Business Ethics Lecture Notes
Business Ethics Lecture Notes
This chapter introduces students to the subject matter of business ethics. It is expected that
Introduction
Every act by businesses, managers, individual employees or a person can be viewed and
analysed from ethical perspective. Apparently, what you may justify as right may be on the
floor when weighed on the ethical scale. Businesses exist to create value for people, enhance
the lives of society (i.e. people and even animals) as well as maintain their existence in
business. To the extent that businesses satisfy this very essence, we can conclusively say that
the business is conducted, performed and implemented in an ethical manner. The big question
is, what has ethics got to do with business? In fact, everyone shares the joke about ‘business
ethics.’ ‘It must be an oxymoron’ or ‘it must be a short course’. Or ‘I didn’t know business
1
had any ethics’. Despite this popular misconception, business ethics is a robust academic
Ethics has become important in business today because increasing reports of scandals and
financial malfeasance has become part of organizational life. Every organizational decision,
made by either a board or a manager has ethical implications. Thus, organizations have
embraced the concept of ethics and have actually encouraged ethical decision making.
Business ethics is a combination of two important words: Business and Ethics. A proper
understanding of business ethics requires decoupling the two words for better understanding
organization to produce and sell, for a profit goods and services that satisfy the needs of
society. Ethics on the other hand is about one’s ability to differentiate right from wrong. Put
together, business ethics is a form of applied ethics or professional ethics that examines
ethical principles and moral or ethical problems that arise in a business environment. It has an
Put together, business ethics refers to the study of people’s tendencies to behave in morally
appropriate ways in organizations. It is sometimes called corporate ethics. Business ethics can
also be defined as the written and unwritten codes of principles and values determined by an
organization’s culture that govern decisions and actions within that organization. It has an
2
The concept of Ethics
It is abundantly clear that people always know the right thing to do. The difficulty however,
is doing the right thing. This notion is central to the distinction between two key terms –
moral values and ethics-that are essential to understanding the nature of ethical behaviour in
organizations. When social scientists speak of moral values (usually more simply referred to
as morals), they are referring to people’s fundamental beliefs regarding what is right or
wrong, good or bad. One of the most important sources of moral values is the religious
background, beliefs, and training we receive. Although people’s moral values may differ,
several are widely accepted. For example, most people believe that being charitable to
someone in need is right whereas killing an innocent person is wrong. Based on these beliefs,
people are guided in ways that influence the decisions they make and the actions in which
Ethics refers to standards of conduct that guide people’s decisions and behaviour (e.g., not
stealing from others). Most organizational scientists acknowledge that it is not a company’s
place to teach employees moral values. After all, these come with people as they enter the
to train employees in recognizing and following them. Just as organizations prescribe other
kinds of behaviour that are expected in the workplace (e.g., when to arrive and leave), so too
should they prescribe appropriate ethical behaviour (e.g., how to complete expense reports
and what precisely is considered a bribe). Not surprisingly, most top business leaders
It seems obvious that we should care about ethics because behaving ethically is the right
thing to do. Indeed, many famous people agree that ethical behaviour is of paramount
3
importance. For example, President George W. Bush said, “At this moment, America’s
highest economic need is higher ethical standards-standards enforced by strict laws and
upheld by responsible business leaders. Similarly, Robert D. Hass, former chairman of Levi
Strauss & Co., posited that “A company’s values what it stands for, what its people believe
in-are crucial to its competitive success.” Despite these lofty and well-meaning statements
from leaders, we already noted that people do not always do the right thing. Under the right
circumstances, even seemingly ethical people behave unethically. Pressure to meet sales
quotas, for example, have led some stockbrokers to boost their commissions by convincing
unknowing clients to make bad investments. Clearly, this is wrong on moral grounds.
Although managers may be uncomfortable changing their morals, they must be concerned
about promoting ethical behavior for two sound business reasons. First, over the long run,
being ethical is profitable. Second, being ethical satisfies many of today’s legal regulations.
Figure 1 illustrates the link between morality, ethics, decision and behaviour.
Although individuals and businesses are expected to act ethically, business ethics scholars
differ in their descriptions of the context of an ethical choice, on the principle to use in
4
making the choice, and on the particular alternative dictated by that principle. Business ethics
is a process of normative thinking about business. Its task is not to hand down ethical
verdicts. The field of business ethics does not 'accuse' anyone else.
Sources of Ethics
All human beings have a basic sense of right and wrong, which develops quite early in life
and is often modified with maturity and experience. However, there are some categories of
people who appear to be without concern for the impact of their actions on other humans.
Are humans born ethical? Or we learn to be ethical? This issue has preoccupied the minds of
scholars for centuries. The argument is, are babies born with some knowledge or inclinations,
or a newborn baby is a blank slate, with knowledge and inclination provided by experience.
This complex issue is sometimes referred to as the “nature vs. nurture”, debate, and has been
a subject of a great deal of study and experimentation. However, present evidence point to the
fact that, in some ways, newborns are not all alike. In layman’s terms, infants are born with
personalities or pre-dispositions. All share certain physical instincts, but such traits as
however, to appreciate the fact that, a baby’s upbringing from its earliest days also has
significant influence on how it reacts to the world around it. There is enough evidence to
conclude, at least tentatively, that children brought up in secure and nurturing environments
show a strong tendency to view the world differently than children raised in less secure and
5
While evolutionary researchers have established that patterns of decision-making and
concepts of right and wrong emerge from early life experience, it important to note that
influence is not the same as determination. This is because unless individuals at least in
some instances make truly free choices, the concept of ethics makes no sense. It is a principle
of both philosophy and law that no one is obliged to do what they cannot do.
It can be said that the sources of an individual’s sense of moral right and wrong lie to some
extent in their personality, and this is impacted by early experience. There are a variety of
Parents
Parents are certainly a major influence on the sense of ethics of that adults bring to their
work. Consider the statement, “She has a good work ethic.” It is a common way of saying
that someone has certain beliefs and attitudes that influence their performance at work. If this
can be said about someone in her first job, then the good work ethics must have been formed
before they became an employee. For most people, this means that it was formed at home as
they were growing up, and this shows the influence of parents in development and
internalization a good work ethic. Even adults who no longer agree intellectually with their
parents’ teaching about right and wrong behaviour sometimes admit that their parents’
teaching influence their thoughts and actions. Therefore, parents are one source of ethics that
Peers
Our siblings, schoolmates, college mates, fellow workers or members of a club, team or
social group to which an individual belongs influence our sense of ethics. Often individuals
define themselves by their group of friends, and adults also have their views shaped to some
6
degree by their peers. It is said that police officers often have a more negative view of
humanity than those in some other professions because they spend so much of their time
Peers can also be members of the same profession. Accountants, attorneys, medical doctors
and members of other professions undergo extensive schooling. They learn not only how to
minimize taxes or diagnose diabetes, but also how member of their profession act and think.
not all accountants or attorneys think alike. However, an argument can be made that members
of a given profession think more alike than non-members of that profession. Another factor
involving peer influence in the profession is the existence of professional code of conduct.
These codes of conducts are not perfect, and they do not influence all members of a
profession equally. However, they do provide a starting point for making some kinds of
ethical judgments, and they are more or less widely known within a profession.
Teachers
They are another important medium of an individual’s sense of morality. Whether it is the
simple but often-repeated rules of grammar school or the more involved exposition that
occurs in college classes, teachers as authority figures do communicate in ways that influence
the reasoning and judgment of at least some of their students. For example, almost all
teachers communicate, subtly or overtly, that cheating is wrong. They say this, they write it in
a syllabi and on exam instructions, and they act on this when they detect cheating. Teachers
also often communicate the value of doing assignments, or thinking clearly, or doing one’s
part in a group projects. The cumulative impact of teachers does have an influence on the
Culture
7
Our cultural values are critical as far as moral lessons are concerned. Culture can be defined
as the unspoken rules and assumptions about how we do things around here. When
considered in this way, culture is subtle because it is unspoken. Most organizations do not
have explicit rules that dictate who shall be called by their first name and who shall be
addressed more formally. They do not have explicit rules about profanity at work, or the
degree to which client information is kept confidential, or the kind of jokes that are
there often are unspoken rules. An observer of the behaviour of workers at a construction site
and at a law firm would notice immediate and profound difference in individual behaviour
and methods of conducting business. The two have different cultures. However, an
Religion
By far religion is regarded as the most important driver of an individual’s sense of ethics.
People who were raised in a religion, even if they no longer believe or practice it, often have
the teachings of that religion as part of their sense of ethics. People who do believe in and
practice religion typically find the moral rules or dictates of their religion the most
meaningful way to answer questions about right and wrong behaviour. However, most
religious people would agree that it is not a good thing to commandeer passenger airplanes
and fly them and their passengers into building in order to avenge one’s god or to send a
religious message. Most religious people would agree that doing such things in the name of
8
It is not enough to simply say that our conduct is lawful. The law is the floor. Compliance
with it will be the absolute minimum with respect to the individual and business, no matter
where he or she works or sector the business operates. Thus, ethics go beyond the legal code.
This statement underscores two important points—namely, (1) that following ethical
standards is not merely the same as obeying the law, and (2) that the law may be considered
the minimum acceptable standard to which companies must adhere. Over the years, as people
have become appalled by breaches of ethics in the government and corporate worlds, it is not
surprising that they have looked to their political leaders for long-term solutions.
It is important however, to indicate that law influences people’s sense of morality. In fact,
business people often equate ethics and law; however, the two differ to some extent. For
example, businesses involved in scandals have had their executives said, in effect, “What we
did was not wrong because we complied with the law, or with Generally Accepted
Accounting Principles.” In other words, many people, at least some of the time, do not make
While ethics is a branch of philosophy, law is seen as a quite distinct field. Legal systems, or
groups of laws, have existed for thousands of years. Law is a function of government, in that
laws are made, changed and enforced by governments. Law apply in specific places and have
their standing from the government of countries, states or other political entities or group of
rules for how laws are to be made and changed. Directly related to laws are regulations.
Regulations have the force of law, but are generally more specific and are written and
approved by regulatory agencies within the framework of the elected government. Regulators
are generally appointed rather than elected. Regulations are intended to provide detail
specifying how broader laws apply to specific cases and examples. Most businesses are
9
subject to several regulatory agencies and must comply with detailed regulations in such
matters as taxation, financial disclosure and product safety. All businesses are also subject to
First, law-makers are often not noted for their refined moral sensibility. For example,
students, scholars and professionals would not subscribe to the notion that either national or
local legislators make up their moral code. This should not be surprising, for in a democracy,
candidates for office generally do not claim to be the most virtuous or the most morally
sensitive individuals in the country. This is not however, to say that most politicians and
regulators are liars and thieves. It is merely to say that they are not chosen and kept in office
Finally, it is dangerous to equate law to ethics because laws change, while many people
expect at least the basics of morality/ethics to be unchanging. For example, in some parts of
the world prostitution is legal and even same sex marriage. While the legal status of an act
can change from country to country, it is difficult to argue that prostitution or same sex
marriage is moral or ethical in one country and immoral or unethical in the next.
Although it is dangerous to equate law to ethics, it is ethical to follow the law. This is because
all of the major systems of ethics include an assumption in favour of obeying the law. Note
that this is the assumption, not an absolute mandate. This reasoning is premise on the
following: (a) Laws are made to reflect and protect the values of a society, at least in a
democracy. If they do not reflect society’s values, new law-makers are elected by the people.
10
(b) Ethics is about values. If a society’s values the individual’s rights to speak his or her
mind, its laws will tend to protect free speech, and most censorship will be considered illegal.
The social responsibility of business is to increase its profit or effectiveness. Friedman, the
famous Nobel Prize-winning economist noted that the role of the manager is to act as the
agent of the owners of the business that he or she managers, namely, the stockholder.
business in accordance with their desires, which generally will be to make much
money as possible while conforming to the basic rules of society, both those embodied
Earlier ethics was defined as the discipline that studies interpersonal or social values and the
rules of conduct that derives from these values, certainly the decisions of managers do affect
other people, including their subordinates, others within their organizations and various
people beyond the organization, including but not limited to the stockholders or owners.
Managerial ethics, then, must of necessity examine the impacts of the actions of managers.
with laws and regulations. Several studies on leadership exist, but almost none of it refers to
complying with the law as a characteristic of a successful leader. It is assumed that good
leaders do not run afoul the law, but it is not at all assumed that compliance with the law is
the same as good leadership. Not all managers are leaders, but both managers and leaders
11
Psychologists and social theorists tell us that individuals have trouble dealing with
inconsistency. It is hard for the same person to be warm and nurturing with spouse and
children, and cold and impersonal with subordinates at work. The ethical or virtuous person,
according to Aristotle, is the person who shows consistency and moderation in all their
2. Individual characteristics – values, knowing right from wrong. Ego strength, the
power of your convictions. Locus of control, an internal locus of control means that
you believe you control your own destiny, an external locus of control means you
4. Organisational culture – this is made up of the values and norms shared by people
working for an organisation. A strong culture will exert more influence than a weak
one.
5. Issue intensity – this refers to how important an issue is. Something not so important
(e.g. making private local calls) has different ethical implications to something very
large (e.g. embezzling GH¢1 billion). The act is the same (theft) but the intensity of
A story by Heinz:
A woman was near death from cancer. One drug might save her, a form of radium that a
druggist in the same town had recently discovered. The druggist was charging $2,000, ten
times what the drug cost him to make. The sick woman’s husband, Heinz, went to everyone
he knew to borrow the money, but he could not get together about half of what it cost. He
told the druggist that his wife was dying and asked him to sell it cheaper or let him pay later.
But the druggist said “no.” the husband got desperate and broke into the man’s store to steal
2. To what extent can you say that the act by Heinz was ethical?
3. To what extent can you say that Heinz was constrained by law?
Questions
1. Identify and discuss two reasons why business ethics is relevant for business
professionals
2. Briefly discuss the statement that “Ethics and law are not the same”.
13
CHAPTER TWO
14
THEORIES OF ETHICS
Ethical issues are better explained from a theoretical perspective than from a layman point of
view. This chapter addresses the various ethical theories and how they facilitate our
understanding of business ethics and the implications of manager’s decisions. At the end of
Explain the utilitarian theory of ethics with focus on act and rule utilitarianism
Explain Kantian theory of ethics with focus on universalizing maxim and persons as
ends
Introduction
Throughout the history of philosophy, thinkers have addressed the question of what makes an
act moral or immoral. In this book, the terms “moral” and “ethical” will be used
interchangeably. Ethical decisions are usually viewed from a theoretical perspective. Thus, a
utilitarian theory. This chapter addresses theoretical issues as they relate to ethics in business.
Is there a single view of right or wrong? These questions can be complex, since there is no
single view in general ethics of what makes something right or wrong. People or
and this is expressed in ethical criteria normally grounded in ethical theories (Victor &
15
Cullen, 1988). The theory-based criteria contain information about the recommended action
and about the reasons for that recommendation. These criteria comprise the logic for action,
"the underlying assumptions, deeply held, often unexamined, which form a framework within
which reasoning takes place" (Horn, 1983). Broadly speaking, ethicists put ethical theories
Teleology
when studying various phenomena (Kagan, 1997). As such, theories based on this approach
to the study of ethics are sometimes referred to as consequential theories. The notion behind
such theories is that the morality of behaviour can be judged by the consequences of that
behaviour. Specifically, a consequentialist view of ethics holds that the goodness or badness
of a proposed action is evident only in the consequences of that action: whether a lie is good
or bad depends upon the consequences of that particular lie at the time. Utilitarianism, for
example, is a consequentialist theory, in that it seeks to maximize the net happiness for
everyone affected by a particular action (‘the greatest good for the greatest number’, as it is
sometimes expressed).
Teleological Theories
Consequential Theories
Many theorists contend that the moral rightness of an action can be determined simply by
looking at its consequences. If the consequences are good, the act is right; if the
16
consequences are bad the act is wrong. Consequential theories measure the morality of
actions on the basis of their non-moral consequences (Barry, 1979). Simply put, actions
good or bad action simply by looking at the ratio of goodness or badness the action produces;
and eventually choose the course of action that would seem to produce the most good. Under
Egoism
Egoism is a branch of teleology, which focuses on the consequences of behaviors on the self
as opposed to others (Tsalikis & Fritzsche, 1989). Egoism is a moral act which promotes the
individuals best long-term interests. In determining the morality of an action, egoists use
their best long-term advantage to measure the action’s goodness (Barry, 1979). Egoism
measures the morality of a behavior by the extent to which the behavior promotes one’s own
interests. Under this approach, an action that promotes a person’s knowledge and self-
actualization is considered ethical, whereas an action that does not is considered unethical.
There are a few variations of the theory; one school of thought views two forms of egoism
and these are psychological egoism and ethical egoism. Psychological egoism is a descriptive
theory of human behavior that holds that people are naturally programmed to behave only in
their own self-interest. Ethical egoism is the normative theory whereby people ought to act
exclusively in their self-interest (Reidenbach & Robin, 1990; Jones et al., 2007). Thus, the
moral principle of ethical egoism suggests that an act is ethical when it promotes the
individual's long-term interest (Shultz & Brender-Ilan, 2004; Jones et al., 2007). Note that it
is possible for people to help others, follow the rules of society, and even grant gifts if they
17
Some moralists also distinguish between two kinds of egoism: personal and impersonal.
Personal egoists claim that they should pursue their own best long term interests and
impersonal egoists also claim that everyone should follow their own best long term interests
(Barry, 1979). Hinman (2007) on the other hand sees three categories of ethical egoism;
personal ethical egoism which believes that “I am going to act only in my own interest, and
everyone else can do whatever they want.” Individual ethical egoism also believes that
“everyone should act in my own interest.” and universal ethical egoism contends that “Each
individual should act in his or her own self-interest.” Ethical egoists sometimes maintain that
if each person took care of himself/herself, the overall effect would be to make the world a
Utilitarianism
The theory most commonly associated with the teleological approach is known as utilitarian
theory. Utilitarianism is the philosophical approach which says that the moral act is the one
that creates the greatest happiness or good for the greatest number of people. To Rachels
(1993), the belief that actions should be appraised in terms of their effect on happiness is
asserts we should always act so as to produce the greater ratio of good to evil for everyone
and therefore emphasizes the best interests of everyone concerned. Lewis (1991) defines it as
society’s net benefit over harm. To Hinman (2007) the fundamental imperative of
utilitarianism is to always act in the way that will produce the greatest overall amount of good
in the world. Conversely, behaviour is deemed to be unethical if it either does not maximize
the benefit individuals receive, or produce more benefit for some people than for others. In
terms of organizational policies, utilitarianism holds that rules are ethical if they promote
18
behaviours that maximize the benefit for all members and other stakeholders, and are
Utilitarianism has been linked to the modern welfare state which has found some special
interest for students of philosophy and society. It has also been associated with reform or
social improvement (McPherson, 1970). Hosmer (2003) contends that in applying the
utilitarian theory to the outcome of an action or decision, the principle is that everyone should
act to generate the greatest benefits for the largest number of people. The ultimate goal of
utilitarianism is not the happiness of the individual, but the happiness of society (Rossouw,
2002). Are the greatest happiness and the greatest good the same thing? Broadly speaking,
Utilitarianism focuses on ends and not on the means required to achieving those ends, and it
takes into account all present and future benefits and harms that accrue or might accrue to
anyone who is affected by the action, including items that may be difficult to evaluate
accurately (Schumann, 2001). According to the utilitarian moral principle, an act is morally
acceptable if it produces the greatest net benefit to society as a whole, where the net social
benefit equals social benefits minus social costs (Bentham, 1789; Mill, 1957; Brandt, 1979;
The primary way of assessing “the greatest good for the greatest number” is by performing a
social cost/benefit analysis. All possible benefits and costs of the assessed act are listed and
summarized as the net of all benefits minus all costs. If the net result is positive, the act is
morally acceptable; if the net result is negative, the act is not acceptable. Utilitarianism seems
to have been accepted by business people, which may in part be due to its tradition in
economics. The ensuing economic philosophy of capitalism, alongside Adam Smith (1776),
provides a rich traditional heritage to the utilitarian concepts. Capitalist systems, by providing
19
the greatest material good for the greatest number, get to be considered ethical from the
perspective of the traditional economic philosophy. It should be noted here that the utilitarian
analyses of moral philosophers extend beyond material good to the much broader concept of
The theory of utilitarianism is associated with two English philosophers: Jeremy Bentham
(1748-1832) and John Stuart Mill (1806-1873). In expressing the theory of utilitarianism,
Bentham said:
Nature has placed mankind under the governance of two sovereign masters, pain and
pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we ought to do, as well as to determine
what we shall do. On the one hand the standard of right and wrong, on the other the
augment or diminish the happiness of the party whose interest is in question: or, what
The creed which accepts as the foundation of morals, Utility, or the Greatest
Happiness Principle, holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote
happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended
pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure. To
give a clear view of the moral standard set up by the theory, much more requires to be said; in
particular, what things it includes in the ideas of pain and pleasure; and to what extent this is
20
left an open question. But these supplementary explanations do not affect the theory of life on
which this theory of morality is grounded – namely, that pleasure, and freedom from pain, are
the only things desirable as ends; and that all desirable things (which are as numerous in the
utilitarian as in any other scheme) are desirable either for the pleasure inherent in themselves,
Although it could be interesting to actually sit back and think about what our ultimate ends
might be, in most cases we make decisions based on more immediate concerns – what
may add six new salespeople because he/she is persuaded that the additional revenue they
generate will not only cover their own costs, but also provide an increment of profits to the
company. Also, we choose to go to the dentist and have a root canal performed not because
we enjoy pain as an ultimate end, but because the temporary pain of the dental procedure will
When we decide on the morality of an action based on the results that will be achieved, we
are engaging in utilitarianism. This is different from choosing an action because it is simply
the right thing to do. Thus, the charge is sometimes raised that utilitarianism is wrong
because it is based on the notion that the end justifies the means.
For too many people, the statement “the end justifies the means” is the same as “a good end
justifies any means.” Increased profit for my business is a good end, but it does not justify my
employing eight-year-old children for twelve hours a day and paying them a dollar an hour. It
also does not justify ignoring safety concerns and selling a product or service with a high
company operating and prevent all employees from losing their jobs.
ethics) are problematic in that they focus on ends as opposed to means (Tsalikis & Fritzsche,
1989). That is, a behavior might achieve an outcome that is beneficial for all stakeholders of
an organization, but accomplish the outcome in a way that is detrimental to long-term well-
being, for example. It can also be argued that a utilitarian outcome is not always a fair
outcome in that some people may contribute above-average inputs to a task, but receive equal
Types of Utilitarianism
Act utilitarianism
Is the theory stipulating that the morally right act is the one that produces at least as much
overall happiness in the circumstances as any alternative act. This means that when deciding
which act would be ethically right, a person must investigate the reasonably foreseeable
consequences of the different possible acts she could perform; the act that would produce the
Example: this scenario involves two parties and two alternative courses of action. Consider a
request made by your aunt in the local retirement home that you visit her one evening. She
can be a difficult person and you do not particularly like visiting, though you know she is
lonely and your visits do her a world of good. If you agree to her request and visit her, she
will be very happy, but you will miss your favourite television show, causing you to
experience a certain amount of unhappiness. If you decide not to visit her, she will be
extremely disappointed, but you will be able to watch your television programme, gaining
some happiness (though a twinge of guilt takes away just a bit of that happiness). Act-
22
utilitarianism requires this sort of thinking – analyzing the effects on the happiness of the
individuals involved for each alternative course of action. The morally right action is the one
producing the most overall happiness. The following chart captures these various effects:
Total +5 -12
Notice that the amount of happiness gained or lost is quantified. However, in line with the
formal definition of act-utilitarianism provided here, it should also be pointed out that in the
case where there is a “tie” in that two alternative courses of action would produce the most
happiness, either of the two acts may be performed. This sort of possibility is covered by the
specification that the right act would produce “at least” as much overall happiness as any
alternative act. If, for example, the total effects on happiness would be identical for ACT X
and Act Y (if, say, each would produce a net gain of 5 units of happiness), then either of
those two actions would be morally permissible. To say that an act is morally permissible, is
to say that it is allowed but not required; the performance of the act is not morally wrong, but
neither is the failure to perform it. However, performing one of those two acts, instead of Act
Z (that would, say, produce an overall gain of only 2 units of happiness), would be morally
required.
