"Let's Argue!": Communicative Action in World Politics Author(s) : Thomas Risse Source: International Organization, Winter, 2000, Vol. 54, No. 1 (Winter, 2000), Pp. 1-39 Published By: The MIT Press
"Let's Argue!": Communicative Action in World Politics Author(s) : Thomas Risse Source: International Organization, Winter, 2000, Vol. 54, No. 1 (Winter, 2000), Pp. 1-39 Published By: The MIT Press
"Let's Argue!": Communicative Action in World Politics Author(s) : Thomas Risse Source: International Organization, Winter, 2000, Vol. 54, No. 1 (Winter, 2000), Pp. 1-39 Published By: The MIT Press
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The MIT Press , Cambridge University Press , and University of Wisconsin Press are
collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to International Organization
Introduction
The controversy between social constructivism and rational choice has become one
of the most significant recent debates in the field of international relations and has
largely crossed disciplinary boundaries between international relations and compara-
tive politics.' In the U.S.-dominated intellectual community, this debate largely fo-
cuses on the differences between the "logic of consequentialism" theorized by ratio-
nal choice approaches and the "logic of appropriateness" conceptualized by mostly
sociological institutionalism. Using insights from recent controversies within the
German-speaking international relations community, I claim that processes of argu-
mentation, deliberation, and persuasion constitute a distinct mode of social interac-
tion to be differentiated from both strategic bargaining-the realm of rational choice-
and rule-guided behavior-the realm of sociological institutionalism. Apart from
utility-maximizing action, on the one hand, and rule-guided behavior, on the other,
human actors engage in truth seeking with the aim of reaching a mutual understand-
Earlier versions of this article were presented to the annual meeting of the American Political Science
Association, Washington, D.C., August 1997; the 3rd Pan-European Conference on International Rela-
tions, Vienna, September 1998; and the Max Planck Institute for the Study of Societies, Cologne, Ger-
many, 1998. I thank Michael Barnett, Tanja B6rzel, Mlada Bukovansky, Jeffrey Checkel, Thomas Diez,
Martha Finnemore, Stefano Guzzini, Anja Jetschke, Otto Keck, Mathias Maier, Marc Lynch, Rodger A.
Payne, Fritz Scharpf, Hans Peter Schmitz, Kathryn Sikkink, Jens Steffek, Katia Tieleman, Alexander
Wendt, Bernhard Zangl, Michael Zurn, two anonymous reviewers, and the editors of IO for their ex-
tremely helpful and constructive comments on the draft. Moreover, I thank the Ph.D. researchers at the
European University Institute for their lively arguing over "arguing" during my spring 1999 seminar.
Finally, while Harald Muller never commented on this particular article, his work strongly influenced my
own thoughts on the subject. Research on this article was partly funded by a research grant from the European
University Institute and by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (German ResearchAssociation).
1. For recent contributions and reviews of the debates in international relations, see, for example, Adler
1997; Checkel 1998; Finnemore 1996b; Finnemore and Sikkink 1998; Hopf 1998; Katzenstein 1996;
Klotz 1995; Price and Reus-Smit 1998; Schaber and Ulbert 1994; Wendt 1992 and 1999; as well as several
contributions in Katzenstein, Keohane, and Krasner 1998b. On related debates in comparative politics, see, for
example, Hall and Taylor 1996; Powell and DiMaggio 1991; and Steinmo, Thelen, and Longstreth 1992.
structivism. Is the debate about the role of ideas or cultural factors as opposed to
material interests in political life? Does it concern constitutive norms and identities
as opposed to instrumental interests of actors? Does it center on deep ontological,
methodological, or even epistemological differences?
Regarding epistemology, constructivists of various orientations disagree among
themselves as to the possibility of making truth claims and generalizations in social
sciences. But the methodological, epistemological, and ontological differences be-
tween, say, sophisticated rational choice and moderate social constructivism are usu-
ally vastly overstated. Rather, it might be helpful to distinguish between the two
metatheoretical approaches as emphasizing different logics or modes of social action
and interaction that are characterized by different rationalities as far as the goals of
action are concerned (Handlungsrationalitdt; see Figure 1).2 Each mode of action
can be thought of as an ideal type that rarely occurs in pure form in real life. If the
"games real actors play"3 usually combine several modes of social interaction, we
should not exaggerate the differences among metatheoretical orientations, such as
rational choice capturing the logic of consequentialism, on the one hand, and social
constructivism encompassing both rule-guided and deliberative behavior, on the other.
If behavior in the real social world can almost always be located in some of the
intermediate spaces between the corners of the triangle in Figure 1, one single meta-
theoretical orientation probably will not capture it. Rather, the controversies mainly
focus on how far one can push one logic of action to account for observable practices
and which logic dominates a given situation.
I start with the distinction introduced by James March and Johan Olsen between a
"logic of consequentialism" and a "logic of appropriateness."4 The "logic of conse-
quentialism" is the realm of rational choice approaches that treat the interests and
preferences of actors as mostly fixed during the process of interaction. Rational choice
focuses on strategic interactions in which agents participate on the basis of their
given identities and interests and try to realize their preferences through strategic
behavior. This is the realm of instrumental rationality whereby the goal of action is to
maximize or optimize one's own interests and preferences. To the extent that this is
only possible through cooperative behavior, egoistic utility maximizers are expected
to collaborate or coordinate their behavior with others. This is where rational choice
approaches are at their best, since they analyze those modes of action and interaction
where instrumental rationality prevails: "Rational choice is instrumental: it is guided
by the outcome of action. Actions are valued and chosen not for themselves, but as
more or less efficient means to a further end."'5 In international relations, neoliberal
institutionalism or rationalist regime analysis have convincingly shown that "coop-
eration under anarchy" is possible and that self-interested actors can achieve stable
2. In other words, I am not concerned with irrational behavior, which, by definition, is not goal-
oriented. But I want to emphasize that the term rationality cannot be and should not be confined to rational
choice and its specific understandings.
3. Scharpf 1997.
4. March and Olsen 1989 and 1998. I owe the suggestion of the triangle to the editors of IO.
5. Elster 1989, 22.
Logic of arguing
Logic of Logic of
consequentialism appropriateness
and enduring cooperation and overcome collective action dilemmas.6 Many ide-
ational accounts are compatible with an instrumentally rational logic of action. Un-
der conditions of uncertainty or incomplete information, for example, instrumentally
rational actors can use ideas as road maps or signposts indicating how they could best
realize their interests under given circumstances.7 Moreover, principled and causal
beliefs can enter the utility functions of actors, affect cost-benefit calculations, and
influence the strategic interactions themselves.
Most social constructivists in international relations and comparative politics em-
phasize a different rationality, the "logic of appropriateness": "Human actors are
imagined to follow rules that associate particular identities to particular situations,
approaching individual opportunities for action by assessing similarities between
current identities and choice dilemmas and more general concepts of self and situa-
tions."8 Rule-guided behavior differs from instrumentally rational behavior in that
actors try to "do the right thing" rather than maximizing or optimizing their given
preferences. Normative rationality implies constitutive effects of social norms and
institutions, since these rules not only regulate behavior, that is, they have causal
6. See, for example, Hasenclever, Mayer, and Rittberger 1997; Keohane 1984 and 1989a; Martin and
Simmons 1998; Oye 1986; and Zurn 1992. For general accounts, see Ostrom 1998; Ostrom, Gardner, and
Walker 1994; and Scharpf 1997.
7. Goldstein and Keohane 1993.
8. March and Olsen 1998, 951. On the following, see also Finnemore and Sikkink 1998.
effects, but also define social identities ("good people do X"). This is where the
"value added" of constructivism comes in. Following Nicholas Onuf, Fritz Kratoch-
wil, and Alexander Wendt, constructivism points to the constitutive role of ideational
factors.9 Socially shared ideas-be it norms ("collective expectations about proper
behavior for a given identity" 10) or social knowledge about cause-and-effect relation-
ships-not only regulate behavior but also constitute the identity of actors. The norm
of sovereignty, for example, regulates the interactions of states in international affairs
and also defines what a state is. Human rights norms not only protect citizens from
state intervention but also (and increasingly) define a "civilized state" in the modern
world. Although it is difficult to develop valid empirical indicators for distinguishing
the regulative from the constitutive effects of socially shared ideas,"1 social construc-
tivism's contribution to the study of ideas in international relations consists of empha-
sizing that collective norms and understandings constitute the social identities of
actors and also define the basic "rules of the game" in which actors find themselves
in their interactions. This does not mean, however, that constitutive norms cannot be
violated or never change. The content of the norm of sovereignty has changed dra-
matically over time, becoming more circumscribed, particularly when it comes to
human rights. But sovereignty still constitutes a state-as opposed to any other cor-
porate actor (a multinational corporation, for example)-insofar as we cannot define
what a state is without reference to the notion of sovereignty.
The constitutive effects of social norms also point to a further difference between
social constructivism and rational choice. Proponents of the former emphasize against
the latter the social aspect of ideational factors. They disagree with a methodologi-
cally individualist view of human action according to which "the elementary unit of
social life is the individual human action." 12 The fundamental insight of the structure-
agency debate is not just that structures and agents are mutually codetermined in a
causal way. The crucial point is that social constructivists insist on the mutual consti-
tutiveness of (social) structures and agents. Constructivists claim against individual-
ism that human agents do not exist independently from their social environment and
its collectively shared systems of meanings ("culture" in a broad sense). At the same
time, social constructivists maintain that human agency creates, reproduces, and
changes culture by way of daily practices. In sum, social constructivism occupies
a-sometimes uneasy-ontological middle ground between individualism and struc-
turalism by claiming that there are properties of structures and of agents that cannot
be reduced to or collapsed into each other.'3 This means for the study of ideas that
one can continue to study "beliefs" in terms of what is inside people's minds and
9. See Onuf 1989; Kratochwil 1989; and Wendt 1999. For an excellent review of their work, see
Zehfuss 1998.
