Governance Vs Politics The European Union S Constitutive Democratic Deficit
Governance Vs Politics The European Union S Constitutive Democratic Deficit
Governance Vs Politics The European Union S Constitutive Democratic Deficit
Myrto Tsakatika
To cite this article: Myrto Tsakatika (2007) Governance vs. politics: the European Union's
constitutive ‘democratic deficit’, Journal of European Public Policy, 14:6, 867-885, DOI:
10.1080/13501760701497840
ABSTRACT Governance practices fail key democratic tests coming from interest
aggregation, deliberative and agonistic theories of democracy. It is argued that the
European Union is best described as a complex web of governance practices and,
therefore, that its ‘democratic deficit’ is constitutive. In contrast to what is often
thought, it is not by strengthening ‘good governance’ practices but by treading par-
allel paths of constitutionalization and politicization that the European Union could
eventually close the democratic gap.
KEY WORDS Agonism; democratic deficit; European Union; governance;
politicization.
INTRODUCTION
The early 1990s witnessed the transformation of the citizens’ ‘permissive
consensus’ that sustained élite decisions in the direction of European integration
into a ‘constraining dissensus’ (Hooghe and Marks 2005). Its latest and to date
gravest manifestation has been the rejection of the European Constitution in
popular referenda held in two of the Union’s founding member states: France
and the Netherlands. A persistent phantom, long familiar to observers of Euro-
pean Union (EU) politics, is once again casting its shadow over the continent:
the ‘democratic deficit’.
It is often thought that addressing the ‘democratic deficit’ is a question of
appropriate institutional engineering. If we agree on a democratic constitution,
if we further strengthen the European Parliament, if the Commission is better
held under check, if the Council is more transparent and national parliaments
more involved in the political process at EU level, the problem is bound to dis-
appear. On the other hand, there is the view that the EU cannot be democratic
because it lacks essential preconditions of democracy. There is no European
‘demos’ (Weiler 1995). The Union is not a sovereign state, but a union of sover-
eign states whose component parts are the only entities with legitimacy to make
and enforce democratic decisions. In the absence of a pan-European demos,
Journal of European Public Policy
ISSN 1350-1763 print; 1466-4429 online # 2007 Taylor & Francis
http:==www.tandf.co.uk/journals
DOI: 10.1080/13501760701497840
868 Journal of European Public Policy
institutional engineering will be pointless and the ‘democratic deficit’ a peren-
nial feature of European public life. A third cut on the ‘democratic deficit’ is
that if the EU is to be evaluated from the democratic point of view, such assess-
ment must involve non-statist democratic canons (Banchoff and Smith 1999;
Eriksen and Fossum 2000: 6– 9). The EU is, notoriously, neither a state nor
an international organization; it is a sui generis political entity. Consequently,
we should revise our democratic theories in order to set up novel democratic
tests appropriate for the evaluation of the kind of entity that the EU is.
In what follows the claim will be that the Union is not one of a kind. Rather,
it is best described as a complex web of governance practices. If we must revise
our theories of democracy in order to be able to capture a changing political
reality, this is the reality of a world populated with governance practices. It
will be argued that the EU is faced with a constitutive ‘democratic deficit’,
not by virtue of the fact that it is badly constructed in institutional terms or lin-
guistically and culturally diverse, but by virtue of the fact that it is a system of
governance. From the perspective of our revised theories of democracy, govern-
ance as such is argued to fail the democratic test. Therefore, if the ‘democratic
deficit’ is to be addressed, what needs to change is the EU’s governance
texture. Institutional engineering will be necessary but can only be part of the
solution. Another equally significant part will be the gradual development of
practices of political contestation, the sine qua non for the emergence of a
pan-European demos.
Deliberative
Governance Interest aggregation democracy Agonism
CONCLUSIONS
We are led to the conclusion that any future European Constitution should be
so articulated as to encourage popular participation and contestation and there-
fore greater popular ownership of the democratic process; at the same time, it
may be the case that EU citizens will be ready to accept a constitution only
when EU-level political agonism has fired up, triggering a process of identifi-
cation of EU citizens with a common EU democratic arena.
