Obeying The Law

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 38

The University of Sydney Law School

Legal Studies Research Paper Series

No. 18/45

August 2018

Obeying the Law


Michael Sevel

This paper can be downloaded without charge from the


Social Science Research Network Electronic Library
at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


Forthcoming in Legal Theory (2018)

OBEYING THE LAW

Michael Sevel 1
Senior Lecturer in Jurisprudence
University of Sydney Law School
[email protected]

What is it to obey the law? What is it to disobey? Remarkably little attention has been

paid to these questions. The inattention is remarkable because the concepts of obedience and

disobedience have long been central to several perennial debates in moral, legal, and political

philosophy, and yet participants in those debates have either given unreflective, cursory

accounts or said nothing substantive about them at all. Examples of the inattention are not

hard to find. It has been debated whether we have a duty or obligation to obey the law for

nearly as long as there has been law. But the vast majority of theorists of political obligation

have been far more interested in the normative features of that alleged duty – its grounds,

whether it is universal, overriding, absolute, pro tanto, and so on – than with its content, that is,

with what sort of thing a person must do, or what sort of thing must happen, in order for that

1
For helpful discussions, I thank Farrah Ahmed, Mitch Berman, Michelle Dempsey, Tom Dougherty, David Estlund,
Jessica Flanagan, Jeff Goldsworthy, Scott Hershovitz, Robert Hughes, Matt Lister, Adam Perry, David Plunkett,
Veronica Rodriguez-Blanco, Massimo Renzo, Enzo Rossi, Wojciech Sadurski, Fred Schauer, Stefan Sciaraffa, David
Shoemaker, A. John Simmons, Dale Smith, Larry Solum, Nicos Stravropouls, and Kevin Walton. I also thank
audiences at the Analytic Legal Philosophy Conference at the University of Virginia, the Institute for Law &
Philosophy at the University of Pennsylvania, the Legal and Political Theory Workshop at the National University of
Ireland Galway, the Irish Jurisprudence Society at Trinity College Dublin, the Association for Social and Legal
Philosophy Conference at the University of Warwick, the Department of Politics at Princeton University, the
University of Tartu Centre for Ethics, the Centre for Legal Governance at Macquarie University, the Legal Theory
Workshop at Melbourne Law School, and the Julius Stone Institute of Jurisprudence at the University of Sydney
Law School. This research was supported by the Centre for Ethics and Public Affairs, Murphy Institute, Tulane
University, and the National University of Singapore Faculty of Law.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


person to obey the law and thereby discharge the duty, whatever it is. 2 To take another

example, over the past fifty years, legal and political philosophers have been increasingly

interested in the nature and practice of civil disobedience, resulting in an enormous, complex

literature. However, those philosophers have been more interested in giving an account of the

‘civility’ of an act of the relevant sort – for example, that it is done publicly and conscientiously

for a political purpose, and so on – rather than in explaining what the relevant sort of act is, i.e.,

what constitutes disobedience. Indeed, nearly all writers on civil disobedience, from John

Rawls’ seminal discussion in the 1970s to the present, routinely use such terms as “breaches”

or “violations” of law to refer to the relevant phenomena, and leave it at that. 3 Finally, it has

long been a consensus among legal philosophers that it is of the nature of law to claim

authority over its citizens, and in turn that it is of the nature of authority to demand obedience

2
The inattention started early. In the founding text of the political obligation literature, Plato’s Crito, Socrates has
the Laws of Athens require that he either “persuade or obey” the laws (51a-52e), but no characterization of either
alternative is given. The matter is further complicated by the fact that the terms ‘persuade’ and ‘obey’ in Plato’s
Greek have a common verbal root (peithein), such that the active voice is used to express the former idea, and the
passive voice the latter. Socrates also speaks of doing what the law commands (poeteon ha an keleuei, at 51b) but
relies on his audience’s intuitive understanding of what that phrase is to mean. For discussion, see Richard Kraut,
Socrates and the State (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984), pp. 54-114. Modern contributions to the
literature fare no better, even when a writer’s stated purpose is to identify the problem. See e.g. Jonathan Wolff,
“What is the Problem of Political Obligation?,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91 (1991): 153-169, in which
obedience is taken as the central concern but no attention is ever given to saying what it is. More recently,
William Edmundson, in a survey of the duty-to-obey literature, spends several pages characterizing the duty under
discussion, but then stipulates, in a single sentence, what obedience to law is taken to be. He calls this stipulation
an “idiomatic point”, though, as I argue below, it involves substantial theoretical commitments which have rarely
been questioned. See Edmundson, “State of the Art: The Duty to Obey the Law,” Legal Theory 10 (2004), 215-259,
at p. 217. David Lefkowitz, in his survey of the same literature, makes the same stipulation, but oddly as an
explanation of the duty, not as an account of obedience itself. See Lefkowitz, “The Duty to Obey the Law,”
Philosophy Compass 1/6 (2006): 571-598, at pp. 572-573.
3
See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 2nd ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), where his stated
aim is to give an account of action “contrary to law” (p. 320), acts which are “violations” of the law (p. 323). Rawls
provides no further explanation of the relevant sort of action. The most recent substantive contribution to the civil
disobedience literature similarly contains no account at all of what ‘disobedience’ is supposed to be, and frames
the discussion vaguely in terms of “offending.” See Kimberley Brownlee, Conscience and Conviction: The Case for
Civil Disobedience (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), pp. 155-156.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


from those subject to it. 4 But while only theorists of authority have made substantive

philosophical claims about what in general obedience to law requires (though they have been

notably silent about disobedience), their supporting arguments are difficult to discern. In any

event, those claims about obedience, which I will collectively call the Standard View, have been

subject to precious little critical assessment. 5

It might be thought that this inattention is just as it should be, and that systematic

accounts of obeying and disobeying the law are in fact not required to answer such questions.

Philosophers have known well enough what obedience and disobedience are, and any attempt

to say anything more precise would obscure that which was sufficiently clear all along, and

would thus stifle, rather than facilitate, discussion. But a moment’s reflection reveals that

systematic accounts of these responses to law are of central importance in these debates.

4
Beginning in the seventeenth century, legal philosophers drew these connections because they conceived of law
on the model of sovereign command. See Gerald J. Postema, “Law as Command: The Model of Command in
Modern Jurisprudence,” Philosophical Issues 11 (2001): 470-501. While the command model of law has been
mostly jettisoned, the conceptual connection between authority and the demand for obedience continues to be
the orthodoxy. The locus classicus of the modern view is Joseph Raz, “Authority, Law, and Morality,” in Ethics in
the Public Domain (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994), at pp. 212-216. Recent restatements and
endorsements of the view can be found in Richard Dagger, “Authority, Legitimacy, and the Obligation to Obey the
Law,” Legal Theory (forthcoming), Daniel Viehoff, “Democratic Equality and Political Authority,” Philosophy &
Public Affairs 42 (2014): 337-375, at p. 340, and Stephen Perry, “Political Authority and Political Obligation,” Oxford
Studies in Philosophy of Law, Vol. 2 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), at p. 1.
5
See Scott Hershovitz, “The Authority of Law,” in A. Marmor (ed), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Law
(New York: Routledge, 2012), pp. 65-75, for the only critical engagement with the Standard View. Some recent
work in legal philosophy purports to clarify what obeying the law is, if only to contrast it with other possible
responses to law, but in each case the explanandum turns out to be something else. For example, William
Edmundson contrasts obeying the law with ‘law-abidance’, though he never explains either concept; he says that
abiding by the law is in part to ‘comply’ with it, but the notion of compliance is left unexplained. With regard to
obedience to law, he oscillates between what I call (below) the reason-conformity and reason-compliance views.
See William Edmundson, “The Virtue of Law-Abidance,” Philosophers Imprint 4 (2006): 1-21, at pp. 2-3. Another
example is Fred Schauer, who suggests, in his recent book, that he is addressing such questions as “What exactly
does it mean to follow or obey the law?” and “is every act that is in compliance with the law also an act of
obedience to the law?” [The Force of Law (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2015), p. 6], questions
which are in fact the main focus of the present essay. However, he ultimately adopts, without argument (at p. 194
n18), the “conventional” view of obeying the law, which is precisely the Standard View I criticize below. Finally,
Margaret Gilbert acknowledges that the Standard View is inadequate, but does not suggest what account should
replace it. See her A Theory of Political Obligation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006), pp. 210-11.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


Consider, for example, the only two accounts of obeying the law advanced in recent times.

