Sherry B. Ortner - Is Female To Male As Nature Is Tu Culture (Rosaldo & Lamphere, 1974)

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 21

sHERRY B.

ORTNER

Is Female to M a l e a s Nature Is to Culture?

Much of the creativity of anthropology derives from the tension between

two sets of demands: that we explain human universals, and that we

explain cultural particulars. By this canon, woman provides us with one

of the more challenging problems to be dealt with. The secondary status

of woman in society is one of the true universals, a pan-cultural fact.

Yet within that universal fact, the specific cultural conceptions and

symbolizations of woman are extraordinarily diverse and even mutually

contradictory. Further, the actual treatment of women and their relative

power and contribution vary enormously from culture to culture, and

over different periods in the history of particular cultural traditions.

Both of these points-the universal fact and the cultural variation­

constitute problems to be explained.

My interest i n the problem is of course more than academic: 1 wish

to see genuine change come about, the emergence of a social and cultural

order in which as much of the range of human potential is open to

women as is open to men. The universality of female subordination,

the fact that it exists within every type of social and economic arrange­

ment and in societies of every degree of complexity, indicates to me that

we are up against something very profound, very stubborn, something

The first version of this paper was presented in October 1972 as a lecture in the

course "Women: Myth and Reality" at Sarah Lawrence College. 1 received helpful

comments from the students and from my co-teachers in the course: Joan Kelly Gadol,

Eva Kollisch, and Cerda Lerner. A short account was delivered at the American An­

thropological Association meetings in Toronto, November 1 9 7 2 . Meanwhile, 1 received

excellent critica! comments from Karen Blu, Robert Paul, Michelle Rosaldo, David

Schneider, and Terence Turner, and the present version of the paper, in which the

thrust of the argument has been rather significantly changed, was written in response

to t?ose comments. I, of course, retain responsibility for its final form. The paper is

?ed1cated to Simone de Beauvoir, whose book The Second Sex ( 1 9 5 3 ) , first published

�n French in 1949, remains in my opinion the best single comprehensive understand­


mg of "the woman problem."
68 SHERRY B. ORTNER

w e cannot rout out simply by rearranging a few tasks and roles in the

social system, or even by reordering the whole economic structure. In

this paper I try to expose the underlying logic of cultural thinking that

assumes the inferiority of women; I try to show the highly persuasive

nature of the logic, for if i t w e r e not so persuasive, people would not

keep subscribing to i t . But I also try to show the social and cultural

sources of that logic, to indicate wherein lies the potential for change.

I t is important to sort out the levels of the problem. The confusion

can be staggering. For example, depending on which aspect of Chinese

culture we look at, we might extrapolate any of several entirely different

guesses concerning the status of women in China. In the ideology of

Taoism, y i n , the female principie, and yang, the male principie, are given

equal weight; "the opposition, alternation, and interaction of these two

forces give rise to all phenomena in the universe" (Siu, 1 9 6 8 : 2). Hence

we might guess that maleness and femaleness are equally valued in


1
the general ideology of Chinese culture. Looking at the social struc­

ture, however, we see the strongly emphasized patrilineal descent prin­

cipie, the importance of sons, and the absolute authority of the father

in the family. Thus we might conclude that China is the archetypal

patriarchal society. Next, looking at the actual roles played, power and

influence wielded, and material contributions made by women in Chi­

nese society-all of which are, u pon observation, qui te substantial-we

would have to say that women are allotted a great deal of (unspoken)

s t a t u s in the system. Or again, we might focus on the fact that a goddess,

Kuan Yin, is the central (most worshiped, most depicted) deity in Chi­

nese Buddhism, and we might be tempted to say, as many have tried to

say about goddess-worshiping cultures in prehistoric and early historical

societies, that China is actually a sort of matriarchy. In short, we Iliust

be absolutely dear about w h a t we are trying to explain before explain­

ing i t .

We may differentiate three levels of the problem:

1. The universal fact of culturally attributed second-class status of

woman in every society. Two questions are important here. First, what

do we mean by this; what is our evidence that this is a universal fact?

And second, how are we to explain this fact, once having established i t?

2. Specific ideologies, symbolizations, and socio-structural arrange­

ments pertaining to women that vary widely from culture to culture.

The problem a t this level is to account for any particular cultural com-

1 It is true of course that yin, the female principie, has a negative valence. None­

theless, there is an absolute complementarity of yin and yang in Taoism, a recogni­

tion that the world requires the equal operation and interaction of both principies

for its survival.


Is Female to M a l e a s Nature Is to Culture? 69

plex in terms of factors specific to that group-the standard level of

anthropological analysis.

Observable on-the-ground details of women's activities, contribu-


3.
tions, powers, influence, etc., often at variance with cultural ideology

(although always corístrained within the assurnption that wornen may

never be officially preeminent in the total system). This is the level of

direct observation, often adopted now by ferninist-oriented anthropol-

ogists.

This pa per is prirnaril y con cerned wi th the firs t of these levels, the

problem of the universal devaluation of wornen. The analysis thus de­

pends not upon specific cultural data but rather upon an analysis of

"culture" taken generically as a special sort of process in the world. A

discussion of the second level, the problem of cross-cultural variation

in conceptions and relative valuations of women, w i l l e n t a i l a great <leal

of cross-cultural research and must be postponed to another time. As

for the third leve 1, i t w i l l be obvious from rny a pproach tha t I would

consider i t a misguided endeavor to focus only upon women's actual

though culturally unrecognized and unvalued powers in any given so­

ciety, without first understanding the overarching ideology and deeper

assurnptions of the culture that render such powers trivial.

The Universality of Female S u b o r d i n a t i o n

What do I mean when I say that everywhere, i n every known culture,

women are considered in sorne degree inferior to rnen? First of all, 1

must stress that I am talking a b o u t c u l t u r a l evaluations; 1 am saying

that each culture, in its own way and on its own terms, makes this eval­

uation. B u t what would constitute evidence that a particular culture

considers wornen inferior?

