302394256.connecticut Insurance Journal - Good
302394256.connecticut Insurance Journal - Good
302394256.connecticut Insurance Journal - Good
OpenCommons@UConn
2009
Recommended Citation
Lowry, John, "Whither the Duty of Good Faith in UK Insurance Contracts?" (2009). Connecticut Insurance
Law Journal. 59.
https://opencommons.uconn.edu/cilj/59
CONNECTICUT
INSURANCE LAW
JOURNAL
The Journal welcomes the submission of articles and book reviews. Both text and notes
should be double or triple-spaced. Submissions in electronic form are encouraged, and
should be in Microsoft™ Word™ version 97 format or higher. Citations should conform to
the most recent edition of A UNIFORM SYSTEM OF CITATION, published by the Harvard Law
Review Association.
MEMBERS
FACULTY ADVISOR
PATRICIA MCCOY
UNIVERSITY OF CONNECTICUT
SCHOOL OF LAW
OFFICERS OF ADMINISTRATION
Michael J. Hogan, M.A., Ph.D., President, University of Connecticut
Peter J. Nicholls , Ph.D., Provost and Executive Vice President for Academic Affairs
Jeremy Paul, J.D., Dean, School of Law
Anne Dailey, J.D., Associate Dean for Academic Affairs
Michael Fischl, J.D., Associate Dean for Research and Faculty Development
Darcy Kirk, J.D., Associate Dean for Library and Technology
Ann Crawford, M.Ed., Acting Associate Dean for Finance and Administration
Ellen K. Rutt, J.D., Associate Dean for Admissions, Student Finance and Career Services
Karen L. Demeola, J.D., Assistant Dean for Admissions and Student Finance
FACULTY EMERITI
Robert L. Bard, B.A., M.A., LL.B., J.S.D., Professor of Law, Emeritus
Phillip I. Blumberg, A.B., J.D., LL.D. (Hon.), Dean and Professor of Law and Business,
Emeritus
John C. Brittain, B.A., J.D., Professor of Law, Emeritus
Clifford Davis, S.B., LL.B., Professor of Law, Emeritus
Nell J. Newton, B.A., J.D., Dean and Professor of Law, Emeritus
Howard Sacks, A.B., LL.B., Dean and Professor of Law, Emeritus
George Schatzki, A.B., LL.B., LL.M., Dean and Professor of Law, Emeritus
Craig Shea, A.B., LL.B., LL.M., Professor of Law, Emeritus
Phillip Shuchman, B.A., M.A., LL.B., Professor of Law, Emeritus
Eileen Silverstein, A.D., J.D., Professor of Law Emeritus
Lester B. Snyder, B.S., LL.B., LL.M., Professor of Law, Emeritus
Terry Tondro, A.B., LL.B., M.Phil., Professor of Law, Emeritus
Nicholas Wolfson, A.B., J.D., George and Helen England Professor of Law, Emeritus
FACULTY OF LAW
Jill Anderson, B.A., University of Washington; J.D., Columbia University; Visiting
Assistant Professor of Law
Paul Bader, B.A., Duke University; J.D., Mercer University Walter F. George School of
Law; Assistant Clinical Professor of Law
Robin D. Barnes, B.A., J.D., State University of New York at Buffalo; LL.M., University of
Wisconsin; Professor of Law
Jon Bauer, A.B., Cornell University; J.D., Yale University; Clinical Professor of Law
Loftus E. Becker, Jr., A.B., Harvard College; LL.B., University of Pennsylvania; Professor
of Law
Bethany Berger, B.A., Wesleyan University; J.D., Yale University; Professor of Law
Robert Birmingham, A.B., J.D., Ph.D. (Econ.), Ph.D. (Phil.), University of Pittsburgh;
LL.M., Harvard University; Professor of Law
William Breetz, B.A., Dartmouth College; LL.B., University of Virginia; Executive
Director, Connecticut Urban Legal Initiative, Inc.
Sara Bronin, B.A., University of Texas; M.Sc., University of Oxford (Magdalen College);
J.D., Yale University; Associate Professor of Law
Deborah A. Calloway, B.A., Middlebury College; J.D., Georgetown University; Professor
of Law
Marcia Canavan, B.A., University of California, Los Angeles; MPH., University of
California, Los Angeles; J.D., Golden Gate University School of Law and
University of Colorado School of Law; Assistant Clinical Professor of Law
Paul Chill, B.A., Wesleyan University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Clinical Professor
of Law
Anne C. Dailey, B.A., Yale University; J.D., Harvard University; Evangeline Starr
Professor of Law and Asssociate Dean for Academic Affairs
Steven M. Davidoff, B.A., University of Pennsylvania; M.A., London Business School;
J.D., Columbia University; Associate Professor of Law
Geoffrey Dellenbaugh, A.B., Princeton University; M.A., Stanford University; Ph.D.,
University of Pittsburgh; J.D., University of Chicago; Assistant Clinical Professor
of Law
Timothy H. Everett, B.A., M.A., Clark University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Clinical
Professor of Law
Todd D. Fernow, B.A., Cornell University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Professor of
Law and Director, Clinical Programs
Richard Michael Fischl, B.A., University of Illinois; J.D., Harvard University; Professor of
Law and Associate Dean for Research and Faculty Development
Hillary Greene, B.A., J.D., Yale University; Associate Professor of Law and Director,
Intellectual Property Clinic
Kaaryn Gustafson, A.B., Harvard University; Ph.D., J.D., University of California,
Berkeley; Associate Professor of Law
Mark W. Janis, A.B., Princeton University; B.A., M.A., Oxford University; J.D., Harvard
University; William F. Starr Professor of Law
Richard S. Kay, A.B., Brandeis University; M.A., Yale University; J.D., Harvard
University; Wallace Stevens Professor of Law
Darcy Kirk, A.B., Vassar College; M.S., M.B.A., Simmons College; J.D., Boston College;
Professor of Law and Associate Dean for Library & Technology
Peter R. Kochenburger, A.B., Yale University; J.D., Harvard University; Park Associate
Clinical Professor and Director of Graduate Programs
Lewis S. Kurlantzick, B.A., Wesleyan University; LL.B., Harvard University; Zephaniah
Swift Professor of Law
Alexandra Lahav, B.A., Brown University; J.D., Harvard University; Professor of Law
Leslie C. Levin, B.S.J., Northwestern University; J.D., Columbia University; Professor of
Law
Diana L. Leyden, B.A., Union College; J.D., University of Connecticut; LL.M., Georgetown
University; Associate Clinical Professor of Law and Director, Tax Clinic
Peter L. Lindseth, B.A., J.D., Cornell University; M.A., M. Phil, Ph.D, Columbia
University; Professor of Law
Justin Long, A.B., Harvard University; J.D., University of Pennsylvania; Visiting Assistant
Professor of Law
Hugh C. Macgill, B.A., Yale University; LL.B., University of Virginia; Oliver Ellsworth
Research Professor of Law and Dean Emeritus
Neysun Mahboubi, A.B., Princeton University; J.D., Columbia University; Visiting
Assistant Professor of Law
Jennifer Brown Mailly, B.A., Brown University; J.D., Ohio State University; Assistant
Clinical Professor of Law
Margaret Martin, B.A., Boston University; J.D., Columbia University; William R. Davis
Clinical Teaching Fellow
Ruth Mason, B.A., Columbia University; J.D., Harvard University; Associate Professor of
Law
Patricia A. McCoy, B.A., Oberlin College; J.D., University of California, Berkeley;
Director of Insurance Law Center and George J. and Helen M. England Professor
of Law
Barbara McGrath, B.A., Yale University; J.D., University of Connecticut; Assistant
Director, Connecticut Urban Legal Initiative, Inc.
Willajeanne F. McLean, B.A., Wellesley College; B.S., University of Massachusetts; J.D.,
Fordham University; LL.M., Free University of Brussels; Professor of Law
Thomas H. Morawetz, A.B., Harvard College; J.D., M.Phil., Ph.D., Yale University;
Tapping Reeve Professor of Law and Ethics
Lily Neff, B.S.E.E, City College of New York; J.D., Pace University; Assistant Clinical
Professor of Law
R. Kent Newmyer, B.A., Doane College; Ph.D., University of Nebraska; Professor of Law
and History
Angel R. Oquendo, A.B., M.A., Ph.D., Harvard University; J.D., Yale University; Olimpiad
S. Ioffe Professor of Law
Leonard Orland, B.A., Rutgers University; LL.B., University of Pennsylvania; Oliver
Ellsworth Research Professor of Law
Sachin Pandya, B.A., University of California, Berkeley; M.A., Columbia University; J.D.,
Yale University; Associate Professor of Law
Richard W. Parker, A.B., Princeton University; J.D., Yale University; D.Phil., Oxford
University; Professor of Law
Jeremy Paul, A.B., Princeton University; J.D., Harvard University; Dean and Thomas F.
Gallivan, Jr. Professor of Real Property Law
Ellen Ash Peters, B.A., Swarthmore College; LL.B., Yale University; LL.D., Yale
University; University of Connecticut; et al.; Visiting Professor of Law
Richard D. Pomp, B.S., University of Michigan; J.D., Harvard University; Alva P. Loiselle
Professor of Law
Jessica S. Rubin, B.S., J.D., Cornell University; Assistant Clinical Professor of Law
Susan R. Schmeiser, A.B., Princeton University; J.D., Yale University; Ph.D., Brown
University; Professor of Law
Peter Siegelman, B.A., Swarthmore College; M.S.L., Ph.D., Yale University; Roger
Sherman Professor of Law
James H. Stark, A.B., Cornell University; J.D., Columbia University; Professor of Law and
Director, Mediation Clinic
Martha Stone, B.A., Wheaton College; J.D., LL.M., Georgetown University; Director,
Center for Children’s Advocacy
Kurt A. Strasser, B.A., J.D., Vanderbilt University; LL.M., J.S.D., Columbia University;
Phillip I. Blumberg Professor of Law
Colin C. Tait, A.B., Cornell University; LL.B., Yale University; Oliver Ellsworth Research
Professor of Law
Stephen G. Utz, B.A., Louisiana State University; J.D., University of Texas; Ph.D.,
Cambridge University; Professor of Law
Carol Ann Weisbrod, J.D., Columbia University; Ellen Ash Peters Professor of Law
Robert Whitman, B.B.A., City College of New York; J.D., Columbia University; LL.M.,
New York University; Professor of Law
Steven Wilf, B.S., Arizona State University; Ph.D., J.D., Yale University; Professor of Law
Richard A. Wilson, BSc., Ph.D., London School of Economics and Political Science;
Professor of Law
CONTENTS
ESSAYS
ARTICLES
M. Todd Henderson∗
***
***
I. INTRODUCTION
The collapse of the housing bubble and the resulting credit crunch
has caused untold harm to the economy and the lives of millions by
destroying trillions of dollars in global wealth. The search for causes and
remedies has begun in earnest, and chief among these is the largely
unregulated credit derivatives market. Regulation of one form or another is
the proposed solution in many quarters, and one of the prominent proposals
is insurance regulation. At the very least, the analogy between credit
derivatives and insurance is often made, and this faulty comparison may
lead regulators astray, regardless of the mode of regulation ultimately
∗
University of Chicago Law School. Thanks to the George J. Phocas Fund for
research support.
2 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
1
One market failure was the lack of a centralized clearinghouse to manage
and reduce counterparty risk in credit derivative transactions. The Federal Reserve
and Treasury are encouraging exchanges, like the Chicago Mercantile Exchange,
to handle these transactions. See USA Exchanges: Geithner Pushes for Derivatives
Shake-Up, FINREG21, July 11, 2009, http://www.finreg21.com/news/usa-
exchanges-geithner-pushes-derivatives-shake-up.
2
As shown in supra note 1, numerous politicians and observers have made
the linkage. It has also crept casually into numerous media accounts. For example,
in an account of the AIG catastrophe, an author for The New Republic calls credit
derivatives insurance: “Between March, when Greenberg left AIG, and the end of
2005, Cassano's division issued more than $40 billion in credit-default swaps
(essentially insurance) for portfolios of securities backed by subprime mortgages.
This was more than half of all the insurance of this type the company had on its
books.” Noam Scheiber, A New Theory of the AIG Catastrophe, THE NEW
REPUBLIC, Apr. 15, 2009, at 10, 11. Legal scholars believe this too. See Robert F.
Schwartz, Risk Distribution in the Capital Markets: Credit Default Swaps,
Insurance and a Theory of Demarcation, 12 FORDAM J. CORP. & FIN. L. 167, 181
(2007) (arguing that certain credit derivative contracts have “general form and
function reflect[ing] many basic insurance arrangements.”); William K. Sjostrom,
Jr., The AIG Bailout, 66 WASH. & LEE L. REV. (forthcoming 2009) (“A CDS
certainly appears to fall within this definition given that the protection seller
contractually agrees to compensate the protection buyer following the occurrence
of a credit event.”), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?
abstract_id=1346552.
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 3
regulated.”3 New York State went even further. On September 22, 2008,
Governor David Patterson announced plans to regulate credit derivatives as
insurance under the auspices of the state’s insurance department.4 New
York State Insurance Commissioner Eric Dinallo then testified before a
House Committee investigating credit derivatives: “the insurance regulator
for New York is a relevant authority on credit default swaps,” because
“[w]e believe . . . [they are] insurance.”5 Although New York has delayed
its regulatory plans pending a federal review of credit derivative
regulation,6 the question of whether credit derivatives are insurance
remains an open and much bandied about one that needs to be analyzed.
3
60 Minutes: Wall Street’s Shadow Market; Credit default swaps (CBS
television broadcast Oct. 5, 2008), available at http://www.cbsnews.com
/stories/2008/10/05/60minutes/main4502454_page1.shtml. Dr. Greenberger
argued that the industry was able to avoid regulation by simply using the word
“swap” instead of “insurance” to describe the transaction. See id. (“So they use a
magic substitute word called a 'swap,' which by federal law is deregulated.”).
Swaps were specifically excluded from regulation by the CFTC by the
Commodities Futures Modernization Act of 2000.
It is true that a typical CDS transaction does not involve a “swap” in the same
way that an interest rate swap does. In the latter case, two parties agree to swap
risks: the holder of a fixed-rate note agrees to swap that income stream with the
holder of a variable-rate note. But while the term swap is not technically accurate,
it is difficult to imagine that insurance or other regulators would be fooled by the
label.
4
Press Release, Governor Patterson Announces Plan to Limit Harm to
Markets from Credit Derivatives (Sept. 22, 2008) (on file with Errol Cockfield)
available at http://www.ins.state.ny.us/press/2008/p0809224.pdf. See also Danny
Hakim, New York to Regulate Financial Tool Behind the Credit Crisis, N.Y.,” NY
TIMES, Sept. 23, 2008, at C10, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2008/09
/23/business/23swap.html?ref=business (“The governor said the state’s insurance
department would begin regulating credit-default swaps as insurance products in
cases where the buyer of the swap also owns the underlying bond it is meant to
back.”).
5
Hearing to Review the Role of Credit Derivatives in the U.S. Economy:
Hearing before the H. Comm. on Agriculture Committee, 110th Cong. (2008)
[hereinafter Hearing] (testimony of Eric Dinallo, Ins. Comm’r, N.Y. State),
available at http://agriculture.house.gov/testimony/110/h91120/Dinallo.pdf.
6
See id. (“Based on the developments reported on by the President’s Working
Group, it is clear they are committed to comprehensive and effective federal
oversight of credit default swaps. . . . . Accordingly, New York will delay
indefinitely our plan to regulate part of this market.”). It is clear from Dinallo’s
testimony that New York is using the threat of insurance regulation as a weapon to
4 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
Credit derivatives exist in many forms and flavors, but the essence
is simple: it may be more efficient for different entities to handle the
various aspects of lending. A typical loan has many parts, including:
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 7
9
Capital reserves required by the Basle Accords are non-productive, and
therefore reduce a bank’s return.
8 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
bank makes a loan to a borrower. There is some risk that the borrower will
default on the loan, causing losses to the bank.10 Naturally, the bank wants
to minimize these losses. The bank can do this through ex ante selection
(that is, due diligence during the underwriting process), through ongoing
monitoring of the borrower, and through effective ex post workout
procedures. The bank can also contract with a third party to make the bank
whole in the event the borrower defaults.
Consider a simple example: Bank holds on its balance sheet a $100
note for a loan made to Borrower. Bank may want to shift some of the risk
that Borrower will not repay the loan, say because of costly federal capital
adequacy requirements that require Bank to hold some percentage of the
loan’s outstanding balance in cash reserves.11 For a period of (normally)
five years, Investor, who wants to hold risk of Borrower, agrees to make
Bank whole in the event of default, thus assuming the risk of default,12 in
return for a stream of periodic payments from Bank. Voilà, the risk of the
loan to Borrower has been swapped from Bank to Investor. The premium
paid by the Bank is expressed as a risk spread in basis points, say 100 basis
points or 1 percent. For a $100 loan, this would mean the bank would make
quarterly payments of $0.25 to buy protection on the note. (The spread,
which expresses the risk of default during the five-year term of protection,
varies over time, allowing information about the quality of the debtor to be
revealed and allowing investors unrelated to the loan contract to speculate
on changing credit quality for profit.) In the event of “default,”13 Bank
delivers the underlying credit instrument, in this case the loan, to Investor,
and Investor makes a payment to Bank that puts Bank in the position it
would have been in if Borrower had not defaulted.
10
The default risk is only one of many risks embedded in a loan. Lenders
(and borrowers) face interest rate risks, volatility risk, currency risks, and so on.
The significance of credit derivatives (CDSs) is the ability to unpack and isolate
credit risk, and allowed it to be transferred to others who may be more efficient
holders of it.
11
In general, US banks are subjected to the capital adequacy requirements of
the so-called Basle Accords, implemented by the Bank of International
Settlements. See Basle Committee on Banking Supervision, International
Convergence of Capital Measurement and Capital Standards, July 1998, available
at http://www.bis.org/publ/bcbs04a.htm.
12
Default risk is only one of many types of risk. Others include: interest rate
risk, counterparty risk, currency risk, and so on.
13
As described below, see infra p. 7, the issue of when a credit derivative
contract triggers payment is a complicated and tricky issue.
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 9
14
See U.S. GEN. ACCOUNTING OFFICE, CREDIT DERIVATIVES: CONFIRMATION
BACKLOGS INCREASED DEALERS’ OPERATIONAL RISK, BUT WERE SUCCESSFULLY
ADDRESSED AFTER JOINT REGULATORY ACTION, GAO-07-716, p.6 n.8 (2007),
available at http://www.gao.gov/new.items/d07716.pdf (“The top five end-users of
credit derivatives are banks and broker-dealers (44 percent), hedge funds (32
percent), insurers (17 percent), pension funds (4 percent), and mutual funds (3
percent).”).
15
Borrower might not want Bank to sell the loan, since this may signal
something bad about Borrower. The positive signal derived from having Bank be a
creditor and monitor of Borrower may be quite valuable and for this reason, loan
agreements often include no-sale clauses.
16
Conservatism here may derive internally, that is, from managers and
shareholders, or from regulation.
10 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
The risk is not just swapped between two parties. In a typical CDS
contract, the risk can be swapped many times, so that there are numerous
parties in the risk-sharing chain. For instance, A, a manufacturing firm may
borrow from B, a commercial bank. B, not wanting to hold the risk, may
pay a premium to C, a dealer in CDS contracts, in return from a promise to
be made whole if A defaults. (C, like all protection sellers, will be required
to post some collateral with B to ensure payment on this obligation.) Since
C is a dealer, it will look for a buyer willing to provide the ultimate risk-
bearing function. D, an insurance company, agrees to make C whole in the
event of a default by A in return for premium payments by C. Then E, a
different commercial bank, wants exposure to A’s credit risk, so it may
agree to make D whole in the event of a default by A, in return for the
payment of premiums by D. And on and on and on. There is no limit on the
number of links in the risk-sharing chain, and, in practice, credit risk is
often transferred dozens of times after its original creation. A typical credit
derivative contract has hundreds of investors selling protection for
hundreds of lenders and even more underlying borrowers. In the mortgage
securitization market, for example, one of the problems in the collapse of
US house prices was figuring out who actually held the risk of mortgage
default so that workouts or foreclosures could happen efficiently.17
As discussed below, although C, D, E, and parties on down the
chain could be said to be providing risk-sharing contracts in this example, it
would be a dramatic expansion of the concept of insurance regulation to
call them insurance companies. These entities might be individuals, banks,
hedge funds, university endowments, or any other pool of investment
money looking for return. In addition, the kind of insurance they are
providing is not dissimilar from the insurance provided by nearly every
contract that involves risk sharing (that is, every contract), and therefore
raises irresolvable line drawing problems. The closest entity to an insurance
company is, C the original CDS dealer. But, as discussed below, these are
brokers who are regulated by numerous securities and banking laws, and
subject to the oversight of numerous federal regulators.
CDS contracts do have characteristics similar to typical insurance
contracts. Specifically, risk sharing and information asymmetries inevitably
give rise to problems of moral hazard and adverse selection. Bank knows
more about default risk of Borrower than the counterparties, and therefore
17
See, e.g., Mike McIntire, “Tracking Loans Through a Firm That Holds
Millions,” N.Y. TIMES, Apr. 23, 2009, available at http://www.nytimes.com/
2009/04/24 /business/ 24mers.html.
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 11
the latter may be unwilling to sell protection on the notes Bank brings to
the market, since the counterparties may believe these are the debtors most
likely to default. Another problem is that the existence of credit protection
may make Bank less diligent in its monitoring role, thereby increasing the
risk of default as a result of the risk-sharing contract. In theory and
practice, there are steps that can be taken to mitigate these risks. Bank can
hold back a portion of the risk of default, perhaps the first-loss position,
thereby giving it incentives to monitor. This is analogous to a deductible in
insurance contracts, and it can address both the moral hazard and adverse
selection problem. (As it turns out, however, the nature of the securitization
process made these first-loss tranches more valuable, on a risk-adjusted
basis, than their price, while more senior tranches were less valuable.)
These problems and the steps taken to mitigate them are discussed below.
There is also a rich secondary market in which the risk of default of
a particular borrower (known as a “reference entity”) is traded among
parties that have no contact with or affiliation with either the borrower or
the lender. For instance, auto parts maker Delphi had $2 billion in bonds
outstanding at the time it declared bankruptcy, but there were over $25
billion in credit derivative bets outstanding on whether or not Delphi would
default on those bonds.18 The term “bet” is chosen deliberately, since these
contracts are nothing more than wagers on whether Delphi would default.
(As a side note, we do not regulate these bets as gambling for the same
reason that the secondary market in stocks, that is, the New York Stock
Exchange, is not regulated as gambling, even though it is. The reason is
that the gambling is socially useful.) This large ratio of secondary to
primary market is common across companies used as reference entities.
After all, there is nothing (other than perhaps gambling law) that prevents
two parties from writing a contract that replicates the payoffs from the
payment or default of any debt instrument entered into anywhere. These
contracts are called “synthetic,” since they do not involve any physical
obligations to deliver on the underlying debt instrument.
The proposals to date to regulate credit derivatives have focused
entirely on the primary market, specifically disclaiming any authority over
the secondary market. As discussed below, this has something to do with
what insurance experts call “insurable interest,” which is a requirement that
the party allegedly doing the insuring has to pay only when the party that is
18
The Ballooning Credit Derivatives Market: Easing Risk or Making It
Worse?, KNOWLEDGE@WHARTON, Nov. 2, 2005, http://knowledge.wharton.
upenn.edu/article.cfm?articleid=1303.
12 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
19
In the nomenclature, if the underlying is a bond, the instrument is called a
CDO, while if it is a loan, it is called a CLO.
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 13
20
The loss for the senior bank is the probability of firm one defaulting (10
percent) times the probability of firm two defaulting (10 percent).
21
Correlation of risks is obviously the key assumption in the creation of a
CDO. If the risks in the three-bond case are perfectly correlated (that is, the failure
of one firm means all three firms will fail), then the probability of loss for all three
14 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
investors is the same 10 percent. Thus, there are no credit reduction benefits from
securitization.
22
See Posting of Tyler Durden to, Some More Facts about How CDS Market,
http://zerohedge.blogspot.com/2009/02/ (Feb. 1, 2009, 10:31 EST).
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 15
23
Interview with executive at insurance company responsible for credit
derivative transactions, on Mar. 21, 2009.
16 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
premium to a third party in return for a promise to make the bank whole in
the event of a loss related to the loan. If this analogy holds, the lender is the
“insured” and the counterparty is the “insurer.” And, the insurance law of
the fifty states would then regulate the insurer and the content of contracts
it enters into with insureds.
Building on the apparent similarity between typical insurance
contracts (regulated by state insurance agencies) and credit derivatives,
New York State recently proposed deeming credit derivatives “insurance.”
The chief state regulator, Eric Dinallo, offered the rationale during
testimony before a congressional committee: “With [plain-vanilla CDS
contracts], if the issuer of a bond defaults, then the owner of the bond has
suffered a loss and the [CDS] provides some recovery for that loss.”26
Dinallo limited the reach of the proposed regulations of credit derivatives,
however, by asserting the state’s jurisdiction covers only cases where the
credit derivative contract is between an original lender and a third-party
investor, that is, single-name CDS contracts in which an individual or
entity sells protection to an originating bank.27 These are so-called
“covered” transactions (as opposed to “naked” ones), since there is privity
between the insured and the underlying debt instrument. The reason for this
limited scope for insurance regulation is based on a generally accepted
argument that the party being insured has an “insurable interest” in the
underlying amount at risk under the contract. In other words, a contract is
“insurance” only if the insuring party pays when the insured party actually
suffers a harm unrelated to the insurance contract.
This concept can be illustrated by comparing the primary and
secondary credit derivative markets. Where a bank issues a loan and then
buys credit protection on that loan that pays off if the loan defaults, the
argument is that the buyer of credit protection has an insurable interest in
the loan, and that the protection acts as insurance against this loss. In the
secondary market, by contrast, two parties unrelated to the issuance of the
loan (and without the knowledge of the bank making the loan, the borrower
26
Hearing, supra note 5, at 3 (testimony of Eric Dinallo, Ins. Comm’r, N.Y.
State).
27
Id. (“We believe that the first type of swap, let’s call it the covered swap, is
insurance. The essence of an insurance contract is that the buyer has to have a
material interest in the asset or obligation that is the subject of the contract. That
means the buyer owns property or a security and can suffer a loss from damage to
or the loss of value of that property. With insurance, the buyer only has a claim
after actually suffering a loss.”).
18 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
taking out the loan, and any parties contracting with either of them), bet on
whether or not the borrower will repay the loan. According to the
conventional wisdom of insurance regulation, this bet is not insurance. The
reason for this concession is that otherwise “insurance” would include far
too much and things far beyond the ken, expertise, or conceivable reach of
state insurance regulators.
The concession is manifest in the findings of insurance regulators.
For instance, in 2000 after Congress exempted “swaps” and other
derivatives from certain regulation,28 the New York Insurance Department
was asked whether credit derivatives were in fact insurance, which would
be subject to state regulation. The question it was asked by federal
regulators was: “Does a credit default swap transaction, wherein the seller
will make payment to the buyer upon the happening of a negative credit
event and such payment is not dependent upon the buyer having suffered a
loss, constitute a contract of insurance under the insurance law?”29 This
question is aimed at the secondary market, and was answered in the
negative for reasons of a lack of privity with the loss on the part of the
entities engaging in the derivative transaction. In his testimony before the
House, Commissioner Dinallo distinguished this prior finding of the New
York State Insurance Commission that credit derivatives were not
insurance, by pointing out that the question asked was focused only on non-
privity cases or “naked” credit derivatives.30 From this, Dinallo concluded
that a different result could obtain in the privity case (that is, CDS
contracts), since the protection seller was insuring a real loss outside of the
context of the contract. The analogy described above was thus sufficient for
him to conclude that, with privity and a real potential loss, credit
derivatives of the plain-vanilla CDS variety are insurance products.
The argument is not preposterous on its face. Insurance is about
risk sharing, and in that sense credit derivatives, which are fundamentally
risk-sharing contracts, are akin to insurance. But, as shown below, the fact
that credit derivative contracts are providing an insuring or risk-hedging
28
See Commodity Futures Modernization Act of 2000 or [CFMA], H.R.
5660, 106th Cong. §§ 103, 105, 407 (2000); CFMA of 2000, S. 3283, 106th Cong.
§§ 103, 105, 407 (2000); see also Gramm-Leach-Bliley Act [GLBA] (Financial
Services Modernization Act of 1999), Pub. L. No. 106-102, 113 Stat. 1338, 1393-
94 (1999).
29
Hearing, supra note 5, at 4-5 (testimony of Eric Dinallo, Ins. Comm’r,
N.Y. State).
30
Id. (“So at the same time, in 2000, the New York Insurance Department
was asked a very carefully crafted question.”).
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 19
the borrower in order to collect on its bet. Although plausible, this facial
similarity does not justify treating credit derivatives as insurance. As
discussed below, this argument proves too much. Numerous opportunities
exist for similar moral hazard problems outside of the insurance context,
there already exist mechanisms (both market and from industry trade
groups) to ameliorate any moral hazard, and there is nothing about
insurance law that makes it a good fit for further reducing these potential
harms, if they are substantial.
An additional argument for regulating credit derivatives as
insurance is the absence of any existing regulation by other federal or state
agencies, especially of certain players in the market, like hedge funds and
other private pools of money. Many experts and pundits blame the lack of
regulation of the credit derivatives market as contributing to the credit
crisis. The argument goes like this: credit derivatives are not traded on an
exchange, but rather through individualized contracts, known as the over-
the-counter market, and the lack of regulation, either directly or indirectly
through regulation of the exchanges on which securities trade, allowed
private parties to externalize systemic risk costs onto society. The lack of
regulation thus generated an inefficient number or type of these
transactions from a social welfare standpoint.
There may be something to the premise of this argument, that is,
that the lack of regulation exacerbated the risk that private parties would
act in ways that would be privately optimal but increase the risk of a global
financial meltdown. The premise is debatable, but even if it is true, this
Essay shows that insurance regulation is not the only way in which these
systemic costs can be internalized by firms. Most obviously, direct
regulation of the credit derivatives market by existing federal departments
responsible for derivatives and markets, such as requiring derivatives to be
traded on an exchange, is possible under current law.
In fact, it seems from the public statements of New York officials
that the purpose of the characterization of credit derivatives as insurance is
intended to stoke federal regulators to act, more than a firm belief that
credit derivatives are insurance. After all, if they are insurance, then there
should in fact be no need for or call for federal regulation. In testimony
before Congress and other public comments, New York State’s insurance
officials “stopped short of endorsing comprehensive state-level regulation
of this privately negotiated market” and agreed to delay its plan to regulate
credit derivatives based on the indication that federal regulators are
“committed to comprehensive and effective federal oversight of credit
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 21
31
Id. at 7.
32
Dinallo testified that :
Effective regulation of credit default swaps should include the
following provisions: All sellers must maintain adequate capital
and post sufficient trading margins to minimize counterparty
risk; A guaranty fund should be created that ensures that a failure
of one seller will not create a cascade of failures in the market;
There must be clear and inclusive dispute resolution
mechanisms; To ensure transparency and permit monitoring,
comprehensive market data should be collected and made
available to regulatory authorities; The market must have
comprehensive regulatory oversight, and regulation cannot be
voluntary. Id.
33
U.S. GEN. ACCOUNTING OFFICE, supra note 14, at 6 n.8 (“The top five end-
users of credit derivatives are banks and broker-dealers (44 percent), hedge funds
(32 percent), insurers (17 percent), pension funds (4 percent), and mutual funds (3
percent).”)..
34
Sjostrom, supra note 2, at 40 (“A CDS certainly appears to fall within this
definition given that the protection seller contractually agrees to compensate the
protection buyer following the occurrence of a credit event.”).
35
Id. at 26.
22 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
let's put a hedge fund on top of the insurance company and let's sell these
derivative products to banks all around the world."36
As discussed below, this argument proves too much, as many other
entities, like banks, hedge funds, pension funds, and so on, used credit
derivatives too, often disastrously but just as often fantastically, and
therefore there is nothing special about the end users that justifies treating
them as insurance. If anything, the fact that some insurance companies
were harmed by them justifies different regulation on insurance companies.
36
See “President Barack Obama on ‘The Tonight Show with Jay Leno,” N.Y.
TIMES, Mar. 19, 2009, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2009/03/20/us
/politics/ 20obama.text.html.
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 23
1. Line-Drawing Problems
37
Nor is the result different if a third party sells the insurance to Farmer or
Baker. For instance, an individual unconnected with the farming or baking
business may believe that wheat prices will rise/fall in six months based on
predictions about weather, changes in supply or demand, or other factors. This
individual can enter into a forward contract with Farmer or Baker either directly or
24 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
that credit derivatives are. After all, when a firm issues equity interests to
investors, it is entering into a risk-sharing contract (on behalf of managers,
creditors, and other stakeholders) with these investors. Equity holders,
unlike debt holders, have no fixed claim on a firm’s assets, and therefore
provide a source of funding that is less sensitive to downturns in
performance than debt. A firm that has more equity on its balance sheet is,
all else being equal, less risky than a firm that has less. So we could re-
characterize a firm’s decision to issue equity (to lower its debt to equity
ratio) as buying insurance (against a downturn in the firm’s affairs) and the
investors buying the equity as selling insurance to the firm. Of course, no
one thinks of equity in this way. But equity is as much about insurance as
credit derivatives are.
One reason securities are not regulated as insurance is the fact that
equity investments are regulated by a separate body of law – securities law
– specifically designed to address the policy challenges of issuing and
investing in securities. When Congress passed the securities laws in the
1930s, it could have simply called equity investments insurance and
delegated regulation to state insurance law under the same theories as those
calling for this treatment of credit derivatives. But this would have been a
reach – although arguably insurance, equity securities are sufficiently
different along numerous dimensions to justify a separate body of
regulatory law.
Another reason equity might not be regulated as insurance is
because of the particular characteristics of the contracts in question. As
noted above, typical credit derivative contracts look like typical insurance
contracts: one party makes periodic payments to another in return for a
make-whole promise in the event of a future occurrence. This similarity is
only a surficial one, however, since there are many other aspects of credit
derivative contracts that are quite different. For instance, payments may not
turn on actual losses, there may be no pooling of risk, the make-whole
promise may be purely synthetic, and so on. In addition, it is hard to
imagine regulatory treatment turning solely on the question of whether
risk-sharing payments are made on a periodic basis (as in insurance
contracts) or a lump sum basis (as in equity investments, forward contracts,
and so on). This would elevate form over substance in an arbitrary way not
anticipated by the parties, and would provide an easy roadmap to avoiding
any regulation.
Finally, few if any investors making an equity investment think
they are providing insurance. Rather, the investment is made for a whole
host of reasons, including pure investment, speculation, hedging, and so
26 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
forth. Credit derivatives are used for these multiple reasons too, and this
cuts strongly against trying to narrowly pigeonhole them as insurance.
Credit derivatives are also used for speculation about credit risk.
Investors can use credit derivative contracts to speculate on the default
probability of a particular borrower. In general, there are no insurance
contracts like this. Participants in insurance markets do not wager on
whether an individual’s probability of dying or crashing a car is rising or
falling on a daily basis, as they do with firm risk in credit derivative
markets. Insurance is based on probabilities at the macro level and across
large numbers based on actuarial science, and, when it is based on
individuals characteristics, it is done only at the point of origination and not
for speculation purposes. But this is exactly what is done with credit
derivative contracts. For example, an investor who believes that General
Electric’s credit quality is likely to worsen over the next few years can buy
protection against default by GE on its debt. If the credit quality does
deteriorate, the cost of protection will rise, and the investor will earn a
profit. Similarly, if an investor believes that GE’s credit quality is likely to
improve, it can sell protection against default by GE. If the credit quality
does improve, the cost of protection will fall, and the investor will earn a
profit. Before credit derivatives this kind of speculation was extremely
difficult, as it is practically impossible to short bonds or loans. The credit
derivative market thus allows for information about debt quality to be
processed in a market, perhaps with large gains to capital allocation
efficiency. Like the hedging examples above, these transactions are not
insurance in any meaningful sense. Nothing about the speculation contract
requires that it be held for any period of time. An investor can buy or sell
protection and hold it for an hour, a day, a year, or five years (the typical
maximum length), depending on the profit that can be made from buying or
selling at a particular time. The contract does nothing more than offer an
opportunity to buy or sell later at a higher or lower price. In this way, credit
derivatives can be, and are largely, about investment, not insurance.38 In
fact, they resemble secondary market transactions in equities, since they
involve market-based trades about the fundamental value of a third party
unrelated to the transaction in question.
A final (non-insurance) use of credit derivatives is arbitrage, of
either the pure or regulatory variety. Pure arbitrage possibilities arise when
there is temporary mispricing in markets that allows investors to engage in
38
Life insurance could be used for investment in a way, but this is not its
primary purpose or the way it is typically used. Moreover, state insurance
regulators are not really concerned about regulating investment decisions by
sophisticated parties.
28 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
paired transactions that earn sure profits, and thus eliminate the mispricing.
Mispricing in debt securities might arise because the primary and
secondary markets are traded on different markets: a firm’s bonds might be
trading on a bond market, while protection on those bonds might be trading
on over-the-counter markets that are not perfectly correlated with the
public bond markets. This difference might generate opportunities for an
investor to buy/sell the underlying security in one market, while
simultaneously buying/selling protection on it in the over-the-counter
market using a credit derivative in a way that allows it to earn a return that
is independent of the credit risk of the borrower. This kind of arbitrage
opportunity has no insurance-like characteristics, and it is potentially quite
useful in accurately pricing credit risk by removing temporary market
inefficiencies. Participants in credit derivative markets, at hedge funds,
insurance companies, and other large financial entities, describe this as a
major driver of their transactions in credit derivative markets.39
The other type of arbitrage – regulatory arbitrage – is related to
insurance, since it is one of the main reasons insurance companies are
involved in the credit derivatives markets. But the lesson here runs counter
to any regulatory story – in fact, it is a product of regulation itself.
Regulatory arbitrage works like this. Banks are often the most
efficient originators of loans, since they have relationships with lenders and
the back office to underwrite and process loans. However, they are not
always the most efficient holders of loans because of regulations that make
holding risk more costly for them and regulations that make investing in
credit risk difficult for insurance companies and other risk-sensitive
investors. In other words, smaller banks, individual investors, insurance
companies, pension funds, university endowments, foreign governments,
and a whole host of other investors would like to participate in corporate
debt markets, but cannot do so in the absence of financial instruments that
allow large commercial banks to sell the risk, especially in ways, like
securitization discussed above, that recharacterize the risk in ways that
make individual investments in it appear less risky. If insurance companies,
pension funds, or endowments can only invest in corporate debt rated
AAA, banks, who are required to hold cash reserves on corporate debt
rated below AAA will find a way of repackaging the debt so that some of
the sub-AAA debt can become AAA debt – this is the securitization and
tranching process described above.
39
Interview with executive at insurance company, supra note 23.
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 29
firm (or SPV) holding the interests in these future cash flows is not
conceptually different from a firm that sells anything else, be it iPods,
consulting services, or what have you, and then sells interests in the cash
flows these sales generate. When a firm raises money from shareholders, it
is buying insurance in the same way that a bank transfers some risk through
a credit derivative contract. Although equity holders are not liable to make
the seller of the risk whole in the event of some specific default, the equity
investors are providing the firm with an opportunity to reduce its risk.
Equity, like insurance, provides a cushion against a downturn. Of course,
no one thinks of regulating securities as insurance despite the similarity
along this dimension.
There are at least two important differences between these two
types of risk-sharing mechanisms. First, on average the sellers of equity to
regular firms are much less sophisticated than the sellers of risk protection
to lenders. This, of course, cuts the other way from regulating credit
derivatives as insurance. Second, the structure of the standard insurance
contract (and the typical credit derivative contract) is different than the
shareholder contract. Whereas in a credit derivative or insurance contract
the party assuming the risk receives periodic payments in return for a
promise to make the party selling the risk whole, in the shareholder
contract, the sequence of payments is reversed: the party assuming the risk
of default pays the money up front, while agreeing to receive future cash
flows in the form of dividends, capital appreciation, or liquidation value at
some time in the future. This alternative structure has important
implications, which are discussed below, but it does not necessarily
undermine the attempted analogy to insurance. After all, if insurance is
defined as a contract in which risk is moved from one party to the other, the
structure and terms of the contract are, all else being equal, irrelevant to
whether risk is in fact being swapped.
The lesson to be learned from this use, which is also only
superficially similar to classic insurance, is that any regulation of insurance
company participation in credit derivative markets should focus on how
insurance companies invest in credit derivatives. This is especially true
since insurance companies are only a small fraction of the entire market in
credit derivatives.
created SPV. In this case, the analogy to insurance pooling is more apt.
One could view the multiple lending banks whose notes are pooled together
in the SPV as the policyholders, while the SPV and its investors are the
“insurance company.” While this analogy has more surficial appeal than
the case of plain-vanilla CDS’, as discussed below, the policy arguments
for insurance-like regulation do not obtain. So even in the case where there
is risk pooling – a necessary conceptual component of insurance – there is
no policy justification for insurance regulation. This is discussed below.
Even insurance commissioners admit that CDOs are not insurance
for this reason.40 There is a deep irony here. There is generally no risk
pooling – an essential component of “insurance” – in CDS contracts, but
these are the contracts that state insurance regulators and pundits consider
insurance. In contrast, there is at least some risk pooling in more complex
CDO contracts, but there is often no insurable interest in these transactions,
so insurance regulators disavow any regulatory oversight of them. The
reason for the line drawn by insurance regulators has to do with experience
and thus expertise. Insurance regulators are used to dealing with entities
that pool risk, are responsible for ensuring an adequate income stream to
pay for future liabilities, and are contracting with every-day consumers
who rely on the insurance company to make them whole in the event of
large personal losses. This experience is obviously not transferable to a
market in which none of these traditional aspects of insurance exists, nor
are the key regulatory questions. This is explored in greater detail below.
40
See infra note 47 and accompanying text.
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 33
would still make more sense to regulate this contract as a matter of banking
law. After all, the bank is engaging in regulatory arbitrage, which may be
normatively good or bad from the perspective of banking policy. Banks
hedging risk reduces the probability that they will default, and thus
jeopardize the claims of depositors. On the other hand, it is possible that
some banks used credit derivative contracts not to hedge risks but to
increase profits by repackaging loans, moving them off of the bank’s
balance sheet, receiving regulatory relief, and then bringing the risk back
onto the bank’s balance sheet through mechanisms that were not
transparent to regulators. Again, these issues are largely about banking law
– that is, capital adequacy requirements, rules about relief from these
requirements, banking oversight, compensation of bank executives, and so
on.
credit markets, but nothing that calls this equilibrium solution into doubt.
With learning from the recent collapse, it is likely that this discipline will
return to the market.
Even if it does not, there is not much that insurance regulation is
likely to add to solve the problem. No regulators or private actors were
aware of the mispricing problem, despite the fact that there were numerous
regulators, including insurance regulators (AIG is an insurance company
after all!) monitoring these markets closely, and despite the fact that
investors were betting billions of dollars of their own money on these
instruments. To simply declare that more regulation, and in particular more
insurance regulation, is needed, is to simply declare the debate over.
Another type of moral hazard is the potential that the parties to
credit derivative contracts might act in ways that destroy social value but
increase the private value to the party. For instance, a buyer of protection,
like a bank, might have incentives to force a borrower to default on a debt
in order to collect on the credit derivative contract; even if it is not
otherwise efficient for it to do so. This problem arises only because there
may be technical defaults that would otherwise not lead to bankruptcy, but
the bank buying protection could insist upon enforcing covenants against
them now that its downside is limited by its purchase of protection. (The
analogy to insurance here is that the buyer of insurance might willingly
destroy an otherwise valuable asset to collect on an insurance premium in
cases in which the asset has value but this value is less than the value of the
insurance policy.) While this is possible, there are at least three things that
limit its practical effect.
The first of these is the fact that private contracts take this problem
into account, without the need for regulatory mandate. This is not to say
that there are not market failures, but simply that this particular problem is
not unknown or unremedied in credit derivative markets. As in insurance,
where the problem exists too, buyers of protection voluntarily reduce the
risk they will shirk because of the moral hazard problem by agreeing to
bear some of the first losses that may arise from a default by the original
borrower. In insurance, this is called a deductible, and the theory is that it
reduces on the margin the incentive of the insured to engage in socially
destructive behavior. Credit derivative contracts try to reduce this conduct
too – the buyers of credit derivative protection routinely hold the first-loss
position so as to signal to sellers of protection that the bank buying
protection has some skin the game and will not engage in this kind of
destructive behavior. A deductible, being less than 100 percent of the risk,
however, can never fully offset this risk, so there remains some moral
36 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
hazard problem. Part of this can be priced by the market, but industry
norms can try to reduce it too. This is the next solution.
The second way moral hazard is reduced is through the fact that
self-regulatory bodies, like the ISDA, are already aware of this possibility
and are structuring industry norms and boilerplate contracts to mitigate
these potential problems. The moral hazard issue arose for the first time in
the case of credit derivative contracts written on the financial services and
insurance firm Conseco. Credit derivative contracts at that time required a
payment from the seller to the buyer of protection in the event that the
underlying reference entity—in this case, Conseco—suffered a “credit
event,” which included a restructuring of the reference entity’s bank loans.
