII taught that the state should recognize the truth of the
Catholic faith; for the state is governed, just as much as individuals
are, by a duty, under natural law, to worship God in whatever way
he directs and reveals:
All who rule, therefore, would hold in honour the holy name
of God, and one of their chief duties must be to favour
religion, to protect it, to shield it under the credit and sanction
of the laws, and neither to organize nor enact any measure
that may compromise its safety. Immortale Dei §6
And elsewhere
Therefore the law of Christ ought to prevail in human society
and be the guide and teacher of public as well as of private
life. Since this is so by divine decree, and no man may with
impunity contravene it, it is an evil thing for any state where
Christianity does not hold the place that belongs to it. Tametsi
Futura §8
But Leo XIII insisted that, though the state should legislate to
protect the Catholic faith, the authority to legislate in matters of
religion belongs to the Church, not to the state. The state must
therefore legislate to support the Catholic faith as the Church's
agent. For Leo XIII carefully distinguished the directive
competences of Church and state, the two sovereign powers
(potestates) with authority to legislate and punish. He excluded
legal direction in matters of religion from the native competence of
the state:
While one of the two powers [the state] has for its immediate
and chief object care of the goods of this mortal life, the other
[the Church] provides for goods that are heavenly and
everlasting. Whatever, therefore, in things human is in any
way of a sacred character, whatever belongs either of its own
nature or by reason of the end to which it is referred, to the
salvation of souls or to the worship of God, falls wholly within
the power of the Church and is wholly subject to her
judgment (id est omne in potestate arbitrioque Ecclesiae).
Immortale Dei §13–§14
So the authority behind any legal direction by the state in support
of religious truth must be that of the Church. 2
…the political power of the Holy Empire and the kings was
an instrument for the spiritual aims of the Church. Man and
the State (Washington: Catholic University of America
Press, 1998), chapter 6 'Church and state', p158
2
The soul-body model of Church-state relations, as understood within the Church's theological
tradition up to and including the time of Leo XIII, centres on the doctrine that a Christian state
should act as the Church's agent - her bracchium saeculare - in spiritual matters in which the
Church alone has legislative competence, as the body acts at the soul's direction in intellectual
matters.
Various ecumenical councils have instructed Christian rulers to act as the Church's
agents in support of the Catholic faith: these include Lateran IV, Constance (and, following and
confirming Constance, Pope Martin V), and Trent. For specific references and discussion see my
‘The interpretation of Dignitatis Humanae: a reply to Martin Rhonheimer’ Nova et Vetera,
(English edition), 11, No. 1 (2013): pp77–121 - especially pp99-103.
Far from being viewed as outmoded by the late nineteenth century, this teaching that
the Christian state should act as the Church’s agent or secular arm is maintained in the 1917
Code of Canon Law - see canon 2198 discussed below. Authorities cited in the Code for that
canon come from the conciliar tradition just mentioned - specifically Martin V Inter Cunctas,
article 32; and the Council of Trent, Session 25, Decretum de Reformatione Generali, chapter 20,
in Decrees of the Ecumenical Councils, eds Tanner and Alberigo, (Washington: Georgetown
University Press, 1990), volume 2, p795.
For a classic theological defence of the model of soul-body union, still cited in theological
manuals under Leo XIII, see Robert Bellarmine, Tractatus de Potestate Summi Pontificis in Rebus
Temporalibus, adversus Gulielmum Barclay, translated in On Temporal and Spiritual Authority:
Robert Bellarmine, ed. Stefania Turtino (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund 2012).
3
In this Maritain was more careful, and more respectful of the magisterium, than Martin
Rhonheimer, who openly accuses the pre-conciliar magisterium of error in teaching the state’s
duty legislatively and coercively to support the Catholic faith and enforce ecclesiastical law – see
his “Benedict XVI’s ‘Hermeneutic of Reform’ and Religious Freedom,” Nova et Vetera (English
between, on the one hand, accusing the Church of error in her past
teaching, and, on the other, descending to a brute relativism of ‘that
was then, this is now’.
The modern age is not a sacral, but a secular age. The order of
terrestrial civilization and of temporal society has gained
complete differentiation and full autonomy, which is
something normal in itself, required by the Gospel's very
distinction between God's and Caesar's domains. Man and the
State p159
In the secular age, the superiority of Church over state must take
moral rather than juridical form. The secular age involves a new
form of Church-state cooperation, without legal privilege for the
Church but with shared agreement on the rights of individuals – the
rights belonging to individuals under natural law. These include an
individual right to religious liberty against the state and other civic
institutions, and full freedom for the Church and all other religious
communities to pursue their own conceptions of religion, true or
false. State law, especially when inspired by the moral example of
the Church, will be consistent with natural law. But the Church will
give only a moral example. The state will no longer be subject to
ecclesial direction in spiritual matters.
In demanding only that the state grant the Church freedom rather
than juridical privilege, Maritain anticipated Dignitatis Humanae –
a declaration that owed much to Maritain. Indeed at the Second
Vatican Council on 21 September 1965, in the final debates before
that declaration’s passing in November, Maritain’s friend and
collaborator Charles Journet gave Dignitatis Humanae a highly
Maritainian endorsement. He repeated core Maritainian claims:
that in the modern world under the influence of the Gospel, the
distinction between things spiritual and temporal, between God and
Caesar, was more clearly established, leading to a new way of
applying the principle of the subordination of the temporal to the
spiritual:
One figure who poses a serious problem for Maritain and Journet
is the pope who in recent times taught the model of soul-body union
most clearly and formally: Leo XIII. It is obvious why the teaching
of that pope should be an embarrassment for Maritain’s theory.
Pope Leo's vigorous defence in Immortale Dei of the soul-body
model as an ideal comes in 1885, long after the sacral period of the
Middle Ages, and well into the age of the modern nonconfessional
state - that is the secular age. But according to Maritain’s theory,
far from still ideal, soul-body union is the wrong model of Church-
state relations for the secular age. On Maritain’s terms, in still
presenting soul-body union as a modern ideal, Leo XIII must be
teaching error. Maritain had hoped to use his theory of successive
historical climates to ring-fence his theory from conflict with the
magisterium - the Church’s previous commitment to soul-body
union would be respected, though only as a feature of the sacral
age. However, since clear magisterial defence of soul-body union
as the continuing ideal occurs long after, well into the secular age,
conflict is inescapable. Indeed Maritain was in conflict not only
with papal teaching but also with canon law. A canon, 2198,
insisting that the Christian state act as the Church’s secular arm to
enforce her laws, with supportive citations of decrees to that effect
from Constance and Trent, was included in a new Code of Canon
Law introduced as late as 1917 and in force for much of the
twentieth century.
5
In his "Dignitatis Humanae - Not a Mere Question of Church Policy: A Response to Thomas
Pink" in Nova et Vetera (English edition) 12, no. 2 (2014): pp445–470, Rhonheimer seeks to
show that the Council fathers shared his own understanding of the declaration as a contradiction
of previous magisterial teaching by citing (461-62) this specific address by Journet. But this is to
misunderstand the Maritainian project, which was, unlike Rhonheimer, to avoid supposing the
magisterium to have taught error. Journet's careful refusal, in an important and influential speech,
to present the declaration as a contradiction of previous doctrine, does nothing to support
Rhonheimer's reading of it.
Maritain was evasive about the Church’s continuing and
unmistakably modern defence of the soul-body model. He sought
to present Leo XIII as concerned fundamentally to teach the
autonomy of the state.6 And indeed, Leo XIII did teach that
autonomy, for temporal matters where the state is sovereign; but in
Man and the State Maritain is silent about Leo’s equal emphasis on
soul-body union, and the state’s proper subordination to the Church
in spiritual matters. Maritain also attempted to claim that canon
2198’s talk of the state being required to act as the Church’s secular
arm was really designed to secure the same legal protection for the
Church from the state as was owing to any religious association.7
But the explicit reference in the canon to the state as the Church’s
‘secular arm’ speaks the language of something very different – a
principal-agent relation between Church and state. And that is
confirmed by the 1917 Code’s citations of Constance and Trent,
which call for the coercive enforcement by the state of Church laws
generally, not mere legal recognition of the Church’s rights as one
voluntary association among many. Maritain’s minimizing reading
makes no sense of the texts, a reading that was clearly not shared
by others. For once the Church, with Dignitatis Humanae, finally
gave up her extraordinarily persistent attempt to continue to apply
the model of soul-body union, she gave up canon 2198 as well.