Three types of data would suffice: ( 1 ) elernents of cultural ideology

and inforrnants' statements that explicitly devalue women, according

them, their roles, their tasks, their products, and their social milieux

less prestige than are accorded men and the male correlates; (2) symbolic

devices, such as the attribution of defilernent, which may be interpreted

as implicitly making a statement of inferior v a l u a t i o n ; and (3) social­

structural arrangements that exclude wornen frorn participation in or

contact with sorne realm in which the highest powers of the society are
2
felt to reside. These three types of data may all of course be interrelated

2
Sorne anthropologists might consider this type of evidence (social-structural ar­

rangements t h a t cxclude women, e x p l i c i t l y or de facto, from c c r t a i n gr o u p s , roles, or

�tatuses) to be a subtype of the second type of evidence (symbolic formulations of

mferiority). 1 would not disagree with this view, although most social anthropologists

would probably separate the two types.


SHERRY B. ORTNER

in any particular system, though they need not necessarily be. Further,

any one of them will usually be sufficient to make the point of female

inferiority in a given culture. Certainly, female exclusion from the most


sacred rite or the highest political council is sufficient evidence. Cer­

tainly, explicit cultural ideology devaluing women (and their tasks,

roles, products, etc.) is sufficient evidence. Symbolic indicators such as

defilement are usually sufficient, although in a few cases in which, say,

men and women are equally polluting to one another, a further indi­

cator is required-and is, as far as my investigations have ascertained,

always available.

On any or all of these counts, then, 1 would flatly assert that we find

women subordinated to men i n every known society. The search for a

genuinely egalitarian, let alone matriarchal, culture has proved fruitless.

An example from one society that has traditionally b een on the credi t

si d e of this ledger w ill su ffi ce . A mo n g the matrilineal Crow, as L owie

( 1 9 5 6 ) p oints out, "W omen . . . had hi g hly honori fi c o ffi.c es in the S un

D ance ; they could become directors of the Tobacco C ere m on y and

played, if anythin g, a more conspicuous pa rt in it than the men ; they

so m etimes played the hostess in the Cooked M e a t F estival ; they were

not d e ba rr ed from sweatin g or docto r ing or from see k in g a vision" (p .

6 1 ) . N onetheless , "Women [ durin g menstrua ti on ] formerly rode inferior

horses and evidently this loomed as a source of contamination, for they

were not allowed to ap p roach either a wounded man or men startin g

on a war p art y . A taboo still lin g ers a g ainst their coming near sacred

ob j ec ts at these times " (p . 44) . Further, j ust before enu m erating women's

righ ts of partici p ation in the various ri tuals noted above, L owie men ­

tions one particular S un D ance D oll bundle th a t was not sup p osed to

be u nwrap p ed by a woman (p . 60). P ursuing th is trail we fi n d: "Accord­

ing to ali Lodge Grass informants and most others, the d oll o w ned by

Wrinkled-face took precedence not only of other d olls b ut of al i o ther

Crow med i cines whatsoever . . . . This particul a r d oll was not s u p p osed
3
to be handled by a woman" ( p. 2 29).

In sum, the Crow are p robably a fairly ty p ic a l c a se . Ye s , women have

certain powers and ri g hts , in this case s o rn e that p lace them in fairly

high po si tions. Y et u ltimatel y the I ine is drawn : m e nstr uat ion is a threat

to warfare, one of the most valued insti t utions of the tri b e , on e tha t is

central to the i r self - d efi nition ; and the most s acred o bj ect of the tribe

is t aboo to the direct sight and touch of women.

s While we are on the subject of injustices of various kinds, we might note that

Lowie secretly bought this doll, the most sacred object in the tribal repertoire, from

íts custodian, the widow of Wrinkled-face. She asked $400 for it, but this price was

"far beyond [Lowie's] meaos," and he finally got it for $8o (p. 300).
Is Female to M a l e as Nature Is to Culturel

Similar examples could be multiplied ad infinitum, but I think the

onus is no longer upon us to demonstrate that female subordination is

a cultural universal; it is up to those who would argue against the point

to bring forth counterexamples. 1 shall take the universal secondary

status of women as a gíven, and proceed from there.

Nature and Culture»

How are we to explain the universal devaluation of women? We could

of course rest the case on biological determinism. There is something

genetically inherent in the male of the species, so the biological deter­

minists would argue, that makes them the naturally dominant sex; that

"something" is lacking in females, and as a result women are not only

naturally subordinate but in general quite satisfied with their position,

since i t affords them protection and the opportunity to maximize ma­

ternal pleasures, which to them are the most satisfying experiences of

life. Without going into a detailed refutation of this position, 1 think

it fair to say that i t has failed to be established to the satisfaction of

almost anyone in academic anthropology. This is to say, not that bio­

logical facts are irrelevant, or that men and women are not different, but

tha t these facts and differences only take on significance of superior/ in­

ferior within the framework of culturally defined value systems.

If we are unwilling to rest the case on gene tic deterrninism, i t seems

to me that we have only one way to proceed. We must attempt to inter­

pret female subordination in light of other universals, factors built into

the structure of the most generalized situation in which ali human be­

ings, in whatever culture, find .themselves. For example, every human

being has a physical body and a sense of nonphysical mind, is part of a

society of other individuals a n d a n inheritor of a cultural tradition, and

must engage in sorne relationship, however mediated, wi th "nature,"

or the nonhuman realm, in order to survive. Every human being is born

(to a mother) and ultimately dies, ali are assumed to have an interest

in personal survival, and society /culture has i ts own interest in (or at

least momentum toward) continuity and survival, which transcends the

lives and deaths of particular individuals. And so forth. It is in the realm

of such universals of the human condition that we must seek an expla­

nation for the universal fact of female devaluation.

I translate the problem, in other words, into the following simple

question. What could there be in the generalized structure and condi­

tions of existence, common to every culture, that would lead every cul­

ture to place a lower value upon women? Specifically, my thesis is that

4
With all due respect to Lévi-Strauss (1969a,b, and passim).
SHERRY B. ORTNER

woman is being identified with-or, if you will, seems to be a symbol

of-something that every culture devalues, something that every culture

defines as being of a lower order of existence than itself. Now it seems

that there is only one thing that would fi t that description, and that is

"nature" in the most generalized sense. Every culture, or, generically,

"culture," is engaged in the process of generating and sustaining systems

of meaningful forms (symbols, artifacts, etc.) by means of which hu­

manity transcends the givens of natural existence, bends them to its

purposes, controls them in its interest. We may thus broadly equate

culture with the notion of human consciousness, or with the products

of human consciousness (i.e., systems of thought and technology), by

meaos of which humanity attempts to assert control over nature.

