5 Hessen
5 Hessen
5 Hessen
THOMSON
BORIS HESSEN
Keywords: Boris Hessen, Isaac Newton, René Descartes, history of natural science,
classical mechanics, quantum mechanics, Marxism, Soviet philosophy
The bicentennial of Newton‟s death was celebrated all over the world with a
series of celebrations, speeches, reports and articles. Newton‟s works and thoughts
have been acquiring a renewed interest in the context of the revolution currently
taking place in modern, natural science. Many of his ideas, above all those in the
Translated by Sean Winkler; Faculty of Humanities – School of Philosophy; National Research
University – Higher School of Economics; ul. Staraya Basmannaya, 21/4 – L307; 105066, Moscow;
Russian Federation. E-mail: [email protected]
87
Sean Winkler - Translation of Boris Hessen’s “Preface to Articles by A. Einstein and J.J. Thomson”
Opticks, are once again acquiring significance and attracting interest. At the same time,
however, in the context of the crisis in modern physics, the weaknesses of his “Natural
Philosophy” are beginning to appear with a particular clarity. The basic methodological
concepts and foundations of the system of Newtonian physics must be reassessed.
The need for such a revision is the result of the course of the development of the
theoretical knowledge of nature. How should the revision and further development
of Newtonian physics be carried out? How do new concepts which have been
advanced as a result of the development of physics over the last twenty years relate to
Newtonian physics and is there any connection between them at all?
Of course, all of these questions inevitably arise without any connection to
the 200th-year anniversary, but it has, nevertheless, greatly stimulated the formulation
of such questions.
The articles published below by Einstein, J.J. Thomson and H. Lamb each
offer a different approach to the question of Newton‟s role and significance as well as
to the evaluation of his works.
Commemorations of Newton in England were particularly noteworthy for
their pomp. The most prominent members of the Royal Society, also among the most
prominent physicists in England, dedicated speeches to Newton‟s works. Thomson,
Jeans, Lamb, Glazebrook and many others sketched a picture of Newton‟s
accomplishments in the fields of physics, mechanics, astronomy and mathematics.
But in these speeches, which were often brilliant in form, there are almost no
generalizations. Almost no attempts are made to question Newton‟s methodology
and philosophy in connection to modern physics. In most cases, the articles provide
interesting accounts of Newton‟s works in a particular field, but often without any
attempt to raise the question of the connections between his works. The birthplace of
classical empiricism makes itself felt here.
J.J. Thomson‟s speech, at least, provides deeper content than the others, but it
still does not raise basic questions about the nature of fundamental principles. The
speech perhaps most concerned with generalizations and the nature of fundamental
principles and which seeks to link Newton‟s work with the revolution taking place in
modern physics, was that by . . . the Lord Bishop of Birmingham and member of the
Royal Society, Dr. E.W. Barnes.
In a lengthy speech, the Lord Bishop tries to prove that
theology does also follow the times. “[I]ts theology has been continuously re-shaped
by its leading divines, and the process has not yet ended.”7 Theology must build upon
and use all of the achievements of science, both past and present. Newton‟s name is,
therefore, as dear to the church as it is to science.
Having presided over the memorial service for Newton that ended the
celebration at the request of the Yorkshire Mathematical Society, in his closing
88
Society and Politics Vol. 13, No.1(25)/April 2019
remarks, the bishop summed up all of the previous speeches and noted the unity of
science and religion with satisfaction, even stressing that the decision to end the
celebration with a religious service came from a group of leading scientists. Here,
English empiricism has not strayed from its traditions.
In contrast to the English spirit, Einstein‟s article precisely poses the most
general, fundamental questions concerning the influence of Newton‟s ideas on the
development of theoretical physics and the relationship of these ideas with modern,
scientific methodology.
Therefore, it would be appropriate to say a few words regarding some of the
main points that Einstein puts forward.
The 17th century is a turning point in the history of the development of
physics: beginning with Galileo, the struggle against Scholastic Aristotelian physics
was successfully completed by the beginning of the 18th century. „Hidden qualities‟,
the horror vacui [horror of the void] are forever banished from physics. The general
laws of terrestrial and celestial mechanics are established. Gassendi and Boyle clearly
formulated the principles of atomism.
The basic tools for the study of nature (i.e., the telescope, microscope,
thermometer) are being developed and improved.
Strong foundations are being laid for a quantitative, mathematically-based
study of nature.
The reaction against Scholastic physics is fueled by two sources: Bacon‟s
empiricism and the mechanistic principles of Descartes‟s physics.