That canon has no equivalent in the 1983 Code, and that is not
surprising. That canon was phrased and referenced as it was in the
1917 Code precisely to express in law the Church’s doctrinal
commitment to soul-body union at least as an ideal – a commitment
that until 1965 was as much a feature of ecclesial modernity and of
the secular age as Vatican radio and papal photographs.
On Maritain’s theory, it seems that Leo XIII was not only teaching
error, but damaging error too. For on Maritain’s view the pope’s
teaching, when given in the secular age, could only tend to hold
back clearer understanding of the distinction between God and
Caesar – a distinction that Maritain made out to be best displayed
6
See for example Man and the State p153.
7
See Man and the State p161, footnote 17.
by a fully secular state that refused juridically to privilege the
Church. But of course that was not Leo XIII’s view, and the
distinction between God and Caesar was hardly downplayed by
him. The clear distinction between God and Caesar, between
spiritual and temporal authorities and their proper concerns, and
the sovereignty of each in its proper sphere, was fundamental to
Leo’s teaching in Immortale Dei, as it had been to the Jesuit
political theology of the Counter-Reformation (a decadent
‘baroque’ age in Maritain’s view, and openly despised by him) to
which Immortale Dei clearly owed so much. For Leo XIII, a
juridical superiority of Church over state in spiritual matters, far
from endangering the distinction between Church and state, was
important to its proper recognition. The subordination of state to
Church in spiritual matters followed, in Leo’s view, from a right
understanding of the spiritual and its superiority. The soul-body
model that Maritain dismissed as an imperfect and by now
outmoded realization of the distinction between the spiritual and
the temporal was for Leo XIII dictated, at least as an ideal, by that
very distinction, and was fundamental to proper respect for it.
The issue between Leo XIII and Maritain comes then to this: Does
political secularization – the detachment of the state from any
particular religion and so from the Church - now provide the best
means to ensuring that religion is respected as a transcendent good,
as Maritain supposed? Or are things instead as Leo XIII supposed:
does soul-body union still provide the best means to ensuring that
religion is so respected – perhaps because such a Church-state
union, or at least something approximating to it, provides in the
long term the only possible such means? If Leo XIII turns out to
have been right, then we are left with a bleak conclusion. In so far
as soul-body union, or even anything at all like it, is now
impossible, so too, at the political level, is the respect for religion
as a good that Dignitatis Humanae demands along with previous
Catholic tradition.
But, as we will now see, that claim was not obviously true in 1965,
and half a century later it is even less true now.
This right to liberty meant for Suarez that no other private human
individual has any natural right to coerce me – to issue directives
that I am to follow, and that threaten me with punishment or
sanction if disregarded. Licit coercion requires special justification.
The one coercing me must be a public authority with jurisdiction
over me, a jurisdiction that extends to the kind of activity it is
seeking to direct. So our power of freedom protects us against
coercion, not unconditionally, but in those cases where the
authority to coerce is lacking.
9
See Toledo IV, canon 56 in Corpus Iuris Canonici ed. E. Friedberg (Leipzig: Bernhard Tauchnitz,
1881), volume 1, pp161-2. Toledo IV is a basis of canon 14 of Trent’s decree on baptism,
condemning those, such as Erasmus, who opposed the coercion of the heretical or apostate
baptized back into the faith. For citation of Toledo IV at Trent in support of canon 14, see
Concilium Tridentinum Diariorum, Actorum, Epistularum, Tractatuum, ed. Societas Goerresiana
volume 5, ed. S. Ehses, (Freiburg im Breisgau: Herder 1911), p855 and p864. Toledo IV is also
cited by Dignitatis Humanae to show that the Church has never coerced the unbaptized into the
faith. For discussion of Toledo IV in relation both to Trent and to Vatican II, see my ‘The
interpretation of Dignitatis Humanae: a reply to Martin Rhonheimer’ Nova et Vetera, (English
edition), 11, No. 1 (2013): pp77–121.
that holds against the authority of the state. We have a
distinctively political right to religious liberty – just as Dignitatis
Humanae teaches. It needs to be established, however, why this
is so.
The fact that humanity bears the image of God allows for two
forms of religion. The first is natural religion, a worship and love
of God as creator whose existence is known to us by reason
through created things. The communal practice of natural religion
is a distinctive and vital part of natural human flourishing. As
rational monotheism, it is obligatory under natural law, and
obligatory because essential to the purely natural happiness and
justice that is served, at the level of the community, by the
authority of the state. The second form of religion is supernatural.
It involves our being raised, through divine grace, to a level of
happiness that transcends the capacity of human nature, to enjoy
the beatific vision of God. This supernatural life, though beyond
our natural capacity, is still consistent with our human nature
(which we retain) and is so consistent only because at the natural
level we already bear the image of God.
10
Thus the 1917 Code of Canon Law uses ‘human authority’ to refer to natural-law-based
authority, such as that of the state, in contrast to the divine-law-based authority of the Church.
See canon 2214 §1: ‘The Church has the native and proper right, independent of any human
authority, to coerce the delinquent among those subject to her with both spiritual and temporal
penalties.’
Omnia, volume 12, p451
The only authority with the competence to legislate and punish in
matters of supernatural religion, therefore, is the revealed
authority of the Church. The state has no jurisdiction in this
matter:
Punishment of crimes only belongs to civil magistrates in so
far as those crimes are contrary to political ends, public peace
and human justice; but coercion with respect to those deeds
which are opposed to religion and to the salvation of the soul,
is essentially a function of spiritual power [the power of the
Church], so that the authority to make use of temporal
penalties for the purposes of such correction must have been
allotted in particular to this spiritual power. Suarez, Defensio
Fidei Catholicae adversus Anglicanae Sectae Errores, book 3,
chapter 23 §19 in Opera Omnia, volume 24, pp320-21
But what of natural religion? It might be thought that natural
religion at least, as essential to natural happiness and required by
natural law, would fall like other natural goods within the
jurisdiction of the state. Just as the state has the authority to
regulate goods such as education or transport, so too the state
has the authority to regulate religion at the natural level at least.
This, however, was not the view finally taken within the Catholic
tradition.
The Catholic view is that natural religion would indeed have fallen
within the jurisdiction of the state had some form of supernatural
religion not been revealed. But the coming of Christ decisively
changed the situation, by changing the orientation of divine
worship and so of religion generally from a natural to a
supernatural end. As the Second Vatican Council put it, Christ is
he
While one of the two powers has for its immediate and chief
object care of the goods of this mortal life, the other provides
for goods that are heavenly and everlasting. Whatever,
therefore, in things human is in any way of a sacred character
(quoque modo sacrum) whatever belongs either of its own
nature or by reason of the end to which it is referred, to the
salvation of souls or to the worship of God, falls wholly within
the power of the Church and is wholly subject to her judgment.
Immortale Dei §13-§14 (emphases added)
12
There are those who oppose this implication that in legislating for religion the state can only
act as agent to the Church as principal. They often appeal to past teaching by the popes that divine
providence itself had given the state the duty to legislate and coerce on behalf of the Catholic
faith. Thus Pope Leo the Great informed the Emperor Leo that ‘you ought unhesitatingly to
consider that the kingly power has been conferred on you not for the governance of the world
alone but more especially for the guardianship of the Church’ (Letter 156). This is supposed to
establish that the state has a native right and duty, under its own authority, to legislate and coerce
on behalf of the Catholic faith. The state is not acting just as the Church’s agent, under the
Church’s authority. (My thanks to John Lamont for pressing this objection.)
But these past papal claims about a providential role and duty given to the state are in no
way inconsistent with the principal-agent model - which is why they are so often repeated or
referred to in expositions of that very model, such as in Bellarmine’s Tractatus (see, for example,
chapter 18, on the prince’s duty to protect the true religion), or in Leo XIII’s Immortale Dei itself
(see §6 for repetition of such teaching on the state’s duty). Crucially, such papal claims say
nothing about how providence gives the state this duty – whether through some authority in
religious matters native to the state, or through the authority of the Church and the providential
establishment, via baptism, of a principal-agent or soul-body relation between Church and state.
