Nothing To Fear But Fear
Nothing To Fear But Fear
Nothing To Fear But Fear
AND
Alexander D. Barder
Johns Hopkins University
Whereas late-modern societies thought they had conjured away the specter of a
state-of-nature-like violence, recent events have reminded people in developed,
rich and supposedly danger-free (often Western) nations that physical harm and
material destruction can hit anyone, anywhere, at any moment. Since the attacks
of 9 ⁄ 11 (New York and Washington, DC), 3 ⁄ 11 (Madrid), and 7 ⁄ 7 (London),
people in the West have realized that they are living ‘‘the terrifying experience
of heteronomous, vulnerable populations overwhelmed by forces they neither
control nor truly understand, horrified by their undefendability and obsessed
with the security of their borders’’ (Bauman 2006:96). An important part of this
apparent accentuation of fear has been the perception that today’s enemy, envi-
sioned as an amalgamation of forces often referred to as terrorism and poten-
tially present everywhere (Cavarero 2009), is an enemy like no other in history.
The acts of 9 ⁄ 11, 3 ⁄ 11, and 7 ⁄ 7, among others, have radicalized the idea that the
enemy is beyond any form of restraint, located in a domain where it no longer
obeys any political rationality. In 2005, George W. Bush sought to capture the
‘‘novelty’’ of this danger by claiming that this terrorizing enemy is ‘‘as brutal an
enemy as we’ve ever faced. They’re unconstrained by any notion of our common
humanity, or by the rules of warfare’’ (Bush 2005).
If one of the main arguments for the justification of the modern state (since
Hobbes in particular) has been the ability of the sovereign state to defend the
1
An earlier version of this paper was presented at the 2008 BISA annual meeting in Exeter. We would like to
thank the editors of IPS and two anonymous reviewers for their comments and suggestions.
property and basic rights of individuals (starting with their right to be free from
harm), a crucial question, possibly rendered more urgent by events of the past
decade, must be asked: what happens to practices of sovereignty and state power
when the fear of the enemy borders on the absolute? The Hobbesian solution to
create a sovereign power with a primary capacity to offer protection from violence
necessitates a concentration or centralization of fear. This fear resides in the very
persona of the sovereign. Yet, as Hobbes’ state of nature was supposed to demon-
strate, when fear escapes the sovereign domain and instead is disseminated
throughout the members of the social compact, absolute terror and the specter
of total annihilation easily can return. Such a fear of catastrophic terror is not
only a fear of potential physical harm or possible violent death. This fear is also
crucial to the maintenance or replacement of political institutions as it allows
those who mobilize its specter periodically to call into question practices that have
accompanied the development of the modern state, possibly since its inception.
For example, over the past two decades, the eliding of traditional political geo-
graphical boundaries, deterritorializing flows associated with nomadic groups
(sometimes bands of warriors or so-called terror networks) no longer under the
control of state apparatuses, or the observation of a growing global disorder more
akin to generalized civil war conditions may have reinforced the sentiment among
modern Western political leaders (and sometimes their subjects too) that a trans-
fer of responsibility and power from the sovereign to some of its order-enforcing
or risk-managing agents (police forces, the military, immigration officers, and so
on) is required. Although these phenomena are not very new, the recent resur-
gence of a discourse of totalizing fear in the wake of 9 ⁄ 11 and the Global War on
Terror has led critical political theorists to notice the multiplication of all sorts of
executive and decisionistic measures and policies. Still, many of these measures
and policies have not always been the result of a sovereign decision on the excep-
tion (as Carl Schmitt would have argued), but rather of techniques and tactics
deployed by various public agents ⁄ agencies and designed to recapture security,
order, and the law (Butler 2004; Brown 2006; Paye 2007).
