Leo Strauss and The Quarrel Between Poetry and Philosophy
Leo Strauss and The Quarrel Between Poetry and Philosophy
Leo Strauss and The Quarrel Between Poetry and Philosophy
Dolores Amat1
Modern and classical alternatives
Leo Strauss writes under the shadow of what he calls the contemporary collapse of
rationalism. This collapse leads him to consider the origin of rationalism, which according to his
perspective “can be identified with the problem of Socrates, or the problem of classical political
philosophy in general”2. This problem appears clearly in the difference between Aristophanes` and
Plato's presentation of Socrates. According to Strauss, this difference is an expression of a
fundamental quarrel of Western tradition, the secular quarrel between poetry and philosophy as
alternative solutions to the problem of human happiness. In this sense, if Plato and Aristophanes
represent the classical options, Strauss` position can be interpreted as a modern affirmation of
philosophy as the answer to the fundamental problems of our time. Hence, the author speaks out
against the many voices that declare the end of philosophy and argues for the possibility of
resuming the path outlined by Plato, in addressing the challenges that arise in modernity. This paper
seeks to explore this return to classical philosophy to which the author invites, to consider its
possibilities and implications.
8 Strauss, Leo, “The Origins of Political Science and The Problem of Socrates: Six Public Lectures”, in Interpretation. A
Journal of Political Philosophy, Volume 23 Number 2, Winter 1996, pp. 157.
9 Ibid., pp. 158.
10 Ibid. pp. 157.
11 See Strauss, Leo, Socrates and Aristophanes, Chicago – London, The University of Chicago Press, 1980, pp. 136-
159.
12 See Strauss, Leo, On Plato`s Symposium, Chicago – London, The University of Chicago Press, 2001, pp. 6.
say, and they are meant to say, different things to different men”13. The author points out in the first
place that the platonic writings are works of art rather than reports. He therefore proposes paying
attention to the settings of the dialogues, to the actions and to everything which is not clearly stated
in the speeches. Something essential is generally subtracted from the play, and this abstraction is
always eloquent regarding the most important subject in the work. Besides, Strauss states that the
number and variety of the Platonic works can help understand the whole collection: there are
different kinds of dialogues, and each one is characterised by the way it treats the subject, rather
than by the subject itself. Among other distinctions, Strauss discriminates between dialogues
in which Socrates leads the conversation and those in which he doesn't, between narrated and
performed dialogues, and also between volunteer and compulsive dialogues, either sought by
Socrates or not.
The Republic, which among other things is presented by Strauss as Plato's response to the
Clouds and the Assembly of Women, “is the only dialogue narrated by Socrates which is
compulsory”14. A group of young men urges Socrates to stay in the Piraeus and he accepts as a
courtesy. There, a conversation on justice takes place. Strauss points out which is the abstraction of
this dialogue: the body and, more generally, eros, are ostentatiously absent in the play15. Socrates
and the rest of its participants remain in the Piraeus with the promise of a meal as well as of a torch
race, but no further mention to the meal or the race is made. They are replaced by a conversation
about justice. “The feeding of the body is replaced by the feeding of the soul” 16. During the dialogue
Socrates founds the perfect city in speech. Thus, while in the Clouds the philosopher is responsible
for revealing the weakness of the Just Speech, here Socrates' mission is to demonstrate the strength
of justice. Thrasymachus, the rhetorician, is his rival: he is of the opinion that what is fair equals
what is legal, and since what is legal depends on the decisions of those who rule, justice is identical
to the will of the strongest. “The manner in which Thrasymachus behaves -he forbids to say certain
things, or forbids to give certain answers, and he demands a fine from Socrates for payment, for
which Plato's brother vouches, just as Plato himself vouches for a payment of another kind
demanded from Socrates on the day of his accusation- the manner in which Thrasymachus behaves
reminds us of the behaviour of the city of Athens towards Socrates. The thesis of Thrasymachus,
that the just is the legal, is the thesis of the actual polis, which does not permit an appeal beyond its
laws”17.
Taking this as a starting point, Plato will address in his dialogue the conflict that was clearly
reflected in the death sentence of his teacher. He will seek to change the ending of the story, he will
call on a kind of justice superior to any particular law. Hence, the Socrates from the Republic
distinguishes justice from mythology and tradition. What is just appears in his speech as an eternal
standard, a rule no longer dependent on convention but rather on unalterable nature. Since this
natural parameter appears to be rational (nature is presented as intelligible, rational), the faculty by
which is possible to get to know it, is reason. “The just city is a perfectly rational society” This way,
justice is presented “as the preserve of the wise”18.