10. Jepperson, Wendt, and Katzenstein 1996, 54.
11. A general rule could be that we find constitutive norms and the like whenever we cannot even
describe the very properties of actors, including corporate actors, without reference to some underlying
social rules. The same applies to interaction processes. We only "know" a chess game by its rules.
12. Elster 1989, 13. See Adler 1997, 324-25; and Wendt 1999, chap. 4, for the following.
13. For excellent statements on these positions, see Wendt 1999, chap. 4, and Adler 1997. On the
agency-structure debate in general, see Wendt 1987; Carlsnaes 1992; and Dessler 1989.
simultaneously insist that these beliefs are representations and enactments of social
and intersubjective culture. 14
So far, most of the controversy between rational choice and social constructivism,
at least in American international relations, has focused on the relationship between
the "logic of consequentialism" and the "logic of appropriateness." Thus, the debate
is concentrated on the lower axis of the triangle in Figure 1.15 Rationalist institution-
alism, for example, explains a great deal about the emergence of norms and institu-
tions, about the norm of reciprocity as the result of and the condition for cooperative
strategic interaction, and about the behavior of "boundedly rational" actors whose
information-processing capacities are constrained by social norms.16 The extent to
which an imagery emphasizing the constraining effects of norms can account for and
accommodate their constitutive effects is the subject of the debate between rationalist
and sociological institutionalism.
But this debate has overlooked the proposition that the "logic of appropriateness"
as introduced by March and Olsen actually encompasses two different modes of
social action and interaction. In many social situations, actors regularly comply with
norms that they have thoroughly internalized and that, therefore, are "taken for
granted." Whereas strategic behavior is explicitly goal-oriented, the "taken for grant-
edness" of norm-regulated behavior implies that enacting the norm need not be a
conscious process, even though norms that are no longer believed will probably
disappear or soon change. This is how the most powerful social institutions influence
behavior, and theorizing about the process is the realm of sociological institutional-
ism, which points to various socialization processes to explain how actors internalize
a given social norm. 17
However, March and Olsen also talk about rule-guided behavior as a conscious
process whereby actors have to figure out the situation in which they act, apply the
appropriate norm, or choose among conflicting rules.18 The more the norms are con-
tested, the less the logic of the situation can be captured by the statement "good
people do X" than by "what does 'good' mean in this situation?" or even "what is
the right thing to do?" But how do actors adjudicate which norm applies? They
argue. I suggest, therefore, that social constructivism encompasses not only the logic
of appropriateness but also what we could call a "logic of truth seeking or arguing"
(moving toward the upper corner of the triangle in Figure 1). When actors deliberate
14. There is a further corollary of this statement. Rational choice, beginning with methodological
individualism, has a hard time theorizing the social realm and nonindividualistic logics of social action,
whereas constructivism can easily accommodate the logic of consequentialism in the sense that there are
social circumstances in which acting instrumentally is appropriate and legitimate.
15. See the various reviews of this debate in Adler 1997; Checkel 1998; Katzenstein, Keohane, and
Krasner 1998a, 674-82; Kahler 1998; and Ruggie 1998.
16. See, for example, Axelrod 1997; Axelrod and Keohane 1986; and Keohane 1984 and 1989b. On
bounded rationality, see Simon 1982.
17. See, for example, Finnemore 1996b; Finnemore and Sikkink 1998; and Powell and DiMaggio
1991. For an excellent review of the various institutionalisms, see Hall and Taylor 1996.
18. See March and Olsen 1989 and 1998.
about the truth, they try to figure out in a collective communicative process (1)
whether their assumptions about the world and about cause-and-effect relationships
in the world are correct (the realm of theoretical discourses); or (2) whether norms of
appropriate behavior can be justified, and which norms apply under given circum-
stances (the realm of practical discourses).
Arguing implies that actors try to challenge the validity claims inherent in any
causal or normative statement and to seek a communicative consensus about their
understanding of a situation as well as justifications for the principles and norms
guiding their action. Argumentative rationality also implies that the participants
in a discourse are open to being persuaded by the better argument and that
relationships of power and social hierarchies recede in the background.19 Argum
tive and deliberative behavior is as goal oriented as strategic interaction, but the goal
is not to attain one's fixed preferences, but to seek a reasoned consensus. Actors'
interests, preferences, and the perceptions of the situation are no longer fixed, but
subject to discursive challenges. Where argumentative rationality prevails, actors do
not seek to maximize or to satisfy their given interests and preferences, but to
challenge and to justify the validity claims inherent in them-and they are pre-
pared to change their views of the world or even their interests in light of the better
argument.
Communicative action and the logic of argumentation and persuasion have not yet
been systematically explored in the American international relations debates.20 But
they have been the focus of a distinct German version of the controversy between
rationalists and social constructivists that has taken place in the Zeitschriftfiir Inter-
nationale Beziehungen (ZIB, Journal of International Relations) since 1994.2' This
debate focuses on the relationship between the "logic of consequentialism" and the
"logic of arguing" (the left-hand axis of the triangle in Figure 1). I use the ZIB debate
to conceptualize the logic of argumentative rationality and to make it empirically
applicable to international relations. Turning to this debate, I begin with some concep-
tual clarifications of the logic of arguing using Juirgen Habermas's theory of commu-
nicative action.22
19. Jurgen Habermas calls this "communicative action." Habermas 1981, vol. 1, 141-51. Since com-
munications are all-pervasive in social action and interaction-including strategic behavior (see later), I
prefer the term "argumentative" rationality, since the goal of such communicative behavior is to reach
argumentative consensus on validity claims of norms or assertions about the world.
20. See, however, Kratochwil 1989; and Onuf 1989. Although Kratochwil's and Onuf's work on norms
has been widely received in the American international relations community, their emphasis on communi-
cative behavior derived from speech act theory has been largely ignored. See also Alker 1996; Linklater
1996; and most recently Lynch 1999; and Payne 1999.
21. See Muller 1994 and 1995; Schneider 1994; Keck 1995 and 1997; Risse-Kappen 1995; Schmalz-
Bruns 1995; Jaeger 1996; Muller 1996; Prittwitz 1996b; and Zangl and Zurn 1996.
22. I am not interested in the endless debates about whether or not Habermas's social philosophy is
purely normative or can be applied to tackle empirical questions (see the various contributions in Elster
1998b and the excellent discussion in Chambers 1996, 155-72). My aim is to illustrate that we can shed
light on many important issues in international relations when we incorporate argumentative rationality
and deliberative processes in our theoretical "tool kit."
23. Elster 1986. For excellent reviews, see Saretzki 1995 and 1996.
24. See Morrow 1994; Schneider 1994; Cooper et al. 1992; and Farrell and Rabin 1996.
25. Schimmelfennig 1995 and 1997.
26. Habermas 1981, vol. 1, 385 (my translation). For the following, see Prittwitz 1996a; Saretzki 1996;
Lose 1998; and Eriksen and Weigard 1997.
27. Miller 1994, 28 (my translation).
28. Habermas 1981, vol. 1, 397-452.
ily causal assertions and beliefs. The second validity claim focuses on the moral
rightness of the norms underlying arguments (is writing an article on Habermas
morally justifiable while innocent children die?). Practical discourses justify and
criticize the validity claims of principled beliefs and norms. The third validity claim
concerns the truthfulness and authenticity of the speaker (do I mean what I say about
arguing, or am I just trying to position myself in an academic discourse?). The authen-
ticity of a speaker can be challenged in a discourse only to some extent (for example,
by probing the consistency between my words and deeds) but ultimately relies on
trust.
Habermas posits that our communicative practices work and are effective only
because we assume that we can revert to argumentation in order to challenge validity
claims made in our daily utterances. Communicative processes oriented toward achiev-
ing mutual understanding counterfactually presuppose an "ideal speech situation"
whereby nothing but the better arguments count and where actors try to persuade
each other and are themselves open to being convinced:
Interests and identities are no longer fixed, but subject to interrogation and chal-
lenges and, thus, to change. The goal of the discursive interaction is to achieve argu-
mentative consensus with the other, not to push through one's own view of the world
or moral values. Since the validity claims of identities and interests are at stake in
theoretical and practical discourses, an argumentative consensus has constitutive ef-
fects on actors. This point helps to clarify the mutual constitutiveness of agents and
social structure that social constructivism emphasizes. Agents are not simply the
puppets of social structure, since they can actively challenge the validity claims
inherent in any communicative action. At the same time, they are social agents that
produce and reproduce the intersubjective structures of meanings through their com-
municative practices.30
Argumentative rationality in the Habermasian sense is based on several precondi-
tions. First, argumentative consensus seeking requires the ability to empathize, that
is, to see things through the eyes of one's interaction partner. Second, actors need to
share a "common lifeworld" (gemeinsame Lebenswelt), a supply of collective inter-
pretations of the world and of themselves, as provided by language, a common his-
tory, or culture. A common lifeworld consists of a shared culture, a common system
of norms and rules perceived as legitimate, and the social identity of actors being
capable of communicating and acting.3' It provides arguing actors with a repertoire
of collective understandings to which they can refer when making truth claims. At
the same time, communicative action and its daily practices reproduce the common
lifeworld. Finally, actors need to recognize each other as equals and have equal
access to the discourse, which must also be open to other participants and be public
in nature. In this sense then, relationships of power, force, and coercion are assumed
absent when argumentative consensus is sought. This implies respect for two prin-
ciples: all interested parties may participate in the argumentative discourse, and all
participants have equal rights concerning making an argument or challenging a valid-
ity claim.32 I discuss these conditions further in the following sections.