Now the categories of "nature" and "culture" are of course conceptual

categories-one can find no boundary out i n the actual world between

the two states or realms of being. And there is no question that sorne

cultures articulate a much stronger opposition between the two cate­

gories than others-it has even been argued that primitive peoples (sorne

or all) do not see or i n t u i t any distinction between the human cultural

state and the state of nature at all. Yet I would maintain that the uni­

versality of ritual betokens an assertion in all human cultures of the

specifically human ability to act upon and regulate, rather than pas­

sively move with and be moved by, the givens of natural existence. In

ritual, the purposive manipulation of given forms toward regulating

and sustaining order, every culture asserts that proper relations between

human existence and natural forces depend upon culture's employing

its special powers to regulate the overall processes of the world and life.

One realm of cultural thought in which these points are often articu­

lated is that of concepts of purity and pollution. Virtually every culture

has sorne such beliefs, which seem in large part (though not, of course,

entirely) to be concerned with the relationship between culture and

nature (see Ortner, 1 9 7 3 , n.d.). A well-known aspect of purity /pollution

beliefs cross-culturally is that of the natural "contagian" of pollution;

left to i ts own devices, pollution (for these purposes grossly equated with

the unregulated operation of natural energies) spreads and overpowers

ali that it comes in contact with. Thus a puzzle-if pollution is so strong,

how can anything be purified? Why is the purifying agent not itself

polluted? The answer, in keeping with the present line of argument, is

that purification is effected i n a ritual context; purification ritual, as

a purposive activity that pits self-conscious (symbolic) action against

natural energies, is more powerful than those energies.

In any case, my point is simply that every culture implicitly recognizes


Is Female to M a l e a s Nature Is to Culture1
73

and asserts a distinction between the operation of nature and the opera­

tion of culture (human consciousness and its products); and further,

that the distinctiveness of culture rests precisely on the fact that i t can

under most circumstances transcend natural conditions and turn them

to its purposes. Thus culture (i.e. every culture) at sorne level of aware­

ness asserts itself to be not only distinct from but superior to nature,

and that sense of distinctiveness and superiority rests precisely on the

ability to transform-to "socialize" and "culturalize"-nature.

Returning now to the issue of women, their pan-cultural second-class

status could be accounted Ior, quite simply, by postulating that women

are being identified or symbolically associated with nature, as opposed

t o m e n , who are identified with culture. Since i t is always culture's proj­

ect to subsume and transcend nature, i f women were considered part

of nature, then culture would find it "natural" to subordinate, not to

say oppress, them. Yet although this argument can be shown to have

considerable force, i t seems to oversimplify the case. The formulation I

would like to defend and elaborate on in the following section, then, is

that women are seen "merely" as being closer to nature than men. That

is, culture (still equated relatively unambiguously with men) recognizes

that women are active participants in its special processes, but at the

same time sees them as being more rooted in, or having more direct

affi.nity with, nature.

The revision may seem minor or even trivial, but I think it is a more

accurate rendering of cultural assumptions. Further, the argument cast

in these terms has severa! analytic advantages over the simpler formu­

lation; I shall discuss these later. It might simply be stressed here that

the revised argument would still account for the pan-cultural devalua­

tion of women, for even if women are not equated with nature, they are

nonetheless seen as representing a lower order of being, as being less

transcendental of nature than m e n a r e . The next task of the paper, then,

is to consider why they might be viewed in that way.

Why Is Woman Seen as Closer to Naturel

I t all begins of course with the body and the natural procreative func­

tions specific to women alone. We can sort out for discussion three levels

at which this absolute physiological fact has significance: (1) woman's

�ody a n d its functions, more involved more of the time with "species

Iife," seem to place her closer to nature, in contrast to man's physiology,

which frees him more completely to take up the projects of culture; (2)

woman's body and its functions place her in social roles that in turn

are considered to b e a t a lower order of the cultural process than man's:

'
SHERRY B. ORTNER
74

a n d (3) woman's traditional social roles, imposed because of her body

and its functíons, in turn give her a different psychic structure, which,

like her physiologícal nature and her social roles, is seen as being closer

to nature. I shall discuss each of these points in tum, showing first how

in each instance certain factors strongly tend to align woman with na­

ture, then indicating other factors that demonstrate her full alignment

wi th culture, the combined factors thus placing her in a problema tic

intermediate posi tion. It will become clear in the course of the discussion

why meo seem by contrast less intermediate, more purely "cultural" than

women. And I reiterate that I am dealing only at the level of cultural

and human universals. These arguments are intended to apply to gen­

eralized humanity; they grow out of the human condítion, as humanity

has experienced and confronted i t up to the present day.

I. Woman's physiolog;y seen as closer to nature. This part of my argu­

ment has been anticipated, with subtlety, cogency, and a great deal of

hard data, by de Beauvoir ( 1 9 5 3 ) . De Beauvoir reviews the physiologi­

cal structure, development, and functions of the human female and

concludes that "the female, to a greater extent than the male, is the

prey of the species" (p. 60). She points out that many major areas and

processes of the woman's body serve no apparent function for the health

and stability of the individual; on the contrary, as they perform their

specific organic functions, they are often sources of discomfort, pain,

and danger. The breasts are irrelevant to personal health; they may

be excised at any time of a woman's life. "Many of the ovarian secretions

function for the benefit of the egg, promoting its maturation and adapt­

ing the uterus to its requirements; in respect to the organism as a whole,

they make for disequilibrium rather than for regulation-the woman

is adapted to the needs of the egg rather than to her own requirements"

(p. 24). Menstruation is often uncomfortable, sometimes painful; it

frequently has negative emotional correlates and in any case involves

bothersome tasks of cleansing and waste disposal; and-a point that de

Beauvoir does not mention-in many cultures it interrupts a woman's

routine, putting her in a stigmatized state involving various restrictions

on her activities and social contacts. In pregnancy many of the woman's

vitamin and mineral resources are channeled into nourishing the fetus,

depleting her own strength and energies. And finally, childbirth itself

is painful and dangerous (pp. 24-27 passim). In sum, de Beauvoir con­

eludes that the female "is more enslaved to the species than the male,

her animality is more manifest" (p. 2 3 9 ) .