In 2000, Conseco’s credit quality deteriorated and began to suffer liquidity
problems, so it went to its borrowers in search of a restructuring agreement.
The lenders agreed, including an extension of maturity, increased interest
rates, and new covenants. The restructuring triggered payment under the
existing credit derivative contracts.
This fact created a serious moral hazard problem. The original
lenders to Conseco, who had purchased protection against a credit event,
were the ones who got to decide whether to restructure Conseco’s debt, and
thus whether a restructuring event transpired.41 The lenders could trigger
payment simply by agreeing to extend the maturity of the loan or make
other trivial changes to the loan that would cost them little (and would be
readily agreed to by the borrower) and yet trigger potentially large
payments from the sellers of protection. In fact, the situation under the
then-prevailing boilerplate terms was much worse than that. Under the
ISDA’s 1999 version of the boilerplate terms (called the “Definitions”), the
buyers of protection could deliver any debt instrument of the same kind as
that on which the lender or other party bought protection. Since Conseco
had a number of outstanding debt instruments of varying maturity, the bank
triggering a restructuring credit event could choose the cheapest of these
outstanding debt instruments, thereby making large profits on its self-
triggering claim. Specifically, Conseco had short-term bonds that were
trading at about 90 percent of face value, while its long-term bonds were
trading at about 60 percent of face value. This meant the original lender
could declare default, and then buy long-term bonds at 60 cents to settle out
its much more expensive short-term bonds. This exposed the sellers of
41
SATYAJIT DAS, CREDIT DERIVATIVES: CDOS AND STRUCTURED CREDIT
PRODUCTS 101-103 (3d ed. 2005).
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 37
42
See Viktor Hjort, The Xerox Debt Restructuring – A Moral Hazard Issue?,
Morgan Stanley, Fixed Income Research (July 19, 2002).
43
DAS, supra note 41, at 103.
44
See William Rhode, Fed Says No To Credit Restructuring, DERIVATIVES
STRATEGY, Dec. 2000, http://www.derivativesstrategy.com/magazine
/archive/2001/1200shrt.asp.
45
See Restructuring Supplement to the 1999 ISDA Credit Derivatives
Definitions, ISDA (2001); see also Donald A. Bendernagel & Oussama Nasr,
Legal Documentation and the Restructuring Debate, CREDIT DERIVATIVES ISSUES
AND OPPORTUNITIES, 2001, at 21.
46
DAS, supra note 41, at 105.
38 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
always keep a look out for the possibility of sabotage, since reporting it to
the market and prosecutors is likely to provide sufficient deterrence.
***
As this section has showed, regulators are likely to find it very
difficult to draw sensible lines or regulate financial products in a coherent
and efficient manner under the rubric of insurance regulation. This means
that regulation might more sensibly focus on investors instead of
investments. Insurance law is based less on regulating insurance than on
regulating insurance companies. In other words, we do not regulate
insurance companies because they sell insurance, but rather regulate
insurance contracts because they are sold by insurance companies. The
right question to ask is not whether credit derivatives are “insurance,” but
rather if they are sold or issued by “insurance companies.” This, of course,
begs the question of what should count as an insurance company.
The next Part tries to answer this question by looking at the policy
reasons for having a separate body of insurance law to regulate insurance
companies. The policy reasons are uniquely applicable to insurance
companies, not all firms that participate in credit derivative markets, and
thus there is no good policy reason for applying insurance regulation.
47
There is another justification for insurance regulation that has to do with the
consumer-facing nature of some insurance contracts. See infra p. 32.
40 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
The first unique feature of insurance companies is the fact that they
sell their products long before they are delivered to customers. This means
the normal production cycle is inverted. The typical (that is, non-insurance)
firm produces products and then sells them in return for cash. Payment and
delivery are linked closely in time and there is an immediate feedback from
customers. Insurance companies, however, have a much different
production cycle that causes unique governance problems. An insurance
company’s customers are policyholders, who pay (in the form of premium
payments) in advance for products (payments on claims) that come many
years later, if at all.48 This is important because the discipline on how cash
can be spent that comes with having to sell valuable products or services in
the market is missing or attenuated. Payments are made based on promises
alone, and there is thus the risk that the cash reserves given in advance to
the insurance company will be squandered on risky investments, and thus
unavailable to pay off claims when they come due. This is the Ponzi-
scheme problem discussed above. When there is continuous solicitation of
investment by outsiders and a mismatched payment scheme (current
investments pay liabilities of previous investors), there is a risk that
managers will engage in too much risk when the liabilities that arise are
greater than predicted. In these bad states of the world, insurance company
managers have incentives to attract more capital on irrational terms to pay
current liabilities owed to prior investors.
The inverted production cycle of insurance companies has another
problem where there are competitive markets for insurance services. In an
unregulated market, insurance companies are bound to compete heavily on
price, and this may lead to under reserves such that future liabilities will
not be covered by sufficient assets. There are two parts of this claim, so it is
worth unpacking it.
First, competition among insurance companies is likely to focus
primarily and perhaps excessively, on price. This is because the quality of
the products insurance companies are selling (the other thing on which they
compete) is identical or unobservable. The repayment of losses less the
deductible is the same regardless of the insurer. There is some risk that the
insurer will fail and be unable to repay the liabilities, but this is something
that is, by its very nature, unobservable by the insureds. Reputation and
longevity may be correlated with this risk, but these factors coupled with
48
The payout for life insurance policies may obviously be decades away.
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 41
the governance problems noted above may simply lead to more risky
investment choices by the insurer in the next period. Another unobservable
component of potential competition is service quality – that is, the
timeliness of payments, the cost of the claims process, the quality of
customer service, and so on. Like the risk of default, these will be
unobservable by the insureds in the period when they make their
investment decision, since they happen only many years later and after
premiums have already been collected. For these reasons, price is likely the
primary way in which insurance companies would compete in an
unregulated market.
Second, price competition for insurance products is different from
price competition for non-insurance products, and, if unregulated, may lead
to pricing at below marginal cost. Non-insurance firms have no incentive to
price below marginal cost, since, as a consequence, every sale would lose
the firm money. Insurance companies, however, have inverted production
cycles, which translates that the costs of the product being sold are felt long
after the cash is collected by the firm for the sale. This means myopic
managers, hubristic managers, over-confident managers, or desperate
managers may charge too little for new insurance premiums. Insurance
involves extensive long-range forecasting and the potential for costs, which
are realized only after sales, to be much higher than expected. Absent the
immediate feedback loop of typical production cycles, the possibility of
competition leading to destructive price wars is greater than for normal
firms.
It is true that credit derivative contracts are somewhat based on
future results and forecasting problems may arise. But this is concern is
ameliorated by several factors. Credit derivative contracts are generally
much shorter in term than insurance contracts, lasting a maximum of five
years, and very often held for much shorter than that. So although make-
whole payments under the contract may occur in the future, the potential
for error is reduced by the fact that forecasting need be made over a much
shorter period. The risk is also priced much more frequently, since
payments made by protection buyers are due quarterly. For most credit
derivative contracts, the prices of buying and selling production are
adjusted quarterly depending on the financial condition of the underlying
borrower, and this generates the kind of frequent pricing data that is
common in regular product markets. Even where it is not, the continuous
pricing of the same debt in the market allows holders of risk to engage in
pairwise transactions that allow them to rebalance their portfolio on short
time horizons. In addition, the parties on both sides are highly sophisticated
financial institutions (and their investors), and it is unlikely that any
42 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
outsider, like a regulator, could do a better job at estimating the future cash
flows from particular debt instruments so as to improve pricing.
The pricing problem for insurance companies is exacerbated by the
weak governance structure described below, which may encourage overly
risky actions when policy payouts exceed expectations. In short, the
managers of an insurance firm that charges too little, for whatever reason,
and finds itself unable to meet claims as they come due, may be less
constrained by creditors in the kind of response it will take. The managers
may simply try to sell more policies to pay off existing claims from other
policyholders with the hope of someday righting the ship. This potential
that arises from price competition may turn an insurance company into a
sort of Ponzi scheme.
This super risk preference situation is unlikely to arise in the case
of non-insurance firms because of the discipline of product markets and
because of the discipline of creditors when times are bad. For credit
derivative firms (that is, SPVs holding the rights to the cash flows from
various debt instruments), the probability of this arising is even lower. This
is because investment by the SPV managers happens before any investment
is made by shareholders in the SPV. A pot of cash is created and then sold,
with an implicit promise that no more assets will be added that that
particular pot. The possibility of super risk preferring managers is thus
extremely unlikely.
49
Assuming, of course, the managers aren’t acting in their own interest.
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 43
50
See, e.g., Douglas G. Baird and Robert K. Rasmussen, Private Debt and the
Missing Lever of Corporate Governance, 154 U. PA. L. REV. 1209, 1209-11
(2006).
44 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
among the alleged insurer’s “policy holders.” In addition, banks that buy
credit protection are nothing like individuals that buy auto or life insurance
policies. Banks are sophisticated, repeat players, represented by counsel,
capable of processing information about the riskiness of their counterparty,
and have tremendous bargaining power.
It is possible for a protection seller to write many CDS contracts,
and thus put any individual buyer of credit protection into the position of
holding a small claim against the firm, say insurance company or hedge
fund. Although this would not change the nature of the protection buyer
and the ability of it to fend for itself, it does raise potential concerns about
the management of the protection seller. But this just then puts the inquiry
about governance back at that level, and tied to the nature of the seller of
protection. If the protection seller has a weak governance model, like that
of a bank or an insurance company, then it may be susceptible to this
problem, but if it is an entity with strong governance in bad times, then the
concern about too much risk on the part of managers (on behalf of
shareholders) is much lower. Hedge funds, for instance, must return to the
market frequently for capital (that is, they do not have capital lock in) and
are funded by extremely sophisticated investors. They are decidedly not
subject to this concern. In short, insurance companies with weak
governance should be subject to regulation to avoid the social inefficiency
that might arise from their governance structure, while non-insurance
companies, with strong governance, are less worrisome.
The same result obtains even when we consider a more
complicated credit derivative contract. The parties buying protection that
have their default risk pooled into a CDO structure are large financial
entities with much greater sophistication and risk-bearing ability than
individuals buying typical insurance products. The risk that the sellers of
protection will “pull a fast one” on them is much lower given this
sophistication. In addition, the investors in the SPV holding the default risk
(the analogous insurance company) are likewise large financial entities
capable of making risk assessments, demanding and processing
information, pricing risk, and wielding their bargaining power in the event
a bad future state arises.
Moreover, the nature of the typical CDO structure is effectively a
one-time game, in which credit risks are pooled and the cash flows sold off
to investors. The sponsor and manager of the SPV does not continue to sell
protection based on a pool of funds provided by investors (as in an
insurance company), but rather makes the investments first (by choosing
risks to pool), then goes to the market to sell cash flow rights to investors.
This means that managers of the SPV do not really do much or can do
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 45
much in terms of risk alteration of the SPV once it has raised money from
investors. The future course of the SPV is set, and the payouts are what
they are. No future investments are made, no additional investors are
brought in, and there can be no change in strategy for the firm. Therefore,
there is less chance for abuse in the event the SPV payouts are less than
expected. Governance quality is largely irrelevant in this model firm.
Applying this governance model to the insurance company model,
it is as if the insurance company wrote all of its policies before raising
money in the market. In that case, investors would worry less about the
governance of the insurance company, since its job would simply be to
process claims from the policies it had written – it would not take on new
policies (and a new source of cash) on terms likely to be unfavorable to
existing investors. There would still be some governance risk, however,
since the decisions on what policies to pay out on, how much to
compensate executives, and other firm costs still have to be made. In some
of these, managerial interests may be aligned with those of investors, while
in others they may diverge. Importantly, however, this residual governance
risk is not present in the CDO case, since all of these decisions are made
before the investment in the firm (for example, management fees) or are
automated (for example, the amount of payouts). In short, any governance
problems simply do not obtain in the typical structure of credit derivative
contracts.
3. Consumer Protection
The third policy reason for a separate body of insurance law is the
need for strong consumer protection. While the concern with the inverted-
production-cycle and governance problems was basically insurance firms
not charging insureds enough, the consumer protection concern is that
insurance firms will charge too much. As mentioned above, the concern is
based on the following syllogism: insurance is a critical product for most
individuals; individuals are not sophisticated about insurance products or
contracts; and therefore insurance companies will take advantage of
customers by overcharging them. Accordingly, (the bulk of) state insurance
law regulates the substance and terms of insurance policies (to make them
simpler to understand and compare across firms), as well as regulating
service and coverage issues (to make sure insurance firms do not back
away from promises to pay). In other words, insurance is sometimes
regulated as a specialty consumer product in which informational and
bargaining power asymmetries are sufficiently large that social losses may
be generated from an unregulated market.
46 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
1. Jurisdictional Issues
51
See This American Life #382: The Watchmen (Chicago Public Radio
broadcast Jun. 5, 2009), available at http://www.thislife.org/extras/radio/
382_transcript.pdf.
48 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
2. Substantive Law
i. Licensing
First, entities could not sell protection unless the seller was a
licensed insurance company. All fifty states require a state-issued license
before a firm may issue an insurance policy.52 Such a pre-screening
requirement might make some sense as part of trading on a credit
52
See N.Y. INS. LAW. § 1102(a) (2006). “No person, firm, association,
corporation or joint-stock company shall do an insurance business in this state
unless authorized by a license in force pursuant to the provisions of this chapter, or
exempted by the provisions of this chapter from such requirement.” Id.
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 49
ii. Duties
53
See N.Y. INS. LAW. §§ 1322, 1324 (2006 & 2009).
50 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
54
See N.Y. INS. LAW. § 1402(a) (2006). “Before investing its funds in any
other investments, every domestic insurer shall invest and maintain an amount
equal to the greater of the minimum capital required by law or the minimum
surplus to policyholders required to be maintained by law for a domestic stock
corporation authorized to transact the same kinds of insurance, only in investments
of the types specified in this section which are not in default as to principal or
interest.” Id.
55
The Model Insurance Act, for instance, provides for three “risk-based
capital” levels: (i) mandatory control level risk-based capital (measured at .7 times
authorized control level risk-based capital), (ii) regulatory action level risk-based
capital (measured at 1.5 times authorized control level risk-based capital), and (iii)
company action level risk-based capital (measured at 2.0 times authorized control
level risk-based capital). NAT’L ASS’N OF INS. COMM’RS, MODEL LAWS,
REGULATIONS, AND GUIDELINES vol. III (2009).
56
See Number of Hedge Funds up by Two Thirds in Two Years, Concludes
PerTrac Study, THE TRADE NEWS, Mar. 5, 2007, available at
http://www.thetradenews.com/hedge-funds/prime-brokerage/613.
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 51
regulators. The job would be made even more overwhelming since selling
protection is not necessarily a full-time job. Hedge funds and other sellers
may hold the default risk for a very short time (a few months or less) and
may engage in transactions only periodically or on a one-off basis. Unlike
insurance companies that exist to provide risk sharing services, protection
sellers are not necessarily in the business of holding debt risk. The fluid
nature of market participants would make any licensing or ex-ante
regulatory regime incredibly costly and drive many participants out of the
market.
In addition, capital requirements did not work well if at all in
preventing insurance companies, such as AIG, from investing aggressively
and, as it turns out, dangerously in credit derivative markets. The state-
based model was manipulated by AIG and others, and this possibility could
only be expected to be worse if every credit derivative protection seller
becomes a ward of insurance regulators. In other words, the job of
regulation would get much more difficult without any obvious way of
increasing the capabilities of regulators. This point is made even clearer by
reiterating the point made above about how insurance regulators are not
experts in financial markets in which most protection sellers participate. If
insurance companies can avoid insurance regulation, it is very likely that
hedge funds and other sophisticated and fast-moving private money funds
will also be able to do so.
Moreover, capital adequacy requirements imposed by regulators
(as opposed to margin requirements required by exchanges) generated the
incentive for regulatory arbitrage described above. Firms subjected to these
requirements had incentives to hold higher quality debt risk, which
received lower capital charges, and to move debt risk off of their balance
sheets and into bankruptcy-remote SPVs. Although this type of arbitrage is
likely inevitable at some level, the current regulatory model for insurance
proved ineffectual at preventing arbitrage that imposed systemic risk
externalities on society.
Finally, insurance regulators are not experts about the amount,
type, and structuring of capital requirements to reduce counterparty risk in
non-insurance financial transactions. It is arguable that insurance
regulators, representing the state, have incentives to determine the amount
of social cost from the failure of an insurance company, since many of the
social harms that would result would be paid for by a state-funded social
safety net or would otherwise result in state-based harms. But the failure of
a hedge fund or foreign bank or other protection seller may generate no
social losses, because gains from bets on one side cancel out losses from
bets on the other side, or are ones that are not clearly within the purview or
52 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
iv. Disclosure
57
See N.Y. INS. LAW §§ 307(a), 308 (2006) (requirements for filing an annual
financial statement and a quarterly financial statement).
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 53
disclosure by firms issuing securities and by brokers and dealers that buy
and sell securities, and the reason that insurance regulators are responsible
for the disclosure by insurance firms. To require an investment fund to
make disclosures to insurance regulators solely because it engaged in a
credit derivative transaction will impose potentially large costs on funds
based on potentially a single or small number of transactions. If the
disclosure rules are tied instead to how often a fund trades or how many
trades it makes in these markets, the funds will inevitably try to avoid these
costs by making the decisions on whether to sell protection based in part on
the arbitrary triggers. For example, if ten incidents of protection selling
trigger a disclosure obligation, we shouldn’t be surprised to see funds
selling protection nine times.
If the reason for insurance-based disclosure rules is because of the
lack of disclosure to other regulators – hedge funds have little or no
disclosure obligations under the securities laws – this is not an argument
for disclosure to insurance regulators, it is an argument for a securities law
disclosure regime. The regulator that can best calibrate what kinds of
disclosure are cost justified, what form disclosures should be made in, and
what to do with the disclosed information, if anything, is the regulator that
should require and monitor disclosure. For one, it is not clear what
insurance regulators would do with the disclosures, especially if the bulk or
almost all of it is about activities that are unquestionably not insurance.
v. Contract Regulation
58
Under New York law, life, accident and health and annuity policy forms are
subject to prior regulatory approval. Compare N.Y. INS. LAW. § 1102(a), with N.Y.
INS. LAW § 1108(a) (2006).
54 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
59
Compare N.Y. INS. LAW §§ 2305(b), 2310(a), 2344 (2006), and N.Y.
COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 11 §§ 161.1-161.12 (2009), and N.Y. INS. LAW §§
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 55
63
See JOHN B. TAYLOR, GETTING OFF TRACK: HOW GOVERNMENT ACTIONS
AND INTERVENTIONS CAUSED, PROLONGED, AND WORSENED THE FINANCIAL
CRISIS (Hoover Inst. Press 2009) (showing how the credit crunch was not caused
by a liquidity shortage but by an increase in counterparty risk).
2009] CREDIT DERIVATIVES ARE NOT “INSURANCE” 57
with the same. If A defaults on its ability to pay B, B can still be paid by
the clearinghouse. As long as the clearinghouse is solvent, the counterparty
risk for B is eliminated.
The risk-reducing qualities of an exchange can be seen more
clearly when the number of trading parties increases. Consider the case
where A is owed $100 by B, B is owed $90 by C, and C is owed $80 by A.
In this case, A has a net risk exposure of $180 to B and C, since if they
both default, A is owed $100 from B and owes $80 to C. If these three
liabilities are managed through an exchange, however, A’s risk exposure to
B and C is reduced to zero. In this scenario, A is owed $20 from the
exchange, and B and C each owe the exchange $10. Thus, A’s risk to B and
C has been eliminated, and the netting of liabilities has reduced the
magnitude of the overall amounts owed to much more manageable sums.
So long as the exchange can ensure, say through margin requirements, that
B and C can make good on their $10 (about 10% of the total bets), the
market stays together.
It is for this reason that the clearinghouse model is used for other
derivative markets, like commodities markets, futures markets, and
currency markets. Of course, the clearinghouse must be solvent and for this
it needs sufficient scale of operations and the ability to impose rules on
trading parties that help reduce the risk that they will not be able to make
due on their contracts. This last point is precisely about the locus of
regulatory authority – who knows better how to regulate the leverage or
other characteristics of market participants? Since the clearinghouse,
typically a for-profit enterprise, stands to lose personally and dramatically
in the event of a failure, it has arguably better incentives along this
dimension than government regulators, who are not betting their own
money and who, perversely and ironically, may see increased funding from
any failures.
Given these benefits, the question is why the exchange did not
arise as a natural part of the market. One answer might be that an exchange
has some elements of a public good, since it reduces the potential for
systemic risk by decreasing the likelihood of a credit crunch from the
failure of a single firm, and public goods are chronically under supplied by
the market. But the story here is more complicated, because the analysis
above suggests that it is in each individual firm’s interest to reduce risk in
this way. Moreover, the collective action problems that typically cause the
market to under supply public goods do not obtain in this context, since
there were only about eight major intermediary market makers, and they
were all located in New York City.
58 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
VI. CONCLUSION
This Essay has shown that the simple argument that some credit
derivatives help banks and other providers of debt share risk with other
investors is not sufficient for credit derivative contracts in general to be
deemed “insurance.” A separate body of insurance law exists not because
the underlying contracts are insurance, but rather because typical insurance
contracts are sold by insurance companies. It has also shown that the policy
justifications for regulation of insurance companies—an inverted
production cycle, weak corporate governance in bad times, and
unsophisticated insureds—do not obtain in the context of credit derivative
markets or apply to parties to credit derivative contracts. Finally, it has
shown how an exchange for credit derivative contracts can provide most if
not all of the substantive regulation insurance regulators can provide, at
lower cost and in a more efficient manner. There remain unsolved
problems with the exchange solution, including issues of scale and bilateral
netting, but this is a subject for another day.
60 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
THE ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” –
AND THE WAY BACK
Michael W. Taylor *
***
***
I. INTRODUCTION
The Global Financial Crisis has put the spotlight on the United
States’ complex and fragmented regulatory structure as an issue of global
systemic importance. The failure of large investment banks like Bear
Stearns and Lehman Brothers has put into question the adequacy of the
regulation of large non-bank financial intermediaries. The lack of
consolidated supervision of the AIG group, with its Financial Products
*
Adviser to the Governor, Central Bank of Bahrain; formerly Head of
Banking Policy, Hong Kong Monetary Authority; Senior Economist, International
Monetary Fund; Reader in Financial Regulation, ICMA Centre, University of
Reading.
62 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
1
GROUP OF THIRTY, FINANCIAL REFORM: A FRAMEWORK FOR FINANCIAL
STABILITY 10 (2009), available at http://www.group30.org/pubs/recommend
ations.pdf.
2
Heidi Mandanis Schooner & Michael Taylor, United Kingdom and United
States Responses to the Regulatory Challenges of Modern Financial Markets, 38
TEX. INT’L L.J. 317, 327-29 (2003).
3
U.S. DEP’T OF THE TREASURY, THE DEPARTMENT OF THE TREASURY
BLUEPRINT FOR A MODERNIZED FINANCIAL REGULATORY STRUCTURE (2008),
available at http://www.treas.gov/press/releases/reports/Blueprint.pdf.
4
U.S. DEP’T OF THE TREASURY, FINANCIAL REGULATORY REFORM, A NEW
FOUNDATION: REBUILDING FINANCIAL SUPERVISION AND REGULATION (2009)
available at http://www.financialstability.gov/docs/regs/FinalReport_web.pdf.
5
Schooner & Taylor, supra note 2, at 320. For a discussion of reform
elsewhere in the OECD, see id. at 340-44.
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 63
6
Id. at 340-44.
7
Id. at 340.
8
Id. at 323.
9
See Richard K. Abrams & Michael W. Taylor, Issues in the Unification of
Financial Sector Supervision 22-23 (Int’l Monetary Fund, Working Paper No.
00/213, 2000), available at http://www.imf.org/external/pubs/ft/wp/2000/
wp00213.pdf. Within these two broad forms there is also scope for substantial
variation. See id. at 21-24.
10
For a general review of the background to the U.K.’s reforms, see Eilìs
Ferran, Examining the United Kingdom’s Experience in Adopting the Single
Regulator Model, 28 BROOK. J. INT’L L. 257 (2003).
11
MICHAEL TAYLOR, “TWIN PEAKS”: A REGULATORY STRUCTURE FOR THE
NEW CENTURY 10-11 (Ctr. for the Study of Financial Innovation) (1995).
12
SELECT COMMITTEE ON ECONOMIC AFFAIRS, BANKING SUPERVISION AND
REGULATION, 2008-9, H.L. 101-I, at 34.
64 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
13
For an assessment of the FSA more generally, see Howell E. Jackson, An
American Perspective on the U.K. Financial Services Authority: Politics, Goals &
Regulatory Intensity (Harvard, John M. Olin Ctr. for Law, Econ. & Bus.,
Discussion Paper No. 522, 2005), available at http://www.law.harvard.edu/
programs/olin_center/papers/pdf/ Jackson_522.pdf.
14
Clive Briault, The Rationale for a Single National Financial Services
Regulator 6 (Fin. Servs. Auth., Occasional Paper No. 2, 1999), available at
http://www.fsa.gov.uk/pubs/ occpapers/OP02.pdf. These agencies include the
Securities and Investments Board, the Personal Investment Authority, the
Investment Management Regulatory Organisation, the Securities and Futures
Authority, the Supervision and Surveillance Division of the Bank of England, the
Building Societies Commission, the Insurance Directorate of the Department of
Trade and Industry, the Friendly Societies Commission, and the Registrar of
Friendly Societies. Id. at 6 n.1.
15
Id. at 7.
16
See Michael Taylor & Alex Fleming, Integrated Financial Supervision:
Lessons from Northern European Experience 17 (World Bank, Working Paper
2223, 1999), available at http://info.worldbank.org/etools/docs/library/
50180/TaylorFleming_1999.pdf.
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 65
What is striking about the policy debate within the U.K. prior to
the formation of what became the FSA, is just how little attention was
given to the possibility of creating a single integrated financial regulator.
For several years prior to the election of a new Labour government in May
1997, there had been discussion of the need to reform the U.K.’s regulatory
system, but the ideas being debated stopped short of proposing to create a
single regulatory agency with a mandate that covered the entire banking,
insurance and investment industries.18 The concept only came to
prominence on May 20, 1997 with an announcement to the House of
Commons by the new Chancellor of the Exchequer that the government
intended to create a single regulatory authority for the banking and
securities industries. The announcement itself came as a surprise to many
observers and showed signs of having been rapidly prepared. This
impression arose not only because the statement was vague concerning
matters of detail, but also because it did not address some more
fundamental issues, such as whether the prudential regulation of insurance
companies would be included in the scope of the new regulator.19
Prior to this announcement, the British regulatory system combined
institutional and functional regulation, similar to the system created by the
17
For further discussion regarding the Twin Peaks model in a U.S. context,
see Heidi Mandanis Schooner, Regulating Risk Not Function, 66 U. CIN. L. REV.
441 (1998); Howell E. Jackson, A Pragmatic Approach to the Phased
Consolidation of Financial Regulation in the United States, (Harvard Law Sch.,
Working Paper No. 09-19, 2008), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1300431;
Cynthia Crawford Lichtenstein, The Fed’s New Model of Supervision for “Large
Complex Banking Organizations”: Coordinated Risk-Based Supervision of
Financial Multinationals for International Financial Stability (Boston College
Law Sch. Research Paper No. 89, 2006), available at http://ssrn.com/
abstract=882474.
18
Schooner & Taylor, supra note 2, at 320.
19
Ensuring the solvency of insurance companies had been the responsibility
of the Department of Trade and Industry although it was briefly transferred to HM
Treasury before the FSA was established. In July 1997, i.e. two months after the
original announcement, the government confirmed that this function would also
form part of the responsibilities of the new agency.
66 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
20
Schooner & Taylor, supra note 2, at 324-25.
21
Banking Act, 1987, c. 22, § 1 (Eng.) (repealed 2001).
22
Insurance Companies Act, 1982, c. 50, § 3 (Eng.) (repealed 2001).
23
Financial Services Act, 1986, c. 60, § 8 (Eng.) (repealed 2001).
24
L.C.B. Gower, “Big Bang” and City Regulation, 51 MOD. L. REV. 1, 11
(1988).
25
The SIB exercised powers that were transferred to it under the Financial
Services Act by the Secretary of State for Trade and Industry (a government
minister). However, the SIB itself was in the unusual position of being a company
limited by guarantee and not a department of government. A similar structure was
subsequently adopted for the Financial Services Authority.
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 67
26
See the account given by DAVID F. LOMAX, LONDON MARKETS AFTER THE
FINANCIAL SERVICES ACT 78 (1987).
27
Taylor, supra note 11, at 7.
28
These criticisms were recognized in a report issued by Andrew Large when
he assumed the Chairmanship of the SIB in 1993. ANDREW LARGE, FINANCIAL
SERVICES REGULATION: MAKING THE TWO TIER SYSTEM WORK (London:
Securities and Investments Board, 1993).
29
PETER CARTWRIGHT, CONSUMER PROTECTION IN FINANCIAL SERVICES 152
(1999).
30
Michael Taylor, The Policy Background in BLACKSTONE’S GUIDE TO THE
FINANCIAL SERVICES. & MARKETS ACT OF 2000 14 (Michael Blair ed., 2000).
68 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
31
Michael Taylor, Fin. Svcs..& Mkts. Act: The Policy Background-II, 31
AMICUS CURIAE 4, 6 (2000).
32
Whether the individuals were disadvantaged and to what extent depended
on a number of actuarial assumptions and assumptions about investment returns.
The intricacies of these issues were, however, drowned out in the subsequent
political debate.
33
See, e.g., 318, PARL. DEB., H.C. (6th ser.) (1998) 716, 718. (It continued to
be used by Labour ministers against their Conservative opposite numbers even
after the change of government).
34
Mike O’Brien, Labour's Proposals for Regulation into the 21st Century, 5
J. FIN. REG. & COMPLIANCE 115, 115-17 (1997).
35
LABOUR PARTY, LABOUR’S BUSINESS MANIFESTO (1997).
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 69
a separate statute (the Banking Act 1987) and even though, unlike the
SROs, it was a government agency. Labour suspicion of Britain’s central
bank ran deep, with some commentators suggesting that it can be traced to
the Bank’s role in the sterling crisis of 1931 that had helped to bring down
a minority Labour administration headed by Ramsay Macdonald. 36 This
fuelled Labour suspicions that the Bank of England was too closely aligned
with the Conservative party, in which the financial interests of the City of
London had a major influence. Thus when the British government
considered the introduction of statute-based bank regulation in the mid-
1970s some members of the governing Labour party proposed establishing
a banking commission independent of the Bank of England to exercise
regulatory powers. These proposals were rejected by the Cabinet after the
then Governor of the Bank of England fought a rearguard action to ensure
that it became the bank regulator.37 Nonetheless, in subsequent years the
Bank was to show itself a reluctant regulator which above all wished to
maintain its traditional, informal relationship with the leading financial
institutions in the City. Against this background it was possible to present
it as part of the City’s “self-regulating” system and as merely the chief
spokesman for a “cosy club.”
Nonetheless, it is doubtful whether the Bank of England’s
responsibility for regulating the banking sector would have come under
renewed scrutiny had it not been for two incidents in the first half of the
1990s. The first was the failure of the Bank of Credit and Commerce
International (BCCI), which went into insolvent liquidation once it became
clear that it had been a vehicle for a massive fraud.38 Although the bank
only had branches in the U.K. (its holding company was registered in
Luxembourg), the group’s “mind and management” had been in London
and hence there was a case for the Bank of England having taken the lead
in ensuring that the group as a whole was subject to consolidated
supervision. In a subsequent investigation conducted by Sir Thomas (later
Lord Justice) Bingham, a senior judge, the Bank was found to have adopted
36
MICHAEL MORAN, THE POLITICS OF BANKING: THE STRANGE CASE OF
COMPETITION & CREDIT CONTROL 120 (2d ed., 1986).
37
Id.
38
H.M. STATIONARY OFFICE, INQUIRY INTO THE SUPERVISION OF THE BANK
OF CREDIT & COMMERCE INT’L. (1992).
70 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
confidence in the system.” (From the context it appeared that he considered the
Bank of England to be part of the self-regulatory system). Id.
46
See Michael Taylor, Central Bank Independence.: The Policy Background,
in BLACKSTONE’S GUIDE TO THE FINANCIAL SERVICES AND MARKETS ACT OF 2000
at 10 (Michael Blair ed., 1998).
47
See Ferran, supra note 10, at 271-72.
72 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
48
See Ferran, supra note 10, at 271.
49
See SIR MARTIN JACOMB, RE-EMPOWER THE BANK OF ENG. 2-4 (Centre for
Policy Stud.) (2009) available at http://www.cps.org.uk/cps_catalog/Re-
empower%20the %20Bank%20of%20England.pdf.
50
It is important in this regard that the Labour party had been out of power
for 18 years and few of its lawmakers had experience of government.
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 73
51
294 PARL. DEB., H.C. (6th ser.) (1997) 510.
74 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
However, it was left to the FSA itself to provide the most extensive
justification for its own existence. While the FSA was still under
construction, it published a paper written by one of its own officials, Clive
Briault, who set out to defend the single regulator concept.53 He did so by
first invoking the “blurring of boundaries” argument:
52
H.M. STATIONARY OFFICE, FIN. SVCS. & MKTS. BILL: A CONSULTATION
DOCUMENT, pt. 1 (1998).
53
See Briault, supra note 14.
54
Id. at 13-14.
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 75
55
Id. at 14.
56
See id.
57
See id.
58
Id. at 12-13.
59
Briault, supra, note 14, at 13.
60
TRIPARTITE GROUP OF BANK SEC. & INS. REG., THE SUPERVISION OF FIN.
CONGLOMERATES at i (1995). Subsequently the Tripartite Group was renamed the
Joint Forum.
61
Id. at i-ii.
62
See GEORGE ALEXANDER WALKER, INT’L BANKING REGULATION: LAW,
POLICY AND PRACTICE 258 (Kluwer Law Int’l) (2001).
76 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
63
Schooner & Taylor, supra note 2.
64
Briault, supra note 14, at 15.
65
Briault, supra note 14, at 13.
66
Id.
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 77
system, several different regulators had needed to build their own specialist
model review teams, but individuals with the requisite skills were in high
demand which made it difficult for regulatory agencies to recruit them in
sufficient numbers.67 By centralizing the available resources, a single
regulator seemed to offer a way out of this impasse. Similarly, it was also
argued that the creation of a single support infrastructure (e.g. IT system)
would lead to significant cost savings as the duplication and overlap
resulting from the nine pre-existing regulators was eliminated. The
argument that a single regulator would be more cost effective was vital in
selling the concept to the financial industry. It was therefore not surprising
that Briault made much of this argument:
67
See Taylor, supra note 11, at 6.
68
Briault, supra note 14, at 18.
78 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
case constructed for the single financial regulator. The difficulty was that
exactly these same arguments had been made in favor of an alternative
regulatory structure – the so-called Twin Peaks model. It was therefore
also necessary for the defenders of the single regulator to explain why this
structure would be superior to the Twin Peaks alternative.
69
See Jill Treanor, Regulators Back Taylor’s Twin Peaks Theory, THE INDEP.,
Oct. 29, 1996, available at http://www.independent.co.uk/news/business/
regulators-back-taylors-twinpeaks-theory-1360780.html.
70
Taylor, supra note 11, at 1.
71
Id.
72
Id.
73
See id.
74
Id. at 4. However, the earliest occurrence of this argument is to be found in
a working paper published the year before Twin Peaks. See Claudio E.V. Borrio &
Renata Filosa, The Changing Borders of Banking: Trends and Implications, 3, 16
(Bank for Int’l Settlements, Working Paper No. 23, 1994), available at
http://www.bis.org/publ/ work23.pdf?noframes=1.
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 79
The case for Twin Peaks also invoked the economies of scale that would
result from (the admittedly more limited) regulatory consolidation that it
also involved. Thus, because the arguments for a single regulator and for
Twin Peaks were almost identical, it was necessary for the FSA’s defenders
to show that theirs was the superior solution. The crux of the argument
concerned the separation of prudential and conduct of business regulation
that was the main feature of the Twin Peaks model; the defenders of a
single regulator argued that the separation was not so clear cut as the Twin
Peaks model presupposed.75
The first strand of this argument was to contest the claim, central to
the Twin Peaks analysis, that there were two relatively, clearly
distinguishable regulatory objectives – financial stability on the one hand
and consumer protection on the other. This case for treating these two
objectives as interlinked is well summarized by Davies and Green:
Closely related to this was the claim further claim that, in practice,
prudential and conduct of business (sales practice) regulation required
examination of very similar issues, and therefore that there would be
significant overlap between the Twin Peaks agencies.77 Briault put the
point with characteristic clarity:
75
See Briault, supra note 14, at 25.
76
HOWARD DAVIES & DAVID GREEN, GLOBAL FIN. REGULATION: THE
ESSENTIAL GUIDE 192 (2008).
77
Briault, supra note 14, at 25.
80 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
78
Id.
79
H.M. TREASURY, REFORMING FINANCIAL MARKETS, 2009, Cm. 7667, at 56.
80
See FIN. SERV. AUTH., THE TURNER REVIEW: A REGULATORY RESPONSE
TO THE GLOBAL BANKING CRISIS 87 (2009), available at
http://www.fsa.gov.uk/pubs/ other/ turner_review.pdf.
81
Id.
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 81
referred in its final report to the “widely held perception that, in recent
years, the FSA has emphasized conduct-of-business supervision at the
expense of prudential supervision.”82
This situation was especially apparent in the FSA’s supervision of
the mortgage bank Northern Rock which was the first British casualty of
the crisis.83 The bank had received numerous contacts from the FSA
concerning a consumer protection initiative (“treating customers fairly”),
but supervision of capital and liquidity had been deficient and the bank had
been placed in a category that subjected it to one major prudential meeting
once every three years. The FSA’s own report on Northern Rock stated
that “some of the fundamentals of work on assessing risks in firms (notably
some of the core elements related to prudential supervision, such as
liquidity) have been squeezed out.”84
The House of Lords Committee thought it could identify the reason
why the FSA had failed to give sufficient attention to prudential regulation:
In other words, the argument that there were synergies between prudential
and conduct of business regulation overlooked the distinct possibility that
82
SELECT COMMITTEE ON ECONOMIC AFFAIRS, BANKING SUPERVISION AND
REGULATION, 2008-09, H.L. 101-I, at 33.
83
FINANCIAL SERVICES AUTHORITY, THE SUPERVISION OF NORTHERN ROCK:
A LESSONS LEARNED REVIEW ¶¶ 8, 27 (2008), available at http://www.fsa.gov.uk/
pubs/other/ nr_report.pdf.
84
Id. at ¶ 36.
85
SELECT COMMITTEE ON ECONOMIC AFFAIRS, BANKING SUPERVISION AND
REGULATION, 2008-09, H.L. 101-I, at 33.
82 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
One dimension of the Twin Peaks structure that had been actively
debated before the decision to create the FSA was the role of the central
bank. In a number of speeches and articles, the Bank of England’s senior
management defended the Bank’s role as a bank regulator against the
proposed Twin Peaks structure.88 The central bank, it was argued, needed
to be concerned with the financial condition of the banking system, as this
was the conduit through which its monetary policy was transmitted to the
wider economy. As Governor Eddie George argued in a speech given in
1994, before the Twin Peaks debate began, the soundness of banks and the
central bank’s ability to conduct monetary policy were intimately related:
86
See id.
87
Taylor, supra note 11, at 15.
88
Howard Davies, Financial Regulation: Why, How and By Whom, in BANK
OF ENG. Q’LY BULL. 107, 111 (1997).
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 83
89
E. A. J. George, Governor, Bank of England, The Bank of England –
Objectives and Activities, The Capital Market Research Institute, Frankfurt,
Germany (Dec. 5, 1994).
90
Shortly afterwards he was appointed the first Chairman and Chief
Executive of the FSA. His views on the specialness of banks underwent a
subsequent change.
84 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
with those who wish to make the case for disturbing that
relationship.91
The main “synergy” that arose from retaining banking supervision within
the central bank was with the Bank’s role as lender of last resort (LoLR). It
was argued that the information acquired in the capacity of the bank
supervisor was essential to the central bank performing the lender of last
resort function, and that therefore the best arrangement was for LoLR and
banking supervision to be located in the same institution. Following the
Northern Rock experience, a number of commentators have reached the
conclusion that this argument was correct. As Professor Willem Buiter
argued in evidence to the House of Commons Treasury Select Committee:
91
DAVIES, supra note 88, at 110.
92
Id.
93
C. A. E. Goodhart & D. Schoenmaker, The Institutional Separation
Between Supervisory and Monetary Agencies, in THE CENTRAL BANK AND THE
FINANCIAL SYSTEM 341 (1995)..
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 85
103
Id. at 12.
104
Id. at 14.
105
Id.
106
Id. at 13-14.
107
Taylor, supra note 11, at 13.
108
Briault, supra note 14, at 33.
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 87
the framework for both information exchange and for crisis management.109
These are referred to under the MoU as the “Tripartite Authorities” and the
Bank of England’s responsibilities are summarised as contributing “to the
maintenance of the stability of the financial system as a whole.”110 The
FSA has the responsibility of authorising and supervising individual
banks.111 HM Treasury has responsibility for the institutional structure of
the financial regulatory system, and the legislation behind it.112 In a crisis,
the Financial Services Authority would, according to the Memorandum of
Understanding, be responsible for monitoring “the health of institutions
that fall within its regulatory remit” and for ensuring, “as far as is
appropriate in the circumstances, continuing compliance with regulatory
standards.”113 However, the Bank of England would remain in charge of
“official financial operations … in order to limit the risk of problems in or
affecting particular institutions spreading to other parts of the financial
system”.114
The MoU also established a Joint Crisis Management Committee,
chaired by the Chancellor, for dealing with what the MoU referred to
generically as “support operations.”115 It did not, however, clearly
distinguish between those operations that relate to emergency liquidity
assistance and those that would involve solvency support.116 In both cases
the Treasury sat at the apex of a pyramid with both the Bank and FSA in
subordinate roles.117 This contrasts with the practice of most other
countries in crisis management, which is to ensure that as long as the issue
remains one of liquidity the central bank will be in the lead.118 It alone has
(or should have) the information and the ability to react sufficiently
109
GORDON BROWN ET AL., MEMORANDUM OF UNDERSTANDING BETWEEN
H.M. TREASURY, THE BANK OF ENGLAND AND THE FINANCIAL SERVICES
AUTHORITY 4-5 (2009), available at http://www.bankofengland.co.uk/
financialstability/mou.pdf [hereinafter MoU].
110
Id. ¶ 2.
111
Id. ¶ 3(i).
112
Id. ¶ 4(i).
113
Id. ¶ 17(iii).
114
Id. ¶ 2(iv).
115
GORDON BROWN ET AL., supra note 109, at ¶ 14.
116
Id. ¶ 17(iii).
117
Id. at ¶ 4, 10, 13.
118
Dong He, “Emergency Liquidity Support Facilities”, Appendix in
CHARLES ENOCH et al (eds) BUILDING STRONG BANKS THROUGH
SURVEILLANCE AND RESOLUTION (IMF 2002), p.134
88 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
The U.K. was not the first country to establish a unified regulatory
agency outside the central bank: that honor belongs to the Scandinavian
countries, with Norway (1986) as the pioneer followed by Denmark (1988)
and Sweden (1991).123 In these countries an important consideration was
119
Id. at ¶ 2, 4.
120
Id. at ¶ 6.
121
GORDON BROWN ET AL., supra note 109, at ¶ 14.
122
HOUSE OF COMMONS TREASURY COMMITTEE, THE RUN ON THE ROCK,
2007-08, H.C. 56-1, at 107.
123
Taylor & Fleming, supra note 16, at 6-7.
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 89
124
Id. at 25.
125
See id.
126
Id. at 17.
127
Id. at 31.
90 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
The function that receives the greatest emphasis will be that having
the greatest political saliency: this means that in normal times, when bank
failures are rare, consumer protection regulation is likely to be the main
focus of agency attention. Although the FSA has now increased the
resources it devotes to prudential regulation,129 the above analysis suggests
that this is likely to be a relatively short term development, remaining in
place only as long as political attention is focused on the fall-out from the
crisis.
128
SELECT COMMITTEE ON ECONOMIC AFFAIRS, BANKING SUPERVISION AND
REGULATION, 2008-09, H.L. 101-I, at 33.
129
Id. at 32.
130
Id. at 30, 32, 52-53.
131
Id. at 31-32.
132
Id. at 30-31.
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 91
133
Jacomb, supra note 49, at 3-4.
92 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
134
BROWN, supra note 109, at ¶ 8.
135
Id. at ¶ 6.
136
See Schooner & Taylor, supra note 2, at 629-32.
137
Id. at 614-15.
138
INSTITUTE FOR MONETARY AND ECONOMIC STUDIES, FUNCTIONS AND
OPERATIONS OF THE BANK OF JAPAN 80 (2004), available at
www.boj.or.jp/en/type/exp/about/data/ foboj01.pdf
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 93
139
Peter Hayward “The Financial Sector – The Responsibilities of Public
Agencies” in CHARLES ENOCH et al, supra note 118.
