Henry Sidgwick - Essays On Ethics and Method (British Moral Philosophers) (2001)
Henry Sidgwick - Essays On Ethics and Method (British Moral Philosophers) (2001)
Henry Sidgwick - Essays On Ethics and Method (British Moral Philosophers) (2001)
Contents
Preface ix
Abbreviations xiii
Introduction: The Philosophy of Henry Sidgwick xiv
A Note on the Contents xxxix
A Note on Grote xlv
PART I. ETHICS
1. Utilitarianism (1873) 3
1. Utilitarianism
show chapter abstract and keywords
hide chapter abstract and keywords
Henry Sidgwick
In writing the present paper, it has been my object to avoid all but incontrovertible
propositions. I have, therefore, left on one side many interesting questions; and have
been careful not to dogmatise upon any point where scientific certainty did not
appear to be attainable. If it be thought strange to offer to a society that exists for
purposes of debate, a series of incontrovertible propositions, I would urge, first, that
in most discussions on Utilitarianism I find one or more of these propositions, at
important points of the argument, implicitly ignored; and secondly, that a wide
experience shows that an ethical or metaphysical proposition is not the less likely to
provoke controversy because it is put forth as incontrovertible.
By Utilitarianism I mean the ethical theory that the externally or objectively right
conduct, under any circumstances, is such conduct as tends to produce the greatest
possible happiness, to the greatest possible number of all whose interests are
affected.
The statement is not yet quite definite, but whatever vagueness attaches to it will (I
hope) be removed in the course of my observations.
And first, let us distinguish this doctrine from others of a quite different nature to
which the term 'Utilitarian' has been applied, but with which Utilitarianism, as above
defined, has no necessary connection, though with some of them it has a certain
natural affinity.
I. Utilitarianism, according to the definition, is an ethical, and not a psychological
doctrine: a theory not of what is, but of what ought to be. Therefore, more particularly,
it does not include the following psychological theories:—(1) the proposition that in
human action, universally or normally, each agent seeks his own individual
happiness or pleasure. This is obviously compatible with any theory of ethics, i.e., of
right and wrong in outward conduct. For, as Aristotle says, our idea of a virtuous man
includes the characteristic that he takes pleasure in doing what he thinks he ought to
do; and the question whether we are to say that he does his duty because he
recognises it as duty, or because he finds a moral pleasure in doing it, whatever
importance it may have from some points of view, has at least no necessary
connection with the question what conduct he ought to
end p.3
pursue. It may be said that from the psychological generalisation that all men do seek
pleasure there is a natural transition to the ethical principle that pleasure is what they
ought to seek. But, in the first place, this transition is at best only natural, and not
logical or necessary; and secondly, the ethical conclusion to which we thus pass is
primarily that of Egoism or Egoistic Hedonism (which states the agent's own
happiness as the ultimate end of his actions), and not of Utilitarianism, as I have
defined it. Clearly, from the fact that every one actually does seek his own happiness,
we cannot conclude, as an immediate and obvious inference, that he ought to seek
the happiness of other people.
Nor (2) is Utilitarianism, as a theory of ethics proper, connected with the doctrine
(belonging to what may be called ethical psychology), that the moral sentiments are
derived from experiences of non-moral pleasures and pains.
For (a) these moral sentiments are now (considered as facts of our present
consciousness), independent impulses, often conflicting with the more primary
impulses from which they are thought to be derived, and having each its own proper
pleasure and pain consequent on its being followed or resisted. And it seems quite
arbitrary (and indeed opposed to our general notions of progress and development)
to assume that impulses earlier in the growth of the individual or of the race ought
always, in case of conflict, to prevail over those that have emerged at a later period;
especially as the former* are commonly thought to be lower and coarser. In a similar
way, the pleasures of the Fine Arts seem to be derivative from, and a kind of complex
reflection of, more primitive sensations and emotions; but that is not thought a reason
why a cultivated person should now prefer the latter to the former.
And (b) it must be observed, on the other side, that however true this account of our
moral sentiments may be, the conduct to which they impel us is none the less liable
to conflict with the dictates of Rational Utilitarianism. For these sentiments will have
been derived, on this theory, from a very partial experience of the effects of conduct,
apprehended and interpreted by very imperfect sympathy and intelligence.
Indeed (3), even if we hold with Hume that our present moral likings always attach to
conduct that gives non-moral pleasure, directly or indirectly, to ourselves or to others,
and our moral aversions to the reverse, the question still remains undetermined
whether we ought simply to yield to these sentiments, or to replace or control them
by Bentham's calculus of consequences. Nay, further, the mere recognition and
explanation of these sentiments, as facts of consciousness, does not necessarily
affirm the ultimate and supreme authority either of the sentiments themselves or of
Rational Utilitarianism (as above defined). For it may be held that these, along with
other impulses, are properly under the dominion
end p.4
of Rational Self-love; and that it is really only reasonable to gratify them, in so far as
we expect to find our own private happiness in such gratification.
II. It may seem superfluous to state that Utilitarianism (in my sense) or Universalistic
Hedonism, as it might be called, is not to be confounded with the Egoistic Hedonism
to which I have just referred. In fact the two principles are primâ facie incompatible,
as a regard for the interests of society at large frequently imposes on the individual
the (at least apparent) sacrifice of his own interests.
III. I understand Utilitarianism to supply a principle and method for determining the
objective or material rightness of conduct. The distinction and occasional separation
between this and subjective or formal rightness, rightness of intention; and the
question which of the two is intrinsically better and more valuable; need not be taken
as decided by Utilitarianism. The two kinds of rightness cannot present themselves to
anyone as competing alternatives, in the case of his own future conduct. No doubt
they may so present themselves in our dealings with others; for the question may
then arise whether and how far we ought to induce others, by non-moral motives
such as the fear of punishment, to do what we think right contrary to their
consciences. But this question seems to present equal difficulties, whatever theory of
ethics we adopt.
Let us now examine the principle itself somewhat closer. It propounds as ultimate
end and standard of right conduct 'the greatest happiness of all concerned', or (as
the interests of some of the persons concerned must sometimes be sacrificed to the
interests of the remainder) 'the greatest possible happiness' of 'the greatest possible
number'. Now each of these notions requires somewhat more determination and
explanation to make it quite clear. In the first place, 'happiness' must be understood
as equivalent to 'pleasure'. It has, I think, been always so understood in recent times,
both by Utilitarians and their opponents; though in the ethical controversies of Greece
very different views were held as to the relation of the corresponding notions
eudaimonia and hēdonē. And even at the present day, many persons declare that
'happiness' is something quite different from 'pleasure'. But such persons seem to
use the term 'pleasure' in a narrower sense than Utilitarians, who include under it all
satisfactions and enjoyments, from the highest to the lowest, all kinds of feeling or
consciousness which move the will to maintain them when present, and to produce
them when absent. So understood, Pleasure cannot be distinguished from
Happiness, except that Happiness is rather used to denote a sum or series of those
transitory feelings each of which we call a Pleasure. The Utilitarian, then, aims at
making the sum of preferable or desirable feelings in the world, so far as it depends
on his actions, as great as possible. But here another qualification is required. For
much of our conduct inevitably produces pain as well as pleasure to ourselves or to
others; and a recognition of the undesirability of pain, seems an inseparable
concomitant and counterpart of that recognition of the desirability of pleasure on
which Utilitarianism is based. And in fact, Utilitarians have always treated pain as the
end p.5
negative quantity of pleasure. So that, strictly speaking, Utilitarian right conduct is
that which produces not the greatest amount of pleasure on the whole, but the
greatest surplus of pleasure over pain, the pain being conceived as balanced against
an equal amount of pleasure, so that the two mutually annihilate each other for
purpose of ethical calculation.
There is therefore an assumption involved in the very notion of Maximum Happiness,
the magnitude and importance of which have somewhat escaped notice. It is
assumed that all pleasures are capable of being compared quantitatively with each
other and with all pains,—that every kind of feeling has a certain intensive quantity,
positive or negative (or perhaps zero), in respect of preferableness or desirableness,
and that this quantity can be known; so that each can be weighed in ideal scales
against every other. Unless this be assumed, the notion of Maximum Happiness is
logically impossible; the attempt to make 'as great as possible' a sum of elements not
quantitatively commensurable, is as much a mathematical absurdity as an attempt to
subtract three ounces of cheese from four pounds of butter. It does not come within
my plan to discuss whether this assumption be justifiable or not, but I wish to point
out that it is at any rate not verifiable by experience, and that very plausible
objections may be brought against it on empirical grounds. For though, no doubt, we
all of us are continually comparing pleasures and pronouncing one preferable to
another, we are all aware that in different moods we perform the same comparison
with different results; sometimes we are more susceptible of enjoyment from one
source, and sometimes from another; and similarly, in respect of our sensitiveness to
pains. How, then, can we be sure that we are ever in a perfectly neutral mood, in
which all pleasures are represented according to their true hedonistic value? How
can we tell that such a mood is actually possible, and not a philosophical chimaera?
And the difficulty is increased when we take into account the different preferences of
different persons. How, e.g., can we decide scientifically the old controversy between
intellectual and sensual pleasures? When Plato and Mill tell us that we must trust the
decision of the intellectual man, because he has tried both, the argument is obviously
inadequate, for we can never tell that he is capable of experiencing sensual
pleasures equal in degree to those of the sensualist; and in fact, it often appears on
various grounds probable that he is not so capable. Therefore just as, for comparing
the pleasures of a single individual, we have to assume a neutral or standard mood,
in which he is free from any of those tendencies to over-estimate or under-estimate
particular pleasures or pains, to which he continually finds himself liable in other
moods; so for the Utilitarian comparison we require to assume a standard man, who
can represent to himself the pleasures of all men as they actually are, free from any
bias for or against any kind of pleasure or pain. I repeat that I am not arguing against
these assumptions; but since Hedonism is often regarded as 'Relativism' applied to
morals, it seems important to show that, on the contrary, the hedonistic comparison
necessarily
end p.6
assumes an absolute standard of preferableness in feeling which cannot be
empirically exhibited: and that the 'principle of Relativity', if rigorously applied, would
render Utilitarianism a logical impossibility.