The most consistent and principled opponent of Scholastic Aristotlelian
physics, the physics of hidden qualities, was Descartes.
Aristotle identified hidden qualities as those properties of objects that cannot
be directly perceived by our senses, but which are nevertheless the causes of the
actions of the objects that we observe: a magnet attracts because it possesses the
magnetic force to pull. This force is a hidden quality, a qualitas occulta.
Clearly, such a methodology could not serve as an instrument of scientific
research and Descartes strongly opposes it.
“I freely acknowledge,” he states,
89
Sean Winkler - Translation of Boris Hessen’s “Preface to Articles by A. Einstein and J.J. Thomson”
The mechanistic principle of explaining nature became not only a slogan in the
struggle against Scholasticism, but also a basic methodology.
“[T]rue Philosophy,” says Huygens, “conceives the causes of all natural
effects in terms of mechanical motions. This, in my opinion, we must necessarily do,
or else renounce all hopes of ever comprehending anything in Physics.”9
But the mechanical principle is only one component of Descartes‟s physics.
The main question of the era was the question of the general method of
scientific research. If Bacon chose experience as the primary starting point, then
according to Descartes, the only true path to knowledge is deduction. Descartes‟s
physics is a remarkable example of the application of rationalism, coupled with the
mechanical principle of explaining nature. This is its advantage as well as its
disadvantage. Thanks to this synthesis, Descartes managed to create that majestic
picture of the world, which in many respects, has not only not lost its value, but is
even attracting special interest today.
“The greatness of Descartes‟s plan and the courage with which he executed it
stimulated scientific thought in an unrivaled way. From the wreckage of his system,
later scientists created the most stable theories that have retained their significance to
the present day.”10
On the basis of a mechanical worldview, the basic task of Descartes‟s physics
was to provide an exhaustive picture of all natural phenomena:
Having established the concepts of matter and motion, Descartes builds his entire
system of physics according to the plan outlined above.
But his physics is not an encyclopedic summary of modern knowledge.
Physics, as a science, did not yet exist then. From the time of Galileo, it had been
undergoing a period of accumulating factual knowledge about nature, which is now
gathered not only by observation, but also by experimentation. Therefore, Descartes
builds his physics into a complete, rationalistic system, sometimes even at odds with
the known facts of the time (i.e., the collision of bodies).
Newton‟s tasks in the field of physics were different.
For Descartes, the main question was that of method. Once this method was
discovered, the scientific system could be built. Conducting a merciless struggle
against the Aristotelian physics of hidden qualities, Descartes formulated the basic
principles of the mechanistic worldview as general methodological prerequisites for
the study of nature.
90
Society and Politics Vol. 13, No.1(25)/April 2019
Consistently applying this principle, Descartes did not stop at reducing mass
to extension (i.e., volume). For him, any other conception of mass was already a
„hidden quality‟. Phenomena must only be explained by „figure and movement‟.
Newton‟s physics, as a system of mathematical phenomenology, is opposed
to this unified and complete construction of the edifice of physics, which is based on
the unity of the mechanistic outlook and rationalistic method.
“[G]eneral phenomenology,” Boltzmann says,
In fact, although Newton‟s main work is entitled The Mathematical Principles of Natural
Philosophy, within it, we do not find a philosophically grounded and consistently
conducted natural-scientific worldview.
Newton‟s methodology is that of empiricism, which is wrapped in a
mathematical form.
The struggle between Newtonian and Cartesian physics is a struggle between
empiricism and rationalism in the study of natural science. And it should be noted
that Newtonian physics by no means wins out because it is a synthesis of these
approaches, but, rather, because it is a form of mathematical phenomenology.
Therefore, it is only possible to correctly understand and evaluate Newton‟s
historical significance and place by comparing it with that of Descartes.
In this respect, J.J. Thompson is absolutely correct when he, in his speech
about Newton‟s work in the field of physics, pays tribute to Descartes. It is
interesting to note that he points precisely to those general, methodological principles
that Descartes introduced into physics, but he does not stress the fact that the theory
of vortices and the ether are consequences of those same methodological principles.
Both Descartes‟s theory of vortices and the ether are closely related to his
poignant statement about the question of discontinuity and continuity. The issue of
long-range and short-range interaction is essentially a question of discontinuity and
continuity. Classical atomism, which accepts atoms and empty space and considers
any action to not be action at a distance, but a jolt, an „action from behind‟ (vis a tergo),
essentially does not explain anything, because the transmission of an impulse by a jolt
is as methodologically incomprehensible as action at a distance.