140
George Osborne, Foreword, in FROM CRISIS TO CONFIDENCE: PLAN FOR
SOUND BANKING (2009).
94 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
141
See Enhancing Investor Protection and the Regulation Of Securities
Markets: Hearing Before S. Comm. on Banking, Housing and Urban Affairs, 11th
Cong. 36-39 (2009) (testimony of Mr. John Coffee, Professor, Columbia Law
School).
142
See Abrams & Taylor, supra note 9, at 23-24.
2009] ROAD FROM “TWIN PEAKS” 95
143
See C. A. E. GOODHART ET AL., FINANCIAL REGULATION: HOW, WHO AND
WHERE NOW? (1998).
96 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
WHITHER THE DUTY OF GOOD FAITH IN
UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS
John Lowry∗
***
This article explores the current state of the law in the United Kingdom
concerning the duty of good faith in insurance contracts. Recent case law
provides that the duty of disclosure by insureds is constantly being refined.
It argues that due to the current fragmentation of the law, future reform
should be focused on creating a consistent regime for insurance contracts.
Such regime should be flexible enough to encompass both consumer and
commercial insurance, while demonstrating certain and clear objectives.
The first part examines the duty of disclosure by an insured as formulated
by Lord Mansfield CJ. The second part analyzes the case law that followed
Carter v. Bohem, which developed the notion of good faith and expanded it
into a duty of utmost good faith. Third, the discomfort of the UK courts
and UK law reform agencies over the severity of the insured’s duty along
with the injustices that result when insurers avoid a policy for non-
disclosure is explored. Fourth, recent judicial opinions that attempt to
alleviate the position of the insured are assessed. The fifth and concluding
part of this article briefly examines the 2009 [UK] Consumer Insurance
(Disclosure and Representations) Bill published by the English and
Scottish Law Commissions in December 2009. It constructs an alternative
model which takes account of recent developments in Australian law. It is
argued that the focus should be on balancing the economic costs of reform
with the benefits of a more balanced regime which does not create a
distinction between consumer and business insureds.
***
∗
Professor of Law and Vice Dean of the Faculty of Laws, UCL. I owe a debt
of gratitude to the anonymous referees for their helpful comments. Liability for
any errors, however, is mine alone. I would also like to thank the editors of the
Journal for affording me the opportunity to amend the article immediately prior to
its publication so as to include reference to UK reform proposals published in
December 2009.
98 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
discover for himself or herself the circumstances that may impact upon the
risk. For example, one case would be where the insured seeks to take out a
life policy having received a death threat. Or a vessel the underwriter is
asked to insure may be on the high seas and, therefore, not available for
inspection.6 In such circumstances there can be no quarrel with the fairness
of the insured’s duty of good faith. But in the case law subsequent to
Carter v. Boehm, the boundaries of the insured’s duty were expanded
beyond, it is suggested, what Lord Mansfield originally envisaged. For
example, it has been held that the failure of an insured to disclose criminal
convictions and his precarious financial position when applying for fire
insurance will enable the insurer to avoid the policy following a fire caused
by an electrical fault.7
In practical terms, the issue which pervades the duty of good faith
can be reduced to the following question: how can the ordinary insured,
whether acting in a private or commercial capacity, untutored in the
niceties of insurance law, be expected to know what particular
circumstances are material and would, therefore, influence the prudent
underwriter?8 The sheer breadth of the insured’s duty together with the all-
or-nothing consequence of avoidance, therefore, rightly gives rise to
legitimate concern. In a series of recent cases, decided over the last ten
years or so, the English courts have been steadily refining the disclosure
duty while, at the same time, laying considerable emphasis on the mutuality
of the requirement of good faith by giving content to that borne by insurers.
This process is a rebalancing exercise.9 As such, it involves a tacit
6
See NEW ZEALAND LAW COMMISSION, No. 46: SOME INS. LAW PROBLEMS 2
(1998).
7
Quinby Enter. Ltd. v. Gen. Accident Ltd. [1995] 1 N.Z.L.R. 736. But cf.
Waller L.J.’s reasoning in North Star Shipping Ltd. v. Sphere Drake Ins. plc [2006]
EWCA (Civ) 378; see also Doheny v. New India Assurance Co. [2004] EWCA
Civ. 1705; O’Kane v. Jones [2003] EWHC 3470 (Comm.); James v. CGU Ins. plc,
[2002] Lloyd’s Rep. I.R. 206; March Cabaret Club & Casino Ltd. v. London
Assurance, [1975] 1 Lloyd’s Rep. 169.
8
See Lord Mansfield’s formulation of the duty and the Marine Insurance Act,
1906, 6 Edw. 7, c.41, § 18.
9
Indeed, this is in line with various calls for reform which have long gone
unheeded by the legislature. See infra note 15. That said, the UK Financial
Ombudsman Service (FOS) has sought to mitigate the harshness of the duty, at
least in so far as it applies to consumer insureds and small businesses with a group
annual turnover of less than £1 million. For commercial insureds, however, who
100 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
unraveling of case law spanning over a century in which the courts had
adopted an unequivocal stance in permitting avoidance for non-disclosure
across the range of insurance, both consumer and commercial, without
regard to notions of fairness, proportionality, or whether there was actual
inducement.10 Admittedly the anxiety of modern judges has generally been
directed towards relieving the position of the consumer or private insured,
but the limits of this shift of emphasis are not entirely clear. It begs the
question whether commercial insurance is also being targeted. Such doubt
carries the danger of undermining the very certainty that should represent
the cornerstone of commercial law in this respect and the economic
implications are potentially significant.
Taken in the round, it is possible to distill several strands of
reasoning from the modern case law. First, focusing solely upon the
content of the insured’s pre-contractual duty of disclosure, the courts have
sought to limit its scope by refining the conditions, most notably the
requirement of inducement, that must be met before the insurer may
justifiably avoid the policy for non-disclosure. Further, in relation to
avoidance, it is noteworthy that in recent times some judges have had
recourse to notions of good faith, conscience, and fairness when assessing
whether insurers may exercise the remedy. But judicial thinking in this
respect is not entirely consistent for it has been suggested that, as with the
remedy of rescission for misrepresentation, the rights of insurers are
unfettered by such considerations.11 Another strand of reasoning that has
emerged has been directed towards the contours of waiver. An insurer has
every opportunity to ask specific questions of the applicant for insurance in
the proposal form. Typically, those questions will be directed towards
claims history or health where the application relates to life or sickness
insurance. Nonetheless, even where such questions are raised, the insured
is not relieved from his or her duty to volunteer any further material
circumstances that fall outside the scope of them. Any defense that an
insured might seek to raise based on waiver is, in the orthodox view,
doomed to failure.12 However, this has been challenged recently in a
are outwith the FOS jurisdiction, it has been left to the courts to alleviate their
position.
10
See, e.g., the judgments in Lambert v. Co-operative Ins. Soc’y, [1975] 2
Lloyd’s Rep. 485. See also infra notes 82-91.
11
See the judgment of Mance L.J. in Brotherton v. Aseguradora Colseguros
S.A. [2003] EWCA Civ. 705. See infra note 197.
12
See, e.g., Roselodge, Ltd. v. Castle, [1966] 2 Lloyd’s Rep. 113, 132.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 101
13
See WISE Ltd. v. Grupo Nacional Provincial S.A. [2004] EWCA Civ. 962.
See infra note 168-87.
14
This is not a novel development but reflects the view expressed by Lord
Mansfield C.J. in Carter v. Boehm, (1766) 97 Eng. Rep. 1162. However, by the
mid-nineteenth century, the point seems have faded from judicial thinking when
addressing the scope of the disclosure duty.
15
See, e.g., LAW REFORM COMMITTEE, CONDITIONS AND EXCEPTIONS IN
INSURANCE POLICIES, 1957, Cmnd. 62; THE LAW COMMISSION, INSURANCE LAW –
NON-DISCLOSURE AND BREACH OF WARRANTY, 1980, Cmnd. 8064; JOHN BIRDS,
NAT’L CONSUMER COUNCIL, INSURANCE LAW REFORM: THE CONSUMER CASE FOR
A REVIEW OF INSURANCE LAW (1997). Although the UK Department of Trade and
Industry (now renamed the Department for Business, Innovation and Skills
(DBIS)) issued a draft Insurance Bill following the Law Commission’s report in
1980, nothing came of it, the government of the day being satisfied that the
industry’s response via the Association of British Insurers’ Statement of Practice
struck the appropriate balance for the consumer-insured.
16
[1995] 1 A.C. 501 (H.L.).
102 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
proposed that might serve to inform the English and Scottish Law
Commissions’ current re-examinations of insurance law that identifies non-
disclosure as a key issue.17 It will be seen that the current state of the law is
fragmented and complicated and that future reform should be directed
towards constructing a coherent regime for insurance contracts that meets
the objectives of certainty and clarity, while being sufficiently flexible to
encompass both consumer and commercial insurance.
A. CARTER V. BOEHM
17
The English and Scottish Law Commissions are statutory independent
bodies created by the [UK] Law Commissions Act 1965 c. 22, to keep the law
under review and to recommend reform where it is needed. The insurance contract
law reform project was announced on 14 October 2005, the first “issues paper” on
misrepresentation and non-disclosure was published at the end of September 2006.
See The Law Commission, Insurance Contract Law, Misrepresentation and Non-
Disclosure (Sept. 2006), available at http://www.lawcom.gov.uk/docs/insurance_
contact_law_issues_paper_1. See infra notes 305-11. On December 15 2009 the
Law Commissions published their joint report and draft Bill to reform the law on
what a consumer-insured must disclose to the insurers prior to the conclusion of
the policy; see CONSUMER INSURANCE LAW: PRE-CONTRACT DISCLOSURE AND
REPRESENTATION, 2009, Cm 7758, discussed infra note 307 et seq..
18
Carter, 97 Eng. Rep. at 1163. Park notes that Carter is a seminal case
(“. . . . from it may be collected all the general principles which the doctrine of
concealments, in matters of insurance, is founded, as well as all the exceptions. . . .
”). JAMES ALLAN PARK, A SYSTEM OF THE LAW OF MARINE INSURANCES 193
(Thomas & Andrews 1800) (1787).
19
Carter, 97 Eng. Rep. at 1163.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 103
20
Id. at 1162-63.
21
Id. at 1163.
22
Carter, 97 Eng. Rep. at 1164.
104 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
B. THE RATIONALE
23
This is a narrower view than that expressed over a century later by
Channell J in Re Yager & Guardian Assurance Co., [1912] 108 L.T. 38 (K.B.), to
the effect that the rationale underlying the disclosure duty is not the need to
prevent harm to the insurer as such, but the need for a true and fair agreement
whereby risk is transferred. Id. at 44-45.
24
Carter, 97 Eng. Rep. at 1163.
25
Id. at 1167.
26
Id.
27
Id.
28
Id. at 1169.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 105
insureds, and being mutual the problem of unfairness was shared between
the parties.29
Lord Mansfield also placed emphasis on the need for insurers to
demonstrate reliance. He explained that the underwriter “proceeds upon
confidence that [the insured] does not keep back any circumstance in his
knowledge, to mislead the under-writer into a belief that the circumstance
does not exist, and to induce him to estimate the risque, as if it did not
exist.”30 Herein we see the assimilation of non-disclosure with
misrepresentation. The good faith duty converts non-disclosure into
misrepresentation because an insured who fails to disclose a material fact is
effectively misrepresenting the true state of affairs. Lord Mansfield’s
choice of language is critical: it traverses the two vitiating factors and
reliance and inducement lies at the heart of both. For misrepresentation,
the consequence is therefore the same as with pure non-disclosure, namely
avoidance of the contract ab initio.31
Both in Carter v. Boehm, and in subsequent cases, Lord Mansfield
sought to limit the scope of the insured’s duty by, for example, stressing the
need for underwriters to be proactive in ascertaining facts material to the
29
Indeed, Lord Mansfield was scathing in his condemnation of the
underwriter’s defense:
Id. at 1169.
30
Carter, 97 Eng. Rep. at 1164.
31
The insurers remedy in this respect is codified by the Marine Insurance Act,
1906, 6 Edw. 7, c. 41, § 20 (Eng.).
106 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
32
99 Eng. Rep. 326, 326-27.
33
Id. at 326.
34
Id.
35
Id.
36
Id. at 327.
37
Mayne v. Walter, (1782) 99 Eng. Rep. 548, 548-49. PARK, supra note 18,
at 196.
38
PARK, supra note 18, at 196.
39
Id.
40
See R. A. Hasson, The Doctrine of Uberrima Fides in Insurance Law - A
Critical Evaluation, 32 M.L.R. 615, 618 (1969).
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 107
41
Friere v. Woodhouse, (1817) 171 Eng. Rep. 345, 345. See also Gandy v.
The Adelaide Marine Ins. Co., 6 Eng. Rep. 746, 757 (Q.B.).
42
Friere, 171 Eng. Rep. at 345.
43
It has long been settled that the Marine Insurance Act, 1906, 6 Edw. 7, c.
41, §§ 17-18 (Eng.) are of general application in insurance law. See, e.g., P.C.W.
Syndicates v. P.C.W. Reinsurers, (1996) 1 W.L.R. 1136, 1140 (A.C.); Australia
and New Zealand Bank, Ltd. v. Colonial and Eagle Wharves Ltd., (1960) 2
Lloyd’s L. Rep. 241, 251 (Q.B.D ); Cantiere Meccanico Brindisino v. Janson,
(1912) 3 K.B. 452, 467. More recent cases have also proceeded on the assumption
that the provisions apply to all types of insurance. See Pan Atlantic Ins. Co. Ltd. v.
Pine Top Ins. Co. Ltd., [1994] 1 A.C. 501, 518 (H.L.); Lambert v. Co-operative
Ins. Soc’y, (1975) 2 Lloyd’s Rep 485, 487.
44
Marine Insurance Act, 1906, 6 Edw. 7, c. 41, § 17 (emphasis supplied).
45
Friere v. Woodhouse, (1817) 171 Eng. Rep. 345; Mayne v. Walter, (1782)
99 Eng. Rep. 548; Noble v. Kennoway, (1780) 99 Eng. Rep. 326. See also Lord
Ellenborough’s closely reasoned judgment delivered in Haywood v. Rodgers,
(1804) 4 East 590.
46
See note 45 infra for conflicting case law.
108 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
47
See Hasson, supra note 40.
48
Durant v. Durant, I Haggard Eccl. Rep. 733.
49
See M.A. Millner, Fraudulent Non-disclosure 74 S.A.L.J. 177, 188 (1957).
50
Mut. and Fed. Ins. Co Ltd. v. Oudtshoorn Mun. 1985 (1) SA 419 (AD).
51
Id. at 433F.
52
See A. D. M. FORTE, Good Faith and Utmost Good Faith in A.D. M. Forte
(ed), GOOD FAITH IN CONTRACT AND PROPERTY LAW, (Hart Publishing 1999).
Joubert J.A. cites Dalglish v. Jarvis, (1850) 2 Mac. & Gord. R. 231, as the decision
in which the term uberrimae fides is first used in Mut. and Fed. Ins., (1) SA at
431I.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 109
Mansfield’s views expressed over a century earlier.53 The claimant had not
informed the insurer that the insured vessel, the Georgia, had been a
Confederate cruiser.54 The Georgia was well known to the British public,
and when the ship came to Liverpool for breaking she attracted
considerable interest in both the press and in the House of Commons.55
The defendant underwriter admitted he had known of the ship’s history but
that at the time of underwriting it was not present in his mind.56 The jury
found that the underwriter was ignorant of the vessel’s notoriety at that
particular time, although they did go on to express the view that when the
risk was presented, he did have the means available for identifying the
ship.57 The court held that the claimant was in breach of his duty of
disclosure.58 Curiously, the judges in the case went to considerable lengths
to explain that they were merely applying a long established principle.
Lord Cockburn CJ stated that a proposer of insurance “is bound to
communicate to the insurer all matters which will enable him to determine
the extent of the risk against which he undertakes to guarantee the
assured.”59 Shee J., while admitting that the underwriter might through his
own investigations have discovered the material fact about the Georgia’s
history, concluded, however, that he was under no duty to make such
enquiries.60 This fails to sit with Lord Mansfield’s notion of an insurer’s
constructive knowledge - a critical factor in his finding in Carter v. Boehm.
It also fails to sit with Friere v. Woodhouse, in which it will be recalled, the
court, applying Lord Mansfield’s formulation of the duty, had no hesitation
in finding that underwriters had a pro-active role to play during the
disclosure process.61 Nonetheless, towards the close of the nineteenth
century, the consensus of judicial opinion was such that determining if the
duty of disclosure has been discharged requires something more than
merely exacting a duty of honesty from the insured. This came to the fore
in Life Association of Scotland v. Foster, in which the term “utmost good
faith” is adopted by Lord President Inglis: “Contracts of Insurance are in
53
Bates v. Hewitt, (1867) 2 L.R.Q.B. 595; 1867 WL 9866.
54
Id. at 604.
55
Id. at 595.
56
Id. at 604.
57
Id.
58
Id. at 599.
59
Bates, 2 L.R.Q.B. at 604-05.
60
Id. at 611.
61
Friere v. Woodhouse, (1817) 171 Eng. Rep. 345. See also Noble v.
Kennoway, (1780) 99 Eng. Rep. 326.
110 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
this, among other particulars, exceptional, in that they require on both sides
uberrima fides. Hence, without fraudulent intent, and even bona fides, the
insured may fail in the duty of disclosure.”62
This decision is followed soon after by Ionides v. Pender, in which
Blackburn J. was moved to assimilate the prevailing view into the so-called
“prudent insurer” test.63 While the judge accepted that “it would be too
much to put on the assured the duty of disclosing everything which might
influence the mind of an underwriter,” he nevertheless conceded that “a
concealment of a material fact, though made without any fraudulent
intention, vitiates the policy.”64 Blackburn J. concluded by stating that “all
should be disclosed which would affect the judgment of a rational
underwriter governing himself by the principles and calculations on which
underwriters do in practice act.”65
62
(1873) 11 M. 351, 359. It might be the case that this generation of judges
was perhaps placing too much reliance on Park’s Law of Marine Insurance
published in 1787, rather than tracing Lord Mansfield’s reasoning first hand. For
example, chapter 10 of Park’s treatise states that “the learned judges of our courts
of law, feeling that the very essence of insurance consists in a rigid attention to the
purest good faith, and the strictest integrity, have constantly held that it is vacated
and annulled by any the least shadow of fraud or undue concealment.” PARK,
supra note 18, at 174 (emphasis supplied).
63
(1874) 9 L.R.Q.B. 531. This was incorporated by Chalmers into § 18(2) of
the Marine Insurance Act, 1906, 6 Edw. 7, c.41 (Eng.), which provides, “[e]very
circumstance is material which would influence the judgment of a prudent insurer
in fixing the premium, or determining whether he will take the risk.”
64
Ionides, 9 L.R.Q.B. at 537, 539.
65
Id. at 539. A further opportunity to put forward his view on the scope of
the duty of disclosure was taken by him, now Lord Blackburn, in Brownlie v.
Campbell, (1880) 5 App. Cas. 925, in which he noted:
Id. at 954. Material facts are typically categorised as either those relating to
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 111
physical hazard or those relating to moral hazard. See JOHN LOWRY & PHILIP
RAWLINGS, INSURANCE LAW: DOCTRINES AND PRINCIPLES 93-99 (2d ed. 2005).
66
Marine Insurance Act, 1906, 6 Edw. 7, c. 41, § 18 (Eng.).
67
[1908] 2 K.B. 863.
68
See PETER MACDONALD EGGERS ET AL., GOOD FAITH AND INSURANCE
CONTRACTS ¶ 3.10 (2004).
69
Joel, [1908] 2 K.B. at 883-84 (emphasis added). This passage occurs in a
reserved judgment, and there is no indication that Vaughan Williams or Buckley
112 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
Similarly, in Becker v. Marshall, Salter J., also applying the test laid down
by Fletcher Moulton L.J., held on an issue of concealment as to foreign
origin and change of name, that while the claimant:
Such was the momentum of this approach that the 2nd (Hailsham) edition
of the Laws of England, Volume 18, prepared by Scott L.J., stated that:
Id. at 586(3). This passage is repeated in the 3rd (Simonds) ed., vol. 22,
360.
74
[1966] 2 Lloyd’s List L.R. 113, 131-32 (QBD).
75
Id. at 113.
76
Id.
114 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
who had led a totally blameless life.77 This did not convince McNair J.
who held that the 1946 conviction was not a material fact, having “no
direct relation to trading as a diamond merchant.”78 Having examined the
authorities, with particular emphasis being given to Horne v. Poland, the
judge concluded:
As conceded by Fletcher Moulton L.J., the duty does not require the
insured to disclose that of which he or she is ignorant, unless the insured
ought to have known of such circumstances in the ordinary course of
business.80 But, nevertheless, from the insured’s perspective the disclosure
duty laid down by the Marine Insurance Act of 1906, as explained by the
subsequent case law, is particularly harsh and, it is suggested, represents an
overly expanded view of Lord Mansfield’s original formulation which was
premised upon the notion of “concealment.” From a contemporary
standpoint, it is hardly surprising that by the second half of the twentieth
century both the courts and the law reform bodies were questioning
whether such a strict approach was necessarily appropriate for all classes of
insurance.
77
Id. at 132.
78
Id.
79
Id. at 131.
80
See also Lambert v. Co-operative Ins. Soc’y Ltd., [1975] 2 Lloyd’s Rep.
485, 490 (A.C.). See infra notes 63-66. The private insured will not, of course, be
deemed to possess constructive knowledge. See Economides v. Commercial
Union Assurance Co. plc, [1998] Q.B. 587, 601-03 (Simon Brown, L.J.).
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 115
81
[1970] 1 Q.B. 311, 319.
82
[1975] 2 Lloyd’s Rep. 485, 491-93 (A.C.).
83
Id. at 492-93.
84
Id. at 486.
85
Id.
86
Id.
87
Id.
88
Lambert, [1975] 2 Lloyd’s Rep. at 491.
89
LAW REFORM COMMITTEE, CONDITIONS AND EXCEPTIONS IN INSURANCE
POLICIES, supra note 15.
116 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
90
Lambert, [1975] 2 Lloyd’s Rep. at 489. MacKenna J. was particularly
influenced by the opinion of the Privy Council in Mutual Life Insurance Co. of
New York v. Ontario Metal Products Co. Ltd., [1925] A.C. 344, 351-52, to the
effect that the test, as laid down in the Marine Insurance Act, 1906, 6 Edw. 7, c.
41, § 18, is whether the non-disclosed fact would have influenced a reasonable
insurer to decline the risk or to have stipulated for a higher premium.
91
Lambert, [1975] 2 Lloyd’s Rep. at 491.
92
[1978] 2 Lloyd’s Rep. 440, 460 (Q.B.D.).
93
Id.
94
Id.
95
[2002] EWHC 203.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 117
But, having held that the allegation was material, Colman J. nevertheless
mitigated his finding by holding that for the insurers to persist at trial in
taking the point, in the face of evidence that pointed to the suggested facts
being totally false, would be contrary to their obligation of good faith.97 It
is noteworthy that recently, the Court of Appeal in North Star Shipping Ltd.
v. Sphere Drake Ins. plc expressed sympathy for Forbes J.’s views and
urged the insured to argue that allegations of dishonesty which were
unrelated to the risk were immaterial.98 Ultimately though, it felt
constrained by authority to reject the contention which Waller L.J. stated he
otherwise “might be tempted to follow.”99 However, on the issue of
whether the impecuniosity of the insured was a material fact, Waller L.J.
stated that, “the non-payment of premium is either material on its own or
not, and since it seems to go to the owner’s credit risk, and not to the risk
insured, I would have thought it was not material.”100 In so finding, Waller
L.J. admitted that he was placing a significant limitation on section 18(2) of
the 1906 Marine Insurance Act given that this was plainly a material fact
which went to the decision of a prudent underwriter whether or not to
underwrite the risk.101
With respect to the insurers right of avoidance, the judiciary has
also displayed considerable tenacity in its condemnation of the results
which necessarily flow from the exercise of the remedy. To take just one
recent example, in Kausar v. Eagle Star Ins. Co. Ltd., Staughton L.J.
stated:
96
Id. In North Star Shipping Ltd. v. Sphere Drake Insurance plc, [2005]
EWHC 665, Colman J. again took this view. See also Brotherton v. Aseguradora
Colseguros S.A. (No. 2) [2003] EWCA Civ. 705 (Mance, L.J.) (discussed infra
notes 105 and 132); The Dora, [1989] 1 Lloyd’s Rep. 69, 93-94 (Q.B.D.) (Phillips,
J.); March Cabaret Club & Casino Ltd. v. London Assurance, [1975] 1 Lloyd’s
Rep. 169, 175-77 (Q.B.D.). Cf. Norwich Union Ins. Ltd. v. Meisels [2006] EWHC
2811 (Q.B.) (taking a narrower view of materiality).
97
Strive Shipping Corp. [2002] EWHC 203. See infra note 193.
98
[2006] EWCA (Civ.) 378.
99
Id.
100
Id.
101
Id.
118 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
However, the weight of the case law and the force of the 1906 Marine
Insurance Act inevitably present considerable hurdles to judicial
intervention. Nevertheless, the subject of non-disclosure and the insurers’
remedy has not escaped the attention of law reform agencies.
102
[1997] C.L.C. 129, 132-33.
103
See THE LAW COMMISSION, supra note 15, § 1.1.
104
Id. § 1.2. In fact, the Directive did not materialise.
105
CODE DES ASSURANCES, art. L113-9.
106
See THE LAW COMMISSION, supra note 15, § 4.2.
107
Id. § 4.3.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 119
In a case where the non-disclosure is not due to fault, the insurer would
remain liable for any loss.108
The Law Commission concluded that proportionality was
unworkable in England and Wales.109 It stated that the principle gives no
guidance as to how the insured’s entitlement is to be computed if the
insurer would have either declined the risk, imposed additional terms on
the insured, narrowed the risk via exclusion clauses or imposed or
increased “an excess.”110 Further, the Commission found that
proportionality provides no solution where knowledge of the undisclosed
facts would have led the insurer to decline the risk altogether.111 Whatever
the merits of this strident dismissal, such hurdles have not prevented the
Ombudsman importing the principle into the range of his remedies.112 That
aside, the Law Commission did endorse the views expressed by way of
obiter in Lambert to the effect that the law should be changed.113 It found
that the insured’s duty of disclosure can give rise to grave injustice and
there was, notwithstanding the protestations of the insurance industry, “a
formidable case for reform.”114 In essence, the Commission recommended
a substantially revised duty of disclosure that, had it been implemented,
would have resulted in shifting the focus away from the “prudent insurer”
as the determinative test of materiality.115 It proposed a modified duty of
disclosure for both consumers and businesses whereby an insured would be
required to disclose those facts that a reasonable person in the position of
the applicant would disclose.116 However, an insured’s individual personal
characteristics would not be taken into account.117
Despite early optimism that legislative reform would follow the
Law Commission’s recommendations, this soon petered out. While there
was an initial flurry of activity by the DTI (now DBIS), the impetus for
108
Id.
109
Id.
110
Id.
111
Id. § 4.5-4.6.
112
The Ombudsman has adopted proportionality for cases of unintentional
non-disclosure and misrepresentation. See the Ombudsman Report for 1989, para
2.16-7) and the Annual Report for 1994, para 2.10. See infra text accompanying
note 121.
113
THE LAW COMMISSION, supra note 15, § 4.44.
114
See id. § 3.23.
115
Id. § 6.2.3.
116
Id. § 4.47
117
Id.
120 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
118
Paul Channon, Secretary of State, Written Answers (Commons) of 21
Feburary 1986, Insurance Contracts (Feb. 21, 1986) (transcript available at
http://hansard.millbanksystems.com/written_answers/1986/feb/21/insurance-
contracts). The Secretary of State said,
Term Statement remains in place. Long term insurance is governed by COB which
has no equivalent provision to ICOB 7.3.6.
119
See, e.g., INSURANCE OMBUDSMAN, ANNUAL REVIEW 1992/93, ¶¶ 6.48-
6.55 (1993). The Insurance Ombudsman is now part of the Financial Ombudsman
Service, regulated by Part XVI of the Financial Markets and Services Act, 2000, c.
8, §§ 225-34. The Association of British Insurers Statements will continue to
inform the approach of the Ombudsman. See Financial Ombudsman Service, Non-
Disclosure in Insurance Cases, OMBUDSMAN NEWS, May-June 2005, at 8,
available at http://www.financial-ombudsman.org.uk/publications/ombudsman-
news/46/46.pdf.
120
Financial Ombudsman Service, supra note 119, at 8.
121
See INSURANCE OMBUDSMAN, ANNUAL REVIEW 1988/89, ¶ 2.17. See also
Financial Ombudsman Service, Insurance Complaints Involving Non-Disclosure,
OMBUDSMAN NEWS, Apr. 2003, at 9, available at http://www.financial-
ombudsman.org.uk/publications/ombudsman-news/27/27.pdf. See also JOHN
LOWRY & PHILIP RAWLINGS, INSURANCE LAW: CASES AND MATERIALS 129-230
(Hart Publishing 2004). See also P.M. North, Law Reform: Processes and
Problems, 101 L.Q.R. 338, 349 (July 1985); John Birds, The Reform of Insurance
Law, 1982 J. BUS. L. 449, 450, 454 (Nov. 1982).
122 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
122
John Birds Insurance Law Reform: the Consumer Case for a Review of
Insurance Law, National Consumer Council, 1997.
123
Id.
124
British Insurance Law Association, Insurance Contract Law Reform (Sept.
2002).
125
See THE LAW COMMISSION, supra note 17.
126
[1995] 1 AC 501.
127
Pan Atl. Ins. Co. Ltd. v. Pine Top Ins. Co. Ltd., [1995] 1 A.C. 501, 505.
Both parties were insolvent by the time the case reached the appellate courts. Id.
However, it proceeded as a friendly action because of the perceived loss of
business being suffered by the UK, and London in particular, as a result of the
overly insurer-friendly approach being adopted in relation to non-disclosure. Id. It
was hoped that the House of Lords would redress the balance. Id.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 123
reinsurers had written excess of loss policies for three years.128 Their
defence to a claim arising out of losses suffered in the third year was based
on the inadvertent failure to disclose the extent of losses occurring in the
first two years.129 The issues were first, should materiality be measured by
reference to whether its ‘influence’ on the prudent insurer's judgment was
‘decisive’, or should some lesser degree of impact be sufficient?130 Second,
where there has been non-disclosure of a material fact, must it induce the
actual insurer to enter into the contract?131
With respect to the first issue Lord Mustill, with whom Lords Goff
and Slynn concurred, could see no good reason for departing from the
principle which had guided insurance law for more than 200 years.132 Lord
Mustill stated that disclosure was not limited to matters which would have
caused the prudent insurer to decline the risk or increase the premium but
rather the insured’s duty to disclose “all matters which would have been
taken into account by the underwriter when assessing the risk . . . which he
was consenting to assume.”133 On the question of statutory interpretation,
the majority view was that since Parliament had left the word “influence”
in section 18(2) unadorned by phrases such as “decisively” or
“conclusively,” it must bear its ordinary meaning.134 His Lordship stated
that “. . . this expression clearly denotes an effect on the thought processes
of the insurer in weighing up the risk, quite different from words which
might have been used but were not, such as ‘influencing the insurer to take
the risk.’”135 The majority decision therefore was to reject the “decisive
influence” test. The position remains that a circumstance is material and
must be disclosed even though the prudent insurer, had he known of the
fact, would have insured the risk on the same terms.136
128
Id. at 519.
129
Id. at 520.
130
Id. at 516-17
131
Id. at 517-18.
132
Id. at 536.
133
Pan Atl. Ins. Co. Ltd., [1995] 1 A.C. at 538. Lord Mustill thus rejected a
test based upon the decisive influence of the non-disclosed/misrepresented fact: “I
can see no room within [the principle] for a more lenient test expressed solely by
reference to the decisive effect which the circumstance would have on the mind of
the prudent underwriter.” Id. at 536.
134
Id. at 531.
135
Id. See also id. at 517 (speech of Lord Goff).
136
It is noteworthy that Lord Lloyd, in a powerful dissent, agreed with the
appellants' submission that there should be a twofold test under which the insurer
124 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
must show that a prudent insurer, if aware of the undisclosed fact, would either
have declined the risk or charged a higher premium and that the actual insurer
would have declined the risk or required a higher premium. Id. at 554. See also
John Birds & Norma J. Hird, Misrepresentation and Non-Disclosure in Insurance
Law - Identical Twins or Separate Issues, 59 M.L.R. 285, 285 (1996).
137
Pan Atl. Ins. Co., [1995] 1 A.C. at 551. In essence, the House of Lords
were injecting into the law on non-disclosure a requirement of causation analogous
to the “but for” test familiar to tort lawyers. See id. at 551 (Lord Mustill’s
reference to causative effect). In his reasoning, Lord Mustill gave prominence to
the decision of Kerr J. in Berger v. Pollock, [1973] 2 Lloyd’s Rep. 442, in which
the judge stated the principles in a way that suggested that the insurer could avoid
the policy only if he had in fact been influenced by the non-disclosure. Id. at 463.
138
Pan Atl. Ins. Co., [1995] 1 A.C. at 549.
139
Id. Where there is a material misrepresentation, there is a rebuttable
presumption of inducement. See Redgrave v. Hurd, (1881) 20 Ch.D. 1, 21; Smith
v. Chadwick, (1884) 9 App. Cas. 187, 196. Lord Mustill went on to add that, “As
a matter of common sense however even where the underwriter is shown to have
been careless in other respects the assured will have an uphill task in persuading
the court that the witholding or mistatement of circumstances satifying the test of
materiality has made no difference.” Pan Atl. Ins. Co., [1995] 1 A.C. at 551. See
also Svenska Handelsbanken v. Sun Alliance & London Ins. plc, [1996] 1 Lloyd’s
Rep. 519.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 125
140
Pan Atl. Ins. Co., [1995] 1 A.C. at 516-18.
141
Id. at 518.
142
Id. at 542, 571.
143
Id. at 562.
144
The only cases in which the presumption of inducement has been applied
are those involving market subscriptions when one member of the following
market has been unavailable to give evidence of his own state of mind. See, e.g.,
Talbot Underwriting Ltd. v. Nausch, Hogan & Murray Inc. [2006] EWCA Civ.
889, [2006] 2 Lloyd’s Rep. 195; Toomey v. Banco Vitalicio de Espana SA de
Seguros y Reasseguros [2003] EWHC 1102, [2004] Lloyd’s Rep. I.R. 354; St. Paul
Fire & Marine Co. (U.K.) Ltd. v. McConnell Dowell Constructors Ltd., [1996] 1
All E.R. 96, [1995] 2 Lloyd’s Rep. 116. See also Sirius Int’l Ins. Group Corp. v.
Oriental Assurance Corp., [1999] 1 All E.R. (Comm.) 699, [1999] Lloyd’s Rep.
I.R. 343; Ins. Corp. of the Channel Islands v. Royal Hotel Ltd., [1998] Lloyd’s
Rep. I.R. 151.
145
[1996] 1 Lloyd’s Rep. 430. See also Sirius Int’l Ins. Group Corp., [1999]
1 All E.R. (Comm.) 699, where, in relation to misrepresentation, Longmore J. also
stressed that it is for the insurer to prove inducement. The judge did, however,
recognize that the onus of proof is difficult to discharge. Id. In his Pat Saxton
Memorial Lecture, “An Insurance Contracts Act for a New Century”, delivered on
5 March 2001 to the British Insurance Law Association, Longmore J gave death as
an example of a good reason for failing to give evidence. Sir Andrew Longmore,
Pat Saxton Memorial Lecture at the British Insurance Law Association: An
126 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
A. REFINING INDUCEMENT
151
[2003] 1 W.L.R. 577.
128 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
disclosure been made.152 In this case, the insurer sought to avoid the motor
policy on the basis that it would have charged a higher premium had a
speeding conviction been disclosed.153 The insured had disclosed an earlier
fault accident, but failed to disclose before the present policy was
concluded that it had been reclassified as a no-fault accident.154 The
majority of the Court of Appeal held that, even if the conviction had been
disclosed, information would have come to light that the earlier accident
had not been the insured’s fault and this would have resulted in the
proposal being accepted at a normal rate of premium.155
Rix L.J., delivering the leading judgment,156 stated that the issue is
not what actually happened, but what would have happened had the
speeding conviction been declared. To prove inducement, the insurer,
Provident, would need to show that a higher premium would have
resulted.157 This it could not do because it was common ground that it
would not have increased the premium if the earlier accident had been no-
fault: “So the question resolves itself into this: if the conviction had been
mentioned, would the question of the status of the accident have been
discussed? It seems to me to be very likely that it would have been… .”158
It is noteworthy that Rix L.J. went on to express the view that he
could see no reason in principle why an insured should not be able to rely
on facts which would have been material in his favour had they been
disclosed.159 This, after all, is the case with insurers and the logic is,
therefore, compelling. Further, this reasoning marks a clear departure from
the view expressed by Mance L.J. in Brotherton v. Aseguradora
Colseguros SA,160 to the effect that an insured is not entitled to prove what
the true position was at the time the contract was concluded as a means of
proving that a particular fact was immaterial.161
152
[2003] EWCA Civ. 1834; [2004] Q.B. 601.
153
Id.
154
Id.
155
Id.
156
Id. Clarke L.J. agreeing and Pill L.J. dissenting.
157
Id.
158
Drake Ins. [2003] EWCA Civ. 1834.
159
Id.
160
[2003] EWCA Civ. 705. See also Malcolm Clarke, Non-disclosure and
Avoidance: Lies, Damned Lies, and ”Intelligence” [2004] L.M.C.L.Q. 1.
161
Brotherton [2003] EWCA Civ. 705 (rejecting the view of Colman J. in
Strive Shipping Corp. v. Hellenic Mut. War Risks Ass’n (Bermuda) Ltd., (The
Grecia Express), [2002] EWHC 203, 213, that “an insured is, if necessary, entitled
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 129
to litigate the issue of the truth or falsity of known but undisclosed intelligence, in
order to argue that, if it is shown to be incorrect, the insurer would be acting in bad
faith or unconscionably in avoiding.")
162
See R. Merkin, 16 Insurance Law Monthly (2004). See also Bonner v. Cox
Dedicated Corporate Member [2004] EWHC 2963 (Comm).
163
Carter v. Boehm, (1766) 97 Eng. Rep. 1162, 1164-65.
164
Id. at 1165. Lord Mansfield explained that the insured need not disclose
The House of Lords approved Slade L.J.’s reasoning in this respect. The
only remedy available to the insured where the insurer is in breach of duty
is avoidance ab initio. In practice, this affords little or no benefit to
insureds. An insurer’s breach will come to light when the loss has been
suffered – a time when an insured will want full recovery rather than a
return of the premium.
More recently, however, the issue has come to the fore in the
context of determining the insurer’s role during the disclosure process
Id. This particular element of the judgment was later codified, virtually verbatim,
in the Marine Insurance Act, 1906, 6 Edw. 7, c. 41, § 18(3) (Eng.).
165
(1780) 99 Eng. Rep. 326. See also Mayne v. Walter, (1782) 99 Eng. Rep.
548.
166
(1782) 99 Eng. Rep. 591. See also Drake Ins. plc v. Provident Ins. plc,
[2004] Q.B. 601 (reasoning of Rix L.J.).
167
[1990] 1 Q.B. 665 (A.C.) at 772. See also Aldrich v. Norwich Union Life
Ins. Co. Ltd., [1999] 2 All E.R. (Comm) 707.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 131
where the insured has raised the defence of waiver. Of significance in this
respect are the views expressed by the Court of Appeal in WISE Ltd. v.
Grupo Nacional Provincial SA.168 The issue arose in the context of
commercial insurance. The defendant, Mexican insurer GNP, appealed to
the Court of Appeal against a decision of Simon J. that the claimants-
reinsurers WISE were entitled to avoid a reinsurance contract on the basis
that the presence of high-value Rolex watches in the insured consignment
of goods was not disclosed.169 This occurred as a result of a translation
error in which the watches were described as clocks.170 It was held, by a
majority, that GNP was entitled to recover.171 Although it was
unanimously held that WISE had been induced by the presentation of the
risk, Rix and Peter Gibson L.J.J. held that the reinsurers had affirmed the
policy, notwithstanding the breach of the duty of disclosure, by giving
notice of its cancellation.172 Such notice was inconsistent with any claim to
avoid the policy ab initio.173 Both judges took the view that the trial judge
had overlooked a vital email which showed that WISE were unequivocal in
cancelling the policy.174
With respect to the issue of waiver, the parties agreed that the law
was accurately set out in MacGillivray on Insurance Law,175 which, citing
CTI v. Oceanus Mutual Underwriting Association (Bermuda) Ltd.,176 states:
168
[2004] EWCA Civ. 962.
169
Id.
170
Id.
171
Id.
172
Id.
173
Id.
174
WISE Ltd. [2004] EWCA Civ. 962. Longmore L.J. dissented on the basis
that the judge’s findings of fact could not be reversed. Id.
175
NICHOLAS LEIGH-JONES ET AL., MACGILLIVRAY ON INSURANCE LAW (10th
ed. 2003).
176
[1984] 1 Lloyd’s Rep. 476.
132 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
Longmore L.J., with whom Peter Gibson L.J. agreed, took the view that
since the carriage of Rolex watches was a material fact which was not
disclosed, the presentation of the risk was unfair.178 The issue was,
therefore, whether the facts that were disclosed would prompt a reasonably
careful insurer to enquire whether watches were included in the shipment.
As Longmore LJ explained, the issue came down to whether or not the
insurer was “put on inquiry by the disclosure of facts which would raise in
the mind of the reasonable insurer at least the suspicion that there were
other circumstances which would or might vitiate the presentation.”179 On
the facts he held that there was nothing in the presentation of the risk that
could be said to have raised the suspicion that Rolex watches were to be
included in the consignment.180
Of particular interest for present purposes is Rix L.J.’s dissenting
judgment on this issue. In finding that there had been waiver, he placed
particular emphasis on the mutuality of the duty of utmost good faith, and
stated that the only relevant question was whether the presentation was
fair.181 This could not be judged in isolation, although an obviously unfair
presentation would rarely leave room for waiver to operate.182 The
insurers’ reaction and the issue of possible waiver had to be taken into
account.183 The question is not whether an “unfair” presentation had been
waived but whether, taking both sides into account, the presentation was
unfair or, alternatively, it would be unfair of the insurers to avoid the
contract on a ground on which they were put on inquiry and should have
satisfied themselves by making appropriate enquiries.184
177
LEIGH-JONES ET AL., supra note 175, ¶¶ 17-83.
178
WISE Ltd. [2004] EWCA Civ. 962.
179
Id.
180
Id.
181
Id.
182
Id.
183
Id.
184
WISE Ltd. [2004] EWCA Civ. 962.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 133
Rix L.J. therefore concluded that a reasonably careful insurer would have
been fairly put on inquiry given what he knew from GNP's presentation and
his general, presumed knowledge.186 The question as to what types of
clocks were being transported was one that should have been asked by the
reinsurers. He went on to state that:
For Rix L.J., the duty of utmost good faith and, more particularly, its
content insofar as it applies to insurers or reinsurers, requires them to play a
pro-active role in the disclosure process rather than relying solely upon the
insured’s presentation.188 In this respect, his approach resonates with that
taken by Lord Mansfield in Noble v. Kennoway,189 and Court v.
185
Id.
186
Id.
187
Id.
188
See Merkin, supra note 162.
189
(1780) 99 Eng. Rep. 326.
134 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
Martineau.190 Further, the clear implication seems to be that given that the
insurers or reinsurers draft the policy terms; there is more than adequate
opportunity for them to take the necessary steps to protect themselves in
relation to the risks to be underwritten.
190
(1782) 99 Eng. Rep. 591.
191
Abram Steamship Co. v. Westville Shipping Co., [1923] A.C. 773, 781.
See also Glasgow Assurance Corp. v. Symondson & Co., (1911) 16 Com. Cas.
109, 121 (Scrutton J., suggesting that the only remedy available for non-disclosure
is avoidance of the contract).
192
PARK, supra note 18, at 218. The Marine Insurance Act, 1906, 6 Edw. 7,
c. 41, § 83(3)(a) (Eng.) provides, “Where the policy is void, or is avoided by the
insurer, as from the commencement of the risk, the premium is returnable,
provided that there has been no fraud or illegality on the part of the assured . . . .”
193
Strive Shipping Corp. v. Hellenic Mut. War Risks Ass’n (Bermuda) Ltd.
(The Grecia Express) [2002] EWHC 203.
194
Id.
195
[2003] 1 A.C. 469, 496-97.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 135
Against this, a rather more rigid view was taken towards the exercise of the
remedy in Brotherton v. Aseguradora Colseguros SA (No. 2).197 Mance
L.J. explained that the right to avoid is a self-help remedy that is exercised
without the court’s authorisation.198 He stated that avoidance for non-
disclosure is to be treated in the same way as rescission for
misrepresentation under the general law of contract, which is “by act of the
innocent party operating independently of the court.”199 In short, the court
at trial cannot reverse a valid avoidance. This affirms the orthodoxy that
holds that an insurer has an unfettered discretion to avoid the contract in
cases where there has been a breach of the duty of disclosure even where
the facts relied on, which in this case concerned allegations going as to
moral hazard, turn out to be unfounded.