Thomas Hobbes’ famous solution to what he perceived to be the danger of
civil disorder was to create a power that could centralize all individual fears and
all the methods devised by individuals to react to such fears. The arbitrary, exec-
utive, and policing force of the one and undisputed sovereign (in which all indi-
vidual subjects would finally recognize security and well-being) could become the
guarantee that the natural danger of violent death would be done away with,
even if that meant that organized violence against other sovereigns and their
populations had to be undertaken to preserve the domestic compact. This com-
pact for Hobbes was nonetheless predicated on the very condition of possibility
of a latent state of nature whose re-actualization would be taken to be what
can restructure political order. Hobbes thus became a paradigmatic figure for
subsequent theories and models of centralization of state power based upon the
premise of an always possible virtual fear or danger.
In the twentieth century, Hobbes’ model of centralized power would be revis-
ited by Schmitt’s own founding of the state on the sovereign’s prerogative to
mobilize a condition of exception. For Schmitt, the legal and constitutional order
of the modern state must have the capacity to cast itself out through an act or
decision of the executive, but also potentially through the actions of policing or
soldiering agents, during a period necessary to defeat a deadly enemy. At first
glance, Schmitt’s sovereign decision on the exception appears to be the logical
continuation of Hobbes’ desire to preserve the domestic compact and to allow
society to thrive through mechanisms that can ensure control over fear ⁄ danger.
The first part of this essay briefly reviews how Hobbes and Schmitt organized
their thoughts with a view toward perpetuating techniques of centralization of
fear in modern politics. Today, the Hobbesian mechanism of fear concentration
400 Nothing to Fear but Fear
and the Schmittian condition of sovereign exception often look like they have
been generalized to global politics. Instances of war against and destruction of
enemies proliferate across the globe in the hope that such antagonistic and sup-
posedly exceptional operations will make ‘‘us’’ free from fear (Hardt and Negri
2004). Of course, one must recognize that the Global War on Terror has been a
convenient excuse for Western states, as it has allowed them to execute openly
the kind of boundless violence in the name of an eradication of danger that, for
centuries, they practiced with proficiency against the non-West. In the West,
a typical response to the threat of so-called dangerous enemies has consisted in
re-injecting in the sovereign state a capacity to institutionalize fear at any moment
by having recourse to war and warriors (Debrix 2008; Barder and Debrix 2009).
But in this article, we also wish to move past Hobbes’ and Schmitt’s solutions
to the ‘‘fear production’’ dilemma by introducing some of Michel Foucault’s
analyses, particularly those on governmentality (Foucault 1990, 2003, 2007). Fou-
cault allows us to identify an additional dimension in the relationship between
fear and modern power. To be sure, Foucault’s concept of power is radically
different from that introduced by Hobbes and expanded upon by Schmitt. As is
now well-known, Foucault stresses a non-essentialist and relational concept of
power that further allows him to map out a non-sovereign centered potential for
disciplinization and normalization. At the same time, a less debated aspect of
Foucault’s concept of power is its connection to practices and discourses of war.
Foucault’s micro-histories of Western discourses of war, battles, and racialized
antagonistic violence suggest that fear (and the power relations that flow from
its production) is actually not something that the modern state and its agents
ever want to do away with or be free from. Rather, fear is what must be produced
and reproduced by governmental agents in order to establish the control, super-
vision, or enhancement of the social body through multiple mechanisms of mea-
surement, calculation, improvement, and preservation of life. Thus, Foucault
intimates, fear must be made productive and reproductive of society, not only to
allow the sovereign state to mobilize death, terror, or endless destruction
through a recourse to war and warriors, but also to enable life—or a certain con-
ception of what it means to have live bodies in society—to thrive.
It is indeed through a series of governmentalized techniques or procedures of
maintenance of life that, in the modern age, fear has been made ‘‘beneficial’’ to
society by, first, operating at the level of individual docile bodies (through disci-
plinary mechanisms) and later, around the turn of the nineteenth century, work-
ing on the population in its entirety (through methods of rational regulation).
Thus, one could argue that by the time Schmitt (in the twentieth century) seeks
to revisit Hobbes’ model of sovereignty (as a system of power premised upon a
concentration of fear), a generalized biopolitics of fear has already been put to
good, efficient, and ‘‘positive’’ uses in the modern state, through the disciplining
and normalizing efforts of various governmental agents that may or may not
directly serve the interests of the central sovereign ⁄ executive power.