Some have claimed that to obey the law is to act for the reason that the law requires that one

so act; others have argued that it is merely to do what the law says, regardless of the reasons

for which one acts. These views will be discussed and made more precise in a moment, but the

present point is that they assume very different pictures about what law requires of persons,

how law engages their capacities as rational agents, and the normative significance of such

engagement. In particular, what distinguishes these accounts is their different views about the

reason for which a person must act in order to obey the law. And there is of course a tradition,

as old as moral philosophy itself, which holds that the reasons for which a person acts are of

great importance, for example, in judging whether an action is right or permissible, whether the

person acted from good character, and so on. Determining, then, whether the law must figure

in a person’s practical reasoning at all (and if so, how), or whether a person needs to have any

knowledge of the law at all in order to obey it, will bear directly on assessing the gravity (or

levity) of a duty to obey the law, its relation to and priority among other moral duties, as well as

the moral significance of acts of disobedience, civil or otherwise.

Given, then, the central importance of obeying and disobeying the law in these

perennial debates, their enduring role in legal and political argument, and the persistent

reticence of moral, legal, and political philosophers to explain them, a more explicit and

defensible account of each of them is long overdue. I will begin, in Section I, by considering the

Standard View of obeying the law which has long been taken for granted by theorists of

political authority, roughly that for a person to obey the law is to act for a certain sort of reason

provided by the law, as well as an opposing view, according to which obedience requires doing

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


what the law requires, though not necessarily for the reason that the law requires it. I argue

that both views are inadequate because both attempt to explain obedience exclusively in terms

of the concepts of a reason for action, and acting for a reason, which has been for too long the

preference among legal and political philosophers.

In Section II, I expand the possibilities for understanding obeying the law by moving

beyond the general idea of acting for a reason, focusing instead on the content of the intention

and knowledge with which an obedient subject must act. This highlights a different and less

often discussed aspect of law’s normativity: that the law, quite independently of creating

reasons, often creates actions for us to perform: it identifies and in some cases conceptualizes,

in terms far removed from that of ordinary action concepts, actions which it requires, forbids,

or permits of its subjects. This characteristic feature of the law provides the clue as to what

obedience requires. I will argue that the law identifies actions which we are to understand

ourselves to perform when we perform them, such that that understanding moves us to action,

if what we do is to count as obeying the law. In order to obey the law a person must act with

some recognition that she is in fact doing an action which the law requires. In a phrase,

obedience requires knowingly doing the right thing. The ‘right thing’ is not the morally right,

best, or justified thing, but doing the action that is required by the law and not another. What

this knowledge, recognition, or understanding involves may vary across cases, but I will develop

a default view against which exceptional cases can be contrasted.

In Section III, I consider the even more neglected idea of disobeying the law, in light of

the discussion of Sections I-II. I confront the threshold question of the relationship between

obedience and disobedience, in particular whether, as their names suggest, one is simply the

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


negation of the other: whether disobedience should be understood as merely a failure to obey.

The matter turns out to be not as simple as that, and I introduce a two-part account of

disobedience, arguing for both a default sense and a more specialized sense involved in acts of

civil disobedience. Both accounts, however, are compatible with the view of obedience

developed in the earlier sections. Disobedience in the default sense (for example the sense

implicit in much of the criminal law) typically involves an agent intending, and performing, an

action which fails to correspond to an action permissible by law or (what often comes to the

same thing) intending and performing an action which corresponds to one forbidden by it. Acts

of civil disobedience are of this sort as well, but can be symmetrically contrasted with acts of

obedience in that they consist additionally in knowingly failing to do the right thing: that is, in

performing an action one recognizes is at variance with one the law requires. This account of

disobedience fits well not only with the role it plays in theories of civil disobedience, but also

with how practitioners of civil disobedience have often characterized what is required to

successfully engage in the practice.

My discussion of each concept is not meant to be conclusive, and leaves open the

possibility that obedience and disobedience to law, at least as discussed in the various

philosophical literatures, may not form an elegant set of opposing ideas; rather, each may in

the end refer to distinct but related phenomena. However, I have the relatively modest aim of

taking a first step in having a more philosophically substantive discussion about these concepts

which figure in many foundational questions of legal and political philosophy. The broader

purpose is to come to a more systematic understanding of obeying and disobeying the law, so

that we can then identify more precisely what is at stake in debates about, e.g., what practical

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


authorities demand of us, whether there is a duty to obey the law, and whether civilly

disobeying it is ever justified. 6

I. OBEYING THE LAW: THE STANDARD VIEW

Before setting out the only extant philosophical account of obeying the law, an old caveat

should be brought once again to the fore. It should be kept in mind that the Standard View,

and all other accounts of obedience and disobedience discussed in this paper, are meant to

explain a characteristic response to only one (albeit ubiquitous) domain or kind of law, and so

not as a necessary or appropriate response to all law. The domain of law in respect of which

the notions of ‘obedience’ and ‘disobedience’ are appropriate has generally been restricted to

the ‘penal’ law, though distinguishing penal from non-penal law is not straightforward. The

penal law certainly includes most parts of the criminal law, but also encompasses any other

legal norm which explicitly requires or forbids a kind of action, and to which a sanction for

disobedience attaches. So for example many mundane traffic laws, or laws in tax codes which

6
It might be thought that while obeying the law has been given scant attention by philosophers, another, closely
related topic, has generated a voluminous literature which is of obvious relevance here. Inspired by certain
remarks of Wittgenstein, many philosophers of the last thirty years have debated what it is to ‘follow a rule.’ (See,
e.g., Saul Kripke, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1982),
P.A. Boghossian, “The Rule-Following Considerations,” Mind 98 (1989): 507-49, Philip Pettit, “The Reality of Rule-
Following,” Mind 99 (1990): 1-21, and Crispin Wright, “Rule-Following Without Reasons: Wittgenstein’s Quietism
and the Constitutive Question,” Ratio 20 (2007): 481-502.) Indeed, some of the views considered here bear an
affinity to some found in that literature. The debate over the nature of rule-following, however, is largely
irrelevant to a discussion of obeying and disobeying the law, because the notion of a ‘rule’ in that debate has little
in common with the concept of a law as traditionally used by both philosophers and lawyers. For example, it is
widely accepted that a ‘rule’ can have “infinitary contents” (Paul Boghossian “Blind Rule-Following,” in Mind,
Meaning, and Knowledge, ed. Annalisa Coliva (Oxford: Oxford University Press), p.32), that is, it can be stated in
innumerable, acceptable ways. Laws, however, exist at least in part because they have been intentionally laid
down or posited, and so often have a canonical formulation, which delimits the range of reasonable
interpretations which can be given of them. It is also widely agreed in that debate that some kind of ‘commitment’
or ‘acceptance’ of the rule is necessary in order to follow it. But as we will see, obeying the law requires nothing of
the sort, and indeed requires that such commitment is not necessary: it must be possible, for example, for one to
obey an unjust law. The very idea of civil disobedience, in fact, assumes this. And there are other sorts of cases;
for example, it must be possible for a foreigner to obey the laws of a state to which she owes no allegiance.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


impose fines for non-fulfillment of tax obligations may all be considered ‘penal’ for present

purposes. There are surely many marginal cases, but the caveat is that any explanation of

obedience and disobedience will have extensive application to large domains of law in modern

legal systems, though it will not extend to all law, for example to that which Hart called ‘power-

conferring’ rules like those governing the making of wills and other contracts. 7

That caveat aside, the long-standing philosophical account about what obeying the law

requires (the Standard View) arises out of a broader philosophical view about what practical

authority is about, which in turn rests on a view, common among philosophers, 8 about what

we’re about, the sorts of creatures we are as agents. The line of thought proceeds like this: we

are creatures who have rationality or reason, the capacity to recognize certain features of the

world as significant, worthy of our notice, and relevant to deciding what to do and believe.

Those features are themselves said to be reasons, considerations which count in favor or

against doing or adopting some token action or attitude. This capacity to recognize and

respond to reasons is said to be essential to us as persons, as agents who can respond and

affect the world in distinctive ways. Practical authorities such as the law are said to enter the

picture by making demands on us, say, to pay our taxes or refrain from committing murder.

These demands are made on the presumption that we are persons in this sense, and so are

intended to engage our capacities by serving as reasons for action, alongside, and on some

accounts, in place of, all the other reasons that we had before the authority came on the scene.

