By Karl H - Pribram: Transcending T H E Mind/Brain Problem
By Karl H - Pribram: Transcending T H E Mind/Brain Problem
by Karl H . Pribram
Ever since Rent! Descartes enunciated his dictum, Cogito ergo sum,
philosophers have debated the relationship of mental phenomena to
the material universe. Those of us in the laboratory trying to under-
stand the relationship of brain anatomy and physiology to behavior
and to subjective experience continually come up against this issue.
T h e very words we use to describe our work-brain and experience-
embody the problem. I believe the time has come to look at this
problem once more but with the wisdom that ought to come
from recent discoveries in the physical, biological, and behavioral sci-
ences. The time does seem ripe. There has been a surge of publica-
tions on the topic.' However, there appears to be little in the way of
wisdom or often even acquaintance with those scientific discoveries
that bear directly on the issue.
ONTOLOGY
AND SCIENTIFIC
DISCOVERY
A major deterrent to wisdom has been the pronouncement by certain
philosophers that scientific discoveries can have no bearing on the
question.2 T h e issue, we are told, is a philosophical one that must be
resolved through reasoning and not by experiment. It is claimed to be
ontological, not scientific, in nature.
My theme throughout this paper will be that there is some merit to
most of the philosophical arguments but that in essence they can be
transcended. And so I agree that ontology is at the root of the
mind/brain issue. However, it is incorrect to argue that therefore
scientific research has no relevance. My claim here is that the very
assumptions that have given rise to the problem have been shaken by
the results of research.
THEDEMATERIALIZATION
OF MATTER
103
ZYGON
104
Karl H . Pribram
(and neural excitation, the brain’s “energy,” falls readily under this
rubric). But energy is measured by the amount of work that can be
accomplished by using it and the efficiency of its use depends on its
organization as measured by its entropy. The invention of the vacuum
tube and subsequent devices has shown that minute amounts of
energy can control large expenditures and that these minute organi-
zations provide “information,” that is, they inform and organize
energy. Measures of information and entropy thus were seen as re-
lated.6 Computers were constructed to process information, and pro-
grams were written to organize the operations of computers. Is the
information contained in a program “material” or “mental”? If it is
either, what then of the information in a book? Or the entropy that
describes the behavior of a heat engine or of a warm-blooded mam-
mal? Clearly we have come to the limit of usefulness of a distinction
between the material and the mental.
Research on “mind” using behavioral techniques also blurs a dis-
tinction which seems so clear when only the ordinary Euclidean, New-
tonian domain of appearances is considered. As noted above, the
organization of the behavior of organisms can be comprehended best
by recourse to concepts such as “information” and “programs” or
“plans” which serve equally well in understanding the operations of
machine^.^ Once again the question arises: Is information processing
to be conceived as mental or material?
Philosophers and psychologists of a nonbehaviorist persuasion im-
mediately will counter that behavior is not mind and therefore any
argument about mental phenomena derived from behavior is spuri-
ous. They would rather begin with “the phenomenon itself existen-
tially experienced.” But there is little that can be done with such
experiences except to attempt to describe them (behaviorally) and to
organize the descriptions (structurally). Thus Maurice Merleau-
Ponty, an existentialist philosopher, has authored a book entitled The
Structure of Behavior (1963), which in both spirit and content shows
remarkable resemblances to our own Plans and the Structure of Behavior
(1960), which tackles the issues from a behavioral and information-
processing vantage.8 I do not mean to convey here that there is no
distinction between a behavioristic and an existential-phenomenalistic
approach to mind. Elsewhere I detail this distinction in terms of a
search for causes by behaviorists and a search for informational struc-
ture reasonably (meaningfully) composed by phenomenol~gists.~
What I do want to emphasize here is that both approaches lead to
conceptualizations that cannot be classified readily as either mental or
material. Behaviorists in their search for causes rely on drives, incen-
105
ZYGON
DO EXPERIENCES
MATTEROR DOESMATTER BECOMEEXPERIENCED?