Notwithstanding this strict stance, the courts have continued to
subject the conditions governing the right of avoidance to scrutiny and have
suggested that the good faith duty triggers whenever underwriters seek to
exercise the remedy. In his far reaching judgment delivered in Drake
Insurance plc v. Provident Insurance plc, Rix L.J. observed that the
doctrine of good faith should be capable of limiting the insurer's right to
196
Id. at 497.
197
[2003] EWCA Civ. 705.
198
Id.
199
Id. Note the criticism of this reasoning by Malcolm Clarke, Rescission:
Inducement and Good Faith, CAMBRIDGE L.J. 286, 287 (2004). See generally
Peter Macdonald Eggers, Remedies for the Failure to Observe the Utmost Good
Faith, L.M.C.L.Q. 249, 262-71 (2003).
136 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
200
[2003] EWCA Civ. 1834, [2004] Q.B. 601, 628. For criticism of the
court’s finding that the insurer’s right of avoidance was subject to good faith, see
Neil Campbell, Good Faith: Lessons from Insurance Law, 11 N.Z. BUS. L.Q. 479
(2005). It was, of course, inevitable that the Court of Appeal in North Star
Shipping Ltd. v. Sphere Drake Ins. plc, [2006] EWCA Civ. 378, did not permit the
amendment to the notice of appeal and, therefore, did not have the opportunity to
comment on this aspect of Drake.
201
Drake Ins. [2003] EWCA Civ. 1834.
202
Id.
203
Id., [2004] Q.B. at 628, 630.
204
Id. at 629.
205
Id.
206
Id.
207
Drake Ins., [2004] Q.B. at 630. Clarke L.J., denied the existence of “a
general principle that insurers must always give the insured an opportunity to
address the reason why they are considering avoidance.” Id. at 642.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 137
208
Id. at 649.
209
Id.
210
Id.
211
[2001] EWCA Civ. 1047 (Mance L.J.). See also Eagle Star Ins. Co. Ltd.
v. Cresswell [2004] EWCA Civ. 602.
212
Gan Ins. Co. Ltd. [2001] EWCA 1047.
213
Id.
214
Manifest Shipping Co. Ltd. v. Uni-Polaris Shipping. Co. Ltd. [2003] 1
A.C. 469 (Leggatt L.J.) (approving the judgment of Rix J. in Royal Boskalis
Westminster NV v. Mountain, [1999] Q.B. 674, in which the judge cited the
following passage from MALCOLM A. CLARKE, THE LAW OF INSURANCE
CONTRACTS 708 (2d ed. 1994):
138 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
position was stated Mathew L.J. in Boulton v. Houlder Bros. & Co., that it
“is an essential condition of the policy of insurance that the underwriters
shall be treated with good faith, not merely in reference to the inception of
the risk, but in the steps taken to carry out the contract.”215 The underlying
rationale for this view was explained by Hoffmann L.J. in Orakpo v.
Barclays Ins. Services Co. Ltd.216
I do not see why the duty of good faith on the part of the
assured should expire when the contract has been made.
The reasons for requiring good faith continue to exist. Just
as the nature of the risk will usually be within the peculiar
knowledge of the insured, so will the circumstances of the
casualty; it will rarely be within the knowledge of the
insurance company. I think that the insurance company
should be able to trust the assured to put forward a claim in
good faith.217
Sir Roger Parker agreed with Hoffmann L.J..218 There the Court of Appeal
held that a claim which is fraudulent entitles the insurer to avoid the contact
ab initio irrespective of whether there is a term in the policy to that
effect.219 However, Staughton L.J. differed.220 While he thought this
should certainly be the case where the policy so provided,221 he was not
convinced this should necessarily be the case in the absence of such term:
221
Albeit, subject to the Unfair Terms in Consumer Contracts Regulations.
222
Orakpo, [1994] C.L.C. at 382-83 (citing, inter alia, Britton v. Royal Ins.
Co., (1866) 176 Eng. Rep. 843; Black King Shipping Corp. v. Massie (The Litsion
Pride), [1985] 1 Lloyd’s Rep. 437).
223
Britton v. Royal Ins. Co., (1866) 176 Eng. Rep. 843, 844.
224
Id.
225
See, e.g., Gore Mut. Ins. Co. v. Bifford, [1987] 45 D.L.R (Ltd.) 763; Reid
& Co., Ltd. v. Employers’ Accident & Livestock Ins. Co. Ltd., (1899) 1 F. 1031;
The Litsion Pride, 1 Lloyd’s Rep. 437. See also MALCOLM A. CLARKE, THE LAW
OF INSURANCE CONTRACTS, supra note 214, at 859; Malcolm A. Clarke, Lies,
Damned Lies, and Insurance Claims: the Elements and Effect of Fraud, [2000]
N.Z.L.R. 233, 251.
226
The Litsion Pride, 1 Lloyd’s Rep. at 438.
227
Orakpo, [1994] C.L.C. at 385 (Hoffman L.J., Sir Roger Parker). This is
merely the application of the de minimis rule.
140 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
For Lord Woolf M.R., the whole of the claim must be looked at in
order to determine whether the fraud is material.233 On the facts of the
case, the claim for £2,000 amounted to some 10 per cent of the whole.234
This was an amount that was thought substantial and it therefore tainted the
whole claim.235
228
[1999] Lloyd’s Rep. I.R. 209, 213.
229
Id. at 210.
230
Id.
231
Id.
232
Id. at 213.
233
Id.
234
Galloway, [1999] Lloyd’s Rep. I.R. at 213-14.
235
Id. Millett L.J., however, disagreed with this reasoning. He said that the
determination of whether or not a claim is “substantially” fraudulent should not be
tested by reference to the proportion it bears to the entire claim. Id. at 214. To do
so “would lead to the absurd conclusion that the greater the genuine loss, the larger
the fraudulent claim which may be made at the same time without penalty.” Id. In
Millett L.J.’s view, the size of the genuine claim should not be taken into account.
Id. All that matters is that the insured is in breach of the duty of good faith which
leaves him without cover. As a matter of policy, he added that he would not
support any dilution of the insured’s duty of good faith. Id.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 141
The need for certainty was finally addressed by the House of Lords
decision in Manifest Shipping Co. Ltd. v. Uni-Polaris Ins. Co. Ltd. (The
Star Sea).236 While the trial judge had doubted the independent application
of utmost good faith to the claims process, the Court of Appeal, took the
view that the duty of good faith binds both the insured and the insurer when
a claim is made.237 Leggatt L.J. observed that “[i]t is less clear from the
cases whether there is a duty to disclose co-extensive with that which exists
before the contract of insurance is entered into, as opposed to a rather
different obligation to make full disclosure of the circumstances of the
claim. But that distinction matters not.”238 Leggatt L.J. went on to state
that that the insured’s duty of good faith requires that the claim should not
be made fraudulently and that the duty “is coincident with the term to be
implied by law, as forming part of a contract of insurance, that where fraud
is proved in the making of a claim the insurer is discharged from all
liability.”239 In conclusion, the judge stressed that given the draconian
remedy available to insurers where a claim is made fraudulently, there
should be no enlargement of the insured’s duty so as to encompass claims
made “culpably.”240
236
[2001] UKHL 1, [2003] 1 A.C. 469, 508-09. See also Sir Andrew
Longmore, Good Faith and Breach of Warranty: Are We Moving Forwards or
Backwards?, 2004 L.M.C.L.Q. 158, 166-71.
237
Manifest Shipping Co. Ltd. v. Uni-Polaris Ins. Co. Ltd., [1995] 1 Lloyd’s
Rep. 651, 667; aff’d, [1997] 1 Lloyd’s Rep. 360. The judge held that even if it did
operate there had to be at the very least recklessness by the insured and that the
duty came to an end once legal proceedings had been commenced as after that date
false statements were to be dealt with as part of the court’s processes rather than as
part of the claim. Id.
238
Manifest Shipping Co., [1997] 1 Lloyd’s Rep. at 371.
239
Id. See also Orakpo v. Barclays Ins. Servs., [1999] C.L.C. 373, 383
(Hoffmann L.J. stated “[a]ny fraud in making the claim goes to the root of the
contract and entitles the insurer to be discharged.”) As has been seen in Galloway,
the Court of Appeal held that the absence of an express condition providing that
where there was a fraudulent claim the policy would be void made no difference
for the duty of good faith continued long after the policy was effected and applied
to the claims process. Galloway, [1999] Lloyd’s Rep. I. R. at 211.
240
Manifest Shipping Co., [1997] 1 Lloyd’s Rep. at 372. See also Diggens v.
Sun Alliance and London Ins. plc, [1994] C.L.C. 1146 (the duty is not broken by
an innocent or negligent non-disclosure).
142 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
With respect to the majority view in Orakpo, Lord Hobhouse observed that
the decision “cannot be treated as fully authoritative in view of the
contractual analysis there adopted” with respect to the duty of good faith.244
His Lordship, stressing that the duty of utmost good faith applies only up
until the conclusion of the contract, noted that a duty to disclose
information can nevertheless arise later, during the currency of the policy,
as a result of an express or implied term.245
Recently the issue again arose in K/S Merc-Scandia XXXXII v.
Lloyd's Underwriters (The Mercandian Continent).246 The insured
241
Black King Shipping Corp. v. Massie (The Litsion Pride), [1985] 1
Lloyd’s Rep. 437, 437. See also Howard N. Bennett, Mapping the Doctrine of
Utmost Good Faith in Insurance Contract Law, 1999 L.M.C.L.Q. 165.
242
Manifest Shipping Co. Ltd. v. Uni-Polaris Ins. Co. Ltd. [2001] UKHL 1,
[2003] 1 A.C. 469, 494.
243
Id., [2003] 1 A.C. at 496-97.
244
Id. at 501.
245
Id. at 495.
246
[2001] EWCA Civ. 1275, [2001] 2 Lloyd’s Rep. 563.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 143
247
Id., [2001] 2 Lloyd’s Rep. at 567.
248
Id. at 566-67.
249
Id. at 576.
250
Id. at 573.
251
Id. at 575.
252
The Mercandian Continent, [2001] 2 Lloyd’s Rep. at 576.
144 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
consequence, the duty of utmost good faith was broken.253 Holding that the
duty did not apply to fraudulent claims so that the policy could not be
avoided ab initio, Mance L.J. went on to state the position with respect to
fraudulent devices.254 He thought that an acceptable solution would be to
"treat the use of a fraudulent device as a sub-species of making a fraudulent
claim" and to treat as relevant for this purpose
253
[2003] Q.B. 556. See also, H. Y. Yeo, Post-contractual good faith –
change in judicial attitude?, 66 M.L.R. 425 (2003).
254
Agapitos, [2003] Q.B. at 574-75.
255
Id. at 575. In Stemson v. AMP Gen. Ins. (NZ) Ltd. [2006] UKPC 30, the
Privy Council endorsed this approach.
256
The reasoning of Mance L.J. has recently been applied by Simon J. in
Eagle Star Ins. Co. Ltd. v. Games Video Co. SA (The Game Boy), [2004] EWHC
15. See also Interpart Comerciao e Gestao SA v. Lexington Ins. Co., [2004]
Lloyd’s Rep I.R. 690.
257
See also Goshawk Dedicated Ltd. v. Tyser & Co. [2006] EWCA Civ. 54,
[2006] 1 All E.R. (Comm.) 501, which held that any notion that the insured’s duty
of good faith continues post-contractually cannot be divorced from the terms of the
policy. The way in which such a continuing duty can arise is by implying a term
into the contract, on the basis that it is necessary for business efficacy, which
requires the insured to provide information in appropriate circumstances. It
therefore follows that there is no independent post-contractual good faith duty. All
post-contract issues are to be determined according to the terms of the policy and
in this respect, the decision appears to accord with Staughton L.J.’s minority view
in Orakpo v. Barclays Ins. Serv.’s, [1994] C.L.C. 373 (A.C.). See also Bonner v.
Cox Dedicated Corporate Member Ltd. [2004] EWHC 2963 (Comm.) (Morison
J.). Further, following Friends Provident Life & Pensions Ltd. v. Sirius Int’l. Ins.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 145
Court of Appeal also went on to hold that once litigation between the
insurers and the insured has commenced, the consequences of making a
fraudulent claim or promoting a claim with fraudulent devices are
superseded by the procedural rules governing civil litigation.258
Mance L.J. was again given the opportunity to revisit the issue in
AXA General Insurance Ltd. v. Gottlieb.259 The issue was whether under
the common law rule relating to fraudulent claims, an insurer could recover
interim payments made prior to any fraud in respect of genuine losses
incurred on the claim to which the subsequent fraud related.260 The judge
rejected the submission of the insureds’ counsel to the effect that where a
genuine right to indemnity has both arisen and been subject of a payment
made prior to any fraud committed in respect of the same claim, there can
be no conceptual basis for requiring the insured to repay the sums
received.261 Mance L.J. stated that:
Co. [2005] EWCA Civ. 601, it will probably never be the case that breach of such
a term is repudiatory of the policy as a whole. Waller L.J. expressed the
unconvincing view that perhaps a series of breaches might be repudiatory so that,
in effect, the notion of a continuing duty is dead and buried. Id.
258
See also Manifest Shipping Co. Ltd. v. Uni-Polaris Shipping Co. Ltd.,
[2001] UKHL 1, 481. But see Eagle Star Ins. Co. Ltd. [2004] EWHC 15. Simon J.
explained that this could give rise to anomalous consequences: “After litigation has
commenced an insured may advance false documentation and lie without the
drastic consequences which follow if the deployment of false documentation and
lies are less well timed.” Id.
259
[2005] EWCA Civ. 112 (Keene and Pill L.J.J., concurring).
260
Id.
261
Id.
262
Id.
146 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
should the fraud fail, he or she will lose nothing.263 The court should not,
therefore, undermine the prophylactic policy of the common law rule by
holding that forfeiture should not apply to a part of a claim that is otherwise
honest.264 Accordingly, it was held that the effect of the common law is to
forfeit the whole of the fraudulent claim so that the consideration for any
interim payments made on that claim fails.265 Such sums are thus
recoverable by the insurers irrespective of whether they were paid prior to
the fraud.266
The issue of fraudulent claims again came to the fore in Danepoint
Ltd. v. Allied Underwriting Insurance Ltd., in which a block of some
thirteen flats was damaged by a fire. 267 The insured lodged a number of
exaggerated claims together with a fraudulent claim relating to loss of
rent.268 Coulson J. subjected the authorities to thorough review. He
concluded that the duty of utmost good faith declared by section 17 of the
1906 Act does not trigger during the claims process.269 An insurer cannot,
therefore, avoid the policy ab initio on the ground of fraud.270 Where all or
part of the claim is fraudulent, or where fraudulent devices are enlisted to
promote a genuine claim, the insured will not be permitted to recover in
respect of any part of the claim.271 Mere exaggeration will not, in itself,
suffice to substantiate an allegation of fraud.272 But if the exaggeration is
wilful, or is allied to misrepresentation or concealment, it will, in the
judge’s view, probably be held to be fraudulent. In this regard, an
exaggeration is more excusable where the value of the particular claim or
head of loss in question is unclear or is a matter of opinion.273
263
Id.
264
Id.
265
AXA Gen. Ins. Ltd. [2005] EWCA Civ. 112.
266
Id.
267
[2005] EWHC 2318 (TCC). See also J. Lowry and P. Rawlings,
Fraudulent claims: framing the appropriate remedy, [2006] J. BUS. L. 339. Cf.
Stemson v. AMP Gen. Ins. (NZ) Ltd., [2006] UKPC 30.
268
Danepoint Ltd. [2005] EWHC 2318.
269
Id.
270
Id.
271
Id. at 432.
272
Id. at 438.
273
See, e.g., Orakpo v. Barclays Ins. Serv., [1994] C.L.C. 373 (A.C.).
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 147
V. THE FUTURE
274
For example, in the realms of sales law and credit transactions.
275
Clarke, supra note 199, at 288. See supra text accompanying note 9.
276
[1998] 1 W.L.R. 1765.
277
Both Lord Steyn and Lord Hope agreed.
278
Cook, [1998] 1 W.L.R. at 1768.
148 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
279
This objective informed the deliberations and recommendations put
forward by the Australian Law Reform Commission. AUSTRALIAN LAW REFORM
COMMISSION, INSURANCE CONTRACTS, Rep. No. 20, at xxi (1982).
280
See report of the NEW ZEALAND LAW COMMISSION, supra note 6, ¶ 10.
281
See AUSTRALIAN LAW REFORM COMMISSION, supra note 279. The Report
is regarded as authoritative in the interpretation of the Insurance Contracts Act,
1984 (Austl.). See Ferrcom Pty. Ltd. v. Commercial Union Assurance Co. of
Austl. Ltd., (1993) 176 C.L.R. 332, 340. By virtue of §§ 13-14 of the 1984 Act,
utmost good faith is an implied term that applies to both parties to the contract.
Thus, breach of the duty is a breach of contract giving rise to damages or to an
estoppel and not to avoidance ab initio.
282
Most of the 1984 Act’s provisions came into operation on 1 January 1986.
283
See AUSTRALIAN LAW REFORM COMMISSION, supra note 279, ¶ 24, at
xxix. See also ICA 1984, supra note 281, §§ 21 and 21A (as amended).
284
AUSTRALIAN LAW REFORM COMMISSION, supra note 279, ¶ 328, at 202.
285
Id. ¶ 182, at 110.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 149
289
Such a subjective/objective form is now the accepted test for determining
the appropriate standard of care for directors. See, e.g., Norman & Anor. v.
Theodore Goddard & Ors., [1992] B.C.C. 14. This appears in the statutory
statement of directors’ duties contained in the Companies Act, 2006, c.46, § 174
(Eng.).
290
[2003] EWCA Civ. 1834, [2004] Q.B. at 628, 629.
291
For the Law Commission’s reasoning in this regard, see supra text
accompanying note 15.
292
See THE LAW COMMISSION, supra note 15, ¶¶ 4.91-4.97.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 151
While the ALRC had some sympathy for the misgivings expressed
by the Law Commission over the difficulties of proof in relation to
proportionality and causation, it did not think these were insurmountable.
The ALRC saw no reason why in most cases insurers would not be able to
establish, “whether from rating guides, from its instructions to its agents or
staff or from its prior conduct, the nature and extent of the loss which it had
suffered.”294 While conceding that it would sometimes be difficult to
establish how it would have reacted to additional moral, as distinct from
statistical, risks the ALRC concluded, in a robust statement of principle,
that:
It therefore recommended that the nature and extent of the insurer’s redress
should depend on the nature and extent of the loss which it has suffered as
a result of the insured’s conduct and that it should no longer be entitled to
avoid a contract, and a heavy claim under that contract, merely because it
has suffered a small loss as a result of non-disclosure.296 This certainly
293
Id. ¶ 4.94.
294
AUSTRALIAN LAW REFORM COMMISSION, supra note 279, ¶ 194.
295
Id.
296
Id. See Insurance Contracts Act, 1984, §§ 28–31 (Austl.) (as amended).
See Advance (NSW) Ins. Agencies Pty. Ltd. v. Matthews, (1987) 4 ANZ Ins. Cas.
60–813 (Young J.) (New South Wales Sup. Ct.); cf. Lindsay v. CIC Ins. Ltd.,
(1989) 16 N.S.W.L.R. 673; Ferrcom Pty. Ltd. v. Commercial Union Assurance Co.
of Austl. Ltd., (1989) 5 ANZ Ins. Cas. 60-907 (Giles J.) (New South Wales Sup.
Ct.). See also Alexander Stenhouse Ltd. v. Austcan Inv. Pty. Ltd., (1993) 112
A.L.R. 353 (Mason C.J., Deane, Dawson, Toohey & McHugh J.J.). Section 31 of
the ICA provides that a court may disregard an avoidance and order the insurers to
152 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
pay some or all of a claim consistently with what is just and equitable in the
circumstances. It should be noted that the case law on sections 28-31 of the 1984
Act is confusing. The courts have developed their own principles on the
assessment of damages.
297
See Misrepresentation Act, 1967, c. 7, § 2(2) (Eng.). It should be noted,
however, that the Australian courts have frequently questioned whether the
analogy between damages for breach of contract and damages for
misrepresentation/non-disclosure is strictly correct.
298
AUSTRALIAN LAW REFORM COMMISSION, supra note 279, § 194.
299
Id. The Australian Law Reform Commission recommended reforms along
similar lines for the law relating to misrepresentation.
300
Id.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 153
301
Drake Ins. plc v. Provident Ins. plc [2003] EWCA Civ. 1834, [2004] Q.B.
601; WISE Ltd. v. Grupo Nacional Provincial SA [2004] EWCA Civ. 962.
302
Whether this is particularly novel is another question. Certainly, in Carter
v. Boehm, (1766) 97 Eng. Rep. 1162, 1165, Lord Mansfield did not draw any sharp
distinction between them. As Professor Clarke has observed, “If I describe the
shandy that I have just bought you as lemonade, is that non-disclosure of part, the
beer, or misrepresentation of the whole?” Clarke, supra note 199, at 288.
303
Insurance: Conduct of Business Sourcebook, Financial Services Authority
Handbook, Release No. 094, § 8.1.2 (Oct. 2009).
304
Unfair Commercial Practices Directive, Council Directive 2005/29, 2005
O.J. (L 149) 22 (EC). See Hugh Collins, The Unfair Commercial Practices
Directive, 1(4) EUR. REV. CONT. L. 417 (2005); and Hugh Collins, Harmonisation
by Example: European Laws against Unfair Commercial Practices 17 M.L.R. 89
(2010).
154 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
305
See The Law Commission, supra note 17.
306
Id. § 5.24.
307
CONSUMER INSURANCE LAW: PRE-CONTRACT DISCLOSURE AND
REPRESENTATION, supra note 17.
2009] GOOD FAITH IN UK INSURANCE CONTRACTS 155
308
For example, if an insurer only charged a premium of £1,000 but should
have charged £1,500, the consumer will receive two thirds of the claim. See the
Explanatory Notes to the draft Bill, A.17(3), CONSUMER INSURANCE LAW: PRE-
CONTRACT DISCLOSURE AND REPRESENTATION, supra note 17.
309
Such rules will be compulsory for business policies. See Law
Commission, Insurance Contract Law, Warranties (Nov. 2006), available at
http://www.lawcom.gov.uk/docs/Insurance_Contract_Law_Issues_Paper_2.pdf.
See also, the Law Commissions’ Consultation Paper No 182; Discussion Paper No
134, (July, 2007), Insurance Contract Law: Misrepresentation, Non-Disclosure
and Breach of Warranty by the Insured.
310
Regrettably, the Australian ICA 1984, § 21A also draws the distinction
between private and business insureds.
156 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
311
See http://www.lawcom.gov.uk/insurance_contract.htm (accessed 11
January 2010).
RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION
Michelle Boardman∗
***
There are three ways for actuarial data to advance interpretation and
construction. The first is in proving or disproving insurer good faith.
Actuarial data can show an insurer’s bona fides—countering the universal
underlying assumption of the swindling insurer. Comparing money taken
in (the premium calculation) with money paid out (the risks covered) can
confirm or deny a bait and switch scheme. Second, the data can prove an
otherwise abstract claim of actuarial purpose, providing the context that
resolves a nascent ambiguity. This is important because a finding of
ambiguity is four-fifths of a finding that the policyholder wins. Third,
actuarial data can reveal insurer intent—not simply a lack of bad faith but
a particular intent. Recognizing this intent brings some surprising benefits
to both consumers and insurers.
In insurance, courts are often engaged in a project that is both more than
and less than interpretation. Courts are engaged in regulation of the
insurance policy directly, dictating the clauses insurers can and cannot
enforce. Actuarial function provides the court intent on regulating the
insurance field with the policy implications of a particular ruling. The data
∗
Assistant Professor of Law, George Mason University School of Law.
Brown University, B.A. 1994, University of Chicago Law School, J.D. 1998.
Thanks to Tom Baker, Lloyd Cohen, Kimberly Moore, Tony Sebok, James
Siewert, Nicholas Quinn Rosenkranz, Alice Wellford, Hill Wellford, and
participants in the Vanderbilt University Law School faculty workshop. Thank
you to Adina Horvath and Cody Williams for excellent research support.
158 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
***
1
See 1 LEE R. RUSS & THOMAS F. SEGALLA, COUCH ON INS. §§ 2:27, 2:29,
2:31 (3d ed. 2009). See generally, Susan Randall, Freedom of Contract in
Insurance, 14 CONN. INS. L. J. 107, 124-34 (2007).
2
To whom the insurer offers its explanation is not an easy question. From a
contractual standpoint, the policyholder should be the audience. For my
explanation of why insurers might be more interested in communicating with the
courts, see Michelle Boardman, Contra Proferentem: The Allure of Ambiguous
Boilerplate, 104 MICH. L. REV. 1105 (2006).
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 159
the act of interpretation than the fact that the policy was issued on a
Tuesday. In insurance, however, courts are often engaged in a project that
is both more than and less than interpretation. Courts are engaged in
regulation of the insurance policy directly, dictating the clauses insurers
can and cannot enforce. Actuarial data can directly address the
construction and judicial regulation of insurance contracts.
This article offers three main ways in which actuarial data can
advance interpretation and construction. The first is in proving or
disproving insurer good faith, an area of heightened relevance in insurance
because insurers have a near-fiduciary duty toward policyholders.
Actuarial data can show an insurer’s bona fides—countering the universal
underlying assumption of the swindling insurer. Is an insurer arguing for a
particular reading of a provision, not because the insurer “means it” in
some sense, but because the insurer seeks to avoid paying for any loss, at
any time, under any theory? At times, actuarial data can answer this
question. Comparing money taken in (the premium calculation) with
money paid out (the risks covered) can confirm or deny a bait and switch.
Ultimately, the threat of this comparison will shrink the number of genuine
swindlers by bringing the con to light.
Second, the data use contains within it its own purpose. It can
prove an otherwise abstract claim of actuarial purpose, such as avoiding
synchronized losses across many people or avoiding moral hazard.3
Actuarial purpose supports a “reasonable reading” of a clause, perhaps
providing the context that resolves a nascent ambiguity. This is important
because a finding of ambiguity is four-fifths of a finding that the
policyholder wins.4 Actuarial purpose also provides the court intent on
regulating the insurance field with the policy implications of a particular
ruling. Courts are accustomed to looking beyond (or over and around) the
language of insurance policies to determine not just their written meaning,
but the meaning the court is willing to enforce. Kenneth Abraham’s central
3
Black’s Law Dictionary defines “moral hazard” as a “hazard that has its
inception in mental attitudes,” such as the “risk that an insured will destroy
property or allow it to be destroyed (usually by burning) in order to collect the
insurance proceeds is a moral hazard.” BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY 786 (9th ed.
2009). In modern insurance discussions, however, it is used to refer to the danger
that a person may take less care in avoiding a hazard, knowing that insurance will
cover part of the loss. See generally, Tom Baker, On the Genealogy of Moral
Hazard, 75 TEX. L. REV. 237 (1996).
4
See TOM BAKER, INSURANCE LAW AND POLICY: CASES AND MATERIALS 466
(2003).
160 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
5
Kenneth S. Abraham, A Theory of Insurance Policy Interpretation, 95
MICH. L. REV. 531, 532 (1996) (Some of the doctrines “have nothing to do with
‘interpretation’ as it is normally understood.”).
6
For a modern defense of (limited) judicial regulation, see Daniel Schwarcz,
A Products Liability Theory for the Judicial Regulation of Insurance Policies, 48
WM. & MARY L. REV. 1389 (2007). Schwarcz does not advocate the introduction
of specific actuarial data but his framework requires courts to consider whether the
policy causes “insurance harm” and to “ask whether the insurer has any legitimate
underwriting purpose for not insuring against the specific loss that befell the
insured.” Id. at 1448 (emphasis added).
7
See Tom Baker, Insuring Liability Risks, 29 GENEVA PAPERS ON RISK & INS.
128, 139-40 (2004).
8
Howard Kunreuther, Robin Hogarth & Jacqueline Meszaros, Insurer
Ambiguity and Market Failure, 7 J. OF RISK AND UNCERTAINTY 71, 79 (1993).
The 1993 Kunreuther et al. studies of insurer ambiguity presented the insurance
actors with a set probability on which “all experts agree” and contrasted that with
an ambiguous probability, defined as a “wide disagreement about the estimate of p
[the probability of loss] and a high degree of uncertainty among the experts.” Id. at
72. See also Howard Kunreuther et al., Ambiguity and Underwriter Decision
Processes, 26 J. ECON. BEHAV. & ORG 337, 342-44 (1995). Instead of a wide
range in the probability that a loss will occur, here the issue is a wide range that a
policy will be read to cover the loss. The surveys also found some evidence that
the risk premium could be double-charged: “To the extent that primary
underwriters do not recognize that the prices of actuaries may already include
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 161
clause makes it possible to assess whether the clause could have been
written more clearly. Where the intent, while legitimate, is too complex to
be conveyed well to consumers, courts must decide whether to effectuate
the intent or forbid any similar clause.
Courts adopt a regulatory view toward the health of the insurance
industry and the interests of those policyholders not before the court. If the
purpose of the clause is insurer solvency, for example, a regulatory court
may prefer to protect solvency over literal language interpretation or other
values. Courts most commonly regulate by mandating coverage and
forbidding exclusions to coverage. But regulating the substance of
insurance clauses without access to the actuarial function of those clauses is
looking left and leaping right. Insurer purpose and intent do not need to
control the outcome of a court’s decision to improve the outcome of its
regulation.
adjustments for ambiguity and uncertainty, they may recommend a premium that
reflects their concerns with these factors.” Kunreuther, Hogarth & Meszaros at 75
(emphasis added).
9
“First, insurance looks at groups, at the socialization of risk through
standard contracts sold to large numbers of similarly situated persons who face an
uncertain risk. What is good for the group, as a whole, in face of uncertainty, may
not be what is good for any individual when sued.” Kent D. Syverud, What
Professional Responsibility Scholars Should Know About Insurance, 4 CONN. INS.
L.J. 17, 19 (1998). “The needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few or the
one.” Spock’s dying words, with help from Captain Kirk. STAR TREK II: THE
WRATH OF KHAN (Paramount Pictures 1982).
162 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
10
BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY 41 (9th ed. 2009).
11
Hence the individual members of the Lloyds insurance market are called
Names. See PETER L. BERNSTEIN, AGAINST THE GODS: THE REMARKABLE STORY
OF RISK 90-91 (1998).
12
F. Daniel Perkins, Can “Sound Actuarial Principles” Be Found in Life
Insurance Underwriting?, 38 TORT TRIAL & INS. PRAC. L.J. 125, 138 (2002).
13
The actuarial portion may include “feature rating,” where “[d]ata collected
over the years and intuitive hunches by insurers suggest which features are
correlated with loss rates.” “Experience rating,” which is coupled with feature
rating, “uses the loss experience of the insured during one period to help set the
premiums charged” in the next. KENNETH S. ABRAHAM, DISTRIBUTING RISK:
INSURANCE, LEGAL THEORY, AND PUBLIC POLICY 72 (1986).
14
Ralph H. Blanchard, The Basis of Premium Rates, J. OF AM. INS. (Feb.
1928), reprinted in RALPH H. BLANCHARD, RISK AND INSURANCE AND OTHER
PAPERS 159, 161 (1965). What was true in 1928 is true today.
164 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
15
See NEIL A. DOHERTY, INSURANCE PRICING AND LOSS PREVENTION 16-21
(1976).
16
Come the start of 2009, some are laughing at this statement.
17
The process gets more complex, of course. On the surface, the timeline for
loss payments in the Commercial General Liability context is often years if not
decades after the collection of the original premium. This puts a strain on even the
most careful predictions of interest rates, taxes, loss amounts, and reserves for
payment.
18
This is not to say there are not questions the data will not answer. There
are many. See infra text accompanying notes 73-74.
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 165
19
EMERIC FISCHER, PETER NASH SWISHER, & JEFFREY W. STEMPEL,
PRINCIPLES OF INSURANCE LAW 90 (rev. 3rd ed. 2006).
20
See, e.g., Prudential Ins. Co. v. Lamme, 425 P.2d 346, 347 (Nev. 1967)
(policies are “complex instrument[s], unilaterally prepared [by the insurer], and
seldom understood by the assured.”).
21
So says The Red Queen. LEWIS CARROLL, THE ANNOTATED ALICE:
ALICE’S ADVENTURES IN WONDERLAND AND THROUGH THE LOOKING-GLASS 210
(New American Library ed. 1960).
22
“The distinction [between interpretation and construction] is, for the most
part, not dwelled upon by the courts, with the result that it is difficult to tell which
process is being employed.” JOHN D. CALAMARI & JOSEPH M. PERILLO, THE LAW
OF CONTRACTS 165 (3rd ed. 1987). The distinction will be partially honored here
because the two approaches call for distinct uses of actuarial data.
23
“Alice . . . explained, as well as she could, that she had lost her way. ‘I
don't know what you mean by your way,’ said the Queen: ‘all the ways about here
belong to me.’” CARROLL, supra note 21, at 206.
166 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
24
Of course, it is foolish to expect the sins of inadequate counsel to be
remedied by asking that same counsel to present actuarial data. Unless the insurer,
the policyholder, or the court invokes the data, the lawyer who fails to explain the
function of a clause will also fail to introduce the data behind it.
25
See infra notes 71-74 and accompanying text.
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 167
to flee or prices to rise.27 The court faces a tradeoff, although it may not
know or care to know.
Let us assume that insurers fail to provide the best coverage the
market will bear. Policyholders as a group want and are willing to pay for
a particular coverage, call it the happy clause. Should not judges simply
award that coverage to the policyholder seeking redress in court? Courts
could read the happy clause into policies, perhaps under the reasonable
expectations doctrine because policyholders reasonably expect it. 28 After
all, if judges regularly award happy coverage, in theory insurers will soon
sell what they are being forced to provide. Sure, the premium will rise to
reflect the cost of the new coverage but recall that in this example
policyholders as a group are willing to pay.
Still, policyholders in general may ask the court not to do them any
favors. The specific preference of a given policyholder after a loss can
easily be at odds with the preference of policyholders generally. Moreover,
policyholders’ preferences are not simply cumulative. Case by case,
policyholders might approve of each of one thousand subtypes of coverage
at various prices. There are therefore one thousand “units” of coverage that
Every Policyholder would be willing to buy at its market price. However,
the Policyholder is not willing to buy all thousand because he has a limit on
how much he is willing to devote to insurance, say $1000 a year.
If he can rank the units of coverage, his ideal policy will include
unit 1 to unit 100, or wherever the premium reaches $1000. If a third party
(the courts, legislature, or regulators) instead requires that unit 20 be
expanded or that unit 500 be added, he either will have to let unit 100 go or
pay more than his maximum price. Of course, the policyholder cannot go
to the insurer in response to a court case and request the substitution; the
insurer will decide for him. If the insurer removes nothing, but adds in the
court’s mandated coverage, the insurer will eventually charge more.
Whatever insurers are selling today, we can be sure that Every
Policyholder is not in fact receiving his perfect policy at his perfect price.
The question is whether the terms that courts “add” are likely to make the
policy better or worse. To the extent courts are regulating insurance—
mandating coverage because policyholders deserve it or intractably expect
27
On fleeing insurers, see Daniel Hays, State Farm to Leave Florida
Homeowners Insurance Market, NAT’L UNDERWRITER PROP. & CASUALTY, Feb. 2,
2009, at 7. See also Richard A. Epstein, Exit Rights and Insurance Regulation:
From Federalism to Takings, 7 GEO. MASON L. REV. 293 (1999).
28
See infra notes 32-34 and accompanying text.
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 169
it—that regulatory decision is poorly made if the court does not consider
(or makes erroneous assumptions about) the actuarial facts behind
coverage.
29
The text will be weighed in context with intent and purpose potentially
providing part of the context. It may be better to consider the policy’s purpose
before the specific intent of the parties, as evidence of intent will be extrinsic and
potentially less reliable than the self-evident purpose of a policy. On the other
hand, undue confidence in the “self-evident” purpose of particular clauses is one of
the ripest areas for the introduction of actuarial data.
30
Some of the best works on insurance interpretation are: ABRAHAM, supra
note 13, at 101; Abraham, supra note 5; James M. Fischer, Why Are Insurance
Contracts Subject to Special Rules of Interpretation?: Text Versus Context, 24
ARIZ. ST. L.J. 995 (1992); Michael B. Rappaport, The Ambiguity Rule and
Insurance Law: Why Insurance Contracts Should Not be Construed Against the
Drafter, 30 GA. L. REV. 171 (1995); Peter Nash Swisher, Judicial Interpretations
of Insurance Contract Disputes: Toward a Realistic Middle Ground Approach, 57
OHIO ST. L.J. 543 (1996).
170 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
Note that this model sensibly does not attempt to claim a hierarchy for the
treatments of ambiguity.
If the language is not ambiguous on its face, the textual court may
admit extrinsic evidence to determine (a) a latent ambiguity; (b) the intent
31
Mut. Life Ins. Co. of N.Y. v. Hurni Packing Co., 263 U.S. 167, 174 (1923).
32
See Abraham, supra note 5, at 533.
33
Abraham, supra note 5, at 532 (citing ROBERT E. KEETON & ALAN I.
WIDISS, INSURANCE LAW §§ 6.1(a)-(b), at 614-21 (Practitioner’s ed. 1988)).
34
See infra Section II.C. Keeton “introduced” the doctrine in Robert E.
Keeton, Insurance Law at Variance with Policy Provisions, 83 HARV. L. REV. 961
(1970).
35
ANDERSON ET AL., INSURANCE COVERAGE LITIGATION § 2.01 (2nd ed. 2009
& Supp. 2010).
36
Id.
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 171
of the drafters; (c) any accepted usage in the industry; (d) if the
policyholder’s interpretation is reasonable in light of the insurer’s; and (e)
insurer bad faith.37 According to Anderson et al., if after this investigation
the court finds the language ambiguous, it will construe it in favor of
coverage.38 This is accurate as long as one understands that a finding of
ambiguity after the total analysis is a legal conclusion that is the same as
finding that the court will construe in favor of coverage.
A formalist judge will start with the policy text and veer off-
document with reluctance. Actuarial data could be viewed as extrinsic
evidence but it can also be viewed as a contextual fact about the purpose of
the document. Purpose, text, and logic will help resolve a budding
ambiguity or surface tension between two clauses.
As with non-insurance contracts, the “modern contract theory”
model does not completely supplant this textual approach. The tools used
are the same, but with a greater focus on reasonable expectations and the
intended use and purpose of the policy.39 On the one hand, the contextual,
functionalist approach should be less open to actuarial data because it
rejects the idea of subjective mutual intent in the standardized adhesive
contract.40 On the other hand, it also rejects a full obligation on the part of
the policyholder to read the policy; as the policy language loses its use in
determining the meaning of the contract, other sources, including insurer
intent and actuarial purpose, become more useful. Moreover, the actuarial
purpose discussed below may be of greatest use to those courts taking a
regulatory approach to policy language. Regulating courts are more prone
to be in the “modern” interpretative camp.
That said, all judges behave somewhat curiously in the insurance
realm.41 A functionalist or realist judge views a policy through its purpose
but will focus on the public purpose; this judge will be more open to
evidence about actuarial purpose than to an insurer’s specific intent. He
37
Id.
38
Id. §2.02
39
Id. § 2.01.
40
See, e.g., E. Allan Farnsworth, “Meaning” in the Law of Contracts, 76
YALE L.J. 939, 943 (1967).
41
Associate Justice of the Supreme Court, Sonia Sotomayor provides one
example of unexpected behavior in insurance cases. On the lower bench, then
Judge Sotomayor ruled “consistently, across the board in favor of insurers.”
Andrea Ortega-Wells, Supreme Court Nominee Sotomayor Shows Record of
Favoring Insurers, INSURANCE JOURNAL, June 1. 2009,
http://www.insurancejournal.com/news/national/2009/06/01/101001.htm.
172 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
B. CONSISTENT INTENT
42
FISCHER ET AL., supra note 19, at 95 n.10.
43
ANDERSON ET AL., supra note 35 at xx. See also Jarrett v. E.L. Harper &
Son, 235 S.E.2d 362, 366 (W.Va. 1977). The West Virginia Supreme Court wrote:
Insurance is different from any other business. If a man goes
into a butcher shop, asks for two pounds of ground meat, and
tenders $2.89 in payment, he will expect his meat to be
forthcoming from the grinder. Imagine the scene were the
customer to ask for his meat, and be answered that the butcher
has no intention to deliver the same. ‘Where is my meat?’ the
customer would reply, possibly in other than dulcet tones. ‘I
won't give you any meat,’ replies the butcher firmly. ‘Then give
me back my $2.89 and I shall go elsewhere,’ says the customer.
‘I won't give you the $2.89 either,’ replies the butcher, ‘for you
must bring a law suit to get it from me.’ Sock! Pow! Blam!
And much property damage of a different sort. Id.
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 173
44
See JEFFREY W. STEMPEL, LAW OF INSURANCE CONTRACT DISPUTES, §
10.01 (2d ed. 1999 & Supp. 2005); see also William T. Barker, Paul E.B. Glad,
and Steven M. Levy, Is an Insurer a Fiduciary to Its Insureds?, 25 TORT & INS.
L.J. 1 (1989).
45
See, e.g., Tank v. State Farm Fire & Cas. Co., 715 P.2d 1133, 1137 (Wash.
1986); Short v. Dairyland Ins. Co., 334 N.W.2d 384, 387 (Minn. 1983).
46
FISCHER ET AL., supra note 19, at 93. Fischer et al. describe the “tension of
sorts between [an insurer’s] duty to its shareholders or other investors (to make
money) and duty to its policyholders (to pay money).” Id. One could add the
tension with the duty to other policyholders to pay other money or money in the
future.
47
State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co. v. Kastner, 77 P.3d 1256, 1259-60 (Colo.
2003) (quoting Farmers Group, Inc. v. Williams, 805 P.2d 419, 423 (Colo. 1991)).
48
FISCHER ET AL., supra note 19, at 88.
49
E.I. DePont de Nemours & Co. v. Pressman, 679 A.2d 436, 447 (Del.
1996).
50
See, e.g., Tibbs v. Great Am. Ins. Co., 755 F.2d 1370, 1375 (9th Cir. 1985)
(“[T]here is sufficient evidence to support a finding that Great American refused to
defend Tibbs in bad faith and is guilty of oppression, fraud, or malice,” triggering
punitive damages).
174 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
51
Most people report being able to do this with ease.
52
Some speculate that insurers care not for litigation costs because the time
value of the money being retained while the litigation progresses pays for itself,
but this cannot be true in small cases. See Alan O. Sykes, “Bad Faith” Breach of
Contract by First-Party Insurers, 25 J. LEGAL STUD. 405, 413 (1996).
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 175
This arrangement should be profitable for few insurers, far fewer than
courts assume can profit from the pretense of coverage.
The sole potential benefit to the tricky type of duplicitous insurer is
in an increase in clients. It hasn’t increased its rates, after all. To be a
profitable ruse, the increase in sales from pretending to provide coverage C
would have to outweigh the costs of litigating and the cost of covering
some percentage of C risks. Recall, no premium was charged for C.
How does the insurer lure in new clients using risk C? Given that
most policyholders do not fully read or understand their policies, the
creation of the expectation of coverage C would either have to come from
(a) fraudulent advertising or (b) taking advantage of a pre-existing
expectation of coverage. Fraudulent advertising is a dicey proposition; it
will invite the scrutiny of state insurance commissioners and the attention
of class action lawyers. On an individual basis, an ad that promises a
particular type of coverage will solidly support the consumer’s claim of
“reasonable expectations” in court. The percentages of those who sue on C
and win will rise, leading to a rise in the percentage of consumers who sue.
This may explain why most insurance ads make vague promises of “good
neighbors” with “good hands” in the “company you keep.”53
In the second, more likely scenario, the insurer does not advertise
but relies on expectations to ensure sales. But an insurer will be hard-
pressed to increase sales based on the expectations of coverage C because
the policyholder’s pre-existing expectations of coverage are not insurer
specific—the policyholder will assume all policies include coverage for
risk C. Thus, a Tricky Insurer who does not charge more but only hopes to
increase sales based on a universal assumption is not so tricky. In other
words, this scenario seems an unlikely one for swindling insurers, but this
is an empirical question courts can investigate on their own using actuarial
data.
A more likely model for the swindling insurer is one who
calculates and charges a premium based on risks A + B + C but, when C
loss occurs, does not intend to provide coverage. (This differs from the
insurer above because the premium actually includes risk C here.)
53
State Farm Mutual Automobile Insurance Company: “Like a good
neighbor, State Farm is there.”® Allstate Insurance Company: “You’re in Good
Hands with Allstate.”® New York Life Insurance Company: “New York Life.
The Company You Keep.”®
176 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
The benefit here is obvious: collect money for C and keep it. This
Breaching Insurer may be similarly happy where policyholders either fail
to claim the coverage or do not sue when denied. If the pretense of
providing for C is in the ether, not an ad or the policy language, the insurer
can hope that many will not sue after a loss. But if courts look to the
actuarial data when the policyholder does sue, the court should be able to
readily grant the C coverage paid for (assuming the policyholder has
suffered C).