7
Richard Wasserstrom made the point long ago in “The Obligation to Obey the Law,” UCLA L. Rev. 10 (1962-63):
780-807, p. 785.
8
See T.M. Scanlon, Being Realistic about Reasons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), Derek Parfit, On What
Matters, Vol. 1 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), Joseph Raz, Engaging Reason (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1999), Jonathan Dancy, Ethics Without Principles (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), among others.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


The theories about how this is supposed to work are varied and complex, but one influential

theory, Joseph Raz’s “service conception” of authority, 9 says that it is in the nature of authority

for authorities to assess the reasons that apply to us for us, that is, on our behalf, and issue

demands on the basis of those assessments. It is then part of the justification of our obedience

to authority that authoritative directives reflect the reasons that we have anyway. Authorities

are thus said to be a “service” or benefit to their subjects in the sense of helping the subjects do

many of the things they have independent reason to do.

On this kind of theory of practical authority, and the authority of law, in which the

concepts of a reason and acting for a reason take center stage, what does obedience require?

To state the view precisely, it is helpful to introduce a distinction between complying with a

reason, and merely conforming to it. 10 To comply with a reason is to act for that reason; to

conform to a reason is simply to do the action for which the reason is a reason, but not to act

for that reason. For example, I may have several reasons to have a glass of wine at the party:

the wine has a pleasant flavor, it will relax me, it will enhance my sociability, it may have certain

beneficial effects on my health, and so on. Suppose then that I drink the wine, and do so for

the reason that it’s pleasant but not for the others. In drinking, I have complied with the

reason that it’s pleasant because I have acted for that reason. If you asked me why I drank it, I

9
Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), pp. 23-109 and Between Authority and
Interpretation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), pp. 126-165. See also David Enoch, “Reason-Giving and the
Law,” Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law, Vol. 1, eds. Leslie Green and Brian Leiter (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2011), pp. 1-38.
10
See Joseph Raz, Practical Reason and Norms, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), pp. 178-180, and
John Gardner and Timothy Macklem, “Reasons,” in The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence & Philosophy of Law,
Jules Coleman and Scott Shapiro eds. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002), pp. 462-463. Gardner and
Macklem draw a similar distinction between “deliberately” and “accidentally” doing what reasons recommend.
The distinction is less precise, however, since one can ‘deliberately’ conform, or fail to conform, to a reason, ideas
which will be of use below.

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


would say: because it’s pleasant. Moreover, the fact that the wine has a pleasant flavor in some

sense explains why I did what I did. But with regard to those other reasons to drink the wine –

that it relaxes me, is healthy, and so on – it can only be said that I have conformed to them; it is

the case only that I’ve done the action for which those reasons are reasons: I drank wine. It is

to that extent that I have ‘satisfied’ those reasons and, as it were, done all that they ask of me.

Now back to obeying the law. With the compliance-conformity distinction before us,

the Standard View starts with the idea that law provides reasons for action to its subjects, and

claims that obedience requires compliance, and not merely conformity, with those reasons.

That is, a person obeys the law only when she does what the law requires for the reason that

the law so requires. “Obedience is not a matter of doing what someone tells you to do. It is a

matter of doing what he tells you to do because he tells you to do it.” 11 The ‘because’ here is

not, or is not merely, causal; it is normative, and so refers to the reason for which a subject

must act if she is to obey. For analytical purposes, the Standard View can be called the reason-

compliance view:

Reason Compliance [RC]: If it is a fact, F, that a law, L, requires A to ϕ, then A obeys L by


ϕing for the reason that F. 12

11
R.P. Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism, 3rd. ed. (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998), 9. While Wolff
appears to be the modern source of the Standard View, its influence has come by way of the work of Joseph Raz,
who explicitly accepts Wolff’s view of obeying the law as ‘essentially sound.’ See Raz, The Authority of Law
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), p. 11, and his introduction to the collection of essays in Joseph Raz (ed.),
Authority (New York: New York University Press, 1990), 1-19. See also Donald Regan, “Reasons, Authority, and the
Meaning of ‘Obey’: Further Thoughts on Raz and Obedience to Law,” Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence 3:3
(1990), 3-28.
12
I assume that the object of obedience is a particular law. One may object that this runs afoul of the orthodoxy in
the theory of authority that authorities are persons, and therefore only persons can be obeyed. I wish to remain
agnostic about the proper object of obedience, and RC can harmlessly be reformulated given one’s position on
that issue.

10

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


Those who accept RC assume that obeying the law requires explicit and rather precise

knowledge of the content of the law. The assumption seems plausible for the more general

reason that in order for a person to act for a reason, that person must have knowledge of, or at

least be aware of, that reason. 13 So just as I can’t drink the wine because it’s pleasant unless I

have knowledge of its pleasant flavor, similarly I can’t pay my taxes because the law says so,

unless I know that the law says so, and what exactly it says. 14

RC has considerable intuitive appeal, especially across a wide range of cases involving

one person obeying the orders of another. While it is apparently widely held as an account of

obeying the law, it has been, however, more often assumed than argued for. Perhaps for that

reason it has only very recently been criticized as not fully taking account of our experience of

living and acting under the law. It has been suggested that reflection on various examples

shows that RC is false and rather that obeying the law requires only conformity, and not

compliance, with the reasons for action the law provides. 15 This opposing view is that for many

of the actions required, permitted, or prohibited by law, we usually already have many reasons

to do them or not to do them, independently of the law; and that in those cases, acting on

13
Cf. Joseph Raz, The Authority of Law, 2 ed (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 214: “Therefore if the law is to
be obeyed it must be capable of guiding the behavior of its subjects. It must be such that they can find out what it
is and act on it.” In the meantime, whether acting on a reason requires an agent to know that reason has become
a contentious issue among moral philosophers. See John Hyman, Action, Knowledge & Will (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2015), pp. 133-158.
14
It is an open question, and one I set aside here, as to whether knowledge, merely a reasonably justified belief, or
some other epistemic standard, is required. Raz and others speak loosely of having ‘knowledge’ of the law, and
writers in legal philosophy have not yet sought to make the epistemic standard more precise. It ought to be made
more precise, but doing so will not matter for present purposes.
15
For example, Scott Hershovitz suggests we should “identify obedience with conformity – with simply doing as
the law requires whatever one’s reasons” (“The Authority of Law,” in A. Marmor (ed), The Routledge Companion to
Philosophy of Law (New York: Routledge, 2012), p. 67). See note 18, below, for discussion of others who have
endorsed the reason conformity view.

11

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


those other (non-legal) reasons is sufficient for obedience, so long as we simply do what the

law requires. We may formulate the weaker, reason-conformity view more precisely this way:

Reason Conformity [RF]: If it is a fact, F, that a law, L, requires A to ϕ, and given the
existence of another (normative, non-legal) reason, G, to ϕ, then A obeys L by merely
conforming to reason F, that is, by ϕing for the reason that G. 16

Cases in which the law requires something for which there is already clear and compelling

moral reason have been adduced to show why RC is mistaken and RF is correct. For example,

we would find a person peculiar if her only, or even primary, reason for refraining from murder

was that the law said so. There are plenty of other good reasons not to commit murder which

we would expect to be acted upon by law-abiding citizens, quite apart from the reason that the

law forbids it. And further, it seems, the law is indifferent as to which of these reasons we

choose to act on. “The law certainly does not regard your behavior as defective if you refrain

from murdering for the reason that murder is wrong. No prosecutor will investigate. No

charges will be brought. No judge will take you to task for failing to pay proper heed to the

law.” 17 There are also examples which show that most of the time it is not plausible to suppose

that a demand for compliance is even implied by a given legal requirement. Consider a law

requiring citizens to pay tax in proportion to one’s income. Again, there are likely innumerable

reasons to pay taxes that depend on the various worthwhile ends which the state (let’s assume)

will pursue with the resulting revenue: enhance national security, relieve suffering of the worst

16
The view Hershovitz argues for may be even weaker than this, since conformity may not require acting for a
reason at all. For example, if while driving I depress the car brake purely out of anger as I approach an intersection
at which the traffic light has just turned red, then it would seem that I have conformed to the relevant traffic law
without acting for any reason. An argument for the existence of such merely expressive actions can be found in
Rosalind Hursthouse, “Arational Actions,” The Journal of Philosophy 88 (1991): 57-68.
17
Hershovitz, “The Authority of Law,” p. 67. See also Stephen Perry, “Political Authority and Political Obligation,”
pp. 10-11, for this and similar counter-examples to the Standard View.