Act-utilitarianism has been endorsed by philosophers because (a) it assesses the morality of
actions in terms of the consequences of those actions, and utilitarians suggest that this is
commonsensical, that what we mean by the morality of actions is just the consequences that
those actions might bring about. Thus, in what other ways, they ask, could morality be
assessed except by appealing to the consequences? (b) It is relatively simple and (all things
professional ethics), it is desirable to have a basic moral theory that can be applied to real-life
cases without undue difficulty. (c) act-utilitarianism possesses the characteristics that are
Rule-Utilitarianism
Act-utilitarianism calls for the maximization of overall happiness in the circumstances. Rule-
utilitarianism differs in that it calls for an analysis that extends beyond the immediate
circumstances. Instead, it calls for a closer look at the long-term consequences that would be
generated by performing the act in all relevantly similar situations. More formally, according
to rule-utilitarianism, the right act conforms to the rule which, when followed, produces at
least much overall happiness over the long run as any alternative rule. More broadly, that rule
must then itself be a member of a set of rules that would produce at least as much overall
The claim made by rule-utilitarianism is that their theory will generate rules, and will thus
prescribe actions in accordance with those rules, that are much more in line with our
intuitions. For example, the rule requiring people to keep their promises is likely justified by
rule-utilitarian considerations. A society in which people can rely on others to keep their
word will be happier than a society in which promises are broken on a regular basis. Keeping
one’s word will thus be a fairly stringent moral obligation under rule-utilitarianism; it is a
rule that would produce at least as much happiness as any alternative rule pertaining to
promise-keeping, and that rule can likely be integrated into a set of rules that would
maximize overall societal happiness. Thus, when a lawyer agrees in principle to a settlement
in a lawsuit and then goes back on that agreement just before the schedule trial date (in order
to cause confusion on the part of the opposing lawyer), rule-utilitarianism could perhaps be
24
Conclusion
Criticizing utilitarianism is not enough to demonstrate that it should not be used in ethical
provided. It is much easier to criticize than to defend. (Political campaign advertisements are
examples of this; the faults of the other candidate are often highlighted rather than the merits
of the candidate himself.) Utilitarians sometimes acknowledge that their theory is not perfect,
but they challenge their critics to point to a better one. After all, they say, there is not perfect
moral theory; rather, it is the best moral theory that is sought. The following theories are
or in government. The basic concept behind cost-benefit analysis is that spending money,
time and effort might be justified by the results to be achieved, but it might not. Since this
expenditures that have already been made and results that have already been achieved.
Cost-benefit analysis conceptually underlies the whole process of budgeting. It does not make
good business sense to plan to spend money, under either expense or capital budgets, that will
not yield a benefit at least equal to the expenditure. The budget process is often conducted
with a good deal of politics involved and, as the saying goes; the devil is in the details.
However, when money could be spent in one of several ways, but not all of them, then
aiming to get the biggest bang for the buck is not really different than aiming to create the
25
While cost-benefit analysis is utilitarian in spirit, it is narrower in scope. Whether in business
or in government, the most common benefit weighed against costs is financial in nature. If a
project or an addition to staff will either generate enough revenues or reduce enough future
financial cost, then it is approved. The principal metric used in cost-benefit analysis is
efficiency-will the expenditure in question generate the most output with the least input?
While it might legitimately do so, cost-benefit analysis does not always take into account
impacts beyond expenses and revenues. To give one example frequently raised in business
ethics textbooks, a cost-benefit analysis of a plant closing in a small town might not address
the impact on the town’s unemployment rate or tax base, while in utilitarian analysis would
expenditures are sometimes approved on the basis of necessity rather than amount of dollar
benefits. One relatively small hospital group with which I am familiar recently decided to
spend tens of millions of dollars integrating its more than twenty software systems so that
medical and financial information would be available to everyone involved with a patient
hospital group felt that they simply could not continue to provide adequate service without
such systems integration. The project was approved on the basis of necessity rather than of
quantified savings or additional revenue and profits. It appears that, in deciding to spend this
amount of money on systems integration, they were aiming in a broad sense to achieve the
Deontology
One school of thought emphasises duties, things that must be done (or refrained from)
irrespective of the consequences. This deontological point of view holds that goodness or
26
badness is evident only in the action itself: that, for example, lying is bad because it is bad in
itself. Thus, deontological approach to the study of ethics differs from teleological
approaches in that it does not focus solely on consequences when assessing the morality of
actions. Instead, this approach places more emphasis on the extent to which a person’s
decisions and behaviours conform to existing standards of morality such as rules and rights.
Deontology deals with actions, which are inherently right or wrong, without taking their
alternative of action, we do not have to know its probable outcomes. The foundation of moral
duty is an “a priori” belief. Reason can reveal the basic moral principles. In order to define
what I should do, I must consider what all rational beings must do. Moral laws are valid for
The deontological school of thought focuses on the preservation of individual rights and on
the intentions associated with a particular behaviour, rather than on its consequences.
Deontologists look for conformity to moral principles to determine whether or not an action
is ethical. They also feel that individuals have certain undeniable rights, which include
freedom of conscience, freedom of consent, freedom of privacy, freedom of speech, and due
process.
Both duties (deontological) and consequences (teleological) are plainly important in the way
we deal with ethical issues in everyday life. Unfortunately, however, they are very different
ways of reasoning, which can lead to contradictory outcomes in some cases. An exclusively
duty-based view of ethics, for example, must sooner or later run into problems such as
absolutism, or the difficulty of deciding which duty should take precedence over others in a
particular situation. If, for example, both lying and killing are held to be inherently wrong, is
it acceptable to lie in order to avoid a killing? And whatever answer is given, how do we
know?
27
The approaches of two leading deontologists will be discussed in this course. The first is a
strict deontology described by Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), who is credited with providing
the details of the theory. In fact deontological ethics is sometimes thought to be synonymous
with “Kantian ethics”, though this equivalence is misguided, one can believe that deontology
is the best moral theory without agreeing with the specifics of Kant’s claims. This was true of
Sir W.D. Rose (1877-1971), a more moderate deontologist whose views would be discussed
in this text.
The purpose of a moral theory, Kant is to provide a way of discovering whether certain
actions or policies are ethically right, wrong, or permissible. Example, Martell Welch, Jr.
attacked Deletha Word because she accidentally dented his car. He stripped and beat her in
broad daylight on the Bell Isle Bridge in Detroit, Michigan. While he beat her, over forty
people watched him and, according to reports, at times cheered for him. No one on the bridge
offered any kind of assistance to Word, not even a phone call for help. To escape from
Welch, she threw herself over the side of the bridge and drowned. It seems to us, according to
our moral vision that Welch’s actions were ethically wrong, and it also seems that the other
people on the bridge were wrong for failing to act on her behalf. A moral theory, though, is
supposed to test these sorts of intuitions to see if they reflect moral truth; it is supposed to
clarify things, so that we can determine whether our initial moral vision is accurate.
From Kantian perspective, the determination of whether Welch’s action was morally right,
wrong or permissible requires carefully consideration of the act under the following thematic
concepts. According to Kant, the answer to each question is a “proposition” of morality and a
revision of these propositions leads to a better understanding of the theory and how it works.
28
The first question, which is very basic, is: what makes a person morally good? Kant posits
that the intention (motive) one chooses makes one morally good. When we judge people as
morally good or bad, we do not look at whether they happen to achieve their goals. People
often fail to accomplish set goals through no fault of their own. You may set yourself the
general goal of helping others, and this may mean that when the man next to you has a heart
attack, your specific goal is to save his life. It may be, however, that despite your best efforts
to save him, the man dies nonetheless. It should be clear that the man’s death does not mean
you are morally bad. Instead, it is more plausible to claim that you are morally good because
your goal – your intention – was to save his life. This is the idea behind Kant’s first
Next is what sort of intentions makes one morally good? This leads to Kant’s second
proposition of morality. Specifically, Kant indicates that there is a right and a wrong way to
answer this question. The wrong way pertains to happiness. It is a fact of human nature that
people are inclined to act so as to make themselves happy. Perhaps you have the intention of
doing well in school, and this is because you have the yet further intention of being happy.
points out, however, that being happy is not necessarily the same thing as being a morally
good person. After all, some things that make you happy may be unethical. Therefore, it is
not the intention of bringing about happiness that makes one morally good. Instead, it is
acting with the intention of being dutiful – of acting from the motive of duty itself, and not
from the (misguided) motive of bringing about happiness. Stated formally, Kant’s second
proposition is that a morally good intention (the possession of which makes a person morally
29
The second proposition (acting from motive of duty) gives rise to a third question: what
exactly, does this mean? What does it mean for a person to intend to act from the motive of
duty? Kant’s answer which is his third proposition is that acting from the motive of duty is
acting out of respect for the moral law. The moral law to Kant is that which morality
requires. Specifically, the moral law is what morality itself (objective moral truth) requires of
us, and acting out of respect for the moral law means not allowing anything-not happiness,
not fear, not love, not even government’s law – to get in the way of doing what is morally
right. This commitment to doing what is right, and being willing to sacrifice happiness along
the way, is what Kant means to capture by the notion of “respect” in this third proposition.
In brief, Kant’s views about morality or ethics is that a person is morally good (performs
moral actions) if he acts from a morally good intention, and an intention is morally good if
the motive is duty itself, meaning respect for the moral law. First, for Kant, doing the right
thing can be a somewhat complex operation. Acting from the right motive is crucial. Some
Kantians take this to mean that acting from the right motive is a necessary part of performing
the right act-that one cannot perform the right action unless she acts out of respect for the
moral law. Others believe that the two notions are separate, that one must perform the
morally right action, and in addition, must do so with the right motive (respect for the moral
law). Against this backdrop, it is possible to perform the right action without doing so out of
respect for the moral law. Secondly, appeal to consequences to Kant, is irrelevant. Although
Third, in performing a morally right action, one’s inclinations have to be ignored. Inclinations
refer to intuitions, desires, emotions, or any motivations other than respect for the moral law.
Kant believes that when determining the ethical course of action, inclinations can get in the
way; they can skew one’s thinking and lead to misguided conclusions about what is ethical.
Inclinations should thus be set aside. Despite this elucidation about a morally right action, we
30
are unable to determine what this moral law is? To understand this, Kant proposed an answer
In ethics, moral theories serve as tools for sharpening our moral vision, for helping us to
better see things (ethically) as they really are (objectively). The tool of Kantian deontology
focuses on motive, but the more complete account of theory entails categorical imperative,
which serves two purposes. First, it is a command; it instructs us what to do. In fact, it tells us
what we must do if we are to act ethically, and in this way it tells us what the moral law really
is. Second, it is a mechanism for testing actions or rules to see whether they are ethically
First, the theory is premised on the idea of universalizing maxims. In Kant’s words, the
command is, “Act only according to that maxim by which you can at the same time will that
it should become a universal law.” Putting into context, if we asked Martell Welch why he
beat Deletha Word, he might respond by saying, “she made me angry, and beating her made
me feel better.” His motive in some sense pertains to alleviating the anger she caused him.
The second step is to use this motive to ascertain the person’s maxim. A maxim is a more
general type of motive; it is an individual’s reason for acting, but it is expressed as a general
rule that applies to all future actions. Welch’s motive in the specific case can be expanded
into the following general guiding rule: “Whenever anyone angers me, I will beat that person
so that I can feel better.” This is Welch’s maxim; it is the general rule that he was following
in this particular case. The third step would be to universalize this maxim, which means
restating it not just for the individual but for all people (or, as Kant says, for all rational
beings). The universalized maxim would then be: “Whenever anyone angers any person, that
person who is angry will beat the person who caused the anger.” The fourth step is to assess
31
whether this universalized maxim can be a moral law. If this universalized maxim is
consistent – if it can be practiced in the world without any inconsistency – then it can be a
moral law. This would mean that the original action performed is not wrong. If, on the other
hand, the universalized maxim generates a contradiction and is thus inconsistent, then the
original act performed is wrong and may not be performed. In the example, a natural result of
the universalized maxim is that there would be a lot of beatings occurring; it is a natural fact
that people get angry from time to time, and so numerous beatings would be expected to
follow. When people get beaten, they often experience anger (among other emotions), and
Following from the earlier example, Martell beat Deletha because she made him angry and he
wanted to feel better. Thus, on the one hand, he wants his anger to be alleviated. The maxim
underlying his action, however, generates a world in which more anger would come about.
This would be true for him as well, since the people he angers would beat him, causing him
to experience anger at being beaten. In short, he is seeking to lessen his anger, and this is
straightforwardly inconsistent. Another way to characterize the situation is to say that Martell
Simply, an act can be said to be morally right in the opinion of Kant based on the following
four basic steps (a) ascertain the individual’s motive; (b) ascertain the individual’s maxim; (c)
universalize the maxim; and (d) assess the universalized maxim for consistency.
According to Kant “Act so that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in the
person of any other, always as an end and never as a means only”. In this context, the
difference between means and ends is closely related to the difference between people and
32
things. An inanimate object-a “thing”-has value only insofar as someone values it; it does not
have value “in itself,” meaning it would have no value at all without someone to value it. It is
therefore permissible to use things as I see fit in order to accomplish my goals. A computer
for example, is a thing and so has no value in itself. Therefore, since you own your computer,
you can use it as a means to your ends-as a tool for helping you achieve what you want.
Treating your computer as a mere stepping stone in this way does not morally wrong the
computer, for it is not the sort of thing that can be wronged. You can even choose to throw it
out the window if you get frustrated with it (as long as no one outside the window will be
injured).
In all these ways, people are different. People do not need to be valued by others in order to
have value. This formulation underscores Kant’s belief that every rational creature has
inherent worth. This worth does not result from any quality other than the sheer possessing
of rationality. Rational human being possesses what Kant termed an “autonomous self-
legislating will.” In other words, they can evaluate their actions, make rules for themselves,
and direct their conduct according to these self-imposed rules. Kant sums his “categorical
imperative” as “one ought never to act unless one is willing to have the maxim on which one
acts to become a universal law”. To Kant (1959) therefore, good will, and only good will, can
be universalized.
Again Kant indicates that you may not treat another person as a mere means. You may not
simply use another person in an effort to further your own goals. People, unlike computers,
are not mere stepping stones and may not be treated as such. This is Kant’s idea behind the
moral command that we are always to treat people as ends and never as means only; we must
always recognize that people are valuable in themselves (are ends in themselves). He also
uses the terminology of respect and dignity to capture this idea; we are always and
everywhere to demonstrate respect for persons, to recognize the inherent dignity they possess
33
(because of their rational capacities). Kant also makes clear that this is why all people are
moral equals. Each person is an end in himself or herself to the same degree as all other
persons, and so no one is more valuable – more morally important –than anyone else.
Nonetheless, duties and principles clearly do inform our views of how people should treat
and of deciding how to measure those consequences. Some form of utilitarianism can be very
unjust to small minorities, by allowing their unhappiness (i.e. as a result of some proposed
action) to be offset by the increased happiness of a much larger number. Again, however, we
can hardly deny that our assessment of the likely consequences of different actions plays a
lower-cost Anglophone country. The shareholder-centred view would place emphasis on the
unit cost savings to be achieved by moving the operation to a lower-cost area, provided that
the required quality of service can be maintained. Other things being equal, lower unit costs
obviously allow higher margins and improved rewards to shareholders. However, the
assessment would also take into account the possibility of additional risks to be managed,
such as security and quality control issues. Furthermore, this view would also consider the
34
competitive implications of the decisions: if other suppliers all outsource and reduce their
prices to customers, a decision not to do the same could damage the company. On the other
hand, being different could be a viable competitive stance for one or more competitors,
particularly if some customers are concerned about reduced quality of service from off
shoring: at one point, NatWest in the UK seemed to take this stance in its advertising.
A deontological approach to the ethics of off shoring would focus on aspects of the proposal
that might be in breach of clear principles and duties. While no business can reasonably
accept a general duty to keep existing employees on the payroll for ever, a contemplation of
duties might cause a company to do as much as possible to soften the impact of the job
losses, including the possibility of internal transfer, retraining, outplacement and more-than-
minimum redundancy packages. A utilitarian analysis would seek to identify all who would
be affected- anywhere in the world – by the proposed off shoring decision and then assess the
impact (positive or negative) on each person (or, more realistically, group). This would allow
a sort of “trial balance” of the consequences to be drawn up and an evaluation of the net
impact on aggregate happiness. Necessarily in this method, the reduction in happiness for
others, such as those who are made involuntarily redundant, is offset by the extra happiness
created for some-those who get offshore jobs, for example. Obviously, this is of little comfort
to the former group, which illustrates one of the important criticisms of the utilitarian
approach.
How, then, are ethical choices to be made by people working for organizations? No simple
and universal answer is available – ethical awareness is something that can be cultivated and
the different perspectives will often help to shed light on a particular dilemma. Some
35
perspectives may appear to be better suited to particular situations: whereas, for example, it is
difficult to avoid some sort of consequentialist component in thinking about how a company
should act, it is also clear that duty-based (or ‘moral compass’) arguments must also weigh
heavily in thinking about the ethical treatment of people such as employees. The German
philosopher Kant’s view that we should always treat other people as ends in themselves and
never simply as means is surely an important principle for decent human resource
management and one that would often be seen as more important than the prospect of short-
term gain.
Personal integrity and individual values are important elements in ethical decision-making at
work, but the increasingly common company, professional or industry codes of conduct may
also provide support and guidance. This is not to say that these ethical ‘resources’ will always
provide clear and comfortable guidance – sometimes, people in organizations will experience
tension between conflicting demands of, say, their own personal values and the demands
placed on them by their organization. If these conflicts become intolerable and cannot be
resolved through normal means, then an individual may decide to become a ‘whistleblower’
in the public interest, by taking the high-risk approach of placing the problem in the public
domain for resolution. Code of conduct can help reduce the risk of painful situations like this
by providing a published set of values to which the individual can appeal, rather than taking
Ethical Reflections
Case 1:
Imagine that you are an office manager in a law firm. Your responsibilities include
scheduling the only two administrative assistants, Tom and Sue. (You must make sure they
36
do not take the same lunch hour or schedule the same week for vacation, for example.). Next
Monday is a holiday, and you know from past experience with this holiday that this coming
Thursday and Friday will not be busy at all; the lawyers at this firm like to take this
opportunity for an extended weekend. Thus, giving each administrative assistant an extra day
off, one on Thursday and one on Friday, would cause no problems at all in the firm and
would be a nice gesture. But critics of act-utilitarianism argue that in this sort of example a
more detailed analysis is needed. Imagine that Tom enjoys days off, but only moderately, he
might do laundry or catch up on errands, but the happiness he derives from a day off is
limited. Sue, however, derives much more happiness than Tom when she gets a day off, since
she likes to go to the beach, the mountains, or into the city. So if you are the office manager,
do you necessarily give both Tom and Sue one day off apiece?
Case 2
I imagine you are a doctor. At the moment, you are administering a routine physical
examination, and the patient is in excellent health. Your mind, however, is really on more
troubling matters; there are five patients in the critical care wing of the clinic who are
desperately in need of organ transplants. Acceptable donors have not been found, and these
particular patients are now critical; they do not have much time. As you are completing the
physical exam of the healthy patient, it occurs to you that you have a certain choice. It would
be possible for you to administer a shot to this patient that would cause him to fall asleep and
then die painlessly. (You could tell him it is a flu shot or some similar standard precaution).
Because you are very clever, you could concoct an injection that would accomplish this task
37
without anyone being able to discover the true cause of death. The reason for even
considering such an act is that you are an act-utilitarian and you see the possibility of an
overall gain in happiness here. You surmise that it might be possible to take various organs
out of the healthy patient and redistribute them into the five critical patients as needed – a
liver, tow kidneys, a heart, and a lung. Because you want to be sure about the utilitarian
calculations, you quickly do some informal research and learn the following: the patient’s
organ would be excellent matches for the five needy patients (so the likelihood of successful
transplant is very high); the patient has no friends or family to speak of, as he just moved here
from the coast, “to begin with” as he says (so the unhappiness generated by his death would
not be felt by others); each of the five needy patients has children and other family members
and friends (so the unhappiness generated by the death of each would be felt by many
people). Given all of these circumstances, it seems clear that the overall happiness would be
maximized by going ahead and killing the innocent, healthy patient in order to save the lives
of the five others. After all, there would be a net gain of four lives (four saved, one lost), and
consideration of the effects on the happiness of tangential parties (friends and family) adds
38
CHAPTER THREE
This chapter addresses the issue of rights and duties as it pertains to business. Students will
39
Explain Kant’s duty-based approach
Introduction
While rights are often proclaimed, and duties sometimes acknowledged, there is often a lack
of clarity in the discussion of rights and duties once it proceeds beyond proclamation and
Rights
A right should be understood as a “moral claim.” The first part of this definition, the
stipulation that a right is moral, is meant to indicate that it is not necessarily recognized by
any conventional system. A legal right for example, is held by a certain individual or group of
individuals just in case the government decides that the right is held. Whether or not a legal
right is moral is an open question. The second part of the definition indicates that a right is a
claim. The legal scholar Wesley Hohfeld (1919) was the first to use this terminology, and
moral philosophers have followed this practice. A claim, according to Hohfeld (1919), is a
particular type of right, one which is correlative with a duty on the part of the person(s)
against whom the right is held. Thus, my moral right not to be harmed by others is therefore
to be understood as a moral duty on the part of others not to harm me. With respect to work,
an employee’s right to safety in the workplace is held against his/her employer, since the
employer has the duty to provide him/her with a safe work environment; he/she does not hold
this right against members of the general public, since they have no such duty.
Sources of rights
There are four basic sources of rights. Some rights we have as humans, without regard to
position or citizenship, or wealth or skill. Some rights we have by law. Some rights accrue to
40
us by reason of our position. Finally, some rights have their source in contract. Rights from
each of these sources imply duties. Depending on the source of the rights, the corresponding
duty fall upon individuals or groups that might be in daily contact with us, or might be quite
Human Rights
Human rights is a term that is used very loosely. The concept has roots extending back
hundreds of years and is built into American legal system as a foundation. A number of
philosophers have noted that human rights can be grounded in several different theories and
that it is a sign of the strength of the argument for human rights that different approaches lead
Legal rights
These are rights granted to citizens of a government unit by law. They are enforceable
through court systems. Some legal rights embody human rights; others do not. There is both a
legal right and a human right to life, which manifests itself in a duty not to randomly kill
people. Different jurisdictions can and do grant different legal rights, but the hierarchy of
jurisdictions is made clear by legal systems. We may well ask where governments get the
power to grant rights and impose duties. In a democracy, the standard answer is that
governments derive their power from the people. Some individuals are elected by the voting
citizens to represent them (the voters) in deciding what government shall do, and how it shall
do it.