As agencies, arrangements, or assemblages of surveillance and regulation of
bodies and the population disseminate their effects throughout the body politic,
governmentality displaces authority and power away from the centralized sover-
eign (Butler 2004:65; Neal 2008). More than a politics of sovereign exceptional-
ity, it is a biopolitics of fear enacted by way of governmentality that is operative and
that, in a way, disables the state’s central monopoly on power. This pluralization
of fear and power in governmentalized modernity further encourages all sorts of
public agents ⁄ agencies to mobilize the specter of danger, threat, insecurity, and
enmity. Far from mastering the conditions of production and reproduction of
fear (as Hobbes, Schmitt, or even some contemporary proponents of a return to
sovereign exceptionalism would have it), the sovereign is actually made to
depend upon a wide array of decentralized ‘‘executive,’’ sometimes public, and
François Debrix and Alexander D. Barder 401
fear may need to be revisited too. If and (if so) how such a power over life
relates to the modern production of fear, and whether, by seeking to optimize
the living conditions of a population, biopolitics can or even is meant to remove
fear once and for all now emerge as crucial questions. Or, to present the
dilemma of biopower somewhat differently, how a biopolitics of fear may still be
needed for the production of a new modality of power becomes a key problem-
atic.
Although never directly asked by Foucault, these questions are nevertheless
prompted by his reflections. If fear plays a part in biopolitical designs (some-
thing Foucault implies), it can no longer be to prevent a transgression of the
juridico-political order maintained by a central sovereign. Rather, it would have
to be to preserve or enhance the life-efficiency of a given population. Thus, a
new productivity of fear ⁄ terror seems to accompany the deployment of regimes
of biopolitical governance (in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries in partic-
ular, and possibly up until today). This productivity of fear and its connection to
biopolitics make sense, Foucault suggests, if we take into account the way race
comes into play in practices and discourses of power in the seventeenth and
eighteenth centuries. Foucault argues that, around that time, Western European
discourses of racial antagonism—found not just in biological studies but also in
war declarations, political treatises, or nationalist pamphlets—start to introduce a
knowledge that seeks to provide criteria regarding who can live and who, on the
contrary, can die. This biopolitical discourse of race and racial enmity (a precur-
sor to the idea of representing the enemy as a racial other) hopes to dismantle
any understanding of the human species as a biological continuum, and it strives
to impose hierarchical divisions based on categorical racial differences. Geopoliti-
cally, this discourse and subsequent practice of biopolitical racism attempt to
re-territorialize the globe along the lines of such racial profiles and differences, a
process that helps to ‘‘naturalize’’ the Western colonization projects of the eigh-
teenth and nineteenth centuries. Foucault concludes that this biopolitical racism
changes the ‘‘relationship between my life and the death of the other [in] that
it is not a military or warlike relationship of confrontation, but a biological-type
relationship’’ (Foucault 2003:255).
The normalized but supposedly ‘‘secure’’ society (‘‘secure’’ from the racial
other, and with normal living conditions that are not those of the other) that is
created by what Mitchell Dean has called an ‘‘enwrapping of the modern state’’
by biopower (Dean 1996:211) relies a great deal on representations and opera-
tions of biological racism. In many ways, this generalized yet intricate racial dis-
course of normalization (of the inside) and of antagonism (of the outside) does
not just work through a differentiation between races, but also through all sorts
of marginal forms of conduct, such as criminality, madness, underclass habits,
and so on (Foucault 2003:257). Thus, the normalization of the inside (the popu-
lation, society) and the antagonism of the outside (the racial other, the enemy)
increasingly become blurred. The ways the state and its agents start to conceive
of relations with ‘‘other races’’ or with various forms of ‘‘counter-conducts’’
become similar and undistinguishable. In all cases, it is a relation of permanent
hostility (or, perhaps, ‘‘endemic enmity’’) that is being implemented and that
demands a productive disposition on the part of the population vis-à-vis antago-
nism, enemy-construction, and moral and physical confrontation (Foucault
2007:191–226). As Foucault puts it, ‘‘[f]rom this point onward, war… is not sim-
ply a matter of destroying a political adversary, but of destroying the enemy race,
of destroying that [sort] of biological threat that those people over there repre-
sent to our race’’ (Foucault 2003:257).