12

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


off in society, contribute to the education of the young, and so on. And it seems, again, that

the law is, as it were, indifferent as to why citizens pay the tax they are obligated to pay. All the

law requires is that taxes be paid, not that they be paid because the law requires it. The law

doesn’t care whether you pay your taxes for the good of mankind, in order to escape prison, or

just to get your accountant to stop reminding you to pay them: all that it asks is that you act so

as to conform to the requirement that you pay, which of course only requires that you pay,

regardless of the reasons for which you end up paying. 18 To be sure, there may be cases in

which the law requires compliance: imagine a judge issuing an injunction against a recalcitrant

defendant to stop engaging in conduct that amounts to a public nuisance, and requiring that

the defendant abstain from the conduct because she (the judge) required him to stop. Or

again, imagine a police officer giving an order to a citizen to move along on the scene of a riot.

But, the defender of RF maintains, surely these are marginal and rare cases: the law typically

only requires conformity with its directives, and simply does not care why those persons

subject to it do the things they are legally required to do.

Suppose we accept these counterexamples to the Standard View as persuasive and

therefore as prima facie reason to reject RC. What then of the revisionary view, RF? Does

obeying the law generally require only that we do what the law says, without regard to the

reasons for which we act? The view is not without its adherents. For example, RF seems to

have been the going view of obeying the law in the positivist tradition up to and including

18
What the law requires in the tax example may even be weaker than this; it arguably doesn’t even require that
you pay your taxes. That is, your tax obligations can be fulfilled by, say, my paying your taxes without you running
afoul of what the law requires of you. Other examples, like a judicial order in the form of an injunction (e.g., a
restraining order regarding domestic violence), may require that only an action by the addressee will suffice. Raz
once called these ‘action’ (as opposed to ‘outcome’) reasons. See The Morality of Freedom (Clarendon Press,
1986), pp. 145-46.

13

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


Hart, 19 though that was a break from even earlier acceptance of the reason compliance view of

obedience. 20

In fact, obedience as mere conformity to the reasons the law provides is deeply

implausible. If all that is required to obey the law is conformity to its directives – that is, merely

doing the actions required, regardless of the reasons for which one does them – then

obedience would become a ubiquitous and for that reason far less interesting phenomenon

than has been supposed. For on the mere conformity view, there may be little connection

between the issuance of a legal rule or order on the one hand, and an action that amounts to

obeying it on the other. Indeed, if mere conformity is all that is required, there need not be any

connection – normative, causal, or otherwise – between law and citizen at all. For that reason,

the view has bizarre implications. It would open up the possibility that a person could obey

the law while being completely oblivious to the fact that they are doing so, indeed, while

completely unaware of the fact that there is a system of legal rules which applies to her

19
John Austin famously makes the concept of obedience central to his account of sovereignty, i.e., as a person or
persons habitually obeyed by the political community and who obeys no one, which in turn forms an essential part
of his theory of law. He explicitly endorse the reason conformity view of obedience in The Province of
Jurisprudence Determined, ed. Wilfrid E. Rumble (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), pp. 248-249,
where he claims that while acts of obedience must be “voluntary or free,” they can be done from “motives of
some description or another.” H.L.A. Hart follows Austin in The Concept of Law, 3rd ed., eds. Joseph Raz and
Penelope A. Bulloch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2012), where he claims that citizens may obey the law for “a variety
of different reasons” (114) and “from any motive whatever” (116). Himma argues that Hart “overstates” the
extent to which obedience is necessary for the existence of a legal system, but the criticism relies on incorrectly
attributing to Hart the reason compliance (RC) view of obedience. See Kenneth Einar Himma, “A Comprehensive
Hartian Theory of Legal Obligation: Social Pressure, Coercive Enforcement, and the Legal Obligations of Citizens,” in
Philosophical Foundations of the Nature of Law, eds. Wil Waluchow and Stefan Sciaraffa (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2013), pp. 175-176. Hart, much later and under the influence of Raz, did endorse something like the reason
compliance view in Essays on Bentham (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982).
20
Austin likely misunderstood Bentham’s view of obedience, which is more subtle than the conformity view as
represented in RF, and is at least in some aspects a reason compliance view. See Gerald Postema, Bentham and
the Common Law Tradition (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), pp. 233-237, for discussion of various interpretations
of Bentham on this issue. Prior to Bentham, many philosophers in the early modern period took the reason
compliance view of obedience for granted.

14

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


conduct. A person could, moreover, even be said to obey the law if she did so on accident, for

example, if she intended to do something either prohibited by law or to which the law is

indifferent, but by mistake were unsuccessful because of incompetence or weakness of will,

and ‘obeyed’ the law anyway. Or a person could even obey the law while in a sense acting, but

not intending anything at all, e.g., when sleepwalking.

The consequences of a mere conformity view like RF are even more bizarre than that.

Recall the children’s book The Little Prince, in which a confused but confident king claims he

receives perfect obedience from all his subjects, and indeed he guarantees that this be so.

When the prince approaches the king on a planet of which he is the only resident, the exchange

goes like this:

“May I sit down?” came now a timid inquiry from the little prince.
“I order you to do so,” the king answered…
"Sire," [the little prince] said to him, "I beg that you will excuse my asking you a
question--"
"I order you to ask me a question," the king hastened to assure him.
"Sire-- over what do you rule?"
"Over everything," said the king, with magnificent simplicity[…]
The king made a gesture, which took in his planet, the other planets, and all the stars[…]
"Over all that," the king answered.
For his rule was not only absolute: it was also universal.
"And the stars obey you?"
"Certainly they do," the king said. "They obey instantly. I do not permit
insubordination."
Such power was a thing for the little prince to marvel at. If he had been master of such
complete authority, he would have been able to watch the sunset […] two hundred
times, without ever having to move his chair.
"I should like to see a sunset... do me that kindness... Order the sun to set..."
"You shall have your sunset. I shall command it. But, according to my science of
government, I shall wait until conditions are favorable."

15

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


"When will that be?" inquired the little prince...before saying anything else [the king]
consulted a bulky almanac. "Hum! Hum! That will be about-- about-- that will be this
evening about twenty minutes to eight. And you will see how well I am obeyed." 21

There are many lessons in this amusing exchange, but for present purposes the point is that,

according to RF, the king does enjoy the obedience of his subjects. For his subjects clearly do

conform to his requirements – they do what he tells them to do, and on the theory of

obedience as reason conformity, that is all that is required. Now this is obviously absurd –

indeed, that it is absurd is part of the charm of the story. But the charm of the story doesn’t

contribute to the truth of the theory. One way our king has gone wrong is that he

misunderstands what it is to require or command something of someone. He merely describes

what happens, what someone has done, and then ‘commands’ that it be so. But commands,

and the norms they create, are not like that. Commands are not descriptions: they do not ‘fit’

what happens, but rather what happens must in some sense fit them. As philosophers have

sometimes put it, descriptions and things like commands which express an intention or desire,

have different “directions of fit.” 22 Mark Murphy has put the point in regards to commanding

this way:

commanding that p is an attempt to do something with language, to realize some state


of affairs by the performance of a speech-act. It is, in particular, a directive act: the aim
internal to a commanding act is that of having the addressee or addressees carry out the
action represented in the proposition that is the object of the command. 23

21
Antoine de Saint-Exupery, The Little Prince, trans. T V F Cuffe (London: Penguin Books), pp. 35-36. The exchange
is no doubt an elaboration of that aphorism from French revolutionary politics, “There go my people. I must find
out where they are going, so I can lead them.”
22
See Kim Frost, “On the Very Idea of Direction of Fit,” Philosophical Review 123 (2014): 429-484, in particular his
recasting (p. 473) of Anscombe’s original idea as there being different manifestations of practical thought with
their own standards of correctness..
23
Mark Murphy, An Essay on Divine Authority (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2002), p. 24.

16

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


Acts of obedience must ‘fit’ the commands of authority by being those actions which are among

those required; it is not enough for obedient actions merely to correspond to or ‘match’ those

which the law requires. And when a subject fails to obey, the mistake must be in the act and

not, as Anscombe said, 24 in the command. The notion of reason conformity in RF is inadequate

to account for this, as demonstrated by our confused king. A philosophical explanation of

obeying the law requires an answer as to how a subject’s attitudes and actions must “fit” the

requirement of a given law. We will return to this problem in the next section.