In this world of appearances there is no question but that human
mental experience can be distinguished sharply from that which is
experienced. The issue has been labelled “intentionality” (or inten-
tional inexistence) by Franz Clemens Brentano and has given rise to
inferences about the nature of reality.1° The question is often
phrased: Are my perceptions (my phenomenal experiences) the really
“real,” or does the content of those perceptions make up the “real”
world? My phenomenal experiences are mental; the world as it ap-
pears to me is material. I can give primacy to my experience and
become a phenomenologist, or I can give primacy to the contents of
the experience and become a materialist. But I can also give primacy
to neither and attest to the dual nature of reality.
Materialism and phenomenology run into difficulty only when each
attempts to deny the other. As long as only primacy is at stake, either
view can be made consistent. After all, our experiences are primary,
and empiricism is not inimical to a real material world. And we do
appear to be experiencing something(s), so our experiences may well
become organized by those real somethings.
However, by accepting such a moderate position with regard to
mind and matter we immediately come up against a set of dualistic
problems. Are the contents of perception “really” organized by the
106
Karl ff. Pribram
TRANSCENDING
DUALISMS THEM
WITHOUT DENYING
I believe that today there are answers to these questions where only a
few years ago there were none. These answers come from “unpack-
ing” conceptual confusions and demonstrating where each concep-
tualization captures a part of a truthful whole.
A semantic analysis shows that descriptors of brain, senses, and
energy sources are derived from an analysis of experience into com-
ponents. T h e components are organismic and environmental (biolog-
ical and physical or social), and each component can be subdivided
further into subcomponents until the quantum and nuclear levels of
analysis are reached. This procedure of analysis downward in a
hierarchy of systems is the ordinary way of descriptive science. Within
systems, causes and effects are traced. When discrepancies are found
statistical principles are adduced and probabilities invoked. Scientists
have become adept and comfortable with such procedures.
Mental language stems from different considerations. As in the case
of descriptive science, mental terms take their origin in experience.
Now, however, experience is validated consensually. Experience in
one sensory mode is compared with that obtained in another. Then
validation proceeds by comparison of one’s experience with that of
another. A little girl points to a horse. Up to now mother has allowed
her to say “cow” whenever any animal is pointed to. But the time has
come to be more precise, and the experience of horse becomes validly
different from that of cow. Mental language is derived from such
upward validations in a hierarchy of systems.
Elsewhere I detail the differences in scientific approach which this
upward-or outward-look entails.” It is certainly not limited to
psychology. When Albert Einstein enunciated his special and general
theories of relativity he was looking upward in the set of hierarchically
arranged physical systems. T h e resultant relativistic views are as
applicable to mental conceptualizations as they are to physical. It is
these relativisms which existentialists and phenomenologists con-
107
ZYGON
108
Karl H . Pribram
MINDAS EMERGENT
AND AS ACTOR
The views expressed thus far have provided a coherent theory which
accounts for dualistic views but transcends them by showing them to
arise from procedural differences which separately realize a common
structure. That structure is neutrally described in mathematical and
information-processing (or similar) terms-terms which cannot read-
ily be characterized as either material or mental.
This theory is considerably different from more classical dualistic
views which hold to a fundamental separation between mental and
material. I believe that there is considerable merit to these views in
that they pose questions which are not addressed by the construc-
tional realism proposed above. I do not agree with the dualistic solu-
tion (or rather nonsolutions) given by unreconstructed dualists, how-
ever, and will detail an alternative in the last section of this paper. But
let us examine one recent document which states the case for one
form of classical dualism in comprehensive fashion: The Self and Its
Brain by Karl R. Popper and John C . Eccle~.’~
109
ZYGON
The Selfand Its Bruin embodies in its format the views of its authors.
T h e book is divided into two major portions: Popper deals with the
philosophy of mind; Eccles describes the neurophysiology of brain. In
keeping with the interactionist tone of the volume there is a third
section made up of discourse between Popper and Eccles-a sort of
question and answer period. The interaction is somewhat stilted and
one sided; the discourse deals much more often with mind than with
brain. But even this defect is, 1 feel, in keeping with the authors’
philosophy. In their system, mind gently-“with a cognitive caress,” as
Eccles once put it to me-influences and biases brain function. Pop-
per is not quite so gentle as Eccles, however, and I tend to agree with
him. After all, “the pen is mightier than the sword”; there is nothing
gentle about the way I am moved by music, a spouse’s anger, etc.