How far can one push rational choice-based theories to accommodate argumentative
behavior? Otto Keck points out in this context that the assumption of "common
knowledge" about the structure of the game as prevalent in orthodox game theory
presupposes what should be problematic, that is, a common definition of the situa-
tion. In orthodox game theory, any uncertainty or ignorance about the structure of the
game (including the set of feasible actions of each player and the players' prefer-
ences) is common knowledge. The players know what other players are uncertain
about or ignorant of and the others know that they know it, and so on.33 Keck pro-
poses a family of communication games that are no longer based on the "common
knowledge" assumption, but start with incompatible definitions of the situation and
then model the decision of a player whether to communicate to the other in such a
way that points out the differences in their definitions of the situation. He conceptual-
izes communication as a choice between different verbal utterances, such as asking a
question, giving a hint, or concealing something. As a result, recipients of such infor-
mation might choose new ways of acting, learn about unforeseen consequences of
their actions, or even change their utility functions.34 Keck argues that a modification
of the assumptions of orthodox game theory, though not violating fundamentals of
rational choice, can help to incorporate meaningful communication into the game
and address two problems of rational choice identified by social constructivists: (1)
how can common knowledge be achieved? (2) how can preferences change during
the interaction itself?35
But communication in these games still involves exchanging information, whether
it concerns the world outside of the players or the players' utility functions. Players
have the choice of lying or telling the truth, of revealing or concealing their prefer-
ences. They choose according to these preferences and strategies. They want to reach
their goals and strategize. They might well change their view of the world or even
their utility functions resulting from the information received.36 At best, the players
in these communication games engage in rhetorical action as defined earlier. This is
not controversial, but it has little to do with challenging validity claims in a theoreti-
cal or practical discourse.37 Communication in truth-seeking discourses oriented to-
ward reaching a reasoned consensus is not motivated by the players' desire to realize
their individual preferences-be they egoistic or altruistic. Communication is moti-
vated by the desire to find out the "truth" with regard to facts in the world or to figur
out "the right thing to do" in a commonly defined situation.
One could ask, however, why actors are motivated in the first place to seek the
truth in negotiating situations. Rational actors interested in realizing their values and
desires must be interested in correcting false information and cognitions about the
outside world, the consequences of their action, and the preferences of their interac-
tion partners. As a result, they should be willing to discuss the validity claims of their
cognitions and should be open to being persuaded and changing their minds. It is
entirely possible that a slave convinces his or her master that the latter is economi-
cally and socially better off if the former is freed and employed by the master as a
paid worker. Bernhard Zangl and Michael Zurn claim that, therefore, argumentative
processes are entirely consistent with a rational choice program broadly defined.38 In
this case then, searching for the truth is motivated by the desire to change the situa-
tion in such a way as to solve or at least mitigate social dilemmas.
At this point, sophisticated rational choice and moderate social constructivism can
readily admit that each theorizes different modes of social interaction that are both
necessary to explain significant phenomena in the world but cannot be collapsed into
each other. For example, let us assume a dilemma situation that originates because of
differing and conflicting preferences (if preferences are in harmony, we neither need
to argue nor to bargain in order to achieve cooperation; sheer information should do)
and that requires collaboration rather than pure coordination to solve or mitigate it.39
Instrumentally rational actors should be interested in such a situation to "get the facts
right" and to acquire "common knowledge." Thus, truth seeking refers here to a
reasoned consensus on the "facts in the world" reached through a theoretical dis-
course. Although a change in underlying interests might result from such a consen-
sus, such a discourse does not require that actors question their preferences.
But "common knowledge" also refers to the "rules of the game," that is, the
underlying principles guiding the interaction. If the master is convinced to free the
slave, we have witnessed a process of persuasion in a practical or moral discourse
leading to a change of interests and identities. In this case, the participants in the
discourse need to be prepared to have their interests questioned and challenged.
Thus, a reasoned consensus about underlying principles of interaction-the "rules of
the game" -can no longer be reached if the participants follow a logic of consequen-
tialism, since their interests are at stake and subject to justification. Thus, it might be
36. Some of this can be captured by Bayesian updating in standard game theory.
37. Muller 1995. See also Risse-Kappen 1995.
38. Zangl and Zurm 1996. See also Gehring 1999, chap. 5. I owe the following point to Otto Keck.
39. Stein 1983.
necessary for any (distributive) bargaining situation without entering into an argumen-
tative process with the goal of achieving a reasoned consensus. On the basis of these
collective understandings that define and clarify the game they are playing, actors
can then engage in strategic bargaining to reach a distributive compromise.
One could agree with everything so far and still object that this metatheoretical de-
bate about the foundations of social action is utterly irrelevant in furthering our
understanding of world politics. There are essentially two major arguments against
the claim that arguing plays a substantial role in international relations:
44. In his original argument, Juirgen Habermas sharply distinguished the "common lifeworld" from the
"system world," which is functionally differentiated through complex divisions of labor and where instru-
mental rationality prevails. Modem political systems-we could add international relations-were origi-
nally conceptualized as part of the latter. In his later work, however, he no longer maintains this strict
separation and theorized about deliberative politics as institutionalized in the practices of modern democ-
racies. Compare Habermas 1981, vol. 2, 173-296, with Habermas 1992.
in this context does not refer to the pre-social Hobbesian "state of nature," but al-
ready constitutes an, albeit "thin," collective (social) interpretation of the world. But
this point only helps to some degree, since a shared interpretation of the world as a
"dog eat dog" world is not particularly conducive to a reasonable dialogue. Meaning-
ful communication requires that actors see at least some room for cooperation with
their interaction partners and, thus, wish to overcome a world of sheer hostility.45 If
so, they can actually construct their common lifeworld as a prerequisite for building
mutual trust in the authenticity of each other's communications. As Harald Muller
pointed out, prenegotiations usually encompass a phase whereby actors construct
such a common lifeworld in a symbolic sense, mainly through narratives. Almost
ritualistic references to common experiences such as suffering during wars fre-
quently serve such purposes.46 The exchange of memories of World War II, for ex-
ample, has been a regular feature of almost all East-West negotiations during the
Cold War. One might dismiss such practices as sheer rhetoric in light of the tough
bargaining problems at hand. However, they appear to be a precondition for establish-
ing the trustworthiness of negotiating partners.
Second, focusing on international relations allows us to differentiate among social
situations such as "anarchy" where actors have to construct their common lifeworld
almost from scratch and to develop stable patterns of expectations and interactions,
on the one hand, and dense interaction patterns within highly regulated international
institutions, on the other. For example, pluralistic security communities based on a
collective identity and shared values and norms might constitute a common life-
world.47 The European Union or the transatlantic community come to mind. We can
also infer from the literature on the "democratic peace"48 that democracies not only
rarely fight each other but also develop a collective identity based on shared liberal
values and norms constituting a common lifeworld. Moreover, some issue-areas in
world politics, such as trade, human rights, or the environment, are heavily regulated
by international regimes and organizations. A high degree of international institution-
alization might then provide a common lifeworld. International institutions create a
normative framework structuring interaction in a given issue-area. They often serve
as arenas in which international policy deliberation can take place. Whether they can
play this role or not depends largely on their organizational structure. Nonhierarchi-
cal and networklike international institutions characterized by a high density of mostly
informal interactions should provide the structural conditions in international rela-
tions to allow for discursive and argumentative processes.49
Third, one might object here that a common lifeworld resembles "common knowl-
edge" in game theory.50 How can I claim that argumentative reasoning is necessary
to establish the common knowledge that game theory takes as given if a common
lifeworld in terms of a shared history, common experiences, and a common culture is
itself a prerequisite for deliberative discourses? To answer this question, it might be
helpful to distinguish among three social situations. The first situation resembles the
"anarchy" in world politics mentioned earlier, with little common lifeworld and
even less common knowledge. In such a situation, actors can construct the common
lifeworld through narratives by referring to shared experiences, common historical
memories, and the like. This then might enable them to engage in a communicative proces
in order to reach a consensus on a joint definition of the situation and, thus, to develop the
common knowledge necessary for a bargaining process. Second, if actors find themselves
in a densely institutionalized environment, the common lifeworld might not be a problem,
but common knowledge still is, if and when actors are uncertain about their own interests
and/or lack knowledge about important features of the situation. As mentioned earlier, even
instrumentally rational actors should be interested in arguing in such cases. Third, in densely
institutionalized environments, actors might share a common lifeworld and they might
know what they want. Only then would the common lifeworld equal the common knowl-
edge in game theory. Argumentative discourse might still be necessary to reach a coopera-
tive solution, but not to establish common knowledge (see later discussion).
In sum, the degree to which a common lifeworld exists in international relations
varies considerably according to world regions and issue-areas. Even "anarchy"
constitutes an, albeit "thin," common lifeworld from which actors can move on to
refer to common experiences, develop shared understandings of history, and, thus, to
develop a collective culture.
Arguing and power. The second objection raised against emphasizing argumenta-
tive rationality is more difficult to tackle. Habermas's point that relationships of
power are supposed to be absent in ideal speech situations where only the "better
argument" counts has met with considerable criticism and has been labeled both
"idealistic" and "utopian." Power as a relationship of influencing an actor's behav-
ior against the actor's will might affect arguing in at least two ways: First, power
relations might define who has legitimate access to a discourse. The UN Security
Council is a perfect example of how some states are more equal than others in terms
of having permanent access to the deliberations. Second, they might affect what
counts as a "good argument." It makes a difference in the UN Security Council
whether the United States or Cameroon pushes a certain argument. At least, the latter
probably has to make a much greater argumentative effort than the former to gain
support for its views. More important, power asymmetries in the Security Council might
affect who says what and when and how arguments are framed in the first place.
Michel Foucault raised objections against the possibility of an "ideal speech situ-
ation" that go deeper and do not just concern the possibility that power relationships
external to the discourse might influence actors engaged in arguing.51 According to
51. See, for example, Foucault 1978 and 1991; Habermas 1985; and Love 1989. Thomas Diez helped
me to clarify the following points.
Foucault, power as a social structure resides in the discourse itself. The rules of the
discourse prescribe which arguments can be legitimately used by the participants. As
Elster points out, it is virtually impossible in public debates to make self-serving
arguments or to justify one's claims on self-interested grounds.52 Even rhetorical
arguments that try to justify egoistic interests must normally refer to some universal-
istic values or commonly accepted norms. National governments that want to partici-
pate in the global human rights discourse might still object to specific accusations of
norm violations. But it is virtually impossible for them to deny the validity of global
human rights norms themselves without risking being labeled as "pariah" states.
