Principal and Agent: Joseph E. Stiglitz
Principal and Agent: Joseph E. Stiglitz
Principal and Agent: Joseph E. Stiglitz
JOSEPH E. STIGLITZ
The principal-agent literature is concerned with how one individual, the principal
(sayan employer), can design a compensation system (a contract) which motivates
another individual, his agent (say the employee), to act in the principal's interests.
The term principal-agent problem is due to Ross (1973). Other early contributions
to this literature include Mirrlees (1974, 1976) and Stiglitz (1974, 1975).
A principal-agent problem arises when there is imperfect information, either
concerning what action the agent has undertaken or what he should undertake.
In many situations, the actions of an individual are not easily observable. It
would be very difficult for a landlord to monitor perfectly the weeding activity
of his tenant. A bank cannot monitor perfectly the actions of those to whom it
lends money. The employer cannot travel on the road with his salesman, to
monitor precisely the effort he puts into his salesmanship. In each of these
situations, the agent's (tenant's, borrower's, employee's) action affects the
principal (landlord, lender, employer). Clearly, if an individual's actions are
unobservable, then compensation cannot be based on those actions. In some cases,
even if an individual's actions are not directly observable, it may be possible to
infer his actions. Thus, if output were a function just of effort [Q = F(e)] then
even if effort were unobservable, if output were observable, and the relationship
between output and effort were known, then effort could be inferred with perfect
accuracy.
The principal-agent literature focuses on situations where an individual's
actions can neither be observed nor be perfectly inferred on the basis of observable
variables; thus, for instance, it is usually assumed that output is a function of
effort and an unobservable random variable, 0: Q = F(e, 0).
Moreover, in many circumstances, the principal wishes the agent to take actions
based on information which is available to the agent, not the principal. Indeed,
this is the very reason that individuals delegate responsibility. Because of the
asymmetry of information, the principal does not know whether the agent
241
Allocation, Information and Markets
undertook the action the principal would himself have undertaken, in the given
circumstances. Hence, even if the principal can observe the action, he may not
know whether that action was appropriate.
Since, in general, the pay-offs to the agent will differ from those to the principal,
the agent will not in general take the action which the principal would like him
to take, or that they would contract for in the presence of perfect information.
For instance, the employee may not adjust his effort as the situation requires, or
he may engage in too much or too little risk taking.
The principal-agent problem is, then, the central problem of economic
incentives.
In spite of the importance attached to economic incentives, until recently
economic theory had little to say on the matter. In the standard theory, individuals
were paid for performing a particular task. If they performed the task, they
received their compensation; if they failed to perform the task, they did not.
Individuals thus always had an incentive to perform the contracted-for service.
Only if the employer were so foolish as to pay the worker whether he performed
the task or not would an incentive problem arise.
The standard theory was based on the assumption that what action the
'principal' wished his agent to perform was perfectly known, and that the action
could be perfectly and costlessly monitored. Neither assumption is plausible and,
indeed, relatively few workers are paid solely on the basis of their observed inputs.
242
Principal and Agent
hazard problem (see Arrow, 1965), and, by extension, the term has been applied
to the principal-agent problem more generally.
Similarly, in credit relationships, one individual gives another some resource
(money), in return for a promise to repay that money at some later date. So long
as there is some probability of default, which can be affected by the actions of
the borrower, there is a moral hazard or principal-agent problem (provided that
that action cannot be perfectly monitored by the lender).
Many economic relationships have an important element of insurance within
them. The landlord-tenant sharecropping relationship can be viewed as if the
tenant pays a fixed rent, and then receives an insurance policy from the landlord,
in which the landlord agrees to pay the tenant a certain amount if output is low
(equal to the difference between his share and the fixed rent); and the tenant
agrees to pay a premium equal again to the difference between the share and the
fixed rent, when output is high.
Indeed, the credit 'problem' can be viewed as a special form of an insurance
relationship: the lender provides an insurance policy, such that if the borrower's
resources are less than the amount owed, the lender agrees to pay the borrower
the difference (which the borrower then immediately repays to the lender). The
premium is the difference between the rate of interest on a perfectly safe loan
and the rate of interest charged on this risky loan.