So much for 'Greatest Happiness'; let us now consider the notion of 'Greatest
Number'. The first question is, Number of what? Sentient beings generally, or any
particular kind of them? Any selection is primâ facie arbitrary and unreasonable; and
in fact, Utilitarians have generally adopted the former alternative. I notice this chiefly
because the scientific difficulties of the hedonistic comparison just discussed seem
thus considerably increased. Practically, Utilitarians have confined themselves
almost entirely to human pleasures; adding, I suppose, to the assumptions above
mentioned a further special assumption (also incapable of empirical proof) as to the
comparative inferiority of the pleasures of the inferior animals. But even if we confine
our attention to human beings, the notion of 'greatest number' is not yet quite
determinate. For we can to some extent influence the number of future human
beings, and the question arises, how, on Utilitarian principles, this number ought to
be determined. Now, of course, the more the better, supposing average happiness to
remain the same. But supposing we foresee that an increase in numbers will be
accompanied with a decrease in average happiness, or vice-versâ, how then shall
we decide? It seems clear that, on the Utilitarian method, we have to weigh the
amount of happiness enjoyed by the extra number against the happiness lost by the
remainder. I notice this, because the Malthusian economists often seem to assume
that no increase of numbers can be right which involves any decrease in average
happiness. But this is clearly inconsistent with the Utilitarian principles which these
economists commonly avow; on these principles, the point up to which population
ought to increase is not that at which average happiness is a maximum, but at which
the product formed by multiplying the number of men into the amount of average
happiness is the greatest possible.
If now the principle of Utilitarianism may be considered as sufficiently determined, as
far as the limits of the present paper admit, I should like to say a few words about its
proof. It may be said that it is impossible to 'prove' a first principle; and this is of
course true, if by proof we mean a process which exhibits the principle in question as
an inference from premisses upon which it remains dependent for its certainty: for
these premisses, and not the inference drawn from them, would then be the real first
principles. Nay, if Utilitarianism is to be proved to a man who already holds some
other moral principles, say to an Intuitional or Common-Sense moralist, who regards
as final the principles of Truth, Justice, Obedience to authority, Purity, &c.; or to an
Egoist who regards his own interest as the ultimately reasonable end of his conduct:
the process must be one which establishes a conclusion actually superior in validity
to the premisses from which it starts. For the Utilitarian prescriptions of duty are
primâ facie in conflict, at certain points and under certain circumstances, both with
Intuitional rules, and
end p.7
with the dictates of Rational Egoism: so that Utilitarianism, if accepted at all, must be
accepted as overruling Intuitionism and Egoism. At the same time, if the other
principles are not throughout taken as valid, the so-called proof does not seem to be
addressed to the Intuitionist or Egoist at all. How shall we deal with this dilemma?
and how is such a process (certainly very different from ordinary proof) possible or
conceivable? It seems that what is needed is a line of argument which, on the one
hand, allows the validity, to a certain extent, of the principles already accepted, and
on the other hand, shows them to be imperfect—not absolutely and independently
valid, but needing qualification and completion. It may be worth while to investigate
briefly such a line of argument in the two cases of Intuitionism and Egoism
respectively. To the Intuitionist the Utilitarian endeavours to show that the principles
of Truth, Justice, &c., have only a dependent and subordinate validity: arguing either
that the principle is really only affirmed by Common Sense as a general rule
admitting of exceptions, as in the case of Truth; or that the fundamental notion is
vague, and needs further determination, as in the case of Justice; and further, that
the different rules are liable to conflict with each other, and that we require some
higher principle to decide the issue just raised; and again, that the rules are
differently formulated by different persons, and that these differences admit of no
intuitional solution, while they show the vagueness and ambiguity of the common
moral notions, to which the Intuitionist appeals; and that in all these cases Common
Sense naturally turns to the Utilitarian principle for the further determinations and
decisions required. Thus the relation between Utilitarianism and Intuitionism seems
to have both a positive and a negative aspect. Positively Utilitarianism supports and
sustains the general validity of the current moral rules, by showing a further
justification of them, besides the intuitive recognition of their stringency, and also a
principle of synthesis and method of binding them into a complete and harmonious
system. Negatively, in order to show them dependent and subordinate to its own
principle, it has to exhibit their imperfections, as above. I may observe that each of
these two aspects has been too exclusively prominent in different periods of English
ethical thought. Utilitarianism, as introduced by Cumberland, is too purely
conservative; it dwells entirely on the general conduciveness of moral rules to the
general good, and ignores the imperfections of these rules as commonly conceived.
On the other hand, the Utilitarianism of Bentham is too purely destructive, and treats
the morality of Common Sense with needless acrimony and contempt.
The relation between Utilitarianism and Egoism is much more simple, though it
seems hard to state it with perfect exactness, and in fact, it is formulated very
differently by different writers who appear to be substantially agreed, as Clarke, Kant,
and Mill. If the Egoist strictly confines himself to stating his conviction that he ought to
take his own happiness or pleasure as his ultimate end, there seems no opening for
an argument to lead him to Utilitarianism (as a first principle). But
end p.8
if he offers either as a reason for this conviction, or as another form of stating it, the
proposition that his happiness or pleasure is objectively 'desirable' or 'a good', he
gives the requisite opening. For the Utilitarian can then point out that his happiness
cannot be more objectively desirable or more a good than the happiness of any one
else; the mere fact (if I may so put it) that he is he can have nothing to do with its
objective desirability or goodness. Hence starting with his own principle, he must
accept the wider notion of universal happiness or pleasure as representing the real
end of Reason, the absolutely Good or Desirable: as the end, therefore, to which the
action of a reasonable agent ought to be directed.
It is to be observed that the proof of Utilitarianism, thus addressed to the Egoist, is
quite different from an exposition of the sanctions of Utilitarian rules; i.e., the
pleasures and pains that will follow respectively on their observance and violation.
Obviously such an exposition cannot lead us to accept Utilitarianism as a first
principle, but only as a conclusion deduced from or a special application of Egoism.
At the same time, the two, proof and sanction, the reason for accepting the greatest
happiness of the greatest number as (in Bentham's language) the 'right and proper'
end of action, and the individual's motives for making it his end, are very frequently
confused in discussion.
This is the last point that it seemed to me necessary to clear up, in order to obtain a
distinct idea of that theory of right conduct which I believe to be generally meant by
the term Utilitarian, and of its relation to other theories of the right or reasonable in
human action. Whether my statements are incontrovertible or not, I think that when
the issues raised by them are definitely settled, it will perhaps be more profitable than
at present to discuss the question whether one is or is not a Utilitarian.
end p.9
can hardly find acceptance. At the same time, we must admit that ζ ν (in Aristotelian
phrase) is a necessary condition of ε ζ ν and, since living at all has been a
somewhat difficult task to human communities, until a very recent period in the
history of our race, the most important part of the function of the moral sense has
consisted in the enforcement of those habits of life which were indispensable to the
mere permanent existence of any society of human beings. This seems to me the
element of truth in Mr. Darwin's view, and in that hypothetical construction of the
origin and growth of the moral sense with which he has connected it. We may admit
further that any defect in the capacity for continued existence would be a fault in a
social system which no excellences of a different kind can counterbalance; but this is
a very different thing from saying that all possible improvement may be resolved into
some increase of this capacity.
IV. If, then, the Well-being of living things is somewhat different from their mere
Being, however secured and extended in space or time, what is the content of this
notion 'well' or 'good'? I have elsewhere tried to show that the only satisfactory
answer to this question is that of the old-fashioned Utilitarianism which Mr. Darwin
and his disciples are trying to transcend. The only rational ultimate ground, in my
opinion, for pronouncing any sentient being in a 'good' condition, is that its condition
is calculated to produce as great an amount as is under the circumstances possible
of Happiness, that is, pleasant or desirable feeling or consciousness: taking into
consideration not its own happiness only—for we have no rational ground for
preferring this to any other happiness—but that of all
end p.16
sentient beings, present or future, on whose manner of existence it exercises any
influence. If this be so, it only remains to ask how far the notion of Progress or
Elevation in the scale of life, as understood by Evolutionists, supplies us with clear
guidance to the right means for attaining this ultimate end. Now, no doubt, in
comparing the happiness of man with that of the lower animals, or the happiness of
civilised man with that of savages, we commonly assume that amount of happiness
varies according to degree in scale of organisation. We do this because what we
really mean by 'higher life' seems, when we look closely at the notion, to be
convertible with more life. As Mr. Spencer says, 'we regard as the highest life that
which shows great complexity in the correspondences, great rapidity in the
succession of them, and great length in the series of them'; the two former
characteristics supplying a measure of the intensive quantity of life lived in a given
time, and the latter adding its extensive quantity. And the experience of mankind, as
a whole—though there are not wanting individual dissentients—seems to support the
belief that Conscious or Sentient Life is, speaking broadly and on the average,
desirable; that some degree of pleasure is the normal state of sentient beings as
such and pain abnormal. Thus it follows that the 'higher' such a being stands in the
scale of organisation, the happier it is, generally speaking. In accordance with this
general principle we regard the exercise of more varied and complicated activities,
the extension of sympathy with the pleasures and pains of others, the development
of scientific and historical interests, of aesthetic sensibilities, &c.—which might all be
brought under the general notion of 'progress in the correspondence between the
organism and its environment'—as involving generally an increase of happiness. Still,
in so far as we pursue any of these elements of culture for their own sakes, our
pursuit is closely guided and checked by experience of the pleasure derived from
them; and it would seem that this ought to be so. For, in the first place, the connexion
above stated is not universal, as the more intense life may be intensely painful; and,
independently of this, the notions of Culture, Elevation of Life, or Perfection of
Organisation are not sufficiently definite to be substituted for that of Happiness as the
immediate object of rational pursuit; indeed, the pleasure actually experienced seems
often a better test of true development in any direction, than the latter (as otherwise
estimated) can be of the pleasure that will ultimately accrue.