Maxwell‟s extremely clever experiment showed that when one body pushes
another, it does not touch it.13
Descartes perfectly understood these difficulties and hence, in his theory of
vortices and the ether, wanted to provide a synthesis of atomism and the theory of
continuous matter.
The problem of continuity and discontinuity is the central problem of
modern physics and, hence, why Descartes‟s methodological studies are fresh and
interesting today.
91
Sean Winkler - Translation of Boris Hessen’s “Preface to Articles by A. Einstein and J.J. Thomson”
Modern natural science owes its independence to its liberation from teleology. It
recognizes only the causal consideration of nature.
One of the battle slogans of the Renaissance was: “to know truly is to know
by causes”---“vere scire [esse] per causas scire.”17
92
Society and Politics Vol. 13, No.1(25)/April 2019
Bacon emphasized that the teleological view is one of the most dangerous of
idola [idols]. The true connection of things is mechanical causality. “Nature knows
only mechanical causality; all of our forces must be directed to the investigation of the
latter.”18
The mechanistic worldview necessarily leads to the mechanical concept of
causality. Descartes establishes the principle of causality (ex nihilo nihil fit) as an
„eternal truth‟.
On English soil, mechanical determinism is generally recognized, but it is
often intertwined with religious dogma (i.e., the “Christian necessitarian” sect to
which Priestley belonged). This is a peculiar combination, which is characteristic of
English thinkers and, which is also what we find in Newton.
The universal recognition that the principle of mechanical causality is the sole
and basic principle of the scientific study of nature is due to the powerful
development of mechanics itself. Newton‟s “Principia” is a grand extension of this
principle to our planetary system. “The old teleology has gone to the devil,”19 but so
far, only in the field of inorganic nature, in the fields of earthly and celestial
mechanics.
The main idea of the “Principia” is to present the motion of the planets as a
consequence of the combination of two forces: “a composition of a Descent towards
the sun, & an imprest motion.”20 Newton attributed this initial impetus to God, but
he “forbade Him any further interference in his solar system.”21
This peculiar „division of labor‟ between God and causality in the oversight of
the universe, the intertwining of religious dogma and the materialistic principle of
mechanistic causality, which Plekhanov also identifies, was characteristic of English
historians.22
The recognition of the modality of motion, the negation of matter in motion
as a causa sui, inevitably led Newton to the concept of an initial impulse.23 From this
point of view, the idea of a deity in Newton‟s system is not accidental, but organically
linked with his views on matter and motion, not to mention his views on space, which
follow from Henry More, who was highly influential on Newton.
At this point, the entire weakness of Newton‟s general, philosophical
worldview is revealed. The principle of pure mechanical causality leads to the concept
of the divine principle. The „bad infinity‟ of the universal chain of mechanical
determinism ends with the initial impulse and together with it, the door to teleology is
opened.
But God, having created the world and having provided the initial impulse to
matter, leaves the world to the dominion of mechanical causality. The world in which
the law of gravitation is enacted exists independently.
In this respect, as Einstein emphasizes in his article, Newton‟s system is truly
a complete system of physical causality.
Newton gave the law of causality a mathematical form and endowed it with a
form that theoretical physics now considers the only possible formulation of the
principle of causality in physics.
Just as the development of natural science led to a revolution in the concepts
of space and time, the study of microcosmic and intra-atomic processes and the
93
Sean Winkler - Translation of Boris Hessen’s “Preface to Articles by A. Einstein and J.J. Thomson”
We do not have the means, Born argues, to observe the behavior of each individual
atom or electron when we perform a complex experiment.
At best, we can observe the final and initial state. What happens in the
interval between these two states, how the electron behaves at a given time, is
unknown to us. The initial and final states are not connected by an unambiguous
chain of causal states, as is the case in the dynamic regularities of classical, Newtonian
physics. Therefore, the initial state does not determine the final state absolutely, but
only probabilistically. Knowing the position of the earth, we can unambiguously and
accurately determine the position that it will occupy after a certain period of time;
knowing the state of a given set of atoms, however, we can only determine its
subsequent state with a certain degree of probability.
95
Sean Winkler - Translation of Boris Hessen’s “Preface to Articles by A. Einstein and J.J. Thomson”
Researchers are questioning determinism for other reasons as well. With the
transition from classical physics to quantum theory, we enter the domain of
discontinuous processes.