Leo XIII’s Immortale Dei clearly teaches that the principal-agent model applies; and this
is entirely consistent with the state’s lacking the duty, and even the right, to coerce on behalf of
the faith, under those (unideal) circumstances where the state is not acting as the Church’s agent.
Likewise, Bellarmine makes it particularly clear that the duty to protect the true faith belongs to
the state in the context of a soul-body union of Church and state, where the state is said to protect
the Church as the Church’s servant (see Tractatus, chapter 18, in On Temporal and Spiritual
Authority, p. 85).
If the state is to act as the Church’s agent, baptismal obligations must of course take
political and not merely private form. But this is the clear implication of canon 2198 of the 1917
Code, which, like all canonical obligation, presupposes baptism, but puts requirements
specifically on the state. See also Bellarmine: ‘In fact, since kings through baptism have subjected
themselves to the spiritual authority of the Pontiff, they are considered to have subjected also
their kingdoms and their political authority to the same spiritual authority; that is, they wanted
to be directed and corrected by the Pontiff if they have strayed in any way from the path to
salvation in temporal matters.’ Tractatus Chapter 16, in On Temporal and Spiritual Authority, p.
266 (emphases added)
the state should acknowledge revealed truth when presented with
it, as is its duty under natural law – just as this is a natural-law duty
on private individuals. But the authority to direct and coerce
religiously still belongs to the Church. It no more belongs to the
state than it belongs to private individuals.13
13
In his "Dignitatis Humanae - Not a Mere Question of Church Policy: A Response to Thomas
Pink", Martin Rhonheimer accuses me of a contradiction. He argues that if, as Leo XIII teaches,
there is a natural law duty on the state to acknowledge religious truth when God communicates it
to us, "...this means that the state has also a genuine right to enforce this truth..." (see p468). So,
he alleges, it would follow that the state does, after all, have an authority under natural law to
legislate in matters of revealed religion - which, however, Leo XIII and I deny.
But what Rhonheimer alleges to follow, simply does not follow. Just because some person
or group or institution has a duty to recognize a given truth, it does not follow that on the same
basis it need have any authority of its own to enforce that truth and coerce on its behalf. This does
not follow for private individuals, nor for institutions - not even when, unlike a private individual,
that institution has a coercive authority of its own in other matters.
Unsurprisingly, given his unwarranted inference from a native duty on the state to
recognize religious truth to a native authority to enforce it, Rhonheimer is led to conclude that in
my work on religious liberty, "Professor Pink's error lies in construing Leo XIII's doctrine on
Church-state relations as a fully coherent doctrine, which it is not" p469. Leo XIII's doctrine is,
however, entirely coherent.
and Journet fondly hoped, by any renewed allegiance to this view
of religious liberty, but by its increasing rejection.
14
For discussion of Hobbes’s highly innovative theory of liberty and his opposition to scholastic
conceptions of freedom both as a power and as a right, see my 'Thomas Hobbes and the ethics of
freedom', Inquiry, 54, (2011), pp541-64; and my ‘Hobbes on liberty, action and free will’, in The
Oxford Handbook of Hobbes eds Kinch Hoekstra and Al Martinich (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, forthcoming).
15
For the refusal to base the right to liberty on metaphysics, see John Rawls, Political Liberalism
(New York: Columbia University Press 2011). For the appeal to the human capacity for reason,
see Philip Pettit, A Theory of Freedom (Cambridge: Polity 2001).
involves a capacity on our part to be moved by justifications.
Unfortunately, in a theory of the right to liberty, the capacity for
reason cannot substitute for the old appeal to freedom as a power
over alternatives.
But good alternatives are of course what coercion seeks to deny us.
The one coercing, unless immediately applying chains, or making
threats that are unusually terrifying, does not actually remove
freedom as a power. It usually remains within our control to act
other than as we are directed. Rather coercion serves to remove not
alternatives as such, but alternatives that are good. Essential to
coercion, and to the pressure that it applies, is the threat of sanction,
which works by making all options bar one, the option directed,
worse. That is why our possession of freedom as a power was long
seen as creating a presumptive normative block to coercion. If we
possess a nature the point of which is to put alternative goods
within our power, there must be some justification for the
deliberate removal of those goods.
The idea of a capacity for reason does not have the same
normative implications. For that capacity’s function is not to
provide us with alternative goods, but to enable us to respond to
justifications. Coercion does not threaten or work against such a
capacity, but simply addresses it. Coercive threats work precisely
by providing us with further justifications for acting as directed –
justifications rooted in the desirability of avoiding threatened
sanctions.
We can know that God exists as our creator, and that we exist as
his creation and as bearing his image through our rationality and
freedom. From this arises the intelligibility, as a distinctive and
essential part of human happiness, of the activity of worshipping
God and loving him. Good religion involves rational monotheism,
which includes loving and honouring God with public and
communal forms of worship worthy of the divine, and relatedly
worthy too of our dignity as bearing the image of the divine. Bad
or defective religion involves various kinds of failure to meet these
demands.
16 Or, to similar effect, wider forms of personal commitment may be redefined as ‘religion
properly understood’: see Ronald Dworkin Religion without God (Cambridge, Massachusetts:
Harvard University Press 2013), where religion is reduced to a form of commitment to value.
ethnic and cultural identity generally.
These are not mere possibilities for the future. The secularization
of religious liberty is already well underway. Hence we read in the
work of a contemporary political and legal philosopher:
The modern age is not a sacral, but a secular age. The order of
terrestrial civilization and of temporal society has gained
complete differentiation and full autonomy, which is
something normal in itself, required by the Gospel's very
distinction between God's and Caesar's domains.
…where religion has been removed from civil society, and the
doctrine and authority of divine revelation repudiated, the
18
This teaching does not imply that all forms of state establishment of Catholicism have been
benign, for not all have corresponded to Leo XIII's ideal. One form, especially common since the
Reformation, and highly problematic in its effects on Church and state alike, clearly has not. This
is ancien regime Gallicanism or various kinds of 'state' or 'national' Catholicism. This form of
establishment is highly damaging insofar as it reduces the Church to acting as, in effect, an agent
of the state - rather than the state acting in specifically spiritual matters as genuinely the agent of
the Church. This form of establishment is obviously not Leo XIII's model, but its opposite.
19
The magisterium has long taught that in a fallen world the natural good served by the state
depends on the state’s adherence to and support for the Catholic faith: for some further
examples of such teaching see, for example, Gregory XVI, Mirari Vos, §§14 and 20, and Pius XI,
Ubi Arcano Dei Consilio §48. But if the state serves the natural good, and the natural good
depends on the Catholic faith of its people, does that not show that the state must have a native
authority to legislate on behalf of the Catholic faith? (My thanks again to John Lamont for
pressing this point.)
The supposed conclusion does not follow. The natural good served by a state can often
depend on matters outside that state’s jurisdiction; in which case the state must support or
cooperate with whatever other authority does have the required jurisdiction. The natural
happiness of the population may depend on the international economy, which is largely outside
the jurisdiction of any particular state; this is why states have to cooperate in economic matters
with other states. Similarly, in a fallen world, the natural happiness of a people will depend on
the provision of healing grace through the Church, and so on religious arrangements over which,
as Leo XIII clearly teaches, the state has no jurisdiction of its own. If it is to attain its natural end,
the state as body must therefore recognize the spiritual authority of the Church as soul, and
subject itself to that.
genuine notion itself of justice and human right is darkened
and lost… Quanta Cura §4
Leo XIII developed the point. United to the soul that is the Church
and under the Church's direction, the state must help the Church to
bring us to our supernatural end, because otherwise the state will
likely fail in bringing us even to our natural end:
22
‘Indeed, since people’s demand for religious liberty in carrying out their duty to worship God
concerns freedom from compulsion in civil society, it leaves unchanged (integram) the
teaching, Dignitatis Humanae therefore leaves intact the Leonine
model too. The declaration simply develops what follows from
traditional Catholic teaching for state authority if the Leonine ideal
cannot in fact be realized, and the state is no longer acting on
Church authority as her religious agent.
traditional catholic teaching on the moral obligation of individuals and societies towards the
true religion and the one Church of Christ.’ Dignitatis Humanae §1 in Decrees of the Ecumenical
Councils, volume 2, p1002
good. This is a failure that the Leonine model and its theology was
well able to predict. Soul-body union may not now be feasible, but
the Leonine soul-body theology still applies to our situation,
explaining the modern state's failure to respect and even understand
the distinction between spiritual and temporal. The state flails
about in matters spiritual, uncomprehending of their true nature,
like a body barreling about detached from its intellectual soul.