While de Beauvoir's book is ideological, her survey of woman's phys­

iological situation seems fair and accurate. I t is simply a fact that pro-
Is Female to M a l e a s Nature Is to Culture,
75

portionately more of woman's body space, for a greater percentage of

her lifetime, and at some-sometimes great-cost to her personal health,

strength, and general stability, is taken up with the natural processes

surrounding the reproduction of the species.

De Beauvoir goes on-to discuss the negative implications of woman's

"enslavement to the species" in relation to the projects in which humans

engage, projects through which culture is generated and defined. She

arrives thus at the crux of her argument (pp. 58-59):

Here we have the key to the whole mystery. On the biological level a species is

maintained only by creating itself anew; but this creation results only in

repeating the same Life in more individuals. But man assures the repetition

of Life while transcending Life through Existence [i.e. goal-oriented, meaning­

ful action]; by this transcendence he creates values that deprive pure repetition

of all value. In the animal, the freedom and varíery of male activities are vain

because no project is involved. Except for his services to the species, what he

does is immaterial. Whereas in serving the species, the human male also re­

models the face of the earth, he creates new instruments, he invents, he shapes

the future.

In other words, woman's body seems to doom her to mere reproduction

of life; the male, in contrast, lack i n g natural creative functions , must

(or has the o pp or t u n i ty to) assert his crea ti vit y e x ter n ally , "artificially,"

through the m edium of te c hno l o gy and s y mbo l s . I n so doing, he creates

r e la t i v el y la sti n g, ete rna l, tr anscendent objects, while the woman creates

only perishables-human bein gs.

T his f o rm ula t i o n o p ens up a number of im p ortant ins ig hts . I t speaks,

for e xa m pl e , to the gr eat puzzle of why male acti v ities invol v i n g the

destructi o n of l i fe ( hun t in g and warfare) are often g i v en more prestige

than the f e m a le's a bi li t y to give b irth , to cre a t e li f e . Wi thin de B eau ­

voir's framework, we reali ze i t is not the k i ll in g th at is the rele v ant and

valued as p e ct of hun t in g and warfare; rather, it is the t ranscen d ental

(s ocia l, cul t ural ) nat u re of these activities, as opp osed to the naturalness

of the process of b irth : "For i t is not i n giving life but in ris ki n g l ife that

man is raised above the an i mal ; t h a t is why s up er i or it y ha s b een accord­

ed in humani ty not to the sex t h a t b rin gs forth but to that w hi ch kills"

(ibid.).

Thus if male is, as I am sugg est in g , everywhere (u n co n sci ousl y) asso­

c i a te d with culture an d female seems closer to nature, the ra ti ona l e for

these associat i ons is n ot very d i fficul t to gr as p, merely from co nsidering

the im pli cations of the p h ys i o log ic al co n tra s t between m ale and female.

At the same time , however, wo m an c a nn o t be c o nsigned fully to the

category of nature, for it is perfectly obvious t ha t she is a full-fledged


SHERRY B. ORTNER

human being endowed with human consciousness j u s t as a man is; she

is half of the human race, without whose cooperation the whole enter­

prise would collapse. She may seem more in the possession of nature than

man, but having conscíousness, she thinks and speaks; she generares,

communicates, and manipulates symbols, categories, and values. She

participates in human dialogues not only with other women but also

with men. As Lévi-Strauss says, "Woman could never become j u s t a sign

and nothing more, since even in a man's world she is still a person, and

since insofar as she is defined as a sign she must [still] be recognized as

a generator of signs" ( 1 9 6 9 a : 496).

Indeed, the fact of woman's full human consciousness, her full involve­

ment i n and commitment to culture's project of transcendence over

nature, may ironically explain another of the great puzzles of "the

woman problem"-woman's nearly universal unquestioning acceptance

of her own devaluation. For i t would seem that, as a conscious human

and member of culture, she has followed out the logic of culture's argu­

ments and has reached culture's conclusions along with the men. As de

Beauvoir puts i t (p. 59):

For she, too, is an existent, she feels the urge to surpass, and her project is not

mere repetition but transcendence towards a different future-in her heart of

hearts she finds confirmation of the masculine pretensions. She joins the roen

in the festivals that celebrate the successes and victories of the males. Her mis­

fortune is to have been biologically destined for the repetition of Life, when

even in her own view Life does not carry within itself i ts reasons for beíng,

reasons that are more important than life itself.

In other words, woman's consciousness-her membership, as i t were, in

culture-is evidenced in part by the very fact that she accepts her own

devaluation and takes culture's point of view.

1 have tried here to show one part of the logic of tha t view, the part

that grows directly from the physiological differences between men and

women. Because of woman's greater bodily involvement with the natu­

ral functions surrounding reproduction, she is seen as more a part of

nature than man is. Yet in part because of her consciousness and partici­

pation in human social dialogue, she is recognized as a participant in

culture. Thus she appears as something intermediate between culture

and nature, lower on the scale of transcendence than man .

.2 . Woman's social role seen as closer to nature. Woman's physiological

functíons, 1 have j u s t argued, may tend in themselves to motívate! a view

G Semantic theory uses the concept of motivation of meaning, which encompasses

various ways in which a meaning may be assigned to a symbol because of certain

objective properties of that symbol, rather than by arbitrary association. In a sense,


Is Female to M a l e a s Nature Is to Culturet
77

of woman as closer to nature, a view she herself, a s a n observer of herself

and the world, would tend to agree with. Woman creates naturally from

within her own being, whereas man is free to, or forced to, create artifi­

cially, that is, through cultural meaos, and in such a way as to sustain

culture. In addition, 1.- now wish to show how woman's physiological

functions have tended universally to limit her social movement, and to

confine her universally to certain social contexts which in turn are seen

as closer to nature. That is, not only her bodily processes but the social

situation in which her bodily processes locate her may carry this sig­

nificance. And insofar as she is pennanently associated (in the eyes of

culture) with these social milieux, they add weight (perhaps the decisive

part of the burden) to the view of woman as closer to nature. 1 refer

here of course to wornan's confinement to the domestic family context,

a confinement motívated, no doubt, by her lactation processes.