This will be most straightforward where risk C falls within the
general grant of coverage, say to a small guesthouse near the insured home,
but is removed by an exclusion, such as if the guesthouse is used as an
office part-time.54 Many homeowners policies “cover other structures on
the ‘residence premises’ set apart from the dwelling by clear space,” but
not “[o]ther structures from which any ‘business’ is conducted,” where
“business” is defined as “[a] trade, profession or occupation engaged in on
a full-time, part-time or occasional basis.”55 If the premium charged takes
into account the loss data for all “other structures” but fails to exclude those
losses where “business is conducted,” the consumer has been charged for
and deserves compensation.
Of course, the set-up need not be so formalized or consistently
applied. Many people and judges seem to believe that insurers randomly
deny payment for losses that are covered, for which the policyholder has
paid a premium. Actuarial data should be able to give a clearer picture of
how often this happens. If courts regularly examine actuarial data, as time
goes by insurers should become less and less willing to charge for coverage
and then deny the claim.
In addition to tricks and breach, there is a middle way. An insurer
may have created an expectation of coverage from past sales; all prior
policies did cover risk C, at price P. When a new day dawns, the insurer
54
INSURANCE SERVICES OFFICE, INC., STANDARD HOMEOWNERS POLICY,
HOMEOWNERS 3 – SPECIAL FORM HO 00 03 10 00 1, 3 (1999), quoting p. 3,
Section I – Property Coverages, B.1. & B.2.c. and p. 1, Definitions, B.3.a,
available at http://www.mypolicyforms.com/ho3/default2.aspx. The definition of
“business” contains other provisions not relevant here.
55
Id. at 1, 3.
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 177
continues to charge P (or even slightly less than P) but removes risk C from
the policy language and stops compensating for C loss.56 Behold the
Tricky Breaching Insurer. The marketing of the policy is unchanged, so
applicants assume C coverage continues to exist. If the coverage is sold at
slightly less than P, it appears to the unsophisticated buyer to be a great
bargain.
What will the actuarial data show here? The analysis parallels that
of the Breaching Insurer if the premium fully includes the risk of C. If the
premium is the original P, discounted slightly, the analysis may be
identical. It depends on how the discount is taken. If the actuarial data
continues to include risk C but a slight discount is taken from the total
premium calculation at the end, the court still easily sees that C has been
charged for but denied. Breach. If the C component of the premium is
itself reduced by some percentage, as long as the basis is still C, breach is
found again.
This is not to say that the calculation cannot be too convoluted to
prove breach. Indeed, if actuarial data becomes widely used in court, some
swindling insurers can be counted upon to re-master the premium
calculations to increase convolution. On the other hand, honest insurers
who currently operate under a cloud of doubt may work to ensure their
calculations show their honesty to its best advantage.
Let us return for a moment to methods of misleading the consumer
at the front end. We can imagine either that the insurer actively attempts to
provide the illusion of coverage C, as in the first example, or that the
insurer simply takes advantage of a pre-existing consumer misconception
about that type of coverage. It would be easy for insurers to identify the
many misconceptions policyholders have about their insurance coverage.
A 2007 phone survey of policyholders found that 71% of Americans with
homeowners insurance believed they had full coverage to rebuild after a
natural disaster or fire and 72% believed their personal belongings were
covered at the cost of replacement.57 Their actual coverage had caps below
56
This is a common marketing move in the grocery aisle. You may
sporadically find your cereal box is slightly thinner or has fewer flakes, although
the price per box does not decrease. See, e.g., Jessica Dickler, The Incredible
Shrinking Cereal Box: The packaging may look the same but the amount inside has
gone down, that’s how companies try to pass on food inflation, CNNMONEY.COM,
Sept. 10, 2008, http://money.cnn.com/2008/09/09/pf/food_downsizing/index.htm.
57
Press Release, Metlife Auto & Home, Insurance Surprises: Survey Finds
Many Americans Dramatically Overestimate the Level of Insurance Protection
178 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
full coverage and would cover the depreciated value of personal items, well
below replacement cost.
Do insurers take advantage of mistakes like this? Oren Bar-Gill
and Richard Epstein recently asked the more general question “do
sophisticated sellers respond strategically to consumer misperception? In
particular, do sellers design their products, contracts, and pricing schemes
in response to consumer misperception?” 58 They consider the answer in a
debate between behavioral and neoclassical law and economics; Bar-Gill
emphasizes that the answer is ultimately empirical.59 Contrary to courts’
assumptions, both conclude that it “is probably correct” that “mistakes
about a standardized product are not sustainable.”60
Insurance may be the exception. Under a reasonable conception of
standardization, homeowners insurance policies are a standardized product
and consumer mistakes certainly persist. Whether insurers are strategically
taking advantage of these mistakes can be answered by actuarial data. And
while Bar-Gill is correct that the question is ultimately empirical, the
analysis of premium calculation presented here can provide some initial
answers even before the actuarial data is reviewed by courts.
The point here is that if the insurer attempts to swindle
policyholders by the second breaching method—charging for A+B+C but
not covering C—actuarial data should reveal the C charge and confirm that
policyholders are due C coverage. The assumption here is not that there
are only honest insurers, but that actuarial data can either keep insurers
honest or at least allow courts to identify the dishonest ones. 61
C. SPECIFIC INTENT
importantly, the data are actual proof of intent; insurers would no longer
have to rely on their mere claims of intent in the face of skeptical courts.
If courts could be made more comfortable that an insurer’s
representation of its intent was its actual intent, the question becomes what
to do with the knowledge. On the day the contract was formed, the insurer
had a definite intent as to what the words meant; the (consumer or
unsophisticated) policyholder had a general intent—cover my losses if my
house is partially or totally destroyed. Karl Llewellyn called a consumer’s
intent in a standardized contract the “blanket assent . . . to any not
unreasonable or indecent terms the seller may have on its form, which do
not alter or eviscerate the reasonable meaning of the dickered terms.”65 In
keeping with this, not all reasonable expectations options require the
policyholder to have had an actual expectation before the loss occurred;
many courts are content to ask what the policyholder would have expected
had the question come to mind. Indeed, the policyholder is rarely asked to
explain, let alone prove, the source of his expectation.
But what if the policyholder would not have had a particular
expectation even had the question come to mind? For example, does your
homeowners policy provide coverage if the fence around your yard is
damaged?66 Does it provide coverage for limited personal effects lost in
hotel rooms while traveling? (Yes, to some extent).67 If your spouse
intentionally burns down your house, are you still covered for your half of
the loss? (It depends). 68 Does the pollution exclusion exclude coverage
65
KARL N. LLEWELLYN, THE COMMON LAW TRADITION—DECIDING APPEALS
370 (1960) (emphasis added); see also Swisher, supra note 30, at 570 n.77.
66
Your homeowners policy may cover your neighbor’s fence—if you
negligently set a fire in your backyard. See Prather v. Audubon Ins. Co., 488 So.
2d 383, 384-85 (La. Ct. App. 1986). A homeowner was recently paid $25,000 for
damage from Hurricane Katrina to a den and the fencing around his home.
Although the plaintiff was not happy with the sum he received, a portion was
attributed to the fence. See Gustings v. Travelers & Standard Fire Ins. Co., No. 07-
4443, 2008 WL 4948837 at *1 (E.D. La. Nov. 18, 2008).
67
INSURANCE SERVICES OFFICE, supra note 54, at 3 (“We cover personal
property owned or used by an ‘insured’ while it is anywhere in the world.”).
68
See Rachel R. Watkins Schoenig, Note, Property Insurance and the
Innocent Co-Insured: Was It All Pay and No Gain for the Innocent Co-Insured? 43
DRAKE L. REV. 893, 895-96 (1995). If the policy is jointly held between husband
and wife, the non-arsonist has suffered an unintentional loss; whether that loss is
covered depends on the contract and the state. See Randall, supra note 1, at 144-
45. “Whether the intentional acts of a co-insured will defeat coverage for an
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 181
for the injury to people who inhaled fumes from floor cleaner? (Depends
on the jurisdiction).69
If the policyholder would not have had a particular view, it could
not be disappointed in a lack of coverage. If the insurer has a particular
intent, one acted upon in premium calculation, it has something to lose
from an adverse interpretation. There is always a decent chance that
nonetheless a court will apply contra proferentem, construing the language
in favor of coverage. The undercurrent of contra proferentem is protection
of the policyholder against a scheming insurer and “encouragement” to the
insurer to draft more clearly. In circumstances where neither of these
motivations applies, courts that give lip service to valuing the insurer’s
intent could pay up, with the aid of actuarial data.70
For example, commercial general liability policies provide
coverage for liability arising from damage to “tangible property.”71 Data
stored on computers came along, quickly followed by possible liability
arising from its destruction. When policyholders first started seeking
72
See, e.g., Computer Corner Inc. v. Fireman’s Fund Ins., 46 P.3d 1264, 1266
(N.M. Ct. App. 2002) (electronically stored data is “tangible property”); Am.
Online, Inc. v. St. Paul Mercury Ins. Co., 207 F. Supp. 2d 459 (E.D. Va. 2002)
(electronically stored data not “tangible property”).
73
Of course, threats to physical property also threaten the physical storage of
electronic data. When fire destroys a computer, it destroys any data stored on that
computer but electronic data are subject mainly to electronic threats.
74
Try this experiment. Show the policy language on tangible property to
several friends and ask each one (a) if the clause covers electronically stored data
and (b) if the question is close, i.e. if the language is ambiguous as applied to
electronic data. You will find that people vary in their answer to (a) but do not
believe (b).
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 183
As with the other three risks, the higher the contract risk, the more
expensive it will be to cover and the more policyholders will have to pay.
Another way to think about contract risk is as a species of
ambiguity aversion for which insurers will charge a risk premium. Surveys
of actuaries, underwriters, and reinsurance underwriters suggest strong
aversion to loss ambiguity. These surveys “illustrate that uncertainty about
75
See Baker, supra note 7, at 139-40.
76
Id. at 128, 130. Kenneth Abraham calls this an “uncertainty tax.” Kenneth
S. Abraham, The Insurance Effects of Regulation by Litigation, in REGULATION
THROUGH LITIGATION 212, 222-23 (W. Kip Viscusi ed. 2002).
77
Baker, supra note 7, at 128-30.
184 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
D. ACTUARIAL PURPOSE
78
Kunreuther, Hogarth & Meszaros, supra note 8, at 79. See also sources
cited supra note 8.
79
Inflicting a high contract risk for unavoidably complex language is another
story. See Michelle Boardman, Insuring Understanding: The Tested Language
Defense, 95 IOWA L. REV. (forthcoming 2010).
80
But see Boardman, supra note 2, at 1112-17.
81
As with any increase in litigation certainty, decreasing the contract risk
should also increase the resolution of claims out of court.
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 185
82
Ohio Cas. Ins. Co. v. Henderson, 939 P.2d 1337, 1339 (Ariz. 1997)
(quoting Transamerica Ins. Group v. Meere, 694 P.2d 181, 185 (Ariz. 1984)).
83
Id. at 1339 (emphasis added). See also Cal. Cas. Ins. v. Am. Family Mut.
Ins., 94 P.3d 616, 618 (Ariz. App. 2004).
84
Transamerica Ins. Group v. Meere, 694 P.2d 181 (Ariz. 1984).
On March 27, 1980, at about 12:30 a.m., Meere and a friend,
Leon Ivey, were leaving Lindy’s, a bar in Florence, Arizona.
Outside Lindy’s, Meere and Ivey were confronted by several off-
duty employees of the Arizona State Prison. Meere alleges that
he was quite apprehensive because he had been informed by a
captain at Arizona State Prison that a rumor was circulating
among the guards that Ivey and Meere, both ex-police officers,
were undercover investigators of narcotics flow into the prison.
One of the guards, Dennis Pruitt, approached Meere. Meere and
Pruitt exchanged words. Pruitt then struck Meere, knocking him
to the ground; Meere put up his hands, said ‘I don’t want to
fight,’ and was struck again by Pruitt. The two then exchanged
blows. The fight ended when Meere knocked Pruitt to the
ground and kicked Pruitt as he attempted to get up and come at
Meere again. Pruitt lost partial use of an eye as a result of this
fight. Id. at 183.
186 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
85
See, e.g., Lockhart v. Allstate Ins. Co., 579 P.2d 1120, 1122-23 (Ariz. Ct.
App. 1978); Auto-Owners Ins. Co. v. Harrington, 538 N.W.2d 106, 108-10 (Mich.
Ct. App. 1995); Grange Ins. Co. v. Brosseau, 776 P.2d 123, 126-27 (Wash. 1989).
86
The dissent in Meere characterized the decision by the majority as one
“based on policy to distribute the consequences of the loss on an insurance
company.” Meere, 694 P.2d at 190.
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 187
87
ROBERT H. JERRY, II & DOUGLAS R. RICHMOND, UNDERSTANDING
INSURANCE LAW § 63C(c) (4th ed. 2007). See, e.g., Stout v. Grain Dealers Mut.
Ins. Co., 201 F. Supp. 647 (M.D.N.C. 1962) (coverage for intentional shooting and
unintentional killing of persistent prowler excluded). What is at stake in these
cases is the insurer’s duty to defend, or pay for the defense, of the policyholder. A
policyholder who is found in a civil action to have acted properly in self-defense is
not liable to his foe. A policyholder whose claim of self-defense is rejected is
liable to his foe but his intentional act and harm clearly falls within the intentional
act exclusion. See also John Dwight Ingram, The Expected or Intended Exclusion
in Liability Insurance: What About Self-Defense?, 42 CREIGHTON L. REV. 123
(2009).
88
Tuepker v. State Farm Fire & Cas. Co., No. 1:05CV559 LTS-JMR, 2006
WL 1442489 at *4-*5 (S.D. Miss., May 24, 2006).
89
Id. at *4.
90
STATE FARM HOME OWNERS POLICY 24100401-1 (2005), reprinted in
Tuepker 2006 WL 1442489 at *2.
We do not insure under any coverage for any loss which would
not have occurred in the absence of one or more of the following
events. We do not insure for such loss regardless of: (a) the cause
of the excluded event; or (b) other causes of the excluded event;
or (c) whether other causes acted concurrently or in any sequence
with the excluded event to produce the loss; or (d) whether the
event occurs suddenly or gradually, involves isolated or
widespread damage, arises from natural or external forces, or
188 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
For these purposes, the policy would therefore exclude wind and rain
damage (otherwise covered) if it would not have occurred but for the storm
surge (excluded water damage). If a house withstood the wind up until the
storm surge knocked down a wall, for example, leading wind and rain to
damage the inside of the house, all would be excluded. On the other hand,
if wind tore a hole in the roof, letting rain in to damage the second story,
both would be covered whether or not the first floor was also flooded.
This is a simple explanation of what is admittedly dense policy
language. Given that the court had to find some meaning in the language,
however, it is a reasonable reading that does not torture or ignore any of the
policy language. However, the judge in Tuepker—a capable judge who
handled many Katrina cases with some skill—found the addition of the
hurricane endorsement to the rest of the policy (wind covered, flood
excluded) ambiguous.91 The judge seemed to conclude that since the
hurricane coverage must have meant something, and the policy already
covered wind and rain damage, it must have meant that the “combined
cause” exclusion did not apply during a hurricane.92
This reading may be less reasonable than the one offered above or
it may be an improvement; the point is that the actuarial data should have
been able to answer the question. The policyholder paid an additional
premium for the hurricane endorsement. Which risks did the insurer enter
in calculating that premium? Which risks are excluded? In particular, the
93
ABRAHAM, supra note 13 at 101. Abraham is right that while “judicial
techniques of interpretation frequently create insurance coverage where policies do
not provide for it,” the total interpretation “practice turns out to be considerably
more complicated” than courts simply handing money from wealthy insurers to
policyholders. Id. at 101-02.
94
For example, state regulation can have disastrous results. State Farm is
currently withdrawing all homeowners insurance from the state of Florida. The
last straw for State Farm was not court action but the denial by the state Insurance
Commissioner of State Farm’s request to raise rates 47.1 percent. State Farm Can
Go? But Not on Its own Terms, SUWANNEE DEMOCRAT, Feb. 19,2009 available at
http://www.suwanneedemocrat.com/archivesearch/local_story_044133837.html.
State Farm claims that Florida’s policies, such as required discounts to its
customers “have further reduced needed revenues. During the first three quarters
of 2008 (a year with relatively modest catastrophe impact and no major hurricane),
State Farm Florida saw its surplus reduced by $201 million.” Hays, supra note 27,
at 7.
190 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
1. Ambiguity
A side note about ambiguity is called for here. More than half of
insurance disputes involve some claim of ambiguity. 95 If a court concludes
that a clause (or collection of clauses) is ambiguous, it will be construed
against the insurer and in favor of coverage under the doctrine of contra
proferentem. Actuarial data can help here too, although its role is more
amorphous.
In an opinion that is a favorite of insurance textbooks, a court
found the phrase “occupied as Janitor’s residence” ambiguous.96 The
question was whether a floor, a portion of which was used as a massage
parlor, was “occupied as a janitor’s residence” because a janitor slept there
on occasion. The court attempted to consider the purpose of the clause
from the insurer’s perspective but did so by guessing. The court assumed
the value of the janitor’s residence was to monitor for fire or trouble, and
this may have been so. On the other hand, the court also speculates that the
insurer may have wanted the janitor to exclusively occupy the floor,
keeping out more dangerous uses.97
Actuarial data should have been provided or solicited to prove one
of these purposes. The kink here is that the data would not directly have
addressed the question of whether the clause was ambiguous; either the
clause is susceptible of two plausible interpretations, in context, or it isn’t.
Appropriately or no, if one reasonable meaning of a clause is proven and
sensible, courts are less likely to find ambiguity. First, while courts often
admonish themselves not to “seek” or “create” ambiguity for policy
reasons, more factors go into the decision than the sheer ambiguity of the
word at hand. Second, once a plausible meaning is available, backed with
proof of consistent intent, the mind is less willing to entertain a weaker
alternative as proof of legitimate ambiguity.
95
See Rappaport, supra note 30, at 173. (“The ambiguity rule is probably the
most important rule in insurance law.”).
96
Vlastos v. Sumitomo Marine & Fire Ins. Co., 707 F.2d 775, 776 (3d Cir.
1983) (warranty as to state of building on day policy issued).
97
Id. at 779. The court hypothesizes why having a janitor occupying the floor
would be in the best interest of the insurance company, and states “[a] full-time
resident janitor might also deter prowlers and vandals from entering the building,”
among other reasons. Id.
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 191
101
LA Sound USA, Inc. v. St. Paul Fire & Marine Ins. Co., 67 Cal. Rptr. 3d
917, 924 (Cal. Ct. App. 2007). See, e.g., Hill v. Allstate Ins. Co., No. 04-CV-
0865-REB-CBS, 2006 WL 173693, at *2 (D. Colo. 2006) (Insurer “charged a
premium based on the actuarial risk associated with a one-household [auto]
policy,” and “[a]bsent the fraudulent misrepresentations and concealment” of the
policyholders “it would not have issued and renewed the policy as it did.”). In
L.A. Sound, the court held that the insurer did not need to produce the specific
underwriter who had processed the policyholder’s application. L.A. Sound, 67 Cal.
Rptr. 3d at 924.
102
See CAL. INS. CODE § 791.10 (2006) (Adverse underwriting decisions;
declination, cancellation or nonrenewal of enumerated policies; specific reasons
for decision). Discriminatory underwriting was treated under the McBride-
Grunsky Insurance Regulatory Act of 1947, but repealed by Prop 103. CAL. INS.
CODE § 1861.05 (2009).
103
CAL. INS. CODE § 791.10 (2006).
104
See, e.g., Gonzales v. Pac. Specialty Ins. Co., No. B193051, 2007 WL
2005059 (Cal. Ct. App. July 12, 2007).
105
See, e.g., Mass. Auto. Rating & Accident Prevention Bureau v. Comm’ r,
453 N.E.2d 381 (Mass. 1983) (Action by insurers challenging the Massachusetts
Insurance Commissioner’s establishment of automobile insurance rates).
106
As with most forms of evidence or logical support, courts at times include
a reference to the actuarial function of a clause or policy where the point is not
outcome determinative but merely serves to buttress the court’s conclusion as
doubly right. The non-essential support for a legal outcome is not necessarily
dictum but nor is it always as well-considered as the evidence upon which the
court actively relies. Current judicial use of abstract actuarial principles is more
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 193
the fact that a particular type of coverage can be had for an additional
premium as proof that, in the absence of that premium, the loss is not
covered. Courts may but often do not require the insurer to demonstrate
that the policyholder was aware of the additional coverage for sale. Thus
courts are at times willing to use “inside” insurer information to interpret a
clause despite the information asymmetry between the parties. (Focusing
on a policyholder’s reasonable expectations, ignoring any insurer role in
those expectations, is a more common example of courts using
asymmetrical information, but to the policyholder’s benefit.)
Some courts seem to be open to a more sophisticated use of
actuarial data. If deeds speak louder than words, however, it should be
noted that encouraging language such as this often appears in an opinion
that does not rely upon the data:
If the primary goal is to fulfill the reasonable expectations of the
insured, then there is no need to look at anything beyond the language of
the policy itself. If, on the other hand, the primary goal is to give insureds
what they pay for, then we should, at the very least, be concerned with the
actuarial methods used to arrive at the premium and should look behind the
policy language itself.107
It is an open question whether courts would ever use the same data
to see that an insurer gives no more than he sells. 108
Fourth, in the specific area of uninsured motorist coverage, some
courts have been considering how premiums are calculated in policy
interpretation. In these cases courts look at the structure of the premiums
charged rather than at specific actuarial calculations. The question arises in
likely to fall into this category because a court need not expend much effort to
evaluate these forms of support.
107
Montano v. Allstate Indem. Co., 92 P.3d 1255, 1261-62 (N.M. 2004). The
court went on to “conclude that we need not resolve which rationale to give
primary effect.” Id. at 1262. Other courts have agreed that the “actuarial methods
used to arrive at the premiums [can be] considered to determine whether the
insured gets what he pays for.” Rehders v. Allstate Ins. Co., 135 P.3d 237, 248
(N.M. Ct. App. 2006).
108
In 1934, the Supreme Court expressed a similar sentiment: “While it is
highly important that ambiguous clauses should not be permitted to serve as traps
for policyholders, it is equally important, to the insured as to the insurer, that the
provisions of insurance policies which are clearly and definitely set forth in
appropriate language, and upon which the calculations of the company are based,
should be maintained unimpaired by loose and ill-considered interpretations.”
Williams v. Union Cent. Life Ins. Co., 291 U.S. 170, 180 (1934) (emphasis added).
194 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
109
See Adkins v. Ky. Nat’l Ins. Co., 220 S.W.3d 296, 297 (Ky. Ct. App.
2007).
110
The endorsement page of the policy in Adkins read: “The limit of liability
shown in the Declarations for each person for Uninsured Motorists Coverage is our
maximum limit of liability for all damages ... sustained by any one person in any
one accident.... This is the most we will pay regardless of the number of ...
[v]ehicles shown in the Declarations....” Adkins, 220 S.W.3d at 299. See also
Sturdy v. Allied Mut. Ins. Co., 457 P.2d 34, 42 (Kan. Sup. Ct. 1969) (“When we
pay a double premium we expect double coverage. This is certainly not
unreasonable but, to the contrary, is in accord with general principles of indemnity
that amounts of premiums are based on amounts of liability.”).
111
Adkins, 220 S.W.3d at 300.
112
Id. at 299.
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 195
double that risk to 2R because now both drivers can be on the road at the
same time, although one would have to see the actual data to know.
Adding a third car seems unlikely to raise the risk to 3R, however, even if it
is greater than 2R. (The third car might be correlated with being a higher
risk rather than directly causing the risk to increase, for example if those
who own more than one car per person tend to drive more frequently or
hastily.)
Moreover, the reverse implication of the court’s description is that
the initial per-car premium was not “actuarial.” No doubt the initial
premium charged for one car did reflect the amount necessary for UM
coverage. The shorthand of multiplying that number by additional cars is
not as actuarially precise but nor was it pulled from thin air. Insurers
presumably found that any more elaborate calculation of the risk per added
car was not worth the candle.
This “stacking” question is the one most consistently being
answered with reference to actuarial data. In two exceptionally rare
circumstances, insurance policies refer directly to actuarial data. First,
courts have no choice but to accept actuarial data if the policy is one with a
retrospective premium. “A retrospective premium has two components: a
basic premium and a conversion loss factor to adjust the premium by
consideration of the insured's actual losses during the policy period.”113
Second, in unusual circumstances, actuarial data is incorporated
into the contract.114 Even then, courts will not allow themselves to be
forced to consider data in a policy; courts have shown their willingness to
ignore portions or entire policies that they conclude policyholders could not
113
Hartford Fire Ins. Co. v. Terra Ins. Co., No. CIV.A.01-5961, 2004 WL
1770298 at *2 (E.D. Pa. Aug. 2. 2004). “An insurance policy with retrospectively-
rated premium is sometimes referred to as a form of ‘self-insurance’ because the
policy covers only claims exceeding the maximum premium under the policy.” Id.
See also Douglas R. Richmond, Issues and Problems in “Other Insurance,”
Multiple Insurance, and Self-Insurance, 22 PEPP. L. REV. 1373, 1450 (2002).
114
See, e.g., Conrad v. Ace Property & Cas. Ins. Co., No. CV-05-5117-FVS,
2006 WL 1582376, at *1 (E.D. Wash. 2006) (“The Policy contains the following
definition of ‘Policy’: The agreement between you and us consisting of the
accepted application, these provisions, Special Provisions, actuarial documents,
and the applicable regulations published in 7 C.F.R. chapter IV.”) (emphasis
added)).
196 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
understand. But these examples suggest that judges are able to handle
actuarial data.115
As one of the largest insurance markets in the country (and the
world), California may be a good place to begin the actuarial data
experiment.116 California’s courts often provide a prototype of legal
evolution for other jurisdictions. “Other states may or may not choose to
follow California’s example on a particular issue or principle, but they
certainly note and examine what California does.”117
On the actuarial data front, the California Supreme Court has
repeatedly stated that it will look to “the reasonable expectations of the
insurer and the insured . . . as manifested in the distribution of risks, the
proportionate premiums charged and the coverage for all risks except those
specifically excluded.”118 In a recent decision, a court of appeals held:
No rational insurer would wish to undertake such an insuring
obligation. It would be literally impossible, from an actuarial standpoint,
to set appropriate premiums to guard against the risk that an association
would enter into multimillion-dollar construction contracts, and then not
pay for the construction work. That type of risk would be virtually
impossible to underwrite.119
115
These examples show courts have the ability to handle the data on some
level but in these last three examples, the data are represented in part in the policy
itself. Therefore, these examples are not meant to strongly show that courts are
necessarily inclined to use data more broadly.
116
In California, a search to capture every case that includes the word
“insurance” and some form or either “underwriting” or “actuarial” resulted in close
to 2000 cases. (Westlaw search for “insurance & (underwr! actuar!)”.) More
specific searches were used as well but one extremely broad search proved useful
in locating categories of use.) The majority of these were not relevant to the
question of whether or how California courts currently use the data. Many were
not insurance cases and many simply had citations to common party names that
included the word “underwriters,” such as “Universal Underwriters Ins. Co.” or
“Certain Underwriters of Lloyd’s London.” Some involve the underwriting of
pension plans or other funds that do not involve application of an insurance policy.
117
H. Walter Croskey, The Doctrine of Reasonable Expectations in
California: A Judge’s View, 5 CONN. INS. L.J. 451, 452 n.1 (1998) (“California
insurance jurisprudence has considerable influence on that of other jurisdictions.”).
118
Garvey v. State Farm Fire & Cas. Co., 770 P.2d 704, 711 (Cal. 1989)
(emphasis added).
119
Oak Park Calabasas Condominium. v. State Farm Fire & Cas. Co., 40 Cal.
Rptr. 3d 263, 268 (Cal. Ct. App. 2006) (emphasis added). This approach was
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 197
Although the California courts do not now entertain the data in the
way encouraged here, its use is compatible with the general approach taken
because “[t]he goal is to give effect to the reasonable expectations of both
the insured and the insurer.”120
A. INSURERS
Insurers have voted with their briefs, so to speak, in that they have
access to data and rarely seek to introduce it in court. As I have argued
elsewhere, there is some reason to believe that insurers are resistant to
change.121 Insurers also may assume that courts would not welcome this
development or, and only some will find this plausible, it may be that it has
simply not occurred to insurers to routinely use this type of data in court.122
Based on casual interviews with insurer counsel, I have collected
explanations for why insurers resist the advice of their own counsel that the
use of actuarial data would support an important position. In interviewing
outside counsel I was most interested in cases where the firm lawyer
instigated the idea of using actuarial data and was rebuffed by inside
counsel.123
specifically followed in August Entm’t, Inc. v. Philadelphia Indem. Ins Co., 52 Cal.
Rptr. 3d 908, 914-16 (Cal. Ct. App. 2007).
120
August Entm’t, Inc., 52 Cal. Rptr. 3d at 913 (emphasis added). As with
almost all jurisdictions, the opening move in California is to determine the intent
from the language if possible. California courts are not reticent to move on to
additional inputs, however.
121
See Boardman, supra note 2, at 1116-17.
122
As a lawyer, I would occasionally suggest to in-house insurer counsel that
actuarial data be used to prove a particular point. The resistance I encountered
rested upon some of the reasons discussed below.
123
In a future project I may ask insurers directly, although I would expect to
receive vetted public relations answers.
198 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
Most of the reasons given are not general objections but reasons to
resist the use of actuarial data in certain cases. The approach appears to be
piecemeal rather than a considered policy of always resisting actuarial data.
An insurer who has concluded, on net, that the general use of actuarial data
is not in their interest may of course object to all policyholder attempts to
discover or use it, even in cases where the data could be beneficial.
As expected, sometimes there is no data on point. An outside
counsel suggested backing up an insurer’s claim about an “additional
insured” provision with reference to the data. The insurer response: “There
is no data. We sometimes add ‘additional insureds’ without changing the
premium or putting aside additional reserves;” a fact the insurer did not
want to advertise.124 This does not seem to be an uncommon practice with
additional insured provisions.125
Similarly, there are circumstances where the data would not be
useful because the premium charged does not directly reflect the cost of the
risk but instead reflects interest rates, price competition, (past expected but
not yet incurred losses from past calculations that turned out to be
insufficient), etc. Of course, there are other times when the available
actuarial data just does not speak to the question at hand. In these cases
insurers may not be resistant to the court reading it, if its production were
costless, but they would not seek to introduce it themselves. Given that
production is never costless, an insurer may still object to discovery.
Another common response: “We just don’t refer to actuarial data in
our pleadings and briefs. We never have and nor do our competitors.”126 A
taller objection than inertia: Courts will reject the data but we will be worse
off for having offered it; it creates the impression that in order to
understand our policies a policyholder would need to be an actuary.
Finally, certain applications of actuarial data in the underwriting
process are proprietary. Insurers have moved to quash subpoenas on the
grounds that “materials contain[ing] reserving information and actuarial
124
As with all of these illustrations, this is a paraphrase of the insurer
counsel’s response, not a direct quotation.
125
“In practice, [additional insured] endorsements that are issued
automatically or without charge are usually limited to vicarious liability by express
statement.” James E. Joseph, Indemnification and Insurance: The Risk Shifting
Tools (Part II), PA. B. ASS’N Q. 1, 16 (2009). For a collection of cases in which
courts note that no or little additional premium had been charged for additional
insured coverage, see Note, Recognizing the Unique Status of Additional Names
Insured, 53 FORDHAM L. REV. 117, 120 and n.12 (1984).
126
Again, this is a paraphrase.
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 199
B. POLICYHOLDERS
127
Richter v. Mut. of Omaha Ins. Co., No. 06-Misc.-011, No. CV 05-498
ABC (PJWX), 2006 WL 1277906 at *1 (E.D. Wis. May 5, 2006) (assertion of
privilege deemed waived).
128
See, e.g., Vos v. Farm Bureau Life Ins. Co., 667 N.W.2d 36, 41 (Iowa
2003) (discovery in class action against life insurer for breach of contract and
various fraud claims included “actuarial material regarding the policies in
question”); Frye v. S. Farm Bureau Cas. Ins. Co., 915 So. 2d 486, 490-91 (Miss.
Ct. App. 2005) (denying a policyholder’s motion for discovery of actuarial
information); Robinson v. S. Farm Bureau Cas. Co., 915 So. 2d 516, 520 (Miss.
Ct. App. 2005) (denying a claim by policyholder plaintiffs that “alleged in their
motion for continuance that [the insurer] Southern Farm failed to respond to
written discovery concerning the historical makeup and actuarial composition of
the disability income coverage.”); Beller v. William Penn Life Ins. Co. of N.Y.,
828 N.Y.S.2d 869, 875 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 2007) (actuarial data about life insurance
plan sought and obtained in class action).
129
Note that in considering the benign or evil motives of each player, this last
does not require a dark view. There are policyholders who would prefer their
200 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
Apart from wanting to use specific data that support their view and
exclude data that do not, the increased use of actuarial data should help
policyholders in general across time. Start with the arguable but
contentious assumption that insurers tend to offer the coverage the market
demands. This does not mean that insurance coverage is a wonderland for
consumers. Some coverage that policyholders would like to purchase is
not sold because policyholders are not willing to pay the minimum price
insurers demand. Some coverage is not sold because insurers are not
willing to insure the type of event. To maintain risk distribution in the risk
pool, insurers do not want to sell coverage for correlated large losses, such
as flood coverage in a flood plain. For reasons of public policy, moral
hazard, and adverse selection, insurers limit other options that individual
policyholders desire.
If there are sound actuarial reasons to limit coverage, the limitation
is generally to the benefit of insurers and policyholders. Courts can make a
mistake when they interfere with these types of insurer choices. They do
make a mistake when they choose the needs of one plaintiff policyholder
over all other policyholders. Actuarial data can improve the decision-
making of courts inclined to regulate.
C. COURTS
insurance to cover a loss but who read the policy to exclude it and who thus do not
sue. A particularly rosy view would be required to assume that every policyholder
in court firmly believes in the accuracy of their interpretation, but many no doubt
do. Likewise, insurers pursuing no or low coverage positions in court is not proof
that all insurers deny all claims all the time; if the insurer pays what the
policyholder expects, or close to it, there is no need for court.
2009] RISK DATA IN INSURANCE INTERPRETATION 201
would be hindered in its ability to serve the important function it does in our
society.” Hartzo v. American Nat. Property. & Cas. Ins. Co., 951 So. 2d 1120,
1124 (La. Ct. App. 2006).
133
James C. Hickman & Robert B. Miller, Insurance Premiums and Decision
Analysis, 37 J. OF RISK AND INS. 567, 568 (1970).
134
See supra Section III.
THE LAW AND ECONOMICS OF
FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY
Sharon Tennyson *
William J. Warfel**
***
***
*
Sharon Tennyson is Associate Professor in the Department of Policy
Analysis and Management at Cornell University. She holds a Ph.D. in economics
from Northwestern University with a specialization in industrial organization and
regulation. Her professional interest centers on economic and policy analysis of
insurance markets, and she has published widely on these topics. Sharon is a noted
expert on insurance rate regulation and insurance fraud, and is a frequent speaker
on these issues.
**
William J. Warfel, Ph.D., CPCU, CLU, is Professor of Insurance and Risk
Management at Indiana State University. He received his doctorate from Indiana
University in 1990. His research focuses largely on the interface of law and
insurance; he has published extensively in the CPCU eJournal, The John Liner
Review, Risk Management Magazine, and various legal publications. Also, to
date, he has been retained as a testifying and consulting expert witness in about 45
cases; his specialty includes breach of contract, bad faith, and agent/broker liability
issues. He can be reached at [email protected].
204 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
I. INTRODUCTION
1
See Hadley v. Baxendale, (1854) 156 Eng. Rep. 145 (Exch. Div.).
2
See id.
3
4 NAT’L ASS’N OF INS. COMM’RS, MODEL LAWS, REGULATIONS, AND
GUIDELINES: UNFAIR TRADE PRACTICES ACT (2008).
4
Id. See also Laureen Regan & Paul M. Rettinger, Private Rights of Action
Under State Unfair Claims Settlement Practices Acts: A Review, J. INS. REG.
(1998) (identifies all 14 of the prohibited acts). This model legislation, or some
variant of it, has been adopted by all U.S. states. Efforts to expand first-party bad
faith liability continue today. In Connecticut, for example, a proposal has been
made to delete the requirement that violations occur with such frequency as to
indicate a general business practice. If this proposal is adopted, a single violation
would be sufficient to constitute bad faith.
5
Regan & Rettinger, supra note 4, at 298.
6
See Allen v. State Farm Fire & Cas. Co., 59 F. Supp. 2d 1217, 1227 (S.D.
Ala. 1999) (“[P]laintiffs should follow the procedure for review required by the
2009] FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY 205
insurance code and first seek relief from the insurance department and the
insurance commissioner.”).
7
510 P.2d 1032 (Cal. 1973).
8
See id.
9
See SHARON TENNYSON & WILLIAM J. WARFEL, NAT’L ASS’N OF MUT. INS.
COS., ISSUE ANALYSIS: FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY: LAW,
THEORY, AND ECONOMIC CONSEQUENCES 3 (Sept. 2008) available at
www.namic.org/insbriefs/080926BadFaith.pdf.
10
Id. at 3.
11
Id.
12
Id.
13
RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS §§ 901, 903 (1979).
14
Id. § 908.
15
See Beck v. Farmers Ins. Exch., 701 P.2d 795, 801-02 (Utah 1985).
16
BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY 416 (8th ed. 2004).
206 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
parties at the time the contract was made).17 “Consequential damages may
reach beyond the strict contract terms and include prejudgment interest and
legal expenses, and damages for economic loss and mental distress.”18
However, “an independent tort such as fraud or intentional infliction of
emotional distress must be alleged in order to make a claim for punitive
damages.”19
Statute: The right to file a private cause of action alleging bad faith
is based on statute and judicial recognition of an implied, private cause of
action under an Unfair Trade Practices Act that includes an unfair claim
settlement practices provision.20 Damages may include prejudgment
interest and legal expenses, consequential, or incidental, damages for
economic loss and mental distress. With a few notable exceptions,21 in
states that have adopted a statutory approach to first-party insurance bad
faith, punitive damages are not permitted.22 Or, if punitive damages are
permitted, a cap is placed on such damages and/or the standard of conduct
for awarding such damages is very stringent and thus the exposure to
punitive damages is minimal.23
A majority of states that recognize first-party insurance bad faith
allow actions under tort law. The tort of bad faith is a unique application of
tort law because it applies despite the existence of a contract, and does not
require the policyholder to allege a traditional tort such as fraud or
intentional infliction of emotional distress in order to recover punitive
damages. Relative to other bad faith liability regimes, the tort of bad faith
increases both the potential damages and the uncertainty of judgments for
insurance companies. Thus, the legal basis for a first-party insurance bad
faith allegation determines the realistic potential for a punitive damages
17
Id. at 417.
18
Tennyson & Warfel, supra note 9, at 3.
19
Id.
20
See CONN. GEN. STAT. ANN. §§ 38a-816, 42-110q (West 1995).
21
Pennsylvania statutory law recognizes private actions for first-party
insurance bad faith, and authorizes punitive damages. 42 PA. CONS. STAT. ANN §
8371 (West 2006). The state of Washington recently adopted a bad faith statute that
allows punitive damages awards under a standard similar to that in many tort-based
regimes. WASH. REV. CODE ANN. § 48.30.010 (West 1998).
22
See generally Mark J. Browne, et. al., The Effect of Bad Faith Laws on
First-Party Insurance Claims Decisions, 33 J. LEGAL STUDIES 355, 355-390
(2004).
23
Id.
2009] FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY 207
24
At least eleven states have embraced the negligence standard for first-party
bad faith claims. These states include Alaska (State Farm Fire & Cas. Co. v.
Nicholson, 777 P.2d 1152 (Alaska 1989)); California (Gruenberg v. Aetna Ins.
Co., 510 P.2d 1032 (Cal. 1973)); Connecticut (Grand Sheet Metal Prods. Co. v.
208 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
1. Negligence Standard
Protective Mut. Ins. Co., 375 A.2d 428 (Conn. Super. Ct. 1977)); Hawaii (Best
Place, Inc. v. Penn Am. Ins. Co., 920 P.2d 334 (Haw. 1996)); Nevada (Hart v.
Prudential Prop. & Cas. Ins. Co., 848 F. Supp. 900 (D. Nev. 1994)); North Dakota
(Seifert v. Farmers Union Mut. Ins. Co., 497 N.W.2d 694 (N.D. 1993)); Ohio
(Hoskins v. Aetna Life Ins. Co., 452 N.E.2d 1315 (Ohio 1983)); Oklahoma
(Christian v. Am. Home Assur. Co., 577 P.2d 899 (Okla. 1977)); South Carolina
(Nichols v. State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co., 306 S.E.2d 616 (S.C. 1983)); Texas
(Arando v. Ins. Co. of N. Am., 748 S.W.2d 210 (Tex. 1988)); and Washington
(Griffin v. Allstate Ins. Co., 29 P.3d 777 (Wash. Ct. App. 2001), review denied, 45
P.3d 551 (Wash. 2002)).
25
At least fourteen states have embraced the intentional tort standard for
first-party bad faith claims. These states include Alabama (Chavers v. Nat'l Sec.
Fire & Cas. Co., 405 So. 2d 1 (Ala. 1981)); Colorado (Herod v. Colo. Farm Bureau
Mut. Ins. Co., 928 P.2d 834 (Colo. App. 1996)); Idaho (Robinson v. State Farm
Mut. Auto. Ins. Co., 45 P.3d 829 (Idaho 2002)); Indiana (Erie Ins. Co. v. Hickman,
622 N.E.2d 515 (Ind. 1993)); Iowa (Dolan v. Aid Ins. Co., 431 N.W.2d 790 (Iowa
1993)); Kentucky (Wittmer v. Jones, 864 S.W.2d 885 (Ky. 1993)); Mississippi
(Universal Life Ins. Co. v. Veasley, 610 So. 2d 290 (Miss. 1992)); Nebraska
(Braesch v. Union Ins. Co., 464 N.W.2d 769 (Neb. 1991)); New Mexico (Chavez
v. Chenoweth, 553 P.2d 703 (N.M. Ct. App. 1976)); Rhode Island (Zarrella v.
Minn. Mut. Life Ins. Co., 824 A.2d 1249 (R.I. 2003)); South Dakota (Stene v.
State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co., 583 N.W.2d 399 (S.D. 1998)); Vermont (Bushey
v. Allstate Ins. Co., 670 A.2d 807 (Vt. 1995)); Wisconsin (Anderson v. Cont'l Ins.
Co., 271 N.W.2d 368 (Wis. 1978)); and Wyoming (Hulse v. First Am. Title Co.,
33 P.3d 122 (Wyo. 2001)).
26
Aetna Cas. & Sur. v. Broadway Arms Corp., 664 S.W.2d 463 (Ark. 1984).
See JEFFREY W. STEMPEL, STEMPEL ON INS. CONTRACTS 10-87 (3d ed. 2009)
(1994). According to Stempel, “[t]o appreciate the differences across the states
concerning insurer bad faith, one must pay attention to the nuances of precedent
and doctrine, which tend to be glossed over in any classification….” Id. For this
reason, legal scholars often disagree on occasion over whether a particular state has
adopted the “negligence” standard or the “intentional tort” standard in first-party
cases.
27
See Comunale v. Traders & Gen. Ins. Co., 328 P.2d 198 (Cal. 1958).
2009] FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY 209
28
See id.
29
Id. at 200-201 (citing Ivy v. Pac. Auto. Ins. Co., 320 P.2d 140 (Cal.
1958)).
30
See Gruenberg, 510 P.2d at 1032; Margaret Cronin Fisk, Looking for a
New Cause of Action?, NAT'L L. J., May 19, 1997, at A1.
31
See Brief for Am. Ins. Ass'n et al. as Amici Curiae Supporting Appellant,
St. Paul Fire & Marine Ins. Co. v. Onvia, Inc., 196 P.3d 664 (Wash. 2008) (No.
80359-5), 2009 WL 907292.
32
Tennyson & Warfel, supra note 9, at 4.
33
See id.; see STEMPEL, supra note 26, at 10-38.
34
510 P.2d 1032 (Cal. 1973).
35
Id. at 1038.
36
Id. at 1034.
210 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
37
Id.
38
Id.
39
Id. at 1035.
40
See Gruenberg, 510 P.2d at 1035.
41
Id.
42
Id.
43
Id.
44
Id. at 1036.
45
Id. at 1037.
46
Gruenberg, 510 P.2d at 1037.
47
Id. The California court did address the issue pertaining to recovery for
mental distress. Given that the policyholder alleged substantial economic losses
(e.g., loss of earnings, loss associated with bankruptcy) apart from damages for
mental distress, the policyholder was entitled to make a claim for mental distress.
Generally, when a policyholder substantially prevails in a first-party claim against
2009] FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY 211
3. Quasi-Criminal Standard
53
Id. at 379.
54
Anderson, 271 N.W.2d at 379.
55
See Aetna Cas. & Sur. v. Broadway Arms Corp., 664 S.W.2d 463 (Ark.
1984). Arkansas is the only state that has embraced the quasi-criminal standard.
This standard was upheld in Columbia Nat’l Ins. Co. v. Freeman, 64 S.W.3d 720
(Ark. 2002). In this particular case, which involved a property insurer, the court
held that the conduct of the insurer must be carried out with a state of mind
characterized by hatred, ill will, or a spirit of revenge.