One such example is Boniface VIII’s Unam Sanctam and its still
binding magisterial teaching on papal primacy and the necessity
for salvation of the recognition of that primacy. At the time of its
promulgation that document was closely associated with a political
theology that was hierocratic - that asserted a direct and supreme
papal temporal authority over the earth.23 This theology was not
formally and explicitly taught by Unam Sanctam itself, but was
read into it by papalist theologians of the school of Aegidius
Romanus, and also by their opponents, such as theologians
supportive of Philip the Fair of France. This hierocratic theology
helps explain much of the (literally) violent opposition to Boniface
VIII. The hierocratic theory also remained a theology official
23
On the hierocratic theory see Michael Wilks, The Problem of Sovereignty in the Later Middle
Ages (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1963)
enough in Rome still to cause problems with ecclesiastical
authority for later Catholic theologians who too openly rejected it.
Even as late as 1590 the eminent Cardinal Bellarmine narrowly
escaped official condemnation, from Sixtus V, for denying the
hierocratic conception of Church and state. Bellarmine was saved
from being placed on the Index by the pope’s death.24 But this
hierocratic theology, though for a time officially favoured, was
never formally adopted by the magisterium, and was eventually
rejected by it. The hierocratic theory is quite incompatible with the
sovereignty and autonomy of the state in temporal matters that
Bellarmine and Suarez each defended, and that Leo XIII taught in
Immortale Dei.
24
See Stefania Tutino, Empire of Souls: Robert Bellarmine and the Christian Commonwealth
(Oxford: Oxford University Press 2010) pp. 67-70.
for detaching Dignitatis Humanae from Maritain’s theology. The
theology, with its sunny optimism about political secularization
and its consequences, is by now quite unbelievable. It is
increasingly obvious that the secular state will never be respectful
of the Church’s mission on the terms required by Immortale Dei
and Dignitatis Humanae alike. The more the state is secular, the
less the possibility of a shared vision of religion as a distinctive
good transcending state authority, a vision that leaves a politically
undisputed public space for the Church’s mission. Without that
shared understanding of the good of religion, an understanding that
depends on some form of political recognition of the truth of
revealed religion, there can no mutually acceptable articles of
peace between Church and state.
Thomas Pink
As Suarez argues:
So the baptized, and only the baptized, can be coerced into Catholic
fidelity; and the authority to coerce them attaches, in Suarez's view,
not to the state, but to the Church. However, there is still juridical
warrant, in Suarez's view, for some coercion of unbaptized non-
Christians.
The first form of coercion is under the authority of the Church
herself. But this is not a coercion of belief. Since the unbaptized
are outside the Church's jurisdiction, she has no authority in their
case to coerce belief or force any conversion to the faith. Rather the
coercion is to protect her jurisdiction and the supernatural end it
serves, the Church's mission, from interference from without.
As for the state, so also, according to Suarez, for the Church. The
Church can forcibly prevent those outside her juriosdiction from
interfering with her mission, or with the rights that her mission
serves. The unbaptized may not be forcibly converted; but their
religious activities may be restricted so as to limit their impact on
the lives of Christians.
“If anyone says that when they grow up (cum adoleverint), those
baptized as little children should be asked whether they wish to
affirm what their godparents promised in their name when they
were baptized; and that, when they reply that they have no such
wish, they should be left to their own decision and not, in the
meantime, be coerced by any penalty into the Christian life (suo
esse arbitrio relinquendos nec alia interim poena ad christianam
vitam cogendos), except that they be barred from the reception of
the eucharist and the other sacraments, until they have a change of
heart: let him be anathema”.29 Council of Trent
18
And again:
“And, in fact, the Church is wont to take earnest heed that no one
shall be forced to embrace the Catholic faith against his will, for,
as St. Augustine wisely reminds us, "Man cannot believe otherwise
than of his own will." Immortale dei (on the constitution of states)
para 3631
Again, though Leo XIII teaches a clear duty on the part of the state
to foster and support the true religion, which is of course Catholic
monotheism, his main concern is with the public realm, and a
prudent limitation, for the common good, of the public practice and
preaching of religious error. There is certainly no proposal for the
coercion of the belief or private practice of the errant baptized.
This might lead many to read Leo XIII as actually meaning to state
an early and less liberal version of the modern, person-based
model. On this reading,33 the dignity and nature of the person
protects them directly from any coercion of belief and private
practice, but the public interest may warrant some restrictions of
freedom in the public sphere - which is really the same model that
is so naturally and conventionally read into Vatican II. Though a
more favourable view seems to be taken in Immortale dei than at
Vatican II of the use of coercion to prevent the public practice of
non-Catholic religions, this could be read as a matter of degree, and
as reflecting an earlier more pessimistic view, from within a shared
person-centred model, of the adverse effect on the interests of
individuals generally of the public teaching of, or evangelisation
on behalf of, religious error. On this reading there may indeed be a
basic continuity of development between Immortale dei and
Dignitatis humanae.34
“The ancient world was without the unity of the Christian Church
de facto and de jure. The modern world is without de facto; and
this has changed all the moral conditions of the subject. The Church
never, indeed, loses its jurisdiction in radice over the baptized,
because the character of baptism is indelible; but unless the moral
conditions justifying its exercise be present, it never puts it forth”.
Manning op. cit. p89
Not only did the official theology of the nineteenth century Church
strive to minimise the number of those counting as formally and
culpably heretical. Even the punishment of formal heretics turns,
in the hands of a nineteenth century Catholic bishop Ketteler
addressing worried German liberals and Protestants, into a
'spiritual force', which in its presentation is very deliberately and
carefully made to appear something quite different from any
coercion of belief:
So the 1983 code of canon law, the 'code of Vatican II' undoubtedly
maintains the traditional Tridentine teaching that the Church
possesses a coercive jurisdiction over the baptized.42 Moreover the
penalties applied are not restricted to the spiritual. For example,
expiatory penalties (penalties that serve both to deter and to repair
harm done) can include those that are temporal, as canon 1312 §2
affirms:
“the Church has always affirmed the authority to use such punitive
force on those who are by belief and by baptism her own members.
But such force consists in spiritual and ecclesiastical penalties
which have as their special purpose to bring about their spiritual
improvement”.
In so far as 'spiritual improvement' in heretics or potential heretics
must by its very nature include avoidance of heresy or return from
it, it looks as though we do have here some sort of system of
coercive penalties on religion of the kind that, apparently,
Dignitatis humanae opposes.
But this fails to take into account the penal language. The code
specifically addresses infidelity or heresy not as a simple failure to
meet conditions on membership or employment, but as a wrong or
crime - a delictum - deserving punishment - poena. And the loss of
communion or office or privilege that follows is described in
explicitly punitive terms. And for the Church to threaten a clearly
unwelcome outcome such as job loss specifically as a punishment
for wrong-doing, is precisely to act like any authority seeking
coercively to regulate and influence what people believe and do
and to pressure them away from whatever is being classed as
wrong. By attaching real costs to heresy, and describing those costs
as punishment for what is presented as a crime, the Church is
conveying the very same coercive message that states do when they
attach similarly penal costs to actions classed by them criminal -
namely that what has been penalised really is wrong, and so is not
to be done. The Church is doing exactly what she describes herself
in canon 1311 as having the right to do, namely to give coercive
direction to the baptized - in this case to use the threat of
punishment to influence what the baptized believe, directing them
away from the crime of heresy.