41
Social contract theory is a view in philosophy that explains government power by saying that
it is as if all the citizens yield by contract some of their individual rights in order to obtain the
benefits of social stability available only through a recognized government. The theory
further states that each of us gives up some rights to government and in return gains some
rights that we would not otherwise have. Again, rights are worthless without corresponding
duties. Citizens who have agreed to give up some rights to strengthen others also take on
Position rights
A third source of rights is position. If he has probable cause to do so, a policeman has the
right to stop a motorist, require him to get out of his car, make a physical search of his
person, handcuff him/her and take him/her to jail. These are powerful rights. It is important to
observe some overlap between legal rights and position rights. The policeman has his
authority by law as well as by position, but there is no law authorizing chief financial officer
Positions carry duties as well as rights. Employees have a duty to carry out the
responsibilities of their job. According to the rights and duties approach to ethics, an
individual’s actions will be moral if he recognizes the rights of others and observes the duties
imposed on him by those rights. Everyone has a duty not to randomly kill other people.
Contract rights
The fourth and final source of rights is by contract. Contracts are agreements between two or
more parties. The agreement of both parties to the contract initiates rights and duties spelled
out in the contract, and they will remain in force as long as the contract is valid. Contracts
42
out the terms and conditions of employment for employees who are covered under a
collective bargaining agreement. Such contracts typically oblige managers to pay certain
wages and benefits, provide certain working conditions and refrain from firing employees
except under specified circumstances. Contracts may also affect relations with customers,
Immanuel Kant is the philosopher most often associated with the rights and duties approach
to morality. Kant emphasizes duties rather than rights. He identifies two kinds of rules (he
conditional. If you want to be a good flute player, then you ought to practice every day. The
a) Act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should
b) Act in such a way that you always treat humanity, whether in your own person or in
the person of any other, always at the same time as an end and never as a means
c) Therefore, every rational being must so act as if he were through his maxim always a
Kant gives the example of a man who borrows money, but then has difficulty coming up with
enough to pay it back. The question Kant poses is whether this individual can morally fail or
refuse to repay the borrowed money. He explains that a universal rule that says “repay loans
only if it is convenient” could not work because no one would lend money under such
circumstances. The same sort of analysis would apply to a rule that said “lie when it is
43
convenient or embarrassing to tell the truth.” The categorical imperative imposes duties on
Taking all the different rights into account, it is clear that the universal duty required by the
categorical imperative fits best with human rights because they are not dependent on anything
else to be applicable. One could form a universal rule to obey the tax laws of the countries
where your business is conducted, but this already introduces a certain degree of contingency.
Suppose that I am home at night reading a novel and my next-door neighbour knocks
frantically on my door. When I open the door, she has terror in her eyes and asks me to hide
her because her husband is trying to kill her. I tell her to hurry upstairs and go in the room to
the right. One minute later, her husband pounds on my door. When I open it, he asks me
where his wife is because he wants to kill her. Is the moral answer “upstairs to the right?
Most people would say not. This brings us back to the point made earlier, that no right is
absolute. His right to be told the truth is not made earlier, that no right is absolute. His right to
According to the theory of moral rights, human beings have certain fundamental rights that
should be respected in all decisions: the right to free consent, privacy, freedom of conscience,
free speech, and due process (Cavanagh et al., 1981). A right is a capacity, a possession, or
condition of existence that entitles either an individual or a group to enjoy some object or
state of being. For example, the right to free speech is a condition of existence that entitles
one to express one's thoughts as one chooses (Duska, 2002). Rights theories distinguish
between negative and positive rights. In the case of negative rights, the duty is to allow the
party to act freely within the domain covered by the right. In the case of positive rights, the
44
obligation is to provide the party with a benefit of some type. The moral force of a right
depends on its strength in relation to other moral considerations applicable to the context in
question (Jones et al., 2007). According to rights theory, as long as the distribution of wealth
in society is achieved through fair acquisition and exchange, the distribution is a just one
regardless of any degree of inequalities that may ensue (Budd, 2004). The morally correct
action is the one that a person has the moral right to do, that does not infringe on the moral
rights of others, and that furthers the moral rights of others (Rachels, 1999; Velasques, 1998;
People who rely on rights theory to reason their actions emphasize the entitlement of
individuals (Cavanagh et al., 1981). Restrictions on behavior should prevent harm to others,
but unless your actions harm others, you should be free to do as you please. A manager
making a decision based on this theory should avoid violating the rights of others who may
This theory was propounded by William David Ross who published The Rights and the
Good (1930). In Ross’s theory, he believes there are duties or obligations which bind us
morally. In any moral decision, we must weigh the options with respect to the duties
involved and from the alternatives determine the duty that is most obligatory. To Barry
(1979) an act may fall under a number of rules at once … in such cases, each act is
faithful to a contract, to help someone, to render justice, to be loyal. Each of these moral
duties provides grounds for doing a particular action, but no single one provides sufficient
45
Fisher and Lovell (2006) contend that prima facie evidence is a legal term that refers to
unless or until counter-evidence is discovered. Thus, we can define a prima facie obligation
as one that should be respected in one’s practice, unless and until a different prima facie
obligation, with a superior claim for adherence, is presented. According to Barry (1979), the
term prima facie means “at first sight” or “on the surface”. By prima facie duties, Ross
means ones that at first sight dictates what we should do when other moral factors are not
considered. Stated differently, prima facie duties are ones that generally obligate us, that is,
ones that ordinarily impose a moral obligation but do not apply in a particular case because of
additional circumstances. Thus, prima facie duties must be distinguished from an actual duty,
that is, what one should do after considering and weighting all the prima facie duties
involved.
Ross (1930) and Barry (1979) identified 6 (six) types of prima facie duties which are outlined
as follows:
(1) The first they termed duties of fidelity which include duty not to lie especially in
wrongful acts.
(2) The second category of prima facie duties is/are duties of gratitude and this rest on
acts of other people towards the agents. Ross argues that we are bound by
obligations arising from relationships that exist between persons, such as those
employees.
46
(3) Another category of prima facie duties, are duties of justice which rest on the fact
(4) In addition to the above, the fourth category of prima facie duties are duties of
beneficence which rely on the fact that there are other people in the world whose
instance, the management board of an institution can improve the happiness of its
(5) The fifth category of prima facie duties is/are the duties of self-improvement.
This duty rest on the fact that we can improve our own condition of virtue,
and development, than his present employment. Then on the basis of the duty of
(6) The last category of the prima facie duties is the duty of non-injury (non-
malfeasance), that is, those that do not injure others. Although not injuring others
incidentally means doing them good, Ross interprets the avoidance of injuring
In sum, the six prima facie duties do not represent a complete list of recognizable duties, but
are duties that we accept willingly. In the case of two or more obligatory duties, we take the
one with the greatest amount of rightness over wrongness (Barry, 1979).
47
CHAPTER FOUR
The implications of fairness and justice on business sustainability are enormous. Employees
who perceive injustice may experience low morale and commitment leading to poor
performance. Injustice may also affect the reputation of a business and therefore, managers
are expected to demonstrate justice and fairness in all managerial decisions in order to
maintain stakeholder worth. Students will be expected at the end of this chapter to:
48
Analyse a business case from the point of view of justice/fairness
Introduction
Philosophers and social commentators were writing about justice long before management
scientists were. Among the ancient Greeks, for example, Herodotus' History and Plutarch's
Lives described the achievements of the lawgiver Solon, who reformed Athenian
government. These are the prescriptive approaches, since they seek to logically determine
what sorts of actions truly are just. As such, they reside comfortably within the domain of
business ethics. While organizational justice borrows from these older traditions, it has its
own distinctions. Unlike the work of philosophers and attorneys, managerial scientists are
less concerned with what is just and more concerned with what people believe to be just. In
other words, these researchers are pursuing a descriptive agenda. They seek to understand
why people view certain events as just, as well as the consequences that follow from these
evaluations. In this regard, justice is a subjective and descriptive concept in that it captures
what individuals believe to be right, rather than an objective reality or a prescriptive moral
code. As defined here, organizational justice is a personal evaluation about the ethical and
moral standing of managerial conduct. It follows from this approach that producing justice
requires management to take the perspective of an employee. That is, they need to understand
what sorts of events engender this subjective feeling of organizational justice. On this
Fairness and justice is an approach to ethical reasoning that includes several somewhat
different concepts under one umbrella. This approach defines the moral act as the act that
treats similarly situated people with similar ways with regards to both process and outcomes,
and with a sense of proportionality. Most of us were born in organizations (hospitals), learned
49
organizations and, when we die, will very probably be buried or cremated by an organization.
In all of these contacts between individuals and organizations, there is some sort of exchange.
We exchange labour for wages and pension benefits. We exchange taxes for protection and
other governmental services. We exchange money for goods and services. Our interactions
with organizations and the people who constitute them are basically unceasing. In all these
interactions, we have expectations both for what we will give and for what we will get. When
these expectations are not met, we are disappointed, or angry, or sad. Our lives are affected,
on a daily basis, by the terms of exchanges. One of our most basic expectations in the wide
variety of exchanges that make up our daily lives is that we will be treated fairly.
The principle of justice is another form of deontological ethics which has been used
synonymously with ‘fair play’. The principle of justice could be understood as the obligation
to give each party its due (Reeck, 1979). The maximum principle of justice was propounded
by John Rawls in his Theory of Justice (1971). Rawls (1971) has provided a relatively
modern statement on what is essentially deontological thinking, and his work has had
considerable impact on modern moral philosophy. To Barry (1979) central to Rawls’ theory
is the question of establishing principles of justice, what principles will serve as the basis for
state of nature in which everybody is ignorant of their talents and socioeconomic conditions.
He calls this the “original position”, in this position, people share certain characteristics. The
people are mutually self-interested; rational, that is, they more or less accurately know their
interests; needs and capacities. Given these assumptions Rawls then asks what people in the
original position would be likely to formulate when asked to choose a fundamental principle
of justice to be followed. Two principles would be chosen according to him and these are;
benefits because they would recognize that some of them would put forth greater efforts,
have greater skills, develop greater competences and so on. They would not agree to absolute
inequality based on effort, skill or competence because they would not know who among
them had those qualities and consequently who among them would receive the greater and
the lesser benefits. Instead, they would develop a concept of conditional inequality, where
differences in benefits had to be justified, and then propose a rule that those differences in
benefits could be justified only if they could be shown to result in compensating benefits for
everyone, and in particular for the least advantaged members of their society (Hosmer, 1987).
By the liberty principle Rawls means to say that people in the original position would expect
each person participating in a practice or affected by it to have an equal right to the greatest
amount of liberty that is compatible with a like liberty for all. And by the difference principle
Rawls means that people in the original position would allow inequality only insofar as it
serves each person’s advantage and arises under conditions of equal opportunity (Barry,
1979). Equality simply means all persons should be treated equally or the same. To Rawls
(1971), equality means the impartial and inequitable administration and application of rules
To Barry (1979) crucial to any theory of social justice is the determination of when inequality
is permissible. After all, a just society is not one in which all are equal, but one in which
inequalities are justifiable. Rawls addresses this problem with his difference principle; the
difference principle defines what kinds of inequalities are permissible. It specifies under
what conditions the equal liberty principle may be violated. For Rawls, equality is not
contingent. It does not depend on something else, such as on the greatest happiness for the
most people, for its justification. Equality is fundamental and self-justifying. Inequality is
51
permissible only if in all likelihood the practice involving the inequality works to the
Closely related to the concept of justice is reciprocity. Reciprocity to Rawls (1971) is the
principle that requires that a practice be such that all members who fall under it could and
would accept it and be bound by it. It requires the possibility for mutual acknowledgement of
principles by free people, having no authority over one another that make the idea of
The theory of justice requires decision makers to be guided by equity, fairness, and
(a) That individuals who are similar in a relevant respect should be treated similarly and
individuals who are different in a relevant respect should be treated differently in proportion
(c) That individuals should not be held responsible for matters over which they have no
control, and should be compensated for the cost of their injuries by those responsible for
Decision making and reasoning based on the theory of justice therefore focus on the
Definition of Fairness
One of the most complete sentences spoken by many children (particularly if they have
siblings) is “That’s not fair!” A central issue in considerations of justice is the issue of what
we mean by being fair. Is it fair to provide equal opportunity to all, even if the outcomes are
unequal? Is it fair to distribute some resources (welfare benefits, charitable donations) based
52
on need and other resources (high salaries, prestigious positions) based on merit? Is it fair to
give preference to an individual now because she is a member of a group that was denied
The individual manager’s decision is constrained by the system involved. The kinds of
systems under discussion are not information technology systems but such things as standard
hiring procedures, compensation systems such as salary ranges and guidelines for increases
or stock option awards, and company-wide directives for the conduct of layoffs. These
various systems can be seen as rules for procedural fairness, whereas individual decisions by
Equity theory
Perhaps the earliest theory of distributive justice can be attributed to Aristotle. In his
Nicomachean Ethics, the philosopher maintained that just distribution involved "something
rearrangement, led Adams (1965) to represent his influential equity theory of distributive
justice with the following equation? According to equity theory, we are interested in how
much we get (outcomes) relative to how much we contribute (inputs). Such a ratio is
examine the outcomes and inputs of some referent. Usually, though not necessarily, this is
another person who is similar to us. Things are "equitable" when the ratios, not the individual
terms, are in agreement. When the ratios are out of alignment, employees may feel uneasy.
They are motivated to "balance" the equation by modifying the terms. For example, one who
is underpaid might reduce inputs by a corresponding amount. This simple equation leads to a
number of predictions, some of which are not obvious. For example, an individual who earns
less than another may still be satisfied, as long as he or she also contributes less. Likewise, a
53
person who is paid equally to another may feel unjustly treated if he or she also contributes
substantially more to the organization. These consequences often do not occur to managers,
but they make good sense in light of equity theory. But by far the most famous prediction
from equity theory is the "over-reward effect"? That is, what happens when the equation is
According to equity theory, when one is over paid the two sides of the ratios are misaligned.
Consequently, one must work harder (i.e., increase inputs) in order to be equitable. These
effects seem to occur. Greenberg (1988) studied managers who were temporarily moved to
higher or lower-status offices than their position actually warranted. Those moved to higher-
status offices boosted performance, whereas those moved to lower-status offices showed
decrements. These gains and losses later disappeared when individuals were returned to
status-appropriate office spaces. Apart from its impact on performance, inequity can also
cause workplace sabotage (Ambrose, Seabright, & Schminke, 2002) and employee theft
associated with stress symptoms (Cropanzano, Goldman, & Benson, 2005). Recent advances
in distributive justice. There is more to distributive justice than simple equity. These different
standards can be in conflict with one another. Generally speaking, we can distinguish three
allocation rules that can lead to distributive justice if they are applied appropriately: equality
(to each the same), equity (to each in accordance with contributions), and need (to each in
accordance with the most urgency). These rules map onto Aristotle's famous dictum that
all men wish to be treated like all other people (equality), like some other people
(equity), and like no other person (need). While it is no mean task to find the correct
alchemistic combination among these three allocation rules, there are three basic suggestions
54
First, it is useful to consider one's strategic goals (Colquitt, Greenberg, & Zapata-Phelan,
2005). Equity tends to provide individual rewards for high performance, whereas equality
tends to build esprit de corps among teammates. If one desires to stimulate individual
motivation, err toward equity. If one desires to build group cohesion, err toward equality. We
Second, organizations can balance these considerations by mixing equality and equity
together. It need not be either-or. Experiments with work groups suggest that it is often best
to provide team members with a basic minimum of benefit. This is analogous to equality.
Above that minimum, however, it can be useful to reward based on performance. This is
analogous to equity. This sort of hybrid approach has been adopted by many organizations.
Their compensation systems contain a "fixed" base; everyone in a particular job class and
with a particular tenure receives this base. Employees are also encouraged to go beyond this
minimum, earning additional pay through the allocation of merit bonuses (Milkovich &
Newman, 2005). Third, different rewards should be provided in accordance with different
rules. Equity works well for some things, such as money, but less well for others, such as
status symbols. Among American managers, it is often seen as fair to allocate economic
benefits in accordance with equity (i.e., those who perform better might earn more). On the
other hand, social-emotional benefits, such as reserved parking places, are best allocated
equally (Martin & Harder, 1994). Employees often see themselves and their peers as
belonging to a group or, in the most beneficial case, a community. Allocating social-
emotional rewards equally signals that everyone in the organization matters and is worthy of
respect.
55
Research has shown that employees appraisee three families of workplace events. They
examine the justice of outcomes (distributive justice), the justice of the formal allocation
processes (procedural justice), and the justice of interpersonal transactions they encounter
with others (interactional justice). They can be meaningfully treated as three components of
overall fairness (Ambrose & Arnaud, 2005; Ambrose & Schminke, 2007), and the three
components can work together. However, if one's goal is to promote workplace justice, it is
useful to consider them separately and in detail. This is because each component is
Distributive Justice
Researchers call the first component of justice distributive justice because it has to do with
the allocations or outcomes that some get and others do not. Distributive justice is concerned
with the reality that not all workers are treated alike; the allocation of outcomes is
differentiated in the workplace. Individuals are concerned with whether or not they received
their "just share." Sometimes things are distributively just, as when the most qualified person
gets promoted. Other times they are not, as when advancement goes to corporate "insiders"
Procedural Justice
Procedural justice is intended to achieve distributive justice. In other words, the ultimate
concern when using fairness and justice as an approach to ethics is with results – how do
resources end up being distributed, and is this distribution fair and just? Procedural justice is
instrumental, in that it is concerned with achieving some result. Procedural justice serves two
important purposes: it makes it more likely distribution of resources will occur and it
encourages the perception that results are fair because procedures were fair.
56
Obviously not all procedural systems will be equally fair, and some may be patently unfair. A
system that grants options for large amounts of stock to a few senior managers and none to
anyone else is at least open to a charge of unfairness. A system that grants a greater chance
unfairness on the part of applicants and their parents who are not alumni. Many procedural
systems are designed to assure compliance with laws and regulations, particularly in areas
relating to human resources. While it is certainly important to comply with the law, both in
the design of procedural systems and in their application, doing so does not necessarily
Procedural justice refers to the means by which outcomes are allocated, but not specifically to
the outcomes themselves. Procedural justice establishes certain principles specifying and
governing the roles of participants within the decision-making processes. In three papers,
Leventhal and his colleagues (Leventhal, 1976, 1980; Leventhal, Karuza, & Fry, 1980)
established some core attributes that make procedures just: (a) A just process is one that is
correctable, and consistent with ethical norms. Though surprising to some, research has
shown that just procedures can mitigate the ill effects of unfavourable outcomes. Researchers
have named this the "fair process effect." To illustrate let us consider the case of strategic
planning. Kim and Mauborgne (1991, 1993) reported that when managers believed that their
headquarters used a fair planning process, they were more supportive of the plan, trusted their
leaders more, and were more committed to their employers. In their well-known book, Blue
Ocean Strategy, Kim and Mauborgne (2005) explain why. Fair processes lead to intellectual
and emotional recognition. This, in turn, creates the trust and commitment that build
57
Procedural injustice, on the other hand, produces "intellectual and emotional indignation,"
resulting in "distrust and resentment" (p. 183). Ultimately, this reduces cooperation in
institutional legitimacy. When personnel decisions are made, individuals are likely to receive
certain outcomes. For instance, one may or may not be promoted. According to Tyler and
Blader (2000), outcome favourability tends to affect satisfaction with the particular decision.
This is not surprising. What is more interesting is that procedural justice affects what workers
believe about the organization as a whole. If the process is perceived as just, employees show
greater loyalty and more willingness to behave in an organization's best interests. They are
Interactional Justice
In a sense, interactional justice may be the simplest of the three components. It refers to how
one person treats another. A person is interactionally just if he or she appropriately shares
information and avoids rude or cruel remarks. In other words, there are two aspects of
interactional justice (Colquitt, Conlon, Wesson, Porter, &Ng, 2001). The first part, sometimes
called informational justice refers to whether one is truthful and provides adequate
justifications when things go badly. The second part, sometimes called interpersonal justice,
refers to the respect and dignity with which one treats another. As shown in Table 1, both are
important. Because interactional justice emphasizes one on-one transactions, employees often
seek it from their supervisors. This presents an opportunity for organizations. In a quasi-
experimental study, Skarlicki and Latham (1996) trained union leaders to behave more justly.
Among other things, these leaders were taught to provide explanations and apologies
(informational justice) and to treat their reports with courtesy and respect (interpersonal
58
justice). When work groups were examined three months later, individuals who reported to
trained leaders exhibited more helpful citizenship behaviors than individuals who reported to
untrained leaders.
Any procedural system is general and individual distributions of resources are specific. The
ethical sensitivity, or lack thereof, of the individual manager making an individual decision is
important to the ultimate attainment of distributive justice. In order for a manager to make
decisions that are ethical according to the perspective of fairness and justice, she must be able
to determine who are similarly situated individuals and what constitutes similar treatment.
Managers too often assume that justice, in the minds of employees, means only that they
receive desirable outcomes. These managers are confusing outcome favorability with
outcome justice. The former is a judgment of personal worth or value; the latter is a judgment
of moral propriety. Evidence shows that outcome justice and outcome favorability are distinct
(Skitka, Winquist, & Hutchinson, 2003) and correlated between .19 and .49, depending on
where and how the variables are measured (Cohen-Charash & Spector, 2001). In so many
words, it's important to get what you want, but other things matter as well. For this reason it
is useful to consider three reasons justice matters to people (for details, see Cropanzano,
Long-range benefits: People often "sign on" for the long haul. Consequently, they need to
estimate now how they are likely to be treated overtime. A just organization makes this
prediction easy. According to the "control model," employees prefer justice because it allows
59
them to predict and control the outcomes they are likely to receive from organizations.
According to the control model of justice, appropriate personnel policies signal that things are
likely to work out eventually. Most of us understand that every personnel decision cannot go
our way, but justice provides us with more certainty regarding our future benefits. For this
reason the control model proposes that people are often motivated by economic and quasi-
economic interests (cf. Tyler & Smith, 1998). People want fairness because fairness provides
things they like. There is more than a little truth to this idea. For instance, when individuals
are rewarded for successfully completing a task they report being happy (Weiss, Suckow, &
Cropanzano, 1999) and having pride in their performance (Krehbiel & Cropanzano, 2000).
This is so even when their success resulted from cheating. At the same time, these individuals
also report feeling guilty for their unfair behavior, suggesting that individuals can recognize
and react to injustice, even when it is personally beneficial. There is sometimes a certain
tension between getting what we want and playing by the rules. The two tend to go together,
but less so than many believe. For example, pay satisfaction is only modestly correlated with
perceptions of pay justice (Williams, McDaniel, & Nguyen, 2006). If "justice" were based
exclusively on obtaining benefits, then one would expect a higher association. Later we shall
discuss evidence suggesting that individuals can accept an unfortunate outcome as long as the
process is fair and they are treated with interpersonal dignity (e.g., Goldman, 2003; Skarlicki
Social considerations: People are social animals. We wish to be accepted and valued by
important others while not being exploited or harmed by powerful decision-makers. In the
"group-value model," just treatment tells us that we are respected and esteemed by the larger
group. We are also at less risk for mistreatment. This sense of belonging is important to us
even apart from the economic benefits it can bring (Tyler & Blader, 2000; Tyler & Smith,
1998). As you might expect, this can pose a potential problem for organizations. To the
60
extent that justice signals our value to an employer, the more we care about the organization
the more distressed we become when we are treated unfairly. Brockner, Tyler, and Cooper-
Schneider (1992) assessed the commitment of a group of employees before a layoff occurred.