Perhaps this basic disagreement between Eccles and Popper and their
attempt to deal with it “gently” has led to the somewhat artificial tone
of the interchange. I am sorry about this because I feel that the format
of two views and an interchange between them is potentially power-
ful. (1 suggested it once to Arthur Koestler, but he chose to go it alone
and produced The Ghost in the Machine.)
What does bring power to the format of The Self and Its Bruin is the
book itself. Popper’s interactionism depends on the products of mind,
its contents, becoming manifest in the physical world. T h e physical
world in turn influences the brain through the senses. Books are
prime examples, and The Self and Its Bruin is a prime example of a
book (a medium) being in format what its contents are meant to
convey.
But here we experience in reality the dissonance expressed in the
dialogue between Popper and Eccles. Popper’s books and other con-
tents of mind constitute his World 3. World 3 interacts with the brain
(which is part of the physical world-World 1) through the senses.16
The interaction is clear-cut. By contrast, Eccles has mind selecting
from the sensory input, organizing the functions of the association
cortex especially that of the dominant, speech-producing hemi-
sphere: “In these further stages the different sensory modalities pro-
ject to common areas in the polymodal areas. In these areas. . . wide-
ranging information is processed. How is it selected.. . and put to-
gether?. . . It is proposed that the self-conscious mind plays through
the whole (polymodal) liaison brain in a selective and unifying man-
n e r . . . somewhat like a searchlight. O r better, a multiple scanning
and probing device that reads out from the selects.. . .”I7
Thus mind operates on brain directly for Eccles and indirectly
through World 3 for Popper. For Popper mind is an emergent, and
110
Karl H . Pribram
111
ZYGON
Note also that such interaction does not deny the emergence of men-
tal properties. However, the emergence can stem either from biologi-
cal evolution which has produced novel brain organizations that result
in linguistic capacities or from cultural evolution which can produce
new linguistic modes such as writing and printing.25
Popper by contrast addresses the interaction between mental and
material. And although he reviews the problems faced by materialism
because of the insights obtained from the new physics, he fails to see
that these insights apply as well to a dualism which still holds dear the
separation of mind and matter. I repeat: Are forces “material”? Are
light “waves” waving in vacuo “material”? Are quarks with their
charm and flavors “material”? As noted, Wigner states that modern
physics is based on “relationships between observations not relation-
ships between observables.”26But is not this the self-same definition
which characterizes modern scientific psychology?
I do not of course deny the distinction between observation and
observable-the problem of intentionality (see, e.g., John R. Searle).
What I d o claim is that the distinction no longer distinguishes what we
call the physical from what we call the psychological sciences. I d o not
deny reality to an appearance of the material world as in Newtonian
mechanics o r in Gibsonian perceptual psychology. Nor do I deny that
one can distinguish between these appearances and other realities or
between physical reality and psychological reality. But for me realities
are constructed, often painfully and painstakingly. Appearances are
one such reality, the perceptual reality, beyond which lie others.
I am sitting quietly writing this commentary. I am moving in a
complex trajectory around the earth’s axis, the sun, and within our
galaxy. Both statements reflect a reality-the one my perceptual real-
ity, the reality of appearance; the other, my physical reality based on
the observations and calculations of innumerable scientists. Which
reality is “objective” and which “subjective”? Which is based solely on
the interaction of material observables, and which is based on mental
operations such as calculation and observation?
Popper’s invention of World 3 attempts to cope with these ques-
tions, but I believe the invention does not go far enough. The issue is
not material versus mental but how we construct a material reality and
how we construct one that is apparently mental.
