The Revival of Narrative, Some Comments - Eric Hobsbawm

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 6

THE REVIVAL OF NARRATIVE:

SOME COMMENTS
LAWRENCE STONE BELIEVES THAT THERE IS A REVIVAL OF "NARRATIVE
history" because there has been a decline in the history devoted to
asking "the big why questions", the generalizing "scientific history".
This in turn he thinks is due to disillusionment with the essentially
economic determinist models of historical explanation, Marxist or
otherwise, which have tended to dominate in the post-war years; to the

Downloaded from past.oxfordjournals.org by guest on February 13, 2011


declining ideological commitment of western intellectuals; con-
temporary experience which has reminded us that political aaion and
decision can shape history; and the failure of "quantitative history"
(another claimant to "scientific" status) to deliver the goods.1 Two
questions are involved in this argument, which I have brutally over-
simplified: what has been happening in historiography, and how are
these developments to be explained? Since it is common ground that in
history "the facts" are always selected, shaped and perhaps distorted
by the historian who observes them, there is an element of parti pris,
not to say intellectual autobiography, in Stone's treatment of both
questions, as in my comments on it.
I think we may accept that the twenty years following the Second
World War saw a sharp decline in political and religious history, in the
use of "ideas" as an explanation of history, and a remarkable turn to
socio-economic history and to historical explanation in terms of
"social forces", as Momigliano noted as early as 1954.2 Whether or
not we call them "economic-determinist", these currents of hist-
oriography became influential, in some cases dominant, in the main
western centres of historiography, not to mention, for other reasons,
the eastern ones. We may also accept that in recent years there has
been considerable diversification, and a marked revival of interest in
themes which were rather more marginal to the main concerns of the
historical outsiders who in those years became historical insiders,
though such themes were never neglected. After all, Braudel wrote
about Philip II as well as the Mediterranean, and Le Roy Ladurie's
monograph on Le carnaval de Romans of 1580 is anticipated by a
much briefer, but most perceptive, account of the same episode in his
Les paysans du Languedoc? If Marxist historians of the 1970s write
1
Lawrence Stone, "The Revival of Narrative: Reflections on a New Old History",
Past and Present, no. 85 (Nov. 1979), pp. 3-24.
1
Arnaldo Momigliano, "A Hundred Years after Ranke", in his Studies in
Historiography (London, 1966), pp. 108-9.
3
Fernand Braudel, La Miditerranie et le monde miditerranien a I'ipoque de
Philippe II (Paris, 1960); Emmanuel Le Roy Ladurie, Le carnaval de Romans (Paris,
1979); Emmanuel Le Roy Ladurie, Les paysans du Languedoc, 2 vols. (Paris, 1966),
'» PP- 394-9. *
4 PAST AND PRESENT NUMBER 8 6

entire books on the role of radical-national myths, such as the Welsh


Madoc legend, Christopher Hill at least wrote a seminal article on the
myth of the Norman Yoke in the early 1950s.4 Still, there probably has
been a change.
Whether this amounts to a revival of "narrative history" as denned
by Stone (basically chronological ordering of the material in "a single
coherent story, albeit with sub-plots" and a concentration "on man
not circumstances") is difficult to determine, since Stone deliberately
eschews a quantitative survey and concentrates on "a very tiny, but
disproportionately prominent, section of the historical profession as a
whole".5 Nevertheless there is evidence that the old historical avant-