On this very natural and wide understanding of it, there are at least
two kinds of coercive authority that Dignitatis humanae would
have to address. It would have to address the authority and coercive
power of the state and of other civil institutions. And the nature and
extent of that authority is determined just by the natural law, and is
primarily a matter for reason to determine. Then it would have to
address the authority and coercive power of the Church, both over
people in general, and more specifically and especially over the
baptized. And that would be a matter not just for reason to
determine, but for revelation. That holds true especially for the
relation of the Church to the baptized. For baptism is a sacrament
bringing with it membership of an institution that is not merely
human. That institution is the Body of Christ and new People of
God, governed by a law of the New Covenant that is divine and the
content of which is a matter for revelation, serving ends that are
supernatural. Any comprehensive treatment of religious liberty in
relation both to Church and state would then need to proceed at two
levels: immediately at a level of natural reason, in relation to the
state and civil institutions; and then immediately at a level of the
dogmatic exposition of revealed truth, in relation to the authority
of the Church. And in relation to the Church the treatment would
have to address with particular care the case of the baptized and
their obligations to the Church. For it is precisely through baptism
and its obligations, according to the traditional theology, and
indeed according to modern canon law, that the Church possesses
coercive authority at all.
But this is not the form that Dignitatis humanae takes at all. For it
plainly declares at the outset that its purpose is to address the rights
of individuals and groups in civil society, and, in particular, in
relation to the state. The declaration is entitled: On the right of
persons and communities to social and civil liberty in religious
matters. And the declaration further announces in the first
paragraph that since its concerns are with civil liberty, nothing in
the declaration affects traditional teaching concerning people's
obligations to the Church, including those of the baptized:
Indeed after having stated and argued for 'The general principle of
religious freedom' the declaration states:
“The statements made by this Vatican synod on the right of people
to religious freedom have their basis on the dignity of the person,
the demands of which have come to be more fully known to human
reason from the experience of centuries”. §9, Tanner and Alberigo,
p1006
Why might the policy of the Church towards those not yet baptized
be peculiarly relevant to an argument concerned with a specifically
civil liberty of religion? After all, it might be thought, states may
well be able licitly to do lots of things not open to, or not the
business of the Church. Why should limits to what the Church can
rightly do, and in one specific case, be relevant to determining
limitations on state action? In fact the answer is fairly obvious.
According to perfectly traditional teaching, the metaphysical
freedom of the act of faith leaves the unbaptized believer standing
in relevantly the same normative relation to the Church as all
people, baptized or unbaptized, stand in relation to the state. So if
revealed teaching rules out coercion into the faith of the unbaptized
by the Church, that supports the case initially made at the level of
reason against religious coercion by the state.
Why is the relation of the metaphysically free believer to Church
or to state in these two cases in relevant respects normatively the
same? Because in both cases the bearer of authority is dealing with
a being in possession of metaphysical freedom who is not yet
bound by any specifically religious obligation to that authority.
Why cannot the Church coerce the unbaptized into Christianity?
Because, the traditional answer would go - we have seen Suarez
give it - although the metaphysically free believer has a moral
obligation to God to believe the true divine revelation, being
unbaptized he has as yet no such obligation to the Church.
Therefore given the person's metaphysical freedom and the lack of
any such obligation binding him specifically to the Church, the
Church simply has no authority to coerce him into Catholic fidelity.
But the same would hold of the state, and whether or not the person
is baptized. He is metaphysically free, has an obligation to God in
respect of the true religion - but whether baptized or not has no
specifically religious obligations to the state. So given that no one
has any religious obligations to the state, the state has no
specifically religious authority, and so no authority of its own to
coerce or direct anyone in any way in religious matters. The
parallel between limits to the coercive powers of the Church and
those of the state is in this particular case exact. The
incompleteness of the declaration's account of Church teaching and
history is not a problem; or, at least, it is not a problem as part of
an argument that is primarily based on natural reason, and that
specifically concerns the coercive jurisdiction not of the Church
herself but of the state and other like civil institutions.
One thing is now clear. Dignitatis humanae does not address the
coercive jurisdiction of the Church over the baptized. All it
addresses is the authority of states and other civic institutions to
coerce religion. And so on this ground, by virtue of its very subject-
matter, Vatican II's declaration cannot directly contradict Trent's
teaching on coercion of the baptized, if we take that teaching as
Suarez and Bellarmine would have understood it - to concern the
coercive authority of the Church. The Councils are simply teaching
about different kinds of authority: Vatican II is setting limits to the
coercive authority of the state, while Trent is addressing the very
different coercive authority of the Church. But there are also two
further grounds why Vatican II cannot contradict Trent.
First, does not the declaration talk in many places of limits to the
coercive authority in relation to religion of human authority? To
take an example:
“Such freedom consists in this, that all should have such immunity
from coercion by individuals, or by groups, or by any human power
[ex parte ... cuiusvis potestatis humanae], that no one should be
forced to act against his conscience in religious matters, nor
prevented from acting within his conscience, whether in public or
private, whether alone or in association with others, within due
limits”. ibid para 2 p1002
But a number of things can be said about this passage. First, the
coercive jurisdiction of the Church has centrally and historically
been aimed at using pressure to form and change consciences, not
at getting people to betray them.47 Secondly the qualifying 'due
limits' referred to in the declaration should surely include any set
by people's obligations under baptism to the Church. For the
declaration commits itself to respecting traditional teaching
concerning these obligations.
But in any case and most importantly, the term 'human power' is
fairly obviously ambiguous. Is the declaration in this and other like
passages to be understood as talking of any authority involving
humans in its exercise; or is it talking of authority that is human in
its nature, in that it serves and is defined in terms of ends that are
natural to humanity? If the former, then the declaration would
surely be committed by its fundamental terminology to teaching
about all forms of coercive authority on this earth, including that of
the Church. But then the structure and argumentation of the
declaration becomes a nonsense. For the declaration itself
expressly states that it is concerned with specifically political or
civil coercion. And it relies primarily on natural reason to give that
teaching, which it could not straightforwardly afford to do if
ecclesial authority and its limits were to be included in its subject.
Moreover the incompleteness of the account given of the past
exercise of ecclesial authority and of past teaching concerning that
authority would then be objectionable, as seriously dishonest and
misleading.
But what of the Council's frequently repeated claim that the limits
on the state's power to coerce derive from human nature and its
dignity: does not this dignity ground the same liberty in relation to
the Church, if it grounds the liberty at all? The difficulty with this
line of thought is that it assumes the person-centred conception of
religious liberty in the very strategy it employs to read that
conception into the declaration. The dignity of the person involves
their metaphysical freedom and rationality. And of course if - as
the person-centred conception supposes - those features of our
humanity are sufficient on their own, and apart from any juridical
considerations, to base the right to religious liberty, they suffice to
establish that right for the baptized, even against the Church. But
that of course is the very point at issue. Is the fact that human nature
gives us a right not to be coerced in religion by the state dependent
just on our metaphysical status; or does the generation of this right
also depend on the kind of authority involved and the basis and
extent of its jurisdiction, such as the further fact that we have a
different juridical relation to the state than that we have, through
baptism, to the Church?
And that holds for all the ringing affirmations that pepper
Dignitatis humanae about the value of unconstrained enquiry,
about how coercion of belief and conduct goes against our free and
rational nature, and such like.
But people are only able to meet this obligation [to truth] in ways
that accord with their own nature, if they enjoy both psychological
freedom and freedom from external coercion. Thus the right to
religious freedom is based on human nature itself, not on any
merely personal attitude of mind. Tanner and Alberigo p1003.
It might be claimed that the act of faith would not be free or rational
at all if coerced, and this would be so whatever the coercing
authority. But that is not what Vatican II actually claims. It says
that the freedom and rationality of the believer is a justification, or
part of a justification for not coercing faith; not that the freedom
and rationality of the believer makes faith impossible to coerce.
Nor is the last obviously true in any case. For Suarez, as we have
seen, the use of coercive law to direct the faith of the baptized is no
different from any other legitimate use of coercive law. Such fair
use of coercive law involves threatening penalties that, if actually
inflicted, would be deserved. So, as we noted already, for Suarez
the legal coercion of faith presupposes faith's metaphysical
freedom; as with ordinary state law, the legal threat of punishment
serves to direct metaphysical freedom without removing it.