But the fact is that in the ordering of an individual man's life, Development or
Perfection of Organisation scarcely comes into competition with Happiness as an end
of action. For in this case we cannot alter the structure of the organism much or
directly, but only to a slight extent by altering its functions; and the functions of each
civilised man are, in most cases, determined for him by a combination of imperious
bodily necessities and fixed social relations, and are exercised not for their own
sakes but in order to provide adequately some more indispensable means of
happiness. It is rather when we pass from the individual human being to consider the
far more modifiable social organism of which he forms a part,
end p.17
that it becomes of fundamental importance to know whether the doctrine of Evolution
can guide us to the form of organisation most productive of happiness. For, if this be
so, the efforts of the statesman and the philanthropist should be primarily directed to
the realisation of this form, and empirical utilitarianism would be, to a great extent,
superseded in the political art. The right social order would, no doubt, approve itself
as such by the general experience of happiness resulting from it; but it would become
unscientific to refer to this experience as determining the settlement of great political
questions.
Before, however, we consider if our knowledge of sociology is sufficiently advanced
to enable us to define the political ideal, we must notice one fundamental difficulty in
constructing it, which arises inevitably from the relation of the individual man to
society. For the most prominent characteristic of the advanced development of any
organism is the specialisation—or, as Mr. Spencer calls it, 'differentiation'—of the
functions of its different parts. Obviously the more this is effected, the more 'definite
coherent heterogeneity' will be realised in the organism and in its relations to its
environment. But obviously too, this involves pro tanto a proportionally less degree of
variety and complexity in the life of each individual member of the society whose
functions are thus specialised; and their life becoming narrow and monotonous must
become, according to our present hypothesis, less happy. This result has often been
noticed by observers of the minute sub-division of labour which is a feature of our
industrial progress: but the same sort of primâ facie conflict between individual and
social development occurs in considering most of the great problems of modern
politics; such as the relations between rich and poor generally, the relations between
governors and governed, and the relations of the sexes. Now, as it is the individual,
after all, who feels pleasure and pain, it is clear that his development (or happiness)
must not be sacrificed to attain a higher form of social organisation; the latter end can
only be sought within the limits fixed by the former; the point then is to determine
what these are. It may be thought, perhaps, that the history of past stages in the
evolution of society will indicate the reconciliation or compromise between individual
and social development to which the human race has gradually been working up. It
would seem, however, that history rather shows us the problem than its solution. For,
while a continually greater specialisation of functions is undoubtedly an ever-present
feature of social development, we have to notice as proceeding side by side with this
a continually fuller recognition of the rights and claims of the individual as such. And
this, giving a point of view from which the elements of the community are regarded as
equal and similar, considerably qualifies, and, to some extent, counterbalances the
tendency to 'heterogeneity' above noticed; it is obvious, e.g., that an ancient society
with a fully developed caste-system, where the existence of the individual was
absorbed in and identified with his social function, was, in some respects, more
heterogeneous than our own, in spite of the greater differentiation of functions in the
latter. Hence we
end p.18
have on the one hand an ever increasing social inequality, and, on the other hand, an
ever profounder protest against this inequality; and, whatever the right compromise
between these conflicting tendencies may be, it does not seem possible to determine
it by any deduction from the doctrine of Evolution.
For when we turn to examine the principles of social construction propounded by
eminent sociologists, we see very plainly that any attempt to determine the political
ideal by a scientific formula of Social Evolution must at least fail in obtaining that
'consensus of experts', which is, to common men, the most satisfactory guarantee of
scientific method. Those thinkers who are most confident of having discovered the
law of progress seem hopelessly disagreed as to the next term in the series. For
example, Comte teaches us that the 'influence dispersive du principe de la
spécialisation', tending in its extreme form to a 'sorte d'automatisme humain', must be
met by a corresponding development of that 'réaction nécessaire de l'ensemble sur
les parties', which constitutes the proper function of government. 'L'intensité', he
says, 'do cetto fonction régulatrice, bien loin de devoir decroître à mesure que
l'évolution humaine s' accomplit, doit, au contraire, devenir de plus en plus
indispensable'; and actually, he holds, we find the two tendencies to specialisation
and to central regulation developing, as progress goes on, so as to balance each
other by a continually proportionate increase. And certainly the amount of regulation
contemplated in Comte's Utopia would seem sufficient to counteract any conceivable
development of centrifugal impulses. While Mr. Spencer is no less confirmed by
sociological study in his opposite doctrine that the proper function of government is
what he calls 'negatively regulative control', viz.: the prevention of mutual interference
and the enforcement of free contracts among the members of a community. Mr.
Spencer supports his ideal of organisation by a reference to biological analogies; but,
here again, his view is diametrically opposed to that of our most eminent living
3
morphologist.
3
Cf. Professor Huxley's essay on 'Administrative Nihilism'.
In this diversity of opinion, it is perhaps premature to consider the practical results
that would follow from our attaining really scientific pre-vision of the social relations of
the future. But I must observe that it would still remain to be proved that the mere
advance to a higher stage in social organisation is necessarily accompanied with a
proportionate increase of happiness. Past history shows us the greatest differences
in the prosperity of different nations on approximately the same level of social
development; and it seems most reasonable to suppose that such prevision of social
changes as we are likely to attain will rather define the limits within which the political
art has to operate than furnish the principles of the art itself.
V. Hitherto, in considering the bearing of Evolutionism on the theory of right conduct,
we have assumed that such conduct is to be not only objectively rational, or the best
means of realising what is ultimately good; but also subjectively
end p.19
rational, consciously chosen by the agent as a means to this end. This, however,
though in the view of most moralists it seems to be the ideal form of human action, is
manifestly not the universal or even the most common form. Men are prompted to
action by other appetites and desires far more frequently than by the desire to do
what is reasonable or right: so that some ethical writers even ignore the very
existence of this latter motive, and regard human action as always stimulated by one
or other of the more special impulses; including what are called 'moral sentiments', or
immediate unreflective likings and aversions for particular kinds of conduct,
contemplated without reference to any ulterior end. Indeed the operation of such
unreflective impulses appears to be the most prominent element in the common
notion of 'conscience': so that the denomination by the Utilitarian school of the
common morality which they wish to supersede as 'instinctive' or 'sentimental' is not
infrequently accepted by other than Utilitarian Moralists. Now, if the doctrine of
Evolution, in its application to the origin and growth of such instinctive impulses
generally, and in particular of moral sentiments, is able to exhibit these as Nature's
means of attaining that general happiness which is the conscious end of Utilitarian
calculation; a reconciliation between 'instinctive' and Utilitarian morality seems to be
effected, which composes the long conflict between the two schools. This is, at any
rate, the claim put forward by Mr. Spencer and other expositors of evolutionism.
In proceeding to examine the claim, we must first consider how this part of the
Evolution doctrine is supposed to be proved. Two methods of proof have been put
forward, fundamentally distinct, but yet not incompatible: in fact, so far from
incompatible that one of them almost needs to be supplemented by the other. One
method consists in the application to sociology of that hypothetical deductive use of
the theory of Natural Selection which has of late years been common among
biologists of the Darwinian school. Moral sentiments, it is said, are impulses that tend
to the maintenance of society: hence a tribe in which they were accidentally
developed would tend to be victorious over other tribes in the struggle for existence:
and thus moral sentiments would come to be a part of the essential characteristics of
humanity: hence we may conclude that it was in this way that they were actually
generated. It will be seen that this view of the moral sentiments is in immediate
connection with that account of the Well-being of an organism which, distinguishing it
from Happiness, reduces it (as I have already noticed) to Being actual and potential.
In order therefore to harmonise it with Utilitarianism we require a further application of
the same deductive method: as thus—Men are stimulated to actions and abstinences
in proportion as they find these in the long run pleasurable and their opposites
painful: therefore tribes, whose members derive the greatest balance of pleasure
over pain from actions and modes of existence conducive to the preservation of the
tribe will have a distinct advantage in the struggle for existence: therefore the
societies that in the long run survive will be so constituted that the maximum
happiness of their
end p.20
members will be attained by conduct tending to the preservation of society. But even
the most roseate optimism must admit that this double harmony between pleasant
and preservative conduct, and between individual and universal well-being, is ideal
and future: that it does not represent accurately the present, and still less the past
experience of the human race. And hence (as Mr. Darwin himself has not failed to
observe), the theory of natural selection has less explanatory efficacy here than it
has in its usual biological applications. For in those the variations naturally selected
are taken as accidental, or at least no explanation of them is necessary for the
justification of the theory: we have only to assume generally a slight indefinite
tendency to vary from the parental type in the propagation of life, and then the action
of the environment will do the rest. But in the case of the sociological changes above-
mentioned, this simple account of the matter is hardly admissible. For as the interest
of the community continually involves more or less sacrifice of the individual,
especially in the early stages of human history which the theory contemplates, any
individual varying in the direction of morality would be liable to be cut off, and would
4
fail to propagate his peculiar type.
4
'It is extremely doubtful whether the offspring of the more sympathetic and benevolent parents, or of
those who were the most faithful to their comrades, would be reared in greater numbers than the
children of selfish and treacherous parents belonging to the same tribe. He who was ready to sacrifice
his life, as many a savage has been, rather than betray his comrades, would often leave no offspring
to inherit his noble nature. The bravest men, who were always willing to come to the front in war, and
who freely risked their lives for others, would on an average perish in larger numbers than other men.