Downloaded from past.oxfordjournals.org by guest on February 13, 2011


garde no longer rejects, despises and combats the old-fashioned
"history of events" or even biographical history, as some of it used to.
Fernand Braudel himself has given unstinted praise to a notably
traditional exercise in popular narrative history, Claude Manceron's
attempt to present the origins of the French Revolution through a
series of overlapping biographies of contemporaries, great and small.6
On the other hand the historical minority whose supposedly changed
interests Stone surveys, has not in fact changed over to practising
narrative history. If we leave aside deliberate historiographical con-
servatives or neo-conservatives such as the British "antiquarian
empiricists", there is very little simple narrative history among the
works Stone cites or refers to. For almost all of them the event, the in-
dividual, even the recapture of some mood or way of thinking of the
past, are not ends in themselves, but the means of illuminating some
wider question, which goes far beyond the particular story and its
characters.
In short those historians who continue to believe in the possibility of
generalizing about human societies and their development, continue
to be interested in "the big why questions", though they may some-
times focus on different ones from those on which they concentrated
twenty or thirty years ago. There is really no evidence that such
historians — the ones Stone is mainly concerned with — have
abandoned "the attempt to produce a coherent.. . explanation of
change in the past". 7 Whether they (or we) also regard their attempt
as "scientific" will no doubt depend on our definition of "science", but
we need not enter this dispute about labels. Moreover I very much
doubt whether such historians feel that they are "forced back upon the
4
Christopher Hill, "The Norman Yoke", in John Saville (ed.), Democracy and the
Labour Movement: Essays in Honour of Dona Torr (London, 1954), repr. in Chrif-
topher Hill, Puritanism and Revolution: Studies in Interpretation of the English
Revolution of the 17th Century (London, 1958), pp. 50-122.
3
Stone, op. cit., pp. 3, 4.
* Fernand Braudel, "Une parfaite reussite" [review of Claude Manceron, La
Revolution qui live, 1785-178; (Paris, I979)L L'histoire, no. 21 (1980), pp. 108-9.
7
Stone, op. cit., p. 19.
THE REVIVAL OF NARRATIVE 5
8
principle of indeterminacy", any more than Marx felt his writings
about Louis Napoleon to be incompatible with the materialist concep-
tion of history.
No doubt there are historians who have abandoned such attempts,
and certainly there are some who combat them, perhaps with a zeal
increased by ideological commitment. (Whether or not Marxism has
declined intellectually, it is hard to detect much muting of ideological
controversy among western historians, though the participants and
the specific issues may not be the same as twenty years ago.) Probably
neo-conservative history has gained ground, at any rate in Britain,
both in the form of the "young antiquarian empiricists" who "write

Downloaded from past.oxfordjournals.org by guest on February 13, 2011


detailed political narratives which implicitly deny that there is any
deep-seated meaning to history except the accidental whims of fortune
and personality",9 and in the form of works like Theodore Zeldin's
(and Richard Cobb's) remarkable plunges into those strata of the past,
to which "almost every aspect of traditionalist history" is irrelevant,
including the answering of questions.10 So, probably, has what might
be called anti-intellectual leftist history. But this, except very tan-
gentially, is not what Stone is concerned with.
How then are we to account for the shifts in historical subject-
matter and interests, in so far as they have occurred or are occurring?
One element in them, it may be suggested, reflects the remarkable
widening of the field of history in the past twenty years, typified by the
rise of "social history", that shapeless container for everything from
changes in human physique to symbol and ritual, and above all for the
lives of all people from beggars to emperors. As Braudel has observed,
this "histoire obscure de tout le monde" is "the history towards which,
in different ways, all historiography tends at present". 11 This is not
the place to speculate on the reasons for this vast extension of the field,
which certainly does not necessarily conflict with the attempt to
produce a coherent explanation of the past. It does, however, increase
the technical difficulty of writing history. How are these complexities
to be presented? It is not surprising that historians experiment with
different forms of such presentation, including notably those that
borrow from the ancient techniques of literature (which has made its
own stabs at displaying la comidie humaine), and also from the
modern audio-visual media, in which all but the oldest of us are
saturated. What Stone calls the pointilliste techniques are, at least in
part, attempts to solve such technical problems of presentation.
Such experiments are particularly necessary for that part of history
• Ibid., p. 13.
• Ibid., p. 20.
10
Theodore Zeldin, France, 1848-1945,2 vols. (Oxford History of Modern Europe
ier.,Oxford, 1973-7), tram. atMstoire da passions francaiscs (Paris, 1978); Richard
Cobb, Death in Paris (Oxford, 1978).
11
Braudel, "Une parfaite reunite", p. 109.
6 PAST AND PRESENT NUMBER 8 6