But for Suarez the fair coercive use of law also presupposes a
capacity for rationality in the person coerced and does not remove
or bypass that capacity. The law is not just a brute force, like a kick
or a shove. Pre-modern theology saw coercive penalties as part of
a wider strategy of persuasion that addressed the agent's reason as
well as their freedom. It is often lazily assumed that intellectual
persuasion and the threat of coercive punishment are quite opposed
strategies for altering behaviour. But that was not Suarez's opinion.
Where an authority does have the right to punish, then in his view,
as we have seen, the bearer of that authority can legitimately
combine argumentative persuasion with the threat of coercive
pressure. Now the pressure is indeed intended to motivate
compliance through exploiting dislike of the penalties; but dislike
of the threatened penalties is supposed to work by engaging the
attention of those threatened, and motivating and directing them
seriously to consider what is being argued, thereby facilitating right
understanding. This is precisely how Suarez models the coercion
of believers; as we have already seen him put the matter, coercion
is supposed to help deliver understanding:
“And then the pressure usually gives understanding, so that now
the person believes with a perfect freedom”. Suarez De fide
“... no one can be good against his own will [a state of faith or
charity is not possible per violentiam, in opposition to the person's
then will]; but still, through fear of some unwanted suffering [the
coercive penalties], someone may either lose his spirit of prejudice,
or be compelled to acquaint himself with previously unknown
truth; so that through his fear he should reject the error he once
defended or attain the truth that he did not know before, and now
hold willingly what once he did not wish to hold...[Coercion directs
attention to the truth and thereby motivates a change of will]....We
see that not just these or those persons, but many whole
communities, once Donatist, now are Catholic, and vehemently
renounce devilish schism, and ardently love unity”. Augustine
epistola 93.1649
The laws imposed by modern states arguably work in just the same
way in relation to the various kinds of non-religious action which
those states justly coerce and direct. The function of penal coercion
in the criminal law is often to use the threat of a penalty to engage
attention and help communicate a message that there are anyway
prior grounds to believe - that the action threatened by punishment
really would be seriously wrong. 50 The punishment of crime is
accompanied, in particular, by public witness given by judges and
other representatives of the state for the prior and genuine
wrongness of what is being punished - and it is this witness, and
not an arbitrary command, that the punishment is designed to ram
home. Sentencing is characteristically accompanied by moral
criticism of the criminal - criticism that is revealed as seriously
meant by the gravity of the punishment. Hence the failure to punish
a crime with a penalty of any seriousness can convey the opposite
message: namely that what was done was not, after all, so seriously
wrong. Which is why in such cases of leniency the outrage of the
victim and their friends may not betoken a desire for vengeance,
but rather resentment at what they take to be a literal
understatement of their rights. The function of sanction-backed
criminal law is in part to drive home an argument and change what
people - not non-rational animals but beings equipped with reason
- actually believe. No matter how terrible and unwarranted the
means adopted by the sixteenth century Church's agents, their
conception of the use of law to coerce the baptized into meeting
their obligations was not so very different. The canonical
punishments for heresy and the like threatened by the counter-
reformation Church, or by the modern Church, are no different in
general function from those threatened by today's liberal state: to
communicate testimony or witness to the truth given by
representatives of the coercing authority - witness or testimony that
should anyway be enough to support and warrant assent; and by
impelling attention to the message and its grounds, to pressure
those subject to the authority into believing it.
But here we come across a certain deep irony. Given its subject
matter and the self- imposed restrictions on its scope, even on this
issue the true ground of the declaration is not so obvious. For there
are two quite distinct bases on which the state might seek to coerce
religion: either on its own authority, or acting out of a delegated
competence, through obligation to another competent authority and
on its say-so. The distinction is very important.
One thing is clear. It is evident that for the foreseeable future the
modern Church would always refuse to involve the state in
religious coercion in the ways that, in Ancien Regime Europe, she
once did. And given this refusal to delegate authority on the part of
the Church, the state will indeed have no justification for
involvement in the coercion of religion. Moreover there may also
be compelling moral grounds for the Church's refusal to call upon
the state as she once did, even apart from the fact that no state
would now respond to such a call. But it is not obvious that the text
of Dignitatis humanae is what blocks the Church from ever so
employing its authority. And that, again, is because Dignitatis
humanae simply does not directly engage with the Church's own
authority and with the extent of and limits to her coercive
jurisdiction over the baptized.
7. Conclusion
And again
How far this coercive authority might extend and how and under
what conditions the Church might with strict right give it
expression in various possible canonical obligations or penalties -
that must be a question for dogmatic and moral theology. And this
question has largely been ignored by modern Catholic theology,
though it was, rightly, a central concern for Suarez. One obvious
failing in the modern Church is a lack of any serious reflection,
informed by an honest and comprehensive attention to Catholic
tradition, on the dogmatic basis for and true extent of her own
authority to coerce. The New Commentary on the Code of Canon
Law plaintively complains of the section of the 1983 code that
asserts the Church's authority to impose punishments:
But as we have seen, it was precisely on this ground - that the state's
own authority to coerce serves only natural ends - that the counter-
reformation theology of Suarez also denied the state any authority
to coerce the baptized into fidelity to their baptism.
The Church remains dogmatically committed to her possession of
a coercive power over the baptized unlike any that liberals would
accord the state over its citizens. The Church is given, by virtue of
a mission that transcends nature, a coercive authority over her
members to hold them to the faith - though how extensive this
authority might be and how it might properly be exercised we have
not yet determined; and this authority is of a kind that no earthly
state can possess over anyone, and which (as Trent clearly
indicates) the individual, once baptized, cannot throw off at will.
“In truth Jesus Christ gave his Apostles free authority in matters
sacred, together with a true power to legislate and what follows
therefrom, the twofold power to judge and to punish... Hence, it is
the Church, and not the State, that is to be man's guide to heaven:
and it is to the same Church that God has assigned the charge of
seeing to, and legislating for, what concerns religion”. Leo XIII
Immortale dei §11
And again:
“The Almighty, therefore, has given the charge of the human race
to two powers, the ecclesiastical and the civil, the one being set
over divine, the other over human, things... While one of the two
powers has for its immediate and chief object care of the goods of
this mortal life, the other provides for goods that are heavenly and
everlasting. Whatever, therefore, in things human is in any way of
a sacred character, whatever belongs either of its own nature or by
reason of the end to which it is referred, to the salvation of souls or
to the worship of God, is subject to the power and judgment of the
Church. Whatever is to be ranged under the civil and political order
is rightly subject to the civil authority”. Leo XIII Immortale dei
§13-§14
But the political case does not exhaust the subject, as the dogmatic
teaching of Trent has shown. And deep theological principles are
at stake. Although the language of Vatican II's declaration is often
that of secular liberalism, when integrated into tradition the
fundamental structure really is quite different. Faith is free from
coercion by the state not because of some secular doctrine of simple
respect for persons owed equally by all authorities, but because, as
Dignitatis humanae itself states, our metaphysical freedom is
oriented toward an end that transcends nature, an end to which the
baptized are directed through the authority of the Church. And this
being the true basis of limitations to state authority over religion,
there is no reason why the authority of the Church should be limited
in exactly the same way. Religious liberty is a topic which we shall
only fully understand once we extract ourselves from the
perspective of our immediate political context, and reintegrate
Vatican II and its decrees into the teaching of the magisterium as a
whole and into a richer view of the theological tradition. And so I
have tried here to begin to do.
Thomas Pink
Professor of Philosophy King's College London
Hobbes denied that the Church can licitly coerce as well as teach.