While Habermas's "ideal speech situation" implies that any argument can be used in
a theoretical or practical discourse, Foucault's objection posits that the social context
of such discourses establishes clear boundaries of what can be legitimately argued.
Some of these objections indicate a misunderstanding of Habermas's theory of
communicative action, whereas others reflect deep theoretical disagreements. First,
the ideal speech situation is not meant as a statement about the empirical world
or-even worse-some utopian ideal; instead it constitutes primarily a counterfac-
tual presupposition. To quote Habermas,
I do not assert that a valid consensus can only be achieved under conditions of
the ideal speech situation. Communicative daily practice is embedded in a sea of
cultural taking for grantedness, i.e., of consensual certainties; ... As soon as one
component of this naively known and pre-reflexive background is transformed
into the semantic content of a verbal utterance, the certainties enter the condi-
tions of criticizable knowledge: They may become subject to dissent. Only when
this dissent is persistent enough to provoke a discursive treatment of the disputed
issue, does this become an instance of which I assert that a reasoned consensus
cannot be achieved unless the participants in the discourse assume that they per-
suade each other only on the basis of better arguments. If one side uses privi-
leged access to arms, wealth, or prestige in order to wring agreement from the
other by way of sanctions or rewards, none of the participants will doubt that the
conditions for argumentation are no longer satisfied."53
An alleged reasoned consensus might often be an illusion, and the analyst's task is
then to criticize it. Interestingly enough, we can only "know" such a false agreement
if measured against a reasoned consensus resulting from truth-seeking argumenta-
tion. The earlier-mentioned social psychological literature on persuasion seems to
suggest that people are indeed capable of distinguishing between strategic reasoning
and arguing. Biased or self-interested communicators are far less persuasive than
those who are perceived to be neutral or motivated by moral values.54 The criticism
of rational argumentation as just another form of domination and discipline presup-
poses argumentative rationality in the sense that the objection itself can only be made
within a reasoned discourse.55
Moreover, one should not forget that the various modes of social action-strategic
behavior, norm-guided behavior, and argumentative/discursive behavior-represent
ideal types that rarely occur in pure form in reality (see Figure 1). We often act both
strategically and discursively-that is, we use arguments to convince somebody else
that our demands are justified-and by doing so we follow norms enabling our inter-
action in the first place (language rules, for example). As a result, the empirical
question to be asked is not whether actors behave strategically or in an argumentative
mode, but which mode captures more of the action in a given situation.
These counterarguments to various objections raised against the possibility of an
"ideal speech situation" in international affairs only help to some extent. The Haber-
masian condition of "equal access" to the discourse, for example, is simply not met
in world politics. But does this mean that those actors who are privileged to partici-
pate in the discourse of international organizations or in interstate negotiations never
engage in truth-seeking behavior and in arguing over norms? We can probably relax
the condition of "equal access" as long as the condition of nonhierarchy among
participants in a discourse can be met. Concerning the UN Security Council, for
example, it might not worry us too much that there are permanent and nonpermanent
members, as long as this does not determine what counts as a "good argument."
This latter point concerns precisely the objection that the structure and social con-
text of an argumentative process delineate the boundaries of which types of argu-
ments can be legitimately made or are viewed as "reasonable arguments." But does
this objection imply that truth seeking and argumentative rationality are impossible
within those structural boundaries of a discourse? Furthermore, does it imply that
human beings are forever caught within the boundaries of their discourses and can-
not challenge the very legitimacy of these boundaries under any circumstances? I do
not think so. Rather, I suggest treating Foucault's points as valid objections against
an "anything goes" view of truth-seeking discourses. We can treat these arguments
as attempts to provoke a discussion between the logic of arguing and the logic of
appropriateness along the right axis of the triangle in Figure 1.
The real issue then is not whether power relations are absent in a discourse, but to
what extent they can explain the argumentative outcome. We need some indicators
for knowing an arguing situation in international politics when we see one. The
following criteria offer some clues:
* Assuming that the materially more powerful actors do not necessarily have the
better arguments, an arguing situation should disproportionately empower the
weaker actors who have less material resources at their disposal. This might
refer empirically to small states, such as Cameroon in the earlier example of
the UN Security Council, or to the impact of nonstate actors such as interna-
tional nongovernmental organizations (INGOs) in international negotiations. If
INGOs convince the more powerful actors to change their minds, we have
probably witnessed arguing.
In sum, we do not need to posit an "ideal speech situation" in world politics and
can even relax some of the strict preconditions for argumentative rationality but still
maintain that truth-seeking behavior leading to a reasoned consensus is possible in
international affairs. We have probably witnessed processes of argumentative persua-
sion when powerful governments change their minds and subsequently their behav-
ior, even though their instrumental interests would suggest otherwise, or when mate-
rially less powerful actors such as small states or nonstate actors carry the day.
Moreover, the more the rules of international institutions prescribe nonhierarchical
relations among actors, the more these rules should enable arguing and policy delib-
eration.
So far, I have suggested that it is neither outrageous nor heroic to assume that the
logic of arguing sometimes prevails in international relations. Based on the preced-
ing discussion, the following conditions should be conducive to truth-seeking behav-
ior in world politics:
But does arguing really matter? What can we infer from the preceding discussion
about the consequences of truth-seeking and argumentative processes on the out-
comes of international negotiations and other processes? Does establishing a rea-
soned consensus about the situation on the ground and/or the norms guiding the
interaction make for a "better" outcome? In the following, I distinguish between two
settings in world politics where arguing might be expected under certain circum-
stances: diplomatic negotiations and public debates among various actors.
59. Neofunctionalism talks about "upgrading the common interest" (Haas 1958). The point is not to
reach some solution to a collective action problem, but a solution that the participants perceive as innova-
tive and optimal.
60. Scharpf 1997, 124. See also Lax and Sebenius 1986.
61. See Zintl 1992; and Mayntz 1997.
62. See Habermas 1990 and 1992; and Chambers 1996. I owe the following argument to Marc Lynch.
Lynch 1999. See also Payne 1999.
63. This does not mean that there are no restrictions to public access. Getting attention in the interna-
tional public arena is still hard; but everything else being equal, access for nonstate actors is still easier in
the public sphere than in (secret) diplomatic negotiations.
64. Finnemore 1996a.
65. On this point, see Elster 1986 and 1998b.
66. See, for example, Keck and Sikkink 1998.
A quite extraordinary argumentative process took place during the international ne-
gotiations ending the Cold War in Europe and settling the international issues con-
cerning German unification. In the end, the Soviet Union under President Mikhail
Gorbachev agreed to German unification within NATO in exchange for limits on
Germany's and NATO's military posture in the former East Germany, on the one
hand, and the transformation of NATO from an anti-Soviet alliance to a cooperative
security institution, on the other. At the same time, these negotiations laid the ground-
work for the post-Cold War security architecture in Europe, creating a surprisingly
stable security partnership between the former Soviet Union/Russia and Western
Europe (less so between the United States and Russia). Under circumstances of enor-
mous turmoil and uncertainty on both sides, the outcome of these negotiations went
well beyond a simple compromise and represented an almost optimal solution to the
security problems of all concerned, including particularly Germany's neighbors. In
other words, the Two plus Four talks68 solved the "production" or problem-solving
part of international negotiations to a startling degree that one would not have ex-
pected on the basis of the initial negotiating positions of the governments concerned.
Although several compromise solutions were possible, I claim that this particular
outcome largely resulted from a successful effort on both sides at arguing out the
differences in a true dialogue of mutual persuasion. During these talks, which took
place from late 1989 to September 1990, Western policymakers, particularly the
United States and Germany, engaged the Soviet leadership in a continuous dialogue
to convince Gorbachev to agree to German unification within NATO.
67. This part builds on Risse 1997. "Friendly persuasion" is a chapter title in Zelikow and Rice 1995,
251.
68. "Two" stands for the two Germanies, and "four" stands for the Allied Powers: France, Great
Britain, the Soviet Union, and the United States.
One has to ask, of course, whether Moscow had a genuine choice. The Soviet
Union had already lost its East European empire when the negotiations began in
early 1990. Its economy was in a deep crisis and increasingly dependent on Western
aid and credits. There is no question that the overall balance of power had consider-
ably shifted in favor of the West. The use of force against German unification within
NATO was not a serious option, since this would have ruined relations with the West
and probably Gorbachev's domestic reform program, too. We know in hindsight, of
course, that things worsened for the Soviet Union-Gorbachev lost his job and the
Soviet Union disintegrated. But decision makers in Washington, Bonn, and Moscow
did not anticipate this. Given the speed with which the Cold War order fell apart in
1989-90, they were extremely worried about instabilities in Central Europe and faced
enormous uncertainties.69 It is all the more significant how a cooperative solution
was worked out during the Two plus Four talks.
Although Moscow could no longer influence events or bargaining outcomes in its
desired direction, it still could make life quite miserable for the West and for Ger-
many in particular. First, Moscow could have forced the German people to choose
between unification and NATO membership, thereby triggering a major domestic
dispute in the country during an election year. Second, the Soviet Union could have
provoked an international crisis and confrontation with Bonn and Washington by
fully insisting on its legal rights over Germany as an allied power. The price to be
paid by both sides would have been to start another Cold War just as the first one was
about to end peacefully. Third, in the absence of a cooperative agreement with the
West, the Soviet Union could have decided to leave its 300,000 troops in East Ger-
many. The West could have not done much short of using force to prevent such a
course of action. Each of these three options was discussed in Moscow at the time,
and each was taken quite seriously by Western policymakers.70 In other words, both
sides perceived the situation as rather open; Soviet agreement to German unification
within NATO was not to be taken for granted. The Soviet Union still had some
bargaining leverage.