Insurance (spreading and transferring risk) provides one of the explanations
of sharecropping; were workers to rent the land, they would have to absorb all
the risk associated with output variations. With sharecropping, the risk is shared
between the landlord and the tenant. Since the wealth of tenants is usually much
less than that of landlords, there is some presumption that the landlords are
better able to absorb this risk.
But even if the tenants were risk neutral, there might be a principal-agent
problem. We suggested above that if the landlord were to rent his land to the
tenant, there would be no principal-agent problem. But this is not quite correct.
If the tenant did not have sufficient resources to pay the rent before production,
then the landlord would have to lend the tenant the money. (If he receives the
rent at the end of the period, then it is as if he is lending the individual the
money.) And then, if there are actions which the individual can undertake which
affect the likelihood of not being able to repay the debt (pay the rent), then there
is a moral hazard problem.
There is a second reason why renting land might not solve the moral hazard
problem. There may be actions which the tenant can take which affect the quality
of the land. To the extent that those actions are monitorable, the rental agreement
may specify the actions to be undertaken (e.g. concerning what crops are to be
grown, or grazing patterns). But these actions are not perfectly monitorable, and
thus, even with rental agreements there are important principal-agent problems.
(The same issues arise, of course, with the rental of any durable good.)
Again, one should ask, cannot these principal-agent problems be alleviated,
e.g. by selling the asset. But this entails precisely the two problems we identified
before as giving rise to principal-agent relationships: The agent (tenant,
243
Allocation, Information and Markets
employee) may not have sufficient capital (and thus must borrow to make the
purchase, creating a credit principal-agent problem); and if there is any risk
associated with the future value of the land, it imposes a risk on the agent. Any
attempt to alleviate those risks (through insurance) again gives rise to a moral
hazard problem.
The third major source of principal-agent relationships is rather different. It
arises from the attempt of the principal to extract as much rent (surplus) from
the agent as possible. The employer does not know how difficult the task is that
he would like the worker to perform. He could pay the worker the full value of
his output, but that would leave him no profits. He might pay much less, but
that might result in the worker refusing to work, ifthe task is in fact quite difficult;
and thus he would lose profits that he might otherwise obtain. This rent extraction
problem has been particularly well studied in the context of public utilities: the
government does not know the minimum amount of compensation required to
keep the utility producing. The rent extraction problem may be alleviated within
competitive environments by holding auctions: the individual for whom the asset
(franchise) is most valuable will bid the most. But there may not be enough
bidders to extract all the rents through an auction mechanism; and at least in
the case of utilities, the government may care not only about the rents received,
but also about the actions undertaken by the franchisee. (In some cases, the rent
extraction problem and the insurance problem are closely related: the average
value of rents received may be increased if rents can be varied with the weather,
the state of nature; again, we can think of decomposing the rent payment into
a fixed rent and an insurance payment.)
This list of reasons for the origins of principal-agent relations is not meant
to be exhaustive: yet many of the other reasons cited may be reduced to one of
these explanations. For instance, consider the problem of a production line on
which there are many workers; the output of the production line depends on all
of their efforts. In the absence of risk aversion and credit problems, the incentive
problem could be solved by giving each worker the total value of net output.
He would purchase the right to the job by paying a fixed fee. With such a
compensation scheme, the worker would have full incentives for maximizing the
firm's output. But such a compensation scheme imposes on the worker an
intolerable level of risk; and the fixed fee he would be required to pay necessitates
his borrowing large amounts of money.
244
Principal and Agent
V= L V;(h;)Pi(e).
i
245
Allocation, Information and Markets
recognizing the dependence of the agent's action on </> and recognizing that he
must pay the agent enough to induce him to accept the job,
EU~ 0. (RU)
POOLING VERSUS SEPARATING EQUILIBRIUM. Much of the literature has focused
on situations where the principal wishes to induce the agent to take different
actions in different states. That is, in the simplest case where only output is
observable by the principal, if A*(S) is the action desired in state S, then the
compensation scheme must be such that
EU[</>(Q(A*, S», A*, S] ~ EU[(Q(A, S», A, S] for all feasible A.
These constraints are referred to as the self-selection or incentive compatibility
constraints.