Only the State had the right to legislate and punish. Properly under-
stood, canonical regulation was only ever obligatory law if
voluntarily legislated and enforced as part of their own civil law by
the rulers of states, the only true possessors of coercive authority:
From the same mistaking of the present Church for the Kingdom
of God, came in the distinction between the Civill and the Canon
Laws: The Civil Law being the Acts of Soveraigns in their own
Dominions, and the Canon Law being the acts of the Pope in the
same Dominions. Which Canons, though they were but Canons,
that is, Rules Propounded, and but voluntarily received by
Christian Princes, till the translation of the Empire to Charlemain;
yet after-wards, as the power of the Pope increased, became Rules
Commanded, and the Emperours themselves (to avoyd greater
mischiefes, which the people blinded might be led into) were
forced to let them pass for Laws2.
For scholastic ethical theory, law is closely bound up with one very
special and distinctive human capacity – human freedom
understood as a power or capacity to determine outcomes. We
naturally think of our- selves as having a power to determine for
ourselves how we decide and act. This power of self-determination,
which philosophers call freedom or free will, is multi-way, making
alternatives by way of decision and action available to us. It is up
to me whether I walk away or remain where I am – and also up to
me which of these actions I decide to perform. I have control over
which actions I perform, and, beforehand, over which actions I
decide to perform.
How is our free will taken to base a right to liberty? The answer is
simple. Freedom is a power to determine for ourselves what we do.
And the right to liberty is understood by Suarez as the right to
exercise this power – as the right to determine for ourselves what
we do. The power bases the right because the right concerns the
power. How, without the power, could we possess the right to
exercise it? In everyday English we can use the same terms both to
assert our possession of freedom as a power and to assert freedom
as a right. I might say: «It’s up to me what I do» simply to report
that I actually do possess control over what I do. But I could also
use the phrase to assert not the power but the right – as a right not
to be coerced. If you attempt to direct me to do something, and back
this direction up with threats, I might protest: «Don’t you tell me
what to do; it is up to me what I do». In the scholastic tradition we
find the same shifting application of terms to assert both the power
and the right. Dominium can mean freedom or libertas as a power;
or it can used, as in dominium libertatis, to mean the right to
exercise the power:
‘If, however, we are speaking of the natural law of dominion, it is
then true that liberty is a matter of natural law, in a positive, not
merely a negative sense, since nature itself confers upon man the
true dominion of his liberty (dominium libertatis). For liberty rather
than slavery is of natural right, for this reason, namely, that nature
has made men free in a positive sense (so to speak) with an intrinsic
right to liberty, whereas it has not made them slaves in this positive
sense, strictly speaking’7.
The right to liberty does not rule all coercion out as illegitimate.
But it does establish that no individual naturally has the right
coercively to direct another. Coercion, if legitimate, requires
special justification. In particular it requires some form of public
authority with jurisdiction. That jurisdiction must extend to the
kind of activity that the authority is seeking punitively to direct;
and the individual being directed must fall under that jurisdiction.
“This holy synod teaches however concerning the Jews that no one
then is to be forced to believe (nemini deinceps vim ad credendum
inferre). God has mer- cy as he pleases, and hardens hearts as he
pleases. People are not to be saved against their will, but willingly,
that the demands of justice be respected. For as man perished in
obedience to the serpent by his own will (propria arbitrii
voluntate) so too through the call of divine grace each person is
saved through the conversion of his own mind in faith. Thus people
are to be persuaded to convert by free will (libera arbitrii
facultate), not compelled by force. As for those who have already
been compelled into Christianity (as was done in the times of the
most pious ruler Sisebut) since they are already linked to the holy
sacraments and have received the grace of baptism, and been
anointed with chrism, and have publicly partaken of the body of
the Lord, it is required that they be compelled to hold the faith that
they received by force or necessity, lest the name of the Lord be
blasphemed and the faith that they received be held vile and
contemptible”9.
For the scholastic tradition, then, law and freedom are intimately
related. In affording a right to liberty, and then in licensing
limitation of that liberty through punitively enforced obligations,
law is combining two modes by which the human power of free
will or freedom is given normative recognition.
“For though they that speak of this subject, use to confound Jus,
and Lex, Right and Law; yet they ought to be distinguished; because
RIGHT, consisteth in liberty to do, or to forbeare; Whereas LAW
determineth, and bindeth to one of them; so that Law, and Right,
differ as much, as Obligation and Liberty; which in one and the
same matter are inconsistent”12.
The function of law, for Hobbes, would now be just to limit liberty;
and liberty would come to no more than what is left open to us by
the obligations of the law. This generated a fundamental problem
within Hobbes’s theory of coercive authority and the State. What
was left to limit the attempts of an earthly sovereign to coerce us?
Certainly not any right to liberty on our part, based on our power
of self-determination or free will, that the State might be under an
obligation to respect; and this left Hobbes with a considerable
problem where the coercion of belief was concerned – a problem
to which we shall return.
Nothing thus far would have been controversial for early mod- ern
Catholics. Few Catholics then denied, as Hobbes denied, that the
Church was indeed a coercive authority, with a general right to
legislate canonically and to enforce her laws with punishments.
Suarez and Bellarmine were both of course aware that there was a
very general question about how any form of human legal
direction, be it by Church or State, can play a role in taking us to a
supernatural end. How can hu- man legal direction and correction
play a role in salvation, when salvation is a gift of divine grace?
But there was a ready Catholic answer to this general question, and
one with which most of their co-religionists would have been
comfortable. The answer is that here as elsewhere in the economy
of salvation, grace itself uses human agency as its instrument,
especially through works of charity – in this case moving humans
to assist other humans by correcting them. As Suarez put it:
“It is replied that men cannot by their own power direct others to
the super- natural end, but they can do this with the assistance of
the Holy Spirit, from whom they obtain the authority; and although
the efficacy and the growth is always given by God, through his
grace, yet men too can plant and water and thus direct people
through laws toward the supernatural end; and by the same reason
they can through spiritual or other congruent penalties restrain
people from sins in relation to eternal salvation, which is prevented
by sin. And though human coercion cannot just by itself change the
internal will, where sin properly is to be found, nonetheless this
coercion is necessary; both be- cause discomfort (vexatio) tends to
produce understanding, and also because once the opportunity or
ease of performing the external action is removed, the will
abandons the internal affection much more easily; and finally
because external observance is necessary to the good of the
Church, and to avoiding scandals and dissensions and the like.
Therefore the shepherds of the Church use authority that is both
directive and coercive, and effect through their laws
established”13.
These two questions address the relation in human law between the
spiritual and the temporal, but from opposite directions. The first
question is about whether religion can be the business of a coercive
authority, the State, whose concerns might immediately appear
earthly and temporal rather than heavenly or spiritual. Can the
earthly concern itself with heavenly ends? The second question is
about how far a primarily spiritual authority that serves spiritual
ends can use earthly means. How far can the heavenly make use of
the earthly?
“For the matter of civil law is more principally and mainly what
pertains to human justice: whereas the main concern of canon law
is what pertains to divine justice and religion, for almost everything
else is ordered to this, as evident from what we have said. As
regards this area, civil authority is more limited now within the
Church, than it was before the Christian religion; for once the care
of religion was oriented towards to the virtue and happiness of the
commonwealth, as we noted above from St Thomas; but now
religion itself, and spiritual salvation and spiritual happiness are the
priority, and the rest for their sake; and therefore once the care of
religion either belonged to the authority of the ruler, or was joined
with that authority in one and the same person, or was subordinated
to the authority of the ruler: now however the care of religion is
specially given to the shepherds of the Church”18.
“The Almighty, therefore, has given the charge of the human race
to two powers (potestates), the ecclesiastical and the civil, the one
being set over di- vine, the other over human, things [...] While one
of the two powers has for its immediate and chief object care of the
goods of this mortal life, the other provides for goods that are
heavenly and everlasting. Whatever, therefore, in things human is
in any way of a sacred character, whatever belongs either of its own
nature or by reason of the end to which it is referred, to the salvation
of souls or to the worship of God, is wholly subject to the power
and judgment of the Church” (id est omne in potestate arbitrioque
Ecclesiae)19.
“When Peter was told «Feed my sheep» (John last chapter), he was
given every authority that is necessary for a shepherd to protect his
sheep. To the shepherd a threefold authority is necessary: one
concerns wolves, so that he may keep them away in any way he
can; the second concerns the rams, so that if they ever hit the flock
with their horns he may be able to confine them; the third concerns
the rest of the sheep, so that he may provide each one of them with
the proper forage. And therefore the Supreme Pontiff has this
threefold authority”21.