Elsewhere I argue that the way Popper-and Eccles-describe the
interaction of mind and brain is akin to a colloquial use of the concept
We say that gravity pulls us to the earth. However, the
concept “gravity” was derived from studying the interactions of mas-
ses in motion. Gravity is by definition an interaction term; gravity
Karl H . Pribram
THEBRAINAS A WAVE-FORM
ANALYZER
One example is in the order of such manageability and the precision
with which the problems can be stated. I take this example from my
own work because Eccles reviews it and criticizes it in his part of the
book. The problem relates to both perception and memory. T h e issue
113
ZYGON
is how sensory input becomes encoded in the brain cortex. Eccles puts
the problem in the following way:
What neural events are in liaison with the self-conscious mind both for
giving and receiving.. . . We reject the hypothesis that the agent is the field
potential generated by the neural events. The original postulate of the gestalt
school was based on finding that a massive visual input such as a large illumi-
nated circle resulted in some topologically equivalent potential field in the
visual cortex, even a closed loop! This crude hypothesis need not be further
considered. However a more refined version has recently been proposed by
Pribram (1971) in his postulate of micro-potential fields. It is assumed that
these fields provide a more subtle cortical response than the impulse genera-
tion by neurones. However, this field potential theory involves a tremendous
loss of information because hundreds of thousands of neurones would be
contributing to a micro-potential field across a small zone of the cerebral
cortex. All the finer grain of neuronal activity would be lost in this most
inefficient task of generating a minute electrical potential by current flow in
the ohmic resistance provided by the extracellular medium. In addition we
have the further problem that there would have to be some homunculus to
read out the potentials in all their patterned array! The assumed feedback
from micro-potential fields onto the firing frequencies of neurones would be
of negligible influence because the currents would be extremely small.
We must,believe that there is an essential functional meaning in all the
discrete neuronal interactions in spatiotemporal patterns, otherwise there
would be a great loss of information. In this context, we must consider the
organization of the cortical neurones in the anatomical and physiological
entity that is called a module.. . . In the first place it is inconceivable that the
self-conscious mind is in liaison with single nerve cells or single nerve fibers.
These neuronal units as individuals are far too unreliable and ineffective. In
our present understanding of the mode of operation of neural machinery we
emphasize ensembles of neurones (many hundreds) acting in some collusive
patterned array. Only in such assemblages can there be reliability and effec-
tiveness.. . . the modules of the cerebral cortex.. . are such ensembles of
neurones. The module has to some degree a collective life of its own with as
many as 10,000 neurones of diverse types and with a functional arrangement
of feed-forward and feedback excitation and inhibition. As yet we have little
knowledge of the inner dynamic life of a module, but we may conjecture that,
with its complexly organized and intensely active properties, it could be a
component of the physical world (World 1) that is open to the self-conscious
mind (World 2) both for receiving from and for giving to. We can further
propose that not all modules in the cerebral cortex have this transcendent
property of being “open” to World 2, and thus being the World 1 compo-
nents of the interface. By definition there would be restriction to the modules
of the liaison brain, and only then when they are in the correct level of
activity. Each module may be likened to a radio transmitter-receiver unit.. . .
the module may be thought of as an integrated microcircuit of electronics,
only vastly more c o m p l i ~ a t e d . ~ ~
Although Eccles quotes my Languages of the Brain, he ignores in
the above account whole sections (e.g., pp. 126-31 and pp. 324-27)
devoted to what I label there as “logic modules.”30The structure of
114
Karl W.Pribram
115
ZYGON
116
Karl H . Pribram
of the operation of the local brain circuitry, usually with the aid of
sensory input from the environment, images and mental events
emerge and are constructed. The images are the ghosts resulting
from the operations of the machine (brain).
A similar mechanism involving the motor mechanisms of the brain
can account for intentional, planned behavior. T h e evidence that such
a mechanism exists is presented in Languages of the Bruin and
elsewhere.41 Much of my laboratory research has been involved de-
monstrating that brain function is active, not passive, in its interac-
tions with environment and elucidating the processes operative in this
active aspect of mind. This research has shown that the intrinsic cortex
and limbic formations of the forebrain actively organize sensory input,
etc.
Suffice it here to say that I believe the discovery that certain opera-
tions of the brain can be understood best in terms of processing in the
wave-form domain is as important to the mind/brain problem as the
discovery in quantum and nuclear physics that ultimately the appear-
ances of matter may be immaterial.