56
Broadway Arms, 664 S.W.2d at 464.
57
Id. at 469.
58
Id. at 465-66.
59
Id. at 470.
2009] FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY 213
60
Id. at 467.
61
Id. at 466.
62
Broadway Arms, 664 S.W.2d at 466 (citing ARK. STAT. ANN. § 66-3005(9)
(current version at ARK. CODE ANN. § 23-66-206(13) (2009))).
63
Id. at 467.
64
Id. at 468.
65
ARK. STAT. ANN. §§ 66-3001–3014 (current version at ARK. CODE ANN.
§§ 23-66-201–215 (2009)).
66
Broadway Arms, 664 S.W.2d at 469.
67
Id. at 468.
214 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
68
Beck v. Farmers Ins. Exch., 701 P.2d 795 (Utah 1985). At least six states
have embraced the contract standard for first-party bad faith claims. These states
include Maine (Marquis v. Farm Family Mut. Ins. Co., 628 A.2d 644 (Me. 1993));
Maryland (Johnson v. Fed. Kemper Ins. Co., 536 A.2d 1211 (Md. Ct. Spec. App.
1987)); New York (Bi-Econ. Mkt., Inc. v. Harleysville Ins. Co., 886 N.E.2d 127
(N.Y. 2008)); Oregon (Nw. Pump & Equip. Co. v. Am. States Ins. Co., 925 P.2d
1241 (Or. 1996)) and Virginia (A & E Supply Co. v. Nationwide Mut. Fire Ins.
Co., 798 F.2d 669 (4th Cir. 1986) (interpreting Virginia law), cert. denied, 479
U.S. 1091 (1987)).
69
Beck, 701 P.2d at 796-97.
70
Id. at 801.
71
Id.
72
Id. at 800-801.
73
Id. at 799.
2009] FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY 215
74
See CONN. GEN. STAT. §§ 38a-816, 42-110q (2009).
75
See, e.g., FLA. STAT. ANN. § 624.155(1)(b)(1) (West 2004).
76
See, e.g., MICH. COMP. LAWS SERV. § 500.3148(1) (LexisNexis 2001).
77
See, e.g., Maher v. Cont’l Cas. Co., 76 F.3d 535 (4th Cir. 1999) (applying
West Virginia law).
78
MINN. STAT. ANN. § 604.18 (West 2008).
216 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
reasonable basis for denying the benefits of the insurance policy.79 The law
allows policyholders to be awarded up to $250,000 in “taxable costs” if an
insurer is found to be acting in bad faith and up to $100,000 in attorney's
fees, but specifically precludes punitive damages in the absence of an
independent tort such as fraud or intentional infliction of emotional
distress.80
Recent Colorado legislation lowered the legal standard for
asserting a first-party bad faith claim and increased the penalties levied
against an insurer, relative to existing common law.81 The new legislation
adopts the negligence standard, whereas the intentional tort standard
applies under common law.82 In addition, under common law,
consequential, or incidental, damages for economic loss and mental distress
can be recovered, but the cost of litigation cannot be recovered.83 The new
legislation allows for the recovery of the cost of litigation and caps the
damages award at two times the policy benefit that was unreasonably
denied.84
Recent first-party insurance bad-faith legislation in Maryland85
applies exclusively to property/casualty insurance policies and allows
policyholders to initiate bad-faith claims through the Maryland Insurance
Administration (MIA), the state agency responsible for enforcing
Maryland’s insurance laws.86 The new law adopts the negligence standard
and caps damages the insured can recover at the policy limit.87 In addition,
it provides for recovery of pre-judgment interest and allows recovery of
attorney’s fees, but limits the recoverable amount to one third of the actual
79
§ 604.18(2)-(3).
80
§ 604.18(3)
81
COLO. REV. STAT. § 10-3-1113 (2008).
82
Id.
83
See Am. Family. Mut. Ins. Co. v. Allen, 102 P.3d 333, 342 (Colo. 2004)
(applying Colorado common law).
84
COLO. REV. STAT. §§ 10-3-1116 & 10-16-106.5. Moreover, the new
legislation imposes a special penalty on health insurers that unreasonably delay the
payment of the policy benefit (i.e., the penalty is 20 percent of the policy benefit,
the payment of which was delayed 90 days or longer past the submission of the
claim).
85
MD. CODE ANN., [INS.] § 27-1001(e)(2)(i) – (ii) (West 2006).
86
The law does not apply to claims that fall under the small-claims
jurisdiction of district courts or to commercial insurance policies with policy limits
exceeding $1 million.
87
§§ 27-303(9) & 27-305(c)(2).
2009] FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY 217
88
§ 27-305(4).
89
§ 27-305(3)(1)-(2).
90
WASH. REV. CODE ANN. § 48.30.010.
91
§ 19.86.090 Washington common law provides for the tort of bad faith
with a negligence standard, and the Consumer Protection Act provides for recovery
of actual damages sustained, the cost of litigation, and treble damages, subject to a
cap of $10,000 in the event the insurer violates a claims handling regulation.
92
Id. The specific unfair claims settlement practices covered by the
legislation include misrepresentation of policy provisions, failure to acknowledge
pertinent communications, failure to meet standards for prompt investigation of
claims, and failure to meet standards for prompt, fair, and equitable settlements
applicable to all insurers.
218 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
policyholders for their unwarranted losses; but it may also serve the
broader economic purpose of enhancing the efficiency of insurance
contracting. In competitive insurance markets, systematic bad faith in
claim settlement practices will reduce demand for insurance from a
company that engages in such practices. However, reputation penalties
may not be sufficient to guarantee that an insurer will never have an
incentive to engage in intentional bad faith claim settlement practices. Nor
can reputation penalties guarantee that an insurer will never engage in
behaviors that lead to unintentional bad faith denial of a claim settlement.93
An isolated example of intentional bad faith would include, for
example, if an insurer strategically denies or delays the settlement of a
particularly large insurance claim for the purpose of coercing the
policyholder to accept a reduced claim settlement.94 Market sanctions
alone may not deter this kind of behavior, because the potential cost
savings on the claim could outweigh the cost of reputation penalties meted
out in the market in the form of reduced demand for insurance. In such
cases, the potential for tort litigation creates an incentive for an insurer to
avoid unwarranted strategic denial or delay of a claim settlement, by
imposing a potentially large financial penalty for such conduct.95 Indeed,
the mere threat of substantial extra contractual liability will reduce the
incentive for an insurer to strategically deny or delay a claim settlement.
Most importantly, because a practical mechanism does not exist for an
93
See Joseph M. Belth, Two Recent Court Decisions Critical of UNUM’s
Disability Insurance Claims Practices, THE INS. FORUM, Mar. 2009, at 161.
Perhaps the classic case that demonstrates this point concerns disability insurance
claim settlement practices implemented by several operating companies of the
UNUM Group. These companies implemented a “claims management
philosophy” in 1993; previously these companies had a “claims payment
philosophy.” Various claim settlement practices used to deny, terminate, and settle
disability insurance claims resulted in numerous lawsuits alleging bad faith. The
volume of lawsuits was such that they resulted in widespread media attention, two
far-reaching regulatory probes, and eventual settlements with regulatory authorities
under which UNUM agreed to reassess some denied claims and improve claim
procedures. While the settlements did not include an admission to the effect that a
statute or regulation had been violated, UNUM did agree to pay a $15 million fine
divided among 49 jurisdictions that had signed on to the settlements. Id.
94
Alan O. Sykes, “Bad Faith” Breach of Contract by First-Party Insurers,
25 J. OF LEGAL STUD. 405, 412-13 (1996).
95
Id. See also KENNETH S. ABRAHAM, DISTRIBUTING RISK: INSURANCE,
LEGAL THEORY, AND PUBLIC POLICY 183-85 (1986).
2009] FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY 219
96
Sykes, supra note 94, at 429.
97
For example, the soil was improperly compacted when the sewer lines
were laid.
98
Sykes, supra note 94, at 425-26.
99
Id. at 426.
220 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
policyholder conspired with a friend to set the fire, notwithstanding the fact
that a jury ultimately ruled that the friend acted alone in setting the fire.
With respect to some coverage disputes, further claim investigation
can be helpful in enabling the insurer to reach the correct conclusion
concerning the existence or non-existence of coverage. With respect to
other coverage disputes, however, further claim investigation is not viable
because of cost considerations or factual issues that simply cannot be
resolved.100 In these cases, the discovery process attendant to litigation
may be the best mechanism for bringing a claim to resolution.101 For
example, if an insurer reaches the conclusion that further claim
investigation is not viable, the insurer may offer a nuisance settlement even
though it believes that coverage does not exist.
In the case of suspected fraud, if we assume that it is more costly
for a policyholder to pursue a fraudulent claim than a valid claim, a
policyholder with a fraudulent claim will be less likely to persist in the face
of a claim denial than a policyholder with a valid claim.102 This fact implies
that costly litigation may be used as a screening device by insurers for the
purpose of sorting valid claims from fraudulent ones. For this reason, even
though the denial of a claim may lead to litigation, an insurer may find that
the denial of some fraction of suspicious claims is efficient.103 The benefit
of this approach for the insurer is that a policyholder pursuing a fraudulent
claim may drop it rather than engage in costly litigation; policyholders with
legitimate claims will be more likely to pursue the litigation.104 While
some policyholders needlessly suffer because they are forced to litigate
legitimate claims, policyholders as a group benefit from this approach
because it minimizes unwarranted claim costs and results in reduced
insurance premiums.105 In specifying a claims denial fraction, the insurer
will balance the expected reduction in claims fraud with the expected costs
of litigating denied claims.
A similar claims settlement dynamic may occur if we consider the
insurer’s decision regarding the amount of payment, rather than the
decision regarding claim denial. Again, in cases where establishing the
complete truth through investigation is not practical, and assuming that the
100
Id.
101
Id. at 425-29.
102
Id. at 428.
103
Id.
104
Sykes, supra note 94, at 428.
105
Id. at 426-27.
2009] FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY 221
106
Keith J. Crocker & Sharon Tennyson, Insurance Fraud and Optimal
Claims Settlement Strategies, 45 J.L. & ECON. 469, 470 (2002).
107
Id. at 504.
108
Id. at 472-73.
109
Id. at 475.
110
Similar arguments can be made regarding insurers’ claim settlement
strategies for claims disputes centering on contractual language or factual disputes
not involving suspected fraud.
111
Crocker & Tennyson, supra note 106, at 504-505.
222 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
112
See Sykes, supra note 94.
113
ABRAHAM, supra note 95, at 184.
114
Id.
115
Id.
116
Id.
2009] FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY 223
117
Picard provides an excellent discussion of the theoretical literature on
insurance fraud. See Pierre Picard, Economic Analysis of Insurance Fraud, in
HANDBOOK OF INSURANCE 337, 339 (Georges Dionne ed., 2000).
118
See id. at 337.
119
Sykes, supra note 94, at 407-408.
120
See T.D.S. Inc. v. Shelby Mut. Ins. Co., 760 F.2d 1520, 1527-29 (11th
Cir. 1985); Capstick v. Allstate Ins. Co., 998 F.2d 810, 815-16 (10th Cir. 1993).
121
See Aetna Life Ins. Co. v. Lavioe, 475 U.S. 813, 823 (1986).
122
See id. and Nationwide Mut. Ins. Co. v. Clay, 525 So. 2d 1339, 1342,
1344 (Ala. 1989).
123
See Silberg v. Cal. Life Ins. Co., 521 P.2d 1103, 1112 (Cal. 1974); Sparks
v. Republic Nat’l Life Ins. Co., 647 P.2d 1127, 1137 (Ariz. 1982).
224 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
124
Sykes, supra note 94, at 405.
125
Id. at 443.
126
Mark J. Browne et al., The Effect of Bad-Faith Laws on First-Party
Insurance Claims Decisions, 33 J. LEGAL STUD. 355, 357 (2004). These authors
study uninsured and underinsured motorist claims using data compiled by the
Insurance Research Council from a survey of closed claims obtained from
insurance companies.
127
Id. at 386.
128
ANGELA HAWKEN ET AL., RAND INST. FOR CIVIL JUSTICE, PUB. NO. MR-
1199-ICJ, THE EFFECTS OF THIRD-PARTY, BAD FAITH DOCTRINE ON AUTOMOBILE
INSURANCE COSTS AND COMPENSATION 49-53 (2001) (analyzing the impact of
Royal Globe Ins. Co. v. Super. Ct., 592 P.2d 329 (Cal. 1979)). In this landmark
case, the California Supreme Court held that third-party claimants may sue insurers
for violating the Unfair Claim Settlement Practices Act. Id. Ultimately, this
decision was overruled in Moradi-Shalal v. Fireman’s Fund Ins. Co., 758 P.2d 58
(Cal. 1988).
129
HAWKEN, supra note 128, at 49-50.
130
Id. at 49.
2009] FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY 225
B. THE DATA
131
See Insurance Research Council Home Page, http://www.ircweb.org. The
IRC is an independent, not-for-profit organization founded in 1977, and it is
supported by leading property-casualty insurance organizations, including
property-casualty insurance carriers and trade associations that represent property-
casualty insurance carriers. Its purpose is to provide timely and reliable
information that examines public policy issues affecting property-casualty insurers,
their customers and the general public. The IRC is devoted solely to research and
the communication of its research findings to interested parties; it does not
advocate for property-casualty insurers on public policy issues as such.
132
Browne, supra note 126, at 360-61.
133
Overall, 76.3 percent of accidents in the dataset occur in 1996-1997, 21.9
percent of accidents occur in 1993-1995 and 1.8 percent of accidents in the dataset
occur prior to 1993.
2009] FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY 227
2. Claim Characteristics
134
See Herbert I. Weisberg & Richard A. Derrig, Fraud and Automobile
Insurance: A Report on Bodily Injury Claims in Massachusetts, 9 J. INS. REG. 523,
534 (1991); Herbert I. Weisberg & Richard A. Derrig, Detection de la Fraude:
Methodes Quantitatives, 35 RISQUES 75-99 (1998) (in English translation).
135
See, e.g., Weisberg & Derrig, supra note 134, at 523.
136
Id. at 534.
137
See Georges Dionne & Pierre St-Michel, Workers' Compensation and
Moral Hazard, 73 REV. ECON. & STAT. 236, 238-39 (1991).
138
See, e.g., Weisberg & Derrig, supra note 134, at 534, 537.
139
Id. at 534, 536.
228 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
3. Claim Investigations
140
Weisberg & Derrig, supra note 134, at III.1.
141
Id.
142
We omit claims for which the accident state or the accident date is
missing. We also omit claims that arise in Pennsylvania, Montana, Puerto Rico and
the Virgin Islands because of ambiguities surrounding the treatment of first part
bad faith claims in these states and territories.
143
STEMPEL, supra note 26, at 10-3 to 10-20; BARRY R. OSTRAGER &
THOMAS R. NEWMAN, HANDBOOK ON INSURANCE COVERAGE DISPUTES 990-1012
(14th ed. 2008) (1988); GENRE & EDWARDS ANGELL PALMER & DODGE LLP, BAD
FAITH LAWS FOR PROPERTY/CASUALTY CLAIMS (2008).
144
Id.
2009] FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY 229
tort-based bad faith actions for a portion of the sample period.145 Seven
states permitted contract-based bad faith actions during the entire sample
period,146 and 2 states permitted contract-based bad faith actions for a
portion of the sample period.147 First-party bad faith actions were
permitted by statute in 5 states during the entire sample period;148 first-
party bad faith actions were not permitted in 4 states during the entire
sample period;149 and first-party bad faith actions were not authorized by
either statute or legal precedent in 4 states during the entire sample
period.150
Table 1 displayed below indicates the number of claims in the
dataset that were filed under each of the bad faith regimes. The majority of
claims in the dataset stem from accidents in states that permit tort actions
for first-party bad faith.
145
Id.
146
Id.
147
Id.
148
Id.
149
STEMPEL, supra note 26, at 10-3 to 10-20; OSTRAGER & NEWMAN, supra
note 143, at 990-1012; GENRE & EDWARDS ANGELL PALMER & DODGE LLP, supra
note 143.
150
Id.
230 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
The first two columns of the table report mean values of variables
in states that permit bad-faith actions and states that do not, respectively.
The third column of the table reports t-statistics and significance levels for
comparisons of the means across the two sets of states. The t-statistics
provide a test of whether the differences in means across these groups of
states are significantly different from zero at the one percent (***), five
percent (**) or ten percent (*) confidence level.
The comparisons reveal significant differences in claim
characteristics in states that permit bad faith actions. We observe that
police verification of accidents is less prevalent for claims in states that
permit bad faith actions; police are less likely to be at the scene of the
accident, and accidents are less likely to be the subject of a police report, as
compared to other states. Specifically, 80.9 percent of claims paid have a
police report from the scene of the accident in states that permit bad faith
while this is true for 85.5 percent of claims paid in states that do not permit
232 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
bad faith actions. The right hand columns of the table confirm that the
differences are statistically significant.
Claims that involve no visible injury at the scene of the accident
are more prevalent in bad-faith states (68.1 percent) than in states with no
bad faith (55.6 percent). Claims in bad-faith states are more likely to
involve a sprain injury (by a margin of 83.3 percent to 76.9 percent).
Similarly, sprain injuries are more likely to be the most severe injury
experienced in bad-faith states (66.6 percent in bad-faith states compared to
58.6 percent in states with no bad faith). All of these differences are
statistically significant, as indicated in the right hand column of the table.
The use of chiropractors by injured policyholders is about the same
across the two sets of states, as is the number of chiropractor visits, and the
differences are not statistically significant. However, the proportion of the
total claimed amount that arises from chiropractor care is larger in bad-faith
states (23.5 percent) compared to states with no bad faith (16.0 percent),
and this difference is statistically significant.
The data also suggest differences in insurer investments in claim
investigation in states that permit bad-faith actions relative to investigations
in other states. Insurers faced with potential bad-faith actions are more
likely to conduct a medical audit (36.7 percent of claims versus 26.1
percent of claims in states with no bad faith actions), and this difference is
statistically significant. However, this result is entirely due to a greater
propensity to conduct in-house medical audits. Insurers in bad-faith states
are slightly less likely to invest in external medical audits than in other
states (although the difference is not statistically significant). This greater
use of in-house medical audits may indicate greater investments in claim
processing bureaucracy so that a defense can be mounted in the event of a
bad-faith lawsuit.
The above interpretation is reinforced by the fact that the potential
for a bad faith claim has the opposite effect on insurers’ IME use; the
proportion of claims for which insurers request an IME is only 6.6 percent
in states that permit bad faith actions, while it is 26.3 percent in states with
no bad faith. This difference is both large and statistically significant.
Because an IME requires the notification and cooperation of the
policyholder, insurers may be particularly reluctant to undertake this type
of investigation when faced with the potential for bad-faith lawsuits. Such
is the case because an IME may lead to an allegation that the insurer
unnecessarily engaged in delay tactics with respect to resolution of the
claim so as to coerce a reduced claim settlement.
Because there are important differences in legal standards and
potential damage awards across different legal regimes for insurance bad
2009] FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY 233
faith, we also separately compare claims filed under tort-based bad faith
regimes to those filed under non-tort-based regimes (contract-based or
statute-based), and to those filed in states that do not recognize first-party
bad faith. Table 3 presents the results of these comparisons.
1. Robustness Checks
The table shows the same general results as the comparisons based
on all claims in the database. Indeed, the comparisons of claims in the
third quarter follow the exact patterns of signs and statistical significance as
those for the full sample of claims. For the smaller claims (those in the
second quarter) there are some differences from the full sample. Most
notable is that there are no significant differences in injury characteristics
(visible injuries, prevalence of sprain) across states with tort-based bad
faith and other states. This suggests that the relevant difference in claim
characteristics is the greater prevalence of large-valued claims that involve
sprain injuries in states with tort-based bad faith, consistent with the
hypothesis that claim exaggeration may be more prevalent in those states.
Overall, it appears from the table that differences in claim size across states
with different bad faith regimes is not the determining factor in explaining
238 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
151
To more fully account for this issue, additional investigations were
undertaken using a logistic regression approach that can account for the clustering
of claims by state. Like the t-tests, this approach analyzes whether different bad
faith regimes are associated with significantly different mean values of each
relevant claim characteristic, but takes into account that claims occur within a state
and the bad faith regime varies only by state and not for each claim. Thus,
clustering by state reduces the likelihood that differences across bad faith regimes
are statistically significant, by allowing for the possibility that variable values are
correlated across claims within each state. Nonetheless, the results of this analysis
remain generally consistent with the t-test results, and are most similar to the t-test
results for the sample omitting the state of California. Claim injury characteristics
remain statistically significant and higher in tort-based states, and insurer
investigations also remain statistically significant and of the same signs as in the t-
test analysis. Police presence and police reports and use of chiropractic treatments
become statistically insignificant in the logistic regression analysis.
152
Browne, supra note 126, at 360-61; HAWKEN, supra note 128.
2009] FIRST-PARTY INSURANCE BAD FAITH LIABILITY 239
The results for the sample which omits claims settled under a no-
fault regime are extremely similar to results obtained from the full sample
of states: the signs and statistical significance of all variables remain the
same. This confirms that the automobile accident compensation regime is
not the determining factor in explaining differences in claim characteristics
and claim investigations.
In contrast, results for the sample from which California claims are
omitted differ from previous comparisons in several ways. Most notable
are the changes in sign for the police report and chiropractor use variables.
In the sample without California, police are more likely to be at the
accident scene and to submit a report of the accident in states with tort-
based bad faith than in other states. The percent of claim costs stemming
from chiropractor use is also smaller in tort-based bad faith states than in
other states, once California is omitted from the sample. Thus it appears
that these claim characteristics may be prevalent in California rather than in
states with tort-based bad faith more generally. On the other hand, several
of the comparisons without California remain statistically significant and
consistent with the findings for the full sample of states. Claims with no
visible injury at the accident scene and claims in which the worst injury is a
sprain remain significantly more prevalent in states with tort-based bad
240 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
V. CONCLUSION
relationship between bad faith liability standards and the insurance claim
settlement process would be useful.
242 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
Appendix Table
State First-Party Bad Faith Regimes for Sample Period of Claims Data
State First Party Bad Faith Law State First Party Bad Faith Law
Alaska Tort Actions Mississippi Tort Actions
Alabama Tort Actions Nebraska Tort Actions
Arkansas Tort Actions New Hampshire Contract Law Actions
Arizona Tort Actions New Jersey Tort Actions (until 1993)
California Tort Actions Contract Law Actions (since 1993)
Colorado Tort Actions New Mexico Tort Actions
Connecticut Tort Actions Nevada Tort Actions
District of Columbia No Private Actions Defined New York No Private Actions Allowed
Delaware Tort Actions (until 1995); North Carolina Tort Actions
Contract Law Actions (since 1995) North Dakota Tort Actions
Florida Statutory Actions Ohio Tort Actions
Georgia Statutory Actions Oklahoma Tort Actions
Hawaii No Private Actions Defined Oregon Contract Law Actions
Iowa Tort Actions Rhode Island Tort Actions
Idaho Tort Actions South Carolina Tort Actions
Illinois Tort Actions South Dakota No Private Actions Defined
Indiana Tort Actions (since 1993) Tennessee Statutory Actions
Kansas No Private Actions Allowed Texas Tort Actions
Kentucky Tort Actions Utah Contract Law Actions
Louisiana Statutory Actions Virginia Contract Law Actions
Massachusetts Statutory Actions Vermont Tort Actions
Maryland Contract Law Actions Washington Tort Actions (since 1992)
Maine Contract Law Actions Wisconsin Tort Actions
Michigan No Private Actions Allowed West Virginia Contract Law Actions
Minnesota No Private Actions Allowed Wyoming Tort Actions (since 1990)
Missouri No Private Actions Defined
Source: Authors' calculations from GenRe (2008), Stempel (2006) and Ostrager and Newman (2008).
Note: The sample period includes years 1986 through 1997.
REGULATION OF LARGE FINANCIAL INSTITUTIONS:
LESSONS FROM CORPORATE FINANCE THEORY
John P. Harding*
Stephen L. Ross **
***
This article applies a model of firm capital structure to the current
financial crisis and summarizes the insights the model provides regarding
the regulation of large financial institutions in a post-crisis world. Firm
capital structure is evaluated by studying how firms finance their activities
using debt and equity, which in turn captures an important element of firm
risk taking. First, the simple model is briefly summarized. Second, the
model’s results are used in order to interpret the evolution of the current
financial crisis and to put it into perspective. Finally, the article presents
forward-looking observations and suggestions for future regulation. The
article concludes that an essential element of a new regulatory framework
must include an effective method for dealing with the extension of the “Too
Big to Fail” umbrella, which has extended the risk of moral hazard beyond
depository institutions. It asserts that a successful new framework must
include stringent capital standards for financial institutions combined with
regulators that have the authority and commitment to enforce those
standards putting owners and managers at risk when capital standards are
violated, even during financial crises when there are strong incentives for
regulator accommodation to preserve asset value. The new framework
must be flexible in order to adapt to changing financial conditions
especially developments that affect franchise value, and contain provisions
that expose uninsured debtors to risk when capital standards are violated
so that debt holders have an incentive to monitor the activities of very large
financial firms.
***
*
John P. Harding, Professor, Finance Department, University of Connecticut
**
Stephen L Ross, Professor, Economics Department, University of
Connecticut. The authors benefited from conversations with Dwight Jaffe, Ed
Kane, Pat McCoy and seminar participants at the Federal Reserve Bank of Boston.
244 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
I. INTRODUCTION
Equity capital is the shock absorber for our financial system and
the current financial crisis, like a bumpy road for an auto designer, provides
a unique opportunity for financial regulators to evaluate the predictions of
theory and improve the design of the regulatory system. The purpose of
this paper is to apply a simple model of firm capital structure to the current
situation and summarize the insights it provides regarding the regulation of
large financial institutions in a post-crisis world. The paper begins with a
brief summary of the model and uses the results of that model to place the
evolution of the current crisis into perspective. The paper concludes with
forward-looking observations and suggestions for future regulation.
1
Hayne E. Leland, Corporate Debt Value, Bond Covenants, and Optimal
Capital Structure, 49 J. OF FIN. 1213 (1994).
2
Id. at 1248. While such a restriction may seem unrealistic, the recent crisis
has demonstrated that firms experiencing financial difficulties often have no access
to additional equity capital at the time of distress. This fact places more
importance on the forward-looking choice of initial leverage. Id.
2009] REGULATION OF FINANCIAL INSTITUTIONS 245
3
A call option provides the holder the right, but not the obligation, to
purchase a security or asset at a fixed price. Such an option always has a positive
value regardless of the current value of the asset as long as there is some chance
that the value of the asset may rise above the strike price. For a complete
introduction to options and their valuation see JOHN C. HULL, OPTIONS, FUTURES,
AND OTHER DERIVATIVES (Prentice-Hall) (2008).
246 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
bad outcomes become worse. Such increased investment risk exposes debt
holders to substantially more risk than the likely investment decisions of a
solvent firm.4
The providers of debt capital can anticipate this behavior on the
part of owners and demand fair compensation for bearing the risk of
significant losses from asset declines by increasing the required coupon
rate on the debt. However, this creates “risky” debt and limits the ability to
allocate risk that was one of the original motivations for leverage.5 A
common solution to this problem is for equity and debt providers to
negotiate bond covenants whereby owners contract to transfer control of
the firm to debt holders at a higher threshold value of assets. For example,
a positive net worth covenant would transfer control when the market value
of assets first falls below the face value of debt.6
A final important result from Leland’s model is that whether or not
the debt is protected by bond covenants, the optimal choice of initial
leverage provides a substantial equity “cushion” above the bankruptcy
threshold. Leverage levels near the bankruptcy threshold raise the risk of
incurring the transactions costs associated with bankruptcy. Since debt
holders will bear those costs in bankruptcy, firm owners must pay for those
costs with higher interest rates and so have an incentive to hold additional
equity in order to lower the interest rate on debt.
4
This behavior arises from the limited liability exposure of equity holders, so
that owners of an insolvent firm face no downside risk and benefit from large risks
that have a low probability of success, but, if successful, create the potential for
future positive net worth of the firm. FRANK H. EASTERBROOK & DANIEL R.
FISCHEL, THE ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF CORPORATE LAW 49-50 (1996).
5
To see the intuition underlying this claim, envision a continuum of risk
measured along a straight line where the firm’s assets are located in the middle of
the line. Adding leverage to the firm creates one security with less risk (debt) and
another with more risk (leveraged equity) – splitting the single center point into
two, one to the safer side of center and one to the riskier side. To the extent that
more of the risk of future outcomes falls on the debt holders, the two new points
must remain closer to the original center point.
6
There are many possible variations of this basic idea. For example, some
covenants might limit the managers’ ability to finance new growth or sell assets in
lieu of transferring total control to debt holders. Another variation might provide
debt holders representation on the board when certain financial thresholds are
crossed. Clifford W. Smith & Jerold B. Warner, On Financial Contracting: An
Analysis of Bond Covenants, 7 J. OF FIN. ECON. 117 (1979).
2009] REGULATION OF FINANCIAL INSTITUTIONS 247
7
See Jean-Pierre Gueyie & Van Son Lai, Bank Moral Hazard and the
Introduction of Official Deposit Insurance in Canada, 12 INT’L REV. OF ECON. &
FIN. 247 (2003); Michael C. Keeley, Deposit Insurance, Risk, and Market Power
in Banking, 80 THE AM. ECON. REV. 1183 (1990); and David A. Marshall &
Edward S. Prescott, Bank Capital Regulation With and Without State-Contingent
Penalties (Federal Reserve Bank of Chicago, Working Paper No. 2000-10, 2000).
8
Stephen A. Buser, Andrew H. Chen & Edward J. Kane, Federal Deposit
Insurance, Regulatory Policy and Optimal Bank Capital, 36 J. OF FIN. 51, 56
(1981).
9
Alan J. Marcus, Deregulation and Bank Financial Policy, 8 J. OF BANKING
AND FIN. 51, 59 (1984); Robert C. Merton, On the Cost of Deposit Insurance When
There are Surveillance Costs, 51 J. OF BUS. 439, 448 (1984).
248 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
10
John P. Harding, Xiaozhong Liang & Stephen L. Ross, Bank Capital
Requirements and Capital Structure, 4-6 (Univ. of Conn., Dept. of Econ, Working
Paper No. 2009-09, 2008).
2009] REGULATION OF FINANCIAL INSTITUTIONS 249
cushion above the minimum capital requirement while the mortgage GSEs,
Freddie Mac and Fannie Mae, who prior to the summer of 2008 were free
from the risk of receivership, held little or no capital cushion through the
same period.11
The origins of the current financial crisis are complex and no single
factor can be singled out as the primary cause. However, most observers
believe that increasing use of leverage, broadly defined, was a contributing
factor. The U.S. Government Accountability Office (GAO) report to
Congress on the origins of the crisis shows that total debt in the U.S.
economy rose significantly in the years preceding the crisis. Measured as a
ratio to nominal GDP, total debt rose from roughly two times GDP in 2002
to 2.25 times GDP in 2007.12
11
Fannie Mae and Freddie Mac first began operating under the statutory
minimum capital requirement in 1993, and in that year they held excess capital of
roughly $1 billion and $0.7 billion, respectively. These amounts expressed as a
percentage of assets plus Mortgage Backed Securities (MBS) outstanding were
.14% and .13%, respectively. In most of the eight subsequent years, Fannie Mae
held excess capital well under $1 billion and in 1998 and 1999 its excess capital
was 1/100th of a percent of the assets and MBS. Freddie Mac’s excess capital,
while slightly higher when measured as a percentage of assets and MBS, was
smaller when measured in dollars and is also consistent with the claim that the firm
intended to meet, but not exceed its capital standard. On average over the period
from 1993 through 2001, Fannie Mae and Freddie Mac held less than 1/10th of a
percent of excess capital. The period from 2002 through 2007 is distorted by the
effects of financial restatements arising from accounting problems experienced in
the period from 2003 through 2005. However, the numbers for 2007 most likely
reflect the firms’ contemporaneous intentions, and they still suggest that the firms
were not holding precautionary excess capital. See FHFA AND OFHEO ANNUAL
REPORTS TO CONGRESS 1994 - 2008 available at http://www.fhfa.gov/
Default.aspx?Page=240. From 2001 through 2008, commercial banks held total
capital (Tier I plus Tier II) of 12.3% of risk-based assets. During this period, a
bank was deemed to be well-capitalized with a total capital ratio of 10% of risk-
based assets and adequately capitalized with a ratio of 8%. Data on commercial
bank capital ratios is available at http://www2.fdic.gov/SDI.
12
See, e.g., U.S. GOV’T. ACCOUNTABILITY OFFICE, FINANCIAL MARKETS
REGULATION: FINANCIAL CRISIS HIGHLIGHTS NEED TO IMPROVE OVERSIGHT OF
LEVERAGE AT FINANCIAL INSTITUTIONS AND ACROSS SYSTEM, GAO-09-739, p.13,
250 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
14
Id. at 19-20.
15
Id. at 56-58.
16
For a detailed timeline of events, see The Federal Reserve Bank of St.
Louis, The Financial Crisis: A Timeline of Events and Policy Actions,
http://timeline.stlouisfed.org/index.cfm?p=timeline.
17
See, e.g., Roddy Boyd, How the Bear Stearns Deal Got Done, CNN
MONEY.COM, Mar. 17, 2008, http://money.cnn.com/2008/03/17/news/companies
/boyd_bear.fortune/index.htm?postversion=2008031717. See also, Economic
Outlook Before the S. Comm. On Banking, Housing, and Urban Affairs, 110th
Cong. (2008) (statement of Federal Reserve Chairman Ben S. Bernanke)
252 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
available at http://banking.senate.gov/public/index.cfm?FuseAction=Files.
View&FileStore_id=5a34e5df-2de7-4c9b-a5a7-4f0893acd79e.
18
See, e.g., Lee Christie, Home Prices See Another Record Plunge, CNN
MONEY.COM, Oct. 28, 2008, http://money.cnn.com/2008/10/28/real_estate/
August_Case_Shiller/index.htm. See also Lee Christie, Home Prices in Record
Decline, CNN MONEY.COM, Nov. 25, 2008, http://money.cnn.com/2008/11/25/
real_estate/third_quarter_case_shiller/index.htm.
19
GAO REPORT, supra note 13, at 20.
20
If a firm is levered 30:1 and experiences a 10% decline in value on 10% of
its assets, its equity base declines by 30% and its leverage increases to more than
40:1. In order to return leverage to the original ratio of 30:1, it must sell close to
one third of its assets.
21
Markus K. Brunnermeier, Deciphering the 2007-08 Liquidity and Credit
Crunch, 1 J. OF ECON. PERSPECTIVES 23, 77-100 (2009); Anil K., Kashyap,
Raghuram G. Rajan, & Jeremy C. Stein, Rethinking Capital Regulation, Jackson
Hole Symposium: “Maintaining Stability in a Changing Financial System” (2008),
available at http://kansascityfed.org/publicat/sympos/2008/KashyapRajanStein.
03.12.09.pdf.
22
Mark-to-Market is a way to measure assets and liabilities that appear on a
company’s balance sheet and income statement that involves an attempt to measure
companies’ assets and liabilities at fair or market value. For more detailed
information, see SEC. AND EXCH. COMM’N, OFFICE OF CHIEF ACCOUNTANT & DIV.
OF CORP. FIN., REPORT AND RECOMMENDATIONS PURSUANT TO SECTION 133 OF
THE EMERGENCY ECONOMIC STABILIZATION ACT OF 2008: STUDY ON MARK-TO-
MARKET ACCOUNTING (2008) available at www.sec.gov/news/studies/2008/
marktomarket123008.pdf.
2009] REGULATION OF FINANCIAL INSTITUTIONS 253
psychology and forced sales, but also reflect declines in value due to
greater economic uncertainty in general and/or a higher likelihood of
extreme or tail events in the fundamental markets on which those assets
draw their value. Further, even without a deleveraging price spiral, real
declines in complex asset values such as subprime mortgage-backed
securities could be exacerbated by a lemons problem where firms have
private information on the quality of securities and sell the lowest quality
assets as they deleverage.23
The initial regulatory reaction focused on the immediate symptom
– the freezing up of markets – by providing liquidity in the hope of
stabilizing the markets by stimulating buyers of assets. In August 2007, the
Federal Reserve publicly emphasized its intention to provide reserves as
necessary to meet the needs of depository institutions,24 and then lowered
the federal funds rate throughout the fall of 2007. In December 2007, the
Federal Reserve Board announced the creation of a Term Auction Facility
(TAF) that would auction fixed amounts of term funds to depository
institutions allowing those institutions to use a wide variety of assets
including mortgage-backed securities as collateral. This action was
followed by related efforts throughout the spring and summer of 2008
including legislative authority to extend credit to the Government
Sponsored Enterprises (GSEs) Fannie Mae and Freddie Mac.25 These
efforts proved to be ineffective in containing the crisis and repeated waves
23
See GAO REPORT, supra note 13, at 15-23 for a general discussion of the
deleveraging of financial institutions during this period.
24
The Federal Reserve is often viewed as limiting the use of its discount
window to meet reserve requirements by requiring detailed explanation for
substantial requests. ROBERT E. HALL & JOHN B. TAYLOR, MACROECONOMICS:
THEORY, PERFORMANCE, AND POLICY, 327 (2nd ed., 1988). Banks usually meet
this requirement via inter-bank lending. See OECD Glossary of Statistical Terms,
http://stats.oecd.org/glossary/detail.asp?ID=1385. Accordingly, this statement
addressed the increasing illiquidity in inter-bank lending markets as indicated by
an increasing London Inter-Bank Offer Rate (LIBOR). Asani Sarkar, Liquidity
Risk, Credit Risk, and the Federal Reserve’s Response to the Crisis. Federal
Reserve Bank of New York Staff Report, available at http://www.newyorkfed.org
/research/staff_reports/sr389.pdf.
25
Credit was not granted prior to the GSEs being placed in receivership in
September. However, the recovery act passed in the summer of 2008 did authorize
the U.S. Treasury Department to extend credit to the GSEs if necessary and was
intended to improve the GSEs borrowing ability by increasing investor confidence.
See Timeline, supra note 17.
254 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
of deleveraging asset sales simply led to further asset value declines and
the need for additional deleveraging. By the end of the summer of 2008,
U.S. regulators shifted focus from providing liquidity and shoring up
specific markets to working to preserve the solvency of financial
institutions through the infusion of capital. Most notably, this shift was
signaled by the U.S. Treasury Department proposed legislation to purchase
“troubled assets” of financial institutions that was eventually passed by
congress in October as the Troubled Asset Relief Program (TARP). Soon
after passage, the plan to purchase “troubled assets” was abandoned and
replaced by efforts to directly infuse capital into financial institutions
through the purchase of preferred shares of stock.26
Clearly leverage was a key element of the financial crisis and
understanding the drivers that led to the sharp increase in leverage is
critical for planning the future regulatory regime.27 HLR’s model of bank
capital regulation provides useful insights. First, consider entities such as
investment banks, the two large mortgage GSEs and other non-depository
financial institutions. Most of the larger firms in this category had
significant benefits from relationships with the federal government and
arguably were protected by the “Too Big to Fail” principle. Such firms
differ significantly from the purely private firms studied by Leland in that
they benefit from an implicit government guarantee of liabilities due to the
risk their failure would pose to the national economy. This implicit
guarantee meant that these institutions were similar in some respects to
depository institutions in that they could issue debt at lower cost and with
less market scrutiny than private firms. Significantly, however, there was
26
See id.
27
As noted earlier, leverage cannot be singled out as the sole or even primary
contributing factor. Like a “perfect storm” several factors came together to create
the financial crisis. Low interest rates encouraged institutions and investors to seek
out higher risk/higher return investment opportunities. Technology enabled
investment banks to quickly create and sell structured securities. The global trade
imbalances led to rapid growth of dollar balances in the portfolios of developing
nations and as those investors sought out higher return investments they financed
increased leverage by consumers and institutions in developed countries. Ethan
Cohen-Cole et al., Looking Behind the Aggregates: A Reply to “Facts and Myths
about the Financial Crisis of 2008” (Fed. Reserve Bank of Boston, Working Paper
No. QAU08-5, 2008) available at http://www.bos.frb.org/bankinfo/qau/wp/
2008/qau0805.pdf; V.V. Chari et al., Facts and Myths about the Financial Crisis
of 2008 (Fed. Reserve Bank of Minneapolis, Working Paper No. 666, 2008)
available at http://www.minneapolisfed.org/research/WP/WP666.pdf.
2009] REGULATION OF FINANCIAL INSTITUTIONS 255
28
For data on commercial bank capital ratios, see Federal Deposit Insurance
Corporation, Statistics on Depository Institutions, http://www2.fdic.gov/sdi/
index.asp (last visited Nov. 3, 2009).
29
GAO REPORT, supra note 13, at 28-42.
256 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
30
In game theory, this situation is known as a non-credible threat where an
individual cannot commit to an action in the future (a priori) because all players
know that the action will be irrational in the future (ex post). A standard solution in
such situations is a commitment device that the player imposes on themselves
requiring the action in the future even though irrational ex post. PRAJIT K.
DUTTA, STRATEGIES AND GAMES: THEORY AND PRACTICE (M.I.T. Press
1999).
31
While a minority view, some have argued that the federal government is
not enforcing PCA in violation of federal law during this crisis. See Bill Moyer’s
Journal, William K. Black on the Prompt Corrective Action Law,
http://www.pbs.org/moyers/journal/blog/2009/04/william_k_black_on_the_prompt
.html (April 6, 2009 8:28 EDT).
32
For a discussion of how increased competition can reduce franchise value
and increase risk taking by financial institutions, see Thomas F. Hellmann et al.,
Liberalization, Moral Hazard in Banking, and Prudential Regulation: Are Capital
Requirements Enough?, 90 AM. ECON. REV. 147 (2000).
2009] REGULATION OF FINANCIAL INSTITUTIONS 257
35
The Resolution Trust Corporation was created by the federal government
during the savings and loan crisis in order to hold and dispose of assets of
insolvent thrifts. Lee Davidson, Politics and Policy: The Creation of the
Resolution Trust Corporation, 17(2) FDIC BANKING REV. 17 (2005).
36
During the savings and loan crisis, S&L’s were subject to Regulatory
Accounting Principles rather than GAAP. In May 1987, the Federal Home Loan
Bank Board began phasing in the use of GAAP in response to concerns that
regulatory accounting principles had contributed to the crisis. See Federal
Department Insurance Corporation, The S&L Crisis: A Chrono-Bibliography,
http://www.fdic.gov/bank/Historical/s&l/ (last visited Nov. 3, 2009).
2009] REGULATION OF FINANCIAL INSTITUTIONS 259
provides incentives for firm managers themselves to assess the risk of new
securities and provide a sufficient capital cushion against future shocks.
Finally, the new framework should provide that when capital
standards are violated, unsecured debt holders are not necessarily fully
protected as they have been in the current crisis. Properly motivated,
unsecured, debt holders can provide significant market discipline to an
institution. Throughout the public debate over “bailing out” various firms,
most attention has been given to the fact that in some cases the owners
have retained a valuable equity stake (e.g., Bear Stearns, Merrill Lynch,
Countrywide and AIG) and managers have received significant bonuses
(famously, AIG).37 However, little attention has been placed on the fact
that in most cases, debt holders were the major beneficiaries of the bailouts.
The government intervention and apparent willingness to fund future
operating losses via further infusions of capital provides assurance of
payment in full to debt holders.38 Regulators should have powers similar to
those of a bankruptcy court to impose modifications to unsecured debt
contracts to avoid such windfalls and in fact to impose a share of the loss
on unsecured debt holders so that debt holders will have an incentive to
monitor and assess the investment and financial decisions of large, highly
levered financial institutions.
Finally, because franchise value plays such an important role in
encouraging prudent managerial choices, the new regulatory framework
must be prepared to react to market developments that affect franchise
value. Global competition, domestic and international tax policies,
technological changes and regulatory changes all have the potential to
erode franchise value. Clearly, concerns about financial institution
franchise value cannot and should not drive policy in these areas.
However, regulators need to be cognizant that financial institution
managers will rationally react to declines in franchise value by taking on
additional risk. Capital standards and regulatory monitoring activities need
to reflect this reality.
37
David Goldman, AIG Bonuses: $235 Million To Go, CNN MONEY.COM,
July 10, 2009, http://money.cnn.com/2009/07/10/news/companies/aig_bonuses/
index.htm.
38
For example, the first business day after the mortgage GSEs were placed in
receivership, the market value of GSE debt and MBS securities jumped
significantly providing a windfall profit to recent purchasers.
260 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
PREDATORY LENDING AND ITS INSURANCE
CONSEQUENCES
Erin O’Leary *
***
***
I. INTRODUCTION
delinquent.2 The fallout from the crumbling subprime market affects not
only subprime borrowers but also their communities.3 The crisis has turned
“subprime” into a dirty word. Many Americans have heard enough on the
news to know that this type of lending is largely to blame for the credit
crisis. However, the subprime market has valid and socially valuable
applications; thus, before one can identify the most troubled areas of the
mortgage industry in order to aim reform measures at these problem spots,
the critical distinction one must draw is between subprime and predatory
lending, which represents only a narrow but dangerous sliver of the
subprime market.