Therefore it hardly seems probable that the number of men gifted with such virtues, or that the
standard of their excellence, could be increased through natural selection, that is, by the survival of
the fittest.'—Darwin, Descent of Man, ch. v., p. 130 (2nd. ed.).
We require therefore some further explanation of the tendency of human character to
take this particular line of change. For it will hardly do to reply that a tribe which
manifested this tendency would necessarily flourish: the chances are so very much
against the production of a tribe of which the individuals accidentally combine to
maintain an individually unprofitable variation in one special direction. This further
explanation is found in the second method to which I referred, which is the one
employed by Mr. Herbert Spencer. His theory, briefly given, is this: that experienced
pleasures and pains produce secondary likings and aversions for pleasure-causing
and pain-causing conduct, which from being habitual become organic and so capable
of being transmitted to posterity: and that through the interdependence of interests
that results from gregariousness and the interchange of emotions that results from
sympathy, it is the common experience of all that practically operates in producing
these derivative sentiments and habits; so that they ultimately appear as instincts
tending to promote the interests of the community.
It appears to me that these two methods, taken together, furnish a highly plausible
explanation of the development of morality in a race of animals gregarious,
sympathetic, and semi-rational—such as we may conceive man to have been in
end p.21
the prae-moral stage of his development. But I fail to see how we are thus helped to
a solution of the conflict between the Utilitarian and Intuitional schools of Ethics: in so
far, that is, as either school professes to supply not merely a psychological
explanation of human emotions, but an ethical theory of right conduct. For, putting
aside the discrepancy before noticed between General Happiness and the
Preservation of Race, we are still left asking the question: what ought we to do when
Moral Sentiment comes into conflict with the conclusions of Rational Utilitarianism?
Granting that both are really akin and spring from the same root, which ought we to
obey, Reason or Instinct? As far as I can see, the 'reconciliation' proposed by
Evolutionists results in a practical surrender on one side or the other; though it is not
always clear on which side, and a plausible case may be made out for either. On the
one hand it may be said that Moral Sentiments (or other derivative likings and
aversions) constitute Nature's guidance to Happiness; and that our power of
calculating pleasures and pains is so imperfect as to make it really rational in the
pursuit of happiness, to disregard the results of conscious calculation when they are
clearly in conflict with any of these embodiments of unconscious reasoning and
outgrowths of ages of experience. On the other hand it may equally be urged that the
symbolical representation and comparison of experienced pleasures and pains which
we call the exercise of practical reason, is only the final phase of that adaptation of
the organism to its circumstances which in its earlier phases took place by the
development of these secondary instincts: that, in short, if Instinct is really implicit
(utilitarian) reason, it is better to perform the calculation explicitly. Certainly we can
balance any statement of the sources of fallibility in utilitarian calculation by an
equally impressive demonstration of the imperfections and misguidance of instinct.
It may perhaps be said that an Evolutionist theory does not profess to prove that
Utilitarian and Intuitional Ethics coincide in detail, but only to afford them a broad
general ground of reconciliation. But in this case it seems to me ethically superfluous,
whatever historical interest it may have. For this general result may be much more
easily and satisfactorily attained by a survey of men's actual moral sentiments, and a
comparison of them with the conclusions of utilitarian calculation. The practical
disagreements between different schools of moralists, though their magnitude and
importance are perhaps commonly underrated—certainly bear a small proportion to
their agreements: but a theory of the origin of morality which merely explains the
latter can hardly be said to effect a settlement of ethical controversy.
end p.22
(2) A 'distributing system', carrying about nutriment in the animal and commodities in
the society, and
(3) A 'regulating and expending system'. By this last notion he represents analogy
between the apparatus of nerves and muscles in an animal which carries on
conflict with other animals and the governments and armies of political society;
taking the governmental system as ultimately developed to correspond to the
brain and nervous centres, the supreme deliberative assembly being analogous to
the cerebrum.
So much for the resemblances between the social organism and the animal or plant.
As we should expect, they belong primarily to the physical life of human societies; but
when we turn to note the differences, we shall be led gradually to contemplate their
intellectual life.
We may begin by observing that a political society has not, like an animal, a normal
period of life and a normal series of vital changes from infancy to senility and death.
Indeed, the political societies historically known to us do not ordinarily die unless they
are assailed and structurally destroyed by other societies; and
end p.65
when death, in a certain sense, thus befalls any such society, it does not entail the
death of the human beings composing it. Some of them, no doubt, perish in the
collision, but the bulk of them are absorbed alive by the conquering society. Even in
peace an important mingling of units from different societies goes on, as is most
conspicuously illustrated at the present time by the comparatively new societies
formed in America. They are largely made neither by 'multiplication of units' nor by
'union of groups', but by composition of units from a number of groups.
But it is still more important to observe that the social organism to which an individual
is found to belong, through the social relations binding him to other men, becomes
very different in its range as we pass from one set of relations to another. There is
nothing corresponding to this in the case of an animal. Each animal has its own
sustaining system, its own distributing system, and its own regulating and expending
system, quite unconnected with the corresponding systems of other animals. The
alimentary organs of one animal do not provide, nor its blood-vessels convey,
nutriment to the organs of other societies, nor does its brain co-operate in directing
their movements, except indirectly by producing external movements of its own
organs. The case is quite otherwise with the organic life of societies. The channels of
communication by which commodities are carried run, as we know, not only within
states, but across states, almost ignoring their boundaries; and the same is true of
the process of differentiation which localizes particular branches of industry in
situations specially favourable to it, and thus tends to bind the inhabitants of the
districts in question into one economic whole. We all know that England forms part of
an economic system extending far beyond the limits of the British empire.
But again a very similar set of cross-divisions, lines of separation that cut across the
boundaries of states, is found in what we cannot but regard as an important part of
the regulative apparatus of social organisms: I mean the ecclesiastical systems. We
all know how throughout the civilised world members from the same states are
divided from another, and members of different states are united by communities
formed for the purpose of religious instruction and worship. No fact is more striking in
the history of regulating social agencies than the manner in which religions claiming
to be world religions—Buddhism, Christianity, Mohammedanism—have arisen and
spread and overleaped all the lines of separation of political societies; binding their
converts through the most powerful ties of common beliefs and common worship into
organisms quite different from states, though they come to have an elaborately
differentiated quasi-political organisation. Now, in studying these ecclesiastical
organisms from the outside, we might of course dwell on the social differences and
relations between priests or monks and laymen, and the organisation of
ecclesiastical government. But it would be a very shallow insight that did not
penetrate further and recognise as the most essential social relation which binds
human beings together on this side
end p.66
of their life community of thought and sentiment; a common stock of ideas and
convictions about the universe, its ground and end, and human destiny. Hence, when
the sociologist studies these ecclesiastical bodies, it is to the laws of change and
growth of this intellectual and emotional context, this common body of ideas and
sentiments, that his deepest attention should be directed.
And this is true also of the political regulation of social man. Mr. Spencer, as we saw,
compares the brain of an animal with the supreme deliberative assembly of a nation.
But surely the political brain of England is not limited to the six hundred and seventy
respectable gentlemen who chiefly make our laws: it is to be found wherever political
thought is going on which will take effect in determining the action of the English
government. And if so, the history of political ideas shows that no modern nation has
a brain strictly and entirely its own. If we insist on keeping the analogy, we have for
the main movements of political thought to trace the operation and development of at
least a West-European brain; whose range of influence in modern times has not only
extended to European colonies in other parts of the globe, but has even included a
people so alien in its origin and previous history as the Japanese.
And, finally, what I have said of religious and political ideas is equally true of moral
ideas and sentiments. Indeed, throughout the history of European civilization morality
has had an intimate connection both with religion and with polity. Still, the study of
the development of morality and its conditions and laws of growth and change may
be pursued, no less than the study of religious or political thought, as a partially
independent branch of sociological inquiry; and when we so pursue it we soon find
that the aggregate of human beings bound together spiritually by sharing a common
moral life is not to be identified with any one of the political societies which we began
by regarding as social organisms. And the same may be said in modern times of the
possession of a common body of scientific knowledge; indeed, science is less
modified by national differences than morality; and European science has united the
educated portion of the Japanese people more completely with our educated world
than European political ideas. Thus, in contemplating the continual enlargement of
these spiritual bonds of social union we are irresistibly led—as the founder of
sociology, Comte, was led—to an ideal future when the whole population of the globe
will form, from an intellectual point of view, a single social organism. There is a
striking passage, remarkable in a writer who claims to expound a purely positive
method, in which Comte tells us that Sociology, reading the future into the past,
'represents the whole human race, past, present, and future, as constituting a vast
and eternal social unit, where different organs, individual and national, concur in their
various modes and degrees in the evolution of humanity'.
To sum up, as we pass from one aspect to another of the many-sided social life of
man, we are led gradually from the conception of an indefinite number of social
organisms, subject, like plants or animals, to the struggle for existence as a
end p.67
main factor in their development,—a conception which physical analogies and the
contemplation of the earlier stages of human history combine to press on us,—to the
idea of a single social organism, which a study of later civilised history, especially in
its spiritual aspect, renders no less inevitable.
I turn now to examine the relation of sociology to ethics, and especially the claim of
the former study to absorb the latter and reduce it to a subordinate department of
itself. I may perhaps say that I come to the examination of this claim in an impartial
spirit. Speaking as a professor of ethics, I do not consider myself as holding a brief
for the independence of my subject. It is for the true good of any department of
knowledge or inquiry to understand as thoroughly as may be its relation to other
sciences and studies, to see clearly what elements of its reasonings it has to take
from them, and what in its turn it may claim to give to them; and the value of this
insight becomes greater in proportion as the steady growth of human knowledge, the
steady extension of the range of human inquiry, brings with it a continually more
urgent need for a clear and rational division of intellectual labour. If, therefore, the
relation of ethics to sociology is truly one of subordination, it is important that
students of ethics should fully recognise this truth and render due obedience to the
superior authority.