A simple way to modify RF to avoid these problems is to add that there must be a

unidirectional causal connection underlying the conformity between law and act: in order to

count as obedience, the law must cause the obedient act. And yet, so modified, the view would

still allow for objectionable cases. Suppose A is an expert on what the law requires of her, and

conscientiously obeys those requirements; suppose B, subject to the same laws, is woefully

uninformed about them, but for reasons completely unrelated to law (e.g., out of respect or

admiration for A), is in the habit of patterning his conduct on A’s. On the suggested revision of

RF, B obeys the law just as A does. (And we could imagine C patterning her conduct on B’s, and

so on, extending a causal chain of agents and actions far removed from the law itself.) One

reason to think that A obeys the law but the others do not - and another, related way our king

(and the mere conformity view of RF) has gone wrong - is in failing to see that in obeying the

law, there must be some acknowledgement of the authority by the obedient subject. 25 The

24
G.E.M. Anscombe, Intention, 2nd ed. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2000), pp. 56-57.
25
Cf. R.B. Friedman, “On the Concept of Authority in Political Philosophy,” in Authority, Joseph Raz ed. (New York:
Blackwell, 1990), p. 64: “…authority is distinguished from coercion as a mode of influence because it involves some
sort of ‘recognition’ on the part of the subject that the person to whom he submits is ‘entitled’ to obedience and it
is distinguished from persuasion in that obedience is not procured by ‘argument’.”

17

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


reason conformity view (RF) requires only a mere correspondence between what the law

requires and what is done, such that the correspondence, one even caused in the right way,

may arise for any reason, or for no reason at all. And as we have seen, the Standard View (RC)

requires a person to recognize a requirement of law in a particular way – as a reason for action,

as well as a reason to act for the reason that the act is required. But we have seen the

problems with that view as well. But that does not mean that the general idea that some

distinctive recognition of authority in acts of obedience is mistaken. Indeed that general idea

explains why the sun and stars cannot obey the law but people can. But it remains to be

explained what that distinctive recognition must be.

A final puzzling consequence of the reason conformity view is this. If obeying the law

requires only a mere correspondence between legal requirement and action, regardless of

whether that correspondence is established by intentional, conscious, and rational action by an

obedient subject, or entirely by chance, then it becomes difficult to explain why moral, legal,

and political philosophers have been concerned, for centuries, with defending (or debunking)

the idea of a moral obligation to obey the law. If that alleged obligation is such that a person

could discharge it without even being aware that she is doing so, or by acting for reasons which

have nothing to do with the legal system to which the person is subject, then it would seem

that philosophical debate about its nature would be of far less importance than has long been

thought. And yet a core assumption of that debate, from Plato onwards, has been that the

question of whether such an obligation exists is an urgent question of great moral and political

significance. Interpretive charity recommends that theories of political obligation are meant to

18

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


explain (and sometimes justify) something more than mere correspondence between law and

obedient action and that therefore RF is false as a claim about what obeying the law requires.

II. OBEYING THE LAW: NEW VIEWS

Let us retrace our steps. We can see now that the standard, reason compliance (RC) view

really consists of two claims: to obey the law is, first, to do what the law says, and second, to do

it because the law says so. The counterexamples showed that this view was too strong and that

all that obedience requires is just the first thing: to do what the law says. This is the reason

conformity view (RF), which as we saw was also objectionable. But in order to introduce new

views of the matter, I now want to suggest that the very idea of ‘doing what the law says’

presents its own questions.

Recall that the Standard View (RC) of obedience presupposes a certain conception of the

agent, upon which a theory of authority and obedience is constructed. That shared conception

assumes that one defining mark of an agent or person is having the capacity to recognize,

appreciate, and appropriately respond to reasons for action and belief. This conception has

long been the orthodoxy in legal and political philosophy and, insofar as the Standard View

assumes it, partly explains why theoretically grounded views about what obeying the law

requires have been so few and far between. I want to now expand the possible views of what

obedience to law might be by reflecting on a different aspect of agency, which in turn allows us

to appreciate a different aspect of the nature and role of authorities, which enables us to

generate new views – and new questions – about what obeying the law amounts to.

The aspect of agency with which I’m concerned is therefore not the capacity to recognize

and respond to reasons, as the Standard View requires, but rather our capacity to engage in a

19

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


distinctive sort of thinking about what we do, thinking which plays a role in determining the

content of our own self-conception over time. This thinking manifests itself in the ways in

which we can spontaneously characterize our own actions, both while we are doing them, and

across time, before and after doing them. This ability to almost always say what we are doing,

have done, and will do – independent of the reasons why we do them – has been recognized by

moral philosophers and social psychologists as having a special significance in that our

characterizations of our actions shape and are shaped by our self-conception. 26 Philosophers

have traditionally focused on the content of future-directed intentions to act; the capacity to

which I refer is broader than that, as it involves the characterization of action diachronically, ie,

before, during, and after the formation and execution of an intention.

This aspect of agency points us to a different aspect of the role and nature of practical

authority: authorities, and especially legal authorities, engage this capacity of conceptualizing

action by giving us things to do – by conceptualizing, and to that extent creating, actions for us

to do and requiring that we do them so conceptualized. This is one primary sense in which law

is a “hermeneutic concept.” As Joseph Raz puts it: “The concept of law is part of our culture

and of our cultural traditions. It plays a role in the way in which ordinary people as well as the

legal profession understand their own and other people’s actions. It is part of the way they

‘conceptualize’ social reality.” 27

26
This capacity of unique and spontaneous action identification was noted by G.E.M. Anscombe in Intention
(Oxford: Blackwell, 1957). For recent discussions in ethics and social psychology, see the essays in Agency and Self-
Awareness, eds. Johannes Roessler and Naomi Eilan (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003) and Agency and
Action, eds. John Hyman and Helen Steward (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), as well as Robin
Vallacher and Daniel Wegner, “Action Identification Theory,” in P.A.M. Van Lange et al. (eds.), Handbook of
Theories of Social Psychology (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, 2012), pp. 327-348.
27
“Authority, Law, and Morality” in Ethics and the Public Domain (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), p. 237. See also
Stephen Perry, “Hart’s Methodological Positivism,” in Hart’s Postscript: Essays on the Postscript of the Concept of

20

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


I suggest that one role the law plays in understanding people’s actions is that it provides

them with characterizations of their actions which are meant to affect the characterizations

those people themselves may formulate of those actions. Sometimes an action required by law

is characterized in a banal way, in a way in which we would conceive of our actions anyway –

for example, “driving 40 mph on a public road”; but others are characterized in ways such that

we would never think to do them, so conceptualized, on our own. For example, the law

requires that we act as the reasonable person would, and refrain from exposing others to an

unreasonable risk of harm (as in tort law), or that we not intentionally kill another person in the

heat of passion and in response to adequate provocation (one formulation of an act of

voluntary manslaughter), or that we may create a non-possessory security interest in the

bottomry of a vessel (as one can do in maritime law).

I think the role that an authority, and in particular the law, plays in conceptualizing

action is both important and has been overlooked by the going views of obedience which

assume that the exercise of authority can be understood only in terms of the creation of and

acting on a certain sort of reason for action. And focusing on this other aspect of authority can

help us better understand obeying the law. Whether or not the law creates reasons for us to

act, and whether or not the law requires conformity or compliance with those reasons, it

remains trivially true that the law requires us to do things. The intuitive reason conformity view

(RF) says that in order to obey we must simply do those things. But what acknowledgement or

Law, Jules Coleman ed. (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001), p. 324. Brian Leiter claims this idea “has been
endorsed by every legal philosopher of the last hundred years, with the exception of the Scandinavian Realists.”
See his Naturalizing Jurisprudence: Essays on American Legal Realism and Naturalism in Legal Philosophy (New
York: Oxford University Press, 2007), p. 173.

21

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


recognition by the person obeying must be involved in even the case of conformity? What

connection must there be between the content of the requirement and an act of obeying that

requirement?

We can start with one lesson from the story of the confused but confident king: that it

can’t just happen to be the case that one has obeyed the law. And one way to ensure that

obedience is non-accidental is to say that there at least must be the possibility of some

awareness that one has obeyed. Perhaps there is more to it. Perhaps in order to obey the law

there must be something we must do accompanied by an intention with a characteristic

content. But what must we intend?