After the downsizing those people who were initially the most committed responded the most
negatively to the downsizing. When we treat workers unfairly, we may end up doing the most
Ethical considerations: People also care about justice because they believe it is the morally
appropriate way others should be treated (Folger, 2001). When individuals witness an event
they believe is ethically inappropriate, they are likely to take considerable risks in the hopes
of extracting retribution (Bies & Tripp, 2001, 2002). Such unfortunate (from the
organization's point of view) reactions may occur even when an employee simply witnesses
the harm and is not personally wronged (Ellard & Skarlicki, 2002; Spencer & Rupp, 2006).
Consider, for example, a day-to-day problem faced by many service workers. When these
employees see a customer treating one of their coworkers unfairly, the observing worker is
apt to experience stress symptoms. Through this mechanism, injustice may spread ill will
throughout a workgroup.
More broadly, we suggest that justice can be a core value that defines an organization's
identity with its stakeholders, both internally and externally. When justice is espoused as a
commitment that is valuable and unique in the eyes of employees and customers, and tough
to copy in the minds of competitors. And that can translate into the makings of sustainable
competitive advantage. In our next section, we will look at management practices that can
61
help develop a culture of justice. How to Create Perceptions of Justice We will now turn to
personnel functions provide a lesson for promoting justice, including some normative
recommendations regarding how individuals should be treated. And in each case we will
return to one or more of our conceptual observations, such as the fair process effect and the
For most job candidates, the recruiting and selection process is their first introduction to an
organization. How they are treated at this time can have ramifications later. Applicants who
feel justly treated are more likely to form positive impressions of the organization (Bauer et
al., 2001) and recommend it to their friends (Smither, Reilly, Millsap, Pearlman, & Stoffey,
1993). And the flip side is also true. When applicants feel unjustly treated they are more
likely to consider litigation as a potential remedy (Bauer et al., 2001). This research suggests
that it pays for organizations to put their best foot forward. By treating applicants justly in the
hiring process, organizations are setting the foundation for a relationship of justice and trust
when those applicants become employees. The research on job candidates' reactions to
recruiting and hiring processes suggests that it is about much more than whether or not
someone gets the job. Further, because applicants don't often know why they didn't get the
job or the qualifications of the person who did, distributive justice is less of a concern in
is also important to realize that the selection process begins with recruiting and initial
communication, and encompasses all contact with job candidates up to and including
extending an offer and rejecting an individual for a job (Gilliland & Hale, 2005). In terms of
procedural justice, research has identified two broad sets of concerns: Appropriate questions
62
and criteria are critical for procedural justice. Job candidates expect interview questions and
screening tests to be related to the job, or at least to appear to be related to the job (Gilliland,
1994; Ryan & Chan, 1999). Overly personal interview questions and some screening tests,
such as honesty tests, are often seen as inappropriate and an invasion of candidates' privacy
(Bies & Moag, 1986; Kravitz, Stinson, & Chavez, 1996). Adequate opportunity to perform
during the selection process means giving job candidates the chances to make a case for
themselves and allowing sufficient time in interviews (Truxillo, Bauer, & Sanchez, 2001). If
standardized tests are used to screen applicants, justice can be enhanced by allowing
candidates to retest if they feel they did not perform their best (Truxillo et al, 2001). On the
face, these two criteria seem reasonable and pretty straightforward. However, when compared
with recommended hiring practices, managers are often faced with a "justice paradox"
(Folger & Cropanzano, 1998). That is, many of the selection procedures with the highest
predictive validity? Those that are the best screening tools? Are unfortunately those that fail
to satisfy these justice concerns? Consider cognitive ability and personality tests. These
screening methods have high demonstrated validity (Schmidt & Hunter, 1998), but both are
seen by job applicants as not particularly fair (Steiner & Gilliland, 1996). Questions on these
tests are often not related to the job, and applicants don't feel they have an opportunity to
present their true abilities. The converse is also observed with the justice paradox. Traditional
unstructured interviews have long demonstrated weak predictive validity, not much better
than chance (Huffcutt & Arthur, 1994). However, job applicants perceive these interviews as
having high procedural justice because they are able to demonstrate their qualifications
(Latham & Finnegan, 1993). Adding structured situations and questions to the interview
increases predictive validity, but decreases perceptions of procedural justice. So how can this
justice paradox be managed effectively? We have three suggestions. First, there are some
screening tools that have both predictive validity and procedural justice. Work sample tests
63
and performance-based simulations demonstrate reasonable predictive validity (Roth, Bobko,
& McFarland, 2005) and are also seen as procedurally just (Steiner & Gilliland, 1996). A
second solution is to modify existing screening tools to increase job applicants' perceived
procedural justice. Smither and colleagues (1993) found that cognitive ability tests with
concrete, rather than abstract, items tended to be viewed more positively by job applicants.
Based on the observation that applicants perceive greater justice in unstructured interviews,
Gilliland and Steiner (1999) suggest a combined interview that has both structured behavioral
questions to maximize predictive validity and unstructured questions to allow applicants the
"opportunity to perform."
The third suggestion is based on our earlier discussion of interactional justice. Recall that
interactional justice can attenuate the negative effects of procedural injustice. Research has
demonstrated that interactional justice is very important for job candidates (Bies & Moag,
information, and timely feedback, organizations can create hiring processes that embody
interactional justice. Research has demonstrated that the informational components are
At the most basic level, rewards systems need to accomplish two goals: They need to
motivate individual performance, and they need to maintain group cohesion. While both
goals are worthwhile, distributive justice research tells us that it is difficult to accomplish
them simultaneously. Equity allocations, which reward for performance, can spur individual
effort. But the resulting inequality that is likely to occur can be disruptive. In a study of
academic faculty, Pfeffer and Langton (1993) examined wage dispersion in their home
64
departments. When wage dispersion was high, faculty reported less satisfaction and less
collaboration with colleagues. Overall research productivity dropped as well. This is not what
merit pay is supposed to do. Paying everyone the same thing, though, is not the answer either.
Indeed, equality distributions can boost group harmony, but they bring troubles of their own.
A key problem is one of external equity. High-performing employees, or those with rare
skills, may be worth more in the external marketplace. If their salaries are "capped" to
maintain internal equality, these workers may seek employment elsewhere. This is just
another way of saying that no matter how people are paid, not everyone will be satisfied.
How then to position rewards? The research discussed earlier underscores an opportunity. To
be sure, individuals who do not receive the compensation they desire will want more.
However, they often remain loyal to their employer if the pay administration procedures are
so and risk internal inequality, but only as long as the allocation process is just. To illustrate,
McFarlin and Sweeney (1992) surveyed more than 600 banking employees. As expected,
when distributive justice was low, workers reported less pay satisfaction and less job
satisfaction. This is bad news, but it is partially compensated for by the procedural justice
results.
When procedural justice was high, workers experienced higher organizational commitment
and a positive reaction to their supervisors. This is the two-factor model in action. Individuals
who were not necessarily satisfied with their pay were still unlikely to derogate the
organization when the procedures were just. In addition to procedural justice, interactional
justice can be helpful in administering pay fairly. To illustrate this point, let us consider a
situation that everyone dislikes: pay cuts. Greenberg (1993) found that differences in how pay
cuts were managed at two manufacturing plants produced dramatically different outcomes.
The key is interpersonal treatment. In one, an executive politely, but quickly in about 15
65
minutes, announced a 15% pay cut. In the other, an executive spent about an hour and a half
speaking, taking questions, and expressing regrets about making an identical pay cut. During
a subsequent 10-week period, employee theft was about 80% lower in the second case, and
employees in that plant were 15 times less likely to resign. No one wanted to have his or her
pay cut. But workers understood why it happened, appreciated the supportive interpersonal
Thomas and Schmidt (1976) tell us that managers may spend about 20% of their time settling
disputes among employees, and they are not always successful (Schoorman & Champagne,
1994). Conflict resolution is likely to be most difficult when one or both parties are
intransigent. At this point the manager may listen to both disputants, but will need to impose
arbitration may sound risky because it hazards a distributive injustice; the settlement is
imposed and not approved in advance by other parties. There is good news, however. If any
the overall appraisal of the situation will be improved (Goldman, 2003). Because arbitration
preserves procedural justice, an unfortunate outcome is less destructive than one might
imagine. Or, we might say, managers can make hard choices, but they have to make them
justly (for details see Folger & Cropanzano, 1998). This illustrates a simple yet powerful
lesson from research on conflict resolution: If you can't give people the outcome they want, at
least give them a fair process. Layoffs: Softening Hardship So far we have reviewed evidence
pertaining to justice in the context of hiring, reward systems, and conflict resolution. These
are everyday events in a large organization, and each will function more effectively if justice
66
is taken into account. Even a reader willing to indulge our arguments so far might be
Among common management situations that affect employees, downsizing is among the
worst (Richman, 1993). Layoffs have pernicious effects, harming the victims while
undermining the morale of survivors who remain employed. Though downsizing is a widely
used cost-cutting strategy, it is highly risky. The costs of workforce reductions often
outweigh the benefits (Kammeyer-Mueller, Liao, & Arvey, 2001). In these circumstances
people not only lose, they lose big. The event can be so negative that a sense of distributive
injustice is virtually a given. Can the guidelines suggested in this paper do any good at all?
As a matter of fact, they can. When a layoff is handled with procedural and interactional
justice, victims are less likely to derogate their former employers (Brockner et al., 1994,
Study 1). Indeed, justice can have direct bottom-line effects. Lind, Greenberg, Scott, and
Welchans (2000) interviewed a large number of layoff victims. Many of these individuals
considered legal action following their downsizing, and almost a quarter of the victims went
so far as to speak to an attorney. The single best predictor of willingness to take legal action
was the justice of the treatment they received at the time of their discharge. Among those
who felt unjustly treated, Lind and his colleagues found that a full 66% contemplated
litigation. Among those who felt justly treated, this dropped to just 16%. These are
impressive findings.
apologizing, an apology can be seen as an admission of guilt? These results suggest that an
apology may help promote the feelings of interactional justice that actually reduce the risk of
litigation. Justice, it would seem, provides a useful way to survive a crisis with one's business
reputation intact. While we have so far discussed the victims of layoffs, workforce reductions
also affect survivors. Those left behind, though retaining their jobs, tend to suffer from
67
"survivor guilt" (Brockner & Greenberg, 1990). However, if organizations provide a good
remaining employees respond much less negatively (Brockner, De Witt, Grover, & Reed,
1990).
these benefits are lacking, an advance warning that a layoff is about to occur will blunt the
negative reactions that might otherwise transpire (Brockner et al., 1994, Studies 2 and 3).
Performance Appraisals: Keeping Score Fairly In order to assign rewards, identify candidates
for promotion, and develop human capital, most large organizations conduct performance
evaluations. While these appraisals are useful, concerns remain, and their implementation is
often troubled. For example, scholars have observed a phenomenon called the "vanishing
performance appraisal" (for a review, see Folger & Cropanzano, 1998). When surveyed, most
managers reported having provided performance reviews, while many of their subordinates
reported never receiving one. Other research suggests that evaluations are affected by
political considerations (Longenecker, Gioia, & Sims, 1987), cognitive processing limitations
of the rater (DeNisi & Williams, 1988), and the social context in which they are conducted
(Levy & Williams, 2004). These concerns tell us that the performance appraisal process often
contains a good deal of ambiguity as well as room for reasonable people to disagree. For this
think of the performance review as a sort of test, whereby the central task is to assign a valid
rating to a more-or-less objective quantity. For example, raters have been advised to "become
expert at applying principles of test development" (Banks & Roberson, 1985, p. 129) and that
"psychometric issues surrounding performance measurement [are] more relevant than ever"
68
understanding of performance appraisal has been termed the "test metaphor" (Folger,
More recent performance appraisal work has taken a broader perspective, emphasizing the
social setting (Levy & Williams, 2004) and input from multiple sources (Smither, London, &
Reilly, 2005). In this vein, Cawley, Keeping, and Levy (1998) meta-analyzed 27 field studies,
each of which examined employee participation in performance appraisal. They found that
when employees had a voice they were more satisfied, saw the process as more fair, and were
more motivated to do better. This is interesting, but probably not terribly surprising. The
really impressive finding was that these effects occurred even when participation could not
affect the rating. Simply being able to speak one's mind (what Cawley and coauthors termed
performance appraisal system. Notice how these findings are consistent with the fair process
performance review. Consistent with Folger, Konovsky, and Cropanzano (1992), we call this
the due process approach to performance appraisal. Adopting a due process metaphor
sensitizes one to the distinct interpretations, potential conflicts of interest, and legitimate
disagreement about facts. The due process approach to performance review has three core
elements: adequate notice, just hearing, and judgment based on evidence. Adequate notice, as
one might expect, involves letting people know in advance when they will be appraised and
on what criteria they will be appraised. However, from a justice point of view, it goes beyond
this. It is also useful to have workers involved in devising performance standards and making
these widely available. Of course, it follows that feedback should be provided regularly. Just
hearing means limiting the feedback review to "admissible" evidence, such as worker
performance rather than personal attacks. It also means providing workers with a chance to
69
provide their own interpretation of events, including disagreeing with the supervisor where
this is appropriate.
Judgment based on evidence means that the standards should be accurate, data should be
gathered, and decisions should be based on this formal process. Steps should be taken to
provide rater training, so as to improve accuracy and to keep the process free of political
influence. Taylor, Tracy, Renard, Harrison, and Carroll (1995) redesigned the performance
appraisal system of a large state agency so that it included these principles of due process.
They discovered that workers preferred the new system, finding it fairer and more effective.
Managers liked it as well, believing that it allowed them to be honest and feeling that it was
more effective for solving work problems. This occurred even though workers in the due
process system received lower ratings than did workers under the older approach. This is all
Adequate notice, just hearing, and judgment based on evidence are complicated to
administer. A key problem is that they may raise expectations while simultaneously
providing employees with a set of tools for making their discontent felt. Consider the case of
two companies studied over six years by Mesch and Dalton (1992). Each firm was in the
same region, and workers in each were represented by the same union. In fact, grievances at
both organizations were assigned to the same union local. After 36 months, one of the firms
decided to improve its grievance process by adding a fact-finding intervention. Before the
grievance process began, both the union and management provided a "fact finder" to
determine the merits of the case, prevent concealment of information, and encourage
negotiated settlements. This provided an additional stage of process protection. The result?
The number of grievances filed skyrocketed at the firm with the new procedural safeguard,
but stayed roughly constant at the other organization. After about two years, the fact-finding
intervention was abandoned, and the grievance rate returned to normal. The new intervention
70
seems to have raised expectations and thereby encouraged workers to complain about real
and imagined ill-treatment. In the long run this was counterproductive. The implications of
Mesch and Dalton's (1992) study need to be appreciated. If procedures are not designed
Concluding Thoughts
There are two sides to the justice coin. On the negative side, the absence of justice is likely to
provide problems for organizations. There is strong evidence that injustice can provoke
retaliation, lower performance, and harm morale (Cohen-Charash & Spector, 2001; Colquitt
et al., 2001; Viswesvaran & Ones, 2002). On the positive side, justice can do more than
forestall these unfortunate outcomes. Justice acts as a sort of buffer, allowing employees to
maintain respect and trust for an organization even when things do not go as they would have
liked (Brockner & Wiesenfeld, 1996). It is inevitable in life that things will not always go our
way. However, the negative effects of an unfortunate event are less severe if an organization
is able to maintain procedural and interactional justice (Goldman, 2003; Skarlicki & Folger,
1997). Justice provides an excellent business opportunity, from reaping specific returns such
resides in a "culture of justice." In this paper we have examined justice from the perspective
of five managerial tasks: hiring, reward systems, conflict management, layoffs, and
performance appraisals. These tasks are diverse, but they all involve a degree of risk. Each
has the potential to designate some as "winners" and others as "losers." After all, there will
always be people who fail to get the job, receive a lower than expected performance
hazard the ill will of employees simply because they are making the sorts of decisions
necessary to run their businesses. Organizational justice allows managers to make these tough
71
decisions more smoothly. Just play certainly does not guarantee all parties what they want.
However, it does hold out the possibility that power will be used in accordance with
normative principles that respect the dignity of all involved. This is sound business advice. It
CHAPTER FIVE
This chapter treats three critical and important ethical issues which have attracted attention
globally. Specifically, this broad chapter will be divided into three specific chapters: whistle
blowing, conflict of interest and corruption. At the end of this chapter, students will be
expected to:
72
Discuss causes of corruption
WHISTLE-BLOWING
Introduction
developed a negative attitude towards whistle blowing as a result of the dangers associated
with the act of whistle blowing especially to the whistle blower. This section addresses
critical issues on the concept of whistle blowing and its relevance in organizations.
Whistle-blowing Defined
The term whistle-blowing is derived from the act of a referee in a sport event where the
referee blows the whistle to stop the action, usually on account of an illegal play (Miceli &
Near, 1992). The official name for whistle-blowing is ‘making a disclosure in the public
interest”, however it is much more commonly called ‘blowing the whistle’ or ‘whistle-
73
blowing’. It means that if you believe there is wrongdoing in your workplace (eg your
employer is committing a criminal offence) you can report this by following the correct
allegations from somebody from inside the company as opposed to allegations of a wrong-
doing by someone from outside the company. Near and Miceli, (1985) define whistle-
practices under the control of their employers, to a person or organisations that may be
Boatright (2000) has also defined whistle-blowing as the voluntary release of non-public
components:
2) The information is transmitted to people outside the organisation who make it public
company; and
4) The individual exposing the organisation is not a journalist or ordinary citizen, but an
74
Whistle-blowing has been recognized as a control mechanism to prevent unethical behavior,
and to protect the organization’s long-term welfare, and to ensure good corporate governance
(Eaton and Akers, 2007). In recent years, scholars’ interest in whistle-blowing within
business and public organizations has been heightened by widely publicized cases (e.g.
Enron, WorldCom, Tyco, Global Crossing, Adelphia, and even the International
Olympic Committee to name just a few of the most prominent (Calvert, 2002) and by
Sarbanes-Oxley Act of the USA, Public Interest Disclosure Act of the UK (Eaton and
Perhaps the most infamous case is that of Enron. Sadly, Enron was regarded as one of the
most promising companies in USA before its collapse. It was even rated the most innovative
large company in America from 1996 to 2001 (Lainson, 2001). As of December 31, 2000,
Enron’s stock was priced at $83.13, and its market capitalization exceeded $60 billion, 70
times earnings and six times book value, an indication of the stock market’s high
expectations about its future prospects. Yet within a year, Enron’s image was in tatters and its
stock price had plummeted nearly to zero (Healy and Palepu, 2003). The recent convictions
of Kenneth Lay and Jeffery Skilling finally brought this sad chapter of business history to a
When Time magazine editors named WorldCom's Cynthia Cooper and Enron's Sherron
Watkins two of their People of the Year for 2002, they were acknowledging the importance
the attention of superiors. At WorldCom, Cooper pushed forward with an internal audit,
75
alerting the Board of Directors Auditing Committee to problems, despite being asked by the
company's CFO to postpone her investigation. According to Fortune magazine, "If Cooper
had been a good soldier, the whole incredible mess might have been concealed forever." At
Enron, accountant Sherron Watkins outlined the company's problems in a memo to then-CEO
Kenneth Lay.
But by the time Watkins and Cooper blew the whistle, much damage had already been done,
and the shareholders and employees were the ultimate losers. So the question is, How does an
organization create a culture that encourages employees to ask questions early-to point out
issues and show courage in confronting unethical or illegal practices? And then how can a
company ensure that timely action is taken? In other words, how does an organization
These questions must be answered in the context of conflicting cultural norms, which make it
likely that whistleblowers will encounter hostility and alienation. As Terance Miethe explains
in his book, Whistle-blowing at Work, many people see the whistleblower as a "snitch," or
"a lowlife who betrays a sacred trust largely for personal gain."
This attitude was illustrated by an arbitrator in a 1972 case, who told the employee that you
cannot "bite the hand that feeds you and insist on staying on for the banquet." Among
others, Peter Drucker, the famed management guru and anti-whistleblower, viewed whistle-
blowing as "informing," illustrating yet another instance of the animus whistleblowers have
On the flip side, whistleblowers such as Frank Serpico and Karen Silkwood are seen as
76
"saviours" who ultimately helped create important changes in organizations. This
advocates such as Ralph Nader. Given this dichotomy, whistleblowers may well encounter
difficulties when they appeal internally or go public with information that may damage their
companies.
Brief History
Attitudes toward whistle-blowing have evolved considerably during the past 50 years in
corporate America, from the early days of the "organization man" ethos where loyalty to the
company was the ruling norm, to the present time when public outrage about corporate
Prior to the 1960s, corporations had broad autonomy in employee policies and could fire an
employee at will, even for no reason. Employees were expected to be loyal to their
organizations at all costs. Among the few exceptions to this rule were unionized employees,
who could only be fired for "just cause," and government employees because the courts
upheld their constitutional right to criticize agency policies. In private industry, few real
mechanisms for airing grievances existed although, for example, IBM claimed from its
earliest days, to have an effective open-door policy that allowed employees to raise any issue.
In part because of this lack of protection for whistleblowers, problems were often concealed
rather than solved. Probably the most egregious example was in asbestos manufacturing,
where the link to lung disease was clearly established as early as 1924 but actively
77
suppressed by company officials. The first product liability lawsuit against an asbestos
The 1970s were notable for cases in which employees who had known of product defects or
hazards decided to "swallow the whistle," as Alan Westin, Henry Kurtz, and Albert Robbins
put it in their book, Whistle-blowing. The result was that consumers and other employees
were seriously harmed; and when the information went public, so were the organizations that
Even in cases where whistle-blowing occurred, it was not always heeded. In 1972, Firestone
Tire Director of Development Thomas A. Robertson sent top management a memo warning
that the 500 tire was inferior and subject to belt-edge separation at high speeds. His warning
was ignored despite reports about poor performance from major customers such as General
Motors, and the 500 tire was kept on the market. By the time Time magazine reported about
this inferior tires, accidents caused by blowouts had resulted in more than 41 deaths and
hundreds of serious injuries, the company had already replaced 3 million tires and spent
hearing or blown the whistle externally, such disasters for the public and the company could
Unfortunately, it appears Firestone did not make the necessary organizational changes to
prevent such debacles, since the story repeated itself in 2000. After an investigation by the
National Highway Traffic Safety Administration, Ford announced a recall and replacement of
3.5 million Firestone tires in October 2000. This recall occurred after 200 deaths and 700
serious injuries had already been reported because of the unsafe tires.
When news of the problem broke in late 2000 and early 2001, it became clear many groups at
78
Ford and Firestone had known about the faulty tires as early as 1996. The ultimate result of
inaction by these groups was that Firestone and Ford were called to testify before Congress,
millions of dollars were spent settling lawsuits, and a century-long relationship between Ford
There have, of course, been successful cases of whistle-blowing although even in these cases,
the personal and professional toll on the individuals has been heavy. In 1968, Ernest
Fitzgerald, who was in charge of cost evaluations of the C-5A air transport program, found a
cost overrun of $2 billion. Although the Air Force dismissed him, he was reinstated through
legal action. He was, however, demoted. He later won another appeal for reinstatement in his
former position. The reasoning for the actions against him was explained in a memorandum
to John Haldeman of the Nixon White House: "Fitzgerald is no doubt a top-notch expert,
but he must be given very low marks on loyalty; and loyalty is the name of the game."