The nexus biopolitics-race-war highlighted by Foucault allows us to re-concep-
tualize the relationship between power and fear in modernity (particularly
from the nineteenth century onwards). Instead of asking how the sovereign can
François Debrix and Alexander D. Barder 407
manage to keep dangers and fears in check, a more pressing question is to iden-
tify the extent to which biopolitical techniques and mechanisms of government
are indicative of a productive fear of not being able to live one’s normal, regu-
lated, or optimized life as a member of the public, population, or society. What
the perspective on biopower and the desire to preserve or even regenerate one’s
own race also suggest is the possibility that various decentralized agents ⁄ agencies
of government will need to make efficient use of fear (once again, a fear of not
being able to live one’s normal life as part of a given population). These govern-
mentalized agents and agencies can have recourse to violent techniques or brutal
force to protect a certain society. But, more often than not, they will only need
to rely on ‘‘benign’’ calculated, rationalized, and calibrated safety measures or
security mechanisms that supposedly leave no physical marks on individual
bodies since they operate at the more abstract level of the organization, normali-
zation, and optimization of the body politic.
With the emergence of those agents ⁄ agencies of government and their con-
stant efforts to regenerate the population through a generalized sense of fear of
not being able to live one’s own life in an era when racial others or unproduc-
tive counter-conducts abound, we enter the realm of what Foucault refers to as
governmentality. For Foucault, governmentality represents the moment in config-
urations of power when methods of scientific, disciplinary, and knowledge-based
rationality and procedures of government come together to organize social life,
often ‘‘through a range of formally nonpolitical knowledges and institutions’’
(Brown 2006:79). The ‘‘governmentalization of the state’’ (Brown 2006:80)
implies that this government by institutions and knowledges can pluralize the
supposedly centralized sites of sovereign ⁄ state power. With governmentality, the
origin of the law is less relevant to social and political designs (and to power’s
applications) since this particular modality of government is ‘‘not a matter of
imposing laws on men, but rather of disposing things, that is to say, to employ
tactics rather than laws, and if need be to use laws themselves as tactics’’ (Fou-
cault 1991:95). It is indeed through techniques and tactics of management and
by way of organizational and procedural dispositifs that governmentality takes
charge of a population, fosters its vital conditions (by trying to control endemic
social ‘‘illnesses’’), and ‘‘orchestrates the conduct of the body individual, the
body social, and the body politic’’ (Brown 2006:81). The ‘‘conduct of conduct’’
within the realm of biopolitics is the main objective of governmentality’s social,
economic, and political, but also cultural, religious, and educational agents and
agencies. In a context of governmentalized power, the biopolitical production of
fear is the result of a series of scare tactics or terror dispositifs put to ‘‘good’’
social effects by agents ⁄ agencies of government.
The Foucaultian concept of dispositif (often translated as ‘‘apparatus’’ in
English) is particularly useful to this analysis of biopolitics and fear. Dispositifs,
Nikolas Rose explains, are ‘‘machines for government’’ (Rose 1996:38). They are
complex apparatuses made up of various economic components, political unities,
discursive elements, and bits of sociocultural information that come together for
strategic reasons (Agamben 2009:3), not to create normative structures or to
maintain legal orders, but to produce power as governance effects. As Giorgio
Agamben has noted, dispositifs demonstrate a ‘‘capacity to capture, orient, deter-
mine, intercept, model, control, or secure the gestures, behaviors, opinions, or
discourses of living beings,’’ often with a view toward achieving some level of
subjectification (Agamben 2009:14). Moreover, the strategic or tactical work of
dispositifs is more likely to be justified (by agents of government) when public
discourses about ‘‘urgent needs’’ proliferate since dispositifs or apparatuses can
‘‘obtain an effect that is more or less immediate’’ (Agamben 2009:8). Thus, the
power of dispositifs has to do with the operational and regulating strengths they
inject into governmentality. Dispositifs can also be thought of as ‘‘lines of forces’’
408 Nothing to Fear but Fear
that seek to relate various points in society without any necessary preexisting
commonality, connectivity, or associative logic (Deleuze 2006:340). To the extent
that it makes sense to use the phrase ‘‘agents or agencies of governmentality’’
(as we do in this article), those agents ⁄ agencies and their tactics of regulation,
normalization, and optimization of life can be seen as layers, collections, or
assemblages of various dispositifs. Dispositifs are indeed machines for government
(but not of government) whose regularities of conduct nonetheless owe very little
to the possible existence of a centralized power or to the traditional model of
sovereignty.