There is a legitimate need for subprime lending. Not all borrowers
can qualify for prime loans, typically because of a negative credit event in
their history or because they lack the cash for a down payment.4 Loan
qualification is typically based on credit scores, as calculated by the Fair
Isaac Credit Organization (FICO). Some examples of negative credit
events that would disqualify a borrower from prime-rate loans include a
history of default, bankruptcy, or low or no credit. Such borrowers are
considered to present too great a risk of delinquency, default, or foreclosure
to justify the prime rate. Nevertheless, there is a strong policy argument in
the United States for enabling as many people as possible to become
homeowners. Therefore, in order for these somewhat risky borrowers to
become homeowners, they may need to resort to other types of loans.
These loans are usually considered subprime. There is no one accepted
2
Id.
3
The Center for Responsible Lending (CRL) estimates that because of what
is known as the “spillover effect,” subprime foreclosures will drain properties
surrounding foreclosed homes of nearly $352 billion in value from 40 million
nearby families, averaging out to almost $9,000 per family. CTR. FOR RESPONSIBLE
LENDING, UPDATED PROJECTIONS OF SUBPRIME FORECLOSURES IN THE UNITED
STATES AND THEIR IMPACT ON HOME VALUES AND COMMUNITIES 1 (2008),
available at http://www.responsiblelending.org/mortgage-lending/research-
analysis /updated-foreclosure-and-spillover-brief-8-18.pdf.. These estimates were
made in August 2008 and update an earlier study made in January 2008 that was
considered “wildly pessimistic” in its estimate of a $202 billion loss in neighboring
home values and an average loss of $5,000 for 40 million nearby families. See
CTR. FOR RESPONSIBLE LENDING, SUBPRIME SPILLOVER: FORECLOSURES COST
NEIGHBORS $202 BILLION; 40.6 MILLION HOMES LOSE $5,000 ON AVERAGE 1
(2008) available at http://www.responsiblelending.org/mortgage-lending/research-
analysis/subprime-spillover.pdf
4
David Anderson, The Subprime Lending Crisis, 71 TEX. B.J. 20 (2008).
2009] PREDATORY LENDING 263
5
See Kathleen C. Engel & Patricia A. McCoy, A Tale of Three Markets: The
Law and Economics of Predatory Lending, 80 TEX. L. REV. 1255, 1265–66 (2002).
(explaining the costs that justify higher rates and fees for subprime loans). It is
important to note that many of the costs that justify higher costs and fees, such as a
more thorough review of a customer’s income and credit, lower loan principal
amounts that lead to higher origination costs as a percentage of the total loan, and
higher incidence of prepayment, are much lower in predatory loans, if they exist at
all. For example, predatory lenders often fail to verify a customer’s income, debt
obligations, and assets before making a loan, thereby erasing most of the cost of
income verification. See id.
6
CRL, A SNAPSHOT OF THE SUBPRIME MARKET 1–3 (2007), available at
http://www.responsiblelending.org/mortgage-lending/tools-resources/snapshot-of-
the-subprime-market.pdf.. That number is probably low; Professors Engel and
McCoy estimate that at least 98% of subprime home loans contain “substantial
prepayment penalties.” Engel & McCoy, supra note 5, at 1285.
7
CTR. FOR RESPONSIBLE LENDING, supra note 6, at 2.
264 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
values reassured lenders that if the properties for which they were issuing
mortgages would at the very least retain their value.8
Predatory lending, on the other hand, has no legitimate basis. The
vast majority of predatory loans occur in mortgages that would otherwise
be considered subprime. While subprime lenders have a legitimate
argument that they must increase the fees and rates associated with their
products in order to hedge against the increased risk of default presented by
borrowers with less than ideal credit, predatory lending practices have no
place in the world of legitimate loans. They are characterized by practices
that strip homeowners of the equity they have in their properties extract as
much in fees, rates, and other charges as possible from the homeowner.
The subprime lending crisis has had obvious and devastating
ramifications for millions of subprime borrowers. There have also been
less apparent consequences for the insurance industry. This industry has
become closely intertwined with the mortgage industry. As the problems
in the subprime market have become exacerbated, so too have the problems
in mortgage-related insurance products. This paper considers how two
mortgage-related insurance products, namely, single premium credit
insurance (SPCI) and private mortgage insurance (PMI), have affected the
predatory lending crisis. I contend that through reform measures that
eliminate SPCI and make PMI a more feasible option, the subprime lending
market can continue to offer mortgages to qualified subprime borrowers
while simultaneously reducing the tide of predatory lending and
foreclosures.9
In Part II of this Note, I examine two issues concerning the role of
insurance in the subprime mortgage market. The first is the declining
centrality of the role played by providers of private mortgage insurance
(PMI) to insure many subprime mortgages. I will explain the effect that
predatory lending has had on legitimate PMI policy providers. The second
issue is the abuse of credit insurance in subprime mortgage loans. In
particular, I will focus on how single premium credit insurance functions as
one of the more abusive terms that predatory lenders employ. I will also
explore the related nature of these two problems. Moreover, I will provide
a brief synopsis of some of the most common abusive tactics used by
8
See Christopher Barlow, Developments in Banking & Financial Law, 2006-
2007: The Subprime Mortgage Crisis: Macroeconomic Implications of the
Subprime Lending Crisis, 27 REV. BANKING & FIN. L. 57, 57–58 (2008).
9
This paper considers primarily legislation-based reform rather than
litigation.
2009] PREDATORY LENDING 265
predatory lenders that have led to the complications that the mortgage
industry is facing today.
In Part III, I discuss the reform measures that will be necessary to
alleviate the problems related to mortgage insurance. I will also focus on
two reform measures: first, the Federal Reserve Board’s newly finalized
amendments to Regulation Z, which implements the Truth in Lending Act
(TILA) and the Home Ownership and Equity Protection Act (HOEPA); and
second, H.R. 3915, or the Mortgage Reform and Anti-Predatory Lending
Act of 2007, which was approved by the House but was never voted on by
the Senate. Additionally, I suggest that PMI is an important product that
can be used to stem the tide of foreclosures because of the mutual interests
shared by borrowers and insurers.
Part IV examines whether the Fed’s new amendments to
Regulation Z can be expected to bring meaningful change and explores
what other measures must be taken in order to stop predatory lending for
good, including the effect that H.R. 3915 would have if re-introduced in the
next session of Congress.
1. Overview
10
There are multiple types of PMI, but the type that is the focus of this article
is primary PMI, which protects against mortgage default. PMI in this article is
used to refer to primary PMI. Other kinds of PMI not discussed in this article
include pool insurance, which insures groups of individual mortgages and provides
100 per cent coverage for any default losses on mortgages in the pool, subject to a
total loss limit on all mortgages in the pool, and PMI reinsurance. Quinton
Johnstone, Private Mortgage Insurance, 39 WAKE FOREST L. REV. 783, 783
(2004).
11
OFFICE OF THE COMPTROLLER OF THE CURRENCY, Answers About Credit
Insurance, http://www.helpwithmybank.gov/faqs/insurance_credit_life.html.
Policies that pay 20-30% of the amount of the outstanding debt typically allow
lenders to retain title to the property after foreclosure. Mortgage INSURANCE
266 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
type of mortgage insurance that lenders can require before making a loan.12
Often, a potential borrower cannot afford a 20 per cent down payment on a
home mortgage.13 On the other hand, most lenders are hesitant to make
such a loan because these borrowers tend to have a higher risk of
defaulting. PMI has served a conciliatory function and permitted these
individuals to become homeowners, while alleviating the fears of lenders.14
Not only is the PMI industry regulated at the state level by laws
that vary from state to state15, but also in part by the federal Homeowner
Protection Act of 1998, which took effect on July 29, 1999.16 If PMI is
required as a condition for a mortgage, this statute protects homeowners by
requiring both automatic cancellation of the PMI and notice of cancellation
rights with respect to PMI.17 For borrowers with good payment history
who are current on their mortgage payments and who can show that the
property has not declined below its original value, the PMI can be
cancelled on a predetermined cancellation date.18 This date typically
occurs when the balance of the mortgage reaches 80 per cent, which occurs
by the borrower making sufficient payments of principal on the mortgage,
through appreciation in the value of the property value, or a combination of
both.19 High risk loans are exceptions, however: lenders must give
piggyback loan did.25Also, PMI is paid for and maintained by the borrower,
thus adding an obvious cost to the loan.26 For many borrowers, this cost
can be especially difficult to swallow because PMI is not first party
insurance; rather, it is in place to protect the lender. By contrast, the costs
of piggyback lending are more subtle, such as higher interest rates.
Additionally, underwriting standards employed by PMI companies tend to
be much stricter than those used by piggyback lenders.27 As I will explain,
this is due in part becausePMI companies and borrowers share a unity of
interest that simply does not exist between brokers of piggyback loans and
their borrowers.
An 80-10-10 loan is actually two loans: one is a first-lien mortgage
on the property that covers 80 per cent of the purchase price. The second
loan is, in most cases, a ten per cent loan that covers part of the remaining
20 per cent so that the borrower does not have to purchase PMI.28 Thus,
with the increase in predatory loans in the past five years, the mortgage
industry has seen a concurrent increase in 80-10-10 loans. Because the 80-
10-10 loan is a tool invented in part to avoid PMI, it is easy to see how a
sharp increase in its usage would translate into decreased profits for PMI
providers.29 As an illustration of this point, piggyback loans were virtually
nonexistent in 2000, but by 2006 about 22% of owner-occupied houses had
piggyback subordinate lien mortgages, and the number and dollar volume
25
See Robert B. Avery, Kenneth P. Brevoort & Glenn B. Canner, The 2006
HMDA Data, 93 Fed. Reserve Bulletin A73, A84-A85 (2007), available at
http://www.federalreserve.gov/pubs/bulletin/2007/pdf/hmda06final.pdf.
26
Todd J. Zywicki & Joseph D. Adamson, The Law & Economics of
Subprime Lending, 80 U. COLO. L. REV. 1, 42 (2009).
27
Id.
28
While most prime loans require PMI if the borrower puts less than 20 per
cent down, many subprime lenders, although they are willing to lend to customers
who cannot put very much down, will demand either PMI or some other type of
credit insurance if the borrower is not able to put down 25 or even up to 30 per
cent. NATIONAL CONSUMER LAW CENTER, INC., supra note 24.
29
Id. Private mortgage insurers have recognized the threat to their product
that is posed by this 80-10-10 or “piggyback” loan. On the website of the
Mortgage Insurance Companies of America (MICA), an industry organization,
there is an entire section dedicated to warning consumers of the dangers of this
type of loan. See MICA, QUICK FACTS ABOUT 80-10-10 LOANS (2009),
http://www.privatemi.com/news/factsheets/quickfacts.cfm; see also MICA,
MYTHS AND FACTS ABOUT PIGGYBACK LOANS (2009),
http://www.privatemi.com/news/factsheets/myths.cfm.
2009] PREDATORY LENDING 269
30
Zywicki & Adamson, supra note 27.
31
Id.
32
Vikas Bajaj, More Lenders Feeling Pain from Defaults, N.Y. TIMES, July
31, 2007.
33
Bankrate.com, The Basics of Private Mortgage Insurance (June 1, 2001),
http://www.bankrate.com /brm/news/mtg/20010601b.asp (last visited July 19,
2009).
34
Brian M. Heat, Note, Hoosier Inhospitality: Examining Excessive
Foreclosure Rates in Indiana, 39 IND. L. REV. 87, 100-01 (2005).
35
Id.
36
See § 2.a.ii, infra; see also Engel & McCoy, supra note 6, at 1260.
270 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
37
See GENWORTH MORTGAGE INSURANCE, POLICY STATEMENT ON
“PREDATORY” LENDING (2008), http://www.mortgageinsurance.genworth.com/
Legal/PredatoryLendingGuidelines.aspx (discussing practices that will cause the
company to refuse to insure the loan in which the practices are found).
38
MORTGAGE GUARANTY INSURANCE CORPORATION, ANTI-PREDATORY
LENDING POLICY (2008), http://www.mgic.com/emergingmkts/antipredatory
lending.html.
39
eBulletin from Radian Guaranty, Inc. (Aug. 28, 2007),
http://www.radian.biz/pdf/EBULLETIN%202007-02%20GUIDELINE%20
CHANGES%20EFFECTIVE%2009-17-07%20Final.pdf. Because the program is
no longer available, Radian does not thoroughly explain it anywhere.
40
eBulletin from Radian Guaranty, Inc. 2 (Dec. 17, 2007),
http://www.radian.biz/pdf/ Radian%20eBulletin%202007-03.pdf.
41
eBulletin from Radian Guaranty, Inc. 2 (Mar. 7, 2008),
http://www.radian.biz/pdf/ Radian%20eBulletin%202008-02.pdf.
2009] PREDATORY LENDING 271
a. Lack of Verification
42
AMERICAN ASSOCIATION OF RETIRED PERSONS, AARP COMMENTS TO
FEDERAL RESERVE BOARD ON THE HOME OWNERSHIP AND EQUITY PROTECTION
ACT (Aug. 15, 2007), available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/SECRS
/2007/August/20070816/OP-1288/OP-1288_51_1.pdf.
43
Center for Responsible Lending, supra note 7.
44
See infra § II.a.ii.2.
45
See infra § II.a.ii.7
46
See Engel & McCoy, supra note 6, at 1273-74.
272 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
bundles serves two crucial functions: it gets the mortgages off of the
originator’s books and also provides an inflow of capital so the originator
can continue to make loans.47 Secondary market purchasers of these
securities were unable to inspect the individual loans underlying the
securities they were purchasing. The securities, however, were rated
investment-grade for the most part by the ratings agencies and were
thought to be safe investments because they were diverse and because it
was thought that with their homes at stake, borrowers would generally not
default. Even if one or two failed, investors reasoned, the rest of the
portfolio would be sound. When they failed in large numbers, the so-called
“subprime crisis” ensued.
However, unlike most brokers or lenders, PMI companies have a
strong interest in their insured’s ability to repay his or her mortgage. The
company will have to pay a claim on the policy if the borrower does not
repay; thus, it is in the company’s best interest to fully investigate a
borrower's ability to repay the loan. The requirement that a customer
document his or her ability to repay is now well-reflected in the
underwriting standards of PMI companies.48
47
See id.
48
See, e.g., RADIAN GUARANTY, INC., UNDERWRITING GUIDELINES, 6-7, 10-
11 (2009), available at http://www.radian.biz/pdf/Radian_Standard_Guidelines_
08_17_09.pdf.
49
CENTER FOR RESPONSIBLE LENDING, supra note 7, at 1-2, 4.
50
Id. at 1. These adjustable rate mortgages typically float in relation to an
index like the London Interbank Offered Rate (LIBOR), but subprime borrowers
often pay a premium over the rate that prime borrowers would pay for a similar
product. Anderson, supra note 5, at 20.
2009] PREDATORY LENDING 273
c. Excessive Fees
d. Prepayment Penalties
51
CENTER FOR RESPONSIBLE LENDING, supra note 7, at 2. While the average
increase in rate is only 30 to 50 per cent, a loan resetting from 7 to 12 per cent
would cause the borrower’s payments to increase by 70 per cent. See Id.
52
Engel & McCoy, supra note 6, at 1263. See also Mincey v. World Sav.
Bank, FSB, 614 F. Supp. 2d 610, 635-638 (D. S.C. 2008) (holding that where a
lender violated TILA where he failed to disclose that if a borrower chose to pay off
his mortgage as an option-ARM, it would cause negative amortization).
53
These fees greatly exceed the amounts justified by the costs of the services
provided and the credit and interest rate risks involved. David Reiss, Subprime
Standardization: How Rating Agencies Allow Predatory Lending to Flourish in the
Secondary Mortgage Market, 33 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 985, 999 (2006).
54
See CENTER FOR RESPONSIBLE LENDING, supra note 7, at 1-3.
274 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
and can easily total five percent of the principal balance of the loan.55 The
penalties usually can only be invoked in the first part of a loan, i.e. within
the first four or five years. Brokers defend these particular penalties with
the argument that by applying a prepayment penalties, lenders are willing
to lower the interest rate because they are more confident that the borrower
will not prepay, such as through a cash-out refinance. Thus, contend
brokers, because of the lower interest rate, there is a net benefit to
borrowers. However, research indicates that even where lenders do lower
the interest rate on mortgage with prepayment penalties, the difference is
made up in added fees, evidencing a lack of correlation between the penalty
and the purported savings to the consumer. Instead, the cost of the penalty
to the average borrower is three to four times the average savings in interest
payments.56
Prepayment penalties are particularly troublesome for borrowers in
two situations. First, if a borrower has successfully improved his credit
score such that he now qualifies for a better loan at a prime rate, he invokes
a prepayment penalty. Those borrowers who cannot afford to pay the
penalty- and there are many- feel they have no choice but to stay with their
current mortgages.57 Many subprime lenders market their product as a loan
that a borrower can use while he or she tries to improve his credit rating
such that he can qualify for a prime loan. Given the fact that prepayment
penalties lock a consumer into the loan, this claim seems ironic at best and
downright fraudulent at worst.58 If the borrower chooses to refinance, he
incurs a large penalty for doing so. In the words of the Center for
Responsible Lending, the borrower incurs “punishment for obtaining a
better loan.”59
The second situation in which prepayment penalties become
onerous for borrowers occurs when the mortgage “explodes” at the end of
the introductory period. The borrower abruptly finds himself owing on
55
A typical prepayment penalty would be six month’s interest, or about 4.5
per cent of the initial loan balance. Supra note 45, at 5. This translates into
thousands of additional dollars required for refinancing. Id.
56
Id.
57
DEBBIE GOLDSTEIN & STACY STROHAUER SON, CRL, WHY PREPAYMENT
PENALTIES ARE ABUSIVE IN SUBPRIME HOME LOANS 1, 4 (2003), available at
http://www.responsiblelending.org/mortgage-lending/research-
analysis/PPP_Policy_Paper2.pdf.
58
See id.
59
Id.
2009] PREDATORY LENDING 275
60
See Ctr. for Responsible Lending, supra note 6, at 2.
61
Id. Prepayment penalties have been limited in the prime market because of
better competition among lenders. Id. But see Engel & McCoy, supra note 6, at
1285 (estimating that at least 98% of subprime loans contain substantial
prepayment penalties).
62
See infra § II.a.6; William F. Bennett, Mortgage Brokers Get Fatter
Payoffs for Selling Riskier Loans, NORTH COUNTY TIMES, May 5, 2007
(considering the case of California mortgage brokers who are legally obligated to
act in the best interest of the borrowers, but who often do not because there is no
enforcement mechanism).
63
See Engel & McCoy, supra note 5, at 1263.
64
Id.
65
Id.
276 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
f. Aggressive Advertising
66
See Goldstein & Son, supra note 57, at 3.
67
Id at 12..
68
See Engel & McCoy, supra note 6, at 1346
69
See id. at 1296.
70
See id.
71
AARP, supra note 42.
72
CTR. FOR RESPONSIBLE LENDING, FACT SHEET: PREDATORY MORTGAGE
LENDING ROBS HOMEOWNERS & DEVASTATES COMMUNITIES (2006), available at
http://www.responsiblelending.org/mortgage-lending/research-analysis/2b003-
mortgage2005.pdf.
73
Ctr. for Responsible Lending, supra note 6, at 2
2009] PREDATORY LENDING 277
g. Yield-Spread Premiums
74
Engel & McCoy, supra note 5, at 1295.
75
See AARP, supra note 42.
76
See Engel & McCoy, supra note 5, at 1267.
77
See id. at 1264-66.
278 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
Mae and Freddie Mac studies have found that up to about 50% of all
borrowers steered into subprime loans could have qualified for a prime
rate.78 This figure is partially a result of brokers working in concert with
lenders to drive up mortgage rates. In addition, many lenders offer these
kickbacks if a brokers can pad the loans with large prepayment penalties.79
Lenders are willing to pay a premium for a prepayment penalty that
functions as a guarantee that the borrower will either stay in the overpriced
predatory loan or that the lender will make money when the borrower is
forced to pay the penalty in order to get out of his expensive loan.80
These kickbacks are dangerous for another reason. Many
unscrupulous brokers employ tactics designed to convince the potential
borrower that they, the brokers, are working on behalf of the borrower to
obtain the best rate possible. Borrowers are lulled into a false sense of
comfort and a belief that the broker is laboring under some sort of fiduciary
duty. In reality, exactly the opposite is true: brokers are motivated to sell
the borrower the most expensive mortgage possible.81
78
See Goldstein and Son, supra note 57, at 1 n.3.
79
See id. at 1.
80
For example, a ContiMortgage Corporation rate sheet shows that for loans
with prepayment penalties, the maximum yield-spread premium is 2.5 per cent.
For mortgages with prepayment penalties, the maximum premium jumps to 4.25
per cent. AARP, supra note 42, at 5-6.
81
Bennett, supra note 62.
82
See 73 Fed. Reg. 44522, 44566 (proposed Jul. 30, 2008) (to be codified at
12 C.F.R. pt. 226).
83
See Christopher L. Peterson, Predatory Structured Finance, 28 CARDOZO
L. REV. 2185, 2223 (2007) (describing a predatory lender who used overstated
appraisals to justify loans packed with excessive fees and charges).
2009] PREDATORY LENDING 279
Instead, in 2007, the bubble burst and home prices fell.84 At the same time,
many rates on subprime loans reset from the introductory “low fixed rates”
to a higher rate. Borrowers who relied on increasing home values were
simultaneously faced with increased mortgage payments, , leading to
increased foreclosures.
called SPCI on mortgages “the worst insurance rip-off in the nation,” and
Fannie Mae and Freddie Mac refuse to purchase loans that included
financed credit insurance.90
While onerous for the borrowers who must pay the premiums,
mortgage credit insurance is lucrative for the lenders. Credit insurance
companies typically sell group insurance products to home mortgage and
other lenders.91 One author suggests that some lenders make up to 50% of
their pre-tax income from the sale of credit insurance.92 The Consumer
Federation of America also found in a 1999 report that the credit insurance
industry had unusually low loss ratios, with the ratio of claims to premiums
often no more than 40% for credit life and disability insurance policies.93
This exceeds the National Association of Insurance
Commissioners’(NAIC) recommended 60% claims to premiums ratio.94
The implication from these numbers is that lenders selling credit insurance
are profiting at the disproportionate expense of the borrowers who are often
deceived into purchasing the policies.95
In theory, these products are voluntary. The only form of
insurance that a lender may legally require in order to obtain a loan is
private mortgage insurance, but once a borrower does purchase credit
insurance, it becomes part of his contract.96 In many cases, the relatively
meager consumer benefits provided by credit insurance last only a few
years, while the borrower continues to pay a high interest fee on a large
premium for years after the benefits have stopped.97 In previous
90
Id. See also Broderick Perkins, California Enforcing New Predatory Loan
Rules, REALTY TIMES, July 10, 2002, available at http://realtytimes.com
/rtpages/20020710_predatoryloans.htm
91
Ronald H. Silverman, Toward Curing Predatory Lending, 122 BANKING
L.J. 483, 504 (2002).
92
Id. at 504-505
93
Id. at 505.
94
Id.
95
See id.
96
NATIONAL ASSOCIATION OF INSURANCE COMMISSIONERS, CREDIT
INSURANCE: SAFETY NET OR NO NET GAIN? (Nov. 2006),
http://www.naic.org/documents/consumer_alert_credit_insurance.htm; see also
Office of the Comptroller of the Currency, supra note 11.
97
Edward M. Gramlich, Governor, Federal Reserve Board, Remarks at the
Housing Bureau for Seniors Conference (Jan. 18, 2002).
2009] PREDATORY LENDING 281
A. OBJECTIVES OF REFORM
1. Competing Interests
98
See id.
99
643 S.E.2d 410, 424-425 (N.C. Ct. App. 2007).
100
Ben S. Bernake, Chairman, Federal Reserve, Statement of Jul. 14, 2008,
available at http://www.federalreserve.gov/newsevents/press/bcreg/bernankeregz
20080714.htm
282 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
101
See, e.g. Manny Fernandez, Helping to Keep Homelessness at Bay as
Foreclosures Hit More Families, N.Y. TIMES, Feb. 4, 2008, at B6 (discussing a
program adopted by New York charitable organizations to help homeowners who
are facing foreclosure avoid eviction by giving them up to $10,000 to pay for the
costs of moving, the first month’s rent at their new apartments, and other related
costs).
102
David Schmudde, Responding to the Subprime Mess: The New Regulatory
Landscape, 14 FORDHAM J. CORP. & FIN. L. 709, 730 (2009).
103
An escrow requirement like the one proposed in the Fed’s finalized
amendments to Regulation Z requires lenders to set up an escrow to cover the costs
of property taxes and insurance. See CENTER FOR RESPONSIBLE LENDING,
PROPOSED RULES REGARDING UNFAIR, DECEPTIVE, ABUSIVE LENDING AND
SERVICING PRACTICES PURSUANT TO HOME OWNERSHIP AND EQUITY PROTECTION
ACT at 52 (Apr. 8, 2008), available at http://www.responsiblelending.org
/mortgage-lending/policy-legislation/regulators/fed-udap-comments-final-
040808.pdf.
2009] PREDATORY LENDING 283
side of the policy argument says that any regulation should favor the
consumer in order to force lenders to internalize the harm they cause.104
The other side of that same policy argument is the side favored by
Senator Phil Gramm, among others. Gramm attributed the increase in
foreclosures, particularly in the subprime market, to “predatory
borrowers,” not predatory lenders.105 With the spectrum of available
subprime products, many borrowers were able to obtain mortgages that
they ultimately could not afford.106 People such as Senator Gramm favor
regulations that require the borrower to be responsible for ensuring that he
only borrows what he can afford. The problem with this, however, is that
predatory brokers and lenders often structure their marketing strategies
around pressure and removing free will.
2. Policy Goals
104
See generally Lauren E. Willis, Against Financial-Literacy Education, 94
IOWA L. REV. 197 (2008) at A1 (discussing the interaction of foreclosures and
societal reaction to the same and positing that regulations are the best way to attack
foreclosures, which are costly to the borrower and to society).
105
Eric Lipton & Stephen Labaton, Deregulator Looks Back, Unswayed, N.Y.
TIMES, Nov. 17, 2008 (emphasis added)
106
See Fernandez, supra note 102, at B6 (discussing the example of a woman
who was able to obtain a $486,000 mortgage with $4,000 monthly payments
despite the fact that her monthly income was only $2,800).
107
Johnstone, supra note 10, at 787.
284 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
predatory lending are a critical first step toward improving the PMI outlook
and making mortgages safer and more affordable for subprime borrowers.
PMI providers avoid predatory loans for reasons that are both
ethical and practical. From an ethical standpoint, it is likely that these
providers do not want to be associated with a product that has gained so
much notoriety as a major cause of rising foreclosure costs and the seizing
up of the capital markets. And from a practical point of view, insurance
companies are loath to insure loans that carry with them a high likelihood
of a borrower default that would trigger payout on the policy. As discussed
above, predatory loans carry with them a higher rate of default. Therefore,
curbing predatory lending would make subprime loans safer and less
expensive for PMI providers to insure. Although there are a relatively
small number of PMI providers,108 there is intense competition among this
limited group of companies. Therefore, if the costs of PMI can be reduced
across the board, then costs of PMI policies are likely to fall, making it a
much more feasible option for borrowers. This will help drop demand for
the 80-10-10 loans. If faced with decreased demand and more of the right
regulations, along with the increased public awareness, predatory lenders
would find it much more difficult to find willing victims.
Perhaps the most appealing aspect of PMI is that it aligns the
borrower’s interest with the insurer’s interest. Restrictive or requirement-
based regulations, such as prohibitions on prepayment penalties or
mandatory disclosures, are often difficult because the brokers and lenders
targeted by these regulations realize that it is frequently not in their best
interests. Brokers in particular have little incentive to ensure that the loans
they write on behalf of their lenders are sustainable and affordable.109 If
the borrower defaults, the broker is not implicated: he or she has likely
already collected his or her yield-spread premium and is unaffected by the
foreclosure.
One author has identified the moral hazard faced by brokers and
explains that at the same time that the law permits and even encourages a
mortgage broker to bargain for the most advantageous outcome, it also asks
that broker to serve as the conduit for information that is intended to reduce
108
Members of MICA, the industry association for mortgage insurers includes
AIG United Guaranty, Genworth Mortgage Insurance Corporation, Mortgage
Insurance Guaranty Corporation, PMI Mortgage Insurance Co., Radian Guaranty,
and Republic Mortgage Insurance Company. Private MI, ABOUT MICA (2009),
available at http://www.privatemi.com/about.cfm.
109
See Bennett, supra note 62.
2009] PREDATORY LENDING 285
110
Lloyd T. Wilson, Jr., Effecting Responsibility in the Mortgage Broker-
Borrower Relationship: A Role for Agency Principles in Predatory Lending
Regulation, 73 U. CIN. L. REV. 1471, 1500 (2005).
111
Genworth Financial has stepped in to facilitate mediations and workouts
that will keep their insureds in their homes and avoid foreclosure and claims. See
Shannon Behnken, Insurance Company Helps Homeowner Avoid Foreclosure,
TAMPA TRIBUNE, Nov. 25, 2008.
112
Johnstone, supra note 10, at 783. This is not to say that regulations are
never needed. The Homeowners Protection Act is an example of regulations that
protect consumers by requiring that PMI be cancelable after a certain loan to value
is reached. See also 47 C.J.S. Interest & Usury § 515 supra note 17.
286 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
B. PROPOSED PROTECTIONS
a. Proposed Measures.
113
See Kathleen C. Engel & Patricia A. McCoy, Turning a Blind Eye: Wall
Street Finance of Predatory Lending, 75 FORDHAM L. REV. 2039, 2041 (2007).
114
See supra § III.a.i.
115
Press Release, Board of Governors of the Federal Reserve System,
(December 18, 2007) (available at http://www.federalreserve.gov
/newsevents/press/bcreg/20071218a.htm).
2009] PREDATORY LENDING 287
116
Id.
288 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
117
See AARP, supra note 42, at 1, 4, 11.
118
Id.
119
Id. at 7-8.
2009] PREDATORY LENDING 289
120
NATIONAL CONSUMER LAW CENTER, INC., THE FRB’S FINAL HOEPA
RULE: A FIRST STEP, BUT REAL REFORMS ARE STILL NEEDED 2 (2008), available at
http://www.consumerlaw.org/issues/predatory_mortgage/content/FRB-HOEPA-
Rule-NCLCquickanalysis.pdf.
121
Center For Responsible Lending, supra note 106, at 4, 22.
122
Id. at 4.
123
National Consumer Law Center, Inc., supra note 120, at 4.
124
CONSUMER BANKERS’ ASSOCIATION, FED ISSUES TOUGH FINAL HOEPA
RULES; DROPS BROKER DISCLOSURE 1 (2008), at 1. http://www.cbanet.org
/files/GRFiles/HOEpfinal.pdf.
125
Letter from the American Securitization Forum & Securities Industry &
Financial Markets Association to the Board of Governors of the Federal Reserve
290 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
After accepting comments, on July 30, 2008, the Fed published the
final rule amending Regulation Z implementing HOEPA and TILA.128
There were some notable changes from the proposed rule. First, at the
behest of consumer groups like the CRL, the Fed changed the definition of
“high-cost” in the context of mortgage loans.129 In the proposed rules,
whether a loan was defined as “high-cost” was determined by comparing
that loan’s rate to the yield on Treasury securities of comparable maturity.
The CRL pointed out that a mortgage-based trigger was more appropriate,
to account for economy-wide wide credit events. As a result, under the
final rules the Fed will publish an “average prime offer rate based on a
survey currently published by Freddie Mac. A loan is high-cost if it is a
first loan and is at a rate that is 1.5 percentage points or more above the
prime offer rate, or for subordinate-lien mortgages, if it is 3.5 percentage
points above the prime offer rate.130
131
Id. at 44551.
132
Id.
133
See id.
134
Truth in Lending (Regulation Z), 73 Fed. Reg. 44522, 44523, 44595 (Jan
9, 2008) (to be codified at 12 C.F.R. 226).
135
Id. at 44598.
136
Id. at 44604.
292 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
137
Id. at 44600-01.
138
See id. at 4457495.
139
Id. at 44563.
140
See id. at 44574.
141
Id. § 129A.
142
Id. at § 206(g).
2009] PREDATORY LENDING 293
143
Id. at § 123(b).
144
Id. at §§ 601-604. Steering incentives are defined as originator
compensation that varies, directly or indirectly, or is based on the terms of any loan
that is not a qualified mortgage as defined in § 129B(c)(3). Id.
145
Id. at §§ 101-113.
146
Id. at §§ 301(aa)(1)..
147
Id. at § 303. “Extremely” high-cost mortgages would be defined as those
with very high points and fees, exceeding 5% of the total loan amount, using a
comprehensive definition of points and fees that would include yield-spread
premiums, and prepayment penalties. Id. at § 301(aa)(1).
148
Id. at § 303(t).
149
Id. at § 303(t).
294 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
the crisis. Both of these phenomena have proved a boon for predatory
lenders.
Single premium credit insurance gets financed into the principal of
the loan, which translates into earnings in interest for the loan originator as
well as a large lump sum. The borrower’s benefits are not nearly as
appealing; usually, the insurance policy expires long before the premium is
paid off. Any effective reforms must ban the use of this; disclosure alone is
not enough.150 At the very least, an intermediate step would be to prohibit
financing the premium; that is, prohibit lenders from charging interest on
the large premium. This will also require lenders to turn increasingly to
PMI if they want extra security for loans on which borrowers are paying
less than 20 per cent down, thereby shifting borrowers into a the much
safer and better-regulated world of PMI.
As predatory lenders became increasingly aggressive, they set their
sights on borrowers who wanted to avoid purchasing PMI when they had
less than 20 per cent to put down on a home. Demand fell for PMI policies
and as a result, predatory loan solutions for the problem of the borrower
with little cash to put down rose. Addressing predatory lending and
restoring PMI to a legitimate, feasible option for borrowers are symbiotic
propositions. The best chance of accomplishing both of these objectives is
for the federal government to use its authority to effectuate sweeping
reforms.
Had the Senate passed H.R. 3915 and the bill had been signed into
law and enacted, it would have represented a major step against predatory
lending that encompassed nearly all abusive practices and also provided
sufficient penalties and remedies to enforce them. As it is, however, the
Fed’s regulations alone are not enough to effectuate the changes needed in
mortgage-related insurance products. What is needed are not strong
disclosure requirements, because even if disclosed, the abusive practices
tend to be complicated and hidden within an even more complicated
framework of loan terms.151 Whereas disclosure may be sufficient for
150
See generally Patricia A. McCoy, Rethinking Disclosure in a World of
Risk-Based Pricing, 44 HARV. J. ON LEGIS. 123 at 147, 154 (2007).
151
See Elizabeth Renuart & Diane E. Thompson, The Truth, the Whole Truth,
and Nothing But the Truth: Fulfilling the Promise of Truth in Lending, 25 YALE J.
ON REG. 181 (2008) (explaining that evaluating the cost of credit and comparison
shopping is very difficult even for sophisticated shoppers, but as lenders
increasingly “unbundle the costs of their loans from the interest into an array of
fees, outsource their overhead to third parties who add to consumers’ costs, and
unveil amazingly complex loan products that dazzle and confuse borrowers,” even
2009] PREDATORY LENDING 295
Sara Nadim *
***
This note examines the 2008 Mental Health Parity and Addiction Equity
Act and argues that even though this Act represents a landmark
improvement in mental illness parity coverage, an amendment should be
passed to define what is specifically considered to be a mental illness or
substance use disorder. The first part explores the history of federal
mental parity law along with the efforts made to achieve parity. The
second part discusses the specific provisions of the 2008 Act, specifically
that it does not provide explicit definitions for mental health conditions or
substance use disorders. Third, state definitions of mental illness are
reviewed. Recent developments supporting the biological basis of mental
illness are presented in the fourth part. Finally, the fifth part of the note
evaluates the diminished societal costs that will come with the addition of
parity in mental illness insurance coverage. This note argues that certain
severe biologically based mental illnesses should be listed under the
definition of mental illness that at minimum insurers should be required to
cover. It supports its proposition by providing evidence that group health
plan costs for employers will not increase greatly, and that societal costs,
such as homelessness and loss of productivity in the workplace, will be
greatly reduced when mental illness and substance use disorders are
adequately treated.
***
*
University of Connecticut School of Law, Juris Doctor Candidate for the
Class of 2010.
298 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
I. INTRODUCTION
1
NAT'L INST. OF MENTAL HEALTH, HEALTH & OUTREACH, STATISTICS
(2009), http://www.nimh.nih.gov/health/statistics/index.shtml.
2
Press Release, Nancy Pelosi, Speaker of the House, House of
Representatives, Pelosi: Passage of Mental Health Parity Bill Gives Hope and Help
to Millions of American Families (Sept. 23, 2008), http://speaker.house.gov
/newsroom/pressreleases?id=0831.
2009] MENTAL HEALTH PARITY AND ADDICTION 299
basis.3 This note suggests that both of these reasons also support the
advancement of an amendment that would provide a specific list of severe
mental illnesses to be covered instead of leaving it up to the states and
group health plans to determine.
While the House of Representatives and a handful of states have
advocated or supported a definition of mental illness that includes all of the
diseases listed in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders
(DSM), published by the American Psychiatric Association, this note does
not advocate for such an approach. Rather, this note suggests that certain
severe biologically based mental illnesses, specifically those based on the
definition advocated by Paul Wellstone and Pete Domenic in 1999, should
be listed under the definition of mental illness that, at a minimum, insurers
should be required to cover. This proposition is supported by evidence that
group health plan costs for employers will not increase greatly and that
societal costs, such as homelessness and loss of productivity in the
workplace, will be greatly reduced when mental illness and substance use
disorders are adequately treated.
Part I will discuss the history of federal mental parity law and the
efforts to achieve parity; Part II will discuss the specific provisions of the
Paul Wellstone and Pete Domenici Mental Health Parity and Addiction
Equity Act of 2008 and the fact that the bill does not provide explicit
definitions for mental health conditions or substance use disorders; Part III
will discuss how the states define mental illness; Part IV will cover recent
developments supporting the biological basis of mental illness; and Part V
will discuss the diminished societal costs that will come with the addition
of parity in mental illness insurance coverage. The argument that coverage
of specific illnesses will be cost prohibitive is not sound. Certain illnesses
have been found to have a biological basis and, at a minimum, a specific
list of illnesses should be included in the parity legislation in order to
ensure that individuals throughout the country receive equal treatment and
coverage.
4
Dana L. Kaplan, Can Legislation Alone Solve America’s Mental Health
Dilemma? Current State Legislative Schemes Cannot Achieve Mental Health
Parity, 8 QUINNIPIAC HEALTH L.J. 325, 329 (2005). “Ninety-one percent of small
firms and 99% of large firms offer mental health and substance abuse coverage in
their most used medical plans.” Id. at n.26. These medical plans restricted one or
all of the following for mental illness treatments: inpatient day limitations, office
visit limitations, annual and/or lifetime maximums, or higher deductibles and co-
payment rates. Id.
5
Id. at 329.
6
See id.
7
Vallerie Propper & Ginger L. Pomiecko, Parity for Mental Health: History
and Consequences, in PUBLIC HEALTH MANAGEMENT & POLICY (2009),
http://www.case.edu/med/epidbio/mphp439 (last visited Nov. 21, 2009).
8
Univ. of Miami, Miller Sch. of Med. Health Insurance and Portability Act
of 1996 (HIPAA), http://privacy.med.miami.edu/glossary/xd_hipaa.htm (last
visited Jan. 25, 2008).
9
142 CONG. REC. H9473-9564 (1996).
2009] MENTAL HEALTH PARITY AND ADDICTION 301
increase the coverage of mental health services under health plans without
increasing such premiums.10 In the end, Senator Kassebaum and Kennedy
decided to remove the amendment in order to pass their bill more swiftly.11
Both of these men had personal experiences with mental illness,
driving them to further advocate for this bill. Senator Domenici’s daughter
suffers from schizophrenia and Senator Wellstone’s brother suffers from
bipolar disease. Wellstone and Domenici once again attempted to gain the
passage of the MHPA when they attached the amendment to the Employee
Retirement Income Security Act of 1974 and to the Public Health Services
Act.12 This time the supporters of the amendment threatened to filibuster if
the amendment was removed, as it had been in 1996.13
10
Id.
11
See id.
12
Mental Health Parity Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-204, § 702, 110 Stat.
2944 (current versions at 42 U.S.C. § 300gg-5 (2006); 29 U.S.C. § 1185a (2006)).
13
See Propper & Pomiecko, supra note 7.
14
29 U.S.C. § 1185a (Supp. II 1996) (current version at 29 U.S.C. § 1185a
(2006)).
15
Glen Cheng, Note, Caring for New Jersey’s Children with Autism: A
Multifaceted Struggle for Parity, 60 RUTGERS L. REV. 997, 1016 (2008).
16
42 U.S.C. § 300gg-5(f) (Supp. II 1996) (repealed 2008).
17
See Cheng, supra note 15, at 1016 & n.135. “Public Law 107-116, § 701(a)
extended the sunset to December 31, 2002. Public Law 107-313, § 2(a) extended
the sunset to December 31, 2003. Public Law 108-197, § 2(a) extended the sunset
to December 31, 2004. Public Law 108-311, § 302(c) extended the sunset to
December 31, 2005.” Id. at n.135.
302 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
18
See Kaplan, supra note 4, at 330.
19
Id.
20
Id. at 342.
21
Id.
22
29 U.S.C. § 1185a(a)(1)(A) (Supp. II 1996) (current version at 29 U.S.C. §
1185a (2006)).
23
Id. § 1185a(a)(1)(B).
24
Id. § 1185a(a)(2)(B).
25
Id. § 1185a(a)(2)(A).
26
Michael J. Carroll, Note, The Mental Health Parity Act of 1996: Let It
Sunset if Real Changes Are Not Made, 52 DRAKE L. REV. 553, 557-58 (2004).
2009] MENTAL HEALTH PARITY AND ADDICTION 303
The bill also did not include coverage for substance abuse
treatment. Many found this to be illogical due to the fact that many people
who suffer from mental illnesses also experience a co-occurring substance
abuse problem.29 The co-occurrence or dual diagnosis is often known as
comorbidity.30 Treatment for substance use disorders is a critical element
in an individual’s treatment for a mental disorder; similarly, treatment for a
mental illness is a critical element in the recovery of a person with a
substance use disorder.31 Often times the two are intertwined and recovery
from either disorder is dependent upon the other.32 Treatment of each
disorder separately has proven to be ineffective and research supports
treatment that addresses both conditions.33 A successful model of such
treatment includes case management, group interventions, and assertive
outreach to bring people into treatment.34
The Journal of the American Medical Association has found that
roughly fifty percent of individuals with severe mental disorders are
affected by substance use disorders; thirty-seven percent of alcohol abusers
and fifty-three percent of drug abusers also have at least one serious mental
27
Id. at 557.
28
Id. at 561.
29
E.g., Charity Felts, Comment, Dealing with a Depressed Workforce: Are
American Employers Doing Enough to Support the Mental Health Challenges
Affecting Today’s Employees? 9 SCHOLAR 119, 129 (2006).
30
Id. at 129-30 & n. 64.
31
Id. at 129-30.
32
Id.
33
See id.
34
NAT’L ALLIANCE ON MENTAL ILLNESS, DUAL DIAGNOSIS AND INTEGRATED
TREATMENT OF MENTAL ILLNESS AND SUBSTANCE ABUSE DISORDERS (2009),
http://www.nami.org/Template.cfm?Section=By_Illness&Template=/TaggedPage/
TaggedPageDisplay.cfm&TPLID=54&ContentID=23049.
304 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
35
Id.
36
Id.
37
Id.
38
Julie Rovner, Mental Health Parity Approved with Bailout Bill, NAT’L PUB.
RADIO (2008), http://www.npr.org/templates/story/story.php?storyId=95435676.
39
Id.
40
Id.
2009] MENTAL HEALTH PARITY AND ADDICTION 305
41
Id.
42
Nancy Shute, Paying a High Price for Mental Health, U.S. NEWS, Oct. 25,
2007, available at http://health.usnews.com/articles/health/health-plans/2007/10
/25/paying-a-high-price-for-mental-health.html.
43
CONGRESSIONAL BUDGET OFFICE COST ESTIMATE (2007), available at
http://www.cbo.gov/ftpdocs/88xx/doc8837/hr1424ec.pdf.
44
Robert Pear, Bailout Provides More Mental Health Coverage, N.Y. TIMES,
Oct. 5, 2008, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2008/10/06/washington/
06mental.html.
45
Frederic J. Frommer, Wellstone Son Launches Push on Mental Health Bill,
BOSTON GLOBE, July 9, 2008, available at http://www.boston.com/news/
local/rhode_island/articles/2008/07/09/wellstone_son_launches_push_on_mental_
health_bill/.
46
See Pear, supra note 44.
306 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
Middle East with serious mental health issues.47 And lastly, the
experimentation with parity at both the state level and in the health
insurance program for federal employees, including members of Congress,
has proved workable.48
The new bill provides parity between medical and surgical benefits
and mental health or substance use disorders for all “deductibles,
copayments, coinsurance, and out-of-pocket expenses,” specifying that
there are to be no separate cost sharing requirements that apply only to
mental health or substance abuse disorder benefits.55 The bill also states
that there shall be no difference between treatment limitations for mental
47
Id.