Of course, in order that this authority, however ideally unquestionable, should be
actually unquestioned, sociology must have become an established science, and be
not merely struggling towards this position. And if I were speaking as an advocate of
the claims of ethics to actual independence, I should have much to say on this topic. I
should take the simple criteria of the real establishment of a science laid down by
Auguste Comte, which we may briefly characterize as a Consensus of experts,
Continuity and Prevision, and try the claims of sociology by the standards of its own
founder. I should give you in Comte's own words his negative application of the test
of continuity: 'When we find that recent works, instead of being the result and
development of what has gone before, have a character as personal as that of their
authors and bring the most fundamental ideas into question',—then, says Comte, we
may be sure we are not dealing with any doctrine deserving the name of positive
science. And my brief would be stuffed with quotations from very recent treatises on
sociology, whose authors—to quote a well-known epigram,—show themselves most
emphatically 'conscious of one another's shortcomings'.
But this advocate's work is not now my affair. I wish to assume for the purposes of
my present discussion that the struggle of sociology to become an established
science, a struggle carried on now for three-quarters of a century, has been crowned
with the success which I hope will ultimately crown it. I will assume that it has
attained as much consensus as to principles, method, and conclusions, and as much
continuity of development as the physical sciences dealing with organic life, and as
much power of prevision as Comte hoped for it;—for he was not sanguine enough to
suppose that sociology could ever predict with the exactness
end p.68
and minuteness of astronomy, and foretell the stages of a political revolution as
astronomy foretells the stages of a solar eclipse.
Let us suppose this consummation attained and consider how far this scientific
prevision of social effects will so far determine ethical reasonings as to reduce ethics
to a subordinate department of sociology.
I think it must be admitted that this effect will be produced to a considerable extent,
upon any view of ethics except the ultra-intuitional, in respect of the deduction of
particular rules of morality from fundamental principles. For all schools, except that
which takes the immediate judgments of conscience as infallible guides in all
questions of conduct, admit that the application of moral principles to practice must
be largely governed by foresight of consequences, and must therefore admit that
rules of social behaviour will properly be determined in detail by the scientific
prevision of social consequences so far as such prevision is available. We may
compare, as a parallel case, the relation of the moral duty or virtue of temperance to
human physiology, including pathology; the ethical maxim that the bodily appetites
ought to be strictly obedient to the regulation of reason must receive its practical
application from a forecast of consequences; and this, with the development of
physiological knowledge, must change from a merely empirical to a more or less
scientific forecast. We commonly recognise that the diet scientifically known to be
promotive of health and efficiency is the truly temperate diet; and the most ascetic
moralist has to admit that self-denial, no less than self-indulgence, must be limited
and guided by medical prevision. Similarly we must admit that our social affections
and sentiments will have to yield to the control and obey the guidance of sociological
prevision when sociology has become a really established science.
Indeed, some effect of this kind has already been produced on current ethical notions
and habits by the branch of sociology which has been separated from the general
science of society, and received a development in advance of the rest under the
name of political economy. For instance, under the influence of the economic
forecast—deductively and inductively established—of the bad consequences of
indiscriminate almsgiving, the old and eminent virtue of charity, in its narrower
signification, has materially changed its practical content for the modern educated
man, while retaining its principle and motive unchanged. Its application to conduct
has become more complex and exacting; it is recognized as demanding thought and
care, besides the mere altruistic preference of the satisfaction of others' desires to
the satisfaction of our own, and as imposing restraints on sympathetic impulses as
well as on self-regarding ones.
A similar effect of economic forecast on ethical conceptions and accompanying
sentiments is traceable in the case of justice; but with the difference that in this case
we have marked ethical divergences resulting from divergences in the economic or
sociological prevision of consequences. Suppose we take the principle that desert
ought to be requited as expressing the abstract essence of distributive
end p.69
justice. Its practical application cannot but be different, on the one hand, for the
individualist who holds that any important relaxation in the competitive struggle for
existence must result in the arrest and decline of human improvement, through the
equalizing of the prospects of survival of the unfit along with the fit; and, on the other
hand, for the socialist who forecasts a more rapid and effective improvement under
the stimulus of altruistic affection, sympathy, and public spirit, when these nobler
impulses are no longer starved and depressed by the egoistic habits and sentiments
that necessarily result from the present competitive struggle. The former will tend to
interpret the requital of desert to mean securing to each man the precise social value
of his services; the latter will tend to interpret it to mean securing him what he
requires for the most efficient performance of his social function.
Of course, as sociological prevision extends in range and increases in exactness, we
must suppose fundamental divergences of this kind to diminish and a more decisive
effect to be produced.
I have said enough to show the import of my admission as a representative of ethics
that if we suppose sociology as an established science, we must suppose its forecast
of social consequences to exercise a fundamentally important effect on the practical
application of general ethical principles or maxims, and the deduction of subordinate
rules of conduct from these.
I now turn to the more important and more disputable element of the claim of
sociology to absorb and subordinate ethics,—i.e., the claim not merely to modify the
practical application of ethical principles, but to determine these very principles
themselves.
Here, first, I quite admit that the connection of sociology, supposing it an established
science, with the subject-matter of ethics must necessarily be so intimate and so
comprehensive, that its claim to dominate and subordinate ethics is natural and
almost inevitable; and we cannot be surprised that it should appear irresistible to
students of sociology who have never made a systematic attempt to purge their
moral notions of the confusions of popular thought. For, as we have seen, sociology
undoubtedly comprehends in its subject-matter the study of morality as a social fact,
and this study must include morality as a whole, the principles accepted in any age
and country, no less than the accepted and current application of the principles to
particular concrete problems of conduct. It is a part of the business of sociology—at
least as important, from a purely sociological point of view, as any other part—to
ascertain first the facts, and then, as far as possible, the laws of the development of
moral opinions and sentiments, as one element in the development of human society
as a whole; to show how it has influenced and been influenced by other elements in
the whole social evolution; to trace it back, if possible, to its origin; and—always
supposing sociology to have arrived at the stage of scientific prediction—to foretell its
future conditions.
end p.70
It is natural to infer that a sociology supposed able to accomplish all this—and I am
willing, for the sake of argument, to make the supposition—would reduce ethics to a
subordinate department of itself. I do not, however, think that this inference is
logically sound. Indeed, I think that in most cases it arises from a confusion of
thought that a little reflection ought to dispel.
To show this, let us suppose ethics and sociology as independent and established
systems of thought, and then try to imagine a conflict between them, a conflict such
as sometimes takes place between established sciences,—e.g., there was one some
time ago between physicists and geologists as to the time of duration of the earth.
We shall find that we cannot really suppose such a conflict possible. No ethical
proposition can possibly contradict a sociological proposition, since they cannot
relate to the same subject-matter,—that is, so long as ethics is understood in the
limited sense that I have defined and so long as sociology keeps strictly within the
bounds of its domain as a positive science. Sociology thus conceived is strictly
incapable of answering any ethical question, and ethics thus understood is strictly
incapable of answering any sociological question,—for ethics is only concerned with
what ought to be, and sociology, even when it deals with ethical judgments, is only
concerned with what is, has been, and will be judged, and not at all with the question
whether it is, has been, or will be truly judged. So far as any sociologist expresses
any opinion on the latter point, he assumes a knowledge which the method of his
science, regarded as a study of empirical fact, is quite incompetent to supply.
I do not think that this is likely to be disputed, so far as sociology is concerned with
the mere ascertainment of particular facts, past and present; but it may be disputed
in respect of the general truths which sociology as a science must be supposed to
have established. And I admit that if we examine this dispute with care we shall find,
not indeed a possible conflict between ethics and sociology, but a possible
coincidence so close as, if actually accepted, to justify the view that sociology is
destined to absorb ethics.
But here again I must point out that the dispute sometimes arises from mere
confusion of thought. It is rightly seen that the aim of sociology is not merely to
ascertain, but to explain, the variations and changes in social morality, and that this
explanation must lie in reducing to general laws the diversity of moral opinions
prevalent in different ages and countries; and it is vaguely thought that these general
laws, at any rate when brought to a sufficiently high degree of generality, must
coincide—if they do not clash—with ethical principles. But not only is there no primâ
facie reason why they should coincide, but primâ facie every reason why they should
not. For the sociological laws must explain and be manifested in the erroneous moral
judgments that have been prevalent in human society no less than in true moral
judgments; they must explain the prevalent opinion of certain
end p.71
groups of primitive men that successful thieving is honourable and virtuous, or that
the revenge of a blood-relation is the holiest duty that man can perform, no less than
the opposite moral opinions now prevalent in Europe.
There is, however, a subtler form of the same view which cannot be so decisively put
on one side. It may be urged that the subject-matter of sociology, no less than the
subject-matter of animal or vegetable biology, is a kind of organic life; and that as the
varied structures and functions of animal or vegetable organisms can only be
understood if we regard them as adapted or adjusted to the preservation either of the
individual organism or its type, so sociology requires the same conception of
adaptation to the end of social preservation in its explanation of social facts.
Accordingly, morality, prevalent moral opinions and sentiments, being an important
complex of relations among the members of a society, must be brought under the
same general conception; so that the most comprehensive and fundamental
sociological law, explaining the development of morality, will consist in just this
statement of Preservation of the Social Organism as the end to which morality is
normally and broadly a means,—though in any particular society at any particular
time details of positive morality may not be perfectly adapted to this end. If this is so,
it may be said the moralist must adopt this sociological end as his ultimate ethical
end, since otherwise he would be setting up an ideal opposed to the irresistible drift
1
of the whole process of life in the world, which would be obviously futile.