Why does the status of being a sheep involve the political as well
as the private person of the ruler? The fundamental argument is
from the unity of the flock, and so of the Christian community as a
whole. This unity means that in matters of religion, while it is true
that people retain their temporal rights, no part of that community’s
temporal or earthly nature is exempt from ecclesial direction for
spiritual ends. So, for example, individual Christians continue to
have a right to private property; but they can nevertheless be
obligated by their baptism to make a portion of their goods
available at the Church’s direction when needed for the Church’s
mission:
“I reply that private men who are admitted into the Church do not
forfeit their goods and other temporal rights, and yet they can be
obliged by the Church to support their parish priests and, as the
Apostle says, let those who sow spiritual things reap carnal things
(1 Corinthians 9:11), and they were hardly bound to do these things
before accepting the faith”23.
“By the same token, temporal princes who join Christ’s household
lose neither their power nor their jurisdiction but subject
themselves to him whom Christ has put in charge of his household,
to be ruled and led by him in the path that leads to life”24.
Suarez emphasizes that this subjection has to be political because
the flock of the baptised must be one:
Scripture was used to establish not only that coercive authority ex-
tending to the use of temporal means had been given to the
Apostles, but that this authority to coerce had actually been
exercised by them. One important passage appealed to in this
connexion is from Acts, where, appealing to the authority of
Augustine28, Ambrose and Gregory the Great, Suarez interprets
the deaths of Ananias and Saphira as a punishment inflicted on
them by St Peter – a just penalty imposed by the apostolic possessor
of a coercive jurisdiction over the baptized:
“And finally, lest this power [to use temporal means of coercion]
be completely hidden at the beginning of the Church, since the
Apostles could not then exercise it in the ordinary way because of
the numbers and strength of the unbelievers, some miraculous signs
were given of this power: such a sign was made through Peter in
Acts 5, when at his command Ananias and Saphira died, about
which Ambrose says (sermon 19), «While he punishes one, he
corrects others, for he wanted punishment to touch one and fear to
touch the others»29.
Other passages are cited by Suarez to establish the apostolic
punitive authority not only of St Peter but also of St Paul, as in 1
Corinthians 5 where St Paul decrees that for the good of his
salvation a member of the Church at Corinth guilty of incest be
«handed over to Satan for the destruction of the flesh» (that is, as
Suarez understands St Paul’s decree, subjected to a temporal
punishment).
‘If anyone says that when they grow up [cum adoleverint], those
baptized as little children should be asked whether they wish to
affirm what their godpa- rents promised in their name when they
were baptized; and that, when they reply that they have no such
wish, they should be left to their own decision and not, in the
meantime, be coerced by any penalty into the Christian life [suo
esse arbitrio relinquendos nec alia interim poena ad christianam
vitam cogendos], except that they be barred from the reception of
the eucharist and the other sacraments, until they have a change of
heart: let him be anathema’37.
The coercion of the act of faith has often been seen as raising
special problems. But the perceived nature of these problems has
taken very different forms.
Within the Catholic tradition, the issue was not traditionally the
very possibility or legitimacy of coercing belief – that possibility
and legitimacy was taken as evident in the early modern period.
The problem within the Catholic tradition had more to do with the
implications of the canonical regulation of belief for the theory of
human positive law. Some canonists saw the coercion of belief as
helping to establish that though just as much a form of humanly
legislated positive law as the civil law of the State, canon law
operated in a fundamentally different way from civil law,
addressing internal acts in a way that civil law did not.
But outside the Catholic Church the issue did indeed involve, from
the early modern period on, the legitimacy and even the very
possibility of coercing belief. And one thinker greatly responsible
for this radical reframing of the issue was Thomas Hobbes.
Some thought that the positive law of the Church had to work
differently, just because it did govern mental states such as belief.
Suarez cites the view, of Pighius and others, that because of the
spiritual nature of the Church, canon law, though a form of positive
humanly legislated law, is fundamentally unlike civil law in that
canon law does directly address internal acts, such as belief
considered as a purely internal mental State:
For granted that we defined above concerning human law in
general that it cannot address internal acts, there is a special
difficulty for that view in the case of canon law, which we have left
for this place. For there is a general reason for doubting the view,
in that ecclesial authority is spiritual, and is principally directed at
the internal good of souls, and has a more elevated principle,
namely God himself supernaturally conferring that authority, and
therefore on either account this authority appears immediately
concerned with internal acts42.
But Suarez did not accept that civil and canon law worked in
different ways. Suarez admitted that canon law might indeed have
addressed internal acts directly, had Christ given the Church the
required authority – which, Suarez conceded, Christ certainly had
had the power to do. But there was, in Suarez’s view, no evidence
that Christ had actually granted the Church such an authority; in
particular, the practice and legal tradition of the Church gave no
support to Pighius’s hypothesis that Christ had done so43.
In Suarez’s view, canon law actually worked exactly as did civil
law. Just like civil law, canon law and its enforcement was directly
concerned with the external good of a human community, and so
addressed external acts. But just as civil law did too, canon law
addressed the character of those external acts as they affected the
community’s good. And external acts could affect the good of a
community through being expressive of internal acts – internal acts
that then formed the public moral character of the external acts that
expressed them, so that positive law could address those internal
acts as well. In such cases, when so constitutive of the moral
character of the external acts, internal acts too could be subject to
the direction of human positive law.
Laws directive of belief were not peculiar to canon law. They could
be part of civil law too, and in Suarez’s view when serving to apply
the natural law could be based on purely political authority. We
have already seen one central case. Natural law-based State
authority might not be competent to direct or enforce any particular
supernatural belief. But it could, at least in principle, enforce
natural religion – belief in rational monotheism:
“As for the inward thought, and beleef of men, which humane
Governours can take no notice of, (for God onely knoweth the
heart) they are not voluntary, nor the effect of the laws, but of the
unrevealed will, and of the power of God; and consequently fall
not under obligation”50.
It is clear from this passage that Suarez is not presuming that belief
can be formed just at will, irrespective of testimony or evidence.
Belief is importantly non-voluntary because it is directed at its
object as true, and so is dependent on truth-related testimony or
evidence. State coercion serves simply to direct attention to that
testimony or evidence: in the case of belief in God, to rational
proofs of God’s existence, or to the witness of experts to the
existence and soundness of such proofs.
But despite all these modern protests that the project of coercing
belief is “essentially fruitless”, the coercive structures of early
modern states could be very effective at changing what large
numbers of people believed. Indeed, modern states do still appear
to go to some length to influence belief, not just by various forms
of positive recognition and endorsement, but also by the threat and
application of sanctions. The function of penal coercion in the
criminal law is often to use the threat of a penalty to engage
attention and help communicate a message that there are anyway
prior grounds to believe – that the action threatened by punishment
really would be seriously wrong.53 The punishment of crime is
accompanied, in particular, by public witness given by judges and
other representatives of the State for the prior and genuine wrong-
ness of what is being punished – and it is this witness, and not an
arbitrary command, that the punishment is designed to ram home.
Sentencing is characteristically accompanied by moral criticism of
the criminal – criticism that is revealed as seriously meant by the
gravity of the punishment. Hence the failure to punish a crime with
a penalty of any seriousness can convey the opposite message:
namely that what was done was not, after all, so seriously wrong.
Which is why in such cases of leniency the outrage of the victim
and their friends may not betoken a desire for vengeance, but rather
resentment at what they take to be a literal understatement of their
rights. The function of sanction-backed criminal law is in part to
drive home an argument and change what people actually believe.
No matter how terrible and unwarranted the means adopted by the
sixteenth century Church’s agents, their conception of the use of
law to coerce the baptized into meeting their obligations was not
so very different. The canonical punishments for heresy and the
like threatened by the counter-reformation Church were no
different in general function from the criminal punishments
threatened by today’s liberal State: to communicate testimony or
witness to the truth given by representatives of the coercing
authority – witness or testimony that should anyway be enough to
support and warrant assent; and by impelling attention to the
message and its grounds, to pressure those subject to the authority
into believing it.