Woman's body, like that of all female mammals, generates milk dur­

ing and after pregnancy for the feeding of the newborn baby. The baby

cannot survive without breast milk or sorne similar formula at this stage

of life. Since the mother's body goes through its lactation processes i n

direct relation to a pregnancy with a particular child, the relationship

of nursing between mother and child is seen as a natural bond, other

feeding arrangements being seen in most cases as unnatural and make­

shif t. Mothers and their chíldren, according to cultural reasoning, be­

long together. Further, children beyond infancy are not strong enough

to engage in majar work, yet are mobile and unruly and not capable of

understanding various dangers; they thus require supervision and con·

stant care. Mother is the obvious person for this task, as an extension

of her natural nursing bond with the children, or because she has a new

infant and is already involved with child-oriented activities. Her own

activities are thus circumscribed by the limitations and low levels of


6
her children's strengths and s k i l l s : she is confined to the domestic family

group; "woman's place is in the home."

Woman's association with the domestic circle would contribute to the

view of her as closer to nature in severa! ways. In the first place, the

sheer fact of constant association with children plays a role in the issue;

one can easily see how infan ts and children might themselves be con­

sidered part of nature. Infants are barely human and utterly unsocial-

this entire paper is an inquiry into the motivation of the meaning of woman as a

symbol, asking why woman may be unconsciously assigned the significance of being

�loser to nature. For a concise statement on the various types of motivation of mean­
mg, see Ullman (1963).
8
A situation that often serves to make her more childlike herself.
SHERRY B. ORTNER

ized; like animals they are unable to walk upright, they excrete wíthour

control, they do not speak. Even slightly older children are clearly not

yet fully under the sway of culture. They do not yet understand social

duties, responsibilities, and morals; their vocabulary and their range of

learned skills are small. One finds implicit recognition of an association

between children and nature in many cultural practices. For example,

most cultures have initiation rites for adolescents (primarily for boys;

I shall return to this point below), the point of which is to move the

child ritually from a less than fully human state into full participation

in society and culture; many cultures do not hold funeral rites for chil­

dren who die at early ages, explici tly beca use they are not yet fully social

beings. Thus children are likely to be categorized with nature, and

woman's close association with children may compound her potential

for being seen as closer to nature herself. It is ironic that the rationale

for boys' initiation rites in many cultures is that the boys must be purged

of the defilement accrued from being around mother and other women

so much of the time, when in fact much of the woman's defilement may

derive from her being around children so much of the time.

The second major problematic implication of women's close associa­

tion with the domestic context derives from certain structural conflicts

between the family and society at large in any social system. The im­

plications of the "domestic/public opposition" in relation to the posi­

tion of women have been cogently developed by Rosaldo (this volume),

and I simply wish to show i ts relevance to the present argument. The

notion that the domestic unit-the biological family charged with repro­

ducing and socializing new members of the society-is opposed to the

public entity-the superimposed network of alliances and relationships

that is the society-is also the basis of Lévi-Strauss's argument in the

Elementary Structures of Kinship (1969a). Lévi-Strauss argues not only

that this opposition is present in every social system, but further that

it has the significance of the opposition between nature and culture.

The universal incest prohibition 1 and its ally, the rule of exogamy

(marriage outside the group), ensure that "the risk of seeing a biological

family become established as a closed system is definitely eliminated;

the biological group can no longer stand apart, and the bond of alliance

with another family ensures the dominance of the social over the bio­

logical, and of the cultural over the natural" (p. 479). And although

not every culture articulates a radical opposition between the domestic

1 David M. Schneider (personal communication) is prepared to argue that the

incest taboo is not universal, on the basis of material from Oceania. Let us say at

this point, then, that it is virtually universal.


Is Female to M a l e a s Nature Is to Culture?
79

and the public as such, i t is hardly contestable that the domestic is al­

ways subsumed by the public; domestic units are allied with one another

through the enactment of rules that are logically a t a higher level than

the units themselves; this creates an emergent unit-society-that is

logically at a higher, level than the domestic units of which i t is com-

posed.

Now, since women are associated with, and indeed are more or less

confined to, the domestic context, they are identified with this lower

order of social/ cultural organization. What are the implications of this

for the way they are viewed? First, if the specifically biological (repro­

ductive) function of the family is stressed, as in L é v í - S t r a u s s ' s formula­

tion, then the family (and hence woman) is identified with nature pure

and simple, as opposed to culture. But this is obviously too simple; the

point seems more adequately formulated as follows: the family (and

hence woman) represents lower-level, socially fragmenting, particular­

istic sort of concerns, as opposed to interfamilial relations representing

hígher-level, integrative, universalistic sorts of concerns. Since roen lack

a "natural" basis (nursing, generalized to child care) for a familia! ori­

entation, their sphere of activity is defined at the level of interfamilial

relations. And hence, so the cultural reasoning seems to go, men are the

"natural" proprietors of religion, ritual, politics, and other realms of

cultural thought and action in which universalistic statements of spiri­

tual and social synthesis are made. Thus men are identified not only

with culture, i n the sense of all human creativity, as opposed to nature;

they are identified in particular with culture in the old-fashioned sense

of the finer and higher aspects of human thought-art, religion, law, etc.

Here again, the logic of cultural reasoning aligning woman with a

lower order of culture than man is clear and, on the surface, quite com­

pelling. At the same time, woman cannot be fully consigned to nature,

for there are aspects of her situation, even within the domestic context,

that undeniably demonstrate her participation in the cultural process.

It goes without saying, of course, that except for nursing newborn in­

fants (and artificial nursing devices can cut even this biological tíe),

there is no reason why it has to be mother-as opposed to father, or any­

one else-who remains identified with child care. But even assuming

that other practica! and emotional reasons conspire to keep woman in

this sphere, it is possible to show that her activities in the domestic con­

text could as logically put her squarely in the category of culture.

In the first place, one must point out that woman not only feeds and

deans up after children in a simple caretaker operation; she in fact is

the primary agent of their early socialization. I t is she who transforms


80 SHERRY B. ORTNER

newborn infants from mere organisms into cultured humans, teaching

them manners and the proper ways to behave i n order to become full­

fledged members of the culture. On the basis of her socializing functions

alone, she could n o t be more a representative of culture. Yet in virtually

every society there is a point a t which the socialization of boys is trans­

ferred to the hands of men. The boys are considered, in one set of terms

or another, not yet "really" socialized; their e n t r é e into the realm of

fully human (social, cultural) status can be accomplished only by men.