If fear is one of these regularities generated by dispositifs of or for government
(if fear becomes a terror dispositif), fear cannot be the outcome anymore of what
the sovereign wishes to contain, control, or localize in some place (in the state
of nature, in the executive decision of the sovereign, in the persona of the king,
in the constitution). Rather, a biopolitical production of fear implies that a mul-
titude of agents for government are in the business of deploying a range of tech-
niques, procedures, and tactics that strive to realize control over or regulation of
the population’s everyday conduct from all sorts of points, positions, or perspec-
tives and through various relations ⁄ lines of force. It is everywhere throughout
society that we find security mechanisms or safety arrangements that are con-
stantly at work mobilizing fear ⁄ terror. In the last section of this article, we reflect
on some of the meanings of this analytical approach to the governmentality of
fear in contemporary settings of social terror.
Bigo’s (2002, 2006) analyses of unease are intriguing, although one may sus-
pect that they still privilege a unidirectional perspective on governmentality and
fear. Fear here is managed at the governmental level (through terror dispositifs),
and it then seeps into the public sphere through a relentless process of normali-
zation. But, unwittingly perhaps, a vertical structure of power is reproduced by
this ‘‘banoptic’’ system of governance and exception. As suggested above, any
‘‘banoptic’’ exercise implies that a condition of exception or a state of emer-
gency has been deployed. More crucially, what is absent from Bigo’s interesting
reflections on governmentality and unease is an elaboration of how the live but
banned bodies of the population, under ‘‘banoptic’’ conditions, internalize or,
rather, are encouraged to make their own a fear of not being able to live accord-
ing to normal or expected conditions. A critical concern about contemporary
regimes of governmentality is not just why individuals and groups in society fear
not being able to live their normal life. It is also how the myriad apparatuses
through which rationalities of government are rendered visible and effective
manage to make fear ⁄ terror the population’s own problem, that is to say, how
they produce fear ⁄ terror as an everyday social reality that populations must own
and become responsible for.
Asking how the productivity of fear by way of agents ⁄ agencies of governmental-
ized terror is realized means questioning the ways in which a biopolitics of fear,
unease, or insecurity takes place and reproduces itself across space and over
time. It means wondering how the governmentality of fear develops today the
conditions of production of its eventual reproduction. Whether we think about
this management of unease or fear—and the methods through which it is kept
active—in terms of special sites or exceptional events (Guantanamo’s Camp
Delta after 9 ⁄ 11), or as a matter of everyday occurrence in public places or
through mundane activities (commuting to work via the London Underground
transit system in the aftermath of the July 7, 2005 attacks),2 exploring how
bodies are mobilized to provide their own responses to the governmental man-
agement of fear ⁄ terror in the particular time-scapes of (bio)power is crucial to
assessing the resilience of contemporary regimes of power, force, and violence.
Here, Dean’s analysis can be useful. Dean writes that ‘‘[o]ur present is one in
which we are enjoined to take care and responsibility for our own lives, health, hap-
piness, sexuality, and financial security’’ (Dean 1996:211; emphasis added). The gov-
ernmentality of fear, unease, or insecurity demands that subjects ⁄ bodies act
upon themselves first and foremost. To borrow Dean’s language, it is one’s own
‘‘enfolding’’ of governmental authority, the application of dispositifs of fear and
security by oneself and onto oneself, that becomes the best guarantee that
regimes of governmentalized terror will remain effective. This individualization,
embodiment, or perhaps incarnation of ‘‘banoptic’’ techniques is a preferred
disposition of contemporary fear (re)production today (Paye 2007:245). It is by
means of such a capillarized, localized, and disseminated, but also maximizing,
totalizing, and regimenting, operation that the quotidian biopolitics of terror is
best maintained.