Although several negotiating outcomes were possible in this particular situation, it
was arguing rather than bargaining that ultimately laid the groundwork for a coopera-
tive post-Cold War security order in Europe. The arguing process in this case was not
so much about establishing "common knowledge." Although it did not take place in
an environment strongly regulated by international institutions, both sides had been
interacting since the mid-1980s when Gorbachev and his foreign minister Shevard-
nadze came into power; they had created a common lifeworld establishing mutual
trust. In this case arguing was about problem solving to establish which norms should
guide the post-Cold War security architecture in Europe. It entailed a practical dis-
course on the "right thing to do" in this peculiar situation.
69. This is the overall impression one gets from the memoir literature on the events in 1989-90. See,
for example, Gorbachev 1995; Shevardnadze 1991; Teltschik 1991; Genscher 1995; and Baker 1995.
70. See Zelikow and Rice 1995; Elbe and Kiessler 1996; and Beschloss and Talbott 1993.
The negotiations between the Western powers and the Soviet Union included tele-
vised public discourses in the East and the West as well as secret negotiations and
fulfilled to a large extent the preconditions for argumentative rationality. Particularly
the U.S. and German governments tried to reassure their Soviet counterparts that
they were not trying to exploit the current weakness of the Soviet Union. President
Bush told Chancellor Kohl, "we will not exacerbate the problem by having the
President of the United States posturing on the Berlin Wall."'71 Both leaders reas-
sured Gorbachev and Shevardnadze time and again that they had no interest in fur-
ther destabilizing an already tense domestic situation in the Soviet Union. Western
leaders treated their Soviet counterpart as an equal and serious negotiating partner,
even though the power relationship between them was increasingly asymmetrical.
That reassurances were also in the Western interest in order to gain bargaining con-
cessions from the Soviet Union is beside the point. Avoiding aggravating language in
a tense negotiation serves a communicative purpose. It acknowledges empathy for
the bargaining partner's concerns and communicates that the partner's demands are
legitimate even if disagreed with.
Of course, traditional distributive bargaining played a significant role in the nego-
tiations settling the Cold War in Europe. But there have been crucial moments-
mostly in a bilateral context-where actors did not pursue instrumentally defined
goals, but communicated in order to learn more about each other and to genuinely
convince each other. At least two of the three main actors did not hold fixed prefer-
ences during the negotiations settling the Cold War. First and most important, the
Soviet leadership changed its preferences not only over policies but also over out-
comes in the course of the talks. The Soviet leaders remained opposed to German
unification prior to 1989, even though they sometimes engaged in speculative talk
about what might happen in the future. When events in Germany unfolded, Gor-
bachev and Shevardnadze gradually changed their minds. They come across as lack-
ing fixed preferences and as being open to persuasion and communication-another
precondition for argumentative rationality. U.S. and German officials frequently con-
cluded from their conversations that "the Soviet government did not seem to know where it
was going," that Gorbachev and Shevardnadze "seem to be genuinely wrestling with these
problems, but [had] yet to fashion a coherent or confident response."72 Gorbachev ap-
peared as an "uncommitted thinker and motivated learner," as Janice Gross Stein put it.73
U.S. and German leaders embarked on a process of fiiendly persuasion and engaged in
almost continuous conversations with Shevardnadze and Gorbachev.
As to the German government, its preferences over outcomes seemed to be fixed
from late 1989 on, when Kohl determined to push for unification. But Bonn's prefer-
ences over policies to attain this goal were influenced by events and by talks with
various world leaders. The strategy toward unification changed several times as events
unfolded, including its form, its speed, and the settlement of its international conse-
71. Quoted from Zelikow and Rice 1995, 112. See also Elbe and Kiessler 1996.
72. Zelikow and Rice 1995, 130, 232. See also ibid., 108-109, 131.
73. Stein 1995.
quences. The only actors whose preferences over outcomes and policies remained
rather fixed during the entire process were U.S. leaders. Once the Bush administra-
tion had decided to push for rapid German unification within NATO, it held this
course rather steadily. U.S. leaders understood that Soviet security concerns had to
be accommodated somehow and that some restrictions had to be placed on NATO
forces in former East Germany. But there is not much evidence that U.S. negotiators
were open to persuasive processes during their talks with German or Soviet leaders.
President Bush and Secretary of State Baker were convinced that their preferred
outcome was the right solution to the problem, and they engaged in a genuine attempt
at persuading their Soviet counterparts whom they trusted as valid interlocutors.
Several conclusions emerge from this variation in the extent to which actors held
fixed preferences during the talks. The United States largely followed a "logic of
consequentialism" and engaged in rhetorical action; its negotiators mainly used argu-
ments and justifications rather than threats to persuade the Soviet leadership. As
suggested earlier, rhetorical action as a tool to reach one's goals can only be effective
if the other listens and remains open to persuasion. The Soviet leadership listened
indeed, thus following the "logic of arguing." Both sides then engaged in a discourse
about the validity claims inherent in each other's preferences and about the norms
that should guide their approach to the issues. Two examples illustrate my point.
The first example concerns a discourse challenging claims over alleged "national
interests." This discourse framed the question in mainly realist terms. In early Febru-
ary 1990, James Baker tried to persuade Gorbachev that a neutral Germany would
pose a greater threat to Soviet security than one firmly integrated in NATO. Thus,
Baker challenged a Soviet policy that dated back to the 1950s whereby unification
would only be acceptable if Germany became neutral and left NATO. Gorbachev had
already acknowledged that there was nothing terrifying about German unification.
Baker then asked the Soviet leader whether he preferred an independent Germany
outside NATO and without U.S. troops on its territory, or a united Germany in NATO
with the assurance "that there would be no extension of NATO's current jurisdiction
eastward." Gorbachev remained noncommittal at first and maintained that any exten-
sion of the zone of NATO was unacceptable. Baker agreed. Gorbachev now seemed
to think openly. He argued that he could see advantages of having U.S. troops in
Germany. He then continued that we "don't really want to see a replay of Versailles,
where the Germans were able to arm themselves.... The best way to constrain that
process is to ensure that Germany is contained within European structures." He
promised that the Soviet side would think about it, but that he could not give a clear
answer right away. While Baker held a firm line in this conversation, Gorbachev
appeared to be genuinely struggling with the question of how to interpret Soviet
security interests. In contrast to other Soviet officials with whom U.S. negotiators
met at the time, he appeared to be "truly flexible on the German question," as Philip
Zelikow and Condoleezza Rice put it.74
74. Zelikow and Rice 1995, 184. The other quotes are from ibid., 183-84. See also Gorbachev's ac-
count in Gorbachev 1995, 715-16.
One could argue, of course, that a unified Germany that remained firmly anchored
in NATO was in the "enlightened" self-interest of the Soviet Union. Of course, it
was-except that the vast majority of the Soviet leadership did not think so until
1990. When the negotiations started, Gorbachev and Shevardnadze were firmly con-
vinced that a neutral Germany was best for Soviet interests. They changed their
minds during the process of negotiations.
The second example concerns a moral discourse about norms. This discourse was
even more important, since it led to Gorbachev's principal agreement that united
Germany could remain in NATO if it chose to do so. During the U.S.-Soviet summit
at the end of May 1990, Bush and Gorbachev chaired a meeting of both delegations.
The conversation started in a rather polemical manner, with both sides accusing each
other of fearing German attempts to threaten peace in Europe once again.75 Gor-
bachev then accepted the realist argument that the U.S. presence in Europe was
stabilizing but requested that NATO needed to change. In a decisive move, Bush
reframed the issue from a realist discourse into a liberal one. He linked German
membership in NATO to the question of self-determination and the principles of the
Conference on Security and Cooperation in Europe (CSCE) according to which Ger-
many should have the right to decide for itself which alliance it would join. Gor-
bachev agreed to this argument right away.76 The two leaders then settled on a for-
mula whereby the United States would advocate Germany's membership in NATO
but Germany's decision would be respected if it chose otherwise.
If Zelikow and Rice are correct, Gorbachev agreed to NATO membership of united
Germany on the spot. His delegation was completely stunned, and some members
started infighting in front of U.S. officials. There was "a palpable feeling ... among
Gorbachev's advisers of almost physically distancing themselves from their leader's
words."77 The authors conclude that Gorbachev changed his mind right at the table.
If so, the incident probably constituted one of the most extraordinary cases of arguing
in intemational negotiations. The two leaders were engaged in a discourse about
norms. Bush apparently persuaded Gorbachev by reframing the NATO issue from
realist terms linked to Soviet security and stability in Europe to a liberal argument
emphasizing democracy and self-determination. He also linked it to the CSCE prin-
ciples in which Gorbachev believed. Persuasion worked when the U.S. president
justified united Germany's membership in NATO on the basis of principled beliefs
that fit the core of Gorbachev's convictions. Thus, the normative claims implied in
the idea of "self-determination" appear to have finally persuaded the Soviet leader-
ship that it should accept rapid German unification within NATO. In a sense then, the
principle of self-determination served as the main and most effective legitimizer of
75. Gorbachev 1995, 722-23. For the U.S. version, see Zelikow and Rice 1995, 276-79.
76. Testifying to the extreme sensitivity of this conversation, Gorbachev's account puts a different spin
on it. According to his version, it was Bush who agreed that Germany was free to leave NATO if it wanted
to. A comparison of the U.S. version and Gorbachev's account appears to indicate that the Soviet leader
quoted selectively from the Soviet records. Compare Gorbachev 1995, 722-23, with Zelikow and Rice
1995, 276-78.
77. Zelikow and Rice 1995, 278.
My second empirical example deals with the process by which actors are socialized
into international norms and start implementing these norms into their domestic prac-
tices.78 Given the stakes in the human rights area, the interference of external actors
in the domestic affairs of state, this case represents a "most unlikely" example of
arguing processes. Two features are of interest here: (1) human rights issues are
identity related and constitutive in the sense of defining membership in the commu-
nity of civilized nations; and (2) the norm-promoting agents, mostly INGOs, do not
command many material resources; they can rely only on the power of the better
argument.79
The socialization of international human rights norms into domestic practices in-
volves all three logics of social action, with each of them dominating in particular
phases of the process. Argumentative processes are particularly crucial (1) when
mobilizing international public opinion, Western govemments, and international or-
ganizations about the human rights situation in a norm violating state; (2) when the
oppressive state starts "talking the talk" and begins justifying its actions at interna-
78. This part summarizes Risse 1999 and is based on research reported in Risse, Ropp, and Sikkink
1999.