We still see this in our own schools, where there is a gradual inversion

in the proportion of female to male teachers up through the grades:

most kindergarten teachers are female; most university professors are


8
male.

Or again, take cooking. In the overwhelming majority of societies

cooking is the woman's work. No doubt this stems from practica! con­

siderations-since the woman has to stay home with the baby, it is con­

venient for her to perform the chores centered in the home. B u t i f it is

true, as Lévi-Strauss has argued ( 1 9 6 9 b ) , that transfor m ing the raw into

the cooked may re p resent, in many s y stems of tho ug ht , the transition

from nature to culture , then here we have woman aligned with t h is im­

portant culturalizing process, which could easily p lace her in the cate ­

gory of culture , trium p hin g over n ature . Y et it is also interesting to n o te

that when a culture ( e .g . F r a nce or C hina ) dev e lops a tradition of h a u t e

cuisine-"real" cooking, as o pp osed to t ri vial ordina ry do m estic cook­

ing-the high chefs are almost always men. T hus the p attern replicates

that in the area of soci a lization-women p erform lower - level conver­

sions from nature to culture, but when the c u lture distin g uishe s a hi g her

level of the sa m e functions, the hig h er l evel is res tricted to m en .

In short, we see once a ga in so rn e sources of woman ' s ap p earing more

inte rm ediate than man with respect to the nature / culture dichotomy .

H er " natural " asso ci atio n wit h the domestic c o nte x t ( moti v ated by h er

natural lactation functions ) tends to compound her potenti a l for being

viewed as closer to nature , because of the ani m a l - l i k e n ature of c hil dr en ,

a nd because of the infrasocial connotation of the domestic group as

a g ainst the rest of societ y . Y et at the same t i me her so c iali z i n g an d cook­

ing functions w ithin the do m estic conte x t s h o w her to be a powerful

a g ent of the cultural process, constantl y t ransforming raw n atural re­

sources into cultura l products. B elonging to c u l t u r e, y et a pp earing to

have stron g er and more direct c onne c t i ons w i th na t u re , s h e is once ag a in

seen as si tua ted between the two r ea lm s.

s I remember having my first male teacher in the fifth grade, and I remember

being excited about that-it was somehow more grown-up.


Is Female to M a l e a s Nature Is to Culturet

J· Woman's psyche seen as closer to nature. The suggestion that

woman has not only a different body and a different social locus from

man but also a different psychic structure is most controversial, 1 will

argue that she probably does have a different psychic structure, but I

will draw heavily on <;Jiodorow's paper (this volume) to establish first

that her psychic structure need not be assumed to be innate; i t can be

accounted for, as Chodorow convincingly shows, by the facts of the

probably universal female socialization experience. N onetheless, if we

grant the empirical near universality of a "Ieminine psyche" with cer­

tain specific characteristics, these characteristics would add weight to the

cultura! view of woman as closer to na ture.

It is important to specify what we see as the dominant and universal

aspects of the feminine psyche. If we postulate emotionality or irration­

ality, we are confronted with those traditions in various parts of the

world i n which women functionally are, and are seen as, more practica},

pragmatic, and this-worldly than men. One relevant dimension that

does seem pan-culturally applicable is that of relative concreteness vs.

relative abstractness: the feminine personality tends to be involved with

concrete feelings, things, and people, rather than with abstract entities;

i t tends toward personalism and particularism. A second, closely related,

dimension seems to be that of relative subjectivity vs. relative objec­

tivity: Chodorow cites Carlson's study (1971), which concludes that

"males represent experiences of self, others, space, and time in individu­

alistic, objective, and distant ways, while females represent experiences

in relatively interpersonal, subjective, immediate ways" (this volume, p.

56, quoting Carlson, p. 2 7 0 ) . Although this and other studies were done

in Western societies, Chodorow sees their findings on the differences

between male and female personality-roughly, that men are more ob­

jective and inclined to relate in terms of relatively abstract categories,

women more subjective and inclined to relate in terms of relatively con­

crete phenomena-as "general and nearly universal differences" (p. 4 3 ) .

But the thrust of Chodorow's elegantly argued paper is that these dif­

ferences are not innate or genetically programmed; they arise from

nearly universal features of family structure, namely that "women, uni­

versally, are largely responsible for early child care and for (at least)

later female socialization'' (p. 43) and that "the structural situation of

child rearing, reinforced by female and male role training, produces

these differences, which are replicated and reproduced in the sexual

sociology of adult life" (p. 44). Chodorow argues that, because mother

is the early socializer of both boys and girls, both develop "personal

identification" with her, i . e . diffuse identification with her general per-


SHERRY B. ORTNER

sonality, behavior traits, values, and attitudes (p. 5 1 ) . A son, however,

must ultimately shif t to a masculine role identity, which involves build­

ing an identification with the father. Since father is almost always more

remote than ..mother (he is rarely involved in child care, and perhaps

works away from home much of the <lay), building an identification

with father involves a "positional ídentification," i . e . identification with

Iather's male role as a collection of abstraer elements, rather than a

personal identification with father as a real individual (p. 49). Further,

as the hoy enters the larger social world, he finds i t in fact organized

around more abstract and universalistic criteria (see Rosaldo, this vol­

ume, pp. 2 8- 2 9 ; Chodorow, p. 58), as I have indicated in the previous

section; thus his earlier socialization prepares him for, and is reinforced

by, the type of adult social experience he will have.

For a young girl, in contrast, the personal identification w i t h mother,

which was created in early infancy, can persist into the process of learn­

ing female role identity. Because mother is immediate and present when

the daughter is learning role identity, learning to be a woman involves

the continuity and development of a girl's relationship to her mother,

and sustains the identification with her as an individual; it <loes not

involve the learning of externally defined role characteristics (Chodo­

row, p. 5 1 ). This pattern prepares the girl for, and is fully reinforced

by, her social situation in later life; she will become involved in the

world of women, which is characterized by few formal role differences

(Rosaldo, p. 29), and which involves again, in motherhood, "personal

identification" with her children. And so the cycle begins anew.