But a question is raised during the discussion: how would the wise obtain the obedience of
those who are not wise? There will always exist different characters and impulses. In every
community there are beings drawn toward the sensual pleasures, others dedicated to the search for
recognition and honour and some others devoted to the challenges of the spirit. There will always
be people unwilling to follow the rules as well. Hence, the Republic seems to suggest that to place
everybody within the limits of the law, persuasion and in certain occasions the use of force are
needed. Besides, if knowledge of justice is the task of the wise, it is to be expected that those who
Subtle differences
Let us go back to the beginning: we stated that philosophy and poetry offer alternative
solutions to the problem of human happiness, we also suggested that this difference could be
appreciated in the divergent Socrates that Plato and Aristophanes present. It was therefore to be
expected that a thorough interpretation of the diverse figures of Socrates would capture the
differences between philosophy and poetry in a clear and antagonistic way. However, in going back
with everything we have said up to now, we are surprised by the fact that we have found nothing but
agreement between Plato and Aristophanes. In Strauss` speech philosophy and poetry are presented
at first as antagonistic views but afterwards they are found to be not so dissimilar.
We found that both the philosopher and the poet write works of art in which they address the
problematic nature of human life. We also discovered that they both deploy fictions with which they
seek to favour justice, and we finally stated that they both recognise and put across the limits of
reason in politics. Their ideas, their intentions, their goals and even their tasks seem to be similar.
By the same token, Strauss asserts in his last lecture on Socrates that “the core, or the arche, the
initiating principle of Platonic philosophy is the doctrine of the soul, and this core, or arche, is
identical with the theme of poetry”.
What is it then that which confronts poetry and philosophy? Why are them presented by
Strauss as being mutually exclusive alternatives? How are their answer to the problem of human
happiness different?
Strauss explicitly addresses this questions only toward the end of his lectures on Socrates. At
that point Strauss asks himself if it is not evident that the way of Platonic philosophy is completely
different from the way of poetry. On the one hand “the poet sets forth his vision of the soul, he does
not try to prove that vision or to refute alternative visions. His organ is a vision with the mind's eye,
nous, not reasoning, logismos”21On the other hand, philosophy “expresses itself in treatises”22 that
present methodical and impersonal reasoning. Nevertheless, after considering the Phaedo, the
dialogue in which Socrates' death is depicted, Strauss points out that Platonic dialogues are a sort
of drama, which are far from being impersonal or detached. Furthermore, the arguments in Plato's
plays are rarely structured in an entirely rational way, but they are rather embedded in the human
drama and are therefore as biassed and defective as those put forward by the characters of poets like
19 Ibid. pp. 185.
20 See Hilb, C., Leo Strauss: el arte de leer. Una lectura de la interpretación straussiana de Maquiavelo, Hobbes,
Locke y Spinoza, Buenos Aires, FCE,, 2005, p. 135.
21 Strauss, Op. cit., pp. 202-203.
22 Ibid. pp. 203
Homer, Dante or Shakespeare.
We keep the question then: what distinguishes Platonic philosophy from poetry? It is often
said that philosophy appeals to our understanding alone, while poetry deals mainly with passion.
However, Strauss says that this would only be true if philosophy were a science like mathematics
and not a solution to the problem of happiness. As such, Platonic philosophy is bound to affect our
whole being, just like poetry. Based on a deep knowledge of the human soul, both poetry and
philosophy are able to guide men and women in the search for happiness, to contribute in the
purification of passion. Therefore, our question remains unanswered: in which sense are philosophy
and poetry two mutually exclusive alternatives?
Strauss talks about a transformation of Socrates, a fundamental change that transformed him
from a simple philosopher of nature into a complete philosopher. He describes this transformation
as a “return from madness to sanity or sobriety” that allowed Socrates to become the originator of
political science. And he asserts that this transformation took place when the philosopher discovered
“the paradoxical fact that, in a way, the most important truth is the most obvious truth, or the truth
of the surface”23. Perhaps we also need to explore this idea in order to be able to grasp the meaning
of the quarrel that according to Strauss is in the origin of political philosophy and rationalism as
well. To find the difference between the poet and the philosopher we thus might need to look in the
surface. And what is in the surface of this quarrel? The figure of Socrates.
Conclusion
Let us trace the way we have followed up to this point. We stated that what Leo Strauss calls
the contemporary collapse of rationalism leads him to consider the origins of rationalism.
According to his perspective, the origins of rationalism can be identified with the problem of
Socrates, which can be appreciated in the traditional quarrel between poetry and philosophy as
alternative solutions to the problem of human happiness. We also said that this quarrel appears
clearly in the difference between Aristophanes` and Plato's presentation of Socrates. Therefore, we
decided to study both portraits, in order to illuminate the case in point and thus consider the return
to classical philosophy or classical rationalism to which Strauss invites.