117
ZYGON
118
Karl H . Pribram
points out that most of our conceptions of the physical world depend
on what we can observe through lenses.42Lenses focus, objectify, and
draw boundaries between parts. Lenses particularize. Holograms by
contrast are distributive, boundaryless, and holistic. Bohm refers to
our lens-given ordinary perceptions and conceptions as explicate and
those that are holographiclike as implicate. Thus there are at least two
discernible orders in the universe-an explicate and an implicate. The
explicate order gives an account in terms of particles, objects, and
images. T h e implicate order, still poorly cognized, begins with den-
sities of the fluctuating properties of wave forms.
Bohm and other physicists have become excited by the similarity of
conceptualizations of the implicate order and those described by mys-
tics who have experienced a variety of religions and other “para-
normal” phenomena.43T h e lack of spatial and temporal boundaries,
the holographic characteristic that the whole is represented in every
part, and the transformational character of shifting from explicate to
implicate order are all beyond ordinary human experiencing which
apparently is limited to the everyday, explicate, Euclidean, Newtonian
universe to which we have become accustomed.
It is probably not an accident that holograms were a mathematical
invention (by Dennis Gabor, who received the Nobel Prize for the
discovery) which used a form of mathematics-the integral
calculus-invented by Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, who also came to a
vision of the implicate order. Leibniz’s monadology is holographic; his
monads are distributed, windowless forms each of which is representa-
tive of the whole. Substitute the term lensless for windowless, and
the description of a monad and a hologram is identical.
T o summarize this section, I propose that Eccles’s suggestion of a
distributed “mind” operating in some “as yet mysterious” way on
brain can be supported by a highly rigorous, mathematical formula-
tion. The fact that the brain is, among other things, a wave-form
analyzer, that it encodes information in a distributed fashion akin to
that which characterizes a hologram also means that the structural
boundaries that characterize the ordinary limits of “brain” and “body”
are transcended. Take as an example our current-day world in a large
city. T h e space surrounding us is filled with wave forms generated by
radio and television stations. We are insensitive to these wave forms
unless we obtain the use of a receiver tunable to one o r another of the
wave forms. Only then do we “explicate” into the everyday domain
the wave forms enfolded in the space about us. The “mystery” is
resolved not by holding to the stance that Eccles has taken which is
appropriate to Popper’s formulation but by recognizing the trans-
formational nature of the implicate domain.
119
ZYGON
120
Karl H . Pribram
121
ZYGON
NOTES
1. See, e.g., R. W. Sperry, “Neurology and the Mind-Brain Problem,” American
Scientist 40 (1952): 291-312; Gordon G . Globus, “Mind, Structure and Contradiction,”
in Casciuusness and the Brain: A Scientific and Philosophical Inquily, ed. Gordon G. Globus,
Grover Maxwell, and Irwin Savodnik (New York: Plenum Press, 1976), pp. 273-92;
Karl R. Popper and John C . Eccles, The Self and Its Brain (New York: Springer-Verlag,
1977).
2. See, e.g., J. W. N. Watkins, “A Basic Difficulty in the Mind-Brain Identity-
Hypothesis,” in The Searchfor Absolute Values in a Changing World, 2 vols. (San Francisco:
International Conference on the Unity of the Sciences, 1978).
3.. Niels Bohr, Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge (New York: Vintage Press,
1966); Werner Heisenberg, Physics and Philosophy (London: Allen & Unwin, 1959).
4. Eugene P. Wigner, “Epistemology of Quantum Mechanics: Its Appraisals and
Demands,” in The Anatomy of Knowledge, ed. Marjorie Grene (London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul, 1969).
5. Erwin Schroedinger, “Quantization as a Problem of Proper Values,” in Collected
Papers a Wave Mechanics, trans. J. F. Shearer and W. M. Deans (London: Blackie &
Son, Ltd., 1928); Louis Victor prince de Broglie, The Current Intwpretatia of Wave
Mechanism: A Critical Study, trans. Express Translation Service (Amsterdam: Elsevier,
1964).