1
Some writers would substitute 'welfare' or 'health' for 'preservation' in this reasoning. But unless
'welfare' or 'health' is interpreted to mean merely preservation in a condition favourable to future
preservation, in which case simple preservation is still the ultimate end, the terms seem to me to
introduce an ethical conception which cannot be arrived at by any strictly sociological method.
Now, supposing a consensus of sociologists to declare that the preservation of the
social organism is the one all-comprehensive end, by continual adjustment to which
the actual evolution of morality may be simply and completely explained; and
supposing a consensus of moralists to accept this sociological end as the ultimate
good to the attainment of which all human action should be directed, then, I admit, it
would be broadly true to say that ethics was absorbed by sociology. For on these
hypotheses there would, firstly, be a complete coincidence between the sociological
and the ethical end; and, secondly, as I have already explained, the working out of
the rules conducive to the end must, so far as social morality is concerned, consist in
an application of sociological knowledge. Ethics would not, indeed, even so, be
exactly a branch of the science, but it would be an art based on the science and
having as its fundamental principle the highest generalization of the science,
modified so as to take on an ethical import.
It would still, I think, be formally important to insist that this fusion of studies can only
be rationally effected by the judgment that identifies the sociological and the ethical
ends; and that is not one to which the moralist can be cogently driven by any
sociological arguments. For the argument that if he declines to
end p.72
accept it he places himself in opposition to the process of nature is only forcible if we
introduce a theological significance into our notion of nature, attributing to it design
and authority; and this introduction of theology carries the sociologist beyond the
limits of his special science. But, though it would be formally important to insist on
this, the fusion would still be complete on the two hypotheses, sociological and
ethical, above stated.
But neither of these hypotheses can be accepted as more than partially true.
Take the ethical question first,—can we regard the mere preservation of the life of a
human being, or of any number of human beings combined in a society, as an
ultimate and paramount end and standard of right action, apart from any
consideration of the quality of the life preserved? I appeal confidently on this point—it
is the only appeal possible—to the deliberate judgment of thoughtful persons, when
the question is clearly set before it. Doubtless a fundamentally important part of the
function of morality consists in maintaining habits and sentiments preservative of
individual and social life; but this is because, as Aristotle said, in order to live well we
must live. It does not follow that life is simply the ultimate end; since if all life were as
little desirable as some portions of it have been in the experience of most of us we
should judge anything tending to its preservation as unmitigatedly bad. It is not life
simply, but good or desirable life, that is the ethical end; and though—as all students
of your school will know —there is still much controversy as to the precise content of
the notion 'good' in this application, it is a controversy which ethics has got to work
through, and in settling which it cannot derive any material aid from sociology.
But, again, the sociological hypothesis seems to me equally unacceptable when put
forward as a complete explanation of the facts to which it relates.
The view that morality has been developed under the influence of the struggle for
existence among social organisms as a part of the complex adaptation of such
organisms to the conditions of their struggling existence is, I think, a probable
conjecture as regards the earlier stages of its development in prehistoric times. It is
reasonable to suppose that the observance of duties to fellow-tribesmen within a
primitive tribe tended to the survival of the tribe in the struggle for tribal existence, by
increasing the internal coherence of the tribe and the effective co-operation of its
members. But it is not reasonable to accept this as the main explanation of the
evolution of morality even in primitive ages, because it is certainly not a cause that
has had any great effect on the important changes in moral beliefs that have taken
place in historic times. Take one of the greatest of such changes, that resulting in the
conversion of the Greco-Roman civilised world to Christianity. Not only would it be
obviously absurd to attribute this change to the struggle for existence among civilised
societies; there is not even any adequate evidence that it had a preservative effect
on the political society in which the conversion took place. I should conjecture that
before Constantine its operation was the other way, considering the passive
alienation of primitive
end p.73
Christians from the secular society in which they lived, over which they believed a
swift and sudden destruction to be impending. And, though this split between religion
and the state was healed by Constantine, it is difficult, even after this, to see any
tendency in Christianity to preserve the Roman empire, or even arrest its decline and
fall. The Christian empire seems simply to continue the process tending towards
surrender to the barbarians outside.
In short, the sociological hypothesis that I am now considering—so far as it is offered
as a complete explanation of moral evolution—seems to me due to the one-
sidedness of view which I before noted as a source of sociological error: the
concentration of attention on the physical side of social life and its primitive
conditions, unduly ignoring its spiritual side and the later stages of its development.
And this is true, not of morality only, but of the development of knowledge, of art,—
indeed of all the chief elements of that ideal good which we most deeply value in
what we call the progress of civilization. We cannot say of the most signal
contributions to this progress that they are always decisively preservative of the
particular nation of which they are made; if we are to view them as adjustments of
means to a social end, it can be no lesser or more limited end than the welfare of
humanity at large.
I now turn to consider an objection that may be taken against the whole line of
thought that I have adopted. I may be asked, 'Why insist on this artificial separation
between the subjects of ethics and sociology? Why not allow the development of
both to be influenced by the natural play of thought between the two? Why attempt
the impossible task of keeping different portions of our thought on human relations in
separate water-tight compartments?'
To objections of this kind my answer is,—First, that I fully recognize the propriety of
the demand that our ethical and our sociological thought should be brought into clear
and consistent relations: indeed, I regard the harmonizing of different sciences and
studies as the special task of philosophy. I think, however, that the impulse to put
together different lines of thought requires methodical restraint, because one of the
most fruitful sources of error in philosophy has been over-hasty synthesis and
combination without sufficient previous analysis of the elements combined. But,
secondly, in order to avoid this error, I by no means wish to prevent altogether mutual
influence, interpenetration of ideas, between the two studies I am now considering. I
only urge that it should be carefully watched and criticised, in order that it may not be
the source of confusion, which is especially dangerous in the condition of controversy
and conflict of opinion on fundamental points from which neither sociology nor ethics
has as yet successfully emerged. To illustrate this, let me consider first the current
influence on ethics of sociological conceptions. I will take the fundamental conception
of the social organism.
Although as a utilitarian I cannot regard mere preservation of the social organism as
the ultimate end and supreme standard of right action, I recognise the
end p.74
value of the conception in making our general view of duty, whether framed on
utilitarian or any other principles, fuller and truer. In any case it is important for an
individual that he should not conceive himself merely as a member of an aggregate,
capable of benefiting or injuring by his actions other individuals as such, but also as a
member of a body formed of individual human beings bound into a whole by complex
mutual relations; a whole of which the parts, whether individuals or groups, have
functions diverse and mutually dependent. Adopting this conception, he will,
whatever view he takes of the ultimate ethical end, judge actions largely by their
effect in promoting or impeding the coherent and harmonious co-operation of
different organs of society, and in strengthening or weakening habits and sentiments
that tend to the efficient performance of social functions.
All this is highly important. But some writers seem drawn by the interest of the novel
conception to regard it as supplying a complete determinant of duty. That is, it seems
to be supposed that adequate guidance to particular duties is given in all cases by
the facts of social relations. 'A man', it is said, 'finds himself as a member of a society
in certain relations to other human beings. He is son, brother, husband and father,
neighbour, citizen. These relations are all facts, and his duties lie in fulfilling the
claims that are essential parts of these relations.' Now, no doubt the claims or
conscious expectations connected with these relations, and the common recognition
of these claims by other members of the society than those primarily concerned are
important social facts. But it can hardly be maintained that it is an absolute duty to
fulfil all such expectations, as they are to a certain extent vague, varying, liable to
conflict with each other, sometimes unreasonable, sometimes sanctioned by custom
but by custom 'more honoured in the breach than in the observance'. In short, so far
as these claims are actual facts they are not indisputably valid and do not form a
harmonious system, and the study of them as facts does not give a criterion of their
validity and a means of eliminating conflict. In considering which of the demands
made on us by our fellow-men have to be satisfied and which repudiated, and, when
two conflict, which is to be postponed, we require a system of principles of right
conduct which the study of social facts as such cannot alone give, but which it is the
business of ethics to give.
On the other hand, just as this wide and quasi-architectonic use of sociological
conception in ethics leads to a mistaken attempt to get the ideal out of the actual, so
the converse influence of ethics on sociology leads to equally mistaken attempts to
get the ideal into the actual,—i.e., to predict a future state of society in harmony with
ethical ideas without any adequate support in scientific induction from the known
facts of past social evolution.
In criticising this 'evolutionary optimism', as we may call it, I ought to explain that I am
not opposing optimism as a philosophical doctrine. I am not myself an optimist; but I
have a great respect for the belief that, in spite of appearances to
end p.75
the contrary, the world now in process of evolution, is ultimately destined to reveal
itself as perfectly free from evil and the best possible world. What I would urge is that,
in the present state of our knowledge, this belief should be kept as a theological
doctrine, or, if you like, a philosophical postulate, and that it should not be allowed to
mix itself with the process of scientific inference to the future from the past.
The sociologist who brings his optimism into his sociological reasonings must, I think,
find the tendency almost irresistible to give a one-sided prominence to those facts in
the past history of society which make for a favourable view of its future progress and
to ignore those facts which make for the opposite conclusion. It is only in this way
that I can account for Mr. Spencer's belief, regarded by him as a strictly scientific
inference from a survey of historical facts, that the evolution of human society will
ultimately bring about a condition of social relations in which the voluntary actions of
normal human beings will produce 'pleasure unalloyed by pain anywhere'. And,
similarly, I think that his hypothetical conclusion that 'there needs but a continuance
of absolute peace externally and a vigorous insistance on non-aggression internally
to ensure the moulding of men into a form naturally characterized by all the virtues'
has not really been reached by a strictly sociological method; but that the sociological
reasoning which has led him to it has been influenced and modified throughout by an
individualistic ideal formed prior to systematic sociological study.