Certainly the proponents of aggregative, deliberative and agonistic con-
ceptions of democracy would opt for different versions of a common consti-
tutional settlement. One issue of contention would be the extent to which
direct or representative democracy ought to be privileged in constitutional
design.
In conceptual terms, the distinction between direct and representative
democracy cuts across all three conceptions of democracy discussed here.
Cohen and Sabel argue that direct participatory democracy is conducted by citi-
zens on the substance of policy, in aggregative or deliberative fashion; I would
here add agonistic. Likewise for representative democracy: citizens choose repre-
sentatives who make decisions on substance of policy in legislative assemblies
that operate in aggregative or deliberative fashion (Cohen and Sabel 1997).
Again I would add agonistic, involving groups of representatives engaging in
open political contestation. Nonetheless, it would be fair to argue that interest
aggregation democrats, deliberative democrats and agonists would differ as to
M. Tsakatika: Governance vs. politics 881
their approach towards institutionalizing forms of respectively direct or repre-
sentative democracy in the European Constitution.
From the point of view of interest aggregation democrats, it would be
important to limit provisions for direct popular participation through pan-
European referenda, petitions and citizen initiatives as much as possible,
given their élitist distrust of citizen involvement and the dangers they see
in ‘back seat driving’. Agonists would oppose, requiring that such measures
be provided for as extensively as possible, given that they would not only
empower citizens at large, but also give expression to and the possibility of
intervening in ‘subaltern counter-publics’. Mid-way between the two, delib-
erative theorists would call for an increased role for the representative insti-
tutions, particularly the European Parliament and the Court and spaces
where deliberation can freely develop along with the coming of age of a
European civil society (Habermas 2001). Among the three there would be
room to discuss which types of decision and which policy areas would be
more appropriate for direct popular involvement and where, on the contrary,
caution would be warranted and more representative forms of democracy are
to be preferred.
A second issue of disagreement might be the extent to which the constitution
should be rigid or flexible. For aggregative democrats it would be important to
fix clear and stable constitutional arrangements in order to ensure accountabil-
ity. From an agonistic point of view, on the other hand, it would be consistent to
require that any constitutional solution for the EU be flexible. For agonists, any
institutional arrangement reflects the dominance of particular interests and
power inequalities; it is therefore best to render the constitution susceptible to
change so as to make it more responsive to shifts in the dialectics of agonistic
contestation (Tully 1999). For deliberative democrats, a constitution should
entrench basic rights and provide necessary safeguards for cultural and linguistic
diversity, preconditions of free and equal deliberation. Yet, they would call for
not too definite a competence catalogue which would be open for revision at
fixed dates, this being the realization of ‘a system of basic rights under changing
historical circumstances’ (Habermas 2001: 23). A discussion would here need to
take place regarding possible ways to reconcile the requirements of accountabil-
ity, the protection of rights and the need to embrace change in line with the per-
ennial open agonistic search that is the political.
With appropriate constitutional arrangements that would provide the insti-
tutional incentives put to one side, which key actors could best provide the cat-
alyst for the articulation and strengthening of agonistic dynamics? Political
parties have traditionally played a crucial role in this respect when it came to
the national context. Yet, as Peter Mair has argued, parties are failing to fulfil
their basic functions: to engage citizens and to serve as the privileged political
space for political leaders (Mair 2005: 8).
Citizen participation and identification with political parties is declining,
which is detrimental to agonistic politics. It is giving up its place to apathy
for the many and specialized, partial and discontinuous engagement for the
882 Journal of European Public Policy
few through associations of ‘civil society’. At the same time, politicians are
increasingly engaging with the techniques of power and policy-making, insulat-
ing themselves from ideological party competition for office and popular
control. In other words, they are increasingly engaging in governance practices
rather than in party politics.
Civil society is an insufficient substitute for party political participation. ‘The
networks of global civil society may be useful in manifold ways, but as a substi-
tute for political communities they tend to eliminate the specific qualities of
politics in favour of its convergence with functionally determined social
relations’ (Thaa 2001: 520). However, it cannot be argued that two types of pol-
itical engagement are necessarily direct opponents in a zero-sum game. As Weale
has argued, party competition simplifies and simplification brings exclusion.