79. See Keck and Sikkink 1998; Sikkink 1993; and Smith, Chatfield, and Pagnucco 1997.
tional human rights organizations and the like; and (3) in some rare cases, when the
transnational and domestic advocacy coalition actually manages to convince rather
than force repressive leaders to change course and remedy the human rights situation
for good.
I concentrate on the latter two cases, because we would expect strategic bargaining
or coercion through economic sanctions, rather than argumentative processes, to be
decisive here. The communications between governments accused of norm viola-
tions and transnational advocacy networks as well as domestic opposition groups
initially do not fulfill any of the conditions for argumentative rationality specified
earlier. The speakers do not recognize each other as equals, and they certainly do not
empathize with each other. We can nevertheless observe a gradual process whereby
the communications move, by means of rhetorical behavior, from purely instrumen-
tal rationality toward a dialogue.
The communications between norm-violating governments and transnational as
well as domestic advocacy networks resemble a public discourse that is carried out in
front of international as well as domestic audiences in the target state. The interna-
tional audiences include Western states, Western publics, and international organiza-
tions, and the domestic audiences mainly consist of the society of the target state. In
general, instrumental interests and strategic rationality dominate the early phases of
the controversy, whereas argumentative behavior becomes more relevant later. Norm-
violating governments initially deny the validity of international human rights norms
and are not interested in engaging in a serious dialogue with their critics. At this stage
of the process, the two sides do not accept each other as valid and truthful interlocu-
tors. The advocacy coalition treats the norm-violating state as an international pariah,
an outsider to the community of civilized nations. At the same time and in response,
norm-violating governments not only deny the validity of the international norms but
also ridicule their accusers as ignorant "foreigners," "communists," or "terrorists."
Kenya's arap Moi, Indonesia's Suharto, and the communist regimes in Eastern Eu-
rope as well as the white minority in South Africa used very similar rhetoric in this
regard. Their main target audience was domestic society in an attempt to fight off the
challenges to their legitimacy. Many Third World governments engage in an anti-
colonial and anti-imperialist as well as nationalist discourse at this stage.
Under increasing international pressures, norm-violating governments feel that
they must make some concessions in order to increase their international legitimacy
or simply to regain foreign aid. This transition to tactical concessions is accompanied
by an important change in rhetoric. Norm-violating governments no longer deny the
validity of the international norm, but they continue to ridicule their critics and to
reject specific allegations of norm violations. Toward later stages of this phase and in
conjunction with continuing transnational and increasingly domestic pressures, we
observe a striking development toward arguing. The more norm-violating govern-
ments accept the validity of international norms, the more they start arguing with
their critics over specific accusations. If the transnational and domestic pressure in-
creases, norm-violating governments start engaging in a public dialogue with their
critics, and the logic of arguing incrementally takes over. I discuss two cases in more
detail, Indonesia and Morocco.80
When Indonesian police forces committed a massacre in East Timor in November
1991 that was witnessed by the UN Special Rapporteur on Torture, the international
outcry forced the government to move from denial of human rights norms to tactical
concessions. This change was accompanied by a dramatic change in rhetoric. At the
1992 session of the UN Human Rights Commission, the Indonesian delegate claimed
that Indonesia strictly prohibited the practice of torture. He also stated that the invita-
tion of the Special Rapporteur had been motivated by the desire "to learn and benefit
from such a visit in order to minimize, if not eradicate, the practice of torture in
Indonesia."'8' This statement not only acknowledged the validity of the international
norm but also was the first time the Indonesian government accepted allegations of
torture.
From then on, the Indonesian government cooperated fully with the Human Rights
Commission during the 1993-97 sessions and acknowledged specific human rights
violations. In 1996, for example, Indonesia presented the Human Rights Commis-
sion with a list of detailed measures undertaken to deal with human rights violations,
including immediate investigations of some abuses in East Timor. At first, govern-
ment officials differentiated between valid critiques by UN (that is, interstate) bodies
and inaccurate or baseless allegations by INGOs. The attitude toward the latter changed
over time, particularly when two prominent East Timorese NGO leaders gained the
Nobel Peace Prize in 1996. In turn, NGO officials also modified their argumentative
behavior and acknowledged "the legitimate concerns of countries in preserving their
national unity and territorial integrity. Many developing countries, Indonesia being a
prime example, experienced a traumatic nation-building process with numerous at-
tempts from within and without to undermine the unity of the state."82 Such a state-
ment by the most prominent East Timorese opposition leader would have been un-
thinkable only five years earlier. The discourse between the Indonesian government
and its critics shifted dramatically over time. It began with a contestation of the
underlying norm (self-determination and human rights versus noninterference in in-
ternal affairs) and a complete denial of the authenticity and credibility of the respec-
tive speakers. Later, however, the underlying norms became consensual-human
rights in particular-and the speakers accepted each other as valid interlocutors. As a
result, the discourse began focusing on questions of norm compliance and implemen-
tation on the ground.
This change in public discourse had significant repercussions for the domestic
situation, since it empowered the opposition against Suharto. When the economic
crisis hit Indonesia in the fall of 1997, the domestic opposition was fully mobilized,
and Suharto ultimately had to resign. His successor, Habibie, immediately opened a
dialogue with the domestic opposition and began implementing important human
rights norms, even though Indonesia still has a long way to go.
The Moroccan case represents an unusual example of a process of public persua-
sion involving the late King Hassan II, the ruler, and his domestic as well as transna-
tional critics.83 The case is counterintuitive, since Morocco is both an Islamist state
and a monarchy where the king's position constitutes a societal taboo. As in the other
case, King Hassan II claimed the principle of noninterference against international
human rights norms until about 1990. The more the transnational and domestic net-
work pressures increased during the late 1980s and early 1990s, the more the king's
rhetoric changed. When he instituted the Moroccan Human Rights Commission in
1990, for example, he claimed that human rights were a constitutive part of the
Islamic tradition. He also argued at the UN General Assembly two years later that the
principles embodied in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights reflected values
prevailing in Morocco for the last fourteen centuries. He now reconstructed Moroc-
can identity as belonging to the (Western) community of civilized nations: "Our
history, thanks to the creative spirit, which illustrates a large contribution to the
sciences, the arts, to civilization, and to the law, shows that our country has always
seen itself as living in a civilized society next to the developed states and nations."84
Compared to two years earlier, the nationalist discourse had completely changed.
Morocco now desired to be part of the civilized international community, which
included respecting human rights.
At the same time, the king no longer denied that human rights violations occurred
in Morocco and recognized that continuous human rights violations betrayed the
image of Morocco as a civilized nation that he wanted to portray to the outside world.
As a result, the mission of the newly founded Human Rights Commission was to
"purify the face of Morocco."85 His words and deeds set in motion a process that
enabled domestic human rights networks to become more and more outspoken. They
began interacting regularly with the state-sponsored Human Rights Commission,
which later became the Ministry of Human Rights. Today, Morocco is the most
liberal of the Maghreb states; human rights policies have been implemented in domes-
tic law, and violations have decreased substantially. The Moroccan king thus began a
process of controlled liberalization from above. This outcome is all the more remark-
able, since his rule was never challenged domestically and he continued to enjoy
great popularity.
What these and other cases have in common is that the communicative behavior
between a norm-violating government and its transnational and domestic critics
changes dramatically over time. At first, neither side accepts the other as a valid
interlocutor. When the process moves toward tactical concessions, an increasing con-
sensus emerges about the validity of international human rights norms. Norm-
violating governments accept the norms rhetorically in order to decrease the interna-
tional and domestic pressures against them. They keep denouncing their critics and
do not accept the authenticity of their arguments. At this stage, rhetorical action
prevails. Argumentative concessions are part of a larger picture of tactical moves to
fight off the transnational and domestic opposition. So far, the process remains fully
within the logic of consequentialism.
However, when norm-violating governments find it necessary to make rhetorical
concessions and cease denying the validity of human rights norms, a discursive open-
ing is created for their critics to challenge them further: If you say that you accept
human rights, then why do you systematically violate them? The usual response is
that such violations either did not occur or are marginal developments. The discourse
then shifts toward the issue of whether norm violations constitute isolated incidents
or are systematic in character. At this point during the tactical concession phase, the
arguments of both sides become more and more detailed and also more legalistic. It
is no longer a discourse on the validity of the norm, but on the interpretation of the
law of the land. At the same time, the two sides gradually accept each other as valid
interlocutors. They no longer denounce each other as ignorant foreigners or pariah
states. Arguments that would not have been acceptable in earlier stages of the debate
are now treated as valid points. There are many examples whereby norm-violating
Third World governments convincingly argue that they were not fully in control of
their own armed forces or their police. In earlier stages of the argumentative process,
human rights advocates would have dismissed such a point out of hand as self-
serving. Finally, the argumentative consistency of actors irrespective of the audience
increases dramatically. Toward the beginning of the tactical concession phase, norm-
violating governments might "talk the talk" at the UN and toward the Western donor
community but adopt an entirely different language when making statements tar-
geted at a domestic audience. Later, the arguments become substantially more consis-
tent.