I seem to find this confusing effect of 'evolutionary optimism' in an even more
extreme though vaguer form in a good deal of popular discourse about progress. The
believer in a good time coming often seems inclined to believe that what is coming is
good because it is coming, no less than that what is good is coming because it is
good. Now, granting the latter proposition to be well founded, it does not in any way
imply the former; granting that man is destined to unalloyed bliss, still his road to this
bright goal may be in parts very devious and distressful; and some of the most
distressful turns that would otherwise be found in it may be avoidable evils, but only
avoidable by vigorous resistance to present tendencies of change. This seems
obvious enough: but it is an obvious truth which is liable to be missed because the
opposite error is not explicitly propounded, but lurks in a vague acquiescence in the
*
drift of events.
[It was only at the proof stage that I noticed, on page 68, line 6, an error on Sidgwick's part, in mixing
up the words 'former' and 'latter', making the latter do the work of the former and vice-versa. I have
interchanged the words to represent more accurately Sidgwick's meaning. Any reader who thinks the
mistake is mine is of course free to change them back again. Ed.]
end p.76
Part II Value Theory and Moral Psychology
end p.77
end p.78
2. When the object aimed at is good, but the compulsion employed is not calculated
to obtain it.
3. When the object aimed at is good, and the compulsion employed is calculated to
obtain it, but at too great an expense.'
But in so far as he attempts to establish any practical maxims in opposition to Mill's,
he fails just as conspicuously as his opponent and in precisely the same manner. For
example, he lays down that it is right to persecute socially opinions (1) if we believe
them to be false, and (2) if we have bestowed on them 'careful consideration and
mature study'. This second qualification considerably restricts the number of
persecutors: indeed, Mr. Stephen adds that the majority of mankind have no right to
any opinions at all, except for the regulation of their own affairs. Now there is
obviously just as much utilitarian ground for persecuting a true opinion that we
believe to be pernicious, unless we assume (which Mr. Stephen does not) that its
truth must render persecution futile. The manner in which Mr. Stephen meets this
argument is a good example of his headlong style. This 'is a suggestion', he says,
'which it is childish to discuss in public, because no one could avow it without
contradicting himself and so defeating his own object'. He might as well argue that it
was childish to discuss in public, whether it be right to tell lies under certain
circumstances: which would no doubt be the case if the discussion bore upon some
particular lie, and was held with the person to whom the lie was to be told. And as to
the second qualification, it would surely be easy
end p.182
to assail with the reckless controversial tomahawk that Mr. Stephen wields, the
proposition that a conviction sufficient 'for the regulation of one's affairs' is insufficient
for action on society; and that people have no right to be intolerant of unveracity or
unchastity until after 'careful consideration and mature study'.
On the one hand then it appears that Mr. Stephen's own construction is most
imperfect: on the other hand, while dwelling on the formal inadequacy of Mill's
arguments to prove their conclusions, he continually ignores their substantial force.
E.g. if Mill had contented himself with pointing out that by persecuting legally or
socially opinions opposed to our own, we deprive ourselves of a most important and
valuable guarantee for the truth of our own convictions, viz. that given by the free
consensus of experts, I conceive that his position would have been unassailable. At
any rate Mr. Stephen does not assail it, but contents himself with showing that the
guarantee is not strictly indispensable. Such criticism is by no means useless: still,
taken by itself it is not only jejune but misleading.
Similarly, he never seems to have understood the very simple argument for Mill's
view that the penalties of social disapprobation ought to be confined to offences
against society. In the case of these acts—if for any reason they lie out of the reach
of the law—the force of the social sanction is generally required to counterbalance
the immediate gain to the agent accruing from the act, which otherwise would be
actually recommended by rational self-love. But where the consequences of an act
fall primarily on the agent himself, a properly enlightened self-love would forbid it: and
though we may agree with Mr. Stephen in thinking the social sanction more or less
useful in some even of these cases, its influence here is only supplementary to
considerations of self-interest.
When we pass to chapter v, on 'Equality', we find at the outset a very singular
account of justice. Judicial justice, our author thinks, is something altogether different
from legislative justice: we call a judge just when he applies a law impartially to all
persons included under its general terms, but in calling the law itself just we mean
only that it is expedient. Mr. Stephen may mean what he likes by his terms at the risk
of being unintelligible; but it seems clear that in both cases alike the common notion
of justice implies equal consideration for the reasonable claims of all persons
concerned. If justice does not simply direct equality of treatment, it clearly excludes
arbitrary inequality. Indeed Mr. Mill shows (in a passage which Mr. Stephen quotes
but fails to understand) that even in pure utilitarian ethics the idea of expediency
requires this element of justice to explain or supplement it, in order that a complete
criterion of right conduct may be furnished: for the same amount of happiness may
be distributed in an indefinite number of ways, and therefore we require to be told
how to distribute the 'greatest happiness' at which we are told to aim.
Our author then begins a discussion of Mill's Subjection of Women; but is
unexpectedly checked by the consideration that any minute examination of the
differences between men and women is—not exactly indecent, but—'unpleasant
end p.183
in the direction of indecorum'. We should be sorry to encourage any remarks
calculated to raise a blush in the cheek of a Queen's Counsel: but as the only
conceivable ground for subjecting women, as a class, to special disabilities, must lie
in the differences between them and men, it is obviously impossible to decide on the
justice—or if Mr. Stephen prefers it, the 'expediency'—of those disabilities, without a
careful examination of these differences. And in fact Mr. Stephen's sudden delicacy
does not suffice to hinder him from deciding the question with his usual rough
dogmatism: it only renders his discussion of it more than usually narrow and
commonplace.
The third part of the treatise is so far original that it attacks the one element in
Christian teaching which the most virulent antagonists of Christianity have hitherto
left unassailed—the sentiment of human brotherhood. In discussing 'Fraternity' Mr.
Stephen seems to confound two very distinct issues, how far men actually do love
each other, and how far it would be for their mutual benefit that they should.
Sometimes, indeed, the discussion seems to be almost narrowed to the question
whether Mr. Fitzjames Stephen loves his fellow-men: which, he assures us, is only
the case to a very limited extent. Life, to Mr. Stephen, would be intolerable without
fighting: a millennium where the lion is to lie down with the lamb, presents to him a
very flat and tedious prospect: he has no patience with the sentimentalists who insist
on pestering him with their nauseous affection. These facts are not without interest
for the psychological student: and we may admit that they exhibit forcibly the difficulty
of realising the evangelical ideal. But we can scarcely treat them as serious
arguments against the practical doctrine that any possible increase of mutual
goodwill among the members of the human family is likely to be attended with an
increase of their common happiness. 'Yes, but what do we mean by "happiness"?'
Mr. Stephen would reply. Certainly he does not clearly know what he means by it. He
generally assumes that every one must necessarily wish to impose his own idea of
happiness upon every one else: indeed in one place he goes so far as to say that if
two persons' views of what constitutes happiness are conflicting, they cannot have a
mutual wish for each other's happiness. Yet Mr. Stephen is elsewhere perfectly
aware that 'every man's greatest happiness is that which makes him individually most
happy, and of that he and he only can judge'. What confusion this double view
introduces into his utilitarian arguments, we need scarcely indicate. And there are
many similar confusions: in fact we continually find Mr. Stephen assuming in one
place without hesitation a common opinion against which he elsewhere directs page
after page of more or less ingenious sophistry. Throughout the book, too, there is a
great want of clearness of method: applications of utilitarian principles and appeals to
popular prejudices, the logic of Bentham and the rhetoric of Carlyle, succeed each
other with bewildering incoherence.
end p.184
The high that proved too high, the heroic for earth too hard,
The passion that left the ground to lose itself in the sky
present us only with an insoluble problem, I do not see how the philosopher is to fulfil
the task he has undertaken of showing the effort after an 'abiding selfsatisfaction' to
be rational. Nor, again, do I see how this is achieved by adopting the second
alternative, and supposing that the personal self-conscious being, now designated as
John or Thomas, is to be 'for ever continued in God'. For God, or the eternal
consciousness—according to the definition given in Book i.—is necessarily
conceived as unalterable: it is eternally in reality all that the human spirit is in
possibility, and there are no conceivable perfections that could be added to it; and
the process of man's moral effort is surely futile if it is to end in nothing but the
5
existence of that which exists already.
5
It may perhaps be said that I ought not to apply such a conception as 'already existing' to a Being
whose existence is expressly stated to be out of time. And, though I cannot profess to be able to
reason about such a Being without tacitly conceiving it in some relation to time, I should not have
ventured to use the phrase in the text if Green had not set me the example; e.g., in speaking (p. 181)
of a 'best state of man already present to some divine consciousness'.
It may be said that objections
end p.250
of this kind may be brought against every philosophical theology, unless it diverges
widely from religious common-sense: a plain man cannot but conceive the world-
process, divinely ordered, as designed to bring about some good not yet realised
which must be good from a divine or universal point of view, and yet he cannot
conceive the Divine existence as at any time defective or wanting in any respect. I
admit the force of the rejoinder; only, unlike Green, I should draw from it the
inference that we ought not to use these theological notions, while yet unpurged of
such palpable inconsistencies, as the basis of a philosophy of practice.