There seem to be two broad ways to answer this question, using a compliance-

conformity distinction similar to the one we encountered in explaining the Standard View, a

distinction which we may use to generate two further claims about what an obedient subject

must intend or know in order to obey. The stronger, intention compliance, view is that in order

to obey the law, one must intend the action the law requires, precisely as characterized by the

law itself.

Intention compliance [IC]: If a law, L, requires A to ϕ, then A obeys L only by ϕing with
the intention to ϕ.

That is, if the law requires me to ϕ, I can obey only by intending to ϕ: to myself characterize my

action as one of ϕing. To adapt a familiar idea from the philosophy of action, I must act under

the legal description of an act required by law in order to obey it. 28

28
See Donald Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), p. 50. In a
recent essay, Matthew Hanser assumes IC as an account of obedience, but he gives no reason for preferring it over
the Standard View (or any other). See his “Doing Another’s Bidding,” in George Pavlakos and Veronica Rodriguez-
Blanco (eds.), Reasons and Intentions in Law and Practical Agency (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015),
pp. 112-114.

22

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


Does obeying the law require intention compliance, as IC asserts? That is, if the law

requires that I “mitigate damages as the non-breaching party to a contract,” must I intend to

perform an action of just that description, and perform it with an intention of just that content,

in order to obey? While intending to do actions characterized by the sometimes technical

language of the law is uncommon, there are cases in which it does occur as a matter of course.

For example, lawyers, far more often than ordinary citizens, act with an intention of doing

something just as the law characterizes it. This is understandable since lawyers are usually

better acquainted with what actions the law requires, in the language in which it requires it. So

a lawyer may perform “due diligence” for her client, or “protect the attorney-client privilege,”

or provide a “short and plain statement of the claim showing that the pleader is entitled to

relief,” 29 and so on. Sometimes ordinary citizens also engage in this sort of thing; these are

often cases in which there is public scrutiny on a citizen’s conduct and the stakes are high

should the citizen disobey. An example of this comes from the 2012 presidential election in the

United States. Prior to the Republican primaries in 2011, the Federal Election Commission (FEC)

clarified the ruling of the Supreme Court in the notorious Citizens United case 30 that allowed

political action committees to raise unlimited sums of money with which to make

advertisements on behalf of a candidate for president. The FEC deemed that this was

permissible so long as there was no “coordinated communication” between the committee and

the candidate’s campaign. 31 After the adoption of this rule, candidates or their surrogates

made statements to the media using the precise wording of the regulation, in order to claim

29
See Federal Rules of Civil Procedure, Rule 8(a)(2).
30
558 U.S. 310 (2010).
31
See 11 CFR 109.21-22 (2011).

23

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


that they were acting within its boundaries, and saying that they have not engaged in any

“coordinated communication” with a committee that had produced some controversial

advertisement. 32 But suffice it to say that these kinds of cases are rare.

There is, however, an objection to the intention compliance (IC) view that is analogous

to the objection we encountered earlier against the reason compliance (RC) view of obedience.

The law just does not seem on its face to require, as a general matter, that its subjects intend to

act precisely in terms of the characterization of the action it has specified. In fact, just as the

law is (usually) indifferent to the reasons why one does the action which the law requires in a

given instance, so long as one does it, similarly the law seems to be (usually) indifferent as to

what one intends to do when obeying, so long as one does, under some description, what the

law says. If a token law requires that I pay my taxes, it makes no difference in obeying whether,

when I pay my taxes, I think of what I am doing as “getting the government off my back”,

“contributing to the general welfare”, or whatever.

An additional problem with IC is that it implicitly requires a degree of knowledge of the

law which most people most of the time lack. If a person can obey the law only if they intend

to act under a description of the act provided by the law, and given that modern legal systems

typically govern a vast range of human actions, it would appear that IC would require a similarly

vast knowledge of action descriptions in the law, beyond that of even the most seasoned of

lawyers and judges. For that reason it seems to follow from IC that obeying the law is a

32
See, e.g., Mike McIntyre and Michael Luo, “Fine Line Between ‘Super PACs’ and Campaigns,” The New York
Times, Feb 25 2012: http://www.nytimes.com/2012/02/26/us/politics/loose-border-of-super-pac-and-romney-
campaign.html?_r=1.

24

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


exceedingly rare phenomenon, far less common than has been supposed both by theorists of

political obligation and ordinary citizens who self-identify as ‘law-abiding.’ 33

While IC is problematic for these reasons, we can generate a further, weaker view about

what an obedient subject must intend in terms of intention conformity:

Intention conformity (IF): Given that a law, L, requires A to ϕ, then A obeys L by


intending to Ψ, and Ψing, only if it is the case that by Ψing, A ϕs.

The intention conformity view expresses the idea that if the law requires me to ϕ, I can obey by

intending to Ψ, such that there is some entailment relationship between Ψing and ϕing. We

can at present remain neutral as to the precise relationship between Ψing and ϕing: perhaps

the relationship is one of strict identity, or there is a necessary means-end relationship between

Ψing and ϕing, or Ψing is constitutive (perhaps even only partly constitutive) of ϕing.

Whatever the best way to explain this connection, the intention conformity view says that all

that is required for a person to obey the law is to intend (and perform) an action that is

describable as the one the law requires. Again, for example, if the law requires you to pay your

taxes, you can intend to do a wide range of things as you submit payment – “manage my

finances”, “do my civic duty,” “fund all the free loaders,” “perpetuate the welfare state,” and so

on – so long as you do an action that is describable as the one the law required you to do: pay

your taxes.

However, IF suffers from the same problem as the reason conformity (RF) view. It is

perfectly consistent with again finding ‘obedience’ in the story of our confused king. For on the

33
The Standard View (RC) suffers from a similar problem. Cf. note 12, above. A pioneering empirical study of
citizens’ self-understanding as ‘law-abiding’ is Tom Tyler, Why People Obey the Law (New Haven: Yale University
Press, 1990).

25

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


simple intention conformity view, there need not be any connection at all, normative, causal or

otherwise, between legal requirements and the actions of the person who obeys them. There

need not be any recognition or acknowledgement of the law that we found necessary to take

account of in light of the confused king. Purely accidental, and indeed random, intentional acts

by oblivious subjects (or non-subjects) would count as obedience, on the intention conformity

view.

This view, however, does seem to be on the right track. For its failings suggest that one

way to describe the required normative connection between the law and its obedient subjects’

actions is to say that those subjects, while they need not intend to do precisely what the law

literally says to do, in order to count as obeying, they must at least recognize that their conduct

is so describable. 34 Let’s call this view intention conformity with knowledge:

Intention Conformity with Knowledge (IFK): Given that a law, L, requires A to ϕ, then A
obeys L by intending to Ψ, and Ψing, only if it is the case that by Ψing, A ϕs, and A
knows that by Ψing, A ϕs.

While IFK does make some attempt to take account of the platitude that ‘recognition’ of

authority is an essential part of obedience, in the form of knowledge that a subject’s intended

action is describable as one with which the law is in some way concerned, more needs to be

said to avoid mere accidental cases of obedience in which subjects have such knowledge, but it

is inert in bringing about the obedient action. Therefore, we should interpret IFK to claim that

knowledge of the fact that one’s conduct is describable as an act permitted, forbidden, or

required by the law must play some role in the explanation as to why one acts as one does on

34
Raz long ago characterized something like this view of obedience as “conformity coupled with knowledge”. See
The Concept of a Legal System, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), p. 15. There he mentions it in a critical
discussion of John Austin’s view of obedience, but does not pursue it further.

26

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


the relevant occasion of obedience. I haven’t the space here to pursue in any detail the

question, rarely asked by legal and political philosophers, of what role that must be. The

argument to this point, however, suggests that the knowledge of action-description

equivalence need not play an explicit role in the practical reasoning of an obedient subject, for

example by functioning as a reason for performing the required action, but yet may make a

contribution to action by being in the background of that reasoning. 35 Obedience requires that

knowledge of the law at least motivate action, whether or not that knowledge explicitly guides

action in deliberation.