When the individual takes actions in two different states, so that the observable
variables are the same, i.e. so that the principal cannot distinguish which of the
two states has occurred, we say that there is a pooling equilibrium. When the
individual takes actions so that the principal can identify which state has occurred,
we say that there is a separating equilibrium. (This terminology was introduced
within the context of the adverse selection literature by Rothschild and Stiglitz
(1976).) A basic result of the principal-agent literature establishes conditions
under which the optimal contract involves complete or partial separation.
ADVERSE SELECTION. The variable S can be thought of as a characteristic of an
individual, rather than as the state of nature. Then the self-election constraint
says that individuals of type S prefer action A(S) to any other feasible action.
If the self-selection constraints are satisfied, we can identify who is of what type.
The action may consist of nothing more than making a choice. In the adverse
selection interpretations of the model, the constraint (RU) needs to be replaced
by the set of constraints,
U(</>(Q(A,S»,A,S)~ O(S), for all s
246
Principal and Agent
that is, there is a reservation utility level for each individual (an individual
rationality constraint for each type). (Note that a similar set of constraints is
relevant if the contractual arrangement between the principal and agent is not
binding, i.e. the individual can quit after he sees what the state of nature is.)
Some examples follow.
(i) The partially discriminating monopoly (see, e.g. Salop, 1977; Stiglitz, 1977).
The firm knows that different individuals have different indifference curves
between the good he sells and other goods, and different reservation utility levels,
but he does not know who is of which type. Q may be the quantity of some
commodity chosen by an individual in which case ¢(Q) can be interpreted as
the payment to the monopolist. (If one individual unambiguously has stronger
preferences for the good, in the sense that at any quantity and payment, the extra
amount he is willing to pay for a marginal unit is greater, then some separation
is always desirable; this property is called the single crossing property.)
(ii) Optimal tax structures (Mirrlees, 1971). The government wishes to impose
differential taxation on different individuals; it may want to impose a higher tax
on the more able, but cannot tell who is the more able. Neither the individual's
productivity nor the number of hours a week he works is observable, but his
income is observable. The income tax schedule specifies a level of consumption
corresponding to each level of income. The individual chooses (by the amount
of work he undertakes) a point on that schedule. A schedule which results in the
more able earning (choosing) higher incomes is one which separates. This will
be desirable if the indifference curves between consumption and income are flatter
for the more able - they require less of an increase in consumption to compensate
for an increase in income. This will be true, for instance, if the underlying
indifference curves between hours worked and consumption are the same for all
individuals.
(iii) Pareto efficient tax structures (Stiglitz, 1982a). In the previous problem,
the government maximized the sum of utilities, subject to the self-selection
constraints, the revenue constraints and the individual rationality constraints
(which simply required that the individual desire to work). The revenue constraint
was equivalent, in this problem, to the profits (revenues) of the landlord; that is,
while in the landlord problem we maximize the revenue, subject to the expected
utility of the individual satisfying a certain constraint, here the dual ofthis problem
is analysed. The 'sum of utilities' is equivalent to 'expected utility' - where the
probability of each state S is identical. We can directly generalize this by imposing
constraints on the level of utility attained by all individuals other than the first;
we then maximize the first individual's utility subject to these constraints (and
subject to the self-selection constraints, and the revenue constraints). This is the
problem of Pareto efficient taxation. It is equivalent to the problem of maximizing
a weighted sum of individuals' utilities.
(iv) Implicit contracts with asymmetric information. (For surveys, see Hart, 1983;
Stiglitz, 1986; Azariadis and Stiglitz, 1983.) With perfect information, the
employer would provide insurance to the employee, to stabilize the employee's
income. If, for instance, the workers' utility function was separable between hours
247
Allocation, Information and Markets
VARIANTS OF THE GENERAL MODEL. Further results have been obtained for various
variants of the general model. We discuss a few of the more important versions
below:
(i) Adverse selection model. The major qualitative results of this model (other
than the specification of the conditions under which pooling or separation occurs,
discussed above) entail an analysis of the distortions (relative to perfect
248
Principal and Agent
249
Allocation, Information and Markets
which would be associated with the individual bearing the full risk ofthe outcome
for any period is negligible, it is as if the individual is risk neutral; and with risk
neutrality we know that first best optimum can be obtained (if bankruptcy is
ignored).