If insecurity or unease is the problem, and if fear ⁄ terror dispositifs are the
answer, governmental agents ⁄ agencies must ensure that the conduct responsible
for the alleged irregularity or abnormality is done away with (before it turns into
an endemic). But, more importantly, these terror dispositifs upon which govern-
mental agents rely must also make certain that bodies are actively recruited in
the maintenance of these regimes of governance. Thus, individuals and collectivi-
ties must self-rationalize, self-normalize, self-securitize, and indeed self-terrorize.
2
We are referring to the killing by the British police of Brazilian electrician Jean-Charles de Menezes in the Lon-
don Underground in July 2005 while on his way to work. For an excellent study of this shooting and its connection
to biopower, see Vaughan-Williams (2007).
410 Nothing to Fear but Fear
They must be mobilized and they must mobilize themselves against the possibil-
ity that their own conduct (perhaps their thought too) will be what leads to soci-
ety’s overall sense of insecurity, and consequently will be responsible for the
entire population’s ‘‘ill health.’’
A telling example of this self-mobilization and self-anticipation against one’s
own conduct can be found in the way Western states (or, rather, their govern-
mental agencies) along with some transnational organizations (the World Health
Organization, the United Nations) have asked populations to preemptively take
care of their health, hygiene, and everyday routines in the context of the ongo-
ing A ⁄ H1N1 or ‘‘swine flu’’ pandemic. In this recent case of popular health
scare, as with many other instances of spreading epidemics over the past decade
(SARS, the H5N1 ‘‘bird flu,’’ but also AIDS before), individuals and groups are
asked to be the first layers of securitization by turning their bodies (or those of
family members, neighbors, coworkers, etc.) into primordial sites of analysis and
scrutiny from where not only the disease but, just as importantly, the fear about
what might happen with the disease will be monitored. With the ‘‘swine flu,’’ a
constant questioning of one’s body movements and symptomatic features, but
also of one’s daily habits, becomes an automatic (and autoimmune) measure
against the endemic fear. Individual and collective bodies become the most vital
dispositifs of containment of the pandemic and of the terror that inevitably will
spread. This management or governance of the ‘‘swine flu’’ and its scare (the
disease and its terror are inseparable from the moment a pandemic discourse is
launched) is said to require constant self-checking (Do I have a fever? Is my
cough a sign that I have been infected? Did I remember to wash my hands after
riding the bus or the subway?). But it also demands what can be called self-
carceralization measures (we must stay home for several days if we feel sick; we
must wear protective masks if we venture outside and have a runny nose; we
must close entire schools for as long as necessary if we suspect that children
in the community have the flu). In the end, it is a full-blown biopolitics of self-
terror that sets in whereby people must allow themselves to be quarantined, must
accept being placed in hospital isolation, and must even be willing not to be
treated if pharmaceutical companies fail to produce enough vaccines for every-
one. As the A ⁄ H1N1 pandemic preemption regime reveals, individual and collec-
tive bodies must always be prepared to immerse themselves into disciplinary and
regulatory procedures, into security mechanisms, and into governmental tactics.
In fact, they must act as dispositifs of fear governance themselves. This means that
bodies become the required lines of forces that connect the possible localized
symptoms to the global pandemic and its terror.
From this perspective on how bodies in societies of unease enable regimes
of biopolitical terror and are themselves the product of operations of govern-
mentalized fear, no return to a centralized model of power is necessary to
make sense of the terror embedded in contemporary regimes of government.