In 1996, Jeffery Wigand, a tobacco researcher, revealed that Brown & Williamson Tobacco
Corp. knew tobacco was addictive. His revelations had a dramatic impact on public policy
and public perceptions of the tobacco industry. However, although he was vindicated by the
attention he received in the media and by the fact that after his revelations, victims of
companies; he still experienced severe personal consequences including threats against his
family, loss of income, divorce, and the threat of litigation for breach of confidentiality.
In the late 1970s in the wake of the civil rights movement, federal and state laws were
regulate hiring and firing policies. Many of these laws contained provisions forbidding an
79
employer to retaliate against employees for reporting violations to public authorities.
Complaints about reprisals could be filed with agencies such as the Equal Employment
Opportunity Commission (EEOC) and the Occupational Safety and Health Administration
(OSHA).
In addition, new federal and state legislation, such as the Truth in Lending laws, the Fair
Credit Reporting Act, and the Environmental Protection Act, protected the public from illegal
or unethical business practices. Many of these laws also contained provisions against reprisal
for reporting violations. Although these laws appear to protect whistleblowers, a 1976 study
of OSHA showed only 20 percent of the complaints filed that year were considered valid.
About half of these claims were settled out of court, and of the 60 claims taken to court, only
Because of the fear of reprisals, regardless of the legislation available to address issues, Sen.
Patrick Leahy, in a 1977 study entitled The Whistleblowers, reported that "federal employees
are currently afraid to bring problems to the attention of their superiors." In response to such
reports, Congress passed the Civil Service Reform Act in 1978 to protect the rights of
Claims Act, which allows private individuals to sue government contractors on behalf of the
U.S. government if they believe the government is being defrauded. This act protects
employees of government contractors against reprisals and also provides incentives to blow
the whistle by allowing the employee to collect at least 15 percent of damages awarded to the
government.
The Whistleblower Protection Act of 1989 extended protections through the Merit Systems
80
Protection Board and increased the authority of the Office of Special Counsel created in
governmental context, there have been few protections for whistleblowers in private industry.
available under state laws, especially in specific industries or classes of people such as
Devine of the Government Accountability Project, such protections have been inadequate,
and whistleblowers spend many years and dollars trying to prove retaliation. Unless they
were able to gain media attention, whistleblowers in industry faced retaliation from their
In the 1980s, states began to provide whistleblower protection to employees as a result of the
erosion of the at-will employment doctrine, which until very recently meant that private,
nonunionized employees could be fired for any reason, including blowing the whistle. The
courts began to recognize it was against public policy for employees to be subject to
termination for the exercise of a legislatively created right, such as refusing to break the law
employer to be able to fire an employee at will for reporting unsafe or illegal conduct.
With the enactment of the Sarbanes-Oxley Corporate Reform Act of 2002, internal and
external whistleblower protection has been extended to all employees in publicly traded
81
Make it illegal to "discharge, demote, suspend, threaten, harass or in any manner
whistleblowers
complaints
administrative hearings
The passage of this act has created an environment in which many organizations have
realized the importance of instituting ethics policies and codes of conduct to address issues
related to unethical or illegal conduct. The business climate in the wake of Enron and
WorldCom, coupled with Sarbanes-Oxley, is one in which employees can feel more
As the preceding sections illustrate, whistle-blowing to an external entity, such as the media
or government agencies, has been a hazardous activity, both for the individual and the
organization. The ambivalent attitude toward whistleblowers ensures that, even with legal
protection, they may face retaliation in subtle ways: being shunned by co-workers, being
This section provides some best practices for encouraging employees to bring unethical or
82
illegal practices to the forefront and addressing them before they become fatal to an
organization.
To encourage employees to bring ethical and legal violations they are aware of to an
internal authority so that action can be taken immediately to resolve the problem
To minimize the organization's exposure to the damage that can occur when
conduct
Fear of retaliation
83
whistleblower is retaliating against a supervisor with false accusations? What if the
whistleblower is bringing genuine problems to the fore but is also a subpar employee? In that
case, does the whistleblower get a free pass just because he or she exposed an issue? What
should be done when it becomes clear that encouraging employees to bypass the proper
in the very actions they are now exposing, perhaps as a means of escaping the consequences
employee because of his or her race, gender, or ethnicity? These are just a few of the issues to
Create a Policy
Clear communications about the process of voicing concerns, such as a specific chain
In addition, a clear connection should exist between an organization's code of ethics and
performance measures. For example, in the performance review process, employees can be
held accountable not only for meeting their goals and objectives but also for doing so in
84
Get Endorsement From Top Management
Top management, starting with the CEO, should demonstrate a strong commitment to
levels, who are trained continuously in creating an open-door policy regarding employee
complaints.
To create a culture of openness and honesty, it is important that employees hear about the
policy regularly. Top management should make every effort to talk about the commitment to
acknowledging and rewarding employees who pinpoint ethical issues is one way to send the
message that management is serious about addressing issues before they become endemic.
Managers should be required to investigate all allegations promptly and thoroughly, and
report the origins and the results of the investigation to a higher authority. For example, at
IBM, a long-standing open-door policy requires that any complaint received must be
investigated within a certain number of hours. Inaction is the best way to create cynicism
Find out employees' opinions about the organization's culture vis-à-vis its commitment to
ethics and values. For example, Sears conducts an annual employee survey related to ethics.
85
Some questions are: Do you believe unethical issues are tolerated here? Do you know how to
Conclusion
Given the prevalence of corporate misconduct in the recent past, whistle-blowing incidents
have been on the rise. A 2002 article in Business Week called 2002 the "Year of the
Whistleblower" and quoted Stephen Meagher, a former federal prosecutor who represents
likely to be bolstered by the provisions of the Sarbanes-Oxley Act, which for the first time,
organizations will have to institute rigorous policies to allow employees to bring unethical
and illegal practices to the forefront. Companies will have to train managers and executives
on how to encourage openness, not unlike the sexual harassment training of a decade ago.
Putting processes in place will not be quick, but it is certainly necessary given the increased
Qualifying disclosures
criminal offences
miscarriages of justice
86
damage to the environment
There are some disclosures that can’t be qualifying disclosures. You won’t be protected for
whistle-blowing if:
you break the law when making a disclosure (for example if you signed the Official
the information is protected under legal professional privilege (eg if the information
Protected disclosures
For your disclosure to be protected by the law you should make it to the right person and in
make the disclosure in good faith (which means with honest intent and without
malice)
reasonably believe you are making the disclosure to the right 'prescribed person'
If you make a qualifying disclosure in good faith to your employer, or through a process that
your employer has agreed, you are protected. You should check your employment contract to
If you feel unable to make a disclosure to your employer then there are other 'prescribed
people' you can make a disclosure to. If you are unsure, you should always get professional
87
advice before going ahead. Anything you say to a legal adviser in order to get advice is
automatically protected.
You could make a qualifying disclosure to the person responsible for the area of concern to
you. For example, you might raise concerns about health and safety with a health and safety
representative.
Ghana has passed the long-awaited Whistleblowers Act. Under the act, disclosures may be
made regarding:
Miscarriages of justice;
Environmental degradation;
The act is the culmination of stakeholder consultations and lobbying by civil society groups
to enhance probity and accountability in the use of government resources. It outlines the
instances and processes through which employees can disclose information on the illegal
conduct or corrupt actions of their employers or fellow employees without fear of retribution.
The law allows the whistleblower to disclose the misuse of public funds to various groups.
Consequently, the whistleblower is presented with several options on whom to disclose the
88
the whistleblower’s employer;
a police officer;
a member of Parliament;
the Serious Fraud Office (Now Economic and Organized Crime Office);
a Traditional Chief;
a Minister of State; or
Where a disclosure is made to any of these persons or institutions, the recipient of the
information must investigate the matter or refer it to the Attorney General or other body as
directed by the Attorney General, who will initiate an investigation into the disclosure.
unless it is proven that the whistleblower knew that the disclosure was false or that it was
89
an employee from making a disclosure, instituting a court action or claiming a remedy for
victimization.
CONFLICT OF INTEREST
Introduction
Conflict of interest can occur on various levels from the individual to the organization, or
between the internal and the external community. In the end, executives or board members
engaging in a conflict of interest must have used their position to benefit themselves in some
way at the expense of the organization. According to Cooper (2006), conflict of interest
legally is defined as: situations where our personal interests are at odds with our obligations
as a public official or our professional values. There may be combinations of conflicting roles
and tensions between sources of authority, but more typically these occasions simply present
us with an opportunity to use our public office for the sake of our private gain of our friends
or relatives (p.129).
Conflicts of interest from the standpoint of ethics are broader than the legal definition
because the decision to engage in a conflict of interest involves loyalties, concerns and
90
emotions in relationships that collide with the organizational and public interests. The main
ethical issue involved in conflicts of interest is a breach of trust to the public. Whatever an
executive or board member engages in also affects the organizations image by the public.
The term Conflict of Interest means any or other interest which conflicts with the service(s)
an individual provides because it could significantly impair the individual’s objectivity and
create an unfair competitive advantage for any person or organization. A conflict of interest is
competing professional or personal interests. Such competing interests can make it difficult to
Conflicts of interest occur when an officeholder puts his or her personal or financial interest
ahead of the public interest. In the simplest terms, the official reaps a monetary or other
Boatright (1992) has stated that conflict of interest occurs when a personal interest interferes
with a person’s acting so as to promote the interest of another when the person has an
obligation to act in that other person’s interest’’. It could also be viewed as “a conflict
between the public duties and private interests of a public official, in which the public official
has private-capacity interests which could improperly influence the performance of their
private or personal interest sufficient to appear to influence the objective exercise of his or
her official duties as, say a public official, or a professional. Conflict of interest could also be
viewed as a situation that has the potential to undermine the impartiality of a clash between
91
From these definitions, there are three elements that can be examined further; the first
element is a private or personal interest. This interest is often a financial one but it could also
be another sort of interest, say, to provide a special advantage to a spouse or child. Taken by
them, there is nothing wrong with pursuing private or personal interest; for instance changing
jobs but the problem which comes with this private interest comes into conflict with the
second element of the definition (official duty), the duty you have because you have an office
which you acquire obligations to clients, employers, or others. These obligations are
supposed to trump over private or personal interest. The third element has to do with the fact
that conflict of interest interferes with professional responsibilities in a specific way, namely,
interfering with professional judgement. The major reason why clients and employers respect
professionals is that they expect the professionals to be objective and independent. Factors
such as private and personal interest that interfere or appear likely to interfere with objectivity
An apparent conflict of interest is one which a reasonable person would think that the
There are various ways that conflicts of interest can occur that are not illegal but may be an
ethical violation of the organization. Ritvo, Ohlsen and Holland (2004) emphasized the
difficulty for people in authoritative positions to live active and ethical lives while facing
challenging decisions. Often the person’s ethical obligations to fulfil job commitments can
interfere with the person spending time with the family or others. For example, how could an
executive inform a higher-authority executive that a daughter’s piano recital comes before a
critical meeting with the executive board members? Morrison (2006) mentioned other types
of ethical conflicts of interest. One is when an individual’s personal behaviour conflicts with
92
the organization’s ethics, such as over-indulgence of alcohol or a public use of other drugs.
Because patients safety and competent care are critical to the viability of a health care
personal behaviour inside the organization. Nurses, particular, are open to scrutiny by the
public and by hospital officials because of their nursing license and direct care patients.
The following are categories of conflicts of interest identified by Kernaghan and Langford
1. Self-dealing: This occurs where one works with the government and uses one’s
owns. Or using your government position to get a summer job for your daughter.
3. Influence peddling: Here, the professional solicits benefits in exchange for using
blatant as stealing office supplies for home use. Or it might be a bit more subtle,
say, using software which is licensed to your employer for your private consulting
client, you learn that the client is planning to buy land in your region. You quickly
93
6. Outside employment or moonlighting: An example would be setting up a
business on the side that is in direct competition with your employer. Another case
would be taken on so many outside clients that you don’t have the time and
sells private consulting services to an individual with the insurance that they will
secure benefits from government; if you use my company, I am sure that you will
resigns from a public or private employment and goes into business in the same
area. For example, a former public servant sets up a practice lobbying the former
1. Serving the public interest: Public officials should make decisions and provide
advice without regard for personal gain. The decision maker’s religious, professional,
party-political, ethnic, family, or other personal preferences should not affect the
integrity of official decision making. At the same time, public officials should dispose
of, or restrict the operation of, private financial interests, personal relationships or
affiliations that could compromise official decisions in which they are involved.
Where this is not feasible – an official can hardly be expected to abandon her
relationship with her husband or children in the interests of her job – a public official
private interests.
94
Public officials should also avoid taking improper advantage in their private lives from
“inside information” not available to the public that is obtained in the course of official
duties. So public officials should not engage in a private financial transaction which
must not misuse their position and government resources for private gain, such as
awarding a contract to a firm in the hope of obtaining a job with that firm on leaving
public office.
2. Supporting transparency and scrutiny: Public officials and public organisations are
expected to act in a way that will bear the closest public scrutiny. Public officials
should disclose any private interests and affiliations that could compromise the
Public organisations and officials should also ensure consistency and openness in
have been handled in the past and are expected to be handled in the future. Organisations
particularly public office holders and senior managers, should act at all times in a
manner that demonstrates integrity and thus serves as an example to other officials
and the public. When dealing with individual cases, senior officials and managers
should balance the interests of the organisation, the individual and the public. Public
95
officials should also accept responsibility for arranging their private affairs so as to
prevent conflicts of interest and for identifying and resolving conflicts in favour of the
public interest when a conflict does arise. So an official could sell a relevant financial
interest, or declare an interest in a particular issue and withdraw from the decision-
making process.
to create an organisational culture that does not tolerate conflict of interest. This can
interest policy, giving regular reminders, developing learning tools to help employees
apply and integrate the policy and by providing concrete advice when the need arises.
Organisational practices should encourage public officials to disclose and discuss real,
protect them from retaliation. Public organisations should also create and sustain a
1. Avoidance: The best way to handle conflict of interest is to avoid them entirely. This
may mean pulling oneself from all identifiable potential conflict of interest situations.
declarations of Assets and interests to the Auditor General and documents can be
assessed by state bodies. In any given situation, office holders have a duty to disclose
96
3. Excuse: Those with the conflict of interest are expected to excuse themselves from
(e.g, abstain from) decisions where conflict exists. The imperative for excuse varies
depending upon the circumstance and profession, either as common sense ethics,
agency is considering hiring a consulting firm for some task and one firm being
considered has, as a partner a close relative of one of the board’s members, then that
board member should not vote on which firm is to be selected. In fact, to minimize
any conflict, the board member should not participate in any of the decisions,
including discussions.
Judges are supposed to excuse themselves from cases when personal conflicts or
interest may arise. For example if a judge has participated in a case previously as
some other judicial role he or she is not allowed to try that case. Refusals is also
expected when one of the lawyers in a case might be a close personal friend, or when
the outcome of the case might affect the judge directly, such as whether a car maker is
obliged to recall a model that a judge drives. This is required by law under continental
civil court systems and by the Rome statute, organic law of the international criminal
court.
4. Third party evaluations: Third- party evaluation can be used to mitigate conflict of
interest as proof that transactions were; above board’ or fair (arms-length). For
example, a corporation that leases an office building that is owned by the CEO might
get an independent evaluation showing what the market rate is for such leases in the
locale, to address the conflict of interest that exist between the fiduciary duty of the
CEO (to the stakeholders) and the personal interest of that CEO (to maximize the
97
Case 1:
Betty, the chief nursing officer, had to make a decision about buying 120 new hospital beds
for patient rooms. After she interviewed nurse managers at the units where the beds were
going to be placed, Betty compiled her findings and decided to contact a well-known
equipment company to obtain prices and contracts. The equipment company’s executive sales
person, Jim, discussed options at length with her and invited her and her significant other to
demonstrations of the beds and to hear a comprehensive sales pitch. Betty thought to herself,
“We badly need some relaxation and stress relief. Hawaii would be so much fun. Would it be
1. If you were Betty, what should you do? Give your rationale. Justify your answer with
3. Do you consider this situation a conflict of interest? Why or why not? Give your
rationale
4. How would Betty handle this case if she believed she needed to seek advice from
someone in a higher authority? With whom would she discuss this issue?
Case 2:
Savannah, a registered nurse attended a party the night before a schedule 12-hour work day,
overindulged in cocktails, got to bed around 3am, and came to work the next morning at
6:45am with a hangover and alcohol still on her breath. This situation placed Savannah in
98
ethical violation of the organization’s values and the Code of Ethics for Nurses, as well as a
legal violation of the state board of nursing, because if alcohol is smelled on her breath, it is
still in the blood stream, which could alter her judgment. Savannah’s altered judgment could
Questions
1. Discuss the ethical implications of Savannah’s partying before work. Do you believe
that Savannah engaged in an ethical conflict of interest? Why or why not? Please
2. What ethical violation existed in Savannah’s case regarding her personal behaviour,
the hospital’s ethics and values, patient safety, and the state board of nursing?.
3. What other options could Savannah have considered other than going to work in an
altered state of mind? Make a list of the pros and cons of at least two other
4. Describe and justify how you would have handled this situation had you been
or principle.
5. What are the risks of Savannah attending work after drinking so much at the party?
6. Do you believe that the nursing supervisor should take action against Savannah? Why
or why not? If you believe that the supervisor should take action against Savannah,
describe the specific options for disciplinary action based on your general knowledge
99
CORRUPTION
Introduction
Corruption remains a threat to countries and in fact, corruption has been reported to be the
bane of Africa’s development. Governments after governments have tried to fight this cancer
but the situation seems to be increasing instead. For example Corruption-free society is
another value enshrined in the 1992 constitution. President Kuffour on assumption of office
declared Zero tolerance for corruption. What is corruption and how is it being managed in
Ghana?
It is easy to talk about corruption, but like other complex social phenomena, it is difficult to
define corruption in concise and concrete terms. Not surprisingly, there is no generally
accepted definition on what constitute corruption. The term “corruption” comes from the
Latin word which means “moral decay, wicked behavior, putridity or rottenness”.
from the formal rules of conduct governing the actions of someone in a position of
public authority because of private regarding motives such as wealth, power, or status”.
The World Bank and Transparency International define corruption as “the abuse of power for
private benefits”.
100
Brooks (1974) defined corruption as the internal mis-performance or neglect of a
recognized duty, or unwarranted exercise of power, with the motive of gaining some
Senturia (1931) sees it as the misuse or abuse of public power for private gains.
Alatas (1990) characterizes corruption as the abuse of trust for the sake of private
benefits.
deviate from and alter the just behaviour and accepted societal propriety in order to
From the above, corruption could be thus, said to be any wrongdoing on the part of an
incompatible with ethical standards in order to satisfy his or her personal gains. The
practice of corruption among other things tarnishes the image of the organization, and makes
These definitions are fairly embracive of the issues subsumed under corruption but do not
sufficiently bring out what Gire (2001) calls the prioritization process by the individual’- that
Therefore in this lecture corruption is defined as; the sacrifice of statesmanship on the altar
of partisanship. It is seen as an act that is crafted and undertaken with the deliberate
intent of deriving or extracting personal reward (Werlin, 1994, Dey 1989). Such behavior
acquaintances, and the abuse of public authority to exact money or other privileges.
101
The term corruption is used as a shorthand reference for large range illicit or illegal
definition shares a common emphasis upon the abuse of public power or position for
personal advantage.
accountability.
Owusu- Frempong (2003) has argued that this formula should attract transparency to make it
C=M+D-A-T.
According to the Anin report, Bribery and corruption involve both the giving and the
kind-with the object of influencing a person in a position of trust to act in a way favourable to
the interest of the giver’. Justice Anin’s commission of Inquiry into bribery and corruption
identified one hundred and sixty-two separate activities where corruption was practiced.
Justices Anin’s report enumerated among others, the following corrupt activities; Priests
extracted gifts from bereaved families of non-church goers in exchange for burying the
corruption. Their demand for money has become insatiable. Rich people are given
prominent seats and recognition at churches and functions irrespective of how they get
accommodating. The rich are idolized and worshipped and the poor are tempted to
102
work, issue of import and export permits, waiving or exemption of custom duties by
custom officers, collusion of police with offenders, improper closure of police dockets,
magistrates and judges, staff appointments, promotion and transfers and even
mortuary attendants demand payment before releasing dead bodies to relatives, match
Affairs, Dr. Ken Attafua among others had this to say “the cost of corruption is enormous,
covering the loss of development funds, retardation of economic growth, flight of capital, and
inflation of administrative costs. Corruption also frequently results in the loss of legitimacy
and respect for legally constituted authority by among other things, undermining the integrity
of the socio-legal foundations of that authority. It debases the moral fibber of a society by
nibbling away at the core values that bond the society together. In this sense, corruption is
FORMS OF CORRUPTION
Corruption can be categorized in various ways. Ofori-Kwafo (2003) has put corruption into
corruption is that it takes place many times (high frequency). Included in this type are
103
Grand Corruption: Corruption involving substantial amounts of money engaged in
by businessmen and government officials of senior rank and the figures involved are
significant. Kickbacks to government officials for public works contracts fall under
this category.
Looting (Lootocracy): This is the type of corruption that involves the illegal transfer
scams/scandals that are so huge that when they have been successfully concluded;
inflation rising and declining exchange rate. Usually under the direction of powerful
political actors and involves paying for big service contracts that are never delivered.
The difference between grand corruption and looting is that in grand corruption, the kick
back is usually a fraction of the project but the project is completed though with bad quality.
In looting, the kick back is the whole amount (100%) and the project is never completed and
regularly and frequently experienced. It takes place where wrong doing has become
the norm and common where officers that have regulatory services such as licenses,
friends are rewarded. Funding comes from forced or voluntary business contributions
The issues or factors included in this definition are so broad to warrant a further refining for
the nature and scope of this article. In an elaborate analysis, Alatas (1990) gave a typology of
the perpetrator. A good example would be what happens in the case of insider
trading. A person learns some vital information that may influence stocks in a
company and either quickly buys or gets rid of large amounts of stocks before the
business trip within a certain time frame needs a passport in order to undertake the
journey but is made to pay bribe or (unofficial money) or forfeits the trip. This person
is in self defence.
direct link to any particular favour at the present but with the anticipation of future
accepted guidelines.
105
6. SUPPORTIVE: The supportive type usually does not involve money or immediate
gains, but involves actions taken to protect or strengthen the exciting corruption. For
example a corrupt official may try to prevent the election or appointment of an honest
District Chief Executive, Mayor, local council member or the regime for the fear that
successor(s) and
parties are mutual and willing participants in the corrupt practice to the advantage of
both parties. For example a corrupt business may willingly bribe a corrupt
CAUSES OF CORRUPTION
Parochialism
106
CONTROL / REMEDIALS SRATEGIES
Socialization agencies
Family
Mass media
Political Parties
Corruption involves the improper and unlawful behavior of public- service officials, both
politicians and civil servants, whose positions create opportunities for the diversion of money
2. Corruption constrains investment and retards growth. Investors are asked for
bribes before setting up enterprises and become a tax to them and discourage
107
3. Corruption leads to low quality social infrastructure; this affects movement of
performing loans and people lose confidence in banks and hoard their money making
5. Corruption, if not checked, leads to impunity; a culture develops where every one
GHANA
Below are some of the measures put in place to combat corruption; political leaders coming
out boldly to declare their assets before assuming political power, political leaders coming
out with proclamations like probity, integrity and accountability, zero tolerance for
corruption, embarking on anti-corruption activities like retrieving assets that have been
embezzled by public officials’. Using the mechanisms bequeathed to us by colonial rule, that
is, parliament, courts, police and audit service to deal with corruption.
