Legal Positivism: Notre Dame Law Review
Legal Positivism: Notre Dame Law Review
Legal Positivism: Notre Dame Law Review
12-1-1956
Legal Positivism
Reginald Parker
Recommended Citation
Reginald Parker, Legal Positivism, 32 Notre Dame L. Rev. 31 (1956).
Available at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/ndlr/vol32/iss1/3
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Notre Dame Law Review by an
authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected].
LEGAL POSITIVISM
The legal positivist holds that only positive law is law;
and by "positive law" he means legal norms by authority
of the state. Nothing else is "law" to him, even though
he may recognize other normative orders such as the
religious or moral orders, or etiquette. Furthermore, every-
thing thus created by state authority is law to the posi-
tivist, even though he may deplore the state of the law
and seek to change it. The name "legal positivism," inci-
dentally, appears to be preferable to "analytical juris-
prudence" or "analytical positivism," which are often
used, especially in connection with John Austin's work.'
The legal thinking of the positivist is no more "analyti-
cal" (either in the sense of critical thinking or pertaining
to analysis as opposed to synthesis) than that of, say, an
adherent of the historical school.
It is beyond the scope of this brief exposition to outline
the history of legal thinking, on which there exist many
excellent works.' Suffice it here to remind ourselves that
until the eighteenth century most, if not all, legal philoso-
phy was steeped in the theory of natural law. We may add
the observation that many of the great protagonists of one
or another natural law idea, such as Plato,3 Aristotle (to
some extent),' Cicero,' St. Thomas Aquinas, Richard
I E.g., Friedmann, LEGAL THEoRY 133 passim (3d ed. 1953).
2 See, e.g., ibid; CAINS, LEGAL PHLosoPHY From PLATO To HEGEL (1949).
3 For two recent studies of Plato's natural law, see: STmUSS, NATURAL
RIGHT AND HISTORY (1953); WILD, PLATO'S MODERN ENEWIIES AND THE THEORY
OF NATURAL LAW (1953). But see the somewhat skeptical review of these
two books in Friedrich, Two PHLosoPHIcAL INTERPRETATIONS OF NATURAL
Lv, 10 Diogenes 98 (1955).
4 KELSEN, The Metamorphoses of the Idea of Justice, in INTERPRETATIONS
OF MODERN LEGAL PHsaOsOPms 390, 399-409 (Sayre ed. 1947); Cairns, op. cit.
supra note 2, 77, 118, 121 (1949).
5 Who, contrary to some popular notions - e.g., WILKIN, ETERNAL
LAwYER: A LEGAL BIOGRAPHY OF CICERO (1947) -was not a lawyer but an
orator and politician with some legal training. Parker, Book Review, 60
HARv. L. REv. 1371 (1947); SCHULZ, HISTORY OF RoATAN LEGAL SCIENCE 51, 68-
69 (2d ed. 1953).
NOTRE DAME LAWYER [Vol. XXXII
41 Id. at 163. See also the quotation from Kelsen, note 20 supra.
NOTRE DAME LAWYER ('Vol. XXXII