which cannot be subsumed under "analysis" (or the rejection of


analysis) and which Stone rather neglects, namely synthesis. The
problem of fitting together the various manifestations of human
thought and action at a specific period is neither new nor unrecog-
nized. No history of Jacobean England is satisfactory which omits
Bacon or treats him exclusively as a lawyer, a politician, or a figure in
the history of science or of literature. Moreover even the most con-
ventional historians recognize it, even when their solutions (a chapter
or two on science, literature, education or whatnot appended to the
main body of politico-institutional text) is unsatisfactory. Yet the
wider the range of human activities which is accepted as the legitimate

Downloaded from past.oxfordjournals.org by guest on February 13, 2011


concern of the historian, the more clearly understood the necessity of
establishing systematic connections between them, the greater the
difficulty of achieving a synthesis. This is, naturally, far more than a
technical problem of presentation, yet it is that also. Even those who
continue to be guided in their analysis by something like the "three-
tiered hierarchical" model of base and superstructures which Stone
rejects,12 may find it an inadequate guide to presentation, though
probably a less inadequate guide than straight chronological narra-
tive.
Leaving aside the problems of presentation and synthesis, two more
substantial reasons for a change may also be suggested. The first is the
very success of the "new historians" in the post-war decades. This was
achieved by a deliberate methodological simplification, the concentra-
tion on what were seen as the socio-economic base and determinants
of history, at the expense of — sometimes, as in the French battle
against the "history of events", in direct confrontation with — tradi-
tional narrative history. While there were some extreme econo-
mic reductionists, and others who dismissed people and events as
negligible ripples on the tongue duree of structure and conjoncture,
such extremism was not universally shared either in Annales, or
among the Marxists who — especially in Britain — never lost interest
in events or culture, nor regarded "superstructure" as always and
entirely dependent on "base". Yet the very triumph of works like those
of Braudel, Goubert and Le Roy Ladurie, which Stone underlines, not
only left "new" historians free to concentrate on those aspects of
history hitherto deliberately set aside, but advanced their place on the
"new historians" agenda. As an eminent Annalist, Le Goff, pointed
out several years ago, "political history was gradually to return in
force by borrowing the methods, spirit and theoretical approach of the
very social sciences which had pushed it into the background". 13 The
new history of men and minds, ideas and events may be seen as com-
12
Stone, op. cil., pp. 7-8.
" J. Le Goff, "Is Politics Still the Backbone of History?", in Felix Gilbert and
Stephen R. Graubard (edl.), Historical Studies Today (New York, 1972), p. J40.
THE REVIVAL OF NARRATIVE 7

plementing rather than as supplanting the analysis of socio-economic


structures and trends.
But once historians turn to such items on their agenda, they may
prefer to approach their "coherent explanation of change in the past"
as it were ecologically rather than as geologists. They may prefer to
start with the study of a "situation" which embodies and exemplifies
the stratified struaure of a society but concentrates the mind on the
complexities and interconnections of real history, rather than with the
study of the structure itself, especially if for this they can rely partly on
earlier work. This, as Stone recognizes, lies at the root of some
historians' admiration for works like Clifford Geertz's "close reading"
of a Balinese cock-fight.14 It implies no necessary choice between