Rather, as the ‘‘swine flu’’ case shows, it is the horizontality, the capillarity,
and the propagation of carceral effects across space and through time that
authenticates this (self) imposition of governmental power and force. But what
this system of reproduction of self-governmentalized scare tactics and biopoliti-
cal (in)security calls for, however, is the beginning of a different understand-
ing of life, or of what life means. Indeed, it is not enough anymore to think
of life as docile or regulated. It may also not be sufficient to think of today’s
living bodies as abandoned beings (Agamben 1998) caught in a state of sover-
eign exception. Rather, the self-rationalizing, self-securitizing, and self-terroriz-
ing bodies that act, react, and interact in coordination with agents ⁄ agencies of
government and are found at the heart of societies of fear production are
more likely to represent what Mick Dillon has called ‘‘emergent life’’ (Dillon
2007).
François Debrix and Alexander D. Barder 411
argument is not to be interpreted to suggest that they give their full consent to
the power of biopolitical regimes of fear production (indeed, consent, free-will,
or individual choice—actual or coerced—plays no part in this system of gover-
nance, and this is one of its main differences from the Hobbesian model), its
implication is nonetheless that emergent lives are not excluded from what terror-
izes them. This point also suggests that, as Dillon implies, emergent life is inca-
pable of thinking of itself as separate from mechanisms and dispositifs of fear
management.
In a Foucaultian fashion, we could conclude that, under emergent living con-
ditions, mobility, adaptability, and contingency are the traps of the contemporary
biopolitical order that emergent bodies fall into. But we also have to recognize
that they fall into those traps because they never cease to set them up for them-
selves. In today’s governmentalized configurations of ongoing (in)security, life
gets fused and confused with fear. Together, as one, they form the prime objects
of government and biopower. Terrifyingly, as this condition of governmentality
of fear takes charge of (emergent) life, the terror of terror, the fear of fear, or
the insecurity of insecurity become ‘‘our’’ best guarantees that human
bodies—adaptative, uncertain, vulnerable, yet also active and mobilized—will
retain a semblance of social meaning and purpose.
References
Agamben, Giorgio. (1998) Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Stanford, CA: Stanford Univer-
sity Press.
Agamben, Giorgio. (2009) What Is an Apparatus? Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Barder, Alexander, and François Debrix. (2009) Au-delà de la souveraineté biopolitique: Schmitt,
Arendt, Foucault, et les usages de la violence dans la politique internationale. E´tudes internatio-
nales 40(1): 95–124.
Bauman, Zigmunt. (2006) Liquid Fear. Cambridge: Polity.
Bigo, Didier. (2002) Security and Immigration: Toward a Critique of the Governmentality of
Unease. Alternatives 27(1): 63–92.
Bigo, Didier. (2006) Globalized-in-Security: The Field and the Ban-Opticon. In Translation, Biopoli-
tics, Colonial Difference, edited by N. Sakai, and J. Solomon. Hong Kong: Hong Kong University
Press, pp. 109–156.
Bigo, Didier. (2007) Detention of Foreigners, States of Exception, and the Social Practices of
Control of the Banopticon. In Borderscapes: Hidden Geographies and Politics at Territory’s Edge, edi-
ted by P. K. Rajaram, and C. Grundy-Warr. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Brown, Wendy. (2006) Regulating Aversion: Tolerance in the Age of Identity and Empire. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, pp. 3–34.
Bush, George W. (2005) President Discusses War on Terror at National Endowment for Democracy.
Available at http://www.whitehouse.gov/news/releases/2005/10/20051006-3.html. (Accessed
January 8, 2008).
Butler, Judith. (2004) Precarious Life: The Powers of Mourning and Violence. London: Verso.
Cavarero, Adriana. (2009) Horrorism: Naming Contemporary Violence. New York: Columbia University
Press.
Coker, Christopher. (2007) The Warrior Ethos: Military Culture and the War on Terror. London:
Routledge.
Dean, Mitchell. (1996) Foucault, Government, and the Enfolding of Authority. In Foucault
and Political Reason: Liberalism, Neo-Liberalism, and Rationalities of Government, edited by A. Barry,
T. Osborne, and N. Rose. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 209–229.
Debrix, François. (2008) Tabloid Terror: War, Culture, and Geopolitics. London: Routledge.
Deleuze, Gilles. (2006) Two Regimes of Madness: Texts and Interviews, 1975–1995. New York:
Semiotext(e).