6. E.g., L. Brillouin, Science and Information Theory, 2d ed. (New York: Academic
Press, 1962); E. von Weizsacker, Offene Spteme I (Stuttgart: Verlag, 1974).
122
Karl H . Pribram
7. See, e.g., G. A. Miller, E. H. Galanter, and Karl H. Pribram, Plans and the
Structure of Behavior (New York: Henry Holt & Co., 1960).
8. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, The Structure of Behavr’or, trans. Alden L. Fisher (Bos-
ton: Beacon Press, 1963); Miller, Galanter, and Pribram.
9. Karl H. Pribram, “Behaviorism, Phenomenology and Holism in Psychology: A
Scientific Analysis” (paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Psycholog-
ical Association, Toronto, Ontario, Canada, August 28-September 1 , 1978).
10. Franz Clemens Brentano, Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint,, trans. Antos
C. Rancmello, D. B. Terrell and Linda L. McAlister (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul,
1973); R. M. Chisholm, Realism and the Background of Phenomenology (New York: Free
Press, 1960).
11. Karl H. Pribram, “Proposal for a Structural Pragmatism: Some Neuro-
psychological Considerations of Problems in Philosophy,” in Scientqic Psychology: Princi-
ples and Approaches, ed. B. Wolman and E. Nagle (New York: Basic Books, 1965), pp.
426-59.
12. See, e.g., William James, A Pluralistic Universe (London: Longman’s, Green &
Co., 1909); Bertrand Russell, Human Knowledge, Its Scope and Limits (New York: Simon
& Schuster, 1948).
13. Karl H. Pribram, ”The Realization of Mind,” Synthese 22 (1971): 313-22.
14. Pribram, “Proposal for a Structural Pragmatism” and “Realization of Mind’’;
idem, Languages of the Brain: Experimental Paradoxes and Principles in Neuropsychology, 2d
ed. (Monterey, Calif.: Brooks/Cole, 1977).
15. Popper and Eccles (n. 1 above).
16. E.g., ibid., p. 449. [For a discussion of Popper’s three worlds see John C. Eccles,
“Cultural Evolution versus Biological Evolution,” Zygon 8 (September-December 1973):
282-93.-ED.]
17. Popper and Eccles, p. 163.
18. E.g., ibid., p. 127.
19. Ibid., p. 35.
20. See Popper’s discussion of Gilbert Ryle, ibid., pp. 104-7.
21. See the “subjective behaviorism” of Miller, Galanter, and Pribram (n. 7 above).
22. Popper and Eccles, p. 514.
23. Sigmund Freud, “Project for a Scientific Psychology” (1895), in The Standard
Edition of the Complete Psychologzcal Works of Sigmund Fveud, trans. James Strachey et al.
(London: Hogarth Press, 1950), 1:281-397; Karl H. Pribram and M. M. Gill, Freud’s
“Project” Reassessed (New York: Basic Books, 1976).
24. Popper and Eccles, pp. 104-8;James Jei-ome Gibson, The Perception of the Visual
World (New York: Houghton Mifflin, 1950).
25. Karl H. Pribram, “Language in a Sociobiological Frame,” Annals ofthe New York
Academy of Sciences 280 (1976): 798-809.
26. Wigner (n. 4 above).
27. Karl H. Pribram, “Problems Concerning the Structure of Consciousness,” in
Globus, Maxwell, and Savodnik (n. 1 above).
28. See, e.g., my “Realization of Mind” (n. 13 above).
29. Popper and Eccles, pp. 365-66.
30. Pribram, Languages of the Brain (n. 14 above).
31. D. N. Spinelli, “Visual Receptive Fields in the Gat’s Retina: Complications,”
Science 152 (1966): 1768-69; R. W. Phelps, “Effects of Interactions of Two Moving
Lines on Single Unit Responses in the Cat’s Visual Cortex,” Vision Research 14 (1974):
1371-75; B. Bridgeman, “Metacontrast and Lateral Inhibition,” Psychological Review 78
(1971): 528-39; Karl H. Pribram, M. Nuwer, and R. Baron, “The Holographic
Hypothesis of Memory Structure in Brain Function and Perception,” in Contemporary
Developments in Mathematical Psychology, ed. R. C. Atkinson et al. (San Francisco: W. H.