The new legal, constitutional and democratic approach to fighting corruption in Africa is
liberal constitutions in the 1990s. The new constitutions typically describe limited
government, formal separation of powers, checks and balances, judicial independence and the
108
Following the new legal, constitutional and democratic approach to fighting corruption, the
1992 Republic Constitution has enumerated some measures to curb corrupt practices in
Ghana. Article 35 (8) of the Constitution states that “the State shall take steps to eradicate
corrupt practices and the abuse of power”. The above declaration is re-emphasize with more
urgency in sections 179C (a) and (b) of Act 458 which amended the Criminal Code of 1960
(a) While holding a public office corruptly or dishonestly abuses the office for private
profit or benefits; or
(b) Not being a holder of a public office acts or is found to have acted in collaboration
with a person holding public for that latter to corruptly or dishonestly abuse the office
functions and powers of the Commission are mainly derived from the constitution
(Article 218) and the Commission’s Act (Act 456) of 1993. Article 218(a) and (e) of
investigations.
109
Examples of some investigations carried out by CHRAJ include; the case of Dr.
Richard Anane during President Kufour’s administration and the Marbel and
2. Serious Fraud Office (SFO): the SFO is a specialised agency of government which
prosecute any offence involving serious financial or economic loss to the state. Act
466 of 1993 gives the SFO the power to investigate any suspected offence provided
for by law which appears to the Executive Director on reasonable grounds to involve
mandates the Auditor-General to “audit the public accounts of Ghana and of all public
within six months after the end of each financial year, drawing attention not only to
irregularities but also to any other matter in his opinion should be brought to the
attention of parliament. Through this article, the Auditor-General has brought to light
code of conduct for public officers. For instance, article 284 states that “a public
officer shall not put himself in a position where his personal interest conflicts or is
Again, Article 285 states that “no person shall be appointed or act as the chairman of
110
In addition to the Constitutional provision, the Civil Service has its own Code of
Conduct (1993) which spells out the relationship between the Civil Servant and its
principal stakeholders.
5. Asset Declaration: in addition to the above, the 1992 constitution requires certain
categories of public officials to declare their assets and liabilities under the following
a. Within three (3) months after coming into force of the constitution or before
c. At the end of his term of office. This article also disqualifies people from holding
6. Parliament: the constitution also gives parliament the power to hold public officials
accountable for their actions or inactions. This can be found in article 103:3 in the
form of;
7. Setting up Commissions of Inquiry: Article 278 of the 1992 Constitution gives the
President, Cabinet and Parliament the ability to set up a commission of inquiry when
they feel it is in the best interest of the nation. The Article states that “the President
111
c. Parliament, by a resolution request that a commission of inquiry be appointed to
inquire into any matter, specified in the resolution as being a matter of public
interest.
Many Commissions of Inquiries have been set up in the country to handle cases that are
inquiry set up to look into the cause of bribery and corruption and bring out recommendations
was the Justice Anin’s commission of Inquiry. A recent commission set up to look into the
cocaine scandal was the Justice Georgina Wood Commission or Committee. The Minister of
the Interior, Mr. Kan-Dapaah in his reaction to the Georgina Wood Commission of Inquiry in
the Daily Graphic of September 30, among others had this to say “The committee further
found from the recorded discussions other acts of corruption, abuse of office, professional
corruption and encourage ethics is the “Protected Public Interest Disclosure Act”
referred to as the “Whistle-Blower” Act 2006, (Act 720). As part of the need to
reduce corruption to be able to achieve the necessary poverty reduction, meet the
Millennium Development Goals and move Ghana into the middle income country, a
bill to encourage and protect whistle blowing was enacted in 2006. The proposed bill
presented to Parliament after various consultations was to provide for the manner in
which individuals may in the public interest disclose information that relates to
unlawful, corrupt or other illegal conduct or practices in the country. The Bill ensures
that persons who make the disclosures are not subjected to victimization, recognizes
that corrupt and other illegal conduct in the organs of State, the private sector and
112
governance and good corporate practice. It was therefore important to establish a
mechanism that will lead to the detection of criminal, corrupt and other illegal
The Bill further explains that it does not in any way affect in any manner the role of
informants. Security agencies can therefore continue to solicit and receive complaints whose
identity may not be disclosed. After consultations with different stakeholders led by members
of the Ghana Anti-Corruption Coalition, the bill was passed by Parliament and given assent
on 20th October 2006. Under this new act, disclosures may be made regarding: breaches or
of individual and community health and safety; and waste, appropriation or mismanagement
of public resources.
The act is the culmination of stakeholder consultations and lobbying by civil society groups
to enhance probity and accountability in the use of government resources. It outlines the
instances and processes through which employees can disclose information on the illegal
conduct or corrupt actions of their employers or fellow employees without fear of retribution.
The law allows the whistleblower to disclose the misuse of public funds to various groups.
Consequently, the whistleblower is presented with several options on whom to disclose the
information to. These include: a staff member of the intelligence agencies; a Member of
Parliament; the Serious Fraud Office; the Commission on Human Rights and Administrative
Justice; the National Media Commission; the Narcotics Control Board; a traditional chief; a
Where a disclosure is made to any of these persons or institutions, the recipient of the
information must investigate the matter or refer it to the attorney general or other body as
directed by the attorney general, who will initiate an investigation into the disclosure. A
113
whistleblower is not liable to civil or criminal proceedings in respect of the disclosure unless
it is proven that the whistleblower knew that the disclosure was false or that it was made with
employee from making a disclosure, instituting a court action or claiming a remedy for
victimization.
overemphasized. It provides a check on the actions of persons charged with the management
9. Public Procurement Act, 2003: Over a period of time, public procurement in Ghana
and weak institutions for managing the procurement process. Responding to this
Public Procurement Act, 2003 (Act 663). This Act establishes the Public Procurement
and also stipulates tendering procedures. Thus, the act deals with procurement
also deals with submission of tenders and methods and procedures of engaging the
services of Consultants. Section 3 of Act 663 provides for the functions of the
Authority as to:
b. Ensure policy implementation and human resource development for public procurement
114
c. Develops draft rules, instructions, other regulatory documentation on public procurement
and
e. Monitor and supervise public procurement and ensure compliance with statutory
requirements;
f. Have the right to obtain information concerning public procurement from contracting
authorities;
h. Publish a monthly Public Procurement Bulletin which shall contain information germane
One of the achievements of the Public Procurement board is enhanced transparency and
fairness in tendering process. Procurement reform has become a key governance issue. It was
also one of the considerations for which Ghana received 100 percent debt relief from the
Millennium Challenge Fund Account from the United States Government. Competition in
public procurement is also increasing. This is a testimony that the procurement reform is
beginning to achieve one of its key objectives i.e., transparency, accountability and openness.
10. The Anti-Money Laundering Act, 2007 (Act 749) is also one of the measures put in
place to reduce corruption and enhance ethics. Sections 1 and 2 of the Anti-Money
Laundering Act, 2008 (Act 749) criminalize money laundering in Ghana. The
transfer of property knowing that the property is or forms part of the proceeds of
115
unlawful activity. One of the measures taken under the Act to prevent money-
The centre has as its core object, the identification of proceeds of unlawful activity,
The Act also requires accountable institutions to identify their customers, keep
laundering Regulations) provide for the regulatory framework for the Anti-Money
Laundering Act.
11. Internal Audit Agency Act, 2003 (Act 658) is an additional measure to enhance
ethics and reduce corruption. The Act seeks to establish a central agency of
Government Ministries, Departments and Agencies. The Act creates standards and
procedures for the conduct of internal audit activities intended to secure transparency
In conclusion it could be said that, corruption thrives best in environments that are
citizen’s rights and disregard for fundamental human rights, values, principles and norms.
These notwithstanding, the effective control of corruption apart from what has been
situation and the expansion of the scope of citizen enjoyment of administrative justice in the
country.
116
CHAPTER SIX
The term corporate social responsibility is now a celebrated concept in business circles as
most organizations now have incorporated social responsibility into their business operations.
In fact, businesses now use CSR as a strategy to appeal to the conscience of customers and
society regarding how ethical they are with respect to their responsibility to society. Students
will be introduced to the concept and theories and therefore, students will be expected after
Dimensions of CSR
Introduction
The development of a country is not solely the responsibility of the government; every citizen
should take part in achieving social welfare and improving the quality of life of the
community. The business world’s role is to increase healthy economic growth, taking
environmental issues into account. Nowadays, the business world does not focus only on the
financial aspect (single bottom line); it considers financial, social and environmental
aspects (triple bottom line). The definitions of CSR are many and may refer to ethical
important that organizations are committed to fulfilling expectations and moral obligations at
117
the level of society. This means that right conduct takes into account the welfare of the larger
society.
And more recently, McWilliams and Siegel (2001:117) define it as “… actions that appear to
further some social good, beyond the interests of the firm and that which is required by law”.
While the CSR construct is a new coinage, it is not a new practice. It could be traced back to
such examples as the Quakers in 17th and 18th centuries whose business philosophy was not
primarily driven by profit maximisation but by the need to add value to the society at large –
business was framed as part of the society and not separate from it. The resurgent interest in
the practice provides a fertile ground for different discourses and actors, which lends it to
multiple and contested constructions (Moon 2002). Corporations around the world are
struggling with a new role, which is to meet the needs of the present generation without
compromising the ability of the next generations to meet their own needs. Organizations are
being called upon to take responsibility for the ways their operations impact societies and the
natural environment. They are also being asked to apply sustainability principles to the ways
Robbins and Decenzo (2001) see social responsibility as the obligation of a firm, beyond
that required by law or economics, to pursue long-term goals that are good for society.
Hopkins (2003), state that CSR is the ethical, responsible and integrated business
implementation applied to all operations. Lesmana, (2007) opines that corporate social
responsibility (CSR) is one of the roles performed by the business world and it is aimed
at encouraging business entities to run their activities ethically, minimizing bad effects
on communities and the environment so that, ultimately, they can continue to carry on
118
Presently, the ideal definition of CSR is given by The World Business Council for
Sustainable Development (2001) and cited in Jamali (2006) as a business commitment that
and their representatives, their families, and local and public communities, to improve
the quality of life by means of beneficial ways both for the business itself and for
development.
Citizenship and Corporate Accountability. While some may argue over the distinctions
among these terms, at the core they all point towards the same fundamental principle: that a
company is responsible for providing more benefits than just profits for shareholders. It
has a role to play in treating its employees well, preserving the environment, developing
respecting cultural differences and helping to promote fair trade, among others. All are
meant to have a positive impact on the communities, cultures, societies and environments in
According to the Commission of the European Communities (2001) and cited in Jones et al.,
2006), the activities of CSR have been categorized in two dimensional approaches, i.e.
internal and external and have to be implemented in three aspects, i.e. economic, social
and environmental (Jamali, 2006). The internal dimensions include human resource
environmental and natural resources effect management. The external dimension consists
of a wider area, including investors, the local community, business partners, suppliers
119
Sustainability refers to an organization’s activities, typically considered voluntary, that
demonstrate the inclusion of social and environmental concerns in business operations and in
from those agents impacted by its actions. A firm must now focus its attention on both
increasing its bottom line and being a good corporate citizen. Keeping abreast of global
trends and remaining committed to financial obligations to deliver both private and public
benefits have forced organizations to reshape their frameworks, rules, and business models.
To understand and enhance current efforts, the most socially responsible organizations
continue to revise their short- and long-term agendas, to stay ahead of rapidly changing
business and society literature, addressing topics of business ethics, corporate social
education can be an important source of new ideas about shifting toward an integrated rather
than fractured knowledge economy, but this means also that the role and meaning of socially
clearer understanding of what is required, both in leadership itself and in the field of
leadership development.
Carroll, (2000) states that organizations are expected to practice “social responsibility” or be
a good “corporate citizen”. Carroll (1979) argues that corporations should not only be judged
on their economic success but also on non-economic criteria. To fulfill the good corporate
citizen role, a corporation should fulfill the following responsibilities (Carroll, 2000):
120
1. Economic: Earn a fair return on capital to satisfy the shareholders, deliver value for
money products to satisfy customers, create new jobs and new wealth for the
3. Ethical: Be moral, fair, just, respect people’s rights, avoid harm or social injury and
Lantos (2001) cited in Wan-Jan (2006) on the other hand put CSR into three categories:
responsible morally in preventing loss and damage as a result of its activities. This
CSR is expected from all companies and stands as the minimum requirement fulfilled
by the company.
3) Strategic CSR: This means corporate care activities implemented to complete the
Dimensions of CSR
The Global Reporting Initiative (2001) stated the key dimensions of CSR or triple bottom
line. The first is economy. In this dimension, CSR should delve into more than traditional
financial accountancy by looking into new measurements of wealth, like HRD and the
Examples would be reducing business costs through appropriate business integrity policy,
and increasing employees’ productivity by conducting research and HRD development and
121
The second dimension is the environment. This means that CSR should study the
implications of resource and energy usage, and the company’s effect on the integrity of the
environment. Examples of this would include environmental policy and audit, and
The third dimension is social. In this dimension CSR should maximize the positive influence
community health problems, social justice, and inter- and intra-organizational justice.
In addition to the above three dimensions, scholars have made references to two (2) other
sustainable development program, since it will give a better positive outcome and benefits to
the company and its stakeholders. Furthermore, a sustainable CSR program will help to
establish a prosperous and independent community (Lesmana, 2007). According to the World
development that fulfills current needs without sacrificing the ability of future
generations in fulfilling theirs (Porter and Kramer, 2006). The International Institute for
Sustainable Development and Deloitte & Touche also defined sustainable development for
business entities as a process of adopting business strategies and activities to fulfill the
present company’s needs and the needs of stakeholders as well as protecting, supporting and
increasing the human and natural resources needed in the future (Labuschagne and Brent,
2005; cited in Malovics et al., 2007). A sustainable development does not focus on
environmental issues only. Its policy covers three public areas: Economy, Social issues; and
122
Reputation: The social responsibility of a company is recognized as an aspect, an appeal and
an activity that influences its reputation (Zyglidopoulos, 2001; Fombrun and Shanley, 1990;
Carroll, 1979; all cited in Siltaoja, 2006). Deephouse (2000) and Fombrun (1996, 1998; all
cited in Siltaoja, 2006) revealed that reputation is often defined as the most important
competitive excellence a company can have. For Brown and Logsdon (1999; cited in Siltaoja,
how well the organization executes its commitments and fulfills stakeholders’
expectation, and how effective the organization’s performance is according to its soc-
political environment. Accountability and sustainability are certainly used in assessing the
company’s reputation. For business world and community, the concepts of accountability and
sustainability can be developed consistently to the power and capacity of the company, to act
according to the company’s and the worlds interest together (Freeman, 2006).
Product/service quality;
Financial performance;
Environmental responsibility;
Leadership.
Porter and Kramer (2006), in the context of a sustainable CSR programs implemented by a
company, suggested that CSR is more than a cost, an obstacle or charity – CSR can be an
(2006) revealed that strategically, CSR can be the source of excellent social advancement,
sustainable CSR programs as a part of their business strategy (Porter, 2003) and implement
them accordingly (Lewis, 2003) to achieve further excellence. The key factor that initiates
CSR is stakeholders’ expectations that an investment decision should generate not only
financial profit, but should also take into account the social and environmental aspect so that
ensure integrity. In a global stakeholder society, accountability is among the key challenges
of organizations. Responsible leaders are concerned with reconciling and aligning the
A company’s track record in terms of CSR accounting will be effective when appropriate
CSR measures are included in its internal as well as its supply-chain activities. Furthermore,
the literature reflects a growing need for dissemination of good practice in CSR
accountability and a need for more pressure to be exerted on NGOs to prove themselves as
ethical, transparent, and accountable as those they seek to influence (Frame, 2005). A
relevant point raised in some literature has to do with the effectiveness of strategies
This literature argues that the success of community-based strategies for corporate
accountability is conditional upon the right combination of state, civil, societal, and corporate
factors.
124
Frynas (2005) makes the point that accountability is more than making false promises. In the
oil, gas, and mining sectors, despite the promise of CSR and the spending of over US $500
million in 2001 alone on a long list of community development programs and other CSR
initiatives, the effectiveness of the initiatives has been increasingly questioned. Frynas points
out that there is mounting evidence of a gap between the stated intentions of business leaders
and their actual behavior and impact in the real world of financial funding. CSR requires
community members, and yet accountability is complex. The factors which influence the
interconnectedness and its relationship to accountability are represented in the work of Dolan
(2004), which uses the example of his own company to illustrate the idea of considering a
business as an interconnected web of relationships, with the consequences of every action the
company takes having an impact on both the world and the company’s long-term business.
The CSR is well understood when viewed from a theoretical perspective. This section
Stakeholder theories
The stakeholder theory of the firm is used as a basis to analyse those groups to whom the
firm should be responsible. As described by Freeman (1984), the firm can be described as a
series of connections of stakeholders that the managers of the firm attempt to manage.
Freeman's classic definition of a stakeholder is ``any group or individual who can affect or
Stakeholders are typically analysed into primary and secondary stakeholders. Clarkson
including ``shareholders and investors, employees, customers and suppliers, together with
what is defined as the public stakeholder group: the governments and communities that
provide infrastructures and markets, whose laws and regulations must be obeyed, and to
whom taxes and obligations may be due''. The secondary groups are defined as ``those who
influence or affect, or are influenced or affected by the corporation, but they are not
engaged in transactions with the corporation and are not essential for its survival''.
In terms of the issue of social responsibility, the central issue is whether stakeholder analysis
is part of the motivation for business to be responsible and, if so, to which stakeholders.
Hamil (1999), adopting Donaldson and Preston's (1995) typology, finds that corporate
giving is nearly always instrumental. An important question that has been addressed is to
which groups do managers pay attention? Mitchell et al. (1997) develop a model of
stakeholder identification and salience based on stakeholders possessing one or more of the
attributes of power, legitimacy and urgency. Agle et al. (1999) confirm that the three
attributes do lead to salience. Thus, we might anticipate that firms would pay most attention
to those legitimate stakeholder groups who have power and urgency. In practice this might
mean that firms with problems over employee retention would attend to employee issues and
those in consumer markets would have regard to matters that affect reputation.
Stakeholder groups may also become more or less urgent; so environmental groups and
issues became more urgent to oil firms following the Exxon Valdez oil spill (Patten, 1992).
We note from the current commercial approaches to CSR that stakeholder analysis is
important, but that the rationale remains largely instrumental (WBCSD, 1999; Business
Impact, 2000). However, there are elements that are also normative. For example, Business
Impact begins by advocating that CSR should be based against set purposes and values,
126
nevertheless such purpose and values are also linked to ``contributing to [the firm's]
Gray et al. (1996) describe society as ``a series of social contracts between members of
society and society itself''. In the context of CSR, an alternative possibility is not that
business might act in a responsible manner because it is in its commercial interest, but
because it is part of how society implicitly expects business to operate. Donaldson and
Dunfee (1999) develop integrated social contracts theory as a way for managers to take
example, would be an expectation that business provide some support to its local community
and the specific form of involvement would be the micro-social contract. Hence companies
who adopt a view of social contracts would describe their involvement as part of ``societal
expectation'', however, whilst this could explain the initial motivation, it might not explain
Legitimacy Theory
Suchman (1995) defines legitimacy as ``a generalized perception or assumption that the
constructed system of norms, values, beliefs and definitions''. Bringing together prior
theory (Pfeffer and Salancik, 1978) and the institutional traditions (DiMaggio and Powell,
1983), he identifies three types of organisational legitimacy: pragmatic, moral and cognitive.
127
He further identifies three key challenges of legitimacy management: gaining, maintaining
and repairing legitimacy. Suchman points out that ``legitimacy management rests heavily on
Thus there is a need to examine any particular corporate behaviour within its context and in
particular to look for alternative motivations. Thus legitimacy might be seen as a key reason
for undertaking corporate social behaviour and also then using that activity as a form of
publicity or influence (Lindblom cited in Gray et al., 1996 and in Clarke, 1998). A converse
view to this, i.e. not that business uses its power to legitimate its activity but, rather that
society grants power to business which it expects it to use responsibly, is set out by Davis
(cited in Wood, 1991): ``Society grants legitimacy and power to business. In the long run,
those who do not use power in a manner which society considers responsible will tend to lose
it.'' In effect, this is a re-statement of the concept of a social contract between the firm and
society.
Many factors and influences have led to increasing attention being devoted to the role of
Sustainable development: United Nations’ (UN) studies and many others have
underlined the fact that humankind is using natural resources at a faster rate than they
are being replaced. If this continues, future generations will not have the resources
they need for their development. In this sense, much of current development is
unsustainable—it can’t be continued for both practical and moral reasons. Related
issues include the need for greater attention to poverty alleviation and respect for
128
human rights. CSR is an entry point for understanding sustainable development issues
protection, and health and safety, among other things. CSR can play a vital role in
detecting how business impacts labour conditions, local communities and economies,
and what steps can be taken to ensure business helps to maintain and build the public
economies.
declarations, guidelines, principles and other instruments that outline norms for what
internationally-agreed goals and laws regarding human rights, the environment and
anti-corruption.
Corporate sector impact: The sheer size and number of corporations, and their
governments and civil society, raise questions about influence and accountability.
Even small and medium size enterprises (SMEs), which collectively represent the
129
Communications: Advances in communications technology, such as the Internet and
mobile phones, are making it easier to track and discuss corporate activities.
Internally, this can facilitate management, reporting and change. Externally, NGOs,
the media and others can quickly assess and profile business practices they view as
companies are addressing risks and opportunities related to social and environmental
issues. A sound CSR approach can help build share value, lower the cost of capital,
ethical standards.
Consistency and Community: Citizens in many countries are making it clear that
corporations should meet the same high standards of social and environmental care,
no matter where they operate. In the CSR context, firms can help build a sense of
government legislative and regulatory initiatives to effectively capture all the issues
that CSR address. CSR can offer the flexibility and incentive for firms to act in
130
Business Tool: Businesses are recognizing that adopting an effective approach to
CSR can reduce the risk of business disruptions, open up new opportunities, drive
innovation, enhance brand and company reputation and even improve efficiency.
stakeholder scrutiny of corporate activities, can improve the security of supply and
overall market stability. Considering the interests of parties concerned about a firm’s
CSR can build their reputation, while those that perform poorly can damage brand and
company value when exposed. Reputation, or brand equity, is founded on values such
as trust, credibility, reliability, quality and consistency. Even for firms that do not
have direct retail exposure through brands, their reputation for addressing CSR issues
as a supply chain partner (both good and bad) can be crucial commercially.
3. Enhanced ability to recruit, develop and retain staff: This can be the direct result
result of programs and activities that improve employee morale and loyalty.