Chodorow demonstrates to my satisfaction at least that the feminine

personality, characterized by personalism and particularism, can be ex­

plained as having been generated by social-structural arrangements

rather than by innate biological factors. The point need not be bela­

bored further. But insofar as the "ferninine personality" has been a

nearly universal fact, it can be argued that its characteristics may have

contributed further to the view of women as being somehow less cul­

tural than men. That is, women would tend to enter into relationships

with the world that culture might see as being more "like nature"­

immanent and embedded in things as given-than "Iike culture"­

transcending and transforming things through the superimposition of

abstract categories and transpersonal values. Woman's relationships tend

to be, like nature, relatively unmediated, more direct, whereas man

not only tends to relate in a more mediated way, b u t i n fact ultimately

often relates more consistently and strongly to the mediating categories

and forms than to the persons or objects themselves.

I t is thus not difficult to see how the feminine personality would lend
Is Female to M a l e a s Nature Is to Culturet

weight to a view of women as being "closer to nature." Yet a t the same

time, the modes of relating characteristic of women u n d e n i a b l y play a

powerful and important role in the cultural process. For j u s t as rela­

tively unmediated relating is i n sorne sense at the lower end of the spec­

trum of human spiritual functions, embedded and particularizing rather

than transcending and synthesizing, yet that mode of relating also stands

at the upper end of that spectrum. Consider the mother-child relation­

ship. Mothers tend to be commi tted to their children as individuals,

regardless of sex, age, beauty, clan affiliation, or other categories in

which the child might participate. Now any relationship with this qual­

ity-not just mother and child but any sort of highly personal, relatively

unmediated commitment-may be seen as a challenge to culture and

society "from below," insofar as i t represents the fragmentary p o t e n t i a l

of individual loyalties vis-a-vis the solidarity of the group. B u t i t may

also be seen as embodying the synthesizing agent for culture and society

"from above," in that it represents generalized human values above and

beyond loyalties to particular social categories. Every society must have

social categories that transcend personal loyalties, b u t every society must

also generate a sense of ultimate moral unity for ali its members abovc

and beyond those social categories. Thus that psychic mode seemingly

typical of women, which tends to disregard categories and to seek "com­

munion" (Chodorow, p. 55, following Bakan, 1 9 6 6 ) directly and person­

ally with others, although i t may appear infracultural from one p o i n t

of view, is a t the same time associated with the highest levels of the cul­

tural process.

The lmplications o/ Intermediacy

My primary purpose in this paper has been to attempt to explain the

universal secondary status of women. Intellectually and personally, 1 felt

strongly challenged by this problem; 1 felt compelled to d e a l with it

befare undertaking an analysis of woman's posi tion i n any particular

society. Local variables of economy, ecology, history, political and social

structure, values, and world view-these could explain variations wi thin

this universal, but they could not explain the universal itself. And if

we were not to accept the ideology of biological determinism, then ex­

planation, i t seemed to me, could only proceed by reference to other

universals of the human cultural situation. Thus the general outlines

of the approach-although not of course the p a r t i c u l a r solution offered

+-were determined by the problem itself, and not by any predilection

on my part for global abstract structural analysis.

I argued that the universal devaluation of women could be explained

by postulating that women are seen as closer to nature than men, meo
SHERRY B. ORTNER

being seen as more unequivocally occupying the high ground of cu}.

ture. The c u l t u r e / n a t u r e distinction is itself a product of culture, cu}.

ture being minimally defined as the transcendence, by means of systems

of though t- and technology, of the natural givens of exis tence. This of

course is an analytic definition, b u t I argued that at sorne level every

culture incorporates this notion in one form or other, if only through

the performance of ritual as an assertion of the human ability to ma­

nipulate those givens. In any case, the core of the paper was concerned

with showing why women might tend to be assumed, over and over,

in the most diverse sorts of world views and in cultures of every degree

of complexity, to be closer to nature than men. Woman's physiology,

more involved more of the time with "specíes of life"; woman's associ­

ation with the structurally subordinate domestic context, charged with

the crucial function of transforming animal-like infants into cultured

beings; "woman's psyche," appropriately molded to mothering func­

tions by her own socialization and tending toward greater personalism

and less mediated modes of relating-all these factors make woman

appear to be rooted more directly and deeply in nature. At the same

time, however, her "membership" and fully necessary participation in

culture are recognized by culture and cannot be denied. Thus she is

seen to occupy an intermediate position between culture and nature.

This intermediacy has several implications for analysis, depending

upon how it is interpreted. First, of course, i t answers my primary ques­

tion of why woman is everywhere seen as lower than man, for even if

she is not seen as nature pure and simple, she is still seen as achieving

less transcendence of nature than man. Here intermediate simply means

"middle status" on a hierarchy of being from culture to nature.

Second, intermediate may have the significance of " m e d í a t í n g , " i.e.

performing sorne sort of syn thesizing or converting function between

nature and culture, here seen (by culture) not as two ends of a con­

tinuum but as two radically different sorts of processes i n the world.

The domestic unit-and hence woman, who in virtually every case

appears as its primary representative-is one of culture's crucial agen­

cies for the conversion of nature into culture, especially with referencc

to the socialization of children. Any culture's continued viability de­

pends upon properly socialized individuals who will see the world i n

that culture's terms and adhere more or less unquestioningly to its moral

precepts. The functions of the domestic u n i t must be closely controlled

in order to ensure this outcome; the stability of the domestic unit as

an institution must be placed as far as possible beyond question. (We

see sorne aspects of the protection of the integrity and stability of the
Is Female to M a l e a s N a t u r e Is to C u l t u r e l

domestic group in the powerful taboos against incest, matricide, patri­


9)
cide, and fratricide. Insofar as woman is universally the primary agent

of early socialization and is seen as virtually the embodiment of the

functions of the domestic group, she will tend to come under the heavier

restrictions and circumscriptions surrounding that u n i t . Her (culturally

defined) intermediate position between nature and culture, here having

the significance of her mediation ( i . e . performing conversion functions)

between nature and culture, would thus account not only for her lower

status but for the greater restrictions placed upon her activities. I n vir­

tually every culture her permissible sexual activities are more closely

circumscribed than man's, she is offered a much smaller range of role

choices, and she is afforded direct access to a far more limited range of

its social institutions. Further, she is almost universally socialized to

have a narrower and generally more conservative set of attitudes and

views than man, and the limited social contexts of her adult life rein­

force this situation. This socially engendered conservatism and tradi­

tionalism of woman's thinking is another-perhaps the worst, certainly

the most insidious-mode of social restriction, and would clearly be

related to her traditional function of producing well-socialized members

of the group.