Derrida, Jacques. (1997) Politics of Friendship. London: Verso.
Dillon, Michael. (2007) Governing Terror: The State of Emergency of Biopolitical Emergence.
International Political Sociology 1(1): 7–28.
Dyzenhaus, David. (1999) Putting the State Back in Credit. In The Challenge of Carl Schmitt, edited
by Chantal Mouffe. London: Verso, pp. 75–91.
François Debrix and Alexander D. Barder 413
Foucault, Michel. (1965) Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason. New
York: Vintage Books.
Foucault, Michel. (1979) Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. New York: Vintage Books.
Foucault, Michel. (1990) The History of Sexuality: An Introduction. Volume 1. New York: Vintage
Books.
Foucault, Michel. (1991) Governmentality. In The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, edited
by G. Burchell, C. Gordon, and P. Miller. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 87–104.
Foucault, Michel. (2003) ‘‘Society Must Be Defended’’: Lectures at the Colle`ge de France, 1975-1976. New
York: Picador.
Foucault, Michel. (2007) Security, Territory, Population: Lectures at the Colle`ge de France, 1977-1978.
New York: Palgrave.
Hardt, Michael, and Antonio Negri. (2004) Multitude. New York: Penguin.
Hobbes, Thomas. (1985) Leviathan. New York: Penguin.
Hobbes, Thomas. (1998) On the Citizen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hobbes, Thomas. (1999) The Elements of Law, Natural and Politic: Part I, Human Nature; Part II, De
Corpore Politico; With Three Lives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Huysmans, Jef. (2006) The Politics of Insecurity: Migration and Asylum in the EU. London: Routledge.
Minca, Claudio. (2006) Giorgio Agamben and the New Biopolitical Nomos. Geografiska Annaler
88B(4): 387–403.
Münkler, Herfried. (2007) Empires. Cambridge: Polity.
Neal, Andrew. (2008) Goodbye War on Terror? Foucault and Butler on Discourses of Law, War,
and Exceptionalism. In Foucault on Politics, Security and War, edited by M. Dillon and A. Neal.
Basingstoke: Palgrave, pp. 43–64.
Paye, Jean-Claude. (2007) Global War on Liberty. New York: Telos.
Robin, Corey. (2004) Fear: The History of a Political Idea. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rose, Nikolas. (1996) Governing ‘‘Advanced’’ Liberal Democracies. In Foucault and Political Reason:
Liberalism, Neo-Liberalism, and Rationalities of Government, edited by A. Barry, T. Osborne, and
N. Rose. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 37–64.
Schmitt, Carl. (2005) Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Schmitt, Carl. (2007) The Concept of the Political. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Smith, Neil. (2004) The Endgame of Globalization. London: Routledge.
Strauss, Leo. (1984) The Political Philosophy of Hobbes: Its Basis and Its Genesis. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Strauss, Leo. (1996) Notes on Carl Schmitt. In The Concept of the Political, edited by C. Schwab.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 81–107.
Strong, Tracy. (2005) Foreword: The Sovereign and the Exception. In Political Theology: Four Chap-
ters on the Concept of Sovereignty, edited by C. Schwab. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp.
vii–xxxv.
Vaughan-Williams, Nick. (2007) The Shooting of Jean Charles de Menezes: New Border Politics?
Alternatives 32(2): 177–195.
Vaughan-Williams, Nick. (2008) Borders, Territory, Law. International Political Sociology 2(4):
322–338.
Weiler, Gershon. (1994) From Absolutism to Totalitarianism: Carl Schmitt on Thomas Hobbes. London:
Hollowbrook.
Whitehall, Geoffrey. (2009) The Aesthetic Emergency of the Avian Flu Affect. In The Geopolitics of
American Insecurity, edited by F. Debrix and M. Lacy. London: Routledge, pp. 161–180.
Williams, Michael C. (2005) The Realist Tradition and the Limits of International Relations. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
ˇ ižek, Slavoj. (1999) Carl Schmitt in the Age of Post-Politics. In The Challenge of Carl Schmitt, edited
Z
by C. Mouffe. London: Verso, pp. 18–37.