Employees are not only front-line sources of ideas for improved performance, but are
131
stakeholders can be a rich source of ideas for new products, processes and markets,
The history of good business has always been one of being alert to trends, innovation,
5. Enhanced operational efficiencies and cost savings: These flow in particular from
energy aspects of an operation can reveal opportunities for turning waste streams into
revenue streams (wood chips into particle board, for example) and for system-wide
6. Improved ability to attract and build effective and efficient supply chain
relationships: A firm is vulnerable to the weakest link in its supply chain. Like-
standards, and thereby reducing risks. Larger firms can stimulate smaller firms with
whom they do business to implement a CSR approach. For example, some large
apparel retailers require their suppliers to comply with worker codes and standards.
7. Enhanced ability to address change. A company with its “ear to the ground”
Increasingly, firms use CSR as “radar” to detect evolving trends in the market.
8 More robust “social licence” to operate in the community. Improved citizen and
stakeholder understanding of the firm and its objectives and activities translate into
132
improved stakeholder relations. This, in turn, may evolve into more robust and
enduring public, private and civil society alliances (all of which relate closely to CSR
environmental criteria into their assessment of projects. When making decisions about
where to place their money, investors are looking for indicators of effective CSR
have expedited approval processes for firms that have undertaken social and
consumption patterns and lifestyles through the goods and services they provide and
the way they provide them. “Responsible consumerism” is not exclusively about
changing consumer preferences. It is also about what goods are supplied in the
marketplace, their relationship to consumer rights and sustainability issues, and how
133
CHAPTER SEVEN
This section highlights the ethical implications of marketing- the engine of most
organizations and how specific marketing activities have tended to take advantage of
customers. How through marketing communication, companies create the impression that
they are socially responsible when indeed, these companies are a menace to society. At the
theories
Introduction
Johnson (1981) argues that most business decisions involve choices between two or more
goods or two undesirable options. A related challenge to ethical decision making is that
sometimes good and evil seem to be joint products. In other words, a desirable result is
Within business firm, the functional area most closely related to ethical abuse is marketing.
This is because marketing is the function of business charged with communicating and
openly satisfying customers. Thus, marketing is closest to the public view and, consequently,
134
The trouble with marketing communications ‘‘the public increasingly wants to know about
that stand behind the brands and products presented to them. And use their power to reward
‘good’ companies and punish the ‘bad’ ones’’ (Lewis, 2001). The two ‘C’s of marketing
communications: Contact and Convince border on ethics. The first part may be a great deal
simpler than the second, and this is where the importance of source credibility becomes
paramount, considering customer cynicism. It can be argued that any and every marketing
communications tool is capable of conveying a company’s corporate image and brand equity.
However, some communications vehicles can be more powerful and effective than others,
marketing).
In a major cover story, Sales & Marketing Management (S&MM) provided the results of a
survey of 200 sales managers designed to find out just how far professional salespeople will
49 Percent of surveyed managers say their reps have lied on a sales call.
34 Percent say they have heard reps make unrealistic promises on a sales call.
22 Percent say their reps have sold products their customers did not need.
30 Percent say customers have demanded a kickback for buying their product or
service.
54 Percent say the drive to meet sales goals does a disservice to customers.
This section discusses theories such as justice, deontology, and utilitarian theories. Most
135
Justice Theory
Much of the most influential and fundamental concepts of justice theory comes from the
writing of Aristotle. For marketers, the most important philosophy to aid in the distribution of
value is the concept of procedural justice. As the name applies, its purpose is to develop rules
or procedures that result in fair or just outcomes. Procedural justice for marketers can be
applied in their dealings with customers, employees and suppliers. A clear understanding of
the procedures, rules, and responsibilities governing these relationships by all parties is
When for some legitimate reason this information is not part of the relationship, ideals of
justice dictate that the more knowledgeable parties not take advantage of their position.
Justice provided by marketers to their publics is the relationships, and relationships based on
Deontology
This theory suggests that individuals have a duty to satisfy the legitimate claims or needs of
others. These claims are determined by applying logic to an ethical rule, and the duties to
others are many and diverse under this philosophy it is our duty to pay our debts, care for our
children, and tell the truth because it is the “right” thing to do. According to the theory of
categorical imperative proposed by Kant “I ought never to act except in such a way that I can
also will that my maxim should become a universal law.” With this rule and the use of logic
any action can be evaluated to determine if it is ethical or unethical. These duties on the part
of one individual toward another create rights for the other. Thus, the duty of parents creates
rights for children, and the duty of debtors creates rights for the lender. For marketers,
deontology is recognition that all of the public’s with whom they deal have certain rights and
that they have respective duties. President John F. Kennedy provided a list of four basic
136
rights for consumers, the right (a) to safety, (b) to be informed, (c) to choose, and (d) to be
heard, apply directly to retailers. Concomitant duties of the marketer would be (a) to protect,
(b) to fully inform, (c) to provide and allow choice, and (d) to listen.
Utilitarianism
Is the teleological theory which states that individual should act so as to produce the greatest
possible ratio of good to evil for all of society. It forces the actors to consider all of the
outcomes of their action or inaction and to weigh one against another to determine that which
is best for society. Since one action is compared to another, utilitarianism promotes
efficiency. That is, a less efficient action is likely to produce less utility than a more efficient
action, and is therefore less ethical. Much of the justification for capitalism is based in
utilitarianism. In addition, the general public learns about the ideas of utilitarianism through
the concept of the democratic process which focuses on the majority rule. An important key
for applying utilitarianism to marketing is that the concept of “social good” includes
“economic good” but is not limited to it. The primary function of a marketing operation is
economic, but society expects that this function be carried out in a society responsible
manner.
The trouble with advertising, as the most visible communications tool, is continuously
blamed for a number of problems, including child obesity (see Kitchen et al., 2004), for being
pervasive, intrusive and pernicious (Laczniak & Laczniak, 1985). Nairn and Fine (2008)
agree that the presence of persuasion knowledge or cognitive defence can offer a plausible
test of fairness for informative advertising formats. However, they state that research findings
change. Nairn and Fine (2008, p. 460) argue that: ‘‘… for these formats the appropriate test
of fairness is the ability to resist implicit persuasion. Without this, the child is like the target
137
of subliminal advertising: preferences are mediated by non-conscious, non-rational means
that are impossible to resist’’. The concern is not merely with children, however. Nairn and
Fine write that even adolescents may have difficulty to resist implicit persuasion, due to lack
of possession of sufficient cognitive control capacities. It can be argued that children tend to
pay more attention to and be concerned with ethical and environmental issues compared with
their parents.
Heavy press advertising in the UK by major oil companies such as BP and Shell, usually
covering an entire page or even two pages at times (see Shell’s advert in The Guardian
newspaper, 1st December, 2008) boasting about their ‘green’ initiatives is one example of
such a persuasive approach. These companies’ main products are pollutants, and any
itself. It uses lower case letters ‘bp’ to denote a more friendly face, and uses the letters to
highlight its move to ‘beyond petroleum’. It, too, advertises heavily in the UK press for
reasons similar to Shell. Greenpeace’s media head refers to the growing amount of ‘cynical
advertising’ by organisations with poor environmental track records, such as oil companies.
Claims made by advertisers about their green attempts do not negate the overall impact of
their operations and/or products on the environment. Shell’s adverts in The Guardian
suggested that it had come to save the world (Monbiot, 2009), ‘‘tackling climate change and
providing fuel for a growing population seems like an impossible problem, but at Shell we try
to think creatively’’. The same company boasted in the year 2000 that it would be investing
US $1 billion in renewable energy between 2001 and 2005. However, no figures for its
renewable budget have been produced. The company states that it is investing ‘significantly’
in wind energy, but not clarifying what ‘significantly’ means. Car manufacturers, too, have
138
jumped on the green/ethical bandwagon, and use advertising in newspapers for this purpose.
Fiat combined lower cost and ecology to advertise its cars (see The Guardian newspaper 29th
February 2008), while Toyota was actually criticised by the Advertising Standards Authority
(ASA) for making misleading claims about the environmental credentials of its Prius hybrid
Volkswagen was also under the spotlight for an advertisement in which its Golf GT TSI was
claimed to have lower CO2 emissions than ‘other engines with similar power outputs’.
Scottish and Southern Energy Group in the UK made an unsubstantiated claim that it planted
trees in order to balance out the CO2 emissions of its customers’ gas heating and household
waste products. It was duly criticised by the ASA in 2007, following a complaint.
EasyJet’s claims to have more environmentally friendly airplanes were inaccurately portrayed
as such according to ASA, again following a customer complaint. Indeed there could be
advertisements that appear to make similar claims but which may escape the watchful eyes of
critics. Amongst the major criticisms of advertising is that, without such expenditure, the
product would cost the consumer less money. However, companies such as Kellogg’s that
spend an approximate £50 million per annum on advertising see it as an investment. The
results of such investment are reflected in their market share (Lawrence, 2008). An
investigative UK magazine called which? Had carried out research that analysed 275 major
breakfast cereals in 2006. The outcome was that 75% contained high levels of salt, based on
the guidelines of Food Standards Agency (FSA). Furthermore, approximately 90% of those
targeted at children were high in sugar, 13% high in salt and 10% high in saturated fat
limitations.
139
According to Lawrence (2008, p. 22) the managing director of the aforementioned company,
when asked to reduce sugar and salt content of cereals even further (following a 25%
reduction in salt by the firm), had replied: ‘‘… and the risk is, if you take the salt out you
might be better off eating the cardboard carton for taste’’. With reference to breakfast cereals,
they are invariably advertised as ‘healthy eating’. However, according to Lawrence (2008),
one of the highest costs is not the value of ingredients, nor the cost of production, but the
marketing, with a typical 20–25% of the sales value. Needless to say, a large percentage of
that expenditure is allocated to advertising with children as the target audience. Shimp (1997)
Fan (2005), while remarking on advertising as the most visible element of marketing,
suggests that it is branding that is at the heart of any marketing communications, citing
578) write that ‘‘it is no longer satisfactory to associate advertising solely with persuasion,
strategic functions’’.
Research carried out by Bowd et al. (2006) amongst stakeholders and managers of a major
northeast England retail centre relating to CSR communications found that both groups
shared a similar view of CSR. Furthermore, the most successful methods of communicating
techniques highly visible to users. Amongst these were the large-screen TV in the shopping
140
centre, centre brochures, signs within it as well as the actual ‘experience’, i.e., experience
from the interaction of stakeholders with the retail mall. From a theoretical point of view, this
emphasises the importance and relevance of the concept of customer involvement. The above
study also found that ‘‘…only a limited range of CSR activities were known to the
stakeholders as a whole and via a limited number of communication methods. This level of
communicated and evident to centre users’’ (Bowd et al., 2006, p. 152). A unique means of
communicating company CSR has been in the form of social responsibility disclosure
utilising marketing communications tools such as advertising and/or the Internet, and so
forth.
Recent press advertising by BP and Shell in the UK explaining carbon footprints and so forth
could not be taken seriously coming from companies whose products pollute the atmosphere
and which minimally invest in renewable energy. In a recent interview carried out by The
Guardian newspaper of the UK, Shell’s chief executive was asked: ‘‘is there any investment
you would make on ethical grounds?’’ (Monbiot, 2009). The chief executive was unable to
provide an example. The critics of advertising see, for instance, the creation of ‘hyper-reality’
by the media, where imagery replaces reality in the society, i.e. the gap between image and
Mellahi and Wood (2003) state that marketing managers have collectively gained the power
to shape the choices and lifestyles of large numbers of consumers. Such power could also be
used to alter existing ethical norms and/or manipulate them in the company’s interest. As for
public relations, it is invariably viewed with suspicion in the oft-ridiculed guise of ‘spin
doctoring’.
141
Ewen (2003) said that the history of public relations (PR) is one of a battle for what reality is
and how people will see and understand it. Public relations can be employed as a major
However, if one is to cite Grunig and White’s (1984) four models of public relations, perhaps
the ‘two-way symmetric’ approach would be an ideal choice. The more recent addition, i.e.
online communications in the form of websites and emails, has not been treated with any
more respect. Regarding CSR communications the examples of British American Tobacco
(BAT) and its social responsibility website or the British arms manufacturer BAE systems’
similarly titled web offerings further fuel suspicion, cynicism and derision. The World Health
Organisation (WHO) states that smoking causes more death and disability than any single
disease. Sadly, profit hungry companies are still permitted an unfettered trade, as well as
investing in branding designed to attract new customers as old ones die off (The Guardian
newspaper, 2008). The defence used by the tobacco companies refers to the advertising ban
that came into effect in the UK in 2003. Alternative means of covert ‘advertising’ have been
found by these firms. The flash of gold that transforms Marlboro Lights into a handbag
In the past, without making text-based claims about their products, visual imagery had been
used, such as the lone cowboy roaming the American West (Schroeder & Borgerson, 2005).
Pollach (2005), in her research on World Wide Web (WWW) and corporate self-presentation,
recommends that companies use a number of persuasive appeals, such as third-party evidence
themselves. Audience involvement can also be employed to remedy this problem. However,
at times, attitude change and image formation might be required to help improve the
situation. The former is required at times when an existing organisation attempts to alter
142
adverse perception of it and thus create loyalty amongst customers. The latter can benefit a
A more credible source might be an organisation that is well known for its CSR reputation.
2008, p. 80) reads in large lettering: ‘‘our green policies are so effective (that) other retailers
are recycling them’’. It says that it would be even more proud if more of its
organisation has been voted Britain’s greenest high-street retailer. This is related to its CSR
schools. A January 2008 press advertisement by the respectable Marks and Spencer (M&S)
company asked readers to take their unwanted M&S clothes to their local Oxfam, and receive
a £5 M&S voucher to use next time they spend £35 or more at a M&S store. What were the
To highlight their CSR credentials by encouraging recycling and helping Oxfam or to create
‘traffic’ in their stores by offering the £5 voucher? Why was there a minimum £35 clause
attached to this CSR effort? Banks and financial institutions do not usually come across as
heroes of morality or CSR. Social responsibility disclosure by six Irish banks and four
international institutions incorporating websites were examined by Douglas et al. (2004). The
findings suggested that the Irish financial institutions seemed to be lagging behind
Media choice
The choice of media for CSR information disclosure is dependent on the target audience.
Zeghal and Ahmed (1990) also add that the lower cost of producing and distributing
143
brochures allows organisations to treat in greater depth themes of special interest. Branco and
Rodrigues (2006, p. 235) suggest that ‘‘such reasoning can also be used when analysing
social responsibility disclosure through the internet…it is natural for companies to give
Pollach (2005) asserts that the WWW and corporate websites are superior to the conventional
mass media in a variety of ways. She cites the WWW’s capacity to transmit an unlimited
amount of information to all potential target audiences, making a reference to Sharp (2001).
Furthermore, Pollach views the WWW as a ‘pull’ medium, indicating that audiences tend to
have more control over what they wish to view compared with the traditional media. As
active information seekers, such audiences process the information available more effectively
than that accessed/offered via traditional media. In addition, messages conveyed to audiences
by organisations are not filtered by gatekeepers, but controlled by the firms themselves
(White & Raman, 1999). Ultimately the WWW provides organisations with the ability to
learn more about their stakeholders by offering interaction and encouraging dialogue. Added
to the usability of the WWW, Pollach (2005) includes credibility and value of the content as
further benefits. However, what Pollach fails to highlight is that, within the choppy oceans of
company websites, locating a beacon of trust, reliability and credibility becomes increasingly
difficult.
In the absence of media gatekeepers or watchdogs, people become more concerned with the
quality and reliability of web-based information, especially when attempting to put across an
ethically glossy corporate image. One method to overcome this mistrust is the provision of
government departments (Stewart, 2003). The reference to the M&S advert earlier
tactic. Other marketing communications tools are not immune to criticism. In the light of the
144
above, the task of the marketing communications manager is not easy and becomes even
more difficult when conveying CSR messages. For any communication to be successful,
source reliability and credibility are essential requirements. Therefore, the nature of the
industry and the company’s perceived image and reputation can play crucial roles in the
Furthermore, the company must also walk the talk, i.e. put words into action. Mere rhetoric
will not fool stakeholders. Overall, an integrated, co-ordinated and holistic approach is
required to ensure CSR communications can be effective. Basu and Palazzo’s (2008, p. 125)
CSR dimensions of the sense making process have the following constituent parts:
explanation of the second component, i.e. linguistics, might be useful here. As far as
justification is concerned, this is the manner in which firms justify their actions to
others or as Ferraro et al. (2005, p. 16) write: ‘‘how we talk about behaviour
fashion, where only positive results are made available. Balmer (2006), in his six ‘C’s
all those mix elements. The absence of or limited attention to one or more could
jeopardise the task of corporate marketing. Below is an explanation of the six ‘C’s:
145
known as corporate communication – ‘‘what we say we are’’ Conceptualisations, also
expected’’ For the purpose of marketing communications and CSR, missing from the
above model are the words consistency, integration and commitment. Messages
should be consistent, and whatever media are employed, the integration of marketing
crucial to the success of such endeavours. Senior management must view expenditure
This section views ethics in marketing from five main perspectives and addresses these issues
from theoretical angles. Understanding this section will help businesses and managers to plan
and implement morally justified relationship marketing operations. The agenda consists of
five parts:
146
The Ethics of Keeping Promises
Deontological ethics provides an appropriate perspective from which we may address and
elaborate the principle of keeping promises. The Kantian perspective suggests this duty as the
basic moral principle which should guide our behaviour. On the practical level, for example,
contract law is promise based. As the “promise principle” provides the moral basis for
contract law, it can be called the legalistic stance. Individuals’ mutual agreements and
It follows that people may voluntarily impose obligations on themselves in order to join
together for mutual advantage. This also includes co-operation: persons may work and act
together and fulfill their own and the other party’s goals and needs. While this kind of co-
operative relationship calls for trust, keeping promises is the means of generating trust. From
the utilitarian perspective it is not obligatory to keep promises if the outcome of an action
including promise violation will be better to most of the people than the outcome of an action
where promises are kept. Utilitarianism does not value people’s will to keep promises
whereas deontology regards this duty as indisputable. The promise principle rejects the
classical utilitarian model of contract as not reflecting contemporary law or legal values.
Business organizations following the promise principle would be morally obliged to keep
their promises regardless of whether or not they are legally binding (Gundlach and Murphy,
1993).
is the link between the manager, his/her position, and the organization. Managers usually
have several private and professional duties. The manager following relationship marketing
philosophy has duties typical for his profession, and thus the ethics of duty must be put
forward. Kantian ethics stresses action motivated by the moral will: an act is morally right if
147
instance, may face many controversial duties which are proper and favourable in certain
situations. However, he/she has to seek a balance between the interests of various
stakeholders with different requirements. Thus priorities must be defined and, for example,
the strict Kantian position does not offer a clear solution. There is, however, an alternative
possibility for solving the problem. The answer may be the prima-facie duties suggested by
Ross (1930). The most important duty is the duty of non-malfeasance. Thus the manager
must be able to ignore all his professional duties (i.e. duties created by his job) if the duty of
Truth telling is an issue often connected with the problems of keeping promises. As a general
maxim it is often stated that you must always tell the truth, nothing but the truth, nothing to
hide, nothing to add. This may be the ideal, but the practices of everyday life are more
complicated and demand more fluid solutions. Let us take a glance at what the different
positions of ethical theories are saying about this issue. If one takes a deontological stance,
one can say that you must tell the truth because “the moral will” demands it, despite the
A utilitarian may say that you must tell the truth only if the outcomes of truth-telling would
cause more happiness or utility to the greatest number of people, compared with not telling
the truth. But you cannot always know all the consequences of your actions. So it is difficult
to modify truth-telling rules (rule-utilitarianism) which would guide you to the best possible
outcomes, which maximize the utility for the majority. Could lying be a virtuous activity?
Virtue ethics offers us a model of virtues which we must obey in order to be moral. An
imaginary test: can we imagine a community of thieves in which lying is seen as a virtue? All
members of the community will lie to each other as much as possible. Further, we must ask if
148
the societal life is then possible at all. The answer is that lying destroys the basis of
communal life, because no one can trust another person’s promises or liabilities. Lying
The considerations mentioned above are quite abstract and the managers operate in the real
world in which all is not black and white. Usually he/she operates in the “grey” zone in which
moral and immoral activities lie near to each other. The manager must decide and act
casuistically; this means that the situation usually rules when he/she must to tell the truth. The
manager is not always able to tell the truth, but as the basic premise he/she is demanded, by
the moral theories, to act mostly honestly and tell the truth. Another interesting issue is the
telling of white lies. A manager may be forced to tell “white lies” for many reasons. He/she
could see the situation as one where his/her business is a source of pressure: “Other people
(in different organizations) tell lies, if I do not, I will miss my business opportunities, so I am
forced to lie”. Is this excuse good enough? In any case, we can try to give the manager some
advice and try to improve his/her decision situation. For example, we can draw on the
Rossian prima-facie duties mentioned earlier; thus one must draw up a schedule of duties to
obey with the order of preferences. A conditional maxim could be that one must never lie if
one can see the direct harm caused by this lying as being so severe that someone could die or
essential feature of action principles. The notion of fairness is widely recognized as essential
for mutually satisfying exchange. Fairness is also tied to the concept of distributive justice.
Furthermore, Kantian ethics stresses equal treatment of all human beings. Kant’s (1959) point
149
officials despair of immoral practices of corporations and denounce executives engaging in
Kant captures this conviction in what he calls the categorical imperative: “One ought never to
act unless one is willing to have the maxim on which one acts to become a universal law”.
Cheating, kickbacks, and bribes cannot be made universal laws. In reality, there are several
societies and business environments where bribery is the necessary practice for successful
and profitable firms. In spite of this, we cannot propose bribery as a general moral maxim.
According to Kant, such actions are universally and necessarily immoral, quite independent
of the desires and culture of the actor. In other words, the principle of equity arises: “treat
other people like you wish to be treated yourself”. Treat all your clients in the same manner
affective attachment to an organization, the intensity of which can vary with the nature of the
identification with, and his/her involvement in, the organization. It is characterized by three
factors. First, stability refers to a strong belief in and acceptance of the organization’s goals
and values. Second, sacrifice means a willingness to exert considerable effort for the benefit
stability business transactions are not possible. Stability presupposes trust, and only mutual
trust can be the cornerstone of successful business organization’s activities. Sacrifice means a
way to sacrifice one’s situational benefit for the sake of the business partner. Through this,
150
commitment to business springs up and good conditions are created for long-term
relationship. Loyalty is necessary for running successful operations. Loyalty means getting
et al., 1979). The ethical question handles the means by which commitment is attained. Some
instruments used by managers, for example strong persuasive elements, persuasive rhetoric or
some psychological tricks, are obviously immoral. To avoid such practices, the golden rule
“do unto others, as you would have others do unto you” is a good guide.