The connection described in IFK between the law and its subjects, which is the

understanding by the subject that her action is characterizable as one with which the law is

concerned, such that that fact in part explains her action, is explained by the broader aspect of

authority I explained earlier. Whether or not the law provides its subjects reasons for action, it

individuates and conceptualizes a wide range of human actions, such that subjects must adopt

those conceptualizations as a condition of obedience. This account does align with a wide

range of cases. For example, it is a striking aspect of legal practice, illustrative of this, that

otherwise ordinary human conduct can and is re-characterized all the time in pleadings written

by lawyers, and submitted in court proceedings, in order to state a prima facie case before a

court. Any plaintiff’s lawyer knows you’d better describe the defendant’s conduct in the

35
I use the phrase ‘in the background’ in precisely the sense developed by Philip Pettit and Michael Smith in
“Backgrounding Desire,” in Frank Jackson, Philip Pettit, and Michael Smith, Mind, Morality, and Explanation
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004), pp. 271-72, that is, as a motivating reason for action: “The desire for S figures in
the background if and only if it explains the agent’s choice of option. It figures in the foreground if and only if the
agent reaches that choice via the recognition that he has that desire and that the option has the desirable
property… More generally, a desire is present in the background of an agent’s decision if and only if it is part of the
motivating reason for it: the rationalizing set of beliefs and desires which produce the decision.” Though they do
not explore the possibility, backgrounding knowledge rather than desire or belief is consistent with their account.

27

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


precise terms of the statute or common law rule so as to avoid having the case dismissed by a

judge as “failing to state a claim upon which relief can be granted.” 36 So, for example, imagine

two men in a pub late on a Saturday night who have a disagreement and come to fisticuffs. We

might suppose that the victor intended to, and did, “teach him a lesson” or “showed him who’s

boss”. But by Monday morning in the courthouse, what he did has been recast (by his

adversary’s lawyer) as “intentionally and without consent caused a reasonable and immediate

apprehension of imminent bodily harm in another person” (a formulation of the common law

definition of assault). And on the view I’m suggesting our bruiser failed to obey because he

failed to see that his intended conduct was characterizable in just this way, as at variance with

what the law required him to do or refrain from doing, and allowed that to play some

motivating role in the explanation of his action.

There are many refinements to be made to this line of thought, but it seems to me that

something like IFK is the most promising. One may object that IFK suffers from a similar

problem raised against both RC and IC: that IFK requires for obedience detailed knowledge of

the law, which most people lack. The consequence of IFK thus would similarly seem to be that

most people most of the time do not obey the law. That is, most people don’t exhibit any

awareness that the things they do in the course of a day is describable in precise legal terms

under the law as permitted, required, or forbidden. To be sure, some do, namely experts in the

law (lawyers, judges, administrators, etc.), who may go through a day “taking reasonable care”,

36
Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 12(b)(6). The rule is an interesting case, as it provides an action description (in
this case an omission) which the law directs plaintiffs, defendants (in order to raise a motion), and the judge (in
order to dismiss a case) to each apply to the conduct of the plaintiff in initiating a lawsuit.

28

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


or “acting in good faith”, or “performing due diligence”, or whatever. But ordinary citizens

rarely exhibit this level of knowledge of the law, and thereby are unable to obey it.

The objection in fact sets the bar far too high in regards to what knowledge of the law

must be in this context and how it must be manifested in acts of obedience and in the

explanations of those acts. For all that IFK requires is knowledge of the relevant legal norms at

some level of description. A person may know the language of a statute or regulation verbatim,

but more often the knowledge which plays a role in motivating action is much more coarse-

grained. One may know the core of a legal requirement without knowing the particulars; in the

extreme, one may manifest sufficient knowledge of a legal norm only by using what Anscombe

once called a ‘stopping modal,’ a deontic locution that is opaque with regard to the content of

the relevant norm, but references it nonetheless (“You can’t cross the street there,” “You have

to pay the fine,” and so on). 37 The character of legal knowledge has received scarce attention

from philosophers of law, but for present purposes, it is enough to say that obedience to law

allows for such knowledge to take many forms, and it nonetheless be the case that the person

who obeys both recognizes a legal norm as an authoritative directive, and allows that fact to

make a difference, both causal and normative, in the production of her action.

III. DISOBEDIENCE

I turn now to the even more neglected topic of disobeying the law; there is not in fact an

articulated (much less defended) view of disobedience to be found at all in the relevant

literatures (on civil disobedience and philosophical anarchism, for example). So it would be of

37
G.E.M. Anscombe, “On the Source of the Authority of the State,” in Collected Philosophical Papers of G.E.M.
Anscombe, Vol. 3: Ethics, Religion, and Politics (Oxford: Blackwell, 1981).

29

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


some interest to arrive at some considered view of the matter, in order to understand better

what is at stake in those debates. Given the foregoing discussion of obedience, one question to

address at the outset is the logical relationship between obeying and disobeying the law. One

view is to treat them as akin to truth values of actions, in the sense that from the point of view

of a legal system, for any possible action, it is a token instance of either obeying or disobeying

that system or one of its constituent legal norms. At first glance, this seems to be a very strong

and capacious take on the proper application of those concepts; it would seem to follow that,

for example, anyone who is not (at a given time) obeying the criminal law of Texas is disobeying

it, and this does not seem to capture the normative relation (if there is one) between, say, the

citizens of France and the relevant parts of the Texas legal system, a relation which seems far

more tenuous than that. 38 A weaker and more plausible view is that while a token action by a

person subject to a given legal system cannot at once be both an act of obedience and

disobedience in respect of the same law, it can be the case that token actions may be neither

acts of obedience nor disobedience. In the language of classical logic, the concepts of

obedience and disobedience are contraries, and not contradictories.

What then does disobeying the law require? A natural place to start is with the negation

of the Standard View of obedience, that of reason compliance.

Reason Non-Compliance [RNC]: Given the fact, F, that a law, L, requires A to ϕ, then A
disobeys L by failing to ϕ for the reason that F.

It is easy to see that this view suffers from problems analogous to the ones raised against the

Standard, reason compliance view of obedience (RC). Reflection on specific cases, like the

38
Hans Kelsen seems to take this view in an argument for the existence of a single, international Grundnorm. See
his Principles of International Law (New York: Rinehart and Company, 1952), pp. 559-662.

30

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


murder example, seems to show that RNC does not capture what it is to run afoul of a legal

requirement, especially in such paradigm examples in the criminal law. For example,

disobeying the law by failing to refrain from murder for a specific reason, that is, for the reason

that the law forbids it implausibly overstates (and drastically complicates) the conditions for the

triggering of a sanction. It is enough, it seems, for a person simply to fail to do what the law

requires, regardless of their reasons for the failing. This is captured by the negation of the

reason conformity view (RF):

Reason Non-Conformity [RNF]: Given the fact, F, that a law, L, requires A to ϕ, then A
disobeys L by failing to ϕ and thereby failing to conform to F.

But again, analogous problems arise with RNF as the ones I raised against RF. Disobedience, on

the interpretation of RNF, could occur by cosmic accident; a person could disobey the law by

scarcely doing anything, for any reason, or for no reason at all. Nor is there, again, any

requirement here of the right direction of fit. The view would therefore entail such absurd

consequences as, for example, the idea that distant peoples of the past disobeyed the current

New York penal code. RNF also runs afoul of a commonplace of the criminal law, according to

which it is often the case that offences (and ipso facto acts of disobedience) are committed

with certain sorts of intentions (for example a ‘mens rea’). So it might be thought that

negation of the intention compliance view (IC) is on the right track:

Intention Non-Compliance [INC]: Given the fact that a law, L, requires A to ϕ, then A
disobeys L only by ϕing with the intention of not-ϕing.

However, yet again, analogous problems arise as we encountered in the discussion of

obedience as stated by IC. It is highly implausible (not to mention a peculiar public policy) to

require that disobeying a law requires acting with a specific intention to fail to do an action

31

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


under the full description contained in the relevant legal norm. As observed in the previous

section, there are exceptional cases in which one intends an action under the legal description

of that action, but even more exceptional would be intentional omissions in regards to those

descriptions; only the most indignant anarchists would engage in such behavior.

The remaining complementary views to those developed with respect to obedience,

however, do seem more promising. Consider:

Intention Non-Conformity (INF): Given that a law, L, requires A to ϕ, then A disobeys L


by intending to Ψ, and by Ψing, only if it is the case that by Ψing, A fails to ϕ.

This seems to at least partially capture the notion of disobedience (or ‘offending’) underlying

the criminal law: to act with an intention to perform an act-token which is reasonably

describable as one which the law forbids. 39 There is a wide range of cases which cannot be

considered here, though I note that INF is consistent with many of the important theories of

the role and content of intentions in the criminal law. 40 I put aside the prospects of INF as a

characterization of standard cases of disobedience, in order to isolate what is involved in acts of

civil disobedience.