If, however, we leave on one side these theological difficulties, can we find the
'abiding self-satisfaction' which a moral agent is supposed to seek, in the first of the
alternatives above suggested—in the conception, that is, of a society of persons who
somewhere, somehow, in the indefinite future, are to carry further that movement
towards perfection which is so seriously impeded among the human beings whom we
know? We might perhaps accept the solution—it being granted that the human spirit
can be abidingly satisfied with movement instead of rest, progress instead of
perfection—if a 'better state of humanity' could be taken as a convertible term for the
'better state of myself' at which, as a moral agent, I necessarily aim. In several
passages Green seems to pass backwards and forwards between these two notions
as if they might be used indifferently in his reasonings; but I cannot see how his
moral psychology justifies this procedure. He has laid it down that 'in all desire, or at
any rate in all that amounts to will, it is selfsatisfaction which the self-conscious agent
necessarily seeks . . . a certain possible state of himself which in the gratification of
the desire he seeks to reach' (pp. 177, 182): and since he has also explained how
the most characteristic human desires depend on the conscious distinction between
the desirer's own individuality and that of other persons, I presume that we must
maintain this distinction in interpreting the account above given of 'all desire'; and
therefore that the 'better state of myself' which I necessarily seek cannot be the
better state of any other person as such. But if so, we must know exactly how the
one comes to be identified or indissolubly connected with the other under the
comprehensive notion of the 'bettering of man' or 'humanity'; by what logical process
we pass from the form of unqualified egoism under which the true end of the moral
agent is represented to us on one page, to the unmediated universalism which we
find suddenly substituted for it on another. I admit, of course, that the Divine Spirit, so
far as it can be rightly conceived to aim at the realisation or reproduction of itself in
men, must be conceived as aiming at its realisation in 'persons', not in 'this person', in
humanity, not in me; but this only brings out more forcibly the difference that has to
be bridged over between the aim of my one indivisible conscious self at its own
satisfaction, and this aim of the Divine Spirit at a satisfaction or realisation which may
just as well be attained in anyone else as in me. The mere fact that I am aware of
myself as a self-distinguishing consciousness and attribute a similar
end p.251
consciousness to other men, does not necessarily make me regard their good as my
own; some rational transition is still needed between the recognition of them as ends
to themselves, and the recognition of them as ends to myself.
Can this transition be obtained by dwelling on the essential sociality of men, the
universal or normal implication, through sympathy, of each one's interest or good with
the interests of some others—according to the plain man's conception of 'interest' no
less than the philosopher's? In some parts of his discussion (e.g., in Book iii., ch. 3)
Green seems to rely to some extent on this line of reasoning, with which the looser
optimism of eighteenth-century moralists appears to have been often entirely
satisfied; but I think that an exact consideration of it will show its inadequacy to
establish the required conclusion. For granting all that is claimed, it only proves that I
cannot realise good for myself without promoting the good of others in some degree;
it does not show that my own good is in any sense identical with the good of others
who are to live after me, so that it will 'abide' in another form when my individual
existence has terminated. And even if we give up the characteristic of 'permanence'
and merely consider whether my good during life can be identified with the good of
humanity at large, I still fail to see how this identification can be justified by anything
that we know of the essential sociality of ordinary human beings. The 'better state of
himself' as conceived even by a voluptuary, who aims at dining well, is a social state:
his dinner must be a convivial dinner if it is to be good; but it does not follow that he
contemplates the waiters who hand round the dishes as ends-in-themselves or has
any interest in future good dinners of which he will not partake. This is a coarse
illustration; but the proposition that it illustrates seems to me equally, if less palpably,
true of all the ordinary exercises and functions of cultivated social existence: the
mere fact that I am a social being, that my life is meagre and starved if I do not
enlarge it by sympathy, and live the life of the community of which I am a member,
does not necessarily constitute the good of humanity my good: it brings me a certain
way towards this, but it has not necessarily any force or tendency to carry me the rest
of the way. Granting that 'to any one actuated by it the idea of perfection for himself
will involve the idea of a perfection for all other beings, so far as he finds the thought
of their being perfect necessary to his own satisfaction', it remains true that to most
persons the dissatisfaction caused by the idea of the imperfection of other beings,
not connected with them by some special bond of sympathy, is at any rate an evil
very faintly perceptible; and the question why in this case they should sacrifice any
material part of their own good or perfection to avoid it remains unanswered.
I shall be told, perhaps, that the true good of man is so constituted that no
competition can possibly arise between the good of one individual and the good of
any other. And, doubtless, Green often affirms with sufficient distinctness that 'the
idea of a true good does not admit of the distinction between good for self and good
for others'. I think, however, that he does not steadily keep before his
end p.252
mind the gulf that he has placed between himself and common sense by the
adoption of this important proposition; and that, in consequence, he wastes his
energies in trying to establish the untenable paradox that civil society is 'founded on
the idea' of a common good of this kind. He admits, indeed, that 'we are very far, in
our ordinary estimates of good, whether for ourselves or for others, from keeping
such a standard before us . . . the conviction of the community of good for all men
has little positive influence over our practical judgments'; good being, in fact, 'sought
in objects which admit of being competed for'. But he does not seem to see that the
acceptance of this proposed standard would radically alter the common notions of
virtue, even the notions to which he himself adheres most unquestioningly in his
delineation of the moral ideal. Consider, for example, his description of the ideally
just man, who is 'so over-curious, as it seems to the ordinary man of the world, in
inquiring, as to any action that may suggest itself to him, whether the benefit which
he might gain by it for himself or for some one in whom he is interested would be
gained at the expense of anyone else'; and so determined not to 'promote his own
wellbeing or that of one whom he loves or likes, from whom he has received service
or expects it, at the cost of impeding in any way the wellbeing of one who is nothing
to him as a man, or whom he involuntarily dislikes' (p. 244). Surely all this scrupulous
investigation, all this resolute impartiality, implies that, in the opinion of Green's
ideally just man, it is at least possible that he and his friends may be benefited at the
expense of others, that the promotion of one's own well-being may really involve the
cost of impeding the well-being of others: in short, that good really consists—at least
to some extent—in 'objects that admit of being competed for'. How, after writing this
description of an ideally just man, Green could go on to say that 'the distinction of
good for self and good for others has never entered into that idea of a true good upon
which moral judgments are founded', I cannot imagine. That the distinction ought to
be banished from our moral judgments is an intelligible proposition—though I think a
moralist who makes it is rather bound to reconstruct our notions of justice and
injustice, and show us the form they will take when the distinction is eliminated—but
the statement that it has 'never entered in' I contemplate with simple amazement.
So again, the 'habitual self-denial', the 'self-sacrificing will' which form an essential
element of Green's moral ideal, seem to me notions with regard to which Kant's
question Quid juris? is very obviously raised by Green's theory of the true good; and
the question one that never finds an answer. If all self-conscious agents are always
aiming each at his own good or self-satisfaction, and the most virtuous man only
differs from the most vicious in that he seeks it with a truer insight into its nature, how
can he—in the strictness of philosophical discourse —be said to 'deny' or 'sacrifice'
himself in so seeking it? What he denies is not 'himself'—according to Green's
psychology as expounded in Book ii.—but those 'impulses', 'influences', or
'tendencies' due to his animal soul with which he does
end p.253
6
not identify himself,
6
Cf. especially Bk. ii. ch. 2, p. 151.
'by which he is consciously affected but which are not he'; and which Green, indeed,
with a certain eccentricity of terminology, is reluctant even to call 'his desires'. I trust
the reader will not think that I am disputing about words; the question, I take it, is not
of language but of the correctness of a certain psychological analysis; I seem to
discern, in Green's account of moral action, pagan or neo-pagan forms of ethical
thought combined with Christian or post-Christian forms without any proper
philosophical reconciliation.
It may be said, however, that these objections are purely formal, or at least that they
do not affect the substance of our author's own doctrine: let us leave them, therefore,
and try if, when we examine in detail the content of Green's conception of a 'true
good' for the individual, we find it really so constituted that it cannot possibly come
into competition with the true good of any other individual. It is difficult to see how this
can be maintained with reference to the wide ideal of human perfection which is put
forward in many passages of the treatise. The 'realisation of human capabilities' at
which we ought to aim is repeatedly stated to include 'art and science' as well as
'specifically moral virtues': we must suppose 'all that is now inchoate in the way of art
and knowledge' to have reached completion in it (p. 309): the development of arts
and sciences is 'a necessary constituent' of any life which 'the educated citizen of
Christendom' presents to himself as one in which he can find satisfaction (p. 415).
But if I am right in thinking the development of artistic faculty and taste a part of my
true good, I surely cannot be wrong in regarding the latter as including 'objects that
admit of being competed for', so long as the material conditions of our spiritual
existence remain at all like what they are at present: indeed I should have thought
that a writer like Green, who steadily refuses to take a hedonistic view of ordinary
human aims and efforts, must regard the 'realisation of scientific and artistic
capacities', taken in a wide sense, as constituting the main motive of the keen
struggle for material wealth which educated and refined persons generally feel
themselves bound to keep up, for their children even more than for themselves. The
thoughtful trader knows that wealth will enable him to provide himself and those he
loves with books, pictures, prolonged education, varied travel, opportunities of
intellectual society: and, knowing this, he allows himself to adopt methods of dealing
which sometimes, perhaps, are hardly compatible with Green's ideal of justice.
Similarly the hardest choice which Christian self-denial imposes is the preference of
the work apparently most socially useful to the work apparently most conducive to
7
the agent's own scientific and aesthetic development.
7
I think Green unconsciously evades the difficulty which this choice presents, on his theory, when he
speaks (pp. 292-3) of 'the conscientious man sacrificing personal pleasure in satisfaction of the claims
of human brotherhood . . . the good citizen has no leisure to think of developing his own faculties of
enjoyment'. Of course his good man, being anti-hedonistic, has no theoretical difficulty in sacrificing
his own pleasure or enjoyment—or indeed that of anyone else: but we may still ask whether and why
and how far he is called upon to sacrifice the realisation of his scientific and artistic capabilities.
end p.254
It may be replied that Art and Science are good, but Virtue better; that the self-
devotion which leads a man to postpone to duty the fullest possible realisation of his
scientific or artistic faculties is an exercise in which a fuller development of his nature
as a whole is attained. I cannot conceive any empirical criterion of 'fulness of
development' by which this could be made to appear even probable as a universal
proposition: but if we grant it to be true, in all cases in which the occasion for such a
sacrifice may be presented, it can only be because the superiority in importance of
the 'specifically moral virtues', as compared with