Freeman & Co., 1974), pp. 416-67.
32. Pasko Rakic, Local Circuit Neurons (Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press, 1976).
123
ZYGON
33. See, e.g., Francis 0. Schmitt, Parvati Dev, and Barry H. Smith, “Electrotonic
Processing of lnformation by Brain Cells,’’ Science 193 (1976): 114-20.
34. G. M. Shepherd, The Synaptic Organization .f the Brain: An Introduction (New
York: Oxford University Press, 1974); W. Rall, “Dendritic Neuron Theory and
Dendrodentritic Synapses in a Simple Cortical System,”in The Neurosciences: SecondStudy
Program, ed. Francis 0. Schmitt (New York: Rockefeller University Press, 1970), pp.
552-65.
35. Pribram, Languages of the Brain, chap. 8.
36. G. S. Ohm, “Uber die Definition des Tones, nebst daran geknupfter Theorie
der Sirene und ahnlicher tonbildener Vorrichtungen,” Annalen der Physikalischen Chemie
59 (1843): 513-65; Hermann von Helmholtz, Lehre uon den Tonempfindungen
(Braunschweig: Vieweg, 1863).
37. George von Bekesy, “Neural Volleys and the Similarity between Some Sensa-
tions Produced by Tones and by Skin Vibrations,” Journal qf the Accoustical Society of
America 29 (1957): 1059-69.
38. F. W. Campbell and J. G. Robson, “Application of Fourier Analysis to the Visibil-
ity of Gratings,” Journal of Physiology 197 (1968): 551-66; J. A. Movshon, I. D.
Thompson, and D. J. Tolhurst, “Receptive Field Organization of Complex Cells in the
Cat’s Striate Cortex,” Journal of Physiology (in press); idem, “Spatial Summation in the
Receptive Field of Simple Cells in the Cat’s Striate Cortex,” ibid. (in press); idem,
“Spatial and Temporal Contrast Sensitivity of Cells in the Cat’s Areas 17 and 18,”ibid.
(in press); R. L. De Valois, D. G. Albrecht, and L. G. Thorell, “Spatial Tuning of LGN
and Cortical Cells in Monkey Visual System,” in Spatial Contrast, ed. H. Spekreijse
(Amsterdam: Royal Netherlands Academy of Sciences, in press); idem, “Cortical Cells:
Line and Edge Detectors, or Spatial Frequency Filters?” in Frontiers of Visual Science, ed.
S . Cool (New York: Springer-Verlag, in press); Karl H. Pribram, M. C. Lassonde, and
M. Ptito, “Intracerebral Influences on the Microstructure of Visual Cortex: Classifica-
tion of’ Receptive Field Properties (I)” (manuscript).
39. Karl H. Pribram, “Some Dimensions of Remembering: Steps toward a Neuro-
psychological Model of Memory,” in Macromolecules and Behavior, ed. J. Gaito (New
York: Academic Press, 1966), pp. 165-87.
40. For evidence see Karl H. Pribram and D. McGuinness, “Arousal, Activation and
Effort in the Control of Attention,” Psychologzcal Review 82 (1975): 116-49.
41. Pribram, Languages .f the Brain (n. 14 above) and “Problems Concerning the
Structure of Consciousness” (n. 27 above); Pribram, Lassonde, and Ptito (n. 38 above).
42. David Bohm, “Quantum Theory as an Indication of a New Order in Physics:
The Development of New Orders as Shown through the History of Physics (Part A),”
Foundations Of‘Physics 1 (1971): 359-81; idem, “Quantum Theory as an Indication of a
New Order in Physics: Implicate and Explicate Order in Physical Law (Part B),” ibid. 3
(1973): 139-68.
43. David Bohm, Fragmentation and Wholeness (Jerusalem: V a n h e r Jerusalem
Foundation, 1976); Fritjof Capra, The Tao ofPhysics (Berkeley, Calif.: Shambhala Publi-
cations, 1975).
124