48
Id.
49
H.R. 1424, 110th Cong. (2008).
50
Pear, supra note 44.
51
See infra Part II.A.
52
Pear, supra note 44.
53
Id.
54
Id.
55
42 U.S.C.A. § 300gg-5(a)(3) (West Supp. 2009).
2009] MENTAL HEALTH PARITY AND ADDICTION 307
56
Id. § 300gg-5(a)(3)(A)(ii).
57
Id. § 300gg-5(a)(3)(B)(iii).
58
Id. § 300gg-5(a)(5).
59
Id. § 300gg-5(c)(2)(A)-(B).
60
H.R. 1424, 110th Cong. (2008).
61
LONG-AWAITED BREAKTHROUGH ON FEDERAL MENTAL HEALTH PARITY
(2007), http://www.mhafc.org/pdf/FedParity2007.pdf.
62
Peter M. Panken et al., Employment and Labor Relations Law for the
Corporate Counsel and the General Practitioner, Litigating Claims of Employee
Benefits, SN020 A.L.I-A.B.A. 169, 179 (2008).
63
Id.
64
Id.
65
Id.
308 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
It is not clear at this time how many companies will qualify for this
exemption. The states that have experimented with parity have found that
costs often did not rise to the one percent exemption level and frequently
costs stayed the same or decreased.66 For example, when Texas
implemented parity for severe mental illnesses and substance use disorders,
a study found that there was a decrease of fifty percent in per-member, per-
person cost.67 Managed care was also introduced at the same time.68
Similar results were found in North Carolina, and a study on the impact of
mental health parity in California revealed that costs did not increase after
one year.69
The bill further states that insurers must publish the criteria for
medical necessity determinations.70 The insurer must also provide an
explanation for any denial of a claim made for mental health services.71
However, the bill does not provide an explicit definition for mental health
conditions or substance use disorders. The bill states that “the term ‘mental
health conditions’ and ‘substance use disorders’ are defined under the
terms of the group plans and in accordance with applicable Federal and
State law.”72
The House of Representatives had urged the inclusion of a
provision that would have required insurers to provide coverage for any
condition listed in the DSM; however this was met with strong
opposition.73 Many opposed the use of the DSM due to the fact that it
contains conditions such as caffeine intoxication, sleep disorders and jetlag.
In the end, the House dropped its requirement that all DMS-IV disorders be
covered equitably.
Without a clear definition of what the federal government
considers to be a mental health condition or substance use disorder, such
determinations will vary widely due to the fact that such definitions differ
greatly from state to state. This will result in a great variation in individual
coverage depending on where people reside. Additionally, with no clear
66
See Kate Mulligan, More Data Confirm Affordability of Parity, 37
PSYCHIATRIC NEWS 18 (2002), http://pn.psychiatryonline.org/cgi/content/full
/37/12/18.
67
Id.
68
Id.
69
Id.
70
See Pear, supra note 44.
71
Id.
72
42 U.S.C.A. § 300gg-5(e)(4) (West Supp. 2009).
73
See Pear, supra note 44.
2009] MENTAL HEALTH PARITY AND ADDICTION 309
74
Marcia C. Peck, M.D., M.P.H. & Richard M. Scheffler, Ph.D., An Analysis
of the Definitions of Mental Illness Used in State Parity Laws, 53 PSYCHIATRIC
SERVICES 1089, 1089 (2002), http://psychservices.psychiatryonline.org/
cgi/content/full/53/9/1089.
75
Id.
76
Id.
77
Id. at 1091.
78
Id. at 1089.
310 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
79
JERRY CONNOLLY & JILL STRASSER, PH.D., DEFINING “MENTAL OR
NERVOUS CONDITIONS,” 1st Sess., at 5 (Feb. 2006), http://www.cbs.state.or.us/ins/
public_meetings/sb_minutes/attachments/SB1_defining-presentation.pdf.
80
Id.
81
Id.
82
See id.
83
See Peck & Scheffler, supra note 74, at 1092 tbl. 2.
84
CONNOLY, supra note 29, at 5.
85
Id.
86
See Peck & Scheffler, supra note 74, at 1093 tbl. 3.
87
Id.; see also, IOWA CODE ANN. § 514c.22 (West 2007); N.J. STAT. ANN. §
17B:26-2.1s (West 2006); VA. CODE ANN. § 38.2-3412.1:01 (2007). On July 1,
2009, Massachusetts began to include autism in its definition of mental illness.
MASS. GEN. LAWS ANN. ch. 176B § 4A (2007).
2009] MENTAL HEALTH PARITY AND ADDICTION 311
88
MASS. GEN. LAWS ANN. ch. 176B, § 4A(a) (West 2009); MO. ANN. STAT. §
376.826(4)(b),(d) (West 2002); S.C. CODE ANN. § 38-71-290 (1976); VA. CODE
ANN. § 38.2-3412.1:01(E) (LexisNexis 2007).
89
VA. CODE ANN. § 38.2-3412.1:01(E) (LexisNexis 2007). See MASS. GEN.
LAWS ANN. ch. 176B, § 4A(c) (West 2009) which states that "[A]ny such
subscription certificate shall also provide benefits on a non-discriminatory basis for
children and adolescents under the age of 19 for the diagnosis and treatment of
non-biologically-based mental, behavioral or emotional disorders, as described in
the most recent edition of the DSM, which substantially interfere with or
substantially limit the functioning and social interactions of such a child or
adolescent." This would include attention deficient/hyperactive disorder; however,
it is not defined as a "biologically based" mental illness by Massachusetts.
90
MASS. GEN. LAWS ANN. ch. 176B, § 4A(a) (West 2009); MO. ANN. STAT. §
376.826(4)(c) (West 2002); N.H. Rev. Stat. Ann. § 417-E:1(III)(i) (LexisNexis
2009).
91
CAL. INS. CODE § 10123.15 (West 2005).
92
ME. REV. STAT. ANN. tit. 24-A § 2843(5-C)(A), (5-D)(A) (2000).
93
See Peck & Scheffler, supra note 74, at 1090, 1091 tbl.1.
312 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
94
Id. at 1090.
95
JERRY CONNOLLY & JILL STRASSER, DEFINING “MENTAL OR
NERVOUS CONDITIONS,” Address before the Senate Advisory Committee,
(Feb. 27, 2006).
96
NAT’L ALLIANCE ON MENTAL ILLNESS, PRIORITY AND SPECIAL POPULATION
(2009), http://www.nami.org/Content/NavigationMenu/Inform_Yourself/About_
Public_Policy/NAMI_Policy_Platform/2_Priority_and_Special_Populations.htm
(last visited January 26, 2009).
97
Peck & Scheffler, supra note 74, at 1091.
98
42 U.S.C.A. § 300gg-5(e)(4) (West. Supp. 2009).
99
In addition to a lack of consensus on the state level for mental illness,
Medicaid coverage that individuals receive also varies greatly from state to state.
The states have wide latitude within the confines of the federal guidelines and
therefore the number of people covered and the amounts that each states spends on
services varies across the states. Similar to this note, this has led to a discussion of
solutions that would result in more equitable coverage across the states. See John
Holahan & David Liska, Variations in Medicaid Spending Among States Series A,
2009] MENTAL HEALTH PARITY AND ADDICTION 313
variation does not appear with regard to what the states view to be a
physical illness. In fact the states do not even deem it necessary to
statutorily define physical illness. Therefore, with such a wide variation on
the definition of mental illness in state laws, insurers will likely try to adopt
the most stringent and narrow definitions of mental illness. As evidenced
by the varying state laws, depending on the state in which one resides, the
illnesses covered vary greatly.
The way society views mental illness has greatly evolved over the
last two centuries.100 The most recent report from the Surgeon General
found that the stigma attached to mental illness dates back to the 19th
century separation between mental health treatment and mainstream
treatment in the United States.101 National surveys have tracked the
public’s perception of mental illness since the 1950’s.102 The Surgeon
General’s Report states that “[i]n the 1950s, the public viewed mental
illness as a stigmatized condition and displayed an unscientific
understanding of mental illness.”103 In contrast, a 1996 survey found that
people had a greater scientific understanding of mental illness; however,
there was still a large amount of social stigma and people were more
inclined to consider an individual with schizophrenia to have a mental
illness in comparison to an individual with depression.104
Mental illness is not diagnosed in the same way that physical
illnesses may be diagnosed. One cannot test for mental illness by doing a
105
NAT’L INST. OF HEALTH, THE SCIENCE OF MENTAL ILLNESS 23 (2005),
http://science-education.nih.gov/supplements/nih5/Mental/guide/info-mental-a.htm
(last visited March 5, 2009).
106
Id.
107
Id.
108
Id. at 23-24.
109
Okianer Christian Dark, Tort Liability and the “Unquiet Mind”: A
Proposal to Incorporate Mental Disabilities into the Standard of Care, 30 T.
MARSHALL L. REV. 169, 202 n.176 (2004).
110
Id.
111
See MENTAL HEALTH: A REPORT OF THE SURGEON GENERAL, supra note
100, at 5, 15.
112
See NAT’L INST. OF HEALTH, supra note 105, at 21.
113
Id.
2009] MENTAL HEALTH PARITY AND ADDICTION 315
114
Id. at 24.
115
Id. at 25.
116
Id.
117
Id. at 25-26.
118
Sarah Kershaw, Insure Me, Please, The Murky Politics of Mind-Body,
N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 30, 2008, at WK, available at
http://www.nytimes.com/2008/03/30 /weekinreview/30kers.html.
119
Proclamation No. 6158, 55 Fed. Reg. 29,553-54 (July 20, 1990).
120
See, e.g., Richard E. Gardner, III, Comment, Mind Over Matter?: The
Historical Search for Meaningful Parity Between Mental and Physical Health
Care Coverage, 49 EMORY L.J. 675, 682 (2000); Kershaw, supra note 118.
121
Gardner, supra note 120, at 682.
122
Id. at 682-83.
316 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
123
See Pear, supra note 44.
124
See Gardner, supra note 120, at 683-85.
125
Id. at 683.
126
NAT’L ALLIANCE ON MENTAL ILLNESS, SCHIZOPHRENIA (2009),
http://www.nami.org/Content/ContentGroups/Helpline1/Schizophrenia_Fact_Sheet
.htm.
127
Subhagata Chattopadhyay, Tracking Genetic and Biological Basis of
Schizophrenia, 2 INTERNET J. MENTAL HEALTH (2004).
128
See generally, Richard E. Straub & Daniel R. Weinberger, Schizophrenia
Genes-Famine to Feast, 60 BIOLOGICAL PSYCHIATRY 81, 82 (2006).
129
Martha E. Shenton et al., A Review of MRI Findings in Schizophrenia, 49
SCHIZOPHRENIA RES. 1, 23, 34-35 (2001).
130
See id. at 35.
131
Jyrki Ahveninen et al., Inherited Auditory-Cortical Dysfunction in Twin
Pairs Discordant for Schizophrenia, 60 BIOLOGICAL PSYCHIATRY 612, 613-14
(2006).
132
See Gardner, supra note 120, at 683.
2009] MENTAL HEALTH PARITY AND ADDICTION 317
133
See Dark, supra note 109, at 202.
134
NAT’L ALLIANCE ON MENTAL ILLNESS, MAJOR DEPRESSION (2009),
http://www.nami.org/Template.cfm?Section=By_Illness&template=/ContentMana
gement/ContentDisplay.cfm&ContentID=7725 .
135
Id.
136
See Gardner, supra note 120, at 684.
137
Id. at 685.
138
Id.
139
NAT’L ALLIANCE ON MENTAL ILLNESS, BIPOLAR DISORDER (2009),
http://www.nami.org/Template.cfm?Section=By_Illness&Template=/TaggedPage/
TaggedPageDisplay.cfm&TPLID=54&ContentID=23037.
140
Id.
141
Id.
142
Id.
318 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
biological basis has emerged through recent research” are excluded from
the definition of mental illness by many states.143
The advocates of mental health parity have tried to incorporate
specific definitions of mental illness in past legislation. In 1999, Senators
Domenici and Wellstone introduced the Mental Health Equitable
Treatment Act of 1999.144 This bill provided for specific illnesses to be
covered called “severe biologically based mental illness” which included
“schizophrenia, bipolar disorder, major depression, obsessive compulsive
and panic disorders, posttraumatic stress disorder, autism, and other severe
and disabling mental disorders such as severe anorexia nervosa and
attention-deficit/hyper activity disorder.”145 This bill did not pass and three
years later they introduced the Mental Health Equitable Treatment Act of
2002.146 This bill advocated for a broader definition of mental illness and
stated that mental health benefits should include “all categories of mental
health conditions listed in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental
Disorders, Fourth Edition, or the most recent edition.”147 This was the
position advocated by the House of Representatives during the debate over
the Paul Wellstone and Pete Domenici Mental Health Parity and Addiction
Equity Act of 2008, but it was ultimately rejected.148
With the growing acceptance of mental illnesses and their
biological basis, there is no reason not to have a specific list of severe
mental illness and substance use disorders in mental parity legislation. The
new legislation states that mental health conditions or substance use
disorders can be defined under the terms of the group health plan in
accordance with applicable federal and state law.149 Certain states do not
even define mental illness at all and leave it solely to the health plan
provider to define.150 The evidence that many mental illnesses are
143
Gardner, supra note 120, at 685. For example, many states exclude
obsessive-compulsive disorder, panic disorder, eating disorders, and post-traumatic
stress disorder. See supra Part III.
144
Mental Health Equitable Treatment Act of 1999, S. 796, 106th Cong.
(1999).
145
Id. § 2(b)(5).
146
Mental Health Equitable Treatment Act of 2001, S. 543, 107th Cong.
(2001).
147
Id. § 2(e)(3).
148
See Pear, supra note 44.
149
Emergency Economic Stabilization Act of 2008, Pub. L. No. 110-343,
§512, 122 Stat. 3881-3892 (2008).
150
See Kaplan, supra note 4, at 353.
2009] MENTAL HEALTH PARITY AND ADDICTION 319
biologically based and treatable is stronger today than it ever has been.
Therefore, moving forward, there should be an attempt to pass an
amendment that would more specifically state which mental illnesses
should be covered instead of leaving it to the states and group plans, which
results in a great variation in coverage that individuals may receive.
A good starting point for defining mental illness in parity
legislation would be the definition of mental illness advocated for in 1999
that listed only severe mental illnesses. This definition was much narrower
than the position advocated in 2002 and advocated by the House of
Representatives in 2008, which was to include all illnesses in the DSM.
While many states provide coverage for schizophrenia, bipolar disorder and
major depression, many states do not cover obsessive-compulsive and
panic disorders, PTSD, autism, ADHD and severe eating disorders, all of
which were included in the list of severe mental illness in 1999. An
amendment defining mental illness under these terms151 would provide the
minimum list of mental illnesses that insurers would be required to cover.
States should of course be allowed to provide additional coverage at their
discretion.
One of the reasons that MHPAEA was able to gain passage is that
concerns over the cost implications of providing parity for mental health
coverage were alleviated. Many feared that the cost of health plans for
employers and insurers would skyrocket, however that was proven to be an
unwarranted concern. As previously mentioned, a 2006 study in the New
England Journal of Medicine found that insurers' costs rose less than half a
percentage point when full parity was required for federal workers starting
in 2001.152 Additionally, the Congressional Budget Office Cost Estimate,
prepared in 2007, found that if the more generous House bill were enacted,
151
The definition would include “severe biologically based mental illness”
defined as schizophrenia, bipolar disorder, major depression, obsessive-compulsive
and panic disorders, posttraumatic stress disorder, autism, the eating disorders
anorexia and bulimia, and severe attention-deficit/hyperactivity disorder.
152
See Shute, supra note 42.
320 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
the costs for premiums would increase for group health insurance by an
average of only about 0.4 percent.153
In addition to the fact that employer costs regarding health plans
will not increase, many factors point towards proving that providing mental
health parity will reduce the costs associated with treating mental illness.154
For example, many studies have shown that individuals who receive
psychiatric care incur fewer medical costs over the long term and less
morbidity than those individuals who do not receive psychiatric
treatment.155
Psychiatrist Stephen M. Stahl, Director of the Clinical
Neuroscience Research Center, has found numerous hidden costs that are
associated with not treating major depression. Examples of these hidden
costs include but are not limited to: fatal accidents resulting from impaired
concentration; patient morbidity such as suicide attempts, accidents,
resultant illnesses, lost jobs, failure to advance in career and school; and
social costs such as dysfunctional families, absenteeism, decreased
productivity, job-related illnesses, and adverse effects on quality control in
the workplace.156 Employers have also found that productivity tends to
increase after workers are treated for mental illnesses and substance abuse
problems and that such treatments can reduce the number of lost
workdays.157 The American Psychiatric Association has reported that
untreated mental illness costs employers $70 billion each year, which is
primarily due to lost productivity.158
In addition to the impact that mental illness has on work
productivity, the mentally ill account for a large portion of both the
homeless and the incarcerated. The Federal Task Force on Homelessness
and Severe Mental Illness found that approximately one-third of the
153
CONGRESSIONAL BUDGET OFFICE COST ESTIMATE (2007) at 4,
http://www.cbo.gov/ftpdocs/88xx/doc8837/hr1424ec.pdf.
154
Maria A. Morrison, Changing Perceptions of Mental Illness and the
Emergence of Expansive Mental Health Parity Legislation, 45 S.D. L. REV. 8, 22-
26 (2000).
155
Id. at 26.
156
Id.
157
See Carroll, supra note 26, at 582.
158
Sara Noel, Comment, Parity in Mental Health Coverage: The Goal of
Equal Access to Mental Health Treatment Under the Mental Health Parity Act of
1996 and the Mental Health Equitable Treatment Act of 2001, 26 HAMLINE L.
REV. 377, 398-99 (2003).
2009] MENTAL HEALTH PARITY AND ADDICTION 321
VII. CONCLUSION
The Paul Wellstone and Pete Domenici Mental Health Parity and
Addiction Equity Act of 2008 is a significant advancement in providing
parity for mental illnesses and substance use disorders in that it finally
provided complete parity between medical and surgical benefits and mental
health and substance use disorders.167 Although it is a significant step up
159
Id. at 399 n.128.
160
John D. King, Candor, Zeal, and the Substitution of Judgment: Ethics and
the Mentally Ill Criminal Defendant, 58 AM. U. L. REV. 207, 211 n.12 (2008).
161
See id. at 212 n.15.
162
Id.
163
Id.
164
Maureen Carroll, Comment, Educating Expelled Students After No Child
Left Behind: Mending an Incentive Structure That Discourages Alternative
Education and Reinstatement, 55 UCLA L. REV. 1909, 1914 n.23 (2008).
165
“Cost was the second most influential factor cited by interviewees as
shaping the definition of mental illness.” Peck & Scheffler, supra note 74, at 1092.
166
See Shute, supra note 42; CONGRESSIONAL BUDGET OFFICE COST
ESTIMATE (2007), http://www.cbo.gov/ftpdocs/88xx/doc8837/hr1424ec.pdf.
167
See 42 U.S.C.A. § 300gg-5(a)(3)(A) (West Supp. 2009).
322 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
from all previous parity bills, the new bill still has a glaring deficiency
which, in order to be remedied, requires the passage of an amendment
which would aid in achieving full parity for all citizens across all states.
The bill currently does not specifically define mental illness or
substance use disorders. It states that the definition of mental illness and
substance use disorders should be in accordance with state and federal
laws.168 As evidenced by the varying state laws, the illnesses covered, and
thus how much coverage individuals are afforded, varies greatly depending
on the state in which one resides. With the growing acceptance of mental
illnesses and the evidence that mental illnesses are biologically based, it is
clear that mental illnesses are serious disorders that can be and must be
treated. Monetary costs have been a central part of the parity debates for
years and have often been a major factor in how states shape their
definitions of mental illness. Now that concerns over cost have been
alleviated, it is no longer a valid argument against a list of specific mental
illnesses to be covered. Furthermore, society as a whole will greatly
benefit from the adequate treatment of the mentally ill.169
An amendment should be passed in order to provide a specific
definition of what constitutes a mental illness or substance use disorder so
that the coverage people receive is not varied. The amendment should be
based on the definition that was advocated in the Mental Health Equitable
Treatment Act of 1999.170 That bill provided for specific illnesses to be
covered called “severe biologically-based mental illness” and included
“schizophrenia, bipolar disorder, major depression, obsessive compulsive
and panic disorders, posttraumatic stress disorder, autism” as well as
“anorexia nervosa and attention-deficit/hyper activity disorder.”171 An
amendment should be passed based on this previously proposed definition
and should identify each of the illnesses listed above. The MHPAEA has
done a great deal in providing parity between mental illness, substance use
coverage and physical illness coverage. However, in order to truly provide
parity for mental illness and substance use disorders, an amendment should
be passed so that individuals throughout the country receive the same level
of coverage and can receive treatment for the most debilitating mental
disorders.
168
Id. § 300gg-5(e)(4).
169
See supra Part V.
170
Mental Health Equitable Treatment Act of 1999, S. 796, 106th Cong.
(1999).
171
Id.
EXAMINING CURRENT PROPOSALS FOR
INCREASING THE FEDERAL ROLE IN
DEALING WITH COASTAL HURRICANE RISK
Louis Cruz *
***
***
I. INTRODUCTION
*
University of Connecticut School of Law, Juris Doctor Candidate for the
Class of 2010.
324 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
1
TOWERS PERRIN, HURRICANE KATRINA: ANALYSIS OF THE IMPACT ON THE
INSURANCE INDUSTRY 4 (2005).
2009] COASTAL HURRICANE RISK 325
II. BACKGROUND
2
COMITÉ EUROPÉEN DES ASSURANCES, REDUCING THE SOCIAL AND
ECONOMIC IMPACT OF CLIMATE CHANGE AND NATURAL CATASTROPHES 10
(2007).
3
Rick Jervis, Data Show U.S. Riding Out Worst Storms on Record, USA
TODAY, Oct. 22, 2008, at 3a.
4
See Eliot Kleinberg, Hurricanes May Trace to Cycles, Not Warming, PALM
BEACH POST, June 3, 2007, at 1C (noting that there are problems with researchers
basing their conclusions on a small statistical sample of scientifically significant
research); but cf. Cathy Zollo, Experts Spar Over Warming’s Impact, SARASOTA
HERALD-TRIBUNE, Apr. 15, 2006, at A1 (many climatologists argue there is
enough data, and some describe the recent uptick in storms as a natural cyclical
occurrence, while others attribute it to global warming).
5
See generally Stanley B. Goldenberg et al., The Recent Increase in Atlantic
Hurricane Activity: Causes and Implications, 293 SCIENCE 474 (2001) (discussing
the years 1995 to 2000 as experiencing the “highest level of North Atlantic
hurricane activity in the reliable record.”).
6
HOWARD KUNREUTHER, REFLECTIONS ON U.S. DISASTER INSURANCE
POLICY FOR THE 21ST CENTURY 2 (Am. Enter. Inst.-Brookings Joint Ctr. For
Regulatory Studies, 2007).
7
PHILIP J. KLOTZBACH & WILLIAM M. GRAY, EXTENDED RANGE FORECAST
OF ATLANTIC SEASONAL HURRICANE ACTIVITY AND LANDFALL STRIKE
PROBABILITY FOR 2009 26 (2009).
326 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
landfall the data is just as striking. From the 1930s to the 1960s, there was
an average of 1.8 storms per year making landfall, while over the last
twelve years that figure has risen to 2.2.8
In spite of the fact that the causes of this trend are beyond the
scope of this study, what is clear is that there has been a pronounced
increase in the number of coastal storms in the southeast Atlantic and Gulf
coasts over the past decade. While this meteorological trend is startling
when considered on its own, what makes it all the more attention worthy is
that it coincides with a trend of increasing coastal populations in the United
States.
8
Manuel Lonfat et al., Atlantic Basin, U.S. and Caribbean Landfall Activity
Rates over the 2006-2010 Period: An Insurance Industry Perspective, 59A TELLUS
499, 500 (2007).
9
KRISTEN M. CROSSETT ET AL., NAT’L OCEANIC AND ATMOSPHERIC ADMIN.,
POPULATION TRENDS ALONG THE COASTAL UNITED STATES: 1980-2008 6 (2004).
10
Id.
11
KUNREUTHER, supra note 6, at 1.
12
See Stanley A. Changnon, Characteristics of Severe Atlantic Hurricanes in
the United States: 1949-2006, 48 NAT. HAZARDS 329, 333 (2009) (noting that in
the 57 year period examined, the Southeast and South ranked first and second in
the United States for the number of losses from storm events).
13
CROSSETT ET AL., supra note 9, at 16.
2009] COASTAL HURRICANE RISK 327
14
Id.
15
Id.
16
Id.
17
Press Release, Prop. Cas. Insurers Ass’n of Am., Coastal Insurance
Concerns Demonstrate Need for New Catastrophe Solutions (Mar. 15, 2007),
http://www.pciaa.net/ (follow "Media Center: News Releases: By Date" menu;
then scroll to Mar. 15, 2007).
18
Id.
19
CROSSETT ET AL., supra note 9, at 18.
20
Id.
21
Id.
22
See Ieva M. Augustums, Nearly $1T of Insured Property in Ike’s Path,
USA TODAY, Sept. 12, 2008, http://www.usatoday.com/money/ economy/2008-09-
11-2141571223_x.htm.
328 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
over 7%.23 This annual growth rate will lead to a doubling of the total
insured coastal value every decade.24 In light of the recent increases in
extreme weather events in the Atlantic and Gulf coasts, this insured growth
takes on a number of serious implications. Due to the increasing frequency
of coastal storms, the growing size of coastal communities and the rapid
growth rate of insured exposure concentrated in coastal areas, extreme
weather related events are becoming increasingly financially destructive.
Five of the ten most expensive storms in U.S. history have occurred since
1990.25 Of particular import, the 2004/05 hurricane season was
unprecedented. In terms of U.S. insured loss, the six hurricanes that hit the
southeast Atlantic and Gulf Coasts make up half of the list of the twelve
largest disasters in the last forty years.26 Katrina alone is the most costly
event the U.S. insurance industry has ever experienced, resulting in more
than $61 billion in insured losses and $125 billion in total losses.27
Another important implication for these current trends in extreme
weather and coastal population growth is the need for a revaluation of
current policy. The federal role in coastal disaster policy has been the
subject of recent intense debate. To date, a flurry of legislative and private
sector proposals have followed in the wake of the 2004/05 hurricane
season. Each of these proposals envisions a reoriented role for federal
government in coastal catastrophe policy in an attempt to overhaul the
current coastal risk policy framework.
36
Id.
37
42 U.S.C. §§ 4012, 4013 (2006).
38
42 U.S.C. § 4012a (b)(1) (2006).
39
DEP’T OF HOMELAND SEC., PRIVACY IMPACT ASSESSMENT FOR THE
NATIONAL FLOOD INSURANCE PROGRAM APPEALS PROCEDURE 2, 5 (2006).
40
WILLIAM O. JENKINS, JR., U.S. GOV’T ACCOUNTABILITY OFFICE GAO-05-
532T, NATIONAL FLOOD INSURANCE PROGRAM: OVERSIGHT OF POLICY ISSUANCE
AND CLAIMS 8 (2005); Robert J. Rhee, Catastrophic Risk and Governance After
Hurricane Katrina: A Postscript to Terrorism Risk in a Post-9/11 Economy, 38
ARIZ. ST. L.J. 581, 610 (2006).
41
JENKINS, supra note 40, at 7.
42
U.S. GOV’T ACCOUNTABILITY OFFICE GAO-06-119, FEDERAL EMERGENCY
MANAGEMENT AGENCY: IMPROVEMENTS NEEDED TO ENHANCE OVERSIGHT AND
MANAGEMENT OF THE NATIONAL FLOOD INSURANCE PROGRAM 9 (2005).
43
Id.
2009] COASTAL HURRICANE RISK 331
came from loans taken directly from the federal treasury.44 Second,
because the premiums are subsidized and therefore artificially low,
property owners have no incentive to avoid moral hazard in or to invest
mitigation measures.45 This dynamic is demonstrated by the fact that
property owners that have repeatedly suffered damage from floods have
rebuilt their property in the same locations and continue to receive
subsidized rates.46 This is in stark contrast to the ideally analogous
scenario in which private insurers have the ability to cancel coverage.
44
See RAWLE O. KING, CONG. RESEARCH SERV., NATIONAL FLOOD
INSURANCE PROGRAM: TREASURY BORROWING IN THE AFTERMATH OF HURRICANE
KATRINA 1, 3-4 (2006).
45
See PIDOT, supra note 31, at 34.
46
Id; Spencer M. Taylor, Insuring Against the Natural Catastrophe after
Hurricane Katrina, 20 NAT. RESOURCES & ENV’T. 26, 28 (2006).
47
See PIDOT, supra note 31, at 21.
48
See Ins. Info. Inst., Residual Markets, Aug. 2009, http://www.iii.org/
media/hottopics/insurance/residual/.
49
Id.
50
ROBERT P. HARTWIG & CLAIRE WILKINSON, INS. INFO. INST.,
PUBLIC/PRIVATE MECHANISMS FOR HANDLING CATASTROPHIC RISKS IN THE
UNITED STATES 33 (2005).
51
See Ins. Info. Inst., supra note 48.
332 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
52
HARTWIG & WILKINSON, supra note 50, at 39.
53
Id. at 32, 34.
54
Id. at 40.
55
INS. INFO. INST., AN EXCERPT FROM: RESIDUAL MARKET PROPERTY PLANS
-- FROM MARKETS OF LAST RESORT TO MARKETS OF FIRST CHOICE 2 (2007).
56
See PIDOT, supra note 31 at 18.
57
John W. Rollins, Florida Property Insurance – The “Citizens” View (June
19, 2007), http://www.casact.org/education/spring/2007/handouts/rollins.pdf.
58
INS. INFO. INST., supra note 55, at 4.
59
Presently the Coalition consists of: Consumer Federation of America,
Defenders of Wildlife, Environmental Defense, Friends of the Earth, National
Wildlife Federation, Republicans for Environmental Protection, Association of
State Floodplain Managers, Americans for Prosperity, Council for Citizens Against
Government Waste, Competitive Enterprise Institute, FreedomWorks, Taxpayers
for Common Sense, Association of Bermuda Insurers and Reinsurers, Reinsurance
Association of America, and the National Association of Professional Insurance
Agents. See Smarter Safer, About Us, http://www.smartersafer.org/about-us/ (last
visited Sept. 30, 2009)(for more information on the coalition’s expanding roster).
2009] COASTAL HURRICANE RISK 333
72
Id.
73
Smarter Safer, supra note 62.
74
Id.; Property Mitigation Assistance Act of 2007, S. 2328, 110th Cong. §
2(m) (2007).
75
Property Mitigation Assistance Act of 2007, S. 2328, 110th Cong. § 2(m)
(2007).
76
See Smarter Safer, The Senate Should Support The Property Mitigation
Assistance Act of 2007, http://www.smartersafer.org/uploads/ S2328.pdf (last
visited Sep.15, 2009).
77
Smarter Safer, supra note 62.
78
Homeowners’ Defense Act of 2007, S.2310 §§ 101-108 (2007).
79
See id. § 201.
80
See id. § 301.
336 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
81
See Smarter Safer, The Senate Should Not Adopt S. 2310 (2007),
http://www.abir.bm/downloads/SmartNatCatBriefingPapers.pdf (last visited
Sep.15, 2009).
82
See id.
83
See id.
84
See id.
85
R.J. Lehmann, A Catastrophic Battle, BEST’S REVIEW, Oct. 2006, at 38.
86
Id.; Business Wire, Allstate CEO to Call for National Catastrophe Plan at
National Press Club on Friday, Jan. 13; Devastation of 2005 Makes Reform an
Immediate National Priority, Jan. 9, 2006, available at
http://findarticles.com/p/articles/mi_m0EIN/is_2006_Jan_9/ai_n15989710/ (last
visited Sept. 30, 2009).
2009] COASTAL HURRICANE RISK 337
87
Lehmann, supra note 85.
88
Press Release, Ins. Info. Inst., Reforms Needed to Prepare for Major
Catastrophes, Insurance CEOs Tell Forum, http://www.iii.org/media/
updates/archive/press.748575/ (Jan.10, 2006).
89
Homeowners Insurance Protection Act of 2005, H.R. 4366, 109th Cong. § 4
(2005).
90
Id. § 7(b)(6)(B).
91
Id. § 7(a).
92
Id. § 7(b)(3).
93
David Dankwa, Allstate Takes Hot Seat as Industry Debates Catastrophe-
Fund Options, BESTWIRE Jan. 16, 2006, available at
http://www3.ambest.com/Frames/FrameServer.asp?AltSrc=23&Tab=1&Site=news
&refnum=80532.
94
The Travelers Cos., Insurance Agents, Travelers, Nationwide Urge Coastal
Wind Policy, INS. J., July 16, 2008, http://www.insurancejournal.com/news
/national/2008/07/16/91909.html.
338 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
95
Id.
96
See id.
97
THE TRAVELERS INST., TRAVELERS COASTAL WIND ZONE PLAN 5 (2009),
http://www.travelers.com/iwcm/Trv/docs/TRV_Coastal_Wind_ Zone_Web.pdf.
98
Id. at 6.
99
Id. at 5.
100
Id.
101
Jay S. Fishman, Before the Next 'Big One' Hits, WALL ST. J., Aug. 27,
2007, at A10.
102
Id.
103
THE TRAVELERS INST., supra note 97, at 6.
104
Id.
2009] COASTAL HURRICANE RISK 339
return for reinsurance that would be used to support the regional fund.105
The threshold for the Travelers/Nationwide federal reinsurance mechanism
has yet to be finalized as it is stated to be for “extreme events (such as
hurricanes causing losses several times greater than those arising out of
Hurricane Katrina).”106
105
See supra Part III.B.
106
The Travelers Cos., supra note 94.
107
See The Hartford Fin. Serv. Group Inc., The Hartford Unveils National
Coastal Home Insurance Plan, INS. J., July 31, 2008,
http://www.insurancejournal.com/news/national/2008/07/31/92393.htm (noting
that the plan will include subsidized premiums for homeowners and a federal
reinsurance program).
108
Daniel Hays, Hartford Proposes National Cat Plan Featuring Federal
Backstop, IRA-Type Fund, NAT’L UNDERWRITER – PROP. & CAS. INS., Aug. 4,
2008, available at 2008 WLNR 14506223 (quotation omitted).
109
Id.
110
See RAMANI AYER, THE HARTFORD FIN. SERV. GROUP, BUILDING A
NATURAL CATASTROPHE SOLUTION 5 (2007), http://www.coastalpartner
ship.org/documents/CCP Plan Outline.pdf (noting that the Hartford proposes “the
creation of IRA-like savings vehicles – perhaps called ‘supplemental catastrophic
security accounts’”).
340 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
111
Id.
112
Id. at 6.
113
Hays, supra note 108.
114
Id.
115
U.S. GOV’T ACCOUNTABILITY OFFICE, GAO-08-7 PUBLIC POLICY OPTIONS
FOR CHANGING THE FEDERAL ROLE IN NATURAL CATASTROPHE INSURANCE 35
(2007).
116
Ayer, supra note 110, at 5.
117
Id.
118
Id. at 6.
119
Id.
120
Id.
2009] COASTAL HURRICANE RISK 341
121
See Amie Parnes, Bill Seeks to Provide Homeowners Insurance Relief,
NAPLES NEWS, Aug. 3, 2007, available at http://www.naplesnews.com/
news/2007/aug/03/bill_seeks_provide_homeowners_insurance_relief/.
122
Id.
123
See Homeowners’ Defense Act of 2007, H.R. 3355, 110th Cong. §§ 2(b),
101(d), 102 (2007).
124
See id. § 102.
125
See id. §§ 301-303.
126
Id. § 305.
127
Id.
128
H.R. 3355, § 305.
342 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
129
See id. § 202.
130
Id. § 201.
131
NAT’L ASS’N OF INS. COMM’RS, NATURAL CATASTROPHE RISK: CREATING
A COMPREHENSIVE NATIONAL PLAN 2 (Version 15a 2009),
http://www.naic.org/documents/committees_c_090615_nat_catastrophe_paper_dra
ft.pdf.
132
See id. at 7.
133
Id. at 7-8.
134
Id. at 9.
135
Id. at 10.
136
NAT’L ASS’N OF INS. COMM’RS, supra note 131, at 8.
2009] COASTAL HURRICANE RISK 343
due to natural disaster.137 At this point coastal the NAIC plan would not
require coastal residents purchase an all perils policy, however, the
availability of such a policy would be mandatory. 138
Pursuant to the catastrophe reserving aspect of the NAIC plan,
private insurers would be permitted to establish tax-deferred reserves to
pay expenses related to natural coastal disasters in order to further expand
the financial base available for underwriting catastrophe risk.139 The idea
underlying catastrophe reserving is that with an additional means of
building cash reserves insurance companies would be more able and
willing to underwrite policies. At present, tax-exempt reserves would
necessarily require amending the US tax code.140
Within the second layer of the NAIC’s plan, each state would be
asked to decide whether its exposure to coastal natural catastrophes
warrants creating a catastrophe fund or whether the private market has the
capacity to provide adequate coverage without additional funding.141 If
established the state catastrophe funds would be responsible for creating
and managing the insurance capacity of their respective regions.142 The
funds would have the discretion to implement their own operating
structures to best fit their particular needs.143 This would entail defining
catastrophic loss thresholds, determining appropriate private insurers/state
fund retention amounts, and ensuring that premium rates are actuarially
sound.144
The third and final layer of the NAIC plan consists of cautious
support for a federal reinsurance role.145 Although the NAIC acknowledges
that a federal reinsurance program seems to be a potential solution, the
Commission also acknowledges that the debate over whether federal
reinsurance involvement is necessary is still ongoing.146 Beyond this, the
specific character of the federal reinsurance mechanism the NAIC would
support is still not clear.
137
Id.
138
Id. at 9.
139
NAT’L ASS’N OF INS. COMM’RS, supra note 131, at 6.
140
Id.
141
Id. at 9.
142
Id.
143
Id.
144
Id.
145
See id. at 10-11.
146
Id. at 11.
344 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
147
NAT’L ASS’N OF INS. COMM’RS, supra note 131, at 11.
148
See Press Release, Prop. Cas. Insurers of Am., Windstorm Coverage
Widely Available, Federal Involvement Unnecessary (April 21, 2008)
(http://www.pciaa.org (follow “MediaCenter: News Releases: By Date:” then
scroll to “April 21, 2008”)).
149
See CHARLES PERROW, THE NEXT CATASTROPHE: REDUCING OUR
VULNERABILITIES TO NATURAL, INDUSTRIAL, AND TERRORIST DISASTERS 65
(Princeton 2007).
2009] COASTAL HURRICANE RISK 345
A. CAPACITY
150
Larry Lipman, Catastrophe Insurance Spawns Storm of Debate, PALM
BEACH POST, April 8, 2007 at A13.
151
Id.
152
Id.
153
Joel Garreau, A Dream Blown Away: Climate Change Already Has a
Chilling Effect on Where Americans Can Build Their Homes, WASH. POST, Dec. 2,
2006 at C01.
154
Lipman, supra note 150.
155
Associated Press, Citizens Property Insurance Increases Upset Policy-
holders in Florida, INSURANCE JOURNAL, http://www.insurancejournal.com
/news/southeast/2006/05/15/68332.htm (last visited Oct. 12, 2009).
156
Id.
346 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
157
See supra notes 61-83 and accompanying text.
158
Id.
159
See supra notes 150-56 and accompanying text.
160
See supra notes 104-6, 118-20 and accompanying text.
2009] COASTAL HURRICANE RISK 347
reinsurance industry does not have the capacity to handle major coastal
catastrophe.
Similarly, the plans put forth by all three of these private industry
leaders signal a perceived lack of private market capacity to cover
catastrophic coastal loss in that all three share common support for a
continued role for state and regional government overseen insurance
pools.161 Although insurance pools essentially spread risk, in part, to
prevent insolvency,162 the history of government organized coastal risk
insurance pools is such that after a catastrophe has struck they are often
funded in part by the public sector.163 In this sense, it is important to note
that each of the private industry backed proposals requires the erection of
some form of a system of government backed insurance pools.
Interestingly, because of their reliance on federal reinsurance
mechanisms, the private industry response to the capacity issue, as seen by
the proposals put forth by Allstate, Travelers’, The Hartford and State
Farm, have less to do with growing private industry capacity than enlisting
the federal government as a reinsurance safety net. Instead of approaches
that would augment private industry ability to cover catastrophic risk, such
as catastrophe reserving, the plans set forth by the three leading insurers
look to the federal government as a potential backstop as a primary means
of shifting the exposure of coastal loss. This approach is undesirable
because over-reliance on federal support implicates creating large liabilities
for the federal government and, as will be discussed shortly, unfairly cross-
subsidizing coastal residents at the expense of non-coastal residents.
161
See supra notes 87-88, 118 and accompanying text.
162
See generally, John Pollner, Catastrophe Risk Management: Using
Alternative Risk Financing and Insurance Pooling Mechanisms 87 (The World
Bank, Working Paper No. WPS2560, 2001), available at
http://www.worldbank.org/reference/ (follow “Documents and Reports” hyperlink;
then search “WPS2560”; then follow “Catastrophe Risk Management…”
hyperlink).
163
Id. at 85-86.
348 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
164
See supra notes 123-30 and accompanying text.
165
See supra notes 123-24 and accompanying text.
166
Id.
167
Id.
168
See Homeowners’ Defense Act of 2007, H.R. 3355, 110th Cong. §102(6)
(2007).
169
See supra notes 145-46 and accompanying text.
2009] COASTAL HURRICANE RISK 349
catastrophe capital bases.170 This sort of option represents the most direct
means of increasing private market capacity to deal with coastal storms.
170
See supra note 139 and accompanying text.
171
Larry Lipman, Catastrophe Insurance Spawns Storm of Debate, PALM
BEACH POST, Apr. 8, 2007, at A13.
172
See id.
173
Press Release, Reinsurance Ass’n of Am., RAA Testifies Before Senate
Banking, Housing, and Urban Affairs Committee (Apr. 11, 2007),
www.reinsurance.org/files/public/pr41107.pdf.174 See supra notes 61-83 and
accompanying text.
174
See supra notes 61-83 and accompanying text.
350 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
175
See supra notes 87-89, 118 and accompanying text.
176
U.S. GOV’T ACCOUNTABILITY OFFICE, supra note 115, at 34-35.
177
Id.
178
See supra notes 123-30 and accompanying text.
179
U.S. GOV’T ACCOUNTABILITY OFFICE, supra note 115, at 33.
180
See supra notes 136-39.
2009] COASTAL HURRICANE RISK 351
181
NAT’L ASS’N OF INS. COMM’RS, supra note 131, at 7; U.S. GOV’T
ACCOUNTABILITY OFFICE, supra note 111, at 34-35.
182
See NAT’L ASS’N OF INS. COMM’RS, supra note 131, at 8.
183
See U.S. GOV’T ACCOUNTABILITY OFFICE, supra note 115, at 34-35.
184
See The Nat’l Flood Ins. and Repetitive Loss Properties: Hearing Before the
Subcomm. on Housing and Cmty. Opportunity of the H. Comm. on Fin. Serv.,107th
Cong. 3 (2001) (statement of Rep. Bereuter, Member House Subcomm. on
Housing and Cmty. Opportunity).
185
See id. at 3-4.
352 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
The NAIC proposal contains policy measures that localize the risk
of catastrophic coastal storms, but also some that may lead to cross-
subsidization of coastal risk. By withholding unreserved support for a
federal reinsurance system, the NAIC plan, in its present form would
essentially only allow for catastrophe reserving and all-perils homeowners’
policies to be provided by private companies.196 These two remaining
aspects of the NAIC proposal would have very different impacts in terms
of cross-subsidization. While catastrophe reserving would allow private
insurers to build up capital reserves to better deal with future catastrophic
events, it would not directly involve having noncoastal tax-payers subsidize
coastal residents. However, the all-perils homeowners’ policy aspect of the
NAIC program may indirectly lead to moderate cross-subsidization. While
193
See supra notes 125-28,189-92 and accompanying text.
194
See KING, supra note 44 at 5; see also supra notes 129-31 and
accompanying text.
195
See supra notes 128-29 and accompanying text.
196
See supra notes 139-46 and accompanying text.
354 CONNECTICUT INSURANCE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 16:1
the NAIC would require these policies be written through private insurers,
the all-perils option could lead to government subsidies for low-income
property owners to afford such coverage.197
VI. CONCLUSION
197
U.S. GOV’T ACCOUNTABILITY OFFICE, supra note 115, at 34-35.
198
See Kerry Emanuel, Increasing Destructiveness of Tropical Cyclones Over
the Past 30 Years, 436 NATURE 686 (2005).
199
See supra notes 9-22 and accompanying text
200
See supra note 24 and accompanying text.
2009] COASTAL HURRICANE RISK 355
Pat Carbray,
Connecticut Insurance Law Journal,
65 Elizabeth Street,
Hartford, CT 06105;
[email protected].
Organization: ________________________________________
Department: _________________________________________
Address: ____________________________________________
____________________________________________________
E-Mail: ____________________________________________
_________________________________________________________
_________________________________________________________
_________________________________________________________
_________________________________________________________