But these results possess a significantly different nature from the results given by
classical physics. “The classical calculation gives us information about our specific
system of planets. The quantum theoretical calculation does not, in general, tell us
anything about a single atom, but only about the mean properties of an assembly of
similar atoms.”25
Thus, the statistical regularity of quantum processes is also due to their
discontinuous nature.
Classical physics was mainly concerned with the study of the sequence of
individual states, the very course of the process. Born stresses how in the new
quantum mechanics, conversely, “the question of the course of phenomena practically
disappeared from [this circle of study].”26
Regularities in the new mechanics are essentially statistical regularities. But
since we are not considering a sequence of phenomena, but only finite, observable
states, is it possible to say that atomic processes are univocally defined along their
entire length? Is it possible to speak of a causal investigation of phenomena if the
final state can only be probabilistically determined from the initial state: does such a
concept of the connection between phenomena raise the question of the causal
sequence of phenomena as such?
These are the questions that arise with the development of the new, quantum
mechanics; this is the sense in which Einstein says that when confronted by the
difficulties posed by the development of modern physics, the law of causality refuses
to waver.27
This rejection of the causal study of phenomena, as we have seen in modern
physics, is understood as a rejection of the establishment of a continuous connection
between the initial and final state and its replacement by the distribution of the
probability of a given state.
Since modern quantum, unlike classical, mechanics does not even introduce
microscopic coordinates, but is limited to observable values, as we saw above, it is
clear that “it does not provide the means for determining particles in space and
time.”28
In the place of dynamic description there arises a kind of statistical
phenomenology. It is in this sense that one can speak of the rejection of the spatio-
temporal description.
96
Society and Politics Vol. 13, No.1(25)/April 2019
The question of whether the modern development of physics gives rise to the
rejection of the law of causality and of the spatio-temporal description can only be
resolved if the question of the relationship between statistical and dynamic regularities
is correctly posed; that is, the question of necessity and contingency.
Abandoning the law of causality can only come about if one metaphysically
opposes the significance of chance.
Indeed, if we consider dynamic regularities to be the only expression of
physical causality, to the exclusion of chance, and contrast these regularities with
statistical regularities based only on the concept of probability, then it is natural to
consider such regularities as the antithesis of causality, favoring total determinism.
Engels was the first to attest to the significance of the concept of chance in
theoretical natural science. He explained that the metaphysical opposition between
chance and necessity cannot be sufficient for the development of research; that bare,
mechanical determinism cannot serve as a sufficient research tool. Accident is an
objective category.
The rejection of fatalistic determinism does not mean the rejection of the law of
causality.
The recognition of chance as a real, objective category, and not just a
consequence of our failure to determine causal connections, does not at all mean
identifying chance with groundlessness, the introduction of cause-lessness, as some
additional „postulate‟.30
But such an interpretation of chance also means a different approach to the
question of statistical regularity.
In fact, statistical regularity is based on the concept of the probability of
phenomena and the concept of probability is based on the concept of contingency.
Thus, if we abandon the fatalistic concept of determinism, on one hand, and
recognize contingency not just as a result of our ignorance, but as an objective
category, the opposition between dynamic and statistical regularity will be eliminated.
They do not exclude, but imply each other. They are both legitimate and necessary.
Statistical regularity is not a consequence of our inadequate knowledge of processes,
but an objective, necessary method of research, rooted in the characteristic features of
the phenomena being studied. Engels‟s concept of chance and necessity provides us
with the key to solving the problem not through the abandonment of causality, but
through a correct synthesis of necessity and chance, and, consequently, of dynamic
and statistical regularity. Since chance is not necessity that we cannot observe, but an
objective, and not a subjective category, the task of this particular science is to decide
what is contingent for this process and, therefore, to decide which regularity is more
applicable to the studies of this group of phenomena, statistical or dynamic. But these
two regularities cannot be regarded as mutually exclusive. If, in statistical regularity,
the initial and the final states are not connected by a continuous sequence of states,
then this only shows that for a given phenomenon, at this stage of research, a certain
number of intermediate states are contingent. The final state is always a necessary
consequence of the elementary processes, its components, but which are accidental
with respect to the whole process, taken as a whole, in this connection of phenomena.
Engels‟s methodological views were confirmed in a very interesting work by
Smoluchowski, entitled „Über den Begriff des Zufalls und den Ursprung der
Wahrscheinlichkeitsgesetze in der Physik.“31
Smoluchowski considers the commonly-accepted concept of chance and
probability in physics to be unsatisfactory.