Finally, woman's intermedia te posi tion may have the implication of

greater symbolic ambiguity (see also Rosaldo, this volume), Shifting our

image of the culture/nature relationship once again, we may envision

culture in this case as a small clearing within the forest of the larger

natural system. From this point of view, that which is intermediate be­

tween culture and nature is located on the continuous periphery of

culture's clearing; and though i t may thus appear to stand both above

and below (and beside) culture, i t is simply outside and around i t . We

can begin to understand then how a single system of cultural thought

can of ten assign to woman completely polarized and apparently con­

tradictory meanings, since extremes, as we say, meet. That she often

represents both life and death is only the simplest example one could

mention.

For another perspective on the same point, it will be recalled that the

psychic mode associated with women seems to stand a t both the bottom

and the top of the scale of human modes of relating. The tendency in

that mode is to get involved more directly with people as individuals

and n o t a s representatives of one social category or another; this mode

can be seen as either "ignoring" (and thus subverting) or "transcending"

9
Nobody seems to care much about sororicide-a point that ought to be investí­
gated.
86 SHERRY B. ORTNER

(and thus achieving a higher synthesis of) those social categories, de­

pending upon the cultural view for any given purpose. Thus we can

account easily Ior both the subversive feminine symbols (witches, evil

eye, menstrual pollution, castrating mothers) and the feminine symbols

of transcendence (mother goddesses, merciful dispensers of s a l v a ti o n,

female symbols of justice, and the strong presence of feminine symbol­

ism in the realms of art, religion, r i t u a l , and law). Feminine symbolism,

far more of ten t h a n m a s c u l i n e syrnbolism, manifests this propensi ty to­

ward polarized ambiguity-sometimes utterly exalted, sometimes utterly

debased, rarely wi thin the normal range of human possibilities.

If woman's (culturally viewed) intermediacy between culture and na­

ture has this implication of generalized ambiguity of meaning charac­

teristic of marginal phenomena, then we are also i n a better position to

account for those cultural and historical "inversíons" i n which women

are in sorne way or other symbolically aligned with culture and men

with nature. A number of cases come to m i n d : the Sirionó of Brazil,

among whom, according to Ingham ( 1 9 7 1 : 1 0 9 8 ) , "nature, the raw, and

m a l e n e s s " are opposed to "culture, the cooked, and Iemaleness't.w Nazi

Germany, in which women were s a i d to be the guardians of culture and

morals; European courtly love, i n which man considered himself the

beast and woman the pristine exalted object-a pattern of thinking that

persists, for example, among modero Spanish peasants (see Pitt-Rivers,

1 9 6 1 ; Rosaldo, this volume). And there are no doubt other cases of this

sort, including sorne aspects of our own culture's view of women. Each

such instance of an alignment of women with culture rather than nature

requires detailed analysis of specific historical and ethnographic d a t a .

But in indicating how nature in general, and the feminine mode of

interpersonal relations i n particular, can appear from certain points of

view to stand both under and over (but really simply outside of) the

sphere of culture's hegemony, we have a t least laid the groundwork for

such analyses.

In short, the postulate that woman is viewed as closer to nature than

man has severa! implications for further analysis, and can be interpreted

in severa! different ways. If it is viewed simply as a middle position on

a scale from culture down to nature, then i t is still seen as lower than

culture and thus accounts for the pan-cultural assumption that woman

is lower than man i n the order of things. If i t is read as a mediating

10 lngham's discussion is rather ambiguous itself, since women are also associated

with a n i m a l s : .• The contrasts m a n / a n i m a l and m a n / w o m a n are evidently similar . . .

h u n t i n g is the means of acquiring women as well as animals" (p. 1095). A careful

reading of the data suggests that both women and animals are mediators between

nature and culture in this tradition.


Is Female to M a l e a s Nature Is to Culturet

element in the culture-nature r e l a t i o n s h í p , then it may account i n part

for rhe cultural tendency n o t merely to devalue woman b u t to circum­

scribe and restrict her functions, since culture must m a i n t a i n control

over its (pragmatic and symbolic) mechanisms for the conversion of

nature into culture. 'And i f i t is read as an a m b i g u o u s status between

culture and nature, i t may help account for the fact that, i n specific cul­

tural ideologies and symbolizations, woman can occasionally be aligned

with culture, and i n any event is often assigned polarized and contra­

dictory meanings within a single symbolic system. M i d d l e status, me­

diating functions, ambiguous meaning-all are different readings, for

different contextual purposes, of woman's being seen as intermediate

between nature and culture.

C onclusions

Ultimately, it must be stressed again tha t the whole scheme is a con­

struct of culture rather than a fact of nature. Woman is n o t "in reality"

any closer to (or further from) nature than man-both have conscious­

ness, both are mortal. B u t there are certainly reasons why she appears

that way, which is what I have tried to show in this paper. The result

is a (sadly) efficient feedback system: various aspects of woman's situa­

tion (physical, social, psychological) contribute to her being seen as

closer to nature, while the view of her as closer to nature is i n turn em­

bodied i n institutional forros that reproduce her s i t u a t i o n . The impli­

cations for social change are similarly circular: a different c u l t u r a l view

can only grow out of a different social a c t u a l i t y ; a different social ac­

tuality can only grow out of a different cultural view.

I t is clear, then, that the s i t u a t i o n must be attacked from both sides.

Efforts directed solely at changing the social institutions-through set­

ting quotas on hiring, for example, or through p a s s i n g equal-pay-for­

equal-work laws-cannot have far-reaching effects i f cultural language

and imagery continue to purvey a relatively devalued view of women.

But a t the same time efforts directed solely a t changing cultural assump­

tions-through male and female consciousness-raising groups, for ex­

ample, or through revision of educational materials and mass-media

imagery-cannot be successful unless the i n s t i t u t i o n a l base of the society

is changed to support and reinforce the changed cultura l view. Ulti­

mately, both men and women can and must be equally involved in

projects of creativity and transcendence. Only then w i l l women be seen

as aligned with culture, in c u l t u r e ' s ongoing d ia l ec t i c with nature.

You might also like