For acts of civil disobedience seem to be markedly different from the ordinary acts of

disobedience of thieves and murderers. The most salient difference of those acts of

disobedience (quite apart from all the aspects, most discussed by political philosophers, which

make those acts ‘civil’) is that they are done with some knowledge of a range of relevant,

39
I mean ‘reasonably describable’ in a non-technical sense so as to avoid any reference to any particular
evidentiary standard of proof in establishing the elements of a given crime.
40
See, e.g., Gideon Yaffe, Attempts: In the Philosophy of Action and the Criminal Law (New York: Oxford University
Press, 2010), pp. 109-119, Michael Moore, Placing Blame: A Theory of the Criminal Law (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1997), pp. 459-469. and R.A. Duff, Criminal Attempts (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), pp. 316-
319.

32

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


applicable laws. These acts are done with knowledge of descriptions of acts provided by the

law which agents may perform deliberately, or as a necessary means to deliberately performing

civilly disobedient acts. The analogue of the intention conformity with knowledge (IFK) view

discussed above captures the idea:

Intention Non-Conformity with Knowledge (INFK): Given that a law, L, requires A to ϕ,


then A disobeys L by intending to Ψ, and Ψing, only if it is the case that by Ψing, A does
not ϕ, and A knows that by Ψing, A fails to ϕ.

Notice that on this view that it is not necessary for A to intend not to ϕ in order to (civilly)

disobey, but rather to intend an action which A knows either is or in some way results in not-

ϕing. And we can add the same qualification to INKF as we did to IFK, that the relevant

knowledge play some role, if only in the background, in producing the civilly disobedient act.

Unlike cases from the criminal law, acts of civil disobedience are a specific kind of intentional

omission, what Clarke calls intentional refraining: “one can carry out an intention to A and be

aware that, in intentionally A-ing, one will not do something B, without then intending not to B,

and yet intentionally refrain from B-ing.” 41 INFK attempts to capture this notion and combine

with the idea that the relevant knowledge or awareness must move the agent to act.

I think the concept of disobeying the law on the model of INFK is at the core of the

explanation of how a person must in fact proceed if they are to perform an act of civil

disobedience. Theorists of civil disobedience rarely look to the actual history and practice of

civil disobedience as a guide to theory construction; 42 but my suggestion of what disobedience

41
See Randolph Clarke, Omissions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), p. 68, and the examples he considers
there.
42
Two notable exceptions are Vinit Haksar, Civil Disobedience, Threats and Offers (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1986) and David Lyons, “Moral Judgment, Historical Reality, and Civil Disobedience,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 27
(1998): 31-49.

33

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


requires in cases of civil disobedience is consistent with the evidence of how practitioners of

civil disobedience themselves characterize what they are in the business of doing.

For example, in one of the classic statements and defenses of civil disobedience, Martin

Luther King, Jr., points out that civil rights protestors engaging in civilly disobedient acts aim

“consciously to break laws,” 43 which I have taken account of in the knowledge constraints of

civilly disobedient action as reflected in INFK. To take another example, Mahatma Gandhi once

wrote that being merely “mentally disobedient” is a necessary but not sufficient condition of

successful civil disobedience; by “mentally disobedient” he seems to have meant intentionally

acting with the knowledge that one’s action was inconsistent with what the law permits,

forbids, or requires, which is precisely the core idea of INFK. 44

Beyond these classical sources, if one looks to the practical literature of civil

disobedience and nonviolent resistance, one finds routine expression of the core idea of INFK.

In many handbooks of ‘direct action,’ used from the 1960s onwards, one finds advice to

protestors as to which laws they should aim to disobey in the course of their activities, and for

which they may be arrested. 45 A recent and striking example is the instructional materials

provided to those engaged in civil disobedience in the 2014 “Umbrella Revolution” in Hong

Kong, in which students publicly protested political oppression by the ruling communist party in

43
Martin Luther King Jr., “Letter from a Birmingham Jail” in A Testament of Hope: The Essential Writings of Martin
Luther King, Jr. (San Francisco: HarperCollins, 1991), p. 293 (my emphasis).
44
See The Collected Works of Mahatma Gandhi, Vol. XX (India: Ministry of Information and Broadcasting,
Publications Division, 1966), pp. 464-66. Gandhi’s point was that mere disobedience of this sort required in
addition the now familiar elements of civility (a public, conscientious act, and so on) in order to qualify as civil
disobedience.
45
See the many historical examples in Gene Sharp’s seminal work, The Politics of Nonviolent Action (Boston, Mass.:
Porter Sargent, 1973), pp. 303-319. Examples of such handbooks can be found at
http://www.directaction.org/handbook/ (accessed January 12, 2018).

34

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


Beijing. 46 In those materials, ordinances of the Laws of Hong Kong are quoted in full (the legal

norms setting out the description of such offences as ‘obstructing a public place,’ ‘unauthorized

assembly,’ and so on), with the clear purpose of providing protestors knowledge of the precise

legal descriptions of forbidden acts, in order for them to knowingly and intentionally fail to do

them.

So according to INFK, the civilly disobedient citizen must know the law they wish to

disobey, and, as it were, take up the point of view of the law regarding her proposed action, in

order to determine whether that action would be an act of disobedience at all. 47 Since this

person actually aims at disobeying, she must make sure that how the law would characterize

what she proposes to do is at odds with the action it forbids. There is therefore a certain

symmetry between the accounts of what obedience and civil disobedience each requires. In

each case, a person subject to the law must, to some extent and at some level of description,

adopt the understanding which the law provides of a given action or range of actions, in order

to act with, and be motivated by, the knowledge or awareness that one is or is not doing

something which corresponds to that understanding.

IV. CONCLUSION

I have argued that some versions of IFK and INFK are the best we can do to explain the

foundational concepts of obeying and disobeying the law, at least as they figure in the

philosophical debates about political obligation, civil disobedience, and legal authority. On the

46
See the civil disobedience handbook provided to protestors in Hong Kong at the website “Occupy Central”,
accessible in English here: http://oclp.hk/index.php?route=occupy/eng_detail&eng_id=28. (accessed January 12,
2018). See esp. Section 1, “Guidance Note on Legal Matters.”
47
The same qualifications on the knowledge condition discussed above (pp. 24-25) apply here as well.

35

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


one hand, requiring any more to obey the law will simply not bear out what the law actually

requires from us in a broad range of cases. On the other, requiring any less would allow us to

find obedience everywhere, and thus nowhere, and would leave us as bad off as our king

without a kingdom. The same can be said of any plausible account of disobedience. But even

so, these accounts begin to clarify what is at issue in the discussions about the possible

justifications of a general duty to obey the law, or whether a citizen is justified in civilly

disobeying the laws of the state. For those questions are in part about when a citizen must, or

should, take up the point of view of the law when understanding their own actions and

intentions, a point of view which is essential to understanding themselves. If these views of

obedience and disobedience are considered within those debates, it becomes clearer why they

are so important, and makes more precise one way in which the state can, and routinely does,

influence those over whom it claims the right to demand obedience and to punish

disobedience.

It may be suggested that the regimentation of the concepts of obedience and

disobedience I have proposed in this paper is more than we should reasonably expect from

them, and that the long-standing inattention to their contours and significance is just as it

should be. Some rough notion of ‘conformity to’ or ‘breach of’ the law is all we need to get on

with our work in legal and political philosophy, and so I have in effect made a mountain out of a

molehill. Nothing is lost, one may think, in the discussions of whether there is a duty to obey

the law, or whether civil disobedience is ever justified, if the notions of obedience and

disobedience are left virtually unexplained; and, further, nothing is gained on the score of

clarity by engaging in the sort of analysis I have offered here.

36

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760


If this criticism is right, then I think that all of the perennial debates in which the ideas of

obeying or disobeying the law feature will continue to be fraught with ambiguity and

uncertainty as to the kind of human actions and attitudes under discussion. The long-standing

questions of, for example, how a duty to obey the law can be justified, what sort of duty it is, as

well as in what sense civil disobedience is permissible or even obligatory, are of course urgent

and important. But unless we have a better understanding of what sort of thing the duty to

obey the law is a duty to do, or just what sort of thing one must do in order for one’s action to

be civilly disobedient, then the very questions which philosophers have long asked about them

will themselves remain obscure.

37

Electronic copy available at: https://ssrn.com/abstract=3226760

You might also like