“My main thought,” he says, “is that the objectivity of the notion of probability,
which has not been fully paid attention to before, should be presented in its proper
light.”32
“The law of probability is subject to those phenomena, the occurrence of
which depends on chance.”33
“If we consider contingency, as is commonly done in popular theories, to be a
negation of regularity, then we will be faced with insoluble contradictions.”34
98
Society and Politics Vol. 13, No.1(25)/April 2019
“As for its application in theoretical physics, all probability theories that
consider contingency to be an unknown, partial cause must be declared unsatisfactory
in advance.”35
“The physical probability of events only depends on the conditions affecting
its outcome, but not on the degree of our knowledge!”36
But if, in contrast to mechanical determinism, we pay attention to the
objective side of probability and chance, if we stop to consider contingency to be
unknown necessity, then we must change our view about the significance of statistical
regularities. Therefore, having established the limits of the old concepts of chance
and probability, Smoluchowski takes a different approach to the issue of statistical
regularities.
“I am fully aware,” he says
that this concept of chance stands in conflict with the usual definition
of chance, which considers partial ignorance of the causes to be its
most significant aspect, so I will note the following in confirmation of
my view: the application of the theory of probability in the kinetic
theory of gases would retain its significance and would be fully justified
even if we knew exactly the structure of the molecules and their initial
positions and were able to accurately mathematically describe the
motion of each in time.37
Thus, statistical regularity and statistical laws, i.e., laws based on the concept of
chance, are not simply a consequence of our lack of knowledge, but represent an equal
method of studying nature. In this respect, the general concept of determinism is not
in the least disturbed. But, determinism will no longer be limited to mechanical
determinism. Determinism and statistical regularity, necessity and chance cannot be
regarded as mutually exclusive. This is what Smoluchowski emphasizes.
“It seems to me,” he says,
With these brief remarks, of course, we have by no means exhausted the problems of
the nature of the laws of physics. In any case, however, it can be said with confidence
that the development of modern physics does not give the slightest reason to question
the causal connection between phenomena and the concept of space-time. Just as the
development of our knowledge has necessitated changing the Newtonian concepts of
absolute space and time, the development of quantum theory raises the question of
the insufficiency of the concept of continuous, mechanical determinism. And in
99
Sean Winkler - Translation of Boris Hessen’s “Preface to Articles by A. Einstein and J.J. Thomson”
[i]t is mainly because the physicists did not know dialectics that the new
physics strayed into idealism. . . . The basic materialist spirit of physics,
as of all modern science, will overcome all crises, but only by the
indispensable replacement of metaphysical materialism by dialectical
materialism.41
Here, we tried to show that by replacing the metaphysical opposition of necessity and
chance with the dialectical concept of causality, pointed out by Engels, there is a way
out of the crisis that would otherwise lead to the rejection of the causal and spatio-
temporal conception of phenomena.42
References
1 Гессен, Б., «Предисловие к статьям А. Эйнштейна и Дж. Дж. Томсона [Predisloviye k
stat‟yam A. Eynshteyna i Dzh. Dzh. Tomsona]», Под знаменем марксизма [Pod Znamenem
Marksizma; Under the Banner of Marxism] 4 (1927): 152–165.
2 Эйнштейн, А., «Механика Ньютона и ее влияние на развитие теоретической физики»,
Под знаменем марксизма 4 (1927): 166–173. See also Einstein, A., „Newtons Mechanik und ihr
Einfluß auf die Gestaltung der theoretischen Physik,“ Die Naturwissenschaften [The Natural
Sciences] 15 (1927): 273–276; Einstein, A., “The Mechanics of Newton and Their Influence on
the Development of Theoretical Physics,” in Ideas and Opinions, ed. C. Seeling, et al. and trans.
S. Bargmann (New York: Crown Publishers, Inc., 1954), 253–261.
100
Society and Politics Vol. 13, No.1(25)/April 2019
3 Томсон, Дж. Дж., «Работы Ньютона в области физики», Под знаменем марксизма 4 (1927):
174–181. See also Thomson, J.J., “Newton‟s Work in Physics,” Nature 119 (1927): 36–40.
4 Ламб, Г., «Работы Ньютона в области меканики», Под знаменем марксизма 4 (1927): 182–
185. See also Lamb, H., “Newton‟s Work in Mechanics,” Nature 119 (1927): 33.
5 Schäfer, W., “Boris Hessen and the Politics of the Sociology of Science,” Thesis Eleven 21
(1988): 114.