THE SET OF ADMISSIBLE CONTRACTS. One of the important and general results to
emerge from the principal-agent literature is that the nature of the equilibrium
contract depends on the set of admissible contracts. Contracts can depend only
on the available information; typically, it is desirable to use all of the available
information, though in practice, many variables which ought to be relevant (have
information value) are not included within the compensation scheme.
Similarly, if one could costlessly implement a non-linear incentive scheme, such
schemes "would, in general, be preferable to linear schemes. Though in practice,
again, most observed schemes seem relatively simple (linear, piece-wise linear,
etc.), much of the literature has been concerned with characterizing in admittedly
simple situations the optimal non-linear scheme.
In a variety of situations, if one could make pay a stochastic function, it would
be desirable to do so, even with risk averse individuals. (Arnott-Stiglitz (1987)
and Holmstrom (1979) show that with separable utility functions, this will not
happen.) The intuition behind this, in the case when actions have to be taken
prior to the agent obtaining information about the state, is that the possibility
that he receives a low compensation so induces him to work hard that the
employer (landlord) can reduce the dependence (on average) of pay on output,
and thus reduce the variability of income.
Though optimal schemes may thus appear to be fairly complex, in practice
most schemes employed are relatively simple. There is an ongoing controversy
between those who seek to consider increasingly complex schedules, dismissing
work which has analysed simple linear schedules as ad hoc, and those who seek
to explain the kinds of compensation schedules actually employed; these dismiss
the complex solutions as being irrelevant. They would argue that efforts should
be devoted to understanding why actually employed schemes take on the form
they do.
One possible explanation of the use of simple schedules is that they may be
more robust. That is, as technology changes or the probability distribution of
states changes (the exogenous parameters in the principal-agent problem) the
optimal compensation scheme changes. But in practice, revisions to compensation
schemes are costly, and one must find a scheme that works under a variety of
situations. Simple, linear schemes may possess this property of robustness.
Another important characteristic of the set of admissible schemes relates to
commitments. Can, for instance, the worker commit himself not to leave, or can
the employer commit himself not to terminate the relationship?
A closely related issue is the set of punishments (rewards) which are admissible.
It makes a great deal of difference ifthere are limits on the negative compensations
that can be provided in the presence of bad outcomes.
We have noted the role of observability in the design of contracts. In some
250
Principal and Agent
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Allen, F. 1981. The prevention of default. Journal of Finance 36, May 271-6.
Arnott, R. and Stiglitz, J.E. 1982. The welfare economics of moral hazard. Discussion
Paper No. 465, Queen's University, Kingston, Ontario, March.
Arnott, R. and Stiglitz, J.E. 1985. Labor turnover, wage structures, and moral hazard: the
inefficiency of competitive markets. Journal of Labor Economics 3(4), 434-62.
Arnott, R. and Stiglitz, lE. 1986. Moral hazard and optimal commodity taxation. Journal
of Public Economics 29(1), February, 1-24.
Arnott, R. and Stiglitz, J.E. 1987. Randomization with asymmetric information: a simplified
exposition. Bell Journal of Economics 17.
Arrow, K.J. 1965. Aspects of the Theory of Risk-Bearing. Helsinki: Yrjo Jahnsson
Foundation.
Azariadis, e. and Stiglitz, J.E. 1983. Implicit contracts and fixed price equilibria. Quarterly
Journal of Economics 98(3), Supplement, 1-22.
Braverman, A. and Stiglitz, J.E. 1982. Sharecropping and the interlinking of agrarian
markets. American Economic Review 72(4), September, 695-715.
Eaton, land Gersovitz, M. 1981. Debt with potential repudiation; theoretical and empirical
analysis. Review of Economic Studies 48,289-309.
Fellingham, J.e., Kwon, Y.K. and Newman, D.P. 1982. Ex ante randomization in agency
models. Rand Journal of Economic Studies 15,290-301.
Gjesdal, F. 1982. Information and incentives: the agency information problem. Review of
Economic Studies 49, 373-90.