Based mainly in the six lectures on Socrates delivered by Strauss in 1958 at the University of
Chicago, we noticed that unlike what we could have expected at first, what confronts poetry and
philosophy is less their irreconcilable differences than their similarities. In Strauss` speech
philosophy and poetry are presented at first as antagonistic views but afterwards they are found to
be not so dissimilar. We saw Aristophanes ascend from vulgarity and Plato descend to the cave.
Their works seem to meet at the highest point of the cave, where they can imitate the human drama,
purify passion and teach justice.
Therefore, we turned to the obvious question: what confronts poetry and philosophy? In other
words, why are them presented by Strauss as being mutually exclusive alternatives? The answer we
found was also obvious: the only thing that distinguishes philosophy from poetry was that thing that
was mentioned from the beginning: the figure of Socrates. The most important difference between
Aristophanes and Plato is the presence or absence of the philosopher at the peak of humanity, above
the human drama depicted in poetry. To put it differently, what is at stake is the possibility of
surpassing the cave, of reaching the higher kind of life that neither tragedy nor comedy can
describe33.
But what we have learnt through the study of the Symposium is that neither the poet nor the
philosopher can demonstrate their point in an entirely rational way, because none of them possess a
complete and conclusive knowledge of nature34. In other words, neither philosophy nor poetry can
31 As regards the meaning of this assertion, the following words by Seth Benardete might be illuminating: “Plato
completes Aristophanes presumably because comedy, though it soars higher than tragedy, is parasitic on tragedy, and
philosophy altogether transcends their difference.” See Benardete, Seth, “Leo Strauss` The City and Man”, The
Political Science Reviewer, vol. 8, 1978, pp. 7.
32 Plato, Symposium, The Ecco Library, UK, 2006, pp. 57.
33 In this spirit, Strauss asserts the following: “...the philosopher is not an individual like myself or like other
professors of political philosophy or of philosophy tout court or tout long”. Strauss, Leo, “The Origins of Political
Science and The Problem of Socrates: Six Public Lectures”, in Interpretation. A Journal of Political Philosophy, Volume 23
Number 2, Winter 1996, pp. 204.
34 See Strauss, Leo, On Plato`s Symposium, Chicago – London, The University of Chicago Press, 2001, pp. 4:
“Everyone knows, or has heard, that according to Plato man is incapable of acquiring full wisdom; that the very
name of philosophy, love of wisdom, indicates that wisdom proper is not accessible to men. Or to use the other
assert conclusively whether eros is horizontal or vertical and the position attributed to Socrates in
the schema of the Whole cannot be proven by any of the two.
It is in this sense that Aristophanes and Plato present two mutually exclusive alternative
perspectives about the world and human life. These alternatives cannot be amalgamated and the
quarrel, that is present in the origins of the rationalism that Strauss praises, has not been settled yet.
Taking this as a starting point, Strauss asserts the dogmatic character of the voices who declare the
definite death of philosophy and he argues for the possibility of resuming the path outlined by Plato
in addressing the challenges of our time.
In any case, we arrive to a paradoxical conclusion: if the figure of Socrates is the sole thing
that allows us to tell apart Plato from Aristophanes, and if the superiority of Socrates` way of life
cannot be proven in a rational way, what distinguishes rationalism from its alternative is not
altogether rational, or it is not completely based in a rational choice. To put it differently, it seems
that Plato's inclination towards philosophy is not entirely due to a reason or an indisputable
argument.
From this starting point, we are compelled to address another question: why does Strauss
choose the philosophical alternative over the poetical one? Is it because of his personal preference?
Because of a particular kind of faith? Because of the implications of the assumption of the
possibility of a higher life? Or is it due to an ineffable or inexplicable experience? As far as we
know, Strauss does not answer to these questions in a clear and explicit manner. However, as we
stated before, he does point to the end of the Symposium when he addresses the possibility of an
agreement between philosophy and poetry.
At the end of the Symposium the agreement is propounded by a philosopher and accepted by
two poets. Socrates compels a tragic poet and a comic poet to accept his thesis on tragedy and
comedy. Then, he leaves everybody sleeping and he rises to start a new day. As we have already
suggested, what the end of the dialogue shows beyond doubt is the factual superiority of Socrates,
who is not only the best in speech but also in deed. Unlike what Aristophanes` portrait of Socrates
implies, philosophers understand and know how to handle nature, human affairs and rhetoric. They
are the key to human happiness not only because of their theoretical wisdom but also thanks to their
practical skills. Unlike the Socrates of the Clouds, who endangers the city and the lives of the
philosophers, the Socrates of the Symposium manages to let others sleep peacefully while he and his
friends devote themselves to their activity.