6 Barnes, E.W., “The Bicentenary of Newton‟s Death,” Nature 119 (1927): 21. Where possible,
Hessen‟s original references have been substituted by contemporary, English translations, but
where such translations were not available, the originals have been left in. In cases where
Hessen quotes a text, but does not himself provide a citation, reference to that text has been
provided by the translator [Translator‟s Note, hereafter „TN‟].
7 Barnes, E.W., (1927): 21 [TN].
8 Descartes, R., Principles of Philosophy, in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, vol. 1, ed. and trans.
1912), 3.
10 Whittaker, E.T., A History of the Theories of Aether and Electricity: From the Age of Descartes to the
Close of the Nineteenth Century (New York/Bombay/Calcutta: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1910),
3.
11 Descartes, R., (1985), 186 [TN].
12 Boltzmann, L., “On the Development of the Methods of Theoretical Physics in Recent
Times,” in Theoretical Physics and Philosophical Problems, ed. B. McGuinness and trans. P. Foulkes
(Dordrecht/Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1974), 95.
13 Maxwell, J.C., “On Action at a Distance,” in The Scientific Papers of James Clerk Maxwell, vol. 2,
ed. W.D. Niven, M.A., F.R.S. (Mineola: Dover Publications, Inc., 1890), 314.
14 “The doctrine of direct action at a distance cannot claim for its author the discoverer of
universal gravitation. It was first asserted by Roger Cotes, in his preface to the Principia, which
he edited during Newton‟s life. According to Cotes, it is by experience that we learn that all
bodies gravitate. We do not learn in any other way that they are extended, movable, or solid.
Gravitation, therefore, has as much right to be considered an essential property of matter as
extension, mobility, or impenetrability. And when the Newtonian philosophy gained ground in
Europe, it was the opinion of Cotes rather than that of Newton that became most prevalent.”
Maxwell, J.C., (1890),316.
15 Engels, F., The Peasant War in Germany, in Marx & Engels: Collected Works, vol. 10 – Marx and
Engels 1849–51, ed. A. Vladimirova and L. Zubrilova and trans. G. Benton, et al. (London:
Lawrence & Wishart, 2010a), 415.
16 Maxwell, J.C., (1890), 317 [TN].
17 Bacon, F., The New Organon, ed. L. Jardine and M. Silverthorne (Cambridge: Cambridge
Smirnova and trans. C. Dutt (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 2010b), 475 [TN].
20 Halley, E., “Halley to Newton (29 June 1686),” in The Correspondence of Isaac Newton, vol. 2 –
1676–1687, ed. H.W. Turnbull, F.R.S. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1960), 441.
21 Engels, F., (2010b), 480. [TN]
101
Sean Winkler - Translation of Boris Hessen’s “Preface to Articles by A. Einstein and J.J. Thomson”
22 Plekhanov, G., The Role of the Individual in History, trans. unknown (New York: International
Publishers, 1940), 11n1. To what “English historians” Hessen sees Plekhanov as referring
here is unclear. Perhaps Hessen means Plekhanov‟s references to “English historical figures”
such as Priestley, etc. [TN].
23 The initial impulse is the tangential component for which Engels blames Newton. See
article published by Campbell and Garnett, namely, Maxwell‟s report presented at the
Cambridge Philosophical Circle (Club of Seniors). The article is Maxwell, J.C., “Does the
progress of Physical Science tend to give any advantage to the opinion of Necessity (or
Determinism) over that of the Contingency of Events and the Freedom of the Will?” in The
Life of James Clerk Maxwell with a Selection from his Correspondence and Occasional Writings and a Sketch
of His Contributions to Science, ed. L. Campbell, M.A., LL.D. and W. Garnett, M.A. (London:
Macmillan and Co., 1882), 434–444.
40 Maxwell, J.C., (1882),444. [TN].
41 Lenin, V.I., Materialism and Empirio-Criticism: Critical Comments on A Reactionary Philosophy, in
V.I. Lenin – Collected Works, Vol. 14; 1908, ed. C. Dutt and trans. A. Fineberg (Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1977 [1962, 1968, 1972]), 262, 306.
42 Thank you to Olga Bashkina and two anonymous reviewers for their assistance in rendering
this translation, and special thanks to one reviewer who tracked down a missing reference. I
would also like to extend my gratitude to the School of Philosophy at the National Research
University – Higher School of Economics for providing the context in which this translation
work could be completed [TN].
102