Downloaded from past.oxfordjournals.org by guest on February 13, 2011


monocausality and multicausality, and certainly no conflict between a
model in which some historical determinants are seen as more power-
ful than others, and the recognition of interconnections, both vertical
and horizontal. A "situation" may be a convenient point of departure,
as in Ginzburg's study of popular ideology through the case of a single
village atheist in the sixteenth century or a single group of Friu-
lian peasants accused of witchcraft.15 These topics could also be
approached in other ways. It may be a necessary point of departure in
other cases, as in Agulhon's beautiful study of how, at a particular
time and place, French villagers converted from Catholic tradi-
tionalism to militant republicanism.16 At all events, for certain
purposes historians are likely to choose it as a starting-point.
There is thus no necessary contradiction between Le Roy Ladurie's
Les paysans du Languedoc and his Montaillou, any more than
between Duby's general works on feudal society and his monograph
on the battle of Bouvines, or between E. P. Thompson's The Making
of the English Working Class and his Whigs and Hunters.11 There is
nothing new in choosing to see the world via a microscope rather than
a telescope. So long as we accept that we are studying the same cosmos,
the choice between microcosm and macrocosm is a matter of selecting
the appropriate technique. It is significant that more historians find
the microscope useful at present, but this does not necessarily mean
that they reject telescopes as out of date. Even the historians of
14
Clifford Geertz, "Deep Play: Notes on the Balinese Cock-Fight", in his The
Interpretation of Cultures (New York, 1973).
15
Carlo Ginzburg, II formaggio e i vermi (Turin, 1976); Carlo Ginzburg, /
benandanti: ricerche sulla ttregoneria e sui culti agrari tra Cinquecento e Seicento
(Turin, 1966).
16
Maurice Agulhon, La Ripublique au village (Paris, 1970).
" Le Roy Ladurie, Les paysans du Languedoc; Emmanuel Le Roy Ladurie,
Montaillou, village occitan de 1294 d 1324 (Paris, 1976), trans. B. Bray as
Montaillou: Cathars and Catholics in a French Village, 1294-1324 (London, 1978);
Georges Duby, Le dimanche de Bouvines, 2j juillet 1214 (Paris, 1973); E. P.
Thompson, The Making of the English Working Class (London, 1963); E. P.
Thompson, Whigs and Hunters (London, 1975).
8 PAST AND PRESENT NUMBER 8 6

mentalite, that vague catch-all term which Stone, perhaps wisely, does
not try to clarify, do not exclusively or predominantly avoid the broad
view. This at least is a lesson they have learned from the anthro-
pologists.
Do these observations account for Stone's "broad cluster of changes
in the nature of historical discourse"?18 Perhaps not. However, they
demonstrate that it is possible to explain much of what he surveys as-
the continuation of past historical enterprises by other means, instead
of as proofs of their bankruptcy. One would not wish to deny that some
historians regard them as bankrupt or undesirable and wish to change
their discourse in consequence, for various reasons, some of them

Downloaded from past.oxfordjournals.org by guest on February 13, 2011


intellectually dubious, some to be taken seriously. Clearly some
historians have shifted from "circumstances" to "men" (including
women), or have discovered that a simple base/superstructure model
and economic history are not enough, or — since the pay-off from
such approaches has been very substantial — are no longer enough.
Some may well have convinced themselves that there is an in-
compatibility between their "scientific" and "literary" functions. But
it is not necessary to analyse the present fashions in history entirely as
a rejection of the past, and in so far as they cannot be entirely
analysed in such terms, it will not do.
We are all anxious to discover where historians are going. Stone's
essay is to be welcomed as an attempt to do so. Nevertheless it is not
satisfactory. In spite of his disclaimer the essay does combine the
charting of "observed changes in historical fashion" with "value
judgements about what are good, and what are less good, modes of
historical writing", 19 especially about the latter. I think this is a pity,
not because I happen to disagree with him about "the principle of in-
determinacy" and historical generalization, but because, if the argu-
ment is wrong, a diagnosis of the "changes in historical discourse"
made in terms of this argument must also be inadequate. One is
tempted, like the mythical Irishman, asked by the traveller for the way
to Ballynahinch, to stop, ponder, and reply: "If I were you, I wouldn't
start from here at all".
Birkbeck College, London E. J. Hobsbawm

'• Stone, op. cit., p. 23.


" Ibid., p. 4.

You might also like