Green, J. and Stokey, N. 1983. A comparison of tournaments and contests. Journal of
Political Economy 91, 349-64.
Greenwald, B. and Stiglitz, J.E. 1986. Externalities in economies with imperfect information
and incomplete markets. Quarterly Journal of Economics 101(4), May, 229-64.
Grossman, S. and Hart, Q. 1983. An analysis of the principal-agent problem. Econometrica
51(1), January, 7-45.
Hart, O. 1983. Optimal labor contracts under asymmetric information: an introduction.
Review of Economic Studies 50, 3-35.
251
Allocation, Information and Markets
Helpman, E. and Laffont, J.J. 1975. On moral hazard in general equilibrium. Journal of
Economic Theory 10,8-23.
Holmstrom, B. 1979. Moral hazard and observability. Bell Journal of Economics 10(1),
Spring, 74-91.
Holmstrom, B. 1982. Moral hazard in teams. Bell Journal ofEconomics 13, Autumn, 324-40.
Keeton, W.R. 1979. Equilibrium Credit Rationing. New York: Garland Publishing.
Lazear, E. and Rosen, S. 1981. Rank order tournaments as optimum labor contracts.
Journal of Political Economy 89,841-64.
Mirrlees, J. 1971. An exploration of the theory of optimum income taxation. Review of
Economic Studies 38(2), April, 175-208.
Mirrlees, J. 1974. Notes on welfare economics, information, and uncertainty. In Contributions
to Economic Analysis, ed. M.S. Balch, D.L. McFadden and S.Y. Wu, Amsterdam:
North-Holland.
Mirrlees, J. 1976. The optimal structure of incentives and authority within an organization.
Bell Journal of Economics 7(1), Spring, 105-31.
Nalebuff, B. and Stiglitz, J.E. 1983a. Information, competition and markets. American
Economic Review 72(2), May, 278-84.
Nalebuff, B. and Stiglitz, J.E. 1983b. Prizes and incentives: towards a general theory of
compensation and competition. Bell Journal of Economics 14, Spring, 21-43.
Pauly, M. V. 1968. The economics of moral hazard: comment. American Economic Review
58, June, 531-6.
Radner, R. 1981. Monitoring cooperative agreements in a repeated principal-agent
relationship. Econometrica 49, September, 1127-48.
Radner, R. and Stiglitz, J.E. 1983. A nonconcavity in the value of innovation. In Bayesian
Models in Economic Theory, ed. M. Boyer and R. Kihlstrom, Amsterdam: North-
Holland.
Ross, S. 1973. The economic theory of agency: the principal's problem. American Economic
Review 63(2), May, 134-9.
Rothschild, M. and Stiglitz, J.E. 1976. Equilibrium in competitive insurance markets: an
essay on the economics of imperfect information. Quarterly Journal of Economics 90( 4),
November, 629-49.
Salop, S. 1977. The noisy monopolist: imperfect information, price dispersion and price
discrimination. Review of Economic Studies 44, October, 393-406.
Salop, S. and Salop, J. 1976. Self-selection and turnover in the labor market. Quarterly
Journal of Economics 90, November, 619-28.
Sappington, D. and Stiglitz, J.E. 1987. Information and regulation. In Public Regulation:
New Perspectives on Institutions and Policies, ed. E. Bailey, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.
Spence, A.M. and Zeckhauser, R. 1971. Insurance, information, and individual action.
American Economic Review 61(2), May, 380-87.
Stiglitz, lE. 1974. Incentives and risk sharing in sharecropping. Review of Economic Studies
41, April, 219-55.
Stiglitz, lE. 1975. Incentives, risk, and information: notes toward a theory of hierarchy.
Bell Journal of Economics 6(2), Autumn, 552-79.
Stiglitz, J.E. 1977. Monopoly non-linear pricing and imperfect information: the insurance
market. Review of Economic Studies 44, October, 407-30.
Stiglitz, J.E. 1982a. Self-selection and Pareto efficient taxation. Journal of Public Economics
17,213-40.
Stiglitz, J.E. 1982b. Utilitarianism and horizontal equity: the case for random taxation.
252
Principal and Agent
253