In sum then, the evidence shows a process of argumentative "self-entrapment"
that starts as rhetorical action and strategic adaptation to external pressures but ends
with argumentative behavior resembling the criteria defined earlier. How can one
explain this process of argumentative "self-entrapment" theoretically? It is not an
"ideal speech situation," since governments do not enter the process of arguing
voluntarily but are forced into a dialogue by the pressures of fully mobilized domes-
tic and transnational networks. They might also face economic or political sanctions
by the international community. At the same time, the dialogue no longer resembles
rhetorical exchanges, either, through which both sides use arguments to justify their
given interests and behavior but are unprepared to reconsider and change their pref-
erences. Even these "forced dialogues" have all the characteristics of a true argumen-
tative exchange. Both sides accept each other as valid interlocutors, try to establish
some common definition of the human rights situation, and agree on the norms guid-
ing the situation. In other words, they behave as if they were engaged in a true moral
discourse. Argumentative rationality has taken over. And it matters: Governments
that started moving down the road of arguing eventually matched words with deeds
in terms of an improved human rights record. Those that did not continued to commit
serious human rights abuses while making some tactical concessions here and there.86
Conclusions
In this article I introduced a mode of social action and interaction that has so far been
largely overlooked in the U.S.-dominated international relations debate between ra-
tional choice and social constructivism, which has mainly focused on the differences
between instrumental rationality, on the one hand, and norm-guided behavior, on the
other. Drawing on insights from a theoretical debate within the German-speaking
international relations community, I suggested that actors have a third mode of social
action at their disposal: arguing and deliberating about the validity claims inherent in
any communicative statement about identities, interests, and the state of the world.
Arguing and truth-seeking behavior presuppose that actors no longer hold fixed inter-
ests during their communicative interaction but are open to persuasion, challenges,
and counterchallenges geared toward reaching a reasoned consensus.
I then posited that the preconditions for argumentative rationality, particularly a
"common lifeworld" and the mutual recognition of speakers as equals in a nonhier-
archical relationship, are more common in international relations than is usually
assumed. International institutions, for example, provide an information-rich environ-
ment and a normative framework structuring interactions. Public spheres enabling
challenges and counterchallenges to validity claims also exist in many issue-areas
and regions of the world. In the absence of these social structures, actors can con-
struct common lifeworlds through narratives during prenegotiations in order to estab-
lish mutual trust in their authenticity as speakers. Arguing processes are more likely
to occur both in negotiating settings and in the public sphere,
* the more actors are uncertain about their interests and even identities;
* the less actors know about the situation in which they find themselves and
about the underlying "rules of the game" ("common knowledge"); and
86. In contrast to Morocco, Tunisia provides an interesting example of a country whose leadership
initially engaged in human rights rhetoric accompanied by tactical concessions but then did not move
further along the path, partly because of a lack of transnational and domestic mobilization. For details, see
Granzer 1999.
Finally, I illustrated my claims with two plausibility probes for the relevance of
arguing in international relations. The first concerned the East-West talks leading to
a negotiated settlement of the Cold War in Europe and German unification within
NATO. The problem-solving part of these negotiations required a reasoned consen-
sus about the underlying principles and norms guiding interactions in the post-Cold
War order. Only when both sides went into an arguing mode and reached an under-
standing about the norm-self-determination in this case-were they able to settle
the distributive issues, too. The second case focused on the implementation of inter-
national human rights norms into domestic practices of Third World states. Sustained
changes in human rights practices occur when governments become convinced
through arguing processes that human rights constitute part of their collective iden-
tity as a modern member of the international community. Moreover, the human rights
case served as an example of how arguing empowers actors who lack material re-
sources and so must rely on the "power of the better argument," transnational advo-
cacy networks in this case.
I do not claim that truth seeking is all-pervasive in world politics. First, even if
actors are engaged in truth-seeking behavior in a given situation, they might still fail
to reach an argumentative consensus. Second, we rarely observe pure argumentative
rationality prevailing in world politics; instead we see various combinations of the
three rationalities identified earlier. But focusing on argumentative processes allows
us to become more specific in the conversation between rational choice and social
constructivism by "unpacking" the latter. As to rational choice, the logic of arguing
challenges the assumption that actors hold fixed interests and identities during the
process of interaction. As to the logic of appropriateness, argumentative rationality
brings agency back in and allows us to overcome the structuralist bias in some social
constructivist statements.87 Social constructivism often emphasizes learning and so-
cialization processes in order to link social structure to agents. The two empirical
cases discussed in this article illustrate how arguing provides a mechanism for both
learning and norms socialization in social settings.
References
Adler, Emanuel. 1997. Seizing the Middle Ground: Constructivism in World Politics. European Journal of
International Relations 3 (3):3 19-63.
Adler, Emanuel, and Michael Barnett, eds. 1998. Security Communities. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press.
Alker, Hayward A. 1996. Rescuing "Reason" from the "Rationalists": Reading Vico, Marx, and Weber as
Reflective Institutionalists. In Alker, Rediscoveries and Reformulations: Humanistic Methodologies
for International Studies, 207-37. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Axelrod, Robert A. 1997. The Complexity of Cooperation: Agent-Based Models of Competition and Col-
laboration. Princeton N.J.: Princeton University Press.
Axelrod, Robert A., and Robert 0. Keohane. 1986. Achieving Cooperation Under Anarchy: Strategies and
Institutions. In Cooperation UnderAnarchy, edited by Kenneth A. Oye, 226-54. Princeton N.J.: Prince-
ton University Press.
Baker, James A. III. 1995. The Politics of Diplomacy: Revolution, War, and Peace, 1989-1992. New York:
G. P. Putnam's Sons.
Beschloss, Michael R., and Strobe Talbott. 1993. At the Highest Levels: The Inside Story of the End of the
Cold War. Boston: Little, Brown and Co.
Borzel, Tanja A. 1998. Organizing Babylon-On the Different Conceptions of Policy Networks. Public
Administration 76 (2):253-73.
Carlsnaes, Walter. 1992. The Agency-Structure Problem in Foreign Policy Analysis. International Studies
Quarterly 36 (3):245-70.
Chaiken, Shelly, Wendy Wood, and Alice H. Eagly. 1996. Principles of Persuasion. In Social Psychology:
Handbook of Basic Principles, edited by E. T. Higgins and A. W. Kruglanski, 702-42. New York:
Guilford Press.
Chambers, Simone. 1996. Reasonable Democracy: Jiirgen Habermas and the Politics of Discourse. Ithaca,
N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
Checkel, Jeffrey T. 1998. The Constructivist Turn in International Relations Theory. World Politics 50 (2):
324-48.
Cooper, Russell, Douglas V. DeJong, Robert Forsythe, and Thomas W. Ross. 1992. Communication in
Coordination Games. Quarterly Journal of Economics 107 (2):739-7 1.
Dessler, David. 1989. What's at Stake in the Agent-Structure Debate? International Organization 43 (3):
441-73.
Deutsch, Karl W., Sidney A. Burrell, Robert A. Kann, Maurice Lee, Jr., Martin Lichterman, Raymond E.
Lindgren, Francis L. Loewenheim, and Richard W. Van Wagenen. 1957. Political Community and the
North Atlantic Area: International Organization in the Light of Historical Experience. Princeton, N.J.:
Princeton University Press.
Elbe, Frank, and Richard Kiessler. 1996. A Round Table with Sharp Corners: The Diplomatic Path to
German Unity. Baden-Baden: Nomos.
Elster, Jon. 1986. The Market and the Forum: Three Varieties of Political Theory. In Foundations of Social
Choice Theory, edited by Jon Elster and Aanund Hylland, 103-32. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
1989. Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
1998a. Introduction. In Deliberative Democracy, edited by Jon Elster, 1-18. Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press.
Elster, Jon, ed. 1998b. Deliberative Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Eriksen, Erik Oddvar, and Jarle Weigard. 1997. Conceptualizing Politics: Strategic or Communicative
Action? Scandinavian Political Studies 20 (3):219-41.
Farrell, Joseph, and Matthew Rabin. 1996. Cheap Talk. Journal of Economic Perspectives 10 (3): 103-18.
Ferreira, J.-L., I. Gilboa, and M. Maschler. 1995. Credible Equilibria in Games with Utilities Changing
During the Play. Games and Economic Behavior 10 (2):284-317.
Finnemore, Martha. 1996a. Constructing Norms of Humanitarian Intervention. In The Culture of National
Security: Norms and Identity in World Politics, edited by Peter J. Katzenstein, 153-85. New York:
Columbia University Press.
. 1996b. Norms, Culture, and World Politics: Insights From Sociology's Institutionalism. Interna-
tional Organization 50 (2):325-47.
Finnemore, Martha, and Kathryn Sikkink. 1998. International Norm Dynamics and Political Change.
International Organization 52 (4):887-917.
Foucault, Michel. 1978. Dispositive der Macht. Berlin: Merve Verlag.
. 1991. Politics and the Study of Discourse. In The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality,
edited by Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon, and Peter Miller, 53-72. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Gehring, Thomas. 1999. Die Theorie spezifischer Institutionen und die Europaische Union. Ein Beitrag
zur Verbindung von Rationalismus und Konstruktivismus. Habilitationsschrift, Fachbereich Politische
Wissenschaft, Freie Universitat Berlin.
. 1993. Information, Macht und gesellschaftliche Rationalitdt. Das Dilemma rationalen kommuni-
kativen Handelns, dargestellt am Beispiel eines internationalen Vergleichs der Kernenergiepolitik.
Baden-Baden: Nomos.
.1995. Rationales kommunikatives Handeln in den internationalen Beziehungen. Ist eine Verbindung
von Rational-Choice-Theorie und Habermas' Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns moglich?
Zeitschriftftir Internationale Beziehungen 2 (1):5-48.
. 1997. Zur sozialen Konstruktion des Rational-Choice-Ansatzes. Einige Klarstellungen zur Ratio-
nalismus-Konstruktivismus-Debatte. Zeitschriftftr Internationale Beziehungen 4 (1): 139-5 1.
Keohane, Robert 0. 1984. After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy.
Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
. 1989a. International Institutions and State Power. Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press.
1989b. International Institutions: Two Approaches. In Keohane, International Institutions and
State Power, 158-79. Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press.
Klotz, Audie. 1995. Norms in International Relations: The Struggle Against Apartheid. Ithaca, N.Y.:
Cornell University Press.
Kratochwil, Friedrich V. 1989. Rules, Norms, and Decisions: On the Conditions of Practical and Legal
Reasoning in International Relations and Domestic Affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lax, David A., and James K. Sebenius. 1986. The Manager as Negotiator: Bargaining for Cooperation
and Competitive Gain. New York: Free Press.
Linklater, Andrew. 1996. The Achievements of Critical Theory. In International Theory: Positivism and
Beyond, edited by Steve Smith, Ken Booth, and Marysia Zalewski, 279-98. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Lose, Lars G. 1998. Communicative Action and the Social Construction of Diplomatic Societies: Commu-
nication and Behavior in the Real World. Paper presented at Femm8ller Workshop, Femmoller AIbel-
toft, Denmark, 24-28 June.
Love, Nancy S. 1989. Foucault and Habermas on Discourse and Democracy. Polity 22 (2):269-83.
Lynch, Marc. 1999. State Interests and Public Spheres: The International Politics of Jordanian Identity.
New York: Columbia University Press.
March, James G., and Johan P. Olsen. 1989. Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis of
Politics. New York: Free Press.
. 1998. The Institutional Dynamics of International Political Orders. International Organization 52
(4):943-69.
Martin, Lisa L., and Beth A. Simmons. 1998. Theories and Empirical Studies of International Institutions.
International Organization 52 (4):729-57.
Mayntz, Renate. 1997. Soziale Dynamik und politische Steuerung. Theoretische und methodologische
Uberlegungen. Frankfurt am Main: Campus.
Morrow, James D. 1994. Modeling the Forms of International Cooperation: Distribution Versus Informa-
tion. International Organization 48 (3):387-423.
Muller, Harald. 1994. Internationale Beziehungen als kommunikatives Handeln. Zur Kritik der utilitaristi-
schen Handlungstheorien. Zeitschriftffir Internationale Beziehungen 1 (1): 15-44.
. 1995. Spielen hilft nicht immer. Die Grenzen des Rational-Choice-Ansatzes und der Platz der
Theorie kommunikativen Handelns in derAnalyse internationaler Beziehungen. Zeitschriftfi'r Interna-
tionale Beziehungen 2 (2):371-91.
Muller, Michael. 1996. Vom Dissensrisiko zur Ordnung der internationalen Staatenwelt. Zum Projekt
einer normativ gehaltvollen Theorie der internationalen Beziehungen. Zeitschrift fur Internationale
Beziehungen 3 (2):367-79.
Onuf, Nicholas Greenwood. 1989. World of Our Making: Rules and Rule in Social Theory and Interna-
tional Relations. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press.
Ostrom, Elinor. 1998. ABehavioral Approach to the Rational Choice Theory of Collective Action. American
Political Science Review 92 (1):1-22.
Ostrom, Elinor, Roy Gardner, and James Walker. 1994. Rules, Games, and Common-Pool Resources. Ann
Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Owen, John M. 1997. Liberal Peace, Liberal War: American Politics and International Security. Ithaca,
N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
Oye, Kenneth, ed. 1986. Cooperation UnderAnarchy. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
Payne, Rodger A. 1999. Persuasion, Frames, and the Construction of International Norms: Evidence from
the Climate Change Debate. Paper presented at the 20th Annual Meeting of the International Studies
Association, Washington, D.C.
Plumper, Thomas. 1995. Quasi-rationale Akteure und die Funktion internationaler Institutionen. Zeitschrift
fur Internationale Beziehungen 2 (1):49-77.
Powell, Walter W., and Paul J. DiMaggio, eds. 1991. The New Institutionalism in Organizational Analysis.
Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.
Price, Richard. 1998. Reversing the Gun Sights: Transnational Civil Society Targets Land Mines. Interna-
tional Organization 52 (3):613-44.
Price, Richard, and Christian Reus-Smit. 1998. Dangerous Liaisons? Critical International Theory and
Constructivism. European Journal of International Relations 4 (3):259-94.
Prittwitz, Volker von, ed. 1996a. Verhandeln und Argumentieren. Dialog, Interessen und Macht in der
Umweltpolitik. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.
. 1996b. Verstandigung tiber die Verstandigung. Anmerkungen und Erganzungen zur Debatte uber
Rationalitat und Kommunikation in den Internationalen Beziehungen. Zeitschrift fur Internationale
Beziehungen 3 (1):133-47.
Risse-Kappen, Thomas. 1995. Reden ist nicht billig. Zur Debatte um Kommunikation und Rationalitat.
Zeitschriftfiir Internationale Beziehungen 2 (1):171-84.
Risse, Thomas. 1997. The Cold War's Endgame and German Unification (A Review Essay). International
Security 21 (4):159-85.
.1999. International Norms and Domestic Change: Arguing and Strategic Adaptation in the Human
Rights Area. Politics and Society 27 (4):526-56.
Risse, Thomas, Stephen C. Ropp, and Kathryn Sikkink, eds. 1999. The Power of Human Rights: Interna-
tional Norms and Domestic Change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ruggie, John Gerard. 1998. What Makes the World Hang Together? Neo-Utilitarianism and the Social
Constructivist Challenge. International Organization 52 (4):855-85.
Russett, Bruce. 1993. Grasping the Democratic Peace: Principles for a Post-Cold War World. Princeton,
N.J.: Princeton University Press.
Saretzki, Thomas. 1995. "Arguing" oder "Bargaining": Selbstbindung der Politik durch offentliche Dis-
kurse. In Macht der Offentlichkeit-Offentlichkeit der Macht, edited by Gerhard Gohler, 277-307.
Baden-Baden: Nomos.
. 1996. Wie unterscheiden sich Argumentieren und Verhandeln? In Verhandeln undArgumentieren.
Dialog, Interessen und Macht in der Umweltpolitik, edited by Volker von Prittwitz, 19-39. Opladen:
Leske und Budrich.
Schaber, Thomas, and Cornelia Ulbert. 1994. Reflexivitat in den Internationalen Beziehungen. Literatur-
bericht zum Beitrag kognitiver, reflexiver und interpretativer Ansatze zur dritten Theoriedebatte.
Zeitschriftfiir Internationale Beziehungen 1 (1): 139-69.
Scharpf, Fritz W. 1997. Games Real Actors Play: Actor-Centered Institutionalism in Policy Research.
Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press.
Schimmelfennig, Frank. 1995. Debatten zwischen Staaten: Eine Argumentationstheorie internationaler
Systemkonfiikte. Opladen: Leske und Budrich.
. 1997. Rhetorisches Handeln in der internationalen Politik. Zeitschriftfiir Internationale Bezie-
hungen 4 (2):219-54.
Schmalz-Bruns, Rainer. 1995. Die Theorie kommunikativen Handelns-eine Flaschenpost? Anmerkungen
zur jungsten Theoriedebatte in den Internationalen Beziehungen. Zeitschrift fzir Internationale Bezie-
hungen 2 (2):347-70.
Schneider, Gerald. 1994. Rational Choice und kommunikatives Handeln. Eine Replik auf Harald Muller.
Zeitschrift fur Internationale Beziehungen 1 (2):357-66.
Sebenius, James K. 1992. Challenging Conventional Explanations of International Cooperation: Negotia-
tion Analysis and the Case of Epistemic Communities. International Organization 46 (1):323-65.
Shevardnadze, Eduard. 1991. Die Zukunft gehort der Freiheit. Reinbek: Rowohlt.
Sikkink, Kathryn. 1993. Human Rights, Principled Issue-Networks, and Sovereignty in Latin America.
International Organization 47 (3):411-41.
Simon, Herbert A. 1982. Models of Bounded Rationality. 2 vols. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Smith, Jackie, Charles Chatfield, and Ron Pagnucco, eds. 1997. Transnational Social Movements and
Global Politics: Solidarity Beyond the State. Syracuse, N.Y: Syracuse University Press.
Stein, Arthur A. 1983. Coordination and Collaboration: Regimes in an Anarchic World. In International
Regimes, edited by Stephen D. Krasner, 115-40. Ithaca, N.Y: Cornell University Press.
Stein, Janice Gross. 1995. Political Learning by Doing: Gorbachev as Uncommitted Thinker and Moti-
vated Learner. In International Relations Theory and the End of the Cold War, edited by Richard Ned
Lebow and Thomas Risse-Kappen, 223-58. New York: Columbia University Press.
Stein, Janice Gross, ed. 1989. Getting to the Table: The Processes of International Prenegotiation. Balti-
more, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Steinmo, Sven, Kathleen Thelen, and Frank Longstreth, eds. 1992. Structuring Politics: Historical Institu-
tionalism in Comparative Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Teltschik, Horst. 1991. 329 Tage: Innenansichten der Einigung. Berlin: Siedler.
Wendt, Alexander. 1987. The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations Theory. International
Organizationt 41 (3):335-70.
. 1992. Anarchy Is What States Make of It: The Social Construction of Power Politics. Interna-
tional Organization 88 (2):391-425.
. 1999. Social Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zangl, Bernhard, and Michael Zurn. 1996. Argumentatives Handeln bei internationalen Verhandlungen.
Moderate Anmerkungen zur post-realistischen Debatte. Zeitschrift fur Internationale Beziehungen 3
(2):341-66.
Zartman, I. William, and Maureen R. Berman. 1982. The Practical Negotiator. New Haven, Conn.: Yale
University Press.
Zehfuss, Maja. 1998. Sprachlosigkeit schrankt ein. Zur Bedeutung von Sprache in konstruktivistischen
Theorien. Zeitschriftffur Internationale Beziehzngen 5 (1): 109-37.
Zelikow, Philip, and Condoleezza Rice. 1995. Germany Unified and Europe Transforned: A Study in
Statecraft. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Zintl, Reinhard. 1992. Kooperation und Aufteilung des Kooperationsgewinns bei horizontaler Politikver-
flechtung. In Horizontale Politikverfiechtung. Zur Theorie von Verhandlungssystemen, edited by Arthur
Benz, Fritz W. Scharpf, and Reinhard Zintl, 97-146. Frankfurt am Main: Campus.
Zurn, Michael. 1992. Interessen und Institutionen in der internationalen Politik: Grundlegung und An-
wendung des situationsstrukturellen Ansatzes. Opladen: Leske und Budrich.