Ethics of Communication
The German social philosopher Habermas (1993) has put forth a theory of communicative
action. It is called “The theory of distorted communication” and includes some strong
The theory displays a rational way to proceed in communication practices; it assumes that it
is possible for the parties to achieve an agreement by using effective negotiating mechanisms
(Habermas, 1993). The basic idea is that every individual has the right to domination-free
Conclusion
In short, marketing communications can be employed for ethical and corporate social
responsibility purposes. It acknowledged the negative perception that consumers and many
The proliferation of ethical and green claims by companies, some of which appear in the so-
151
called ‘sin industries’ category, has contributed to growing consumer scepticism of such CSR
In Ghana, the mining sector is applauded for its significant contribution to the growth of the
Ghanaian economy and therefore, these companies are celebrated. However, the very
activities of these companies are a nuisance and a threat to human society through
part, has been used as a glowing example of a financial institution that offers the customer an
ethical choice. Its communications with the stakeholders could be suggested perhaps as more
Its press advertising was used in this paper to emphasise the usability of marketing
source credibility and reliability were also cited as major requirements for CSR message
acceptance and communications effectiveness. Examples used from the so-called ‘sin
industries’, such as tobacco manufacturers, oil companies and car producers, desperately
There is still a great deal of public scepticism and suspicion in relation to CSR per se. For
Watch 2006 Report makes similar comments. The latter states that ‘‘like the iceberg, most
rather than simply a defensive ‘image management’ operation’’. However, the examples of
the purchase of the Body Shop, Ben & Jerry’s and Green and Black’s by multi-national
Communications will be essential to their survival, as well as maintaining ethical image (and
152
Advertising, PR and sponsorship (cause related marketing) have the potential to make major
manner is absolutely crucial. ‘Shotgun weddings’ may lead to acrimonious divorces and
expenses.
CHAPTER EIGHT
153
HR AND ETHICS
As HR decisions largely affect human beings, subjecting them to ethical analysis has
employment contract was terminated fairly; whether performance was fairly assessed etc. In
this chapter, students will be taken through critical HR issues and therefore, would be
Analyze HR decisions from the point of view of justice/fairness, rights and duties, and
utilitarian perspective
Introduction
A job is much more than an assigned task in an organization or a source of income. It is also
for many people a part of their self-identity, a source of social connections, a source of
important financial benefits such as health insurance and retirement income, and more.
Managerial actions that terminate an individual’s employment have major repercussions for
that individual. Specifically, some of the responsibilities of managers are to choose new
employees from a pool of applicants, assess performance as well as terminate the contract of
engagement between the employer and employee. With respect to job placement, if there is
one open position and there are several applicants, then a valuable resource (the job) will be
awarded to one applicant and denied to others. Anyone who has anxiously awaited the results
of their application and interview for a job knows that what happens here matters. There are
consequences that make the successful applicant happy and satisfied and the unsuccessful
applicants unhappy and dissatisfied. As long as the manager makes the choice, he is making a
decision, in the role of manager that has ethical implications both for the new employee and
154
The hiring process
Let us assume that only one open position exists and that its scope is already determined. Let
us also assume that minimum qualifications for the job have been established and have been
made known to the applicants. Let us further assume that the open position has been
advertised or posted in some manner and that a number of individuals have applied for the
position. Finally, let us assume that more than one applicant meets the minimum
qualifications for the job. There are obviously cases where one or more of these assumptions
will not hold true, but the assumptions as stated will let us make an initial examination of the
To start with, the primary reason why a manager has his/her job is not to be fair, but to
contribute through her section or department or division to the success of the company. So,
when a manager is in the position of selecting a new employee from a pool of qualified
candidates, the primary goal of the decision is to contribute to the success of the company.
The hiring decision has two broad implications for the unit’s and the company’s success: (a)
the person chosen should be the one most likely to perform well in the job for which he is
being hired and (b) the pattern of hiring decisions, in the unit and in the company at large,
Once the most qualified candidates have been identified, the hiring manager must still make a
decision. From the conversation with hiring managers, such decisions are often made based
on what is called “chemistry”. This seems to mean personal intuition, in practice. In other
words, there are no objective, measurable job-related criteria on which the candidates differ,
yet something tells the hiring manager to offer the job to one candidate rather than to another.
Suppose that he prefers working with women and one of the qualified applicants is a woman.
Is it morally acceptable for him to hire her on this basis? If his department or unit has very
155
few female employees, or for that matter, very few male employees, there may be
Problems arise if a series of hiring decisions is based on these personal criteria. Suppose that
manager who prefers working with attractive women has, over a period of time, seven
different hiring decisions to make as natural turnover occur. On each occasion, there are
several qualified candidates and one of these in each case is an attractive woman. Eventually,
this manager will be presiding over a work unit made up entirely of attractive women. There
now appears to be a pattern of discrimination against male and less attractive women.
Utilitarian view
Utilitarianism says that the moral act is the one that creates the greatest good for the greatest
number of people. Using this approach, the manager who is trying to decide which hiring
choice is most ethical will examine the impacts of that hiring choice. Obviously, the
candidate who is hired will experience happiness and feel that he/she has been the recipient
of good. If the manager feels that he has made the best choice, he also will experience
happiness. There is no way to know for sure that any candidate will work out in practice, but
if the manager is able to hire a candidate who meets the minimum qualifications for the job
and appears to be the best candidate in the pool, there is at least a reasonable chance for
success. The manager may also feel a certain degree of happiness because the search is over,
the position is filled and he can get on with other things. Managers are partly evaluated on
their ability to choose new employees, since this is a key part of their jobs. If the new
employee succeeds, the hiring manager also gains by reason of having made a good hire.
156
The candidates who are not hired are also impacted by the decision. Even though they will
probably feel unhappiness at failing to get an offer of the job, they may or may not find
another job that suits them as well or better. It is good for the hiring manager to remember,
though, that those rejected for the position will feel rejected. To the extent that they
understand the hiring process, if they perceive that it was fair, their unhappiness at not getting
the job may be somewhat reduced. The other employees in the unit, who will work with the
new hire, will gain happiness if the choice was a good one and the new employee proves to
be successful. They will suffer unhappiness to the extent that this is not the case.
Thus, the utilitarian approach requires the hiring manager to think about the consequences
that may extend for months or years after the decision is made, especially when the position
At the individual’s disposal are four rights: human rights, legal rights, position rights and
contract rights. In considering the rights and duties approach to employment situation, focus
will be on legal and position rights. To start with, there is no human right to a job. If there
were, someone or some organization would have a corresponding duty to provide a job to
each person. Position rights are rights that an individual holds by reason of their position,
such as police officer or chief financial officer. The position of the applicant does not entitle
an individual to a job, although it does entitle an individual to be treated fairly in the selection
process, and it establishes that employers have a corresponding duty to treat all applicants
fairly. Finally, an individual can have a contractual right to keep a job once it is attained, but
he/she does not have a contractual right to obtain a job. Similarly, individuals do not have a
legal right to be placed in a given job, but in the United States and some other countries, they
do have a legal right to be treated fairly as applicants in the employment process. The right of
157
the applicant to be treated fairly corresponds to a duty of the hiring manager to treat all
applicants fairly. There is also a duty of the human resources department, where one exists, to
see that hiring procedures provide for fair treatment of all applicants and that these
procedures are, in fact, followed by hiring managers. Thus, one obtains the rights of an
applicant simply by applying for a job. Fair treatment for qualified applicants is different
Under this perspective, we defined the moral act as the one that treats similarly situated
people in a similar manner, with regard to both process and outcome. When applied to
employment decision, this is obviously a perspective that has relevance. This perspective
posits that similar treatment is not the same as exactly equal treatment. Accordingly, the
fairness and justice view stipulates that similar treatment is owed to similarly situated people,
Broadly speaking, since the main reason for hiring a person into a vacancy is the expectation
that the person hired will be the best contributor to the success of the work unit by
performing well, it is reasonable to determine what minimum set of knowledge and skills the
person hired should bring to the position. People who lack the minimum knowledge and
skills to perform the job successfully are not similarly situated compared to those who have
the skills. It is fair and just to make this distinction and to make it early in the hiring process.
Some applicants who lack the required skill and knowledge will plead that they really can do
the job, if just given the chance. That task of the hiring manager, though, is to hire the
applicant most likely to succeed in the position. If the minimum qualifications have been
158
determined reasonably, then using these as the first screen to eliminate unqualified applicants
is quite fair.
It sometimes happens that a hiring manager will review a pool of applicants and identify one
or two, saying something like this: “Gee, they don’t meet the minimum qualifications, but
they are very strong in some areas, and I know personally that they are really dependable, so
let’s include them anyway. “ A moment’s reflection will show that what this actually means
is that the minimum qualifications are really not that at all, but a sort of guideline to be
ignored based on the manager’s individual judgment of each candidate. While the setting of
minimum qualifications is probably as much art as science, if they have any meaning for
screening candidates, they must apply to all candidates. Perhaps they are set wrong and
dependability should be allowed to substitute for education or experience. If that is the case,
they should be changed and the new standards should be applied uniformly to the entire
applicant pool. Otherwise, similarly situated people will not be treated in a similar way.
In the normal case, the original pool of applicants will be separated into two groups: those
who meet the minimum qualifications for the position and those who do not. Since the two
Promotion
Assume a job opening is to be filled by promotion instead of by outside hiring. Suppose the
open position is that of supervisor. The hiring manager surveys the employees currently
working in the section that has the open supervisory position, selects the best technician
(accountant, claims examiner, engineer) in the section and promotes him to supervisor. In this
situation, the newly promoted supervisor does not perform well as supervisor and ends up
either being demoted to his former position as a technician or leaving the company entirely.
159
The section has lost a good technician, at least temporarily, and gained a poor supervisor.
The job of supervisor requires different skills than the job of technician. A good technician
knows a lot about some technical area and can apply his knowledge easily to the work at
hand. It could be said that he works best in a world the size of a computer monitor. A good
supervisor is aware of what is going on around him. He knows who is doing what throughout
his section. He is comfortable interfacing with other supervisors, with bosses and with the
people in the section. He switches easily from training a new employee to meeting with the
department’s other supervisors, to working on budget forms. He has a sense of how his
section’s work contributes to the larger efforts of the rest of the company. He is able to adapt
Utilitarian Analysis
promoted, there is a reasonable chance that he will not perform adequately in the new job. If
this occurs, it will result eventually in his removal from the job, after a period of poor
performance. This period of poor performance will most probably be a difficult and unhappy
time for the employee, for those he oversees and for his boss. If he does perform well, he may
well have to overcome obstacles presented by the initial expectation of those he supervises
that he will fail because he lacks qualifications. This period of proving himself will be a time
of struggle for the new supervisor, which he may or may not enjoy. It will probably be an
anxious time for those he supervises and for the boss who promoted him and is observing the
struggle. In neither case is it likely that the promotion will result in the greatest good for the
greatest number.
160
Rights and Duties Analysis
From the purview of rights and duties, an employee does not have a right to promotion
simply by being an employee. He also does not obtain such a right by performing well in his
present job. If managers had a duty to promote all employees who well, many organizations
would soon become exceedingly top-heavy. Senior managers who perform well would have
to be promoted to even more senior positions. Finally, what would we do with CEOs who
perform well? As earlier discussed, employees have a right to be treated fairly if they apply
for a promotion; just as other applicants for the position have a similar right. They do not
have a right, by their position as employee, to extra consideration (unless being an employee
is a legitimate qualification for the job) or to be awarded the job simply because of their
status as employee.
Here, the issue turns on whether the current employee is similarly situated as an applicant
with other applicants from outside the company. Again, assuming that the company does not
have a policy of promoting only from within, and assuming that the similarly situated group
is defined as those having similar qualifications, then the inside employee should be seen as a
member of the applicant pool, or a qualified member of the applicant pool. If, for legitimate
job-related reasons, inside candidates are preferred, then the employee is not similarly
situated with outside candidates, and fairness does not require treating him in a similar
manner in terms of the selection process. This is because fairness and justice requires that
similarly situated people be treated similarly regarding both process and outcome.
There are benefits to promoting good employees in terms of company loyalty and
encouraging other present employees to work hard and strive for promotion within the
qualified is offered the open position. It is unfair to offer the position to those significantly
less qualified or unqualified simply because they currently work for the company and
perform well in their present position (in the case of the unqualified applicants, they will
Introduction
factors. However, these are different bases for making compensation decisions, and the
rationally. Managers generally seem to prefer merit systems, whereby at least part of any
environments, seem to prefer some basis other than merit, so that individual managers will
have no say in which workers receive how much increase in their compensation.
Compensation increase will be granted to some or all the employees reporting to a manager,
and the basis for such increases and their amounts will be the manager’s evaluation of each
employee’s performance during a specified period. There are several reasons why managers
have as part of their job the evaluation of employees who report to them. One is related to
compensation increases. Another is to identify workers who are not performing adequately
and either help them to improve their performance or remove them from their jobs. Another
162
is to identify particularly promising or high-performing employees and prepare them for
promotion if they seem capable of performing in a higher position. Still another reason why
performance evaluation is part of a manager’s job is that almost everyone could do their job
What sort of uses might be made of performance appraisals? First of all, they may be used to
determine compensation increases. They may also be used to identify promising employees
in order to prepare them for higher positions. They may be used for progressive discipline
(graduated warnings leading to possible termination for poor performance). They may be
used in case of layoffs etc. In total, these uses of performance appraisals have a lot to do with
how a company manages its human resources. If all of this is based on lies, things are clearly
not as they should be, and smart managers will no longer rely on performance appraisals as a
source of valid information. For this very negative consequence to occur, it is not necessary
that all, or most, or even half of the performance appraisals contain lies. It is enough that
lying is known or suspected to occur with some frequency for smart managers to decrease or
cease their reliance on the whole performance appraisal system for information.
Employees will sense that lying is occurring. If they are rated higher than their performance
deserves, they are very unlikely to complain. They are more likely to make note of the fact
that their manager is either too dumb to see their real performance or too dishonest to report
it.
163
Utilitarian Analysis
Once again, utilitarianism defines the moral act as the one that produces the greatest good for
happiness for many of those who receive them. Some employees will undoubtedly feel that
they deserved a greater increase than they received but, on the whole, appropriate increases
will produce employee happiness. Such increases will also tend to keep employees
reasonably motivated and loyal to their employer. This is good for the organization as a
whole.
appraisals in a professional and reasonable way. In addition, they have the obligation to be
truthful on performance appraisals. This is where the pattern perspective comes in. It does not
create the greatest good for anyone if the performance appraisal system is permeated with
lies.
This perspective says that the moral act is the one that recognizes the rights of others and the
duties those rights impose on the actor. The actor here is the manager, and the rights of
employees being evaluated, as well as other users of the performance appraisal system, are at
issue. Employees, as humans, have the right to be told the truth about their work performance
by their work supervisor. This right means that managers have a duty to tell employees the
truth on their performance appraisals. Since most performance appraisals forms include a
164
section called something like “areas needing improvement,” most performance appraisal
interviews will include some discussion that amounts to criticism of the current performance.
Thus, managers have a duty to tell employees all these things and to discuss not only what the
employee does well but also what the employee can do to improve his performance. That fact
that this is not an easy conversation to have does not mean that the manager is justified in
omitting it. From a pattern perspective, the manager has a duty, by his/her position, to obtain
good performance from those people that she manages, or to remove them if they cannot or
will not perform well. The only way that this can be done is one person at a time, and one
unit. However, the right of an employee is not to a certain amount of compensation increase
(in a merit system) but to be treated fairly in terms of the amount of increase.
Under the fairness and justice perspective, the moral act is the one that treats similarly
situated people in similar ways regarding both process and outcome and with a sense of
proportionality. It does not say that everyone should be treated equally. To evaluate
employees fairly means that their performance must be judged based on similar standards if
Accomplishing this is a challenge for those who supervise service workers, but it is part of
their job. A more difficult question still is how to reward or compensate similarly situated
employees in similar ways. Part of deciding who is similarly situated involves setting up job
165
descriptions. This is typically the responsibility of the human resources department, with
input from supervisor or manager of the unit where the jobs are being evaluated.
Termination
or unknown, there remains a question of whether it is ethical to treat them differently from
important to help and retain long-term employees than others, then the greatest good for the
greatest number might be achieved by making some extra effort to correct the situation when
termination is not under consideration here. If the employee can be brought back to their
previous satisfactory level of performance, the employee benefits by not losing their job, the
company benefits by retaining a good employee who is experienced and the only unhappiness
caused is to those affected during the employee’s period of unsatisfactory performance. Some
of this would be true of any employee and the aim of progressive discipline is to improve
It is difficult to argue that an employee has a right to special treatment in a situation where
performance has deteriorated, simply because he has been employed by the same company
for a long time. If we take the system perspective, managers have a duty to see that their units
operate well and that their individual decisions support patterns of decision-making that are
favourable to the company. If it is a good thing to encourage good employees to stay with the
decisions are the only way to create and maintain this pattern.
Fairness and justice would ask first whether long-term employees are similarly situated with
other employees. If they are, the conclusion is clear: they are to be treated similarly. Although
166
institutional memory is critical and long-term employees tend to possess institutional
memory, the deterioration in their performance suggests that the organization cannot rely on
them again.
References
Gilbert, J. (2012). Ethics for managers. Philosophical Foundations and Business Realities.
Rowan, J., Zinaich, Jr. S. (2003). Ethics for the Professions. Wadsworth, Cengage Learning.
Budd, J.W. (2004). Employment with a Human Face Balancing Efficiency, Equity, and
Voice. Cornell University Press.
167
Carroll, A.B. (1991). The Pyramid of Corporate Social Responsibility: Toward the Moral
Management of Organizational Stakeholders, London: Business Horizons.
Cullen, J.B., Parboteeah, K.P., and Victor, B. (2003). The Effect of Ethical Climates on
Organizational Commitment: A Two–Study Analysis Journal of Business Ethics, 46,127-141.
De Gorge, R.T. (2010). Business ethics, Upper Saddle River, N.J.: Pearson, Prentice Hall.
Douglas, S.C., & M.J. Martinko (2001) Exploring The Role of Individual Differences in the
Prediction of Workplace Aggression. Journal of Applied Psychology, 86, 547-559.
Ferrell, O. C., & J. Fraedrich (1991) Business Ethics: Ethical Decision Making and Causes.
Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.
Fisher, C. & A. Lovell (2006) Business Ethics and Values: Individual, Corporate and
International Perspectives, Pearson Education Ltd, England
Fletcher, Joseph (1966) Situational Ethics: the New Morality. Westminister Press,
Philadelphia
Freeman, R.E. & Gilbert, D.E. (1988). Corporate Strategy and the Search for Ethics, UK:
Prentice Hall.
Fritzsche, D.J., and Oz, E. (2007). Personal Values' Influence on the Ethical Dimensions of
Decision Making. Journal of Business Ethics, 75: 335-343.
Fritzsche, D.J. (2004). Business Ethics: A Global and Managerial Perspective McGraw–Hill
Irwin, Burr Ridge, IL.
Fritzsche, D.J., & Becker, H. (1983). Ethical Behavior of Marketing Managers. Journal of
Business Ethics, 2: 291-299.
Fritzsche, D.J., & Becker, H. (1984). Linking Management Behavior to Ethical Philosophy-
An Empirical Investigation. Academy of Management Journal, 27(1): 166-175.
Fulmer, R.F. (2004). The Challenge of Ethical Leadership. Organizational Dynamics, 33,
307-317.
168
Habermas, J. (1993), “Morality, society and ethics”, Acta Sociologica, Vol. 33 No. 2, pp. 93-
114.
Harvey, N. P. (2006). The Justification of Unethical Behavior: An Attributional Perspective.
An unpublished dissertation submitted to the Department of Management, Florida State
University, College of Business. In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of
Doctor of Philosophy.
Johnson, R.A. (2003) Whistle-blowing: When it works – and why. Boulder, CO: Lynne
Rienner.
Kant, I. (1959) Foundation of the Metaphysics of Morals (translated by Lewis White), Bobbs-
Merrill, New York.
Loo, R. (2003) Are Women More Ethical Than Men? Findings from Three Independent
Studies, in Women in Management Review. Vol. 18, No.4 pp 169-181
Malovics, G., Noemi, N.C. & Sascha, K. (2007), ‘‘The Role of Corporate Social
Responsibility in Strong Sustainability’’, The Journal of Socio-economics, pp. 1-12.
McWilliams, A. & Siegel, D. (2001), ‘‘Corporate Social Responsibility: a theory of the firm
perspective’’,The Academy of Management Review, Vol. 26 No. 1, pp. 117-27.
Modway, R., Porter, L. & Steers, R. (1979), “The measurement of organizational
commitment”, Journal of Vocational Behaviour, Vol. 14, pp. 224-47.
Reeck, D. (1982) Ethics for the Professions. Augsburg Publishing House. Mineapolis.
Nielsen, R. P., and Lee, J., (2003) Reframing Organizational Ethics from Isolated Individual
to Participative Citizenship Responsibility. Working Paper, Boston College.
169
Nielsen, Richard P. (1993) “Woolman’s ‘I Am We” Triple-Loop, Action-Learning: Origin
and Application in Organization Ethics,” Journal of Applied Behavioral Science, 29, 1,
March, 1993, pp. 117-138.
Rest, J.R. (1979). Development in Judging Moral Issues. University of Minnesota Press,
Minneapolice, MN.
Rest, J.R. (1984). Research on Moral Development: Implications for Training Psychologics.
The Counseling Psychologist, 12: 19-30.
Rest, J.R. (1986). Moral Development: Advances in Research and Theory. New York
Praeger, NY.
Solomon, R.C. (1984). Morality and the Good Life, UK: Peason.
Sims, R.R. (1992), ‘‘The challenge of ethical behavior in organizations’’, Journal of Business
Ethics, Vol. 11 No. 7, pp. 505-13.
Steiner, G.A. & Steiner, J.F. (2000), Business, Government and Society: A Managerial
Perspective, McGraw-Hill, Maidenhead.
Sullivan, R.J. (1989). Immanuel Kant's Moral Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Svensson, G. & Wood, G. (2008), “A model of business ethics”, Journal of Business Ethics,
Vol. 77 No. 3, pp. 103-18.
Trevino, L.K. (1992). Moral Reasoning and Business Ethics: Implications for Research,
Education and Management. Journal of Business Ethics, 11, 445-459.
Trevino, L.K. & Ball, G.A. (1992). The Social Implications of Punishing Unethical Behavior:
Observers' Cognitive and Affective Reactions. Journal of Management, 18: 751-768.
Trevino, L.K., Butterfield, K.D., & McCabe, D.L. (1998). The Ethical Context in
Organizations: Influences on Employee Attitudes and Behavior. Business Ethics Quarterly,
8(3): 447-476.
Tsalikis, J., & D.J. Fritzsche (1989) Business Ethics: A Literature Review with a Focus on
Marketing Ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 8, 695-743.
Tsalikis, J., B.Seaton, & P. Tomaras (2002) A New Perspective on Cross-Cultural Ethical
Evaluations: The Use of Conjoint Analysis. Journal of Business Ethics, 35, 281-293.
Velasquez, M.G. (2009). Business Ethics: Concepts and Cases, New York: Prentice Hall.
170
Velasquez, M.G. (2002) Business Ethics, Concepts and Cases. Fifth edition. Prentice Hall.
Victor, B. & Cullen, J.B. (1988). The Organizational Bases of Ethical Work Climates.
Administrative Science Quarterly, 33(1), 101-125.
Vitell, S.J. & Paolillo, J.G.P. (2004). A Cross-Cultural Study of the Antecedents of the
Perceived role of Ethics and Social Responsibility Business Ethics: A European Review,
WBCSD (1999), Corporate Social Responsibility, World Business Council for Sustainable
Development.
Wotruba, T.R., Chonko, L.B. & Loe, T.W. (2001), “The impact of ethics code familiarity on
manager behavior”. Journal of Business Ethics, Vol. 33 No. 1, pp. 59-69.
Woode, S.N (1997) Values Standards and Practices in Ghanaian Organisational Life,
Asempa Publishers, Accra
Woode, S.N (1998). Ethical Dilemmas and Moral Temptations: Cases in Administration,
Asempa Publishers, Accra.
171