Civil society organizations in many cases bring forth the claims of excluded
groups (Weale 2006). They can and have been complementary components
of political contestation at the national level. There are signs that the develop-
ment of a similar relationship at the European level may be in progress (Wessels
2004). Were civil society organizations to invest a bit more of their efforts and
resources in pushing their claims and concerns up EU-level party agendas and in
public deliberation over how their concerns relate to party political concerns,
and a bit less on lobbying European institutions and participating in governance
practices, their actions would enhance agonistic democratic practice. And were
political parties to keep their doors more open to the concerns, challenges and
expertise of civil society organizations, social movements and ‘subaltern counter-
publics’ there might well be renewal and renewed interest in their activities by
the citizenry at large.
At the EU level the role of transnational political parties is determining the
development of agonistic democratic politics, because they are the only actors
that would be in a position to articulate general European-level political alterna-
tives, thus capturing the imagination of, and engaging, European citizens at
large. This is not only because political parties as types of collective actors are
meant to generate comprehensive political alternatives. It is also because they
would be in a privileged position to creatively reconcile differences in national
political cultures, overcome organizational difficulties, and provide unifying fra-
meworks for national political parties that share common political traditions, by
appealing to common value commitments and articulating principled, clear and
distinct responses to key European and global issues.
Were European-level political parties to assume the responsibility of such
tasks, they would not only become attractive public loci for deliberation intern-
ally and in relation to civil society, but they could also succeed where national
political parties have failed in Mair’s terms, rekindling the kind of agonistic
citizen engagement that is fading in national politics and capturing once
again political leaders’ undivided attention.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
The author would like to thank Dimitri A. Sotiropoulos, Euclid Tsakalotos,
Albert Weale and two anonymous referees for detailed comments on previous
drafts.
NOTE
1 Etymologically, ‘agonistic’, agon ¼ contest and ‘irenic’, irene ¼ peace, in Greek.
REFERENCES
Allison, G.T. (1971) Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis, Boston:
Little, Brown & Company.
Banchoff, T. and Smith, M.P. (1999) ‘Introduction: Conceptualizing legitimacy in a
contested polity’, in T. Banchoff and M.P. Smith (eds), Legitimacy and the European
Union, London: Routledge.
Bellamy, R. and Schonlau, J. (2004) ‘The good, the bad and the ugly: the need for con-
stitutional compromise and the drafting of the EU constitution’, in L. Dobson and
A. Follesdal (eds), Political Theory and the European Constitution, London: Routledge.
Benz, A. and Papadopoulos, Y. (eds) (2006) Governance and Democracy. Comparing
National, European and International Experiences, London: Routledge.
Bohman, J. (2000) Public Deliberation: Pluralism, Complexity and Democracy, Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Cohen, J. and Sabel, C. (1997) ‘Directly deliberative polyarchy’, European Law Journal
3(4): 313 – 43.
Commission of the European Communities (2001) European Governance: A White
Paper, COM (2001), 428 final, Brussels, 25 July.
Dahl, R.A. (1972) Polyarchy: Participation and Opposition, New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Della Sala, V. (2001) ‘Constitutionalising governance: democratic dead end or dead on
democracy?’, Constitutionalism Web-Papers, ConWEB, No. 06/2001.
Downs, A. (1957) An Economic Theory of Democracy, New York: Harper.
Dryzek, J.S. (1994) Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy and Political Science, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Dryzek, J.S. (2005) ‘Deliberative democracy in divided societies: alternatives to
agonism and analgesia’, Political Theory 33(2): 218 –42.
Eriksen, E.O. (2000) ‘Deliberative supranationalism in the EU’, in E.O. Eriksen and
J.E. Fossum (eds), Democracy in the European Union. Integration Through Delibera-
tion?, London: Routledge.
Eriksen, E.O. and Fossum, J.E. (2000) ‘Post-national integration’, in E.O. Eriksen and
J.E Fossum (eds), Democracy in the European Union. Integration Through Delibera-
tion?, London: Routledge.
Føllesdal, A. and Hix, S. (2005) ‘Why there is a democratic deficit in the EU: a response
to Majone and Moravcsik’, European Governance Papers (EUROGOV) No. C-05-
02. http//:www.connex-network.org/eurogov/pdf/egp-connex-C-05-02.pdf
884 Journal of European Public Policy
Fossum, J.E. and Trenz, H. (2005) ‘The EU’s fledgling society: from deafening silence
to critical voice in European constitution making’, ARENA Working Paper, 19/05.
Fraser, N. (1992) ‘Rethinking the public sphere: a contribution to the critique of actu-
ally existing democracy’, in C. Calhoun (ed.), Habermas and the Public Sphere,
Cambridge,: MA MIT Press.
Habermas, J. (1992) ‘further reflections on the public sphere’, in C. Calhoun (ed.),
Habermas and the Public Sphere, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Habermas, J. (1996) Between Facts and Norms, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Habermas, J. (2001) Why Europe needs a constitution’, New Left Review 11: 5 –26.
Hirst, P. (1996) ‘Democracy and civil society’, in P. Hirst and S. Khilnani (eds), Rein-
venting Democracy, Oxford: Blackwell.
Hirst, P. and Thompson, G. (1999) Globalisation in Question; The International
Economy and the Possibilities of Governance, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Honig, B. (1993) Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics, Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
Hooghe, L. and Marks, G. (2005) ‘The neofunctionalists were (almost) right: politiciza-
tion and European integration’, Constitutionalism Web-Papers, ConWEB No. 5/2005.
Imig, D. and Tarrow, S. (2000) ‘Political contention in a Europeanizing polity’, West
European Politics 23(4): 73– 93.
Jachtenfuchs, M. (1997) ‘Democracy and governance in the European Union’, in
A. Føllesdal and P. Koslowski (eds), Democracy and the European Union, Berlin:
Springer Verlag.
Magnette, P. (2003) ‘European governance and civic participation: beyond elitist citi-
zenship?’, Political Studies 51(1): 144 –60.
Mair, P. (2005) ‘Democracy beyond parties’, Center for the Study of Democracy,
University of California, Irvine, Working Paper 05/06.
Mouffe, C. (2000) ‘Deliberative democracy or agonistic pluralism’, Institute for
Advanced Studies, Vienna, Political Science Series.
Pateman, C. (1970) Participation and Democratic Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Pollitt, C. and Bouckaert, G. (2000) Public Management Reform: A Comparative
Analysis, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Przeworski, A., Stokes, S. and Manin, B. (eds) (1999) Democracy, Accountability and
Representation, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Roberts-Miller, P. (2004) Deliberate Conflict: Argument, Political Theory, and Compo-
sition Classes, Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press.
Schmitter, P. (2001) How to Democratize the EU. . . and Why Bother? Lanham, MD:
Rowman & Littlefield.
Schumpeter, J. (1947) Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, New York: Harper &
Brothers.
Scott, J. and Trubek, D.M. (2002) ‘Mind the gap: law and new approaches to govern-
ance in the European Union’, European Law Journal 8(1): 1 –18.
Steinberg, P. (2001) ‘Agencies, co-regulation and comitology – and what about poli-
tics?’. A critical appraisal of the Commission’s White Paper on Governance’. In
C. Joerges, Y. Mény, and J.H.H. Weiler (eds), Mountain or Molehill? A Critical
Appraisal of the Commission White Paper on Governance, http://www.iue.it/RSC
Taylor, R. (2000) ‘Liberalism and democracy in Habermas, Rawls, and Constant’,
http://www.gongfa.com/haeimasiluoersiziyouminzhu.htm
Thaa, W. (2001) ‘“Lean citizenship” The fading away of the political in transnational
democracy’, European Journal of Political Research 7(4): 503– 24.
Tully, J. (1999) ‘The agonic freedom of citizens’, Economy and Society 28(2): 161– 82.
Weale, A. (2006) ‘Party competition and deliberative democracy’, in J. Bara and
A. Weale (eds), Political Democracy and Party Competition, London: Routledge.
M. Tsakatika: Governance vs. politics 885
Weiler, J. (1995) ‘Does Europe need a constitution? Demos, telos and the German
Maastricht decision’, European Law Journal 1(3), 219 – 58.
Wessels, B. (2004) ‘Contestation potential of interest groups in the EU: emergence,
structure and political alliances’, in G. Marks and M. Steenbergen (eds), European
Integration and Political Conflict, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wolin, S. (1996) ‘Fugitive democracy’, in S. Benhabib (ed.